This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
is
-(-chain.
(E 2)
is o b v i o u s .
and ~yy, (y) = y'. N o w d e f i n e
~ y
y 6 ~yT, (X)
=
is n o r m a l
and < ~ y Normality
~ y = id
yy'
X 6 U7 (4) Uy
f~ ~,,
, Uy >
is a m e n a b l e
To p r o v e
y < y'
.
amenability
set U n = U
•
T
It s u f f i c e s
to s h o w t h a t U n 6 ~ But this T Y" O Z - d e f i n a b l e from ~yy, and U nY 6 0 ~ y ÷ .
Since
that z yy'
~
7,
: < ~
N O W set
< < o Z y , Uy >
Y
is i m m e d i a t e
since U n is Y
n = U ny, of U n is u n i f o r m we get ~yy, (Uy) Y is c o f i n a l we have:
the d e f i n i t i o n
So o b s e r v i n g
(5)
N ~n Y
, Uy>
,
T* = sup I ,
, < ~yy.
, ,
U
, >
I* = I U {y*}. C l e a r l y , O~y, ~ O ~
[ y £ I >
I Y 6 I > , < Zyy,
since ef(IIl)
~ and:
62
X 6Uy~
Our
next
.
aim
~ X 6 ~y
is to s h o w
(7) ? (y) D
and
that
M Y { ~n
3 y< y*
I -yc_X
(gZy 6 M Y
for
. We n e e d
first:
y 6 I ,n
for (~.
NY .
the p r o o f
such
~yy, (~y)
= ~y, .
fl j U y ~ J~Y ~+i Hence
Set
there
methods
is a
Z l(NY)
since
it is
'
N Y is a m o u s e ,
be a r e c u r s i v e
By s t a n d a r d
that
of L e m m a 1.3. U O~y 6 J~+l ¥ "
enumeration (cf.
the
of the proof
of
first
63
Lemma and C~y
1.2),
if ~
By
one
v 6X i Y
, ~
~i(~'~)
the
for
Now
I'
set
f o r C Tt,
~
=
' (]rAy b
< ~>
X i 6 N Y such Y
that
Xi £ U Y Y
, < ~ >
6 [ X i - ~ in Y
, then
~ i ( ~' T%) "
choice
i i~< ~ X Y*
is
O~y~
we
"
have
Then
~
OZ.
a mouse.
So
Before is
and
choose
Zyy,(X$)
=
X y, i
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
y < y'
since
N Y~
canonically
< v
canonical
y 6 x y, i
since
may
But
I'
and was
I' 6 K is
proceeding
a natural
I ~I'
further
prewellordering
is
defined
the
let
of
I'
the
set
us
good
for
OZy~
from
N Y*
and
we
were
remind
mice
is
hence
N Y*
£ K,
looking
for.
reader
that
the
which
,
defined
there
as
follows
M
It
is
~ N
shown
iff
in
M 8 6 N8
[4
] that
where
~
@ >M,N
restricted
is
to
regular.
the
core
mice
is
a well-
ordering. We
often
use
Let ~
(¥)
M
D
Our = K.
(cf.
the
HM
= KM
~,T
is
1
Then be
regular.
of
if an
which
It
M
is
is
satisfy
easily
seen
critical,
iterative
of
M
then at
M,
. Hence
model
models
H M< 6 M .
that,
if M. '
W
this
iff
M.
HM < H i <
Let
all
[ 4])
w.
a structure
w1-Erd~s
that
and
application
conjecture
show
immediate.
following
there
proved
is
< is
Then
a model
r be
in w h i c h
proposed
Let
where
1
1
hand
and
~ = w2, ~'
= ~.
starting Kunen
from
showed
existence
of O #.
We
strengthen
in S i l v e r ' s
result
cannot
be
weakened.
Theorem
1.7:
Assume
~-Erd~s
in K.
Proof:
Let
A6~(~)
a good
set
of
fice,
Chang's
N K
and
conjecture.
set
indiscernibles
since
there
will
then
.
K < K ~+" P first By
two
un-
Chang's
P e n~'
Then
is c o u n t a b l e
and
con-
6B
6 ~'.
L e t b':
~-~
~
where ~
a n d b' (~) = ~ .
Our
choice
b' (e) = i s
U is
rug T ~ and g ~
a regularity
(y,~)-regular.
(~) < gT,(~)}.
sequence
Contradiction!
for
U and ~
< ~
for
~ 6 Y.
70
We model T s
return
to
of
+ V = K and
ZF-
: KT s
Case
the
main
Hence ~
I:
is
the
T 6 E
such
of
our
notion
KT c K S T
~ K +"
There
line
proof. of
We
mouse
note
is
that
absolute
KT
is
a
in
KT t
since
s
that
{s 6 C
IK T
J KT
} 6 U.
T Let
~
Set
W
be
be
tion
L e m m a
s Y i -> T
such
KT S
{aE
7s
and
Let
T 6 E,
. Then
~(~)
let
:+ 7~ < ~
2.4:
> T
Suppose -
M.. 1 that
KT
M
= M ~,
2.5: WN C
for
L,
a
since
are
IT 6 r n g
s
since
mouse
KT N s
7~ < ~
There T
K ~
AM, cy.
at
C
set
since
iterate
WN
and
otherwise
ME K { , ~
, s6
all
N
since
for
for
have
a6
the
Hence
and
Bi
7
S
T £ rng
KT ~
at
a
Let
M s with
if
T > T.
a c-~ ,
itera-
M is
= 7~}
, such ~
T: S
KT ~
6 >- ~ , y .
Let
N =
the
large
Let
~ < T
Since
since
contradicts
S
~T
a N f M i . Hence
and
T
of
.
= y s.
M 6K T
arbitrarily
~T S
and
~ < ~
a 6~(~)
- This
iterate
M exists.
N6
K
i-th
:+ i < s
~ l
not
We
M~ be 1
n K TmM ~ - -
then
Lemma
at
Then
N ~ M
~-th
that
7~-
AM, 6 Nc But
}. T h e n for each ~ £ W there is a core mouse s the ~-th iterate of M s is a mouse at a 7 < T . Let s
point
follows Then
such.
J K~
a mouse
Proof: a6
least
{~IK [ ~
Ms ~ K~ Ms
the
M ~ N.
KT
is
a
unique our
T 6 E
But
choice
such
of
K < +t
core
it
(N).
then
model
core
that
mouse
of
ZF-. with
an
M.
that
E U.
+ Proof: fine
Let T ~ 6 E,
~ < K f
. We
6 sT
show ~+
by
that
there
induction
is on
T > ~ ~ < K
with as
-
T~
=
the
least
{a6 WN CTI
T
such
that
T > T,~,
f~ (s) < T s } 6 U;
SUP ~ sup
{T
least
I~ < { a n d
i such
~6 C
that
. T
Let
T = sup
T ~ and
= {e6
C I
sup
T h e n C is c l o s e d Z
= {~6
T~ < f f
unbounded
= sum
{~16
(~) h a s
the
On>
NOW
is
Lemma
Set
2.6: that
Let
we
Z 6 U such
(a) T
~ E Z set
the y~
are
X6~(y~) This by
Lemma
We may
Set
Now
;f
let
This
some
shows
T = sum ~
_ ~a} 6 U. set
Xn
:
Then
Z =
{~ 6 Y N
and
,
fn* = ~ ( f
) . Then
~6
Xn
X* = z n
*
=
hence
pick
~
W-TIT 6 rna~ ~
{~If ~ (~) 6 f ~ ( v ) } , n+1 n
N ~ ~
where
N6
K=+.
T ~ T such
--
and
~(Xn )
T~_> @~} 6 U.
Let
and
*
*
{~I fn+1 (~) 6 f n ( V ) } ,
But
.
~
{~[T
that
~:
hence
*
fn+1(~)6
fn(~)
Contradiction!
Case In
2.2:
this
case
we
theorem
of
Un
normal
K
is
+
(K+) K =
K
actually
[ 3 ] it in
show
suffices K.
This
that
to is
U N L[U]
show
that
equivalent
is
is a m e n a b l e K the following
a
and
+ Claim:
There
are
arbitrarily
large
T <
.
+ Let For W
T
y < K
the =
moment,
{~ 6 C vT :
We
. We
first
~
shall let
PK T = K } 6 U. ~ T~
{X6~(a)nK
see
that
T 6 E be
T
there
arbitrary.
For
~ 6 W
is
T > y
Recall
satisfying
the
claim.
that
define:
I~(X)}.
show
WT = { ~ 6 WTIVT6 6~K} To
show
this
pick
T 6 E,
U. T ~ T.
Then
Y =
{6 6 W - I T 6 r n g
T}
6 U.
Let
a6
T
Let A
A
= o ~ U u0 ~M U u o
= ~
0 = ~ ~
z ~eq~
:]~s
= l~
~ON
£IIeU~ 7 ~M ~ M =
~
z0
pu~
:%~s
'eAT~ISUel]
ST
i0
alaq~ ,D9 ~
"~IOa
IeTOnXo
~q~
£eId
~
s~an~onx~s
~q~
'/ooxd
l~ ~
:1~
1o
'Z ~ {0} 9 i ao 7
~u~s~xd
~q%
uI
o~ 9 x
"g% 3 ]eq~
qons
co> I
sT
~a~N%
pu~
o~9
u~qm
~ ~sooq0"
ST
qons
~)q
pu~
x ~q~ 96A
1
n3 ql~>
A ~]!uT7 ~)
dns
1
( nuo)dns
e
~eq~
n3
X)
o>
" {~n 3 (~) ~0
•~ 9 { ~ =
I D3
~]
{g ~ [g > @ ( i ~ ) q } l -~no~
e UT
~IqeuTl~p-
= ~ u~q& = X 6"g
(g~)q}
ox~q~ %~S
'~>
oS
M
x u~q~
l~ U
~eq~
"~ uI
"s~Inu~xo7
{(x) T~
70
~ou~ H
= x qons x ~q
II~qs sT
~ ~
~AIS
I<X'T>}
:q
H
~.eq
= g~
:7oo~d
:OL'~
,D
~M
0 uaq&
uoI~ex~mnu~
[V]@q3x
0 ~ eq
H9
~oqs
papunoqun
~q;
~0 p u e O
~Iq~uIT~P-
]eq~
• ~D0
0 s!
" ~1 D ~-X
"X3 ~ ~q
eurmaq £ q
= 0 ~S ~ ~o7
"uo!%o~fIq
l
"F/3
'~umi~q
ZL
78
Lemma
2.11:
{sIT
Let
W 6 U,
f 6 ~6
cf(~) +.
Then
there
is T 6 E s u c h
that
> - f(e) } 6 U .
Proof:
Suppose
set
= {~ 6 W f l C ' I T ~ ~ < f ( ~ ) }
YT
not.
(b) (c)
above,
the
K many
predecessors
For
gT
~ 6W
are
let h and
define
pairwise
(mod U)
g
inject
f(a)
into
gT 6 6 ~ T
distinct
mod
(6 < T~,T 6 and v Then
= v
We
now
prove
C
T
we
(?B~) < B) •
then
,
get:
6 [C] n such
that
~ .
Let
f. 6 W, 1
f• :
~ , B , O n R M such iteration
~
Let
some
n. For
= ~o,~+B
(f)
Now define
(x 6 H)
that
only and
an
.
iterable
L~[M]
premouse
is a d m i s s i b l e .
set C = {Kili < ~}.
~ = ~M,a,B
n ~] , < ~ > and
f,
6 [C n 7] <w,
6 W such
1
that
f.
1
:
K
n
~
6 K such
that M,a,6
are
countable
in
is c o n s i s t e n t .
<M,~,B>
= b-l(e),
there
foregoing
is < M , e , 8 > 6 K + such
There
M , ~ , B 6 X. L e t b:
But M,~,8
of the
formula
be as in the
H~-~X
6 = b-l(6).
are
countable
is n o t h i n g
<M,~,8> 6 H L[Vo]= K0
where
lemma.
Let
H is t r a n s i t i v e .
Then
H = H~,~,~
in K +. We
claim
to be proved.
Otherwise
K
argument
. The
X ~ H,
same
~ = w in K + such
Set M = b - l ( M ) ,
and~,~,~ that
that
is c o n s i s t e n t .
< M , ~ , B > 6 K.
If K = K +,
K + = L [ V o] and shows
that M , e , 8
are
countable
K0
in K.
We
are n o w
and ~ = ~ M , ~ , 8 theorem part L~[a]
ready be as
to f i n i s h
in C o r o l l a r y
let 0~6 K be a m o d e l
of O i i s b A(a).
the p r o o f
transitive. It s u f f i c e s
Let
of ~ . a be
to show:
3.12. We m a y
of T h e o r e m By
the
assume
3.1.
Let M,~,8
Barwise compactness that
the ( ~ - i n t e r p r e t a t i o n
the w e l l
founded
of ~. T h e n
87
Claim:
L[a] ~ A(a)
Let ~' be the Z F - l a n g u a g e w i t h the c o n s t a n t ~ and ordinal c o n s t a n t s (~ £ On). Define a class S of ~ ' - s e n t e n c e s • Let 6 [C] n, fi 6 W, fl: Kn
~
6 [C N ~ ] n ~ < ~ > ~ < T > and L~[a] b ~(~(~)))
I n d i s c e r n i b i l i t y a r g u m e n t s show that this is a c o r r e c t d e f i n i t i o n and that (i) S is a consistent, (2)
r~(~)q 6
(3)
rBx ~(x) I 6 S
S
iff
d e d u c t i v e l y closed class of sentences
L~[a] b ~(~) iff
Bt £ T
where T is the class of (4)
rBx 6 On ~(x) I 6 S
Now l e t ~ b e
iff
for ~
)
of
algebra
(F(~) ,e,
otherwise,
have
show
T (b i
smallest
if
B has
to
~
to ( 2 a ° s + 1 )
< ~
with
, and
result
such
. Now by
choice
of
prin-
(P%0,z(~) l d >_ r =
. Thus,
below
all
~ ( x , y I .... ,yt ) 6 ~o set
By
existence
with
bounded M =
~
definable will
subsets
remain
can
now
be
so
that:
established:
2.3
Theorem:
(i)
For
all
finite
If
M ~
PA
(eiJi
sets
, M ~
[a,b]
e. 2 l
n
a < e 1• < b
< max(a,c)),
(I)
F
'
i+I
< max(a
¥x
, then
is
n 6 IN
there
is
a sequence
, satisfying
'
~0(x,y I . .• . . y t ) 6 M ~
there
c)
'
? , i°
n ~
thus
f(m)
its
~ g(m)) . We
S c
T
(the
so
graph
is
to
show
of
3.1),
< g(a)
that < ci(
c,
> g(m)) .
want
T
, a 6 IN , b = f(a)
total
~ g(c)
e i the
definition
of
ci, the
~ x)
i < k}
i K k, graph
"g(y)
of
g
, ~ x"
.
system
of
~ PA.
is
Now
~
function,
S U {c ~ c o } U { V x
the
~ T')
Vm
> n
a ~ d
arithmetical
M'
I'
dicting
total.
~ c O } U { Vx
a model
IN
B m
PA) :
g:IN
a recursive
6 IN
in
in
If
e o , . . . , e k 6 [a,b]
(IN , a , e ° .... ,e k)
abbreviating
:
B n £
be
Z1-definable g
(provability
< ci(~
this, If w e
M'
then had
~ g(c)
It-formula
g(c)
~ x) ]i 6 IN}
the
c
I' ~ d
by
= g(c) ^ d
and
M' l ~
< c
I ' ~Z
d
M'
consistent.
2.3,(ii),(3) , then
for
1
is
we
some
As
we
determine
had
(contra-
i 6 IN might
an
, since
have
added
o Th(IN ) t o 3.4
T'
, we
Corollary
obtain
(Paris,
Harrington)
: PA
U Th
(IN)
~
~
,
nI noting the
that
recursive
total
proof
there
is
2.3(ii) I ~
just
of
3.4:
M ~
for
, a 6 I < b
had
(Xl-formulas
I ~e
contradicts
M
Let b
£ M
models . If
~
of
were end
the minimality
of
f
(a+1) a
M ~
b'
(a+1) a a
there
is
with
. Hence
remark
any
~
extensions) b
the
IN . S i n c e
[a,b]
6 I
. By exceeds
, a 6 M ~
arithmetic)
to
I ~ Th 1 ( I N ) .
up
that
true
there
going
Th(IN)
so
of
totality
~b[O,b]
too.
PA
which
a ~
the
function,
a smallest (only
states
function
recursive
Second
we
a
I =
to
1.4
provably
N ~
a
. Thus
an
I c
[a,b']
M ~
[a,b']
I ~
~ a
~
, by
e ~
M
,
a (a+1) a,
(a+1) a
, and
by
'
167
Remark:
In
finable iff
Paris
function
there
graph
[2]
of
Y:MxM ~ M
is a n
I c M ~e
Y
a
countable
has M ~ PA
Y(a,b)
, then
indicator
M ~ PA
the
in PA,
and
for a l l
, which
which
sentence
the We
can
just
countable
be proved
MI,M 2 ~ PA
one has
MI ~
M3 ~e M2
. This
of
PA
system
formula
~
initial
segment
account,
in
in
by
of
a turns and D.
3.5 C o r o l l a r y : segments
{X c ~
o u t to b e Jensen
There
a nice
asked
are models
(up to i s o m o r p h i s m )
Let
determined
by
language
Define
M 2'
M I' {c i li 6 ~ of P A
S S y ( M I) = SSy(M2) , h e n c e
if
this
MI
part
of t h e
Note
that
for
any in
[5]
3 b 6 M I a z
, cf.
of o n e
. Since
Y(x,y)
for:
T' b e as in the p r o o f
countable.
in a n y
satisfies
in M } , t h e n
S S y ( M I) = S S y ( M 2)
an i n d i c a t o r
is an i n d i c a t o r
JX =
M 2 . Furthermore,
if t h e
for unprovability.
shows
>
that
but
by a r e s u l t
[4] t h a t
M I , is
parameters
, then
Ehrenfeucht
the
of
with
MI,M 2 ~ PA
M I'
also
: Y(a,b)
. He shows
, then with
c a n be r e p l a c e d
showed
a,b 6 M
, Thz1 (M I) ~ Th(M2) , S S y ( M I) = S S y ( M 2 ) ,
standard
Proof:
stated
M ~ PA
M I ~ M2,
H. F r i e d m a n
all
requiring
this
P A to be a d e -
V z H y
(c+I) c} c
If
I c M --e
M ~
defines Vx
latter
exploited
easily
for
for
, a 6 I < b
reading:
indicator
that
= max{cl[a,b]~
indicator-property any
such
, I ~ PA
indicator-property.
function
an i n d i c a t o r
Z1-definition
true but unprovable of the
defines
are mutually that
C--e MI' 2
U T'
substructure of
ThzI(MI)
are m u t u a l l y
M
M I ~ a , M 2 ~ ~ s.
~ Th(~)
the r e d u c t s
initial
of
, M I'
M I' , M 2' = ThzI(M2)
initial
to and
segments,
168
and
by
M I' l= T'
As theorem
a second that
PA
i~
~
3.6
Lemma:
provable
The
PA
is n o t
All
sentences
provable,
Let
us
but
for
now
this for
these.
Cf.
one
be
so
Theorem that
a
even
V x3
y[x,y]
(~+I)[
remark the
to
v xV
Ryll-Nardzewski's First
we
n
~
(n+1) n
being
provided
give
to
, n 6
IN , a r e
one
given
in
Wilkie)
, even
axiomatizable.
Remark:
By
using
3.6
is
[2].
fact,
3.7
:
For
S U Th
all
(~)
restricted
the
"from
i~ a
provable,
do
far
is
Ramsey
outside"
on
.
theorem
by
finite
are
Infinite
will
which
by
Paris
and
than
the
simpler
a corollamyof
S ~
PA
there
. In p a r t i c u l a r ,
2.3,(i)
is PA
n 6 is
not
n
truth-predicates,
induction
of
a proof In
El-sentences,
(Z)y
following
~I
finitely
~
induction
here
the
true
.
version
But
proved,
with
1.4
using
topic.
, being
y H z[x,y]
a definable
this
once
S I~ s
n
~
superscripts,
(Paris,
PA with
reprove
axiomatizable.
=
n
n
to:
can
e-incompleteness:
the
needs
for
game-theoretic
3.7
use
fixed [6]
can
an
H y[O,y]
that
2 . 3 , (i) Wilkie
we
.
mention
Theorem
of
sentences
are
s .
finitely
form
PA
~
application,
the
in
Proof:
, M2 b
the to
result
can
E -formulas
easily
for
be
fixed
extended r 6
r
does
not
Proof:
imply
Let
a finite
meters)
S
set
induction
all
be £
axioms in
such
i_~f (M, (ei) i E ~
the
a
n
a finite of
Eo-fOrmulas
contained a way ) b
subset
in
of
PA.
By
the
~(x,Yl,...,y S
(which
may
be
proof
of
t) m a t c h e s
2.3,(ii) with
assumed
without
(where
TF
the para-
that
PA U {c~
< ci+1 Hi 6 ~ }
U TF
is
,(3)
the
.
169
last
group
of
then
the
initial
Set
M b
Th(~
according [a,b]
~
to
% ~
the
. By
Remark:
the
As
Paris
model
models than
~
PA
(the
T
of
Proof: are
for
is
a model
Let
S
(eili
6 ~
of
so
(M,eo,...,ek) ~
the
in
number
in
F )
) models
M
S
for
Theorem:
There
not
even
with
such
are
.
S
, so
that
, hence (~)
nl [a,b']
, but
not
s
, n
~
(n+1) n n
would
means there
that are
whereas
not
3.8
segments
in models
of
initial
will
segments
imply
modelling
that
PA
in
, other
3.9, from
PA
nonexistence
paragraph
M ~ PRA
defined
, so in
model by
of
, as
same
~
ce M
argument
as
recursive
that
arithmetic)
(M' (ei)i encoded
of
an
PRA of
. By
( ~ , e o , . . . , e k)
recursive
a sequence
a set
T
of
2
(primitive
, ei 6 M
subset
S
on
~
has
b T
by
an
initial
seg-
Eo-indiscernibles.
3.2
and
S
. Hence,
. Using for
6 ~
PRA
~
~
b
a
there
for tro(~,x)
2 . 3 , (ii) ,(I) ,(2)
~ ~(x) yields
) as d e s i r e d .
3.9
,
with
, a ~ ei < b
U Th
I b
) contained
that ~
6 ~
TF
3.7
nonstandard
a finite
6 ~
element
S
6 ~
a natural
ei,i
initial
6 ~ )
6 ~
any
(eili
formulas
.
element,
extract
(eili
the
all.
(eili
which
be
6 ~}U
[2],
nonstandard
. Thus
Eo-fOrmulas
b
application
M
eo,...,e k
of
at
of
M ~ PRA,
< Ci+lii
any
we
3.1),
be
are
to
by
smallest
there
It-induction
any
a sequence
n
in g e n e r a l
models,
is
the
,
} satisfies i b' 6 I with
above
there
ment
6 M
~
induction
third
For
determined
in
present
Lemma:
M
restricted
pointSout
, are
the
3.1
< e
of
of
nonstandard
element
d
# ~
For
b
minimality
prefix-restricted which
of
2 P A U {c i
) ~
in
2.3, (i)
existence
contradict
T
, a 6 M ~
2.3, (i),
{d 6 Mi 3 i 6 ~
since
3.8
of
segment
), M
(n+1)~
(M' (ei)i 6 ~ I =
axioms
no
recursive
recursive addition.
nonstandard
models
of
PRA
,
170
Proof:
Let
M b PRA,
(M'((e)i)i I 6 ~
6~
, the
) b
T
proof
of
(*)
H x I Vx2...
Set
A =
of
Using
Hence PRA be
we
an
2.3,(ii)
G~del
take
initial ,(3)
numbers
one
e 6 M
segment
shows
a 6 M
as
the
but
on
n)
of
realizes
containing
induction
get
taken
the
3.8,
H x n ~(Xl,...,x
tr °
p(z) by
. By
so
I
that
that
given
for
any
by
(e) i
open
~
,
in
the
PA
set
formula
# ~
. For
of
language I b
M
iff
9(y)
that
the
A =
formula
{n
6 EO
there
3 x1 0
fixed
~ a
, tr
n
the
variables,
(3 e tr
E -truth-predicate n
gn:
(c,d,e)
~
~
~
g i v e n by (n)
[x,y]
~
(z+1) z
gn(a) be
tr
-
g b
the
with
3 e < b
n
relation
~
t h e n becomes
formula
saying:
gn(a)
(c,d,e)))
Hn-definable. ~
required
gn(min(X)) formula
a
n =
< Card(X)" ~
=
Let plus
Z
homogeneous
Ix,y]
E n
. The
(z+1) z
Z
"the
for
n
[x,y]
sets
X
(instead
of
z
(z+1) z)
can the
be
chosen
special
such
case
gn
that = id
in
the
. Set
(n) VxV
z 3y[x,y]
~
(z+1) z z
i
n
(n) is
then
a
Hn+2-sentence
, [x,y]
have
(z+1) z is z
a
H -formula. n
172
The paragraph
second
proof
3 generalizes
4.2 L e m m a : language
For
each
is an i n i t i a l
then
PA U Th
the
to
an
for
independence . First,
n 6 ~ :
of P A so t h a t
there
for
If
all
~
there
~(x,y,z)
a
given
is n o t h i n g
is a
M b PA:(if
substructure
(~)
of
new
in
En+1-formula
M k ~(a,b,c), I ~ PA,
I ~e M with
in
in the
c > ~ , then
I _ c M, n
a 6 I < b),
V x V z ~ y ~(x,y,z) .
~n+] Remark:
Such
indicator,
a
~
this
has
the m a i n
time for
property
of
~ -substructures n
a definition
which
of an
are m o d e l s
of
PA
.
(n) NOW we
show
that
[x,y]
~
(z+1)zz
indeed
defines
such
a
Z -indicator: n
(n) 4.3 L e m m a :
If
then
is an
there
M ~ PA,
a,b
I ~ PA,
£
M,
c 6 M \ ~
I --eC M,
I ~
, n > O, M ~
M
with
[a,b]
~
a 6 I
[a,b]
< b
~
c
(c+I) e,
.
n
(n) Proof:
[a,b]
sequence
c (c+I) c
~
Xo-indiscernibles
of
in 2.3, (ii).
Since
a homogeneous
set
[a,b] as
M
for
being
any
<eo,...,ei>
infinite
segment
in
of
6 ~ ),
partition g~(ei)
primitive
recursive
by
6 ~)
< b
, as
[[a,b]]
d
function,
condition
ei+1,
the
. By 2.3, (ii)
from
all
than
be
arises
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
for
I
a
described
, the
if w e w i s h .
Let
(eili
" So w e h a v e
sequence
is s m a l l e r
Zo-indiscernibility.
determined
this
on s o m e
< ei+1,
(c+I) c c
a ~ ei
2.3,(ii)
(sequence-number)
by
M
some
yields
dominates
i 6 ~
(eili
b y the p r o o ~
(~)* (c+1)Cc
gn
implies
all
ei
initial only
I ~
M n
remains
to b e p r o v e d .
We
show
I ~
M, m
~ n, b y
induction
on
m
.
~ 6 ~m+1
"
Zm By
I --eC M w e h a v e
already
I ~ Z M.
Let
m
< n,
I ~
O
~ =
H x ~ ( y I ..... Y t , X ) ,
I ~NmM .
So
let
Equivalently replacing 0
we only
sets
some
and b y i n d u c t i o n
to r e n d e r
For
for
entails
3x the
this
<e i + 2 t r n ( . . . ) , t same
b
holds
in
I .
we need
n in the p r o o f
from
of
an i n f i n i t e
< Card(X)
for
any
~
~ s
set,
the
so it is n o t
fixed
function
f:~.
obtain
n > O
an
Moreover,
if
is a t r u e M ~
PA,
Nn+2-sentence
M e
~
,
there
is
independent an
~n+1 I --eC M,
I
N PA,
so
that
I
~
M
and
I
~
~
~
n
n
Remark: case
i-6
For
the f i r s t
M ~ Th(~
Corollary:
For
of i n i t i a l
complete
extensions
stronger
all
Ehrenfeucht result
completions that
for
with
regard
of
n = O
of
4.5,4.3
is o n l y
needed
in the
special
)
infinity
Remark:
part
that PA 4.6
n 6 ~
any nonstandard
Zn-SUbStructures of
PA
and D.
satisfying
of
Th(~)
pairwise
has
an
different
.
Jensen
proved
a nonstandard satisfied
by
immediately
to the r e s u l t
model
model
in
[3] f o r
of P A h a s
n = 0 2
~o
its i n i t i a l
substructures.
generalizes
to m o d e l s
by Gaifman
quoted
in the
of
remark
the distinct Note PA
U Th
following
(~), 3.4.
174
References
[i]
J. Paris,
L. Harrington:
Ar i t h m e t i c ,
A Mathematical
in: H a n d b o o k
Incompleteness
of M a t h e m a t i c a l
Logic,
ed.
in Peano
Jon Barwise,
1133-1142. [2]
J. Paris:
Some
The Journal
[3]
Proc.
1971
of the
Lecture
H. Gaifman: Proc.
Lecture
J. F. Knight: The Journal
[7]
A Note
J.C.
of Number S6r.
Types
Astr.,
Bull.
vol.
43, No.
1976,
Summer
in Math.,
School vol.
vol.
40,
Model
XII,
of A r i t h m e t i c , London
255,
1975,
1970,
128-144.
Models
of A r i t h m e t i c ,
317-320.
Polonaise
No.
2,
Logic,
539-573.
for a Free V a r i a b l e
l'acad&mie vol.
in:
Logic,
in U n c o u n t a b l e vol.
arithmetics,
in M a t h e m a t i c a l
337,
in M a t h e m a t i c s ,
de
in e l e m e n t a r y
and Submodels
Logic,
725-731.
223-245.
in M a t h e m a t i c a l
Phys.,
4, 1978,
of Set Theories,
A Nonstandard
Theory,
Math.,
Models
Omitted
of S y m b o l i c
Sheperdson:
XCII,
on Models
Notes
for Peano A r i t h m e t i c ,
Some p r o b l e m s
Cambridge Notes,
of the C o n f e r e n c e
Sp r i n g e r [6]
Mathematical, Countable
Results
Logic,
D. Jensen:
H. Friedman:
Sp r i n g e r
[5]
of S y m b o l i c
A. E h r e n f e u c h t , Fundamenta
[4]
Independence
1964,
Fragment
des Sciences, 79-86.