Lecture Notes in Mathematics Edited by A. Dold, B. Eckmann and E Takens
1401 J. Stepr~ns S. Watson (Eds.)
Set Theory a...
210 downloads
1771 Views
12MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Lecture Notes in Mathematics Edited by A. Dold, B. Eckmann and E Takens
1401 J. Stepr~ns S. Watson (Eds.)
Set Theory and its Applications Proceedings of a Conference held at York University, Ontario, Canada, Aug. 10-21, 1987
Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg NewYork London ParisTokyo Hong Kong
Editors
Juris Stepr~ns Stephen Watson York University, North York, Ontario M3J 1P3 Canada
Mathematics Subject Classification (1980): 54-06; 04-06 ISBN 3-540-51730-8 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg NewYork ISBN 0-387-51730-8 Springer-Verlag N e w Y o r k Berlin Heidelberg
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, re-use of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reprod'uction on microfilms or in other ways, and storage in data banks. Duplication of this publication or parts thereof is only permitted under the provisions of the German Copyright Law of September 9, 1965, in its version of June 24, 1985, and a copyright fee must always be paid. Violations fall under the prosecution act of the German Copyright Law. © Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 1989 Printed in Germany Printing and binding: Druckhaus Beltz, Hemsbach/Bergstr, 2146/3140-543210- Printed on acid-free paper
Preface
The Set Theory and its Applications Conference at York University was held in Toronto, Canada during the two weeks of August 10-21, 1987. It was attended by 80 mathematicians from 12 different countries. Financial support for this conference was provided by the Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council under the auspices of the Canadian Mathematical Society and by York University through both the President's Office and the Office of the Dean of the Faculty of Arts. The organizers would like to express their thanks for this financial support without which the conference would not have been possible. The conference featured both contributed talks and a series of invited lectures on topics central to the study of set theory and its applications, particularly to general topology. The organizers would like to thank the invited speakers James Baumgartner, Arnold Miller, Andreas Blass, Neil Hindman, Stevo Todorcevic, Ronald Jensen, Hugh Woodin, Jan van Mill, Boban Velickovic, Menachem Magidor, A. V. Arhangel'skii and Mary Ellen Rudin for a series of highly informative and stimulating lectures. We would also like to thank the many speakers who contributed lectures to the conference, in many cases announcing new and important results for the first time. The organizers would like to thank the staff of the Mathematics Department of York University for their help in the organization of the conference. We would like, in particular, to thank Joan Young for her knowledgeable assistance. All of the articles in this volume have been refereed. We would like to thank the referees for their many helpful comments which have greatly improved the quality of the articles which make up this volume. We would also like to thank Eadie Henry for her tireless work in the preparation of one manuscript from handwritten original draft through several series of revisions to a well-written and clearly presented final copy. This volume of Springer Lecture Notes in Mathematics constitutes the proceedings of this conference. We would like to thank the editors for accepting the proceedings.
Alan Dow Donald Pelletier Juris Steprgms Stephen Watson
Dedication T w o weeks before the conference began, we received the sad news that Eric van Douwen had died. We had been musing about the conference for more than two years and even from the beginning we had decided that Eric would be invited and that he would give a series of lectures. We were curious a b o u t what topics he would choose because we knew that when Eric lectured, people paid attention to his ideas and mathematics would advance a little bit in his direction. We knew we would see a solution to some well-known problem, a completely original proof for some well-known result, and we knew that we would all aim a little bit higher. We also simply looked forward to seeing Eric again. Eric wrote over seventy papers in sixteen years b u t we always felt that the greater part of what he knew had never been written down. We wanted to talk to him and listen to him until we tired from sheer stimulation. General topologists form a c o m m u n i t y and Eric Karet van Douwen was an elder who possessed the knowledge of its oral traditions, but was denied the o p p o r t u n i t y to pass it down. T h e loss to us was devastating, for we lost not only a m a t h e m a t i c i a n b u t a friend.
T a b l e
Murray Spaces
of
C o n t e n t s
G. B e l l of I d e a l s
of P a r t i a l
J a m e s E. B a u m g a r t n e r Remarks on Partition
Functions
Ordinals
..............................
......................................
Andreas Blass Applications of Superperfect
18
D o n n a M. C a r r a n d D o n a l d H. P e l l e t i e r T o w a r d s a S t r u c t u r e T h e o r y for I d e a l s
o n P~(l) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
41
Alan Dow Compact Spaces
in t h e C o h e n M o d e l
55
Tightness
Fons van Engelen, Kenneth Kunen Two Remarks about Analytic Sets Frantisek Franek Saturated Ideals C o l l a p s e of H u g e Nell Hindman Uitrafilters
a n d its R e l a t i v e s
5
............
of C o u n t a b l e
Forcing
1
..........
a n d A r n o l d W. M i l l e r ...................................
68
Obtained via Restricted Iterated Cardinals ........................................
73
and Ramsey
Pierre Matet Concerning Stationary
Theory
Subsets
- an U p d a t e
........................
o f [ ~ + + and q N r ~ #, we see that each
~({r})
To Q1 thru Q3 add Q5:
such that
denote closure
b~l(1).
f-l(1)
there exists
to one map.
ly the same w a y that van Douwen and K u n e n proved that C£
f ~ 2 e,
otherwise
We conclude,
as foll-
then you get the total Q-
For each
A first countable compact ccc space without property
c = e 1. A
P0
0 < u < el; < n}.
can be identified
Together with Len~a 3.1, we see that
cellularity.
(CH)
then
an Eberlein compact.
there exists
Example
with
6({q})
is a countable
C o n d i t i o n Q3' implies that
of Corson compact,
n
and ~ 8
In other words, we have a canonical Hausdorff
I(f,~) = I(f,8).
set; hence
a sigma-disjoint
B~-
and choose
= {q c Q : q ~ f
such that if if
Bn c
We were unable to complete the inductive
7 < @, with
Ae
step while insist-
ing that we also satisfy condition Q4 but if the reader only carries along the weaker Q4': for each completing
s < 8,
A
N B8 =
the inductive step.
separability
of
and
Condition Q5 implies that
Hence,
J(Q)
4.
N A8 =
~;
he will have no difficulty
to prove Q3 and Q5, use the hereditary
2 e. ~0
does not have an uncountable
and so it follows from Le~m~ 3.2 that
have p r o p e r t y
B
Upon completion,
is a first countable,
P
has no uncountable
Corson compact
disjoint
disjoint
space that is
ccc
subcollection
subcollection. but does not
K.
References
i. M. Bell, A normal first countable ccc nonseparable space, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 74(1), 1979, 151-155. 2. M. Bell, First countable pseudocompactifications, Topology Appl. 21, 1985, 159-166. 3. M. Bell, G K subspaces of Hyadic spaces, submitted manuscript. 4. E. van Douwen and K. Kunen, L-spaces and S-spaces in ~ ( ~ , T o p o l o g y Appl. 14, 1982, 143-149. 5. T. Jech, Nonprovability of Souslin's hypothesis, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolinae 8, 1967, 293-296. 6. I. Jubasz, Cardinal Functions in Topology, Mathematical Centre Tract 34, Amsterdam, 1971. 7. K. Kunen, A compact L-space under CH, Topology Appl. 12, 1981, 283-287.
Remarks on partition ordinals by James E. Baumgartner 1
Abstract.
After a brief survey of the theory of partition ordinals, i.e., ordinals ~ such
that a --~ (c~, n) 2 for all n < w, it is shown that MA(R1) implies that
wlw
and
wlw 2
are
partition ordinals. This contrasts with an old result of ErdSs and Hajnal that c~ 74 (c~, 3) 2 holds for both these ordinals under the Continuum Hypothesis. 1. P a r t i t i o n o r d i n a l s . The theory of ordinary partition relations for cardinal numbers is fairly well understood at present (see [EHMR], for example), but the corresponding theory for non-cardinal ordinal numbers seems still to be in its infancy. This paper begins with a survey of results and problems concerning ordinals (~ satisfying the partition relation a -~ (c~, n) u for all n < w and ends with the proof from Martin's Axiom + -~CIt t h a t this relation holds when a is wlw
or
0J1w2`
As usual, if X is a set and n is a cardinal then IX]'* denotes the collection of all n-element subsets of X . If a, ;3, and 7 are ordinals, then the partition relation c~ -~ (;3, 7) 2 means that for all f : [a] ~ --* 2 there is X C a such that either X has order type ;3 and f is constantly 0 on IX] 2 or else X has order type 7 and f is constantly 1 on IX] 2. A convenient alternative definition says that ~ --* (;3,7) 2 iff every graph on a either has an independent set of type ;3 or a complete subgraph of type 7. Here, of course, the set E of edges of the graph is identified with f - l ( 1 } in the other definition. 1 Preparation of this paper was partially supported by National Science Foundation grant number DMS-8704586.
For cardinal numbers there is a strong result due to Erdfs, Dushnik and Miller (see [Wi] for a treatment of it), namely if ~ is a cardinal then ~ --+ (~,w) 2. The machinery of ordinary partition relations for cardinals yields strengthenings of this result for various ~. For example, if ~ is regular and s > w then ~ ---, (~,w + 1)2; if in addition A~° < whenever A < ~ then ~ -* (~,wl + 1)2; and so on. For non-cardinals the situation is quite different. The following result is well-known: Proposition I.I. Ira • [a] then a 74 (]a] + l,w) 2. Proof. Let < be the usual ordering on a and let 1 let F] = { y e Fj : {zl,Y} e E l } .
By
inductive hypothesis we may find xj e Fj~ with [{x2,..., zk}] 2 C El, and now it is clear that [ { z l , . . . , xk}] 2 C E l as well. To treat E = E2, use Le~mna 2.3(5) and choose F C Fk.
3. A p p l y i n g M a r t i n ' s A x i o m . Let us emphasize t h a t Theorem 2.1 was proved in ZFC. Of course, since one application of the theorem is to the case a = w and ~I'
M.
In any model o b t a i n e d by a d j o i n i n g u n c o u n t a b l y m a n y C o h e n
or r a n d o m reals to any model of ZFC,
g = ~I"
26
Proof.
The preceding
The case
of m o r e
adjoining ground
previous as
all
~I
~1
of
but
model,
adjoining
one.
section
with
The
first
remark by
is a n e a s y a r g u m e n t than
~
sets
of
is that
that
shows
that
is s e n t
f:~ --~ ~.
of c a r d l n a l i t y
< ~.
I Between
dense
this
f(n) of
=
X,
function
imply
the
remark
gives
information
Formulation
(d) of N C F
first
for
the [8],
consistency does
not
We show FD, from
the
was
next and
generated
unpublished these
that shown
and
so
u < g
showed
implies
to i m p l y N C F
that
fewer
Then
than
the
successive B ~ ~.
though
results than
So
filter.
weaker
of K e t o n e n
b
sets
is a
and Laflamme
ultrafilters. NCF
implies
shortly
filter
in S e c t i o n
in
t h a n NCF.
dichotomy This
The
he proved
described
weaker
1.
u < b.
before
this model,
is s t r i c t l y the
elements
to the c o f l n i t e
of C a n J a r
that
~ ~ b
on every
by fewer
by Shelah
u < b
are
u < b,
related
fewer by some
B}
between
because
work
1 shows
obtained
CanJar
NCF,
S
there
is a f i l t e r
large
there
values
inequality
interest,
in S e c t i o n
of NCF.
satisfy
introduced [7].
is that
•
of
As
by
u < ~,
family
on intervals
generated
from
to t h e m all.
many
by
filter
that
the
dense). common
finitely
filter
, < b
follows
Suppose
two sufficiently
constant
about
generated
is a n e l e m e n t
but
Recent
filter
The
this
In fact,
to the c o f i n l t e
every
X
u < g.
inequality,
above.
there
any ultrafilter
P-polnt.
model
to t h e
the same
stronger"
B e ~,
groupwise
all
non-Ramsey more
is e x a c t l y
inequality.
[24].)
is of c o n s i d e r a b l e
that
this new
reduces
this
every
each
is a n
IX n nl,
sends
u < g,
[16]
there
takes
The second than
(but n o t
families,
function members
X
about
(This a l s o
in
For
of
these
over
case
reals.
first
but we close
discussed
i.e.,
proof
is c l e a r l y
random
as
principle
section,
"next
diagram
function
of
reals
the
the H a s s e
Solomon's
(X e [~]~
for C o h e n
and a theorem
together
~B =
~i
then,
so t h i s
the n e x t
finlte-to-one
base
and
reals,
the c o m b i n a t o r i a l
occupy
is f e e b l e ,
with
reals
random
study
will
two remarks
is i n c o n s i s t e n t ,
the r a n d o m
of
c a n be v i e w e d
o
our
proof
the c a s e
reals
the proof
reals,
We now begin
covers
random
~1
Finally,
for r a n d o m
consistency
discussion
than
principle, result
is
27
Theorem
3.
Assume
flnlte-to-one
f:~ --~ ~
the c o f l n l t e
< g.
For
Let
We s h a l l
~
such
for e v e r y
B e ~,
For
I There
some
Clearly, finite ~B
is not
assume
~B
set
each
Case
which there S
=
Y
must
or
in
~
f-l(y),
[x,y)
and,
being
infinite
every
by
is d i v i d e d (because for
an ultrafilter,
SUPERPERFECT
section,
by M i l l e r
countable
This
result
was
shown
that
X
an
but
be
can
the
the
f-l(y) x < y
are
f-l{f(n))
H,
B.
so
is a in
is
But
it c a n n o t
coflnite
be
filter.
dense. to all
of
the
intervals X.
with
f(~)
For f(A)
~ f(~).
~B'S.
Let
[x,y)
into
each
B E S,
G f(B). Since
Since f(~)
is
u < g. superfect
a n d we s h o w
over
into we
is f i n l t e - t o - o n e ,
if
is the
as
o
we d e f i n e
[7],
A e ~
of
Suppose
~, m e e t s
on the
x,y
~
then
of
common
that
YIELDS
[18],
of
n
Then
indeed, n,
f(9)
B).
under So,
this
f(~).
intervals
is c o n s t a n t
= f(~).
in
s a y at
meets
intervals,
filter.
_ y) E ~B;
are
sets.
f:~ --~ ~
to n;
is g r o u p w l s e
it f o l l o w s
supports
is f r o m
set
the e l e m e n t s
FORCING
H
x < y
closed
cofinite
Let
interval
is an
f
X 6 ~B)
~, f(~)
~B
there
~
with
that
dense.
cofinlte
of
shows
B e ~,
so
an
union
contradiction
IS I < g,
In this
such
Ix,y)
It is a l s o
all
B.
of
is the
then
By m e r g i n g
meets
f-l(~
exists
f
an u l t r a f i l t e r .
be a p a r t i t i o n
~B"
be a c o i n f l n i t e
IX N [O,n] I ,
same model
is a
of c a r d i n a l i t y
whenever
A,
subsets.
is in
f(~)
[x,y)
is a n
introduced
there
that,
meets
contains
meets
is a b a s i s
3.
•
that
For
•
= f(~),
groupwise
the n th i n t e r v a l
that
let
This
2.
under
and
in
f(~)
[x,y)
witnessing
Since f(n)
sends
and
_ y)
~B"
there
an u l t r a f i l t e r
a base
such
is not
because
interval
show
f-l(~ _ y) in
is c l o s e d
dense,
that
included
Then
~, a f i n i t e - t o - o n e or
A e ~
~B
of w h i c h
A E ~
f-l(w
filter.
is e i t h e r
with
filter
and
no u n i o n
and we shall contrary,
X
groupwise
that
function
f(~)
filter
is
B e ~,
modifications
intervals,
be a n y
let
in I.
~
that
is the c o f l n l t e
~B = (X e [w] W
Case
let
be a n u l t r a f i l t e r
find,
f(~)
each
and
filter.
Proof.
either
~ < 9
forcing,
that
a model
of G C H y i e l d s
most
the p r o o f
to s a t i s f y
of
NCF.
a notion
iterating
it
a model
is as
in
of
~2 of
[10]
forcing times u < g.
where
the
28
B y a tree, ~, o r d e r e d
we mean
by end
many
immediate
with
at
successors
least
two
is s u p e r p e r f e c t We consider
(of s u p e r p e r f e c t
in
G
is a s i n g l e W of
trees this of
that
w.
trees),
W
of
as n o d e s ,
intersection
the
can be viewed
A straightforward [23]
and
It w i l l trees
fusion
in f a c t
this
the set
G
of all
of a l l
initial
are
the
is a g e n e r i c
branch
the
is a n
trees infinite
superperfect
segments
as adjoining
be useful
if
~
[ao,al),
trunk)
of
at t i m e s
max(a)
e Ik,
member
from
a u {n}
tree
so
that
J > k
of
W.
a generic
so t h e
of
The
Thus,
subset
W
into
concept
a
superperfect with
interval
following
in c h o o s i n g
interval
a path
through
tree amounts
to a s p e c i f i c a t i o n ,
Ij,
by the
indexed
stage
and
l's
interval
[0,a0),
(also called n o d e a,
consists
the if
of o n e
branching),
and,
a u (n}
has an
e 1 I.
It
to o n e w i t h
structure
of
j-tuples
the climbing
set.
At
decisions (1 for
by this
J-tuple
choices
that
stage
are
is n o t
if
hard
interval dense
0, w e m u s t
0
is o f f e r e d
contains
for
a tree
for e a c h
in the
take
the
are
"leave"), to
infinitely
trunk.
coded
and
take
j > O, of
whether
or
often
m a y be
of w h a t
("climbing
l's t h a t
we decide
stages
to us,
"take"
such
I0,Ii,-.-
description
of O ' s a n d
process,
from previous
"take",
structure
anthropomorphic
of
J
I0 =
then
max(b)
tree down
The
the
to s u p e r p e r f e c t tree has
is a n o d e }
with
is
[2].
for e a c h b r a n c h i n g
n e Ii;
b
forcing A
node
is i n f i n i t e l y
with
of a t r e e w i t h
by the
a certain
intervals
I a u (n}
successor
conditions
attention
branching
I O,
a
Axiom
forcing.
clarified involved
of
this
that
A superperfect
first
(so
of
branching
an arbitrary
structure,
the
(n > m a x ( a ) 1 I,
is a s u c c e s s o r
to p r u n e
to c o n f i n e sort.
is a s u b s e t
then each
(infinitely)
notion
simple
shows
Baumgartner's
can be partitioned
etc.,
the
argument
satisfies
of a particularly
structure
each
of
If
A tree
successor.
the c o n d i t i o n s
the
as
a node
branching
subtrees.
of
infinitely
branching.
are
G
subsets
branching;
infinitely
the u n i o n
all
finite
~.
proper
I1 =
of
a node with
is c a l l e d
in w h i c h
then
and
determines
forcing
tree
infinitely
has an
forcing
branch,
contain,
notion
node
of
the
successors
and extensions
set
subset
is c a l l e d
if e v e r y
trees
of
In s u c h a tree,
immediate
the n o t i o n
superperfect
a subtree
extension.
to t a k e At s t a g e
of
subsets
with
as a j - t u p l e
leave.
tree").
2 j-I
start
the s u b s e t
is
the
IX
1.
or
j > O, of
O's indexed
Any sequence
represents
an
At
leave
of
infinite
29
path
through
the tree,
a path whose
union
is the u n i o n
of a l l
the
taken
sets. If a s u p e r p e r f e c t we are given of w h i c h
another
tree
partition
is t h e u n i o n
superperfect
to t a k e
most
first
its
interval of
~
with
interval
the subtree
I k.
of
I0,II,"'
intervals
the
I's,
structure
of all
subinterval
structure
into
of o n e or m o r e
subtree
suffices
has
JO,Jl,---,
then
that
J0,J1,... meet
and
if each
tree
has a
Indeed,
nodes
that
We
refer
to s u c h p r u n i n g
each
of
lemmas
it
J in at n as merging
intervals. We now embark consistency Lemma
I.
[~]~,
of
If
then
Proof. with
~
In .
is,in
structure
the union
is
Jn
I's
that
are
J's
that
contain
node has
to a c h i e v e
Then
of
p"
have
comparable color.
have
with
inductively, the
for s o m e
a
the
n
th
Thus, of
p' b y m e r g i n g
as d e s c r i b e d of
X,
every so,
since
p
by
of a s u p e r P e r f e c t all
every
condition
of w h o s e
tree are branching
color.
the second
[]
it
segments
from
that
subtree
p"
intervals
from
initial
conclusion,
nodes
is a s u p e r p e r f e c t
to b u i l d ,
nodes
are
Jo,Jl,...,
the d e s i r e d
dense,
(n + I) st such.
shown
of
finite
Ik'S
be obtained
We have
branching
is if,
that
under
the
to b e a s u b s e t
infinitely
Try
a
W
If the
the s a m e
of
p"
holds.
have
fall
those
structure
forcing
nodes
can
Let
subset
of t h e s e
is c l o s e d
the
just
X.
is g r o u p w i s e
including
conclusion
then there
branching
~
dense
it to a c o n d i t i o n
many)
of
are
of
~
the u n i o n
this
2-colored,
Proof.
not
p" f o r c e s
p"
As
since
interval
clearly
an extension
2.
to t h e
X • ~.
Extend
(infinitely
them.
is a s u b s e t
genericity, Lemma
~ X
of s o m e
be given.
denote
u p to b u t
the
intervals
p
I 0 ~ X,
Let ~ X
is a s u b s e t
of s o m e
the
above.
up
model r a groupwise
IO,Ii,-..
X
We may assume
that
W
condition
modifications. one
the ground
the g e n e r i c
interval
leading
u < g.
Let any
contains
on a sequence
a superperfect
first
color.
node
a, all
color.
But
is s u p e r p e r f e c t
subtree
The only way infinitely
then
and homogeneous
of w h o s e
the c o n s t r u c t i o n
branching
the s u b t r e e
all
successors
of n o d e s for
the s e c o n d
30
Lemma
3.
[18]
generates
I_ff ~
a n u l t r a f i l t e r , in fact
forcing
extension.
Proof.
"In
the
fact
forcing
included
extension.
either
or
Successively (1) node
If
and
decides
if
(2) all
but
about
If
J.
model,
is
to w h i c h
in the g r o u n d
"A ~ ~".
We seek
is a n many
prune
then
the s u b t r e e this
infinitely immediate
the
successor
Call
{j e ~
I "j e A"
that
we
model.
So
in t h e
an extension
such
tree)
of a n
p"
p"
forces
a's
branching
successors
then,
a
have
that:
branching
comparable
opinion
node, of
to a r r a n g e
infinitely
of n o d e s
decision
is t h e o p i n i o n
successors (3)
All
Replacing
or none
A
with
about
a
j.
for e a c h
j e ~,
the s a m e o p i n i o n
by
of
of t h e s e t s
~ - A
of a l m o s t
all
immediate
a}. Aa
are
if n e c e s s a r y ,
in
~;
this uses
we may assume
Lemma
that all
2.
Aa
are
~. (4) As
i.e.,
p ~
included
has
interval
in
Aa
further
(5) (Remember enough
If
successor
(7)
to
If
a ~ ik
of
it w i t h
to The
that
can
f i x a set
branching
to a r r a n g e
node that
B e ~ a
the
is a b r a n c h i n g is f i n i t e ,
node,
of
p.
interval
so we
then
is a l m o s t
Merge
intervals,
structure,
say
just
B - A a C- ik+ I.
need
to t a k e
ik+ 1
large
ik.) is a b r a n c h i n g
node
n > ik+ I,
if
j e A.
and
(Again,
and
branching
node
is
a u (n)
j ~ A a n ik,
just
take
ik. ) first
that
satisfies:
B - Aa
the o p i n i o n
relative
p,
a ~ ik
that
we
for e v e r y
extend
relative
(6)
structure.
is a P - p o l n t ,
[0,i0),[i0,11),...,
has
in t h e g r o u n d
model)
because
Set
Aa =
in
lemma
an ultrafilter
(i.e.,
immediate
j e A.
a
the
in the e x t e n s i o n
generates
forces
p
j ~ max(a),
finitely
of
~
"B ~ ~ - A".
is a n
whether
rest of
is a P - p o i n t ~
then
in the s u p e r p e r f e c t
the
subset
(in t h e g r o u n d
extend
a
from
~
~
that
p
B e ~
"B ~ A"
of
that
So s u p p o s e
and a set
a P-point,
countable
subset
on proving
in the g r 0 u n d m o d e l ,
follows
any
the assumption
we concentrate
p
a P-point"
is p r o p e r ;
in a c o u n t a b l e
can apply
of
is a P - p o i n t
~ i 0.
ik+ 1
is a n
immediate
then
a u (n}
large
enough
31
Since
~
and still
is a n u l t r a f i l t e r , to b e c a l l e d
(of t h e
interval
at most
every
with
the same
from
the
Replace still
then
fourth
trunk as
B
minus
by
B
the proof
there would
exist
Let of
nodes
necessary,
branching by
< ik_l,
and
interval
structure).
the
J e A a.
Thus,
the nodes
that
p
still
fourth Since
minus
the
in
interval B
meets
to a c o n d i t i o n
p"
trunk are disjoint intervals.
of. c o u r s e
of
the proof
turn
CH,
a
the n e w
of
with
the
b
of
in
b
B
is
with
a u (n}
(6)
is,
As
max(a)
if Let
we have
for s o m e
j e B
n a ik+ 2
and
that of
j e A. This
of
J a ik
a u {n) p
But
a
< ik+ 2.
the definition
tells us
j ~ A.
j e B, q
k ik+ 2.
the subtree
forces
forces
J.
If not,
forcing
[ik_l,ik+2),
But
lemma,
has
consisting q
is a n
contradiction
o
of s u p e r p e r f e c t
superperfect
superperfect
p'
from
B - A a ~ i k. and
p"
max(b)
and
That
B ~ A.
of
Extending
has
of
of
a u {n) and
q
a,
iteration
iterate
Because
trunk
choice
j ~ A.
the
forces
containing
is d i s j o i n t
(5) •
condition
to
we
its
j e A a n ik+l,
completes
We now
By
p"
[ik_l,ik+2).
is a s u c c e s s o r
comparable this
interval
from
in t h e
that
extension
support.
every
< i 2.
and an extension
that
As
"last"
the opinion
of
by showing
be t h e
b
of
model
to a set,
the a d j a c e n t p';
predecessor
(7).)
(because
of
nodes
from
t r u n k of
are d~sjoint
we may assume
last
(in p)
can extend
and
j e B
[Ik,~k+l) p"
(This e x i s t s max(a)
B
at m o s t
no members
and whose
the
We complete
the
we
B
~.
"j ~ A".
so
p,
meeting
in
that meets
and has
interval,
intervals
all
be
B,
structure)
we can shrink
forcing
forcing
forcing.
~2
is p r o p e r ,
times
Over
with
Shelah's
a
countable
work
implies Lemma
4 [23,
~2-antichaln Lemma
5.
III.4.1,
Cardinals [23,
see also
condition,
Lemma
6
stage
of c o f i n a l l t y
Lemma
?.
and
V.4.4].
Every
a P-polnt,
Proof.
Use Lemma
Every
The
iteration
satisfies
the
real
are
preserved
by
the
in t h e
iteration
occurs
iteratlon. flrst
at a
D
in t h e g r o u n d
in the 3 and
235].
cofinalltles
~ ~.
P-point
in fact
9, p.
o
iterated
[9,
Section
mqdel
forclng 4].
generates extension. []
an ultrafllter,
[]
32
We are Theorem model
now
4 [7].
of CH,
Proof.
the
By L e m m a
For
7 and
the
rest
of
the
[23,III.3.2
of r e a l s
model
theorem have
the proof,
first
~
in the
[22]
that
in
M 2
has
unbounded then
#
~ n M
for an
given
~l-Closed
unbounded
that
each M .
of
of
the
see
model
~i
to f o r m Mu+1)
has
belongs
of
to all
M
for
to
itself.
Let
closed type
supersets the g i v e n
• n M
R~R
be
the set
By an
ideal,
and
closed
I ~ J
The associated
and
defined
of ~'s,
families.
dense
M
not
is g r o u p w i s e in
M 2
there
is an
these
real
W
only
as a n y
~1
~ < ~2
such
dense
family
(adjoined
restrictions,
Therefore,
family
dense".
then,
to a g r o u p w l s e
generic
to
hence
g > ~I"
Since
o
of n o n - d e c r e a s l n g
under
closed
mean binary
under
therefore
functions
a subset
growth
types,
relation,
of the p r e o r d e r e d in w h i c h
to g r o w t h
from
R/~R maxima.
(hence are
R = ~-{0}
that
also
is
A growth closed
pre-ordered
under
by
the
by
equivalence
diagram,
of
(pointwise)
doubling
f e I)(3 g e J)(¥ s u f f i c i e n t l y
partial d e s c r i p t i o n following
set
families
of
every
for a n
is a g r o u p w l s e
"~ n M
restricts
we s h a l l
ideal
Ideals,
(3 r e R / ~ ) ( V
equivalent
~
intersect,
in e a c h
6 M
from
that
~
If
I, the n e x t
236-237]
TYPES
downward
relation
~2
g = ~2"
a
the e x i s t e n c e
It f o l l o w s
9, pp.
has
unbounded
dense
families
by L e m m a
is a n o n e m p t y
addition).
in
over
g = ~2"
the m o d e l
iteration.
also
M
satisfies
groupwise
g ~ c = ~2' w e h a v e
GROWTH
but
sets
then,
~ < ~2"
~l-Closed
the g i v e n
But
4.
of
as a m e m b e r
If we are
in
set
times
implies
~2 ~l-closed
~2
u < g.
u = ~I a n d
CH
let us w r i t e
III.4.1;
final
iS i t e r a t e d
satisfies
of
u = ~I'
stages
and
the c o n s i s t e n c y
forcing
resulting
immediately
after
properness •
we
the
obtained
to p r o v e
If s u p e r p e r f e c t
then
of P - p o i n t s ,
set
in a p o s i t i o n
types.
underlining
I ~ J ~ I, set
of
large
is w r i t t e n
ideals
is u s e d
n)f(n)
is g i v e n
to i n d i c a t e
~ g(r(n)). I ~ J. by
the
ideals
M
33
???? = {f e ~ / a ~
[ (¥ n)
f(n)
~ n}
I = Uke ~ B k
{ l B k = {f e ~
I (¥ n)
f(n)
~ k}
l l BI =
{I}
i B0 The
only
ideals
in the d i a g r a m . for a n y to a n y
fixed ideal
L
=
that
that
contains
family.
in the d i a g r a m .
Every
The p r e o r d e r i n g in t h e i r
then
the n
study
with
maxk~ n
where
but
is
finitely
was
such
that
is not
If
I
~ g(n)}
an those
by GObel
of a b e l i a n
follows.
I
and Wald
groups.
The
is a g r o w t h
contains
L
is e q u i v a l e n t
to one of
introduced
classes
below
f(n)
L
but
types
the
type,
function
If(k)[ [I] of they
ei
has
many
eI
all
to
group
is
that
there
the a d d i t i v e
clearly
[I]-slender
[I]-slender
components
O.
G6bel
[J]-slender
four
are
contain
if e v e r y
at
therefore
at
least
that,
~
is a n u l t r a f i l t e r ,
if
function
of g r o w t h
proved
[15]
I (¥ n)
generally,
is e q u i v a l e n t
f:~ --~ Z
monotone;
G
indicated
ideal
is as
a subgroup
A group
those
{f ~ ~ 7 ~ More
an unbounded
theory
constitute
e i q Z ~,
.
of s l e n d e r n e s s
are
called
to
are
Borel
group
functions
~-~
~ L
g e ~/~
indicated
[14]
not
is e q u i v a l e n t
unbounded
unbounded
connection
are
group
equal
slenderness then
to
homomorphism and Wald
if a n d o n l y
least
four
0
Such
if
vectors
except
[14]
I ~ J.
inequivalent
ideal
subgroups
unit
el(i)
[I] --~ G
proved
classes. the
Z ~.
the s t a n d a r d
that They
growth
Specifically,
= i.
sends
all
every also
types they
and
showed
$4
I(~) generates strictly
= (f • R/'~R I
(nlf(n)
a growth
(its a d d i t i v e
between
MA,
they produced
open
problem
five,
could
of t h e these
whether
in
[7],
proof
they are
as
of a n u l t r a p o w e r that
all
the
proof
from
First, for
~)
of
this
union
that
NCF
[6] a b o u t
I(f(~))
if
of
the
of
We
this
for
chain
being
in its o w n
therefore
X
and
f(n)
~ n
and
a n
for all
the
the
in a n y b a s e
for all
f • ~/~
right,
observations.
(or
s n
part
modify
information;
X e ~
that
that
to t h e s t a t e m e n t
preliminary
next(X,n)
< ~b~R,
each
interest
it here.
three
the ordering
of t h e n o n s t a n d a r d
is e q u i v a l e n t
next(X,-)
X e ~,
of
n • X
for a l l
so
n • X
~
f(n)
~.
Indeed,
c a n be t a k e n
the
to b e
n,
then
function
r(n)
r
= f(n)
I(~)
required
+ I
~ f(next(X,n))
next(X,--) Third,
Indeed,
if
is m a j o r i z e d
every
finitely
many
t h e m all. because,
ideal
f • (~/~)
the strong
are
Then if
by
then
is
if
infinite),
then
for s o m e u l t r a f i l t e r > g(n))
(i.e.,
I f(n)
by
> g(n))
r(n) • ~,
for
Z
= f(n)
g(n)
~ g(next(X,n))
is m a J o r l z e d
by
~ f(next(X,n)) next(f(X),--)
~ next(f(X),
o r.
~.
g • J
intersections
is a n u l t r a f i l t e r
as witnessed (n
o r.
(nlf(n)
property
so there
X =
+ i)
~ I(~)
the s e t s
intersection
J ~ I(f(~)),
g • J,
next(f(X),-)
J < ~/~ - J
finite
~ next(f(X),f(n)
of
containing + I,
so
f(X)
f(n)
+ I),
and
g
by
because,
then
next(X,n)
have
f E ~/~
for a n y u l t r a f i l t r
the d e f i n i t i o n
so
Just
(for e x a m p l e
ideals
of c h a i n s ,
the r e s t
Indeed,
if
or e v e n
solved
was part
information of all
is of
of
following
I(~). and
part
using
the
below,
from
completion
are equivalent) a small
was
an
f ~ next(X,-). Second,
so
information
some
and
functions
• I(~),
presented
in t h e o r d e r i n g
~,
to a v o i d
generate
next(X,--) then
of
problem
Assuming
it r e m a i n e d
g.
the disjoint
requires the
types,
or the D e d e k i n d
only
[7]
modification
growth
some
Though
I(~)'s
prove
inequivalent
the s o l u t i o n ,
cofinal
ordered
but
This
lies
that
and R/~R.
types,
in ZFC alone.
[7] u s e d
+I(~))
to L)
growth
for d e f i n i n g
a singleton
we shall
this many
I(~). are
closure,
is e q u i v a l e n t
inequivalent
and
in
ideals ideals
either
2c
motivation
The
(which
be produced
negatively original
type +L
~ n) • ~)
e f(~)
35
Theorem R/~
5 [7].
are
Proof. show
!i < ~,
t h e n all
F i x an u l t r a f l l t e r that,
B e S, ~B =
if
J
T
with
(X e [~]~
If all fewer
that,
the
is a n y
sufficiently next(B,--)
g
B • S,
large
~ J,
Suppose, certain
ideal,
betwee n
L
and
of
cardinallty
J • L
or
< g. We
J a I(T).
For
z,
large
z)
~ f(next(X,z))}.
are groupwlse
is
f ~ J
next(B,z)
dense,
a common
then,
member
such
that,
by
for,
there
This
means
for all
~ f(next(X,z));
majorlzed
since
X.
in o t h e r
where
words,
r = next(X,-).
as d e s i r e d .
B e S.
Since there
[al,ai+l),
no
necessary,
we assume
J
•
then
they have
there
therefore,
modifications,
that
~B
of them,
is e v e n t u a l l y
I(~)
a base
I (3 f • J)(V s u f f i c i e n t l y
families
than
for e a c h
Thus,
strictly
let
next(B,z)
are
ideals
eq u i v a l e n t .
first
each
If
that ~B
must
infinite
is c l e a r l y
union
to be g r o u p w l s e
closed
of w h i c h
each
b y the
value
fails
be a p a r t i t i o n
that
is d o m i n a t e d
~B
constant
with
Suppose,
for a c o n t r a d i c t i o n ,
ai+3;
function
B.
J ~ L,
f • J
and
finite
intervals
We shall
on e a c h
that
for a
intervals
Merging
meets
some
subsets
into
~B"
which,
means
that
w
is in
[al,ai+l)
this
under
of
dense
if
show
[ai,ai+l),
is
as d e s i r e d .
were
not
so d o m i n a t e d .
Then X = U an
{ [ a i + l , a ~ + 2)
infinite
witness z, s a y
union
f, in
i
with
f(n)
with
> a i + 3.
X • ~B' This
ideals
J
some
n • [ai,ai+1),
intervals,
to our let
j ~ i+1,
next(B,z) so
of o u r
contrary [a~,aj+l),
some
I For
is n e v e r t h e l e s s of
the
there
since
is B
< a ~ + 2 ~ ai+ 3 < f(n)
So
in
~B'
with
Indeed,
for a n y
x • [ai+l,ai+2)
(by d e f i n i t i o n meets
> ai+3),
intervals.
x = next(X,z).
and
Then,
choice
f(n)
each
of X)
of our
for
n E [al,ai+l)
intervals,
~ f(x)
= f(next(X,z)),
J ~ 5
or
as c l a i m e d .
completes and
the p r o o f
that
for a n y u l t r a f i l t e r
~
J ~ I(~),
generated
by fewer
for all than
g
sets. Now suppose
J ~ L
ultrafilter
generated
preliminary
remark,
and
J < R/~R.
by f e w e r let
~
than
g
Let
Y
still
sets,
and,
be an u l t r a f i l t e r
with
by
be a n the
third
J ~ I(~).
Since
36
u < g,
we
Section
have
i.
function
FD
So
with
one-to-one
by
let f(~)
g,
may
Replacing
assume
that
f
f(n) of
I(f(~))
by
the
second
preliminary
= I(f(r))
as
f(~)
I(Z)
as
f(Z)
J
as
Z
is g e n e r a t e d
by
we
have
the
fact
two
that
neither
depend
equivalent, It
steps,
J,
in
[7],
additive
in
gof
for
for
all
a suitable
n.
Then
we
have
remark
is g e n e r a t e d
invoked
nor
this
J
is
shows
by
fewer
fewer
than
first
~ L°)
that
all
than g
part
sets
sets.
of
Thus,
such
9
the
proof
J ~ I(Z).
ideals
J
and
Since
are
o
is s h o w n
but
out
= f(Z)
I(Z)
on
as p o i n t e d
non-decreasing
with
choice
last
NCF,
a n
our
didn't
I(~)
therefore
a finite-to-one
by
the
the Y
3 and be
= f(T) .
we
J ~ I(~)
(At
Theorem
f:~ ---~ ~
for
filters
closures,
consequence
that
that
the
filter
but
Theorem
there
dichotomy 3 was
implications
in
considering
that the
are
are
used
in
ideals
not
four
the
of
Theorem
(defined
5,
inequivalent
(Thus, proof
I(~)
ultrafilters)
conclusion only
principle.
the
u < g ----~ A l l
by
9
of
Theorem
or
their
or
the
growth
5.)
immediate
types,
5 subsumes
Theorem
like
For
implies
Theorem
all
3,
the
chain ideals
,, ~ O n l y
four
strictly
between
inequivalent
L
growth
and
~/ ~
are
equivalent
types
FD NCF, the
converses
5.
ANOTHER The
are
open
NOTION
following
in a l l
groupwise (a,X)
family The
of
a
pairwise
condition
(b,Y) of
Y
are
such
in
finite
of
X.
(a,X)
the
unions
of
W
of
subsets is
a ~ b members
of
ground
subset
Accordingly, that
is d e s i g n e d
a subset
finite
disjoint
of
forcing
families is a
meaning"
members
of
possible,
dense
of
members
as
where
"intended
union
FORCING
notion
straightforwardly
pair
OF
problems.
and ~
that
a ~ W
an
extension
and of
that
model. ~
of
to a d j o i n , ~
such
that
X.
The
as
has
A
supersets
condition
X
is a n
disjoint
from
and
W - a
of
(a,X)
b - a set
W
and
is a
infinite a.
is a is a all
corresponding
37
to a g e n e r i c
set
of c o n d i t i o n s
the conditions
in t h e g e n e r i c
forces
and
"a ~ W
It is e a s y the s p e c i a l
W - a
to s e e
form
(a,
m a x ( x k)
< min(xk+l)
confine
attention
This step
~,
is a u n i o n adJolnts
If
G
can
of
sort
belong
to
step
Since
both
steps
by Mater
first
of
of
of
~ of
for
X
(a,X) intended. to o n e
of
and
convenience,
iteration.
in
[4]
finite
that
first
finite
member
this
called
of
Y
forcing
a stable
nonempty
under
The
disjoint
if e v e r y
(there
the c l o s u r e s ,
X
subsets
of
finite unions,
~.
of t h e
~.
under
conditions finite
the
two
is c o u n t a b l y condition;
iteration
I shall
Mater
antlchain
first
the
[17],
quotient)
the same
of
at o u r
of p a i r w l s e
shown
is to f o r c e w i t h
the c l o s u r e
consideration, The
families
a base
< min(XO)
as a t w o - s t e p
the s e t
then
as
(a,X)
unions
as above,
is r e q u i r e d
to
~.
considered under
set,
that
X",
of
conditions.
It w a s
on
components
can be extended
So w e may,
of u l t r a f i l t e r
constitute
The second that
X.
of
max(a)
is a n e x t e n s i o n
ultrafilter)
is a g e n e r i c
except
k.
infinite
of m e m b e r s
a special
G
where
first
to c h e c k
of m e m b e r s
condition
be d e c o m p o s e d
Y
of
every
for a l l
where
ordered-union
members
that
of t h e
it is e a s y
to s u c h n o r m a l i z e d
forcing
of
set;
is a u n i o n
{ X k l k e ~}),
is to f o r c e w i t h
subsets
is the u n i o n
were,
as
their
composite,
far as
I know,
first
the f o r c i n g
now
forcing. forcing
closed.
in fact,
component
call
are
notions
The
(or r a t h e r
second
satisfies
it is o - c e n t e r e d compatible.
its s e p a r a t i v e the
countable
since
conditions
wlth
It f o l l o w s
that Mater
forcing
is p r o p e r . If is a n y
~
is a g r o u p w i s e
condition,
~.
Then
(a,Y)
and
therefore,
then
dense
X
has
since
countable-support
after
that
a model
The forcing
We
where
a P-point
(one-step)
forcing.
It f o l l o w s ,
thus
under
just as
iteration g = ~2"
forcing
and
have
another
model
can be clarified
Mater
model
and
whose
union
finite modifications,
model
therefore for
forcing
and
I have
generates also
(a,X) is in
"W - a ~ U Y e ~"
for s u p e r p e r f e c t of M a t e r
"W
forcing,
has that
over a model
of
(independently)
an ultrafilter
after
iterated
Mater
u < g.
forcing
by considering
Y
forcing
Laflamme
in the g r o u n d
between
subset
(a,X)
Mater
similarity
in the ground
infinite of
is c l o s e d
an ~2-step
produces
~".
~
in
GCH
an
is a n e x t e n s i o n
a superset
verified
family
and Miller's
superperfect
the a n t h r o p o m o r p h i c
description
38
of s u p e r p e r f e c t description specified 2 j-l,
subset
initial
segments
branching
above
the
first
than
e
OTHER
|
those
already
of
(a,X)
a u y~ a u y
the branches the same
where
y
is a
themselves but
as
has as nodes
are the
succinctly
of M a t e r
forcing
(selective)
described
of M a t h i a s
ultrafilter
forcing, on
w,
and
it.
INVARIANTS cardinal
invarlants
of
the c o n t i n u u m ,
defined
in S e c t i o n
2, a n d w e e x t e n d
inequalities
in S e c t i o n
2 to
two sets
of
cardinality
infinite in the
~; h e r e
the
family
and
from
the
family
have
of a n y
subsets family
include
the splitting
infinite
number,
the Hasse
these
maximal
"almost
almost
disjoint"
means
intersection. independent
means
that any
finitely
of a n y
finitely
many
family
many
other
sets
sets
intersection.
is the s m a l l e s t
family
~ ~ ~(~);
here
infinite
A ~ e,
there
S e Y
is
infinite
~; h e r e
of a n y m a x i m a l
"independent"
the complements an
of
have a finite
cardinality
splitting
are
to
than Matet
invariants.
from
s,
in w h i c h
decomposition
a
the s t a n d a r d
is t h e s m a l l e s t
of subsets
adjoin
CARDINAL
here
family
that every
decomposition
through
is the s m a l l e s t
disjoint
form
rather
A normalized
essentially
c a n be r o u g h l y
to a w e l l - k n o w n
of p r o v a b l e
additional
the
the s e t s
If that
Mathias forcing. Laver forcing
two-step
a real
We define other
=
generically
APPENDIX:
diagram
of X;
tree
node are
3.
only one
decisions)
forcing.
corresponding
The situation
is a n a l o g o u s
then shoot
of
has
b y the p r o p o r t i o n
that
namely
tree
of s e t s
Mater forcing Miller forcing Notice
The
in S e c t i o n
interval
the previous
to M a t e r
branching
of m e m b e r s
nodes.
summarized
jth
as a superperfect
infinitely
union
structure
the
of
is e q u i v a l e n t
from any other.
finite
interval
so that
can be viewed
from any one those
with
(independent
the result
condition
the
trees
is m o d i f i e d
"splitting" such
that
cardinallty means
that,
both
A n S
of a n y for e v e r y and
A - S
infinite. r
is t h e s m a l l e s t
here
"unspllttable"
such
that
R n A
cardlnallty
means
and
that,
R - A
of a n y u n s p l i t t a b l e
for e v e r y
are not both
A ~ w,
there
infinite.
f a m i l y ~ ~ [e]~; is
R •
39
p every A
is the s m a l l e s t finite
subfamily
s u c h that
A - B
is d e f i n e d inclusion These
cardinallty
modulo
has an infinite
is finite like
finite
cardinals
p
for all
except
in ZFC)
diagram.
I thank Peter
~ ~ Y(~)
intersection
but
such
there
that
is no set
8 e ~.
that
~
must
be l i n e a r l y
ordered
by
sets.
and the ones d e f i n e d
(provably
w h i c h was m i s s i n g
the
of any family
inequalities Nyikos
in S e c t i o n
indicated
for p o i n t i n g
from the d i a g r a m
in the out
the
2 satisfy following
Hasse
inequality
~ s i,
at STACY.
\!/ 9
i I
I P
i
REFERENCES 1,
B. Balcar, N covered
J. Pelant, by n o w h e r e
and P. Simon, The space d e n s e sets, Fund. Math.
2.
J. B a u m g a r t n e r , A.R.D. Mathias,
3.
D. Bellamy, A n o n - m e t r l c 38 (1971) 15-20.
4.
A. Blass, U l t r a f i l t e r s r e l a t e d to H i n d m a n ' s finite u n i o n s t h e o r e m and its e x t e n s i o n s , in Logic and C o m b i n a t o r ! c ~, ed. S. Simpson, C o n t e m p o r a r y M a t h e m a t i c s 65 (1987) 89-124.
5.
, Near c o h e r e n c e of filters, I: Coflnal e q u i v a l e n c e m o d e l s of a r i t h m e t i c , N o t r e Dame J. F o r m a l Logic 27 (1986) 579-591.
I t e r a t e d forcing, L o n d o n Math. Soc.
of u l t r a f i l t e r s on 110 (1980) 11-24.
in S u r v e y s in Set Theory, ed. L e c t u r e N o t e s 87, 1983, pp. 1-59.
indecomposable
continuum,
Duke Math.
of
J.
40
6.
, Near c o h e r e n c e of filters, II: A p p l i c a t i o n s to o p e r a t o r ideals, the S t o n e - C e c h r e m a i n d e r of a half-line, order ideals of sequences, and s l e n d e r n e s s of groups, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 300 (1987) 557-581.
7.
and C. Laflamme, C o n s i s t e n c y results about filters and the number of i n e q u i v a l e n t g r o w t h types, to appear in J. S y m b o l i c Logic.
8.
and S. Shelah, to appear.
9.
,
U!trafilters
w i t h small
, There may be simple
the R u d i n - K e i s l e r order may be d o w n w a r d Logic 83 (1987) 213-243. i0.
, consistency
11.
proof,
, Near coherence to appear.
and
P
dlr~cted,
of filters,
and G. Weiss, A c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n ideals, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc.
operator
P
generating
points
An~.
III:
sets, and
Pure Appl.
A simplified
and sum d e c o m p o s i t i o n 246 (1978) 407-417.
12.
A. Brown, C. Pearcy, and N. Salinas, Ideals of compact on H l l b e r t space, M i c h i g a n Math. J. 19 (1971) 373-384.
13.
E. van Douwen, The integers and topology, in H a n d b o o k of SetT h e o r e t i c Topology, ed. K. K u n e n and J. Vaughan, N o r t h - H o l l a n d , 1984, pp. 111-167.
14.
R. Gbbel and B. Wald, W a c h s t u m s t y p e n S y m p o s i a Math. 23 (1979) 201-239.
15. certain
, slender
und s c h l a n k e
operators
Sruppen,
, M a r t i n ' s a x i o m implies the e x i s t e n c e groups, Math. Z. 172 (1980) 107-121.
of
16.
J. Ketonen, On the e x i s t e n c e of P - p o i n t s in the S t o n e - C e c h c o m p a c t i f i c a t i o n of integers, Fund. Math. 92 (1976) 91-94. Some
filters
17.
P. Mater,
18.
A. Miller, R a t i o n a l perfect set forcing, in A x i o m a t i c Set Theory, ed. J. B a u m g a r t n e r , D.A. Martin, and S. Shelah, C o n t e m p o r a r y M a t h e m a t i c s 31 (1964) 143-159.
19.
J. M i d o d u s z e w s k i , On c o m p o s a n t s of ~R-R, Proc. Conf. T o p o l o q y Measure, I (Zinnowitz), ed. J. Flachsmeyer, Z. Frolik, and F. Terpe, E r n s t - M o r i t z - A r n d t - U n i v e r s i t ~ t zu Grelfwald, 1978, 257-283.
20. Cs~sz~r,
Colloq.
of partitions,
of
to appear.
and
An a p p r o a c h to ~R\R, in Topology, ed. A. Math. Soc. J~nos Bolyai 23 (1980) 853-854.
21.
M.E. Rudln, C o m p o s a n t s and ~N, Proc. General T o p l o g y 1970, pp. 117-119.
22.
W. Rudln, H o m o g e n e i t y p r o b l e m s in the theory of Cech c o m p a c t l f i cations, Duke Math. J. 23 (1956) 409-419.
23.
S. Shelah, Proper Forcing, S p r l n g e r - V e r l a g 1982.
24.
R.C. Solomon, F a m i l i e s 27 ( 1 9 7 7 ) 5 5 6 - 5 5 9 .
25.
E. S p e c k e r , Additive Gruppen Math. 9 (1950) 131-140.
Lecture
of sets and
von
Washington
Notes
Univ.
in M a t h e m a t i c s
functions,
FoJgen
State
ganzer
940,
Czechoslovak
Zahlen,
Conf.
Math.
Portugal.
J.
A STRUCTURE THEORY FOR IDEALS ON P
TOWARDS
DONNA M. CARR AND
k K
DONALD H. PELLETIER 1
Introduction In
their
extended
now
much
classic
of
the
uncountable cardinal Jech (K, ~
(e.g.
ultrafilter
over
for
P A
A
measurable),
that
not
does
there
have
the
is
a
partition
K
property.
Thus
Rowbottom's
this
result.
If
Proof.
Assume
f : [X] 2< --> 2. A
xl
that
over
K
is
= i}.
A ~ U. xl
Moreover,
{X ~ X : A
f[[H]~]
of
and every
P A.
Notice
then
X ~ U,
that
either
and for
x ~ X,
that
let
pick
each
{x ~ X : A
w.l.o.g,
and
Further,
for
every
X ~ (U) 2. < U
be
X ~ U i e 2,
either
A
set
xO
~ U} ~ U
xO B = {x ~ X : A
~ U or
xO
a and
or else
~ U} ~ U,
by
ifa~B
ao
Xa = IPKA Now set
P A generalization
A-supereompact, P A K
x E X
~ U} ~ U. Assume xl and then define (Xa : a E P A) A
a nice
A-supercompact,
over
each
= {y g X : f(x,y)
else
is
U
ultrafilter For
not yield
our notion does:
~
A-supercompact ultrafilter
A-supercompact
does
However,
Theorem.
1.10
property
otherwise. H = B n A A,
bijection
hence
x
{x ~ P X : lxl X K
show that m
{ x e PKA :
(V~ ~ x ) ( ~ - l ( ~ )
< x)} , {x ~ PKA : ~[PK x] ~ x} ~ I .
~ CFKA g I ,
by
Suppose
so
it
remains
to
obtain
way
of
contradiction
that
x
{ x ~ PKA : ~ [ P K x ] g X} ~ I .
Then
x
X = {X ~ P A : ~ [ P
X] ~ x } = { X ~ PKA :
(3y < x)(~(y)
~ x)}
~ I +"
For each
x
x ~ X,
pick
to o b t a i n
Yx < x
y ~ PKA
(¥x ~ Y)(~(y) ~ x) Generic
such that such that
ultrapowers
and then use s t r o n g n o r m a l i t y
Y = {x ~ X : Yx = Y} ~ i +"
thereby c o n t r a d i c t i n g
PMA
where
But
note
that
Y ~ i+ ~ i~A" +
of a transitive
u l t r a f i l t e r over
I-generic
~(yx ) ~ x,
model I
M
[]
of
is (in M) a
ZFC
modulo
an
s t r o n g l y normal,
K
non-principal,
K-complete
ideal
over
F A
will
be studied
in a sequel
to
this p a p e r .
2.
Selective,
I~ey
and quasinormal
ideals
I
over an uncountable
on P A K
Recall
that an ideal
regular cardinal
~
is
f : K --) ~
is an
said to be (i) a A ~ I•
p-point
such that
iff for every
I-small function
(¥~ ~ K)(NA a f-1 [{~}]] < K).
there
47
q-point
(ii) a
iff
(¥~ • K)(If-1[{~}]J (iii) selective A • I"
for
every
< K), there is an
iff for every
on which
f : K --~ K
f
is
A • I"
with
on w h i c h
I-small f u n c t i o n
one-one,
i.e.
iff
the
I
f
property is
one-one.
f : K --> K is beth a
that
there
is an
p-polnt
and a
q-point. (iv) Ramsey
iff
for
every
A ~ (I x I)',
where
= {X g K x K : {~ • K : {~ • K : (~,~) • X} • I +} • I},
I x I
there
is
an
there
is
summarized
in
o
H • I
such that
(H x H) n {(~,~) • K x K : ~ < ~} g A.
(v) quasinormal
iff for every
K-sequence
(X
: ~ < K) • KI
o
an
A • I
such that V(X
Kunen
A) = {~ • K :
: ~ •
(see
[B])
and Weglorz
(3m • ~ n A)(~ • X )} • I.
[W] established
the
facts
the following theorem. 2.1 T h e o r e m Let
(I)
I
is
normal
{infCf-%[{~}])
(2) If (3)
I
I
I
: ~ •
be an ideal over an uncountable regular cardinal
iff
for
every
l-small
function
K} • I'.
iS normal,
is selective
then iff
Our first objective
I I
is selective. is Ramsey
if£
I
is quasinormal.
in this section is to provide a
P k
analogue of
K
Weglorz's prove
c r i t e r i o n for n o r m a l i t y (2.1(1) above).
that
I-s.an
an ideal
function
Z • PKA, Our
I f :
over
~
P A
-~
is
~x,
In particular,
strongly normal
U~y z : z • ~x~
iff
• I"
result.
is a To
PKA
obtain
version the
of
reverse
Pelletier's
implication
proof
we
need
for every
where
Yz = {y • f-l[{z}] : (Vx < y)(f(x) ~ f(y) = z)}
proof
we shall
for
(2.3
in
[P]
the
of
each
below). Weglorz's
following
lemma
which is interesting in its own right. 2.2
Lemma.
Ig(x) t >
we' d
have
IgCg(x))l
Cn = {x • B : nx = n}. E = U{C2n : n ~ ~}.
an
> ....
For
Further,
Clearly
infinite
B
set
descending
each
n •
sequence ~,
D = U{C2n÷1 : n • ca}
is the disjoint
u n i o n of
D and E.
set
and Note
48
(Vn ~ (a)(Vx ~ C ) ( g ( x ) (~ C
that
n
g~'E : E --> (P ~CA - E). positive
Moreover,
Thus
at
g D : D --~ CPKA - D)
least
one
of
D
or
E
and
must
have []
measure.
Notice the
).
n-1
above
that
the
result
(Vx ~ B ) ( f ( x ) 2.3
(P A,c)
for
version
functions
of the a b o v e
d o e s not y i e l d
argument
f : B ---> P A
with
the
property
that
the
following
¢ x).
For
Theorem.
any
ideal
I
PKA,
over
are
equivalent: (i) I is (ii) for
strongly every
normal,
A ~ i÷
and
I-small
every
function
f : A --gPKA,
e
U(Yz : z ~ PKA} ~ (I[A)
where
Y
~ f(y) = z)}
= (y ~ f-i[{z}]
: (~x < y)(f(x)
for
each and
z ~ PKA,
IIA
is
the
ideal
z
{X ~ P A : X ~ A ~ I}, (iii) for
every
and function
I-small
f : P A --9 P A,
U{7
~
where for every
Y
z ~ PKA,
is defined
: z ~ P A} ~ I z
as in (ii) above.
z
Proof.
(ii)
It
is c l e a r
and ( i i i )
an
(ii)
implies
(iii).
This
leaves
Suppose
I-small
that
function
I
is
strongly
f : A --~ P k.
Set
prove
that
(PKA
is
as
hence
end,
notice
that
required.
To
this
: y ~ PKA}
and
I
is s t r o n g l y
g
:
y
that F-~ x
y
for ,
y
~
A - Z.
normal,
each A
-
Z
Because
it n o w
follows
A - Z e I. (iii)
A ~ I÷
--9 (i)
and
Suppose
an
g = f u id~(PKA
- A).
A n B ~ I ÷,
s u c h that It is c l e a r
that
I-small
h
g~C is
g
that
not
is
strongly
I-small,
I-small,
so b y
~ gCy))}
l e m m a 2 . 2 to
: (Vx < y ) ( h ( y ) If
Choose
an
f : A --9 P A.
Let
(iii), : z ~ P k} ~ I'.
gtA n B Define
so we m a y use
Z' ~ P k - C:
normal.
function
: C --) (P k - C).
Z" = U { { y ~ h-i[{z}] But n o w n o t i c e
is
: (Vx < y ) C g C x )
so we m a y a p p l y
C ~ I÷ a n d that
I
~} have disjoint closures ( such a sequence is called a
{x~:~ c . b) PFA implies t h a t if X is compact separable with t -- w then X has cardinality at most c .
57 A RELATED QUESTION. T h e r e is a related question asked by the a u t h o r and independently by van Douwen . Is every (first countable) initially w l - c o m p a c t space of countable tightness compact? A space is said to be initially wl-compact if every open cover of cardinality at m o s t wl has a finite subcover. A space is initially w l - c o m p a c t iff every subset of cardinality at m o s t wl has a complete accumulation point ( i.e. a point whose every neighbourhood hits the set in full size). Both van Douwen a n d the author have shown t h a t the answer is yes if C H holds a n d very recently Fremlin and Nyikos have shown t h a t the answer is yes if P F A is assumed. A ~no ~ answer is not yet known to be consistent. 3. F O R C I N G
PRELIMINARIES
Cohen reals are added to a model by forcing with a poset of the f o r m Fn(I, 2) = ( p C I × 2 : p is a finite function} ordered by reverse inclusion. An antichain of a poset P is a set of pairwise incompatible e l e m e n t s . A poset is said to be ccc if every antichain of P is countable . W h e n the context is clear we shall use elements of V as n a m e s for themselves in a forcing sentence. Furthermore if G is P-generic over V and A C X is in V[G] while X E V then we shall assume t h a t a n a m e for A , say A , is a subset of X×Pandforeach xEX ( p E P : (x,p) E ,4} is an antichain. Recall t h a t i f P i s e c c , X E V , G i s P-generic over V and A E V[G] is a countable subset of X t h e n there is a countable n a m e for A . REMARK: Suppose t h a t 0 and X are Ostaszewski's space and Fedorcuk's space respectively. If G is Fn(I, 2)-generic over V then we m a y ask w h a t becomes of 0 and X in V[G] . It is not difficult to see t h a t 0 remains countably c o m p a c t and locally c o m p a c t (because it is scattered) and it has been shown t h a t it remains hereditarily separable . Therefore this provides an example in V[G] of a c o m p a c t non-sequential space with countable tightness in which there is a point to which no sequence converges. Recall t h a t Fedorcuk's space is a c o m p a c t subspace of 2 ~1 - but we m a y view it as the Stone space of a certain Boolean algebra. We are then iterested in the Stone space of the s a m e algebra in V[G] . S. Todor6evid has pointed out to the author t h a t it is straightforward to check t h a t any property K forcing (in particular Cohen forcing) will preserve the fact t h a t the Stone space of a Boolean algebra is hereditary separable. This provides an example in VIG ] of a separable space of countable tightness of cardinality 2 wl regardless of the size of the continuum. However the resulting space will have converging sequences. Indeed each Knew" point will be the limit of a sequence of ~old" points. In addition, Todor~evid has noticed t h a t (under very general circumstances) the Stone space will acquire points of first countability. 4. E L E M E N T A R Y
SUBMODELS
AND
FORCING
In the next section we shall frequently be discussing a set X , a Fn(I, 2)-name ~ for a topology on X and occasionally some Fn(I, 2)-name of another subset of the power set of X , say y . T h e r e is some cardinal 0 large enough so t h a t any sentence we wish to discuss a b o u t these objects will be absolute for H($) ( i.e. they hold in H(0) iff they hold
58 in V ) . We shall always assume without mention that 0 is this large enough cardinal. F u r t h e r m o r e , when we speak of an elementary submodel we shall mean an elementary submodel of this H(0) and t h a t the X , # (and perhaps y ) under discussion are in the submodel. Recall t h a t M is an elementary submodel of H(0) iff for each finite sequence < r n l , . . . ,rnn > of elements of M and any formula of set theory ~ ( v l , . . . ,vn)
M ~ ~t~Cml, ... , r~rt )
i~
HC0) ~ ~ o ( ~ i , . . . , Tc~rt)
(and by our assumption on 0 iff V ~ ~ ( m l , . . . . m,~) providing the mi's are things we are going to talk about). When we investigate an elementary submodel M we are interested in the following. From X , ÷ and y we define new names which are in a sense the restriction of these names to M . We then use elementarity to deduce what properties the objects n a m e d by these new names will have in the extension obtained by forcing with P N M . Finally we are then interested in the relationship of this object to the space X in the final extension. If G is P-generic over V we can define, in V[G] , the set M[G] by (val(fi,,G) : E M } . If P is ccc (or if M , G are assumed to have additional properties) it can be shown t h a t M[G] is an elementary submodel of H(6) v[G] (for example see [Sh]) . To best exploit this relationship we use the fact that M[G] can often be (essentially) obtained by just forcing with P ;3 M . Indeed, suppose we are given X a set , P a forcing poset and y a P - n a m e such t h a t 11t-p y C P ( X ) . Let M be an elementary submodel and define X M = X A M and P M ~- P f'3 M . For each P - n a m e 12 E M such t h a t l II-P 12 C X , we can define a PM-name 12M so that, for each p, x E M p l~-p~ x E 12M
iff
p I~-p x • 12.
Indeed, for each x E X M , let Ax be any antichain which is maximal with respect to being a subset of {p e P M : P II-P x E 12} • Then define 12M to be the name U{ { x } × A z : x C X M } • In fact, since we are assuming that we are only working with "nice" names we can (by elementarity) define YM to simply be Y M M . Note t h a t if P is t e e , we have t h a t 1 It-p 12 M M = 12M • Now of course we define YM , a P M - n a m e , such t h a t 1 ]~-pu YM : {12M: 12 e M and 1 ]~-p 12 e y } . In this f a s h i o n , we have, for example, t h a t if 1 ]F-p (< X, ~ >
is a regular topological space )
then 1 I~-p~ (< X M , cM >
is a base for a regular topological space) .
We will often be careless in clistinguishing between a topology and a base for a topology. If we assume now t h a t P is ccc and that G is P-generic over V then it follows t h a t V[GI ~
val(?, G) n M
=- valC12M, G A M ) = valC12M, G ) .
Notice then t h a t we also have that, in V[G], the topology induced on X M by GNM) is the same as that induced by val(~,G) t3M[G] .
val(~M,
59 Now suppose we make t h e additional assumption on M , t h a t M ~' c M (i.e. that M is closed under w-sequences) . Recall that the Lowenheim Skolem theorems give us t h a t for any countable set A e H(0) and any set B E H(0) with IBI _< c there are elementary submodels of H(8) M A and M B such that [MA[ = w , [MB[ = c , A C M A , B C M B and MB is closed under w-sequences. If M is closed under w-sequences and P E M is ccc then P n M is completely embedded in P (i.e. every maximal antichain of P n M is maximal in P ) hence if G is P-generic over V then G MM is PM-generic over V as well • Therefore, in this case, V[G AM] is obtained by forcing over V by the poset PM • Yet another consequence of the fact that P is ccc and M is closed under w-sequences is that we get a kind of w-absoluteness for M . For example, suppose that 1 I~-p y is a countably complete filter on X , then we get 1 t~-pM Y M is a countably complete filter on X M • This is almost like saying that, in V[G AM] , the model M[G] is closed under w-sequences. Henceforth when we say "by w-absoluteness" , we shall mean "since M w C M and M is an elementary submodel of H(8)" . As indicated above we shall be interested in < X M ,val(#M ,GAM) > in both models , V[GAM] and V[G] (we are still assuming M is closed under w-sequences) . One thing to be careful of is that , in general, val(#M ,G) is a strictly weaker topology than that induced on X M by val(#,G) . However we shall make frequent appeals to w-absoluteness to overcome this. For example , if A,/~ are both countable names i n M and I[[-PMcl÷~AAcl÷~/~ # ( = ) 0 , t h e n l[F-pcl÷Ancl~/~ (=)9 where the second pair of closures are with respect to the larger topology. 5. MAIN RESULTS Let us begin by considering initially wl -compact spaces of countable tightness. THEOREM 5 . 1 . If P is a ccc poser , 1 I ~ P < X , ~" > iS initially wl -compact and t = w , and if M is an elementary submodel of H(O) closed under w-sequences , then 1 [k-p~ < X M , 7"M ~> ha8 countable tightness. PROOF: Suppose that pI~-v~< X M ,~M > does not have countable tightness. By w-absolutenss, we know that p [F-< X M , ~M > is countably compact. Therefore, by Arhangel'skii's theorem we may choose PM-names { ~a : s < wl ) so that each x~ E M and p i k p M { ~ : s < w l } f o r m a f r e e s e q u e n c e . But now, since l[F-v < X , ~ :> is initially wl-compact, we may choose a condition q E P with q < p and some x E X so that qil- z is a complete accumulation point o f ( ~ a : s < wl } • But now, by countable tightness and the fact t h a t P is ccc we may choose s o < s l < wl so t h a t qIk x E cl~{ ~ : fl < s0 } N cl÷{ ~ : a0 < fl < a l } . This contradicts, by w-absoluteness, t h a t p l F - c l ÷ ~ { ~ : /~<so) M cl÷~(~ : s0 is an initially wl -compact space with countable tightness and ~r is a countably complete filter on the closed subsets of X . If H E ~r+ (i.e. H n F # 9 for each F E ~r ) then clH' E ~r+ for some countab/e H I C H . PROOF: Suppose t h a t H is a counterexample and choose by recursion on s < wl ha E Hnn( F~ : /~ < s ) a n d F ~ E ~r so that F a N c l { h~ : /~ < a} = 9 . But now by countable tightness F = Uz is completely regular) , we m a y choose a p E P and a P - n a m e ] such t h a t p ]F-p ] is a continuous function from < X, # > into the unit interval such t h a t ]*-'(0)M A and ] ' - ( 1 ) n . 4 are u n c o u n t a b l e . For each a E X , choose (if possible) Pa E P such t h a t Pa < P and Pa II- (a E f~ and ](a) = 1) . Let B = {a E X M : Pa was chosen} ; B is uncountable since p ]F-p ]*-(1) N A is uncountable . Let us say t h a t a family S C P forms a A - s y s t e m , if S ' = {dora(s) : s C S} forms a A - s y s t e m of sets and all functions s E S agree on the root of S I . T h e c o m m o n restriction to the root of S ~ will be called the root of S . By passing to an uncountable subset of B , if necessary, we m a y suppose t h a t {Pa : a E B} f o r m a A - s y s t e m with root pt < p . Next, for each a E XM, choose (if possible) ra E P so t h a t r~ < p' and ra It-p a E fi and ](a) = O. Similarly assume t h a t B ~ is an uncountable set so t h a t {ra : a E B ~} forms a A - s y s t e m with root r . By removing at m o s t finitely m a n y m e m b e r s of B we m a y also assume t h a t dorn(pa - p') M dorn(r) = 0 for each a E B . Let B0 = {a E B : P a - P' C M } and B ~ - - {a e B ' : r a - r C M } . C l a i m : Bu and B~ cannot b o t h be uncountable. To see this note first t h a t
C--{(a, pa-p'):aEBo}
C'--{(a, ra-r):aEB~o}
and
are P M - n a m e s such t h a t r
n A
and
r
c
n A.
Therefore r IF'p ct~C M clrG" = 0 . But then, as noted at the beginning of the proof, it m u s t be the case t h a t r N M I ~-PM £1rMC I-t c l r M C I : 0 • By our a s s u m p t i o n on A , r N M [ ~ - ( e i t h e r C o r C ' is countable) . But since { P a - P ' : a E B o } and {ra - r : a E B~} are A - s y s t e m s (with (empty) root compatible with r) , it follows t h a t either B0 or B~ is c o u n t a b l e .
61 Since the proofs are similar, we shall assume t h a t B0 is countable. By considering B - B0 , we m a y assume t h a t for each a • B , it is not the case t h a t (p n M ) U p' I~-p ](a) = 1 (note t h a t it is the case t h a t (p n M)I~-p~ a • -4 ) . Now, for each a • B , choose some qa • P and na • w so t h a t qa < (P N M ) U p' and dom(qa) D dom(pa) a n d q,~ Ik ](a) < 1 - 1/n~,. Choose an uncountable C c B , n • w and q • P so t h a t {qa : a • C} forms a A - s y s t e m with root q and n~ = n for all a • C . Now let qt = q n M a n d choose {an : n < w} any infinite subset of C . For each n • w , let Pn = Pa,, N M and qn = qa,, ;3 M (observe t h a t p= C qn ) • Since M is closed under w-sequences {an : n • w} , {pn : n < w} and {qn : n • w} are all in M . Let us call a sequence { < p ~ , q ~'' > : n < w ) a A-system pair (for { a , ~ : n < ~ } , {p,~:n•w} and {qn: n • w} ) if there is a P - n a m e ] such t h a t : (i) 1 l~-p ] is a continuous real-valued function on < X, # > ; (ii) for each n • w p~ h, ](an) = 1 , q~ t~-p ] ( a , ) = 0 ; (iii) for each n • w , Pn c p~ n q", q~ c q' ; (iv) { p ' : n • w} forms a A - s y s t e m with root p' ; (v) {q~: n • w} forms a A - s y s t e m with root q ' . T h e sequence { < Pa~,qa~ >: rt • w} constructed above witnesses the fact t h a t there are A - s y s t e m pairs for {an : n C w} which are not in M , hence there m u s t be uncountably m a n y in M . We shall inductively choose an uncountable sequence P a = { : n • w } fora<wl of A - s y s t e m pairs for {an : n • w} so t h a t if
D =
U{dom(pn) U dorn(q~):n
• w}
and for each t~ < wl
Da = U {dom(p~ - p~) u dom(q~ - qn) : n • w} t h e n for each a < ~ < w l DanD=0andD~NDp=O. Indeed, suppose we have chosen p ~ for ¢~ < / ~ so t h a t each p~ is a A-system pair which is a subset of M . Since M is closed u n d e r w-sequences the entire sequence < p a : a < ~ > is a m e m b e r of M . T h e A - s y s t e m pair constructed in the above p a r a g r a p h would serve as the next m e m b e r except t h a t it is not a subset of M . However by absoluteness there m u s t be such a A - s y s t e m pair in M , so we m a y choose p p . For each a < wl let q~ be the root of the A - s y s t e m {q~ : n E w} in the A - s y s t e m pair p ~ . By construction {q~ : a < wl} forms a A - s y s t e m with root qt . For each a < wl , fix a P - n a m e , f~ , of a continuous real-valued function which witnesses t h a t p ~ is a A - s y s t e m pair. We are going to prove the following C l a i m ql ]F-p the closure of H~ is initially wx-compact and [0,1] ~ has weight wl , q~ [}-p the image of < X , T > under H ~ < ~ f~ is compact. However by [2.3] this is a contradiction since it means t h a t qt [~- < X, r > does not have countable tightness. Now to establish the claim. If G is P-generic and ql • G t h e n L = {¢~ < w l : q~ • G } is uncountable . Furthermore, let t • F n ( L , 2) and r • G be a r b i t r a r y For each • dora(t), there is an n~ • w such t h a t [dorn(p~ - pt) U dorn(q~ - q~)] N dora(r) = 0 .
62 Therefore there is an rt E w such that p~ and q~ are b o t h compatible with r for each a E dorn(t) . Furthermore, since Da N D~ = 0 for a < fl < wl we have t h a t [dom(p~ - p,~) U dorn(q~ - q,t)] n [dom(p~n - p,~) U dorn(q~ - qr~)] = 0 . Therefore there is an extension r' of r such that for each a E dora(t) r' Ikp ]~(a=) = t(a) . From this it follows that V [ G ] ~ the map H ] a (a E L) takes { a , : n E w} onto a dense subset of 2L • l By a very similar proof one can show the following. PROPOSITION 5 . 4 .
Let P = F n ( I , 2) and suppose that
1 [~-p< X,# > is a completely regular initially Wl-compact space of countable tightness.
Let M be an elementary submodel closed under w-sequences, and suppose that Ji , are PM-names of subsets of X M such that 1 [Fv~ if B is an uncountable subset of /i then cliMB N cl~MC # 0 • Then 1 [F-p cluB ¢3 cl~C # 0 for each uncountable
B cft
.
THEOREM 5 . 5 . [CH] If P -= F n ( I , 2 ) and 1 [~-p< X,~ > is initially wl-compact and has countable tightness, then 1 Ik p < X , Zr > is compact. PROOF: Suppose indirectly that there is some p E P and some P - n a m e ~ such that p [F-p ( ~ is a maximal free filter on the closed subsets of the initially wl-compact space of countable tightness , < X,~ >) . By [5.2] , p]F-p ~ has a base of separable sets. Let M be an elementary submodel containing < p , X , ~ , ~ > which is closed under w-sequences and has cardlnality w 1 . Let ( F a : a < Wl}C M be a listing of all PMnames of countable subsets of X M such that p i ~ p eliza E ~ . By w-absoluteness p [F-p~ { clrM~'a : a < Wl} is a filter base for a countably complete filter on X M • For each ct E Wl , let ha E M be a PM-name such t h a t pl~-pM a~ E N~ is an initially w l - c o m p a c t space of countable tightness.
65
Therefore, by [5.5], we have t h a t < X M , v a l ( # M , G N M ) > is c o m p a c t in V [ G N M ] . Next we use [5.12] to deduce t h a t gIG N M] ~ < XM,val(#M,G n M ) > contains a point, say x , of character wl • But since M is closed under wl-sequences the base for x will actually be a m e m b e r of M[G N M], i.e. it will have a n a m e in M . We can therefore deduce, by elementarity, t h a t this base will be a base for x even in the full V[C] . t
We finish with a s o m e w h a t surprising reflection l e m m a , however I do not have any applications for it. LEMMA 5 . 1 5 . Suppose V is a model of CH , P = F n ( I , 2) and 1 1~-< X, i" > is a compact space of countable tightness. I f M is an elementary submodel closed under w-sequences and G is P-generic then V[G n M] ~ The Stone-¢ech compactiflcation of < X M , P(~I(TM,G n M ) > has countable tightness. Furthermore if we let < K M , a > be this compactification from V[G N M] then V[G]~ (there is a set K ' such that X M C K ' C X , K ' with the topology induced by val(# ,G) is Lindel6f and there is a unique continuous one-to-one map from K ' to KM which is the identity on XM ). PROOF: Let us begin by working in V[G AM] . Define K M to be the Stone-(~ech compactification of < XM,val(#, G) > . By countable tightness and w-absoluteness each continuous real-valued function on X M extends , in V[G] , to one on clXM ; indeed if f : X M --+ [0,1] is such that, in V[G] , c l f ' - ( 0 ) n clf~-(1) # 0 , then this would be exhibited by a countable s e t . Now t h a t we know the continuous real-valued functions are absolute upward , we can use t h e m to lift any free sequence of KM to one in X . Therefore KM has countable t i g h t n e s s . An i m m e d i a t e consequence of this fact is t h a t K M will have character R 1 since the set of c o m p l e m e n t s of the closures of countable subsets of X M which do not have a given point in their closure will f o r m a base for t h a t point. Next, we know t h a t X M is countably c o m p a c t , hence each zero-set ultrafilter on X M is countably complete. F u r t h e r m o r e we claim t h a t each ultrafilter of zero-sets will have a unique accumulation point in X . Indeed, if not, we can choose, by countable tightness, a countable subset of X M whose closure will contain both the p u r p o r t e d limit points. But then we can assume we are working with a separable space in which case there will only be R1 continuous real-valued functions. A routine diagonalization process allows us to pick a set A which will m e e t each m e m b e r of the ultrafilter in a co-countable set and which will have b o t h of the above accumulation points as complete accumulation points. Of course this contradicts the conclusion of [5.3] . To complete the proof of the claim we note t h a t the hypotheses on A in [5.3] can be weakened to just the assumption t h a t no two uncountable subsets can be completely separated (as is the case here) since this is w h a t was proven. We then define the space K ' and the m a p g : K M ---* K ' in the obvious way. It remains to show t h a t K ' is Lindel6f. We first observe yet another consequence of the Main L e m m a which is interesting in its own right. F a c t T h e G6-topologies on K ' generated by val(~:M, G n M )
and
val(~, G)
are i d e n t i c a l .
66 Indeed, suppose t h a t we have a point x • K ' which is in the G~-closure of a set F with respect to the smaller topology. Let {Wc` : a • wl} be a neighbourhood base for x with respect to val(~M, G n M ) . Working in V[GNM] fix a n a m e ~" for F . Let p • G be a r b i t r a r y and for each a • wz , choose a condition p,~ • F n ( I - M , 2) below p and a point xc` • K M so t h a t pc`l~ g(xc`) • F n
N W~ /~ a, Ct~ \ K is nonempty.
proof This follows easily from a well-known theorem of Sierpifiski that every countable scattered space is isomorphic to an ordinal. For simplicity we sketch a proof here. aResearcla partially supported by the Netherlands organization for the advancement of pure research 2Research partially supported by NSF grant MCS-84017U
69 Let D ( X ) be the derivative operator, i.e. D(X) is the set of nonisolated points of X. T h e n let Da(X) be the usual a th iterate of D, defined by induction as follows.
D'~+I(X) = D(Da(X)) DX(X) = N a < x D a ( X ) if)~ a limit ordinal Define the rank of any X (rank(X)) as the least a such t h a t Da(X) is empty. Then the l e m m a follows easily from the following facts: 1. Every compact subset of Q has a countable rank. 2. If X C Y then D(X) C D(Y). 3. If X C Y then r a n k ( X ) < r a n k ( Y ) . 4. r a n k ( C ~ + l ) = a + 1. [] To prove the T h e o r e m let L = Uneo~ L,~ where each Ln is compact. Let Kn C Q be the projection of L , onto the n 'h coordinate. By the l e m m a there exists C~ which is not covered by any Kn. It follows that H~ is not covered by L. Q We don't know whether the theorem is true for T ° sets ( G ~ ) or even for a set which is the union of a countable set and a II ° (G6). Next we prove the following theorem: 3 Suppose that A is an analytic subset of the plane, R 2, which cannot be covered by countably many lines. Then there exists a perfect subset P of A such that no three points of P are collinear.
Theorem
proof A set is perfect iff it is homeomorphic to the Cantor space 2~. The proof we give is similar to the classical proof that uncountable analytic sets must contain a perfect subset. A subset A of a complete separable space X is analytic iff there exists a closed set C C w ~ x X such that A is the projection of C, i.e. A--p(C)={yEX
] 3zew ~ (x,y)•C}
Every Borel subset of X is analytic. Let A be analytic subset of the plane I~2 which cannot be covered by countably m a n y lines. Let S be the unit square ([0, 1] x [0, 1]) minus all lines of the form x -- r or y -- r for r a rational number. Without loss of generality we m a y assume that A is a subset of S. Since S is a complete separable space there exists C C w~ x S a closed set such t h a t
A = p(C). Give S the basis B8 for s • 4 5 so t h a t 13 forms a &-system with root /XC~r for some ~ < 5. P r o o f : W L O G assume t h a t t.AI = 6. Let A = {tiC5 : fl regular]-, a n d let .A -- (X~ : flEA]-. By L e m m a 4, for each X~ there is some cr~ so t h a t 7 $ c~ < 5 and X~Ccr~. Let B = {flEA : tra < fl}. (a) Assume t h a t B is stationary in &
93
f(fl) = "the least T so t h a t X~NflCv ~. Since [X/3Aj31 < fl and [3 is C C B - 7 and g < S so that ] " C = {~r}. Thus, if/3EC, XZNflCo" and XZCo'~C~, so X~Co'. Thus T~ = {XEA : XC~r} has size ~. Now apply the A - s y s t e m l e m m a t o / ) to obtain a &-system BC1) o f size 6. T h e n / X , t h e root of/3, is a subset o f ~r For e v e r y / 3 C B - 7 define
regular, f is regressive. By Fodor's t h e o r e m there are s t a t i o n a r y
(b)
Assume t h a t B is not s t a t i o n a r y in &
BNC = O. D = ANC is s t a t i o n a r y and ifi3ED, t h e n / 3 ~ B and XylthC~" " By Fodor's t h e o r e m there are a s t a t i o n a r y E C D - 7 and ~ < 6 so t h a t f " E = {¢}. So for all/3EE, X~nflCcr a n d / 3 < eZ. By induction choose a sequence (/3a : ct < 6)CE so t h a t cr~ v. If ~ is not Ulam-measurable then {p e U(S): R(p) : ~} is dense in U(S).
Proof. Let V be open in U(S) and pick D ~ IS] A with D 0 U(S) £ V. Pick a one-to-one ~-sequence 0 and a l l A ~ N, i f d(A) > 0 then there e x i s t s n e B with
111
~ ( A n A - n) ~a(A) ~ - ~. Bergelson showed t h a t i f C is any i n f i n i t e subset of N, then D(C) = {x - y: x,y e C and x > y} is a set of nice combinatorial recurrence. He then established [2] the following g e n e r a l i z a t i o n of Schur's Theorem. 7.3 Theorem (Bergelson).
Let m ~ N and let N = Ui< m A i.
Then there exists i < m
such that a(ii) > 0 and for every ¢ > 0 ~({n ¢ ki: a(k i N I i - n) ~ d(Ai )2 - c}) > O.
Bergelson has r e c e n t l y t o l d me in conversation of the following theorem, whose proof we are presenting with his permission.
7.4 Theorem (Bergelson).
Assume that whenever B e IN] w, one has that
{x2: x e FS(B)} is a set of nice combinatorial recurrence. p + p = p. a(A) 2 -
Then for all A e p and all e > O, {x e A: A e and a(A N A -
Proof.
x) > a(A) 2 -
Let p c ~ such that x E p and a(A N A - x 2)
e} e p.
By [5, Lemma 2.11 we have {x E A: A - x e p and a(A fl A - x)
~(A) 2 - ~} e p.
(re e s s e n t i a l l y duplicate the above c i t e d proof in what follows.)
Let B = {x c N: a(A N A - x 2) > a(A) 2
~} and suppose t h a t S ~ p.
pick (see f o r example [37, Theorem 8.6]) C ~ [N1W with FS(C) K N\B. assumption x e FS(C) such that d(A N A - x 2) > a(A) 2 - e.
Since p + p = p, Pick by
But then x e B, a
contradiction. [] The interest in Theorem 7.3 is strengthened by Bergelson's announcement (in conversation) that he and Furstenberg have proved that the hypothesis is true. consequence, they easily obtain a non linear Ramsey Theory result: then there are some i < m and x,y,z e A i with x + y2 = z. p + p = p and pick i < m with A i e p.
If N = Ui< m A i
(To see this let p e A with
Let c = ~(Ai)2/2 and let B = {x e Ai:
A i- x e p and a(l i N i i - x 2) > a(Ai)2y e B,
As a
e and a(A i N A i - x) > d(Ai)2 - e}.
Pick
Pick x e A i fi A i - y2 and let z = x + y 2 )
In [37] we presented the following Theorem of Raimi [45]: There exists E c N such that whenever m e N and N = Ui< m A i there exist i < m and k e N with [(A i + k) N E l = # and l(Ai + k)\E I = w.
Using properties of a probability space, Bergelson and
Veiss [71 have generalized this result.
112
7.5 Theorem.
(Bergelson and Weiss).
There e x i s t s E ~ N such t h a t whenever A [ N
and ~ ( l ) > O, t h e r e i s some k e N with ~((A + k) 0 E) > 0 and ~ ( ( l + k)\E) > O. C a l l a f a m i l y F of subsets of the set Z of i n t e g e r s t r a n s l a t i o n i n v a r i a n t provided, whenever F ~ F and k e Z one has F + k e Z.
C a l l such a f a m i l y p a r t i t i o n
r e g u l a r i f , whenever m c ~ and N = Ui<m Ai t h e r e e x i s t i < m and F e F with F ~ Ai . In [3], Bergelson made the following c o n j e c t u r e : I f F i s a t r a n s l a t i o n i n v a r i a n t p a r t i t i o n r e g u l a r f a m i l y of f i n i t e subsets of Z and i f A ~ N with d*(A) > O, then t h e r e i s F e F with F ~ A.
(The most famous i n s t a n c e of the v a l i d i t y of B e r g e l s o n ' s
c o n j e c t u r e has F c o n s i s t i n g of a l l length k a r i t h m e t i c p r o g r e s s i o n s . ) Davenport and I made the f o l l o w i n g simple o b s e r v a t i o n :
If F is a partition
r e g u l a r t r a n s l a t i o n i n v a r i a n t set of f i n i t e subsets of Z and A = {p e ~N: f o r a l l A e p t h e r e e x i s t F e F with F ~ A}, then A i s a closed i d e a l of (BN,÷). r e g u l a r i t y y i e l d s t h a t A ~ ¢.
(Partition
Translation invariance yields that A is a right ideal.
To see t h a t A i s a l e f t i d e a l , l e t p e A, q e ~N, and A e q + p.
Pick F e F with
F ~ {x e N: I - x e q}. Since [FI < w, nxe F A - x e q. I f t e OxeF A - x, then t + F ~ 1.) B e r g e l s o n ' s c o n j e c t u r e i s e a s i l y seen to be e q u i v a l e n t to the a s s e r t i o n t h a t f o r any such A, A* £ I .
Since A1 i s the s m a l l e s t closed i d e a l of (~N,+) one does
always get A1 [ A and, f a i r l y e a s i l y , t h a t A1 ¢ A.
F u r t h e r by d e f i n i t i o n , p e A1 i f
and only i f f o r each A e p, t h e r e e x i s t s k with d*(U~= 1 A - t ) = 1.
Also, by [29,
Theorem 3 . 8 ] , p e A* i f and only i f f o r each I e p and each e > 0 t h e r e e x i s t s k with d*(~t= 1 A - t ) > 1 - e. The s i m i l a r i t y between t h e s e d e s c r i p t i o n s l e d us to b e l i e v e t h a t perhaps no closed i d e a l s of (~N,+) could be found s t r i c t l y between h 1 and A*, (so one would have a proof of B e r g e l s o n ' s c o n j e c t u r e ) . Observe t h a t , by Theorem 2.5, i f p e ~ \ N , then cl((~N\N) + p) i s a closed i d e a l of (~N,+).
Call such an i d e a l " s u b p r i n c i p a l " .
The answer which we obtained [18] i s
v a s t l y d i f f e r e n t than the one we wanted: 7.6 Theorem. (Davenport and Hindman). A1 i s the i n t e r s e c t i o n of s u b p r i n c i p a l closed i d e a l s l y i n g s t r i c t l y between i t and A*. Presumably one of the main reasons we were unable to o b t a i n our d e s i r e d r e s u l t is that Bergelson's conjecture is false.
We are g r a t e f u l to Imre Ruzsa f o r permission to
p r e s e n t h i s unpublished proof of t h i s f a c t .
( I t i s i n s p i r e d by his [49, Theorem 1 ] . )
Kecall t h a t a s e t B ~ N i s s y n d e t i c i f and only i f B has bounded gaps; t h a t i s , k there e x i s t s k e N with N = Ut= 1 B - t . Also B i s piecewise s y n d e t i c i f and only i f there e x i s t s k with d*(U~= 1 B - t ) = 1.
113
7.7 Lemma.
Let t be piecewise s y n d e t i c .
Then t h e r e e x i s t a s y n d e t i c s e t B ~nd
an i n c r e a s i n g sequence neN such t h a t {Yn + x: n e N, x e B, and x < n} ~ A.
Proof.
Pick k such t h a t d*(U~: 1 A - t ) = 1.
{x n + 1, x n + 2 , . . . , of <Xn>neN so t h a t (1) (2)
For each n pick x n e N with
x n + n} ~ U~=1 A - t and Xn+1 > x n.
Choose a subsequence n,N
f o r each n e N, {Yn + 1, Yn + 2 , . . . , Yn + n} c U~=1 A - t and For n,m, and s in N and t e { 1 , 2 , . . . , k } , i f s < n < m, then Yn + s + t e A f f and o n l y i f Ym + s + t e A.
(See t h e proof of [28, Lemma 3.4] f o r a d e t a i l e d d e s c r i p t i o n of how to do t h i s . ) Let B = {n e N: Yn ÷ n e A}.
Then by (2) we have immediately t h a t {Yn + x:
n e N, x e B, and x < n} c_ I .
k To see t h a t B i s s y n d e t i c we show N = Ut= 1 B -
m e l~ and p i c k t e { 1 , 2 , . . . , k }
with Ym + m + t e A.
so n
e B.
Thus m e Ok
t=l
7.8 Theorem (Ruzsa).
B -
t.
Let n = m + t .
Let
Then Yn + n e A
[]
Bergelson's conjecture is false.
with d ( l ) > 0 and a p a r t i t i o n
t.
regular translation
That i s t h e r e e x i s t A
i n v a r i a n t f a m i l y F of f i n i t e
subsets
of Z such t h a t no member F of F i s c o n t a i n e d i n A.
Proof. Pick any I with d(A) > 0 such that A is not piecewise syndetic. (The sets constructed in Section 11 of [37] are such sets. For a simpler example consider {n e N: for all k > 3 and all m, if 2k-1 < m < 2k-1 + k, then n ~ m (mod 2k)}.) Since A is not piecewise syndetic we have (by simply negating the definition) that there exists b: N ~ N such that for all g,x e N there exists y c {x + i, x + 2,...,
x + b(g)} with {y + 1, y + 2 , . . . ,
y + g} 0 A = ~.
g i n t can be found w i t h i n b(g) of any p o i n t . )
(That i s a gap of l e n g t h
Ve may presume b i s an i n c r e a s i n g
function. Let F = { { a l , a 2 , . . . , a k } : k e N\{1}, each a i e Z, a 1 < a 2 < . . . < ak, and b(max{ai+ 1 - a i : 1 < i < k}) < k}. F i s c l e a r l y t r a n s l a t i o n i n v a r i a n t . To see t h a t F is partition
r e g u l a r , l e t m e N and l e t N = Ui<m Ci .
piecewise s y n d e t i c .
Pick j < m such t h a t Cj i s
(For example, l e t p e A1 and pick j such t h a t Cj e p.)
By Lemma
7.7 pick a s y n d e t i c s e t B and an i n c r e a s i n g sequence neN such t h a t {Yn + x: n e N, x e B, and x < n} £ Cj.
Since B is syndetic, pick g e N such that N = U~= 1 B - t.
Let k = b(g) + i.
Pick a I e B and inductively for 1 < i < k, pick ai+ 1 e {a i + 1, a i + 2,..., a i + g} 0 B. Let d = max{ai+ I - ai: 1 < i < k}. Then d < g so b(d) < b(g) < k so {al,a2,...,ak} e F. Let n = ak. Then {Yn + al' Yn + a 2 ' " " {y + a , y ÷ a , . . . , y + a } e F.
Yn + ak} ~ Cj and
114
Now suppose we have some F ~ F with F ~ A.
Pick k such t h a t F = { a l , a 2 , . . . , a k }
with a I < a 2 < . . . < a k. Let x = a 1 - 1 and l e t g = max{ai+ 1 - a i : 1 < i < k}. Note b(g) < k by the definition of F. Pick y ~ {x + i, x + 2,..., x + b(g)} with {y + I, y + 2,..., y + g} 0 A = #.
Now y < x + b(g) ~ x + k -
the least i such that y < a i and note i > 2.
i = a I-
1 + k-
1 < ak.
Pick
Now a i ~ A and {y + l, y + 2,..., y + g}
o A = # so a i > y + g + 1. Since ai_ 1 < y we have a i - ai_ 1 > g, a contradiction. Since the proof of Theorem 7.8 works on any A which is not piecewise syndetic, one obtains counterexamples with density arbitrarily close to 1.
However, the size of
the finite sets involved is always unbounded. The following result of Krlz [40] is much stronger since only pair sets are used. Its proof is also much more complicated.
7.9 Theorem
(Kfi~).
Let E > O.
There e x i s t a set A with d(A) > 1 / 2 -
c and a
p a r t i t i o n r e g u l a r t r a n s l a t i o n i n v a r i a n t family F of two element subsets of Z such that no F e F i s contained in k.
8.
New Combinatorial Applications of U l t r a f i l t e r s .
In 1982 Tim Carlson proved a remarkable theorem, whose proof u t i l i z e s ultrafilters,
and which has as c o r o l l a r i e s numerous e a r l i e r r e s u l t s in Ramsey Theory.
This theorem i n i t i a l l y c i r c u l a t e d in notes by Prikry. 3 of [13].
I t now can be found as Theorem
U n f o r t u n a t e l y , and perhaps unavoidably, one must develop a large amount of
terminology to s t a t e C a r l s o n ' s Theorem and we w i l l not do t h i s here. A recent r e s u l t [4] addresses the issue of whether one can f i n d s o l u t i o n s to d i f f e r e n t Ramsey type problems a l l l y i n g in the same c e l l of a p a r t i t i o n .
(For
example, if m ~ N and N = Ui< m A i one can certainly find i < m and j < m so that d(li) > 0 and l{x ( N: x 2 ~ lj} I = ~. i = j.)
Dn the other hand, it is easy to prevent
The result extends earlier work of mine [31] and joint work with Deuber [20~.
The proof of this result is very simple, producing an ultrafilter every member of which has the listed properties.
It utilizes the simple fact, using alternatively
(~N,+) and (/~N,.), that if L is a left ideal of a semigroup and R is a right ideal, then L 0 R @ @.
Given I ~ N, D(I) = {x- y: x,y ~ I and y < x}.)
8.1 Theorem. (Bergelson and Hindman) exists i < m such t h a t
(a)
Let m c N and l e t N = ui< m A.. 1
There
Ai c o n t a i n s s o l u t i o n s to a l l p a r t i t i o n r e g u l a r systems of homogeneous l i n e a r equations with i n t e g e r c o e f f i c i e n t s .
(b)
One can i n d u c t i v e l y choose a sequence <Xn>nn<w) ~ k i and for each n, given <xj>j O, d({n e Ai: a ( l i n t i - n) > a(Ai )2 - e}) > O.
(h)
For each k e N, d({m e Ai: ~(n~= 0 t - tm) > 0}) > O.
(i)
There e x i s t s B e IN] W with FP(B) [ t i .
Our f i n a l a p p l i c a t i o n u t i l i z e s an old method of proof of Ramsey's Theorem using ultrafilters. (See [14, page 39].) When I f i r s t saw t h i s proof over ten years ago I was q u i t e unimpressed. I t e s s e n t i a l l y t a k e s a standard p r o o f ' a n d r e p l a c e s appeals to the pigeon hole p r i n c i p l e ( i f m E N and N = Ui<m k i , then some I i i s i n f i n i t e ) with r e f e r e n c e s to a n o n - p r i n c i p a l u l t r a f i l t e r p ( i f m e ~ and N = Ui< m k i , then some t i e p). However, Bergelson pointed out t h a t we could probably get s t r o n g e r r e s u l t s i f we used s p e c i a l u l t r a f i l t e r s . Indeed, t h i s i s so. For example u t i l i z i n g p such t h a t p + p = p, one o b t a i n s the M i l l i k e n - T a y l o r Theorem ([433, [52]).
In [6] we
d i s p l a y the r e s u l t s when we u t i l i z e a " c o m b i n a t o r i a l l y l a r g e u l t r a f i l t e r " . an u l t r a f i l t e r
(That i s ,
used to produce Theorem 8 . 1 . )
I will illustrate
the method here with a simple r e s u l t u t i l i z i n g an u l t r a f i l t e r
every member of which c o n t a i n s a r b i t r a r i l y by van der Vaerden's Theorem.)
long a r i t h m e t i c p r o g r e s s i o n s .
(These e x i s t
The method of proof d i f f e r s somewhat from [6] because
we u t i l i z e here the product ® introduced in D e f i n i t i o n 2.2.
8.2 Theorem.
(Bergelson and Hindman.)
Let m e N and l e t [N] 2 = Ui< m i i .
Then
t h e r e e x i s t i < m and neN such t h a t each Bn i s an a r i t h m e t i c p r o g r e s s i o n of length n and {{x,y}: t h e r e e x i s t n , t e N with t ¢ n and x e Bt and y e Bn} ~ t i . Proof.
Pick p e ~N such t h a t each member of p c o n t a i n s a r b i t r a r i l y
arithmetic progressions.
given y, {x e N: (x,y) e L} i s c o f i n i t e , hence in p. (x,y) e L} e p} = N ~ p . )
long
Observe t h a t L = { ( x , y ) : x , y e N and x > y} e p ® p.
(For,
Thus {y e N: {x e N:
Now given i , l e t Ci = { ( x , y ) e L: {x,y} e l i } and pick i
such t h a t Ci e p ® p. I t thus s u f f i c e s to show t h a t whenever C e p ® p, t h e r e e x i s t s a sequence neN with each Bn an a r i t h m e t i c p r o g r e s s i o n of length n and { ( x , y ) : x > y and t h e r e e x i s t n , t e N with t ¢ n and x e Bt and y e Bn} 5 C.
116
Let D = {y e N: {x e N: (x,y) e C} e p}. Bn ~ D.
Ve choose neN inductively with each
Given n > 1 and ~ ~ we l e t a = max Bml and l e t En = D N
Nt=ln-1NzeBt{x e N: (x,z) e C} N {x e N: x > a}. Pick a length n arithmetic progression Bn ~ En.
Then since each Dt & D we have En e p. Then neN is as required. D
IEFELENCES
1.
R. lrens, The adjoint of a b i l i n e a r operator, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 2 (1951), 839-848.
2.
V. Bergelson, A density statement generalizing Schur's Theorem, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 43 (1986), 338-343.
3.
V. Bergelson~ Ergodic Ramsey Theory, in Lo__ogj~and Combinatorics ed., S. Simpson~ Contemporary Mathematics 69 (1987), 63-87.
4.
V. Bergelson and N. Hindman, A combinatorially large cell of a p a r t i t i o n of N, J. Comb. Theory (Series A), to appear.
5.
V. Bergelson and N. Hindman, Density versions of two generalizations of Schur's Theorem, J. Comb. Theory (Series l ) , to appear.
6.
V. Bergelson and N. ~indman, U l t r a f i l t e r s and multidimensional Ramsey theorems, manuscript.
7.
V. Bergelson and B. Weiss, Translation properties of sets of positive upper density, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 94 (1985), 371-376.
8.
J. Berglund and N. Hindman, F i l t e r s and the weak almost periodic compactification of a discrete semigroup, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 284 (1984), 1-38.
9.
J. Berglund~ H. Junghenn, and P. Milnes, Compact right topological semigroups and generalizations of almost p e r i o d i c i t y , Lecture Notes in l a t h . 663, Springer-Verlag, Berlin (1978).
10.
A. Blass, Selective u l t r a f i l t e r s and homogeneity~ Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, to appear.
11.
A. Blass, U l t r a f i l t e r s related to Hindman's finite-unions theorem and i t s extensions, in Logic and Combinatorics, ed. S. Simpson, Contemporary Mathematics 65 (1987), 89-124.
12.
A. Slass and N. Mindman, On strongly summable u l t r a f i l t e r s and union u l t r a f i t t e r s , Trans. Amer. Math. Soc., 304 (1987), 93-99.
13.
T. Carlson, Some unifying principles in Ramsey Theory, Discrete l a t h . , to appear.
14.
W. Comfort, Some recent applications of u l t r a f i l t e r s to topology, in Proceedings of th__eeFourth prague topological Symposium, 1976, ed. J. Novak, Lecture Notes in Math. 609 (1977), 34-42.
15.
V. Comfort, U l t r a f i l t e r s : an interim report, Surveys in General Topology, Academic Press~ New York, 1980, 33-54.
117
16.
W. Comfort and S. Negrepontis, The theory of u l t r a f i l t e r s , Berlin, 1974.
17.
D. Davenport, The algebraic properties of closed subsemigroups of u l t r a f i l t e r s on a d i s c r e t e semigroup, Dissertation, Howard University, 1987.
18.
D. Davenport and N. Hindman, Subprincipal closed ideals in fiN, Semigroup Forum, to appear.
19.
M. Day, Amenable semigroups, I l l i n o i s J. l a t h . ! (1957), 509-544.
20.
V. Deuber and N. Hindman, Partitions and sums of (m~p,c)-sets, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 45 (1987), 300-302.
21.
E. van Douwen, The ~ech-Stone compactification of a discrete cancellative groupoid, manuscript.
22.
R. E l l i s , Lectures on topological dynamics, Benjamin, New York, 1969.
23.
Z. Frolfk, Sums of u l t r a f i l t e r s , Bull. Amer. Math. Soc. 7_33(1967), 87-91.
24.
H. Furstenberg, Ergodic behavior of diagonal measures and a theorem of Szemeredi on arithmetic progressions, J. d'Analyse l a t h . 31 (1977), 204-256.
25.
H. Furstenberg, Recurrencee in ergodic theory and combinatorial number theory, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1981.
26.
L. Gillman and i . Jerison, Rings of continuous functions, van Nostrand, Princeeton, 1960.
27.
S. Glasner, D i v i s i b i l i t y properties and the Stone-Cech compactification, Canad. J. l a t h . 32 (1980), 993-1007.
28.
N. Hindman, linimal ideals and cancellation in ~N, Semigroup Forum 25 (1982), 291-310.
29.
N. Hindman, gn density, t r a n s l a t e s , and pairwise sums of integers, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 33 (1982), 147-157.
30.
N. Hindman, P a r t i t i o n s and pairwise sums and products, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 3A (1984), 46-60.
31.
N. Hindman, Ramsey's Theorem for sums, products and arithmetic progressions, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 38 (1985), 82-83.
32.
N. Hindman, Su~able u l t r a f i l t e r s and f i n i t e sums, in Logic and Combinatorics, ed. S. Simpson, contemporary lathematics 65 (1987), 263-274. N. Hindman, Sums equal to products in ~N, Semigroup Forum 2_!1 (1980), 221-255.
33.
Springer-Verlag,
34.
N. Hindman, The existence of certain u l t r a f i l t e r s on N and a conjecture of Graham and Rothschild, Proc. lmer. l a t h . Soc. 36 (1972), 341-346.
35.
N. Hindman, The ideal structure of the space of ~-uniform u l t r a f i l t e r s on a d i s c r e t e semigroup, Rocky lountain J. l a t h . 16 (1986), 685-701.
36.
N. Hindman, The minimal ideals of a multiplicative and additive subsemigroup of /~N, Semigroup Forum 32 (1985), 283-292.
37.
N. Hindman, U l t r a f i l t e r s and combinatorial number theory, in Number Theory Carbondale 1979, ed. 1. Nathanson, Lecture Notes in l a t h . 751 (1979), 119-184.
118
38.
N. Hindman and P. Milnes, The LIC compactification of a topologized semigroup, Czech. Math. J . , to appear.
39.
N. Hindman and J. Pym, Free groups and semigroups in fiN, Semigroup Forum 30 (1984), 177-193.
40.
I. K ~ , Large independent sets in s h i f t - i n v a r i a n t graphs. Solution of Bergelson's problem, Graphs and Combinatorics ~ (1987), 145-158.
41.
A. Lisan, Free groups in ~N which miss the minimal ideal, Semigroup Forum, to appear.
42.
P. l a t e t , Some f i l t e r s of p a r t i t i o n s , manuscript.
43.
K. Milliken, lamsey's Theorem with sums or unions, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 18
(1975), 276-290. 44.
J. Pym, Semigroup structure in Stone-Cech compactifications, manuscript.
45.
R. Raimi, Translation properties of f i n i t e p a r t i t i o n s of the positive integers, Fund. Lath. 61 (1968), 253-256.
46.
W. Rudin, Homogeneity problems in the theory of Cech compactifications, Duke Lath. J. 23 (1956), 409-419.
47.
V. Ruppert, In a l e f t topological semigroup with dense center the closure of any l e f t ideal is an ideal, Semigroup Forum, to appear.
48.
~. Ruppert, Rechstopologische Halbgruppen, J. Reine Angew. Lath. 261 (1973), 123-133.
49.
I . Ruzsa, Difference sets and the Bohr topology I . , manuscript.
50.
S. Shelah, Proper forcing, Lecture Notes in Lath. 940 (1982).
51.
E. Szemer~di, On sets of integers containing no k elements in arithmetic progression, Acta. Arith. 27 (1975), 199-245.
52.
A. Taylor, A canonical p a r t i t i o n relation for f i n i t e subsets of w, J. Comb. Theory (Series A) 21 (1976), 137-146.
53.
H. Umoh, Ideals of the Stone-Cech compactification of semigroups, Semigroup Forum 32 (1985), 201-214.
54.
H. Umoh, The ideal of products in flS\S, Dissertation, Howard University, 1987.
CONCERNING STATIONARY SUBSETS OF [X]
c.
(For the
and many other cardinals important to set-theoretic topology,
The issue is whether a negative answer is consistent,
At any rate, every since Eric sent me the diagram,
see
and that is still unsolved.
I have been interested in what
sorts of implications hold between various classes of compact, countably tight spaces. From now on, "space" will mean "Tychonoff space", since all our spaces will be subspaces of compact countably tight spaces and even have the property that countably compact subspaces are compact.
Since no negative answer to Problem C17 has been found in any
model, I have taken the liberty of simplifying the title of this paper. The first two sections are devoted to greatly expanding van Douwen's diagram, to the point where it seemed best to split it into three.
Section 3 gives examples (and some
theory as well) to justify the absence of arrows between the various classes, although some questions still remain in this regard.
Section 4, devoted to some topological games
of Gruenhage, will also justify some arrows that do appear.
In Section 5, it is shown
what happens when one is restricted to the compact scattered spaces, associated with superatomic Boolean algebras via Stone duality.
In anticipation of this, as many
examples in Section 3 as practical are scattered.
Section 6 points the way to further
expansions of van Douwen's diagram.
I.
Additional classes and implications. Most of the classes of compact spaces dealt with here fall into five informal
classifications: A.
Classes definedby convergent sequences:
bisequential,
G-bisequential,
Sequential, Fr4chet,
(weakly) first countable,
B.
Banach space classes:
C.
"Rings of continuous functions" classes:
=i"
Eberlein, Gul'ko, and Corson compact spaces. hereditarily realcompact,
pseudocompact subspaces are compact, countably compact subspaces are compact. D.
Measure classes:
E.
Hereditary covering and separation properties:
Radon, hereditarily a-realcompact. (weakly)
~-metacompact, weakly
O-refinable, metalindel6f, Property wD. Let us look more closely at each in turn. Classification A. sequence in
A
A subset
A
of a space
converges to a point outside
X A.
is sequentially closed in
X
A space is sequential if every
if no
137
sequentially closed subset is closed. whenever
x G A,
there is a sequence from
if for every point subset
{An:
x
An .
A
and every ultrafilter
n G ~o} of
finitely many
A space is Fr4chet-Ur~sohn
~
converging to ~
x.
converging to
X
there is a countable x
contains all but
A space is weakly first countable if to each point
containing
such that
A space is bisequential x,
such that every neighborhood containing
associate a countable weak base, i.e. a countable collection of
(or simply Fr~ehet) if
x
such that a set
Bn(X ) c S.
S
{Bn(X):
is open iff for each
A compact space is
_~_~0-bisequential
x
one can
n ~ o~} of subsets
x E S
there exists
if it is countably
n
tight and
every countable subspace is bisequential. A sheaf at x space
X
sequence ~I:
is a countable collection of sequences converging to
is an g
=i-point (i=1,2,3,4)
converging to
ran ~n o~
ran
g
x
iff for each sheaf
x.
A point of a
{~n: n G ~0} at
x,
there is a
such that:
for all
n;
[As usual, we write
A o~ B
if
A\B
is
finite. ]
=2: 0%:
ran ~n 0 ran a
is infinite (equivalently,
ran ~n 0 ran a
is infinite for infinitely many
n.
=4:
ran ~n 0 ran ~
is nonempty for infinitely many
n.
A space is an The
=i
=i-space if every point is an
nonempty)
for all
=i-point.
properties are primarily of interest when the spaces in question are
Fr~chet, and that is the context in which we will consider them. bisequential or strongly Fr4chet if it is Fr4chet and and
=2,
n.
and a v-space if it is Fr4chet and
a
A space is countably
w-space if it is Fr~chet
~'i" Actually, except for
were originally given completely different-looking definition and equivalences,
=4'
definitions.
"v-space",
see [Mill, [AI, 5.23] and [Sh], [NOl] respectively.
important theorem is that eygr~ qqmpact Fr4chet space is countably bisequential The
these
For the original An [Mill.
~i-properties are especially important in product theorems, as are
(~o)-bisequential.
For instance,
the countable product of countably compact Fr4chet
~i-spaces is again such a space if
i=1,2,3 [Nol, 3.12], and any countable product of
(~o)-bisequential "hisequential"
spaces is again one [A4].
The first definition of
in [A4] is incorrect.)
The equivalence in the definition of is granted,
(Caution:
the implications
=i => ~ + l
and first countable => bisequential => [A4, 6.23] that
~o-bisequential
in the definitions,
~/
above is an easy exercise [No2].
are obvious;
so are
~o-bisenquential.
implies both Fr~chet and
neither of "bisequential"
Once this
Fr~chet => sequential,
Less easy to see is the fact ~3"
Despite some resemblance
or "weakly first countable" implies the
other.
In fact, a space is first countable iff it is weakly first countable and Fr~chet
[Sil].
However,
Problem I.
the following is still unsolved: Is there a weakly first countable compact space that is not first
countable? An affirmative answer is consistent
(Example 3.11).
138 Every weakly first countable space is sequential [Sill, [NY2].
Thus for compact
spaces we have the implications => in:
first
countable
. v -ip a~e
bisequential ~'~0 - bisequential~:
w-space
weakly first countable
~ + Fr~chet (~4 ÷) Fr~chet => sequential
Diagram 1
A remarkable recent result of Alan Dow is: I.i.
Theorem.
[Do]
In the Laver forcing model [L] every
w-space is a v-space.
For more on this and the following result, see Section 4. 1.2.
Theorem.
[Dow and Steprans]
It is consistent that every countable v-space is
first countable. A corollary is that it is consistent that every compact v-space is ~o-bisequential. dotted lines.
I have indicated consistent implications in the above diagram by
No other implications, consistent or otherwise, are possible, except those
embodied in: Problem 2.
Is it consistent that every compact,
"'J"~o-bisequential?
or that every compact w-space is
a3,
Frdchet space is
~o-blsequential?
(See Example
3.8.) Classification B. real lines.
A compact space is Corson compact if
(not the one making it Banach). Cp(X)
it
embeds in a
Z-product of
It is Eberlein compact if it embeds in a Banach space with the weak topology A compact space
X
is Gul'ko compact if the space
of continuous real-valued functions with the product topology is a Lindel6f
Z-space.
(For the concept of a
Z-space see [Bu] or [Gr2].)
Related classes of compact
spaces and many equivalent conditions may be found in [Ne], as well as the implications Eberlein => Gul'ko => Corson and examples showing the arrows do not reverse.
See also the discussion of
Classification E. It is easy to see that every separable subset of a Corson compact space is metrizable, and not too difficult to show that a Corson compact space (in fact a .-product of first countable spaces) is Frdchet [Gr I, 4.6].
Corson compact ~ ~ O - b i s e q u e n t i a l ~v-space
Hence we also have:
139
Classification C.
I assume readers are familiar with the concept of a countably
compact space, but here is a characterization which helps relate it to some of the other classes:
a space is countably compact iff every filterbase of closed sets has the
countable intersection property.
A space is pseudocompact if every real-valued
continuous function is bounded, and realcompact if it can be embedded as a closed subspace in a product of real lines. Although it may grate on some set theorists' nerves, I will follow here the custom of calling a maximal centered subcollection and calling
F
F
of a family
A
of sets an
"A-ultrafilter",
"fixed" if it has nonempty intersection, and "free" otherwise.
[I never
could understand why logicians persist in using the cumbersome expression "non-prlnclpal ultrafilter" when "free ultrafilter" is available.] set if it is of the form Z
f-l{0)
stand for the collection of all zero-sets in 1.3.
(B)
Theorem [GJ,
].
A space is
pseudocompact iff every
A subset of a space
X
for some continuous real-valued function
(A)
X,
is a zerof.
Letting
we recall:
compact iff every
Z-ultrafilter has the c.i.p.
Z-ultrafilter is fixed;
(C)
realcompact iff every
Z-ultrafilter with the c.i.p, is fixed. From this it is obvious that a space is compact iff it is pseudocompact and realcompact, accounting for one arrow in van Douwen's diagram.
Another is accounted for
by the fact (also clear from the above) that every countably compact space is pseudocompact.
We have already provided references for the other implications in his
diagram, as straightened out by Zhou's theorem. Classification D. class
K
if
A Borel measure
U
is inner-reGular with respect to a certain
~(B) = sup {~(K): K c B , K ~ K }
Radon if every finite (i.e.
u(X) < + m)
for each Borel set B.
A space
X
measure on the Borel sets is Radon,
inner-regular with respect to the compact subsets.
A space is
~-realcompact (also known
as closed-complete) if every "closed ultrafilter" (= C-ultrafilter where
C
is the
collection of closed sets) with the countable intersection property is fixed. Radon space is hereditarily
is
i.e. is
Every
o~-realcompact; this follows from 6.8, 7.4, and 8.12 of [GP]
and the diagram on p. 992 of [GP], which gives a number of concepts intermediate between these (but some are equivalent to Radon for compact spaces, cf. [GP, 7.9]). Classification E. open refinement.
A space is metalindel~f if every open cover has a point-countable
A collection
A
is
~-pointlfinite if it is the countable union of
point-finite collections, and weakly ~-point-finite if point
x,
A
members of
is the union of all the An .
a-point finite open refinement.
x
such that
A = U{An: n e ~ } x
A weakly 8-refinable space is one where every open cover
U = U{Un: n G ~]
where for each point
x
there is an
is in at least one, but no more than finitely many, members of
addition each
Un
where, for each
is in at most finitely many
n A space is [weakly] a-metacompact if every open cover has a [weakly]
has an open refinement that
A
can be a cover, then we have the definition of a
Un.
n
such
[If in
8-refinable space.]
140
It is easy to see that the following implications hold: metalindelSf o-metacompact => weakly a-metacompact
~weakly e-refinable Of course, every compact space is
~-metacompact, so that these properties only are
interesting in our context if they are satisfied hereditarily.
Now, as is so often the
case with covering properties, it is enough to check that every open subspace has the respective property. in
Y,
then each
The idea is that, if
V ~ U
is of the form
and if we refine the collection
W
U
is a cover of a subspace
W O Y
for some
W
Y
by sets open
open in the whole space,
of all these expansions on the open subspace
the appropriate way, the traces of the refinement on
Y
t~
in
will also behave as desired.
This is especially worth noting in the context of compact spaces since every open subspace of a (locally) compact space is locally compact, and these hereditary covering properties are neither created nor destroyed in passing to one-point compactifications. It also leads to such simplifications as the following theorem alternate characterizations of weak e-refinability in 1.4.
Theorem.
[BL]
A locally compact space is weakly
of
X
U An
is
which uses
[Bu].
e-refinable iff every open cover
has a G-relatively-discrete refinement by compact subsets. space
[NY5] ,
and
~-relativel~-discrete if it is of the form
[A collection of subsets of a U{An: n G ~]
has a neighborhood meeting at most one member of
where each point
An. ]
It also helps in the analysis of the hereditary metalindelhf property.
In Section 4
we will see that "hereditarily metalindelSf" implies both "v-space" and " ~ o-hisequentlal " " for compact spaces.
See also [PY] for a quick proof that if
point of a compact space
is metalindelSf and
sequence from
A
X
and
converging to
Finally, a space discrete subspace
X
S
each of which meets
X-{m]
satisfies Property
wD
wD
in exactly one point.
X)
collection
(Recall that a collection
U
of open sets, A
is discrete
A.
is the weakest in a hierarchy of properties extending to normal (and
beyond to collectionwise normal, etc.)
[vD, Section 12], [Vl].
because compact sequential spaces which satisfy
wD
realcompact space satisfies is countably compact.
of pseudocompact spaces might be said that normal
wD [VII;
It is included here
hereditarily happen to fit nicely
into Eric's diagram and illuminate some of the relationships.
wD
then there is a
if for every countably infinite closed
if each point has a neighborhood meeting at most one member of Property
iS a
x.
there is an infinite discrete (in S
x G [,
x
On the one hand, every
on the other, every pseudocompact space satisfying
This is easy to see if one considers another characterization [E, 3.10.23]: => wD
every discrete family of open sets is finite.
It
is the "real" reason for the fact, initially surprising
to many students, that every normal pseudocompact space is countably compact. rate, we can squeeze "sequential and satisfying
wD
At any
hereditarily" in between the first
two classes of Eric's straightened-out diagram, because of what happens on the other end:
141
sequential implies countably compact subsets are closed in any space, hence compact in a compact space.
2.
More implications The covering properties in Classification E all imply compactness in a countably
compact space.
This is part of a theme carried considerably further in IV2, Section 6],
[A3] and [T]: "countably compact +
=> compact."
The simplest thing to put in
the blank is "LindelSf," but the weaker the property, the better. So, if one of the Classification E covering properties is satisfied hereditarily in a compact space, it implies all countably compact subspaces are compact.
But, except for
a-metacompactness, I do not know how much further we can go (see Problem 6, and Example 3.6 below). 2.1.
We do have the following 1984 result of Uspensky:
Theorem.
[U]
Every ~-metacompact, pseudocompact space is compact.
Gardner [GP, 10.2-3] showed a hereditarily weakly 8-refinable, locally compact space is Radon iff it has no discrete subspace of a real-valued measurable cardinal, and that a weakly 8-refinable space is =-realcompact iff it has no closed discrete subspace of a measurable cardinal. Gruenhage [Gr3] gave the following unexpected characterizations: 2.2.
Theorem.
(i)
X
(ii)
X2
The following are equivalent for a compact space
X:
is Corson [resp. Eberlein] compact. is hereditarily metalindelSf [resp. ~-metacompact]
(iii) X 2 - A
is metalindel6f [resp. ~-metacompact]
He also showed [Gr6] that
X2
is hereditarily weakly ~-metacompact if
X
is Gul'ko
compact and conjectured that the converse is true, and also asked: Problem 3. metacompact?
If is
X2 - A X
is weakly ~-metacompact, is
X2
hereditarily weakly a-
Gul'ko compact?
So far, we have the following implications,
for compact spaces where
H. stands for
"hereditarily": Eberlein compact
=>
Gul'ko compact
=>
H. ~-metacompact
=>
H. weakly
=>
pseudocompact subspaces are compact
H. weakly ~refinable " l!
~
~ ~
~ ~ H. ~realcompact
H. metalindelSf
~0-~sequential v - s p a c e
~
Radon
Corson compact
~
~
x # ~. ~
2 Diagram 2
142
Here
.... >
cardinals, and
means the implication holds if there are no real-valued measurable +++>
means it is consistent that the implication does not hold, but that
it is not known whether it fails in ZFC. Problem 4.
If a compact space
X
See Problem 7 below, and:
is hereditarily metalindelSf, and no discrete
subspace is of measurable cardinality, is consistent
that
X
I n [GP, Example 1 1 . 2 0 ] constructed cardinal.
X
hereditarily e-realcompact?
Is it
i s a l w a y s Radon? t h e r e i s a compact, h e r e d i t a r i l y
u s i n g CH, i n which no d i s c r e t e
m e t a l i n d e l S f non-Radon space
subspace is of a real-valued
G a r d n e r [Gd2] h a s a s k e d w h e t h e r
MA + -CH
measurable
i m p l i e s no s u c h s p a c e e x i s t s .
I do n o t e v e n know t h e answer t o : Problem 5. cardlnality,
is
If
X
X
i s m e t a l i n d e l B f , and no c l o s e d d i s c r e t e
T h i s i s p a r t o f a theme r e l a t e d section:
"No d i s c r e t e
~-realcompact."
subspace i s of measurable
o~-realcompact? to t h e one m e n t i o n e d a t
subspace of measurable c a r d i n a l i t y
I f one l o o k s a t t h e c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n s
compact i n S e c t i o n 2, i t
is clear
serve for the other one.
the b e g i n n i n g of t h i s
+
of
=> ~ - r e a l c o m p a c t and c o u n t a b l y
t h a t a n y t h i n g one can t r u t h f u l l y
put i n t h i s
But this theme has not progressed nearly so far:
blank will
As I said,
weak 8-refinability works, but it is the weakest covering property I have seen so far that does.
But "metalindelSf" is a reasonable candidate to try since metalindelSf spaces
that are not weakly 8-refinahle are still in short supply. described by Gruenhage (Example 3.5) and they are subspaces of compact Radon spaces if one assumes
The only "real" ones were
~-realcompact; c
in fact, they are
is not real-valued measurable.
It might be said that this second theme is the "real" reason why normal e-refinable spaces
[Z]
and normal, countably paracompact, weakly 8-refinable spaces [Gall with no
closed discrete subspaces of measurable cardinality are realcompact: paracompact space is realcompact iff it is a-realcompact [Dy]~
a normal,
countably
also every 8-refinahle
space is countably metacompact [Gi] and every normal, countably metacompact space is countably paracompact
JR,
] and [RUl, I.I, (i) => (ii)].
A big unknown as far as Diagram 2 is concerned is: Problem 6.
Is a compact space sequential if it is any of the following:
(a)
hereditarily weakly 8-refinable
(b)
Radon
(c)
hereditarily a-realcompact?
Of course, these are special cases of Problem C17.
There are also several problems
about what implies hereditary a-realcompactness, also involving Diagram 2. Problem 7.
Is there a
m-realcompact but is sequential
(d)
(a)
ZFC
example of a compact space which is not hereditarily
Frdchet
(b)
~0-bisequential
Example 3.10 includes a construction using ~ Problem 8. ~-realcompact?
(c)
hereditarily
wD
and
such that every pseudocompact subspace is compact? that satisfies all these properties.
Is there a weakly first countable compact space which is not hereditarily not Radon?
not hereditarily weakly 8-refinable?
143
Here I do not know of any consistency results, not even under large cardinal hypotheses, nor am I aware of bounds on the cardinality of weakly first countable compact spaces. It is quite easy to show that every realcompact space is =-realcompact [Caution:
[DY]"
the collection of all zero-sets in a closed ultrafilter with the c.i.p, is not
always a
Z-ultrafilter, but that is all right:
compare the proof of 2.3 below.]
For
compact spaces satisfying these properties hereditarily, we have an interesting interpolant, 2.3.
independently noticed by Reznichenko and myself.
Theorem.
Proof.
Let
Every compact, hereditarily realcompact space is bisequential.
Y
ultrafilter on
Y
be hereditarily realcompact and compact. converging to a point
F = {F e U: Then
F
F
extends to a unique
disjoint zero-sets such that continuous function such that
y.
Let
is a zero-set of
Z1
X = Y - {y}
Z-ultrafilter
for
H
in
Z 0.
be a free
and let
X.
Indeed, if
F,
let
It is now easy to see that
i,
and so
Zi,
i=O,l
f: X ~ [0,I]
i=0,1 [G3, 1.15].
a base for an ultrafilter that can only converge to is disjoint from
U
X}.
meets every member of
f~Z i = {i}
Let
The image of fell/2,1[
H = {Z ~ Z: Z O F # #
are
be a UIX
is in
is
F
and
for all
F e F}. H
is free because
are all in
H.
intersection.
For each
F n = Cly hi=in f~[0,~] • of
Y
y
has a base of zero-set neighborhoods in
So there is a countable descending family n,
let
Then
H n = f~[O}
A~= I F n = [y}
for a continuous and each
Y
{Hn}~_ I,._
Fn
with empty
H
fn: X ~ [0,1].
is in
as in [E, proof of 3.3.4], we see that the filterbase
and their traces
in
U.
Let
Using compactness
{Fn}n= I
converges to
y.
Hereditary realcompactness is not affected by adding one point, so Theorem 2.3 extends to locally compact spaces. 2.4.
Theorem.
Proof.
Let
Every compact bisequential space is hereditarily =-realcompact.
Y
be a compact space.
there is a free closed ultrafilter regularity) adherent point. extending it converges to in
F,
so we can pick
Let subset of
N
Then y.
x e X
Let
F F
So
Y
Let
is a filterbase on Un
U
for each
Y,
n e ~.
X
y e Y - X
of
Y
on which
be its unique (by
and any ultrafilter The sets
U
(clyUn) N X
are
in their intersection.
be a closed neighborhood of N.
Suppose there is a subspace with the c.i.p.
y
that misses
x.
None of the
Un
can be a
is not bisequential.
Theorem 2.4 does not extend to locally compact spaces. bisequential, as is any first countable space, but not
The ordinal space
oh
is
~-realcompact.
Bisequentiality also interposes between hereditarily realcompactness and another Classification C property: 2.5.
Theorem [A3, in effect].
subspace is compact.
In a compact bisequential space, every pseudocompact
144
Proof.
Theorem 6' of [A3] states:
for any
x G X
and any filterbase
{Pn}~=l_
of regular closed subsets of
meets every member of
~.
Now if
E
Y
A (regular) space is bisequentlal if and only if with X
which we may take to be
which converges to
P
C-decreasing.
intersection of the closures of the
as an adherent point, there is a sequence and such that every
x
is a pseudocompact subspace of
closure, the set of all,lnteriors of the Y
x
Pn'
X
with
x
Pn in its
trace a sequence of relatively open sets on n Then [GJ,9.13] there is a point of Y in the
and this must be
x.
Thus
Y
is closed.
Also hereditary realcompactness interposes between bisequentiality and another classification 2.6.
A
property:
Theorem [GJ, 8.15]
Every first countable realcompact space is hereditarily
realcompact. And so we have the implications => in the following diagram, spaces.
again for compact
The other arrows have the same meaning as in Diagram 2.
f i r s t countable realcompac t
bisequential
H. wD and
\\
\\
H. ~-metacompact
pseudocompact ~
sUb o Z'dre /
~ ~/// H. ~-realcompact Problem 9.
Eberlin compact
Diagram 3
If a compact space has no discrete subspace of measurable cardinality,
it bisequential if it is (a) Eberlein compact?
(b)
hereditarily
is
~-metacompact?
Note that the one-point compactification of a discrete space of measurable cardinality is not even hereditarily
=-realcompact,
but it is Eberlein compact.
clear from Rosenthal's characterization of Eberlein compacta [Ro]: the compact spaces F -sets.
K
which admit a
a-point-flnite,
If one inserts "weakly" in front of
To-separating cover by open
"v-point finite" here, one has Sokolofffs
characterization of Gul'ko compact spaces [So]. And if one has "point-countable" instead, one has the Corson compact spaces [MR].
3.
That is
they are precisely
Counterexamples. We begin this section with a space van Douwen felt could supplant the more
complicated Tychonoff plank in most elementary texts.
145
3.1
Thomas's plank.
Let
W
its one-point compactificatlon. where the underlying set of X
W
be an uncountable discrete space and let Let
X = (W + ~) x (~ + 1).
W + ~
denote
Thomas's plank is the case
is the set of real numbers.
is not hereditarily normal.
corner point does not satisfy
wD.
In fact, the subspace
Y
obtained by removing the
Indeed, no infinite set of points
expanded to a discrete collection of open sets.
Afortiori,
X
can be
is not hereditarily
realcompact. On the other hand,
X
is both bisequential and Eberlein compact.
the significance of the classes of
productive and hereditary [Hil] , [A4]. countably productive:
Indeed, part of
(~'¢0-)bisequential spaces is that they are countably The "Banach" classes of compacts are also
see [AL| for Eberlein compacta and [ ] for Gul'ko compacta.
For
Corson compacta it is trivial. Since every separable subset of
X
is metrizable, it is a
v-space.
Fr~chet but not first countable, it is not weakly first countable. then
X
Since
X
If we make
is
IXI = ~I'
is Radon.
3.2.
Alexandroff's "two arrows".
order topology.
Let
As is well known [E,
X = [0,I] x {0,I}
] [SS],
X
with the lexicographical
is hereditarity separable and
hereditarily Lindel6f, so that it satisfies all the Classification C and E properties. Since every discrete subspace is countable,
X
is Radon.
Since
X
is first countable,
it also satisfies the Classification A properties. On the other hand,
X
satisfies none of the "Banach" properties since it is
separable and nonmetrizable. 3.3.
The Hr6wka-lsbell ¥(+~).
Let
family (HADF) of infinite subsets of topologized by letting the points of a base for the neighborhoods of
A
A
~. ~
be an infinite, maximal almost disjoint The underlying set of
is
e U A,
be isolated and letting {{A} U (A-n): n e e}
for each
be
A e A.
AS is well known [GJ, Exercise 5I] and easy to prove, pseudocompact.
T
T
is locally compact, and
Being a countable union of closed discrete subspaces, it is hereditarily
(weakly) 8-refinable, and so is
T + %
the one-point compactification.
On the other
hand, no separable non-LindelSf space can be metalindel6f, and it is even more obvious that
{~} U {A U {A}: A e A}
has no point-finite open refinement.
T + ~
satisfies none
of the "Banach" properties for the same reason as 3.2. T + ~ sequential: A
is not Fr~chet since no sequence from unless a subset of
e
~
converges to
®.
But it is
has compact closure, it has infinitely many points of
in its closure, and these have a sequence converging to
~
since
A U [~}
is the
one-polnt compactification of a discrete space. From the discussion surrounding Yakovlev's space (3.11) it will be evident that T + ~
is not weakly first countable.
It is Radon whenever
c
is not real-valued
measurable.
Special versions of it are Radon even in models where
measurable.
In fact, as far as I know, no negative answer is known to:
c
is real-valued
146
Problem i0.
Is
a,
the least cardinality of an infinite HADF of subsets of
~,
always less than the least real-valued measurable cardinal? Eric van Douwen [vD] has called a space
Y-like if it is locally compact, has a
countably infinite dense set of isolated points, and the nonisolated points are a closed discrete subspace. x
If
x
is a nonisolated point and
in which all other points are isolated,
is clopen and the sets disjoint family.
N x N W,
where
W
Nx
is a compact neighborhood of
then the Hausdorff condition tells us each is the set of isolated points,
It is maximal iff the space is pseudocompact [vD, 11.6].
Conversely,
any almost disjoint family of infinite subsets of a countable set gives rise to a space as a MADF gives rise to
Nx
form an almost
T-like
V.
Every one-point compactification of a
V-like space is hereditarity weakly
O-refinable, being a countable union of (closed) discrete subspaces, but not hereditarily metalindelBf if the space is uncountable. 3.4.
The Cantor tree + ~.
of height
w + 1
Let
T
denote the Cantor tree, i.e. the full binary tree
with the interval ("tree") topology.
nonmetrizable, hence not metalindelSf.
Unlike
V,
fact, it has a coarser compact metric topology, = {t': t' > t}
where
t
It is a
V-like space and is
it is hereditarily realcompact.
In
for which a base is the set of wedges
is on a finite level of
T,
and their complements.
Vt
And any
space with a finer topology than a first countable realcompact space is hereditarily realcompact [GJ, 8.17]. Todorcevic' has pointed out that coarse wedge topology",
T
with this latter topology, which I call "the
is "really" the tree of all initial segments (which he calls
"paths") in the full binary tree of height discussion of this theme, see [Grs].
m,
with the product topology.
For a fuller
In [NY7] I show a very natural embedding of
T
with this topology in the plane, with the points of the top level topologically identified with the Cantor set. Thus
T + =,
bisequential,
with
etc.
In
T
[NY7]
topology, that it is not a top level of
T
having the interval topology,
I show, u s i n g t h e B a i r e c a t e g o r y theorem on t h e c o a r s e r
v-space.
Also [ibid.], if one removes all points from the
except those corresponding to a
k'-set [Mi2] and then takes the one-
point compactification of what remains, one has a 3.5. of
~i
Let
T
Give
The Todorcevic-Gruenhage space. and let
T
is hereditarily realcompact,
Let
S
w-space. be a stationary, co-stationary subset
be the tree of all compact subsets of
S,
ordered by end extension.
be obtained by adding a point at the end of each branch (maximal chain) of T
the coarse wedge topology (see 3.4).
compact, hence so is Radon if
c
~2,
but
~2 _ ~
is not weakly
is not real-valued measurable.
paracompact, hence it t h e Thomas p l a n k ( j u s t
is hereditarily
In [Gr5] it is shown that O-refinable;
It is also shown that
realcompact, etc.
However,
t a k e t h e s u b s p a c e of p o i n t s of l e v e l
sized subset in each copy).
< 1
T
also that T
@2
T.
is Corson ~2
is
is hereditarily
c o n t a i n s a copy o f
and an a p p r o p r i a t e -
On t h e o t h e r hand, Gruenhage m e n t i o n s a f i r s t
147
countable variant,
and t h a t has a l l c o u n t a b l e powers f i r s t
c o u n t a b l e and so h e r e d i t a r i l y
realcompact, etc. 3.6.
Reznichenko's space.
d i s c o v e r e d i n 1987.
Gruenhage.
This i s a s p a c e w i t h some amazingly s t r o n g p r o p e r t i e s ,
Uspensky p r i v a t e l y communicated a d e s c r i p t i o n
i n E n g l i s h to
Since a full treatment is not likely to appear in print in English anytime
soon, I thought it worthwhile to at least give the definition here. Define sets A With
A8
For each as e A a
and F8
finite sets
defined for all
F
for
B < ~,
= {as: S
F
let
{k
A = U {Aa: ~ < e l } ,
as follows.
Note t h a t the s e t s by i n c l u s i o n .
= U {Fs: ~ < ~},~ A= = U [As: 8 < a}.
C = U~=0 Cn.
|A] 1 U 0
F:}
with
F
Or r a t h e r ,
Tn = {k G F : n e k }
a r e added, the r e s u l t i n g
r e g a r d e d as a s u b s e t o f l e t us r e g a r d
B of
showed t h a t
~
2A
in
2A, t o p o l o g y and
subspace
form a p a r t i t i o n
of UB,
Cn
of
topology is the coarse
2A
is closed.
I t i s not hard to s e e t h a t
C U [A] 1
and each i s a t r e e
c o n v e r g e s to t h e p o i n t Its
By a theorem o f Gruenhage -e[Gr5]~ Cn
i s G u l ' k o compact.
F
Tn
~=
He a l s o showed t h a t
and i f t h e s e p o i n t s
i s E b e r l e i n compact.
C U [A] 1 U 0,
i s t h e o n e - p o i n t c o m p a c t i f l c a t i o n of the d i s c r e t e
Cech c o m p a c t i f i c a t i o n o f
define new elements
F~,
A.
Each b r a n c h
wedge ( " p a t h " ) t o p o l o g y .
A0,= ~, FO = [~]I.
as
F = U {F : a < e l } ,
as t h e power s e t o f
Let
F
is a disjoint sequence in
U {as}: n e ~ ,
t h e n a t u r a l way, w i t h the p r o d u c t t o p o l o g y . all,
a < ~i
~v-sequence s = < kS: n eel> of disjoint members of n with as # as, if s # s'. Let A
Let
and
subspace
and o f c o u r s e [A] 1.
Reznichenko
8(C U [A] 1) = ~, i . e .
i s the o n e - p o i n t c o m p a c t i f i c a t i o n !
Thus
the StoneC U [A| 1
i s pseudocompact (and noncompact). Of a l l
the r e s u l t s
i n t h i s s u r v e y , t h i s was f o r me the most u n e x p e c t e d .
I was
f a m i l i a r w i t h t h e c o n s t r u c t i o n s o f A. Berner [Be] and H.-X. Zhou | Z h ] , which gave s p a c e s w i t h s i m i l a r p r o p e r t i e s under the axioms little role of
a=c
and
b=c
respectively,
and t h e r e seemed
hope o f c a r r y i n g out e i t h e r c o n s t r u c t i o n or a n y t h i n g r e s e m b l i n g i t Cn
was taken o v e r i n Z h o u ' s c o n s t r u c t i o n by the Cantor s e t ,
c o n s t r u c t i o n by a f i r s t
" i n ZFC".
The
in B e r n e r ' s
c o u n t a b l e compact s p a c e i n which e v e r y s e t o f c a r d i n a l i t y
< c
was nowhere d e n s e , and in both c a s e s the r e s t of the s p a c e was the o n e - p o i n t
compactification of a discrete space, with the whole space minus the extra point being pseudocompact.
Their spaces, however, were built by transfinite induction, like the
well-known examples of Ostaszewski [OSl], Juh~sz, Kunen, Eudin [JKR], and many others, including 3.8 and later examples below.
These constructions leave room for a lot of
optional details, whereas Reznichenko's space, as can be seen, is really just one space. (Of course, it is easy to construct variations on it.) Another difference is that Zhou's space is separable, and Berner's seems inevitably to involve separable pseudocompact noncompact subspaces, while in Reznichenko's space,
148
every countable subset has metrizable closure.
Nevertheless, until I saw it, I would
have guessed that the classes "Fr~chet" and "every pseudocompact subspace is compact" were destined for another independence result. 3.7.
Peter Simon's "barely Fr4chet" compacta.
This is a pair of one-point
compactifications of
V-like spaces whose properties are intermediate between those of
and the Cantor tree.
On the one hand, their one-point compactificatlons fail to be
but on the other hand they are Fr~chet, and compactness gives
o~3,
=4"
The product of the two spaces fails to be Fr4chet}on the other hand, the product of an
~3-Fr~chet and a countably compact Fr4chet space is Fr4chet [A4, 5.16], thus both
compactifications fail to be
~3"
These properties of Simon's spaces answer quite a few
questions in [A4]: 5.21, 5.22.1, 5.22.4, 6.12, 6.13, 6.14. There is a close interplay between the construction and Y-like space, with continuous Y + ~
its set of isolated points.
~ Y + =,
is Fr~chet iff
family PI'
f: ~
~
P
f+(Y-~)
of subsets of
such that
with
~
taken onto
(Y-e) U [®}.
is regular open in
~ .
Y ~
be a noncompact induces a
Malyhin [Ma] showed that
Simon was able to find a MAD
which was the disjoint union of two subfamilies
U {A* : A ~ Pi}
denotes the remainder of
~0"
~ko. Let
The identity on
was a regular open subset of
A, i.e.
(cl B~0A) - m.]
~0"
for
PO
i=O,l.
and
[Here
A*
In other words, here we have two
families of disjoint clopen sets, with the union of each family regular open, and the , union of these two regular open sets dense in ~ . It is the fact that the union of these two regular open sets is not regular open that is behind the product of the associated spaces not being Fr~chet. I have called this setup "Petr Simon's checkerboard", with the remainder of each A G PO
a "red square" and that of each
A ~ PI
a "black square".
One might paraphrase
Simon's closing note in [Sil] by saying that every infinite MAD family traces a "checkerboard" on the remainder of some infinite subset of 3.B.
~.
A consistent (b=c) example of a compact w-space which is not
We begin with a ZFC construction which, like the an uncountable
~-bisequential.
k'-modification of the Cantor tree, is
V-like space whose one-point compactification is a w-space.
It is the
example "For later use" in [vD, 12.2], but used for a different purpose there. The set of isolated points is
m×m,
and the ADF is the set of all columns
together with the set of the graphs of a {f : = < b}
of increasing functions
order, i.e.
f 5 a n d i f
then there is W C_ F M T~ such that ~ • W ~
a < fl are in C a n d S •
F N T ~n
~ > ~, and if ~ and ~r are distinct elements of
W then { ~ ( t ) : t • n - G} is disjoint from {Ygt(t):t • n - G}, and for all ~ • £ we have ~(t) • bt for t • G, and W is infinite unless G -- n. A is a finite rectangle if fi_ is a finite sequence with A(i) C_ wt finite for i • dom(.4). V ( ~ , f , A ) iff (Vi < lh(~) = lh(A))(Vy _< ~(i))(f(y) ~ A(i)).
( f , S ) fulfills F iff whenever ~ • r M T a and /3 • C(F) and ]l a finite rectangle, then there is W C_ r n T ~ °' such that W is infinite unless G = n and if ~ and ~ are distinct elements of W then { ~ ( t ) : t • n(£) - G(F)} fq { ~ ' ( t ) : t • n(F) - G(F)} = 0 and, for all ~ • W, _> # and (¢2(#, f, .4) ===~ £)(~, f, A)). For b an uncountable branch of T, we let C2(b,f,F) iff (Vx • b)~)(x, f, F). M a i n D e f i n i t i o n . ( f , S , 3/,g2) • P iff:
( f , S , N ) • Q and • is a countable set of promises
that ( f , S ) fulfills, and if {wl M 3/(/~):fl < a} is unbounded in "~ • S* then a • dora(N) and 3/(a) =
U~ p0 _> pl _> ... such that pi E M and p2~+1 E D , and {Pm:m E ~} is bounded below by some q E P, and in choosing P2n+2 we either have P~,~+2 IF "9 E A , " for some Y < x,~, or we have taken certain steps, described below, towards ensuring q f~- "~, ~ -4n ." Unlike the situation in Iemma 3, we need not have fq defined on T~; however, we still must take steps to ensure that each F E Ume~ ~ w is fulfilled at level 6. Thus, at stage n, we assign finitely many finite sets Fo . . . . Frn. C_ 6 to nodes Xo. . . . , zm. in T~ and declare that fpk (Y) ~ Fi for all y < xi and all k < w. We do this according to our ordering of ( ~ m , F m , . ~ ) (doing nothing, of course, if r ¢
or ht(~ n) > ht(p.) or - ~ ( ~ ,
h . , fi*~)) thereby causing each promise in UnE~ ~v- to
be fulfilled at level 6, The restrictions thus imposed do not hinder us from choosing P2~+1 E D,~ by lemma 3; however, they introduce a further complication towards choosing P2.+2. What we require is the following claim: Claim: Suppose ~ E T ~ and fi~ C_ 6 m a finite rectangle and c3(~,f v. . . . . fi~), and ~ # < ~ and h t ( ~ #) = ht(p2.+l). Then either:
(*) (3q < Pzr,+l)(~y < x.)(ht(q) < 6 and c2('~,fq,fi~) and q IF- "~) E ~{."); or (**)
m ~(..:.::, is comparable to ~ # x,~ E Y = {y E T*:(3~* E T ht(y)jxw
and (Vq < p2,~+,)(if
ht(q) = ht(y) and q)(~*, fq,.~i) then there is a promise r such that o(F) = ht(q) and (fq,S~, J¢~,
• ~ u {r}> t~ "9 ~ 2 . ' ) } . We show that the claim implies the lemma. Suppose (*) holds and q _< P2.+~ and y < x,~ witness (*). Then certainly (~q' _< p ~ + l ) ( h t ( q ' ) = ht(q) and ~)(~',fq,,A) where ~ ' < E and ht(E') = ht(q') and q' It- "9 E ~{,~'); and since ht(q') and ~ ' are in M, we may take P~n+~ to be such a q' in M. If instead (**) holds, we set p~+~ = p:.+~ and we take ~* to be a witness to (**) and demand that h~ (Y) ~ A(i) whenever y < E ' ( i ) and k E w. Having done so, we know by (**) that there is F,~ such that (Ukeo~ fv~, Uke~ SPk, UkEw ~;'~' Ukew ~P~ U {F~}) I~- "~r~ ~ An;" thus, taking q = (U f w , U sp~, U Nw, U kop~ u {F,~: (**) holds at stage 2n + 1}), we satisfy the demands of the lemma. Thus, it suffices to prove the claim. Proof of claim: Suppose (*) fails and y < x,~. We show that y E Y; by choice of x,~ (i.e.,
(VX E N ) ( x . E X ==~ (~y < x . ) y E X)) this suffices. In fact, we show that the unique ~*
ht(q') such that ~ ( ~ ' , fq,, A). Since ~ ' E A, there is no r _< q~ with ht(r) < ht(~') and ~ ( ~ , f~,_A) and r IF "~) • -4n;" but q' witnesses the opposite, a contradiction. Thus q+ 11- "~ ~ An" and we are done. We have proved: T h e o r e m 2. Con(ZFC + ~ is inaccessible) iff Con(ZFC + CH + there is an Aronszajn tree T* and a stationary co-stationary S" such that T* is S-*-special iff S - S* is non-stationary, and every wl-tree is S*-*-special).
References
[Sa}
Baumgartner, James, "Iterated Forcing," in Surveys in Set Theory, A. R. D. Mathias (ed.), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 87, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983.
[DJ}
Devlin, K. J., and H. Johnsbr£ten, The Souslin Problem, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 405, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974.
[Schll
Schlindwein, Chaz, Club Sandwich Forcing, PhD. thesis, University of California, Berkeley, 19xx.
[Sch2] Schlindwein, C., "Proper Forcing, Aronszajn Trees and the Continuum," 19xx.
[sh]
Shelah, Saharon, Proper Forcing, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 940, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1982.
[To]
Todorcevic, Stevo, "A Note on the Proper Forcing Axiom," in Axiomatic Set Theory, J. Baumgartner, D. A. Martin, S. Shelah (eds.), Contemporary Mathematics, rot. 31, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, 1984.
Consistency o f positive partition theorems f o r graphs and models by
Saharon Shelah
Department of Mathematics Rutgers University New Brunswick N.J.U.S.A.
Institute of Mathematics The Hebrew University Jerusalem, Israel
Recently A. Hajnal, P. Komjath [I] have dealt with the partition relation H ~ (G)~ :
if we colour the edges of a graph
induced subgraph isomorphic to the same colour). consistent (with for no graph
G
H
by
~
which is monochromatic
ZFC) that there is a graph
G
of
cardinality
R1
such that
H : H ~ (Gi~ .
is consistent.
We g i v e h e r e an a f f i r m a t i v e
answer (even for much stronger partition relations). class of measurable cardinals (in §I, §2). We can also generalize
result
(i.e. all edges get
They prove (generalizing a proof from Shelah [2]) that i% is
They a s k w h e t h e r t h e n e g a t i o n
morphism of
colours, there is an
N
in which only
([3],[4])
like
discussed elsewhere.
2
R0
M ~ (N) 8(*) < 81
We first prove it using a
In §3, §4 we eliminate this. to
rNl ~ , t h e n we h a v e t o a d d i n f o r m a t i o n So we h a v e f i n i s h e d Secondly,
the case
we a s s u m e
6 J
u C {aj
satisfying
and
E ~p •
for
i < c .
and
v E [u] sup(~jln aj2n M~) = sup(~jN M{j~})
of
if
is
has only two members. Assu~e
to which of the three possible equalities holds) or to
F(Cjl,Cj2)
is strongly inaccessible.
178
[Proof:
Note that all
If each
~i
singular,
fl(6)
cf(a i) E M{i }
realize the same type in
is singular, there is is a club of
clearly
6
Let
fl E M~
cf(6) •
hence for some
f2 E M#
8
onto
As
#
(in the model
and
cf(~i) < @i
6 < A
of cofinality
fl(6) . So easily
fl(@i) N M{i } = fl(ai) N M~ = {f2(@i)(7) : 7 E 8 n M#} ; w.l.o.g, definable over
6 < A
8 E M~ ,
be such that for
is a one-to-one function from
(H(x),E,< ~) •
such that for
of order type
cf(~ i) E ~
(Vi < ~)[cf(~ i) = 8] . 8,f2(6)
~i
(H(X),6, n -I _
then
. . . 1
n > I)
(M,A)
I , s o there is
Choose
For
(~+l)-Mahlo and
by a predicate for n = 1 .
n .
A
= ~ , ~ , (M;i } : i E B)
(Hs, t : [s[ = Itl ; s,t E [B] ~2)
and
W
such that:
+
(a)
6 < A , cf~
(b)
B
is a subset
actually (c)
=~
.
of
b u t then
Ms ~L M ~,~
for
6
of order
M{maxB} s E [B] 2
type
~ + (we c o u l d g e t
~+ + i ,
i s not d e f i n e d ) . and
M{i} ~L
M{i} ~L ~,~
M ~,~
for
i E B
and
184
Me ~2
so
there
+M
are regular and
where = 8
A
is inaccessible
D .
by any fragment of
I1%11
6 .
"
We can instead " A = 8 + " assume
Similarly for
8 , (or at least
is increasing converging to
~{i},{j}(~l)
L D,a
then ~#
, ~e = min{~ 6 W : Be < ~} , ~l # ~2 ' and
(2)
Let
and
o Hs0,sl)
eM{i )-r~,ieB, ~:min{~ : ~ e w , ~ < ~ }
If
Mt
onto
S
M{i,k ) = M(i ) ,
Hs,t(fl) = 7
and
M
B
(~)
Proof:
H s0's2
mops
s,t
Mfi,j }
3.8A
and
H
(a)
(c)
is an isomorphism from
M{j} .
are compatible;
from
, M~ fl B = ~ .
IMoI .
is a model
Let
. ~ :
m'.
Now we can find
and
(q~ : ~ < k(*)) such that
190
(i)
q~ E Mt£
(iii) hto,ti(q) ( q~ if qO El ~ q, E Mt
(iv) for £1 < £2 < k(*) we have: 0 q£2 -< q" E M t£1 and q' I M~ = q" r M~
then we can find
[Why? We define, by induction on i < k(*),
and
£0
r as above. such that
(q~,i : £ < i} satisfies (i),(ii),(iii),(iv) above with the natural restrictions.
For
i = 0 , q~,O = qo ' For
i = j+1 apply the assertion above
(before I. - 6.) so with ht£,to(q~'J ) here standing for q there; get there r and
let q~,i = htoUtl,tjUti(r t Mtl) q~,i = htoUtl,tjUti(r ~ Mto) ,
and for £ < j, q~'i = q~,j . In the end let q~ = q~,k(*)-i .
Let
{(~E,7£) : £ < (k~*)) = m}
list the increasing pairs.
by induction on E < (k~*))
{q~ : ~ < 1.
El
£2
q~ ~q~
for £ 1 ~ £ 2
z. q~ e st~ 3.
4.
q£
= q£
E r
r £+1 "HE
s.
r~,7 r Mt < £
s.
r~,~ F ~ ( ~ , % ) = ¢0
k(*)) ,
r~£,7E such that:
Now we define
191
7.
If
e~.l
i s an edge o f
r~.,75" 1
(MtgE. x MtgE. ) U (Mt
x Mt 7[.
I
then 8.
I
eN,e I If
7 g
7[.
I
not in 1
) U {(W~ ,WT~.)} for i I
6 0 ~ £I
have no vertex in common.
{~,~}
then edges(q~+l) = edges(q~)
Now we d e f i n e dom q =
U
edges o f
dom q ~ U U
E+I
~ M~) .
is tailor-made for this.
dom
q = union o f the s e t o f edges o f
k(*) +I ~
,~
.
is connected.)
are pai~ise compatible.)
The least trivial is to show be a set of
q~ , r
dom r~ ,7 \(Mt U My ) i i Hi 7i
(Note that the q~ . ~ . ~
Assume that
.
edges(qot [
U
q :
(Note that any node in
~
and
I
There is no problem in this - qo
Let
i E 0,I
Kk(,)+l
is not embeddable into
q .
vertices.
is a complete graph fin
q) and we shall derive a
contradiction. I f we omit the edges
{(~i,~j):
i < j < k(*)}
from
q , the resulting
graph is o b t a i n e d by s u c c e s s i v e e d g e l e s s amalgamation (look a t the r e s t r i c t i o n to
i
$ the first measurable. Shelah showed it consistent with GCH that there exist an example of size R2, and, assuming the consistency of a weak compact, the consistency with CH that there exists no example of size R2. One certainly expects that a supercompact should suffice to obtain the consistency of there being no examples of size greater than RI, but as usual, the difficulty is in proving a suitable preservation lemma. All one needs to know about this problem appears in [J]. Shelah's example (reworked and improved in [HJ2]) is a graph constructed by forcing or by a morass with built in o. Definition. L(X) = min{~: every open cover of X has a subcover of cardinality
_ K, an SC can never be cub.
Theorem 1.5
NS ~I B is set-normal for any SC,B, and under the hzpothesis theft
P ~ has an unbounded subset of size ~, every set normal ideal extends ~I~S~
-'i