N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y ‘This remarkable book builds on Chomsky’s key insight that language provides an inbuilt k...
125 downloads
1857 Views
2MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y ‘This remarkable book builds on Chomsky’s key insight that language provides an inbuilt key to our identity as a symbol using species. To the role of grammar as a cognitive tool enabling us to construct “selves”, Nair adds a second tool in the realm of discourse: narrative. She has a wonderfully subtle account of the psychology of narrative as a “species of natural theory”. I anticipate that with this book she will be recognized as a major figure.’ Stephen Greenblatt, Cogan Professor of the Humanities, Harvard University, USA ‘Nair’s brilliant study of narrative combines anthropological and sociolinguistic perspectives with cognitive ones to bring out the magical impulses that animate this genre.’ Michael J. Toolan, Professor of Applied English Linguistics, University of Birmingham, UK ‘An original and deeply grounded work, which thoroughly explores the major dimensions of narrative and yet provides a theoretical basis in the cognitive sciences, Narrative Gravity is eminently worth the intellectual effort required to read it.’ Brian McHale, Professor of English, The Ohio State University, USA Narrative Gravity is an intriguing, foundational exploration of the complex issues surrounding narrative and identity. Human beings have always been compulsive storytellers, inventing narratives in cultures and societies across the world. In this book, Rukmini Bhaya Nair asks why we feel compelled to fabricate stories in this way. Extending current research in cognitive science and narratology, the author argues that we seem to have an innate genetic drive to lie and fabricate as a way of gaining the competitive advantages such fictions give us, both individually and collectively. She suggests that stories are a means of fusing causal and logical explanations of ‘real’ events with emotional recognition, so that the lessons taught to us as children, and then throughout our lives via stories, lay the cornerstones of our most crucial beliefs. A natural and essential part of our ordinary conversations and our lives, the speech act of narrative appears central to the construction of our identities. Nair’s conclusion is that our stories really do make us up, just as much as we make up our stories. This elegantly written and theoretically sophisticated work is essential reading for students of linguistics, philosophy and literary theory – and for anyone who tells, reads, or listens to stories. Rukmini Bhaya Nair is Professor of Linguistics and English at the Indian Institute of Technology, Delhi. Her previous publications include Lying on the Postcolonial Couch: The Idea of Indifference (2002), Translation, Text and Theory: The Paradigm of India (ed: 2002) and Technobrat: Culture in a Cybernetic Classroom (1997).
Narrative Gravity
Conversation, Cognition, Culture
Rukmini Bhaya Nair
First published in 2002 by Oxford University Press, New Delhi
1
This edition first published 2003 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE Simultaneously published in the USA and Canada by Routledge 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group
This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2004.
© 2003 Rukmini Bhaya Nair All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Rukmini Bhaya Nair. Narrative Gravity: conversation, cognition, culture / Rukmini Bhaya Nair. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Discourse analysis, Narrative. 2. Discourse analysis – Psychological aspects. I. Title P302.7.R85 2003 401'.41–dc21 2003041406
ISBN 0-203-30109-9 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-33989-4 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-30735-X (Print Edition)
For my parents Angela and Hiten Bhaya the best of listeners and thus—the best creators of stories
1
qQ CONTENTS
Acknowledgements
ix
Introduction: First Conversational Steps
1
Chapter 1
Structural Simplicities The Grammar and Context of Narrative (Guru: Labov)
26
Chapter 2
Force, Fiction, Fit and Felicity Narrative as a Speech Act (Gurus: Austin, Searle)
69
Chapter 3
Performatives, Perlocutions, Pretence Deconstruction and the Narrative Speech Act (Gurus: de Man, Derrida)
129
Chapter 4
Cooperative Conventions Implied Meanings in Narrative (Guru: Grice)
167
Chapter 5
Rationality and Relevance Mental Codes and Cultural Memes in Narrative (Guru: Dennett)
201
Chapter 6
Turns at Talk Ethnomethodological Analysis of Narrative
249
viii
CONTENTS
Chapter 7
Self, State and Solidarity The Politics of Narrative
288
Chapter 8
Explaining Enigmas from Evidence The Cause of Narrative
311
Conclusion: Final Narrative Sutras
341
Appendix I:
The Flood
380
Appendix II:
Transcription and Translation
385
Appendix III:
Putative Emotive and Emotional Registers An Evolutionary Perspective
390
Appendix IV:
Placements
394
Appendix V:
A Possible Course on Narrative Based on this Book
397
Bibliography
399
Index
418
1
qQ ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
A common convention in many cultures is that moral tags appear at the end of a telling. If so, this is a back-to-front book, for its genesis— or rather the story of origins that I have made up for it over the years— lies in three dicta. These were delivered a very long time ago by my supervisor at Cambridge, Stephen Levinson, when I first began writing my thesis. Remember, declared Steve mysteriously, that a supervisor is only an umbrella. Second, you cannot do research without dirtying your hands. And lastly, style is only the icing on the cake. It was armed with these astonishing hortatory weapons—un-wet perhaps, but also unenlightened, grubby and cake-less—that I set out on the winding pilgrimage that has finally resulted in the present work. And of course, I did have a hermeneutic go at the wisdom of my guru, St. Stephen, along the way. His adages were, after all, brutally easy to unpack. One, do not ask for guidance, find your own path; I am simply a device to protect you from the vagaries of the administrator gods up there. But for this, you are on your own—and so am I. That is the human condition. Two, muck about in the data—it is there that you will find real treasures; and three, don’t ever imagine you can get away with merely fooling around with linguistic niceties. Only the readers of Narrative Gravity can judge whether I have managed to live up to the standards set by Steve so many years ago, but my gratitude to him will always be immeasurable. Today, I can think of no better advice to give my own graduate students. Neither can words adequately describe the enormous grace, dignity and fortitude of the people of the flood-stricken villages of West Bengal
x
A C K N OW L E D G E M E N T S
who willingly shared their narratives and their hospitality even as they were left with nothing. I am deeply grateful to Ashok Mitra and Sujit Poddar for helping me to meet such unforgettable men and women. There were also others both in Cambridge and in Calcutta, the twin stations of my education, without whom I could never have got started. They include my first teachers of literature—Sajni Kripalani, Dipti Mitra, Yashodhara Bagchi, Ranajoy Karlekar; and the first of my literary friendships—with William Da Silva, Shubha Chakraborty, Nisha Grover, and Arun Kumar. John and Rani Drew, Sita Narasimhan, Ranjit, Ratna, Sudarshan, Sarita, Anmol, Michael Small, Leslie Barnett, Marion Owen, Penny Brown, Ursula and Peter Dronke, Nona Pike, Nell Hutton, Martin Rees and Caroline Humphrey, not to mention my comrades at Elmside, each made Cambridge the unforgettable place it will always be for me. At the same time, Roy Harris at Oxford boosted my confidence by suggesting that my thesis was publishable. Still later, Stephen Greenblatt and Richard and Mary Rorty were incredibly helpful at the Dartmouth School of Criticism and Theory— and continue to be the kindest and most admirable of friends. To Daniel Dennett, whom I have never met, I owe the marvellous phrase that I have used as the title of this book. In the millennial year 2001, I was fortunate again. At a seminar on narrative, I encountered Elinor Ochs, in whom I found a wonderful kindred spirit. Dan Slobin, Michael Bamberg, Nancy Budwig, Charles and Marjorie Goodwin, Chris Sinha, Johannes Wagner, Michael Chandler, Jan Anward and several others at the seminar, especially the participants on my course, commented on my work with great generosity. I thank them all—Chris and Johannes, in particular, for their hospitality and the stimulating atmosphere they managed to create around that most human of acts—story-telling. My students through the years have provided just the right doses of scepticism and support. Among many, I must single out Shirshanka Das, Manas Baveja and John Paul Bir Singh, whose suggestion that ‘Narrative’ be renamed ‘Nairrative’ is, fortunately, yet to be taken up! This trio actually managed to install on my computer a story-telling ‘programme’—roughly based on the rules I provide in Chapter 5 of this book—which endlessly churns out little tales about a chai-shop where customers go for all their favourite culinary items. While my admiration for the ingenuity displayed by Shirshanka, Manas and John in their ‘cooking up’ of this programme is boundless, an even greater benefit is the insight I now get whenever I switch my screen on—that even the most
A C K N OW L E D G E M E N T S
xi
boring of human narratives easily surpasses anything the cleverest machine can serve up! I must also, in the same breath, thank Priya Rana for proofing and Sheeba Mathen and Bhumika Sharma, for putting up with the sheer boredom of typing up the appendices to this book. For the vivid painting on the cover, it is a pleasure to acknowledge the contribution of the artist, Arpana Caur. Caur’s figures—call them selfreflexive conversationalists, grim reapers spinning life-sustaining stories out of dark encounters with death or gendered subjects mediating the rise and gravitational fall of cultures—capture in a single image many of the issues it has taken me more than 400 pages to articulate in this book. I shall always be grateful, as well, to Farhad Mehta, who not only apprehended with immediate intelligence the relevance of ‘Harvest’ to the themes of my book, but enlivened our quixotic route through the National Gallery of Modern Art with charm and good humour. Finally, Narrative Gravity owes most to the brilliant comments and the exemplary friendship of Michael Toolan with whom I co-taught my first course on Narrative at the National University of Singapore. Were it not for teachers like Steve, friends like Michael and the inspired narrators of Midnapore District, I would still be dripping out there somewhere— sans umbrella no doubt. If I am home and dry today, it is entirely because of them.
1
qQ INTRODUCTION: F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
The Rigveda is one of the world’s oldest texts. In it, the goddess Speech, personified and self-reflexive, speaks : I move with the Rudras and the Vasus, with the Adityas and all the gods. ... The one who eats food, who truly sees, who breathes, who hears what is said, does so through me. Though they do not realize it they dwell in me. Listen ... what I tell you should be heeded ... I gave birth to the father on the head of this world. My womb is in the waters, within the ocean, I am the one who blows like the wind, embracing all creatures. Beyond the earth, beyond the sky, so much have I become in my greatness. ...1
Three thousand years on, our intuitions about the mysteries of speech, its infinite range and great power, appear to have changed very little. What perhaps has altered more radically is our speech about Speech, the conversations we hold about language and the narratives we tell ourselves about its locus and origins. Most people interested in the relation of language to the world no longer subscribe to the view that speech ‘embraces all creatures’ or ‘moves with the gods’. De-divinized and de-natured, speech is today indubitably a human-centred faculty, located within. Neither Noam Chomsky, nor Jacques Derrida, nor John Searle, all otherwise pulling in very different philosophical directions, 1Translated by Doniger O’Flaherty, The Rig Veda, 1981, p. 63. O’Flaherty annotates the phrase ‘Listen, you whom they have heard...’, which, according to her, means ‘literally, one who is heard, or who is famous; a triple pun on the common root ‘hear’ in ‘listen’, ‘they have heard’ as well as ‘heeded’. Such a pointed reference to ‘famous’ addressees, embedded in this pun, seems to offer evidence of a certain linguistic sophistication.
2
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
would for one moment deny this fundamental premise of twentiethcentury thought. If a creature is born human, there is no escape from speech; if it is not, there is no entry into speech. One consequence of this sealing in of speech within the human ambit alone seems to have been that our theories about language and our theories about ourselves have come very close together. In this book, I present arguments in the interconnected areas of linguistic pragmatics, cultural studies and the philosophy of language that: a) reveal the ways in which recent theories of communication have either eliminated, eroded or foregrounded the role of the speaking human subject; b) highlight those interconnections between speech or conversation and narrative which affect our understanding of the words–world nexus, exhibited in familiar clusters of concepts such as truth, fiction, representation and pretence; or, intentionality, inference, cognitive relevance and conversational implicature; or, speech act, structure, rule, function and use; c) develop the idea of narrative as a species of ‘natural theory’, designed— that is, biologically, psychologically and culturally—to probe into contexts, explore hypotheses and present explanations of the enigmas we encounter in the daily business of living, as well as of facing death.2 Later in that same immodest paean of self-praise I quoted in the beginning, the Rigvedic goddess Vac or Speech comments with mordant irony on what appears to be a causal connection between her queenly pre-eminence and her consequent dismemberment. Speech is so important that she cannot remain whole. She has to be divided. Her riches must be distributed, partitioned by the gods. 2These objectives are related insofar as a) has as its focus not just theories of language, but rather theories of linguistic communication, which perforce make reference to intersubjective notions like ‘speakers’ and ‘hearers’ or, to put it somewhat more loosely for the time being, to conversations. Further, conjectures about ‘narrative as theory’ such as those proposed in b) strongly indicate that we should observe spontaneous story-telling in the conversational domain, where it is most prolific and ‘natural’ (See Chapter 1, for instance, which considers the structuralist approach to the narrative of William Labov, who has long been a spokesperson for the position that complex literary narratives can be analysed with precision only in the wake of studies which record the circumstances of their natural habitat—the conversational space). The attempt to describe narratives in conversation, in turn, then leads us on to underwrite c), because a close study of some extensive domain such as conversational narrative must affect, maybe even significantly alter, our more general ideas about linguistic interchanges, about speech.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
3
I am the confluence of riches. ... The gods divided me up into various parts, for I dwell in many places, and enter into many forms. ...
My own work in this book could be seen as concerning itself with some of the implications of partitioning speech in the several ways we have invented, especially in this century. When Roland Barthes, for example, declares in an imperious sweep that the narratives of the world are numberless, he seems precisely to be echoing the triumphant words of Vac celebrating the ‘many forms’ she ‘enters into’.3 I, for my part, here renew Vac’s claim that the conversations of the world are correspondingly countless. The bangs and whispers, susurrations and explosions that ensue when these two super-genres of discourse—conversation and narrative— fuse, form the subject matter of Narrative Gravity. Storytalk A parodically simple version of the hierarchical embedding that relates those mammoth abstractions—communication, conversation and narrative—might look like this: COMMUNICATION
LANGUAGE-BASED
OTHER e.g. gestures, non-linguistic sign systems such as traffic signals, etc.
ORAL
CONVERSATIONAL
NARRATIVE
OTHER e.g. written texts
OTHER NARRATIVE e.g. speeches, lectures, etc.
OTHER e.g. philosophical tracts, official documents, etc.
OTHER e.g. questions, arguments, greetings, discussions, etc.
Fig. 1 3Barthes, ‘A Structural Analysis of Narrative’, in S. Heath, translated 1977, p. 79.
4
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
At each level of Figure 1, it’s apparent that the left node seems prima facie the more important, even as we recognize that this effect comes to be created, at least partly, as an artefact of the manner in which this node is named, while the ‘other’ node is merely exemplified. However, if conversation is at all to be pursued, we cannot avoid this basic concession to Vac’s dominion. It’s part of the othering nature of language that it forces upon its subjects an endless series of value-laden representational choices. Commonsensically, then, one obvious place to begin a study of communication and its cognitive repercussions is with some hypotheses about the necessary features for a theory of conversation. Over the recent decades, a number of philosophers have attempted to describe the conventions that seem necessary to the maintenance of a conversational exchange (Grice, Austin, Searle, Schiffer, Lewis, Sperber and Wilson, Recanati). Simultaneously, research in ethnomethodology, relying on that wonderful mnemonic invention, the tape-recorder, has turned up a list of features characteristic of the turn-taking mechanisms of conversation. Thus, ordinary language and casual conversation, once almost unnoticed in analyses of communication, have by now gained huge ontological respectability. For this reason, the task for a theory of human communication today may well be to explain the striking similarities in the norms of conversation that appear to have evolved across cultures, as well as account for those nonconformist instances which some researchers (Ochs Keenan, Polanyi) have noted in societies such as the Malagasy. Should we at this point seek a rough-and-ready heuristic that facilitates this task, we could hardly avoid being influenced by that near manic devotion to a procedural logic that distinguishes linguists and philosophers. Such a methodology would require us to begin by outlining—if only ultimately to reject—a Swiftian set of step-by-step operations: Hunting Down a Theory of Communication : Instruction Manual. I. Locate an area of behaviour where communication appears to be taking place, even if a definition of communication is not a priori available— conversational narrative might do as a candidate, for example.4 II. Once an area is located, identify the basic units of ‘communication’ in the area and name and describe them, still without an adequate definition of what ‘communication’ is. Note that, at this second stage, a large number of meta-theoretical terms might be required, such as those invented by 4Wittgenstein’s famous arguments on the difficulties of finding a definition for the
concept ‘game’ in Philosophical Investigations, 1953, p. 432, are obviously relevant here.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
5
speech act theory or the Gricean Theory of Conversational Implicature for just such a purpose. III. Identifying and describing a ‘basic unit’ of communication—let’s say, something like a question or an assertion for instance—must be followed by specifying a set of rules which govern the functioning of these units. Naturally, these rules are not directly observable; rather, they are conceptual devices that enable an explanation of the observations and descriptions made in stages I and II. In the process, some of your original descriptions may have to be ‘corrected’ or reformulated. At this stage, an abstract picture of communication, that is, a ‘theory’ of it, has, speaking optimistically, almost been formulated. IV. The rules devised at stage III have to be inter-related, and inconsistencies minimized; also, concepts such as, for example ‘implicature’, ‘intention’, ‘reference’, etc., that underpin the rules as a whole, have to be explicated. And now hey presto, that we have something like a full-fledged ‘theory’ to be reapplied, with caution, to the ‘data’ with which we began, we might just be able to extract an answer to our original, impossible question— what is communication? Or if we still do not have a satisfactory answer to this mammoth question, we do at least have the resources for generating a great deal of scepticism about the value of such unwieldy questions, about that endless looping back, that almost loopiness, which marks a certain kind of inquiry. I shall begin arbitrarily, by describing narrative as a dynamic structure that converts ‘talk’ into ‘text’. Its function is to make some parts of a communicative loop or chain—in our particular case, casual conversation— both potentially detachable and iterable. A ‘good story’ is one that can be ‘taken away’ by listeners and/or tellers and repeated in other conversations, other contexts, other cultures. It may also undergo further structural conversion into other media such as written text, film, drawings, and back again. While it is true that this aspect of conversational story-telling has not been much remarked on, it is, as I see it, one of the most noteworthy features of narrative as a cognitive format. The structure of narrative appears beautifully adapted to time-transfer, to taking away, to having and holding in some kind of formal permanence. The point becomes clearer if we contrast narrative with conversational structure for a moment, and dwell on the difficulties of ‘fit’ between the two. Conversational structure, it seems to me, is interventionist. It technically permits the possibility of interruptions and/or disruptions of a speaker’s talk at all times with immediacy. Why this technical openness to ‘challenge’ leads, in practice, to far fewer breakdowns of communication than are in theory possible, is an intriguing question that crops up in
6
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
various chapters of Narrative Gravity, especially those that discuss the ‘rationality’ of moves within the language game of story-telling. But let me just note here that conversational structure is typically ‘alternating’, with an ABABAB pattern that requires a constant relocation of the deictic centres of ‘self’. Conversation presumes an exchange of ‘I’ with ‘you’ at every turn, quite literally. What Bakhtin famously called the ‘dialogic imagination’ is nowhere as evident as in ordinary conversation, although, again, Bakhtin himself did not emphasize this almost mechanical aspect of ‘dialogue’. Most researchers, however, now agree that narrative, often idealized as ‘monologic’, is quite unlike conversation in that it is structurally ‘sequential’, displaying an ABCDEF pattern. How to fit the long, monologic, past-ist, narrator-centred and closed ABCDEF sequence of narrative into the short, dialogic, present-ist, deictically changing and open-ended ABABAB alternation of conversation? Solve this puzzle and some of those elusive constraints on communication that Vac in her wisdom decreed so many evolutionary cycles ago might begin to reveal themselves. The Paradoxes of the Authorless Narrative and of Fictional Discourse From puzzles to paradoxes: for a longish stretch of human history, as we’ve just noted, narratives have constituted an integral and extensive part of our oral repertoire, which consists chiefly of everyday conversation. Conversation, in turn, offers the most widespread evidence of our largely language-based, and thus unique communicative gifts, among the world’s species. This is the basic embedded relationship that Narrative Gravity is obsessed with, in one way or another, throughout its ten chapters. Barring this first chapter and a final one, the eight chapters at the centre of the book coil themselves around a set of three ‘paradoxes’, loosely related to the basic three objectives outlined in a), b) and c) earlier. The first paradox is Dennett’s Paradox of the Authorless Narrative. Is it possible to conceive of a narrative without a narrator?, asks Dennett (1991), and proceeds to demonstrate with the concrete example of ‘A Party Game called Psychoanalysis’ that such a situation is indeed imaginable.5 In Dennett’s account of this game, one player—the dupe— is sent out of the room, and told that when he comes back he will have to guess at a story told by one of the people in the room. Once he has 5Compare A. Banfield’s idea of ‘Speakerless Narratives’ in Unspeakable Sentences, 1982.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
7
pieced the story together through a process of asking yes–no questions, he will have to identify the teller of the story and proceed to psychoanalyse him or her. But, unknown to him, there is no story, and the others in the room have simply agreed that if the last letter in the dupe’s question is in the first half of the alphabet, they will answer in the affirmative, and otherwise in the negative.6 For example: Q. A. Q. A. Q. A. Q. A. Q. Y.
Is it a romantic story? No. Has Hollywood made a film based on the theme? Yes. Directed by Hitchcock? Yes. Not Psycho? No. Would it be The Birds, by any chance? Yes.
From this amusing illustration, Dennett7 goes on to contend that just as there can be narratives without narrators, so there can be ‘selves’ or the illusion of identity produced in individuals without any recourse to a foundational notion of personality. Human ‘selves’, according to Dennett are ‘centres of narrative gravity’, since humans are programmed to extrude narratives as naturally as spiders spin webs or beavers build dams. Each day of their lives human beings tell stories—to themselves and to others around themselves. A human life is constructed out of such pre-programmed activity. It is this differentiated layering of multiple narratives that produces in human beings the illusory feeling that they are intentional agents ‘born with’ distinct selves. Two chapters of Narrative Gravity are pulled together by this paradox. They are: Chapter 4 on the work of Grice and Lewis, which presents for the first time a set of maxims for narrative implicature, based on Grice’s more general rules for conversational implicature; and 5 on the mnemonic salience of narrative, which attempts to link Sperber and Wilson’s ideas on 6Daniel C. Dennett, Consciousness Explained, 1990, pp. 10–16. 7Dennett is careful to introduce a ‘contradiction’ clause here, which guards against
an answer lower down in the sequence of questions negating information yielded earlier. This basic concession to ‘rationality’, I will argue, seems reminiscent of a Gricean framework where a language game works only if certain ground rules for communication have been accepted by conversational ‘players’ in the first place. In other words, even ‘authorless narratives’ require ‘conversational agents’ who agree upon, initiate and sustain a logically prior process of communication.
8
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
conversational relevance with Dennett’s own work on cultural memes, and also offers my own theory of narrativity. Many recent novelist–commentators on narrative—Milan Kundera, Italo Calvino, Umberto Eco—have, as we know, remarked on that peculiar sense of an ‘unbearable lightness of being’ to which the human self is naturally subject. If stories indeed anchor the flyaway human soul, then this book—Narrative Gravity—can be read as exploring the psychological antithesis of, as well as antidote to, this particular ‘authoritative’ malaise of the human soul. The second paradox is Searle’s celebrated Paradox of Fictional Discourse. How can words both possess and not possess their ‘ordinary’ meanings in a piece of fiction?8 What are the belief states of ‘selves’ when they enter the universal discourse of ‘fiction’? Searle’s startlingly direct answer to these deep questions is that the speech act of fiction is ‘parasitic’ upon the more basic act of assertion. Fictional discourse is exactly like the assertion except that the ‘sincerity condition’ which enjoins truthfulness is ‘suspended’ in such cases. Hence, ‘truth’ is automatically sacrificed in narrative. My position in Narrative Gravity, on the contrary, is that there can be a lot of truth (facts as well as tenets of cultural faith) in a fictional assertion, and that audiences know how to negotiate facts in a fictional story without a) making a binary distinction between the categories of ‘fiction’ versus ‘assertion’ and b) having to relate fiction ‘parasitically’ to the prior and more basic speech act of assertion. A simple example will make the point. Suppose we were to compare an adult and a child telling the very same story—the story of ‘Goldilocks and the Three Bears’, say. Now let’s have a scenario where the child who repeats this story, which she has first heard from her mother, to her little sister at bedtime, actually believes in the truth of her assertions. She does truly believe Goldilocks ate up the little bear’s pudding, broke his chair and was generally hateful. So does her little sister. Therefore, no ‘sincerity condition’ can, logically, have been suspended during this particular telling of ‘Goldilocks’ for either listener or hearer. But do we then want to maintain that the little girl’s story, which has exactly the same content as her mother’s original account, where we will assume for the sake of sanity that the mother did not believe in the truth of her assertions, is now a genuine assertion, while her mother’s earlier ‘parasitic’ utterance was not? Does the story of Goldilocks really turn ‘factual’ the moment context of belief alters from a mother-to-child telling to a child-to-child telling? It can surely not be so alarmingly simple to effect changes in ‘the 8‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’ in Speech Acts, p. 1972.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
9
logical status of fictional discourse’, unless we have a very weak notion of logic operating here. Might it not be more elegant simply to say that mother and child both intend to produce narrative speech acts, rather than maintain that one is making a specious attempt at assertion while the other isn’t? In fact, the relevant difference for speech act theory between fictional and non-fictional narrative, as I suggest in my chapter on Austin and Searle’s formulation of speech act theory may lie in what Searle himself termed in another context ‘direction of fit’. Earlier I mentioned another problem of ‘fit’, where there’s a tension each time the monologic, closed ABCDEF pattern of narrative has to fuse with the dialogic, openended ABABAB pattern of a conversational sequence. Within speech act theory another, less formal, more semantic ‘fit’ characterizes a division seen as basic within the category of narrative itself. According to Searle, in a fictional representation, the world may be said to be made a posteriori to match the words of the teller; in a factual one, the teller’s words may be taken to conform to certain a priori elements in the world. Hence, if a story is presented as made out of factual material, the element of belief (B) in its truth should ideally be 1. However, if a story is fictional, the element of belief could be either 0 or greater than 0 (but less than 1). The range of B, that is, in the truth of any narrative can be represented as being between the extreme points 0 and 1, but there is no sharp line to be drawn between fictional discourse and factual material. Consequently, a simplifying hypothesis underlying this research is that we neither need to make, nor make, any binary distinctions in our assessments of narrative. Indeed, it may be believability (plausibility) rather than belief (commitment to truth) that is the important criterion in assessing narrative material, both fictional and factual. ‘Truth’ in general seems not to be a critical criterion in the evaluation of narrative. In the context of story-telling, truth could be a standard that is, as Sperber and Wilson might put it, cognitively irrelevant. Instead, I suggest that there is a cline from most fragile (implausible, boring and culturally alienated) to most durable (plausible, interesting and culturally salient) along which audiences can grade all kinds of narrative material— fictional or factual, oral or written, conversational or rehearsed. From this it follows that even if a teller’s narrative is openly presented as fictional, it still has to be organized as ‘non-fragile’, so that its audience agrees, by temporary fiat, to a ‘willing suspension of disbelief’. But if the teller goofs by constantly stressing the dramatic nature of story material, chances are that the audience will respond with yawns (mental yawns, at any rate, even if politeness forbids a physical expression of boredom), because then their reactions become limited to exclamations of horror, surprise
10
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
or disbelief at every turn. Thus, overemphasis on reportability by a teller may often have the paradoxical consequence that audiences are exhausted and ultimately bored to tears. The appeal of telling a story by stressing ordinary common ground is that audiences can participate actively in the process of telling, and so resist boredom. Paul de Man famously described an endemic attitude towards texts in a community of readers as incorporating ‘a resistance to theory’, but if we seek to characterize narrative itself as a kind of proto-theoretical endeavour, then how do conversationalists contrive to ‘resist’ the theory that a story presents them with? An answer that I explore pretty intensively in Narrative Gravity concerns the ways in which conversationalists display an almost programmed commitment to grading or evaluating the stories they are submitted to along a cognitive axis that registers boredom, implausibility and cultural irrelevance. It is as if the ‘self’ that a teller projects through her narrative is being communally tested, examined for its social robustness. As in any exam, the examinee’s production is ‘fragile’ insofar as it is exposed to negative evaluations, for, if listeners as narrative examiners are to perform their own roles with maximal authority, they are bound to seriously ‘resist’ the teller’s narrative, giving it a good grade only if it can manage to overcome their objections. To read the pleasures of the narrative encounter in terms of the metaphor of an examination may be to impose too strict a reading on it. Nevertheless, in a book which attempts to treat narrative as a kind of theory, concerned with matching the ‘evidence’ displayed in a teller’s tale with the knowledge one has of the world, both emotionally and perceptually, there is already incipient a concept of examination—the potential, and often actualized cross-examination of the story and storyteller by a community of listeners, as well as the self-reflexive examination of her own story by a teller. ‘Plausibility’ and ‘fragility’ must thus be understood as interactional concepts when applied to narratives, unlike ‘truth’ or, to a lesser degree, the ‘felicity conditions’ of speech act theory. It is the task of an audience to evaluate a narrative as interesting or credible, and not in the interests of a narrator to inform them that it is so. Whereas a strong case can be made for the truth of a narrative being independent of whether audiences believe it or not, a narrative cannot be said to be plausible unless audiences in particular conversational contexts ‘pass’ it on this count. This, indeed, is where the ‘power’ of an audience resides—to decide from moment to moment, on the basis of incoming evidence, where the boundaries lie between the imagined and the real in a teller’s tale.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
11
There is no safe passage for a story-teller. She can keep only one eye on her story, the other ‘glittering eye’ must constantly be fixed on the Wedding Guest, Coleridge’s ambiguous symbol for an enthralled listener. For, if a teller fails to hold the attention of her listeners, they may at any time mentally break away from her tale, judging her facts too fantastic to accept, or her fiction too mundane. But then, where does such potentially capricious exercise of authority on the part of listeners leave the logical distinction between fact and fiction that is Searle’s concern? Do listeners, for example, use the speech act criteria of sincerity to distinguish between ‘fact’ and ‘fiction’, or do they make use of categories other than, and different from, the speech act ones, in order to ‘make up their minds’ on these questions? Searle’s paradox enables us to focus on some of these issues. In Narrative Gravity I suggest that, despite Searle’s misgivings, no rules of language are ‘suspended’ in either fictional or factional discourse. Rather, it is the intense focus in any story-telling activity on the ways in which the ‘rules’ of language are complied with to yield ‘ordinary meanings’, which any listener can anticipate, that enable us to revel in their ‘extraordinary meaningfulness’—that is, their emotional effect on us. The reason why we accept rather than reject even the uncomfortable effect of fear, anger, dread that a narrative might have on us, derives from our recognition of its specific ‘force’ as a speech act. Narrative creates emotional resonances through purely linguistic means. Stories force upon us a series of judgements about the linguistic construction of our experiences, and especially our most moving mental experiences. This is the main factor that makes Searle’s description of the logic of a fictional story as a wayward non-compliance with the ‘rules’ of language appear just a little perverse to me. Nor is this just to quibble; it’s more to say that, if one were to isolate the phrase ‘fictional story’ in the passage from Searle quoted earlier in this section, the main emphasis in this book will be on the manner in which the linguistic logic of the nominal head ‘story’ contains and subsumes the logic of its adjectival qualifier ‘fictional’. Story-telling seems to me to permit high quality resolutions of experience, either representing it analytically as fiction or reappraising its contingencies as factual narrative. It is this ability to crystallize experience, re-form it, so that it allows us to reform, or at least review, ourselves, that we celebrate when we share our stories. Narrative Gravity thus develops a critique of Searle’s answer to his own paradox by tracking its implications in Chapter 2, which constructs for the first time in the literature on speech act theory, a set of original felicity conditions on the meta-speech act of
12
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
narrative, but which also tries to show why these grid-like conditions in fact fail to capture some of the finer and more interesting features of narrativity. Chapter 3 on deconstruction and Derrida, and on Paul de Man and Jonathan Culler’s critiques of speech act theory, and Chapter 7 on the ‘fictionalization’ of true accounts of disaster return to Searle’s Paradox. Two kinds of crisis come together in this seventh chapter: real life disaster and the linguistic problems of deciding upon meaning, given the fleeting immediacy of natural conversations. How do we cope? It is suggested here that the crises of meaning that Searle discusses are not just characteristic of fiction but could rather be forced on individuals across cultures by the larger structure of narrative, both fictional and non-fictional. The Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick of Narrative Lastly, there is my own paradox. The metaphor it embodies runs through those chapters—1, 5, 6 and 7, 8—which are concerned, respectively, with the grammar of narrative, its cognitive patterns, the mechanisms of conversation, and the cultural forces that shape story-telling. In short, these are the chapters of the book that have to do, in one way or the other, with structural enticements. What is supposed to happen in an Indian rope trick is well known. In some of the more intriguing versions of the trick, a magician cuts up a small boy (or an apple or a wriggling snake, or even, if you will, the afore-mentioned goddess Vac!), and then tosses the pieces into the air where they, predictably, disappear. The magician then unwinds his rope, climbs it, defying small forces like gravity, retrieves the invisible bits, puts them together, and descends with a miraculously coalesced little boy (or snake, or apple, or goddess). Cheers from the assorted audience if our magician gets it right, boos if he does not! It is my contention that a story-teller performs a feat quite similar to the Indian magician’s—and equally mysterious. She takes familiar objects and cuts them up, reorganizes them, defamiliarizes them, involves them in a mythic toss-up. These effects she achieves by flighting the sinuous rope of narrative into the air. But why? Is it not perverse to take ‘reality’, distort or destroy it, and then simply put it together again? There are many answers to this question—answers that are iteratively explored in Narrative Gravity—but one answer is obvious. There is a certain delight, an inexplicable thrill, in challenging the everyday world which we take for granted, a world where our feet are firmly planted on the ground and where the laws of gravity, temporal order, mechanics and
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
13
biology unfailingly prevail. An illusionist’s skill lies in using these very laws to trick us, or our brains, into believing that they no longer hold. So too the story-teller at one and the same time deceives and delights us with her artifice. Indeed, she delights us because she deceives us. At the same time, it is important to recognize that much of the power of narrative comes not just from the fact that it takes us into imaginary or impossible worlds, but that it in fact reassures us, structurally reassures us, that things come right back in the end to where they were in the beginning. The narrative movement is generally from terra firma to terra incognita and back. The linearity and temporality of prototypical narrative, its firm closures, its very constructedness, seems to possess huge psychological advantages. As in the Indian rope trick, the end of narrative is often recovery. All the freely floating parts of a narrative—its snaky tail, its envenomed irony, its spine of content—have to be recombined perfectly in the air, out of sight, and brought down to earth again. That is often the prime satisfaction of narrative. It is what audiences in many cultures, ancient and contemporary, expect of a ‘good’ story. If the postmodern narrative without clear beginnings, middles and ends puzzles and troubles readers, then this book argues that these feelings are not entirely surprising. The epistemology of the postmodern story often runs counter to the narrative teleology that we culturally imbibe. A few years ago, the literary journal Granta published a theme issue entitled ‘The Storyteller’ which asked, and then responded to, a question of semantics displayed prominently on its jacket. What does ‘story-teller’ suggest? Folk-tales, myths, sea-voyages, a cartoon campfire: in short, writing that is distinctly unmodern [italics in original].9
That editorial stress on the ‘unmodernity’ of story-telling is revealing. It implies that the activity of story-telling has its roots in a pre-literate, primarily oral, certainly pre-modern, even perhaps a ‘primitive’ ethos. At the same time, the irrepressible urge to tell a simple story, or alternatively, simply tell stories, is one which contemporary civilization has hardly managed to rid itself of. For, the pre-literate instinct still seems to inform the written corpus of the most sophisticated of twentieth-century writers, such as Bruce Chatwin, Rysard Kapuscinski and John Berger, whose work is foregrounded in this particular volume of Granta. The idea is that we fall back on the strong supportive structure of linear narrativity, especially in those instances when we are exploring ‘strangeness’. For example, when we track cultures far away in time and space from our 9Granta, 1987, book-jacket.
14
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
‘own’, as Chatwin does when he tells of the aborigines of Australia, Kapuscinski when he writes of central Africa, and John Berger when he speaks of other ‘ways of looking’ at Europe’s art and social practices, we tend to follow the distinctly ‘unmodern’, but well-beaten, path of the traveller’s tale. The contours of a classic narrative structure—the rope of narrative—enables us to accept ‘defamiliarization’ more easily, smoothly. Narrative, then, is a linguistic structure designed to facilitate cultural cross-overs. That much is clear, but what makes it a discourse universal is its play, its constant shadow jousts, in all cultures, with death—death which is the most certain of species-happenings as well as the most unimaginable. Among the questions Narrative Gravity asks, for instance is: Why? Why is it that the typical image of the ‘story-teller’ in so many cultures is that of an old person, and seldom that of a child or young adult? One answer is that the collective experience of a community, its longest memories, are embodied in the persona of an old man or woman. Another pragmatic response is to suggest that old people, no longer part of the central labour force, have more time to devote to this activity, to keep children out of mischief, etc. In this book, however, I argue for a more complex position. It is this—not only are the aged perceived in several societies as repositories of cultural meme memory, living memebanks as it were, but they are assumed, reasonably enough, to be closer to death, to the narrative closure of their own lives, than any others. It was in fact John Berger, although not in the Granta volume, who once perceptively referred to the figure of the story-teller as ‘Death’s secretary’. For, even on those rare occasions when the figure of a storyteller turns out to be that of a young and beautiful woman like Scheherazade, it is under the shadow of death that her stories are told. Story-telling thus becomes a mode of keeping death at bay, of sustaining life. The more imaginative excess Scheherazade can come up with, the more Dennettian memes she can recall to add to her narratives, the more she is insured against her death being added to all the deaths before her own. This point has been made in other contexts before, but here I use it to suggest that, of the many psychological boundaries that narrative teaches us to breach, one of the most salient is that between personal extinction and cultural preservation, between the teller’s imminent mortality and her audience’s immanent satisfaction. Among the lessons to be derived from the Indian rope analogy are the following: narrative, like magic, is a culturally approved mode of performance. It involves actors, illusions and the creation of psychological effects in the minds of audiences. Audiences, I argue, are crucial to the successful progress of a narrative because the illusionary effects of story-
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
15
telling have to be played out in their minds, not in the story-teller’s. This is one of the ‘paradoxes’ that the analogy of the Indian rope trick highlights—no audience, no narrative completion. Listening to a narrative, like witnessing a magician’s act, is a relatively inexpensive means of trying out patterns of living, situations and emotional reactions that one may never experience, or want to experience, in one’s own life. The feelings, among others, of curiosity, awe, pity, sheer fun, and final reassurance that a narrative evokes—those indirect ‘perlocutionary effects’ of speech act theory—must occur in our minds, not just or even necessarily, within the story-teller’s. Consider how very curious this ordinary fact is. Most cultures operate within a framework where we believe we do things like eating, sleeping, going shopping and making love primarily for our own benefit and pleasure. Story-telling on the other hand seems to manifest a contrary impulse; our altruistic pleasure in telling a story comes not from pleasing ourselves but others, creating silent effects in their minds that we cannot often physically observe. One can understand why a story pleases, or might please a listener, but what’s in it for the teller? Again, many nuanced answers are possible but here is a straightforward one. Narratives are culturally prized, and sometimes dismissed, because they teach us to extend our experience as well as our powers of reasoning, sometimes dangerously. A skilled teller of narratives may risk disapproval if his stories are judged unsuitable by the community—the cautionary tale of Salman Rushdie is a striking example from our own times.10 Strong social approval and community bonding are the major psychological gains that might accrue for ‘good’ story-tellers. It is my contention that the main battles over the kind of ‘object’ narrative is have to be fought mainly in mental terrain. Victories and losses in the realm of story-telling, which seems so overt an activity, have to be understood in terms of covert and hidden mental evaluations and community judgements.11 Our problem as researchers is to find observable correlates for the complex processes that we ‘know’ must go on out of sight during and after the telling of a story. 10In several of my essays on Rushdie’s novels (see Bibliography), I attempt to explain why Rushdie’s use of the techniques of dream-narrative, gossip, etc., to fictionalize the ‘history’ of religious communities, nations, etc., has provoked such furious reactions. The subversive elements in Rushdie’s three main novels, especially The Satanic Verses, have to be understood, I suggest, at least partly in relation to the idea of a writer’s ‘imagined community’, which may include any community which imagines him, as well as his own imagining(s). 11 See A. McCabe and C. Peterson, Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, Vol. 13, Number 6, 1984, on the psychology of ‘What Makes A Good Story?’
16
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
In the Indian rope trick, the magician reconstructs the mutilated body in an invisible space. This is the most crucial part of his trick, yet we do not get to see it. What we witness is the ‘whole’ once again at the end of the act. How ‘real’ then was the magician’s reconstitution? At one level, we know there was never any cutting up, so there cannot be any glueing together; substitution perhaps, sleight of hand, but no glue. Yet, at another level, we accept the evidence of our ‘senses’ that we did witness a dismemberment and a ‘return to life’. What narratives teach us is to live with this contradiction between beliefs we hold to be true, and ‘facts’ which seem to undermine those beliefs. The ‘paradox’ thrown up—literally!—by my Indian Rope Trick of Narrative is that story-telling enables, even encourages us to enjoy contradictions and irrationalities without having to abandon a basic commitment to ‘rational’ choices, causal explanations and so on. As I show in Chapters 6 and 7, many patently ‘false’ or ‘unbelievable’ narratives may be fashioned so as to provide evidence for a moral truth or a generalization in which we, as individuals or members of a culture, do believe, such as ‘God helps those who help themselves’, or ‘It takes a thief to catch a thief ’. The role that narratives play in naturalizing processes of ‘reasoning’ such as relating causes to effects and inductive evidence to deductive inferences, forms a chief theme of this book. Although it was art that Saint Augustine called ‘reason in the making’, that coldly beautiful definition could apply as well to the narrative process. As ‘art’, stories often present or encourage ‘false’ beliefs; what needs to be emphasized is that this fact does not in any way adversely affect our ability to reason in and through them. Indeed, by driving a wedge between ‘words’ and the ‘world’, between representations and reality, they may encourage exactly the kind of sophisticated reflexivity that is needed for abstract, structured, linear thought. Songlines What do stories achieve? In Australian aboriginal myths, the story-teller is a person whose walkabouts criss-cross the continent, so that it springs into being. Every bush, every stream, every clod of earth and human habitation owes its existence to a performative summoning up via narrative. The acts of naming and reference go together; and prior to naming there is only nothingness. That is why it is so important for the story-teller to cover some ground as he tells his stories; were he to stick to only one place, the world would obviously be much, much smaller. To talk as you walk expands both space and time. What stories do, then, is
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
17
not just to sing the world into existence, but to keep the show going, and growing, afterwards. Socio-biologists now speculate that stories, like gossip, were an ancient means of social grooming, through which individual members of the human species both ratified their own existence in the eyes of the community, and the community’s extension in themselves and others.12 But this notion that we exist individually and communally, in, and through, the production of stories, imaginings, brings us back, circling, to the question of what exactly it is that we share when we share stories. To whom do stories belong? How is individual ownership of a story established and maintained, since it is necessarily a shared resource, depending for its ‘value’ on its hearers acknowledging its perlocutionary force and its performative qualities? When stories are passed on as texts within, as well as across, communities, does not the moral issue of plagiarism, the case of ‘pretended’ authorship, then inevitably arise? Are stories ‘fragile’ in the same way that ‘selves’ are fragile, subject to the same processes of mortality, and the same sorts of morality? Who or what are the subjects of narrative? A slew of questions! In Narrative Gravity, we are especially concerned with narratives of disaster, which are required to create a world—an ante-deluvian world, pre-flood. As we know, the theme of havoc wrought by flood is an archetypal one in many cultures, often directly associated with myths of creation. The contemporary, first person, factual, oral, spontaneous, conversational, and in the main, female, witnessing of suffering recorded in this book thus form an intriguing continuum with the traditional third person, fictional, written, literary, rehearsed, and on the whole, male, narrativization on the same theme. Indeed, it could be argued that all these narratives demonstrate something similar—that the human self at an unnatural time, a time of crisis, responds by weaving extra self-protective shells of narrative. Which may be why ancient cultural flood narratives remain with us still, still displaying that durable weave. Likewise, the stories of flood recorded in my corpus could remain in their community repertoires many centuries from now—ensuring the long-term survival of their tellers. We live through our narratives, and the images we make of ourselves in our narratives are the ones that circulate in perpetuity. So what kinds of images of ourselves can we discover in our narratives, past and present? Harriet Ritvo, discussing in another context the classes or categories of 12I refer here to current work on language as an early species ability, carried out, for
example, by researchers like Robin Dunbar and his group at University College, London.
18
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
being to which humans could saliently compare themselves, found only two—a) animals, surrogate nature, and b) God(esses?).13 Through, or in, these forms of existence, Ritvo suggested that we perceive self-images— mortal or immortal; either morally debased or almost divine. In Narrative Gravity, I speculate about adding a third category to hers—machines, and particularly machines like robots and computers which are explicitly created to be human or humanlike, but thought to be lacking a ‘self’, and therefore neither moral nor immoral but simply a-moral. Certainly Dennett, whose anti-foundationalist work on the ‘narrative self’ this book considers in detail, believes that we are comparable to machines, if not actually machines.14 Dennett tells us that narrative activity is our chief mode of self-creation. I argue further that narrative is probably an important instrument of selfprotection as well. It provides, by convention as well as by implication, a format for defining an individual’s social territory, and thereby, that individual’s unique identity within a community. The detours into discussions of Labovian and psycholingusitic ‘story grammars’(Chapter 1); of narrative as a fictional speech act which pays rich dividends in terms of inducing affect or ‘perlocutionary effects’ (Chapter 2); of the deconstruction of performative speech act analyses of interpersonal communication (Chapter 3); of Gricean ‘implication’ and Lewisian ‘convention’ in narrative (Chapter 4); of the enthnomethodology of oral, conversational narrative (Chapter 5); of the mnemonics and meme-power that stories characteristically display across cultures (Chapter 6); of the politics of narrative as ‘real’ accounts, ‘crisis’ or ‘disaster’ (Chapter 7); and, finally, of fiction as enigmatic truth tales (Chapter 8), each leads back ultimately to the question of the ‘sources of self’. Every bend in the theory of narrative seems to affirm the existence of a self who remains ‘fragile’ to the extent that her stories can at any time come under attack from other narrators/tellers. At worst, she can be turned into a social pariah by any widespread and/or powerful perception that she is unable to handle the demands of ‘impliculture’—my extension of the Gricean concept of 13Ritvo, H. The English and Other Creatures in the Victorian Age, 1990. 14I’ve read with interest that Dennett is actually a consultant to a project at the
Massachussetts Institute of Technology which aims to construct a machine, ‘a life-like robot called COG, which will be able to see, touch, and talk to you ... what will all this yield? The hope is that it will explain nothing less than what makes us tick’ (Times Higher Educational Supplement, June 3, 1994). As I had already written on the subject of Nair’s Communicating Cogs for a draft version of this book, I am particularly amused by this development, and wish it all the success it deserves!
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
19
implicature, explained in Chapters 4 and 5—and so does not ‘fit into’ the cultural group. Thus, her claims to identity, to a place within society, can result in mental death through a negative evaluation of her stories. In this respect, a kind of ‘care of the self’—its protection and projection as it is achieved through narrativization—becomes an important concern in the final chapters of this book, where various moral discomforts, pushed away in the earlier chapters, gather darkly and can no more be ignored. These last exploratory chapters of Narrative Gravity consider tape-recordings made, for the most part, in several severely flooded Bengal villages during the major floods of 1978. The ‘self’ is obviously under severe assault, physical and mental, at such times, when one’s whole existence is, literally, awash. At such times, narratives become almost a sole means for rebuilding a lost world, and embankments of words become a chief way to shore up the ‘self ’ and somehow ensure the survival of memory in a community immersed all at once in a tragic logic.15 At any rate, it seems a reasonable hypothesis that the ‘self’ and all that it ‘means’ can most acutely be understood through those devastating stories of crisis that describe a near death of selfhood. In a way, therefore, these personal narratives of calamitous ‘natural kind’ disaster cannot help but constitute an extensive and homogenous corpus in another language of the classic danger-of-death stories first studied in English by Labov and Waletsky (1966) and Labov (1972). There are, however, differences. Labov recorded ‘nominal kind’ dangers, such as fights and knifings, and his environments were metropolitan and rural. Chapter 7 shows how the apparently inconsequential differences between dangers to the self from a natural-kind source and a nominal-kind source have major consequences for how we theorize narrative and its role in a wider political context. This change of gears from ‘problems and paradoxes’ to ‘enigmas and empathies’ in Chapters 7 and 8 means, effectively, that they form what Labov would call a kind of evaluative ‘coda’ to the book. The silt of human emotion that such narratives carry seem to me to problematize anew those ‘logical’ problems of the distinctions between factual and fictional narrative by carrying them over into a ‘real world’ where ‘historical’ accounts of disaster, classically concerned with 15Since the floods in question were possibly the most severe known in the region for the century, they formed a topic of conversation almost everywhere and at all levels. This data is therefore of some socio-linguistic interest. In view of this and of its relative unfamiliarity, I include in Appendix I, an extract from an official statement made at the time, detailing the nature and extent of these floods. In Appendix II, I set out the notation I have used in transcribing this and other data, as well as the procedures I have broadly followed in my translation of Bengali into English.
20
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
recording ‘facts’, are contrasted with the quasi-literary ‘personal’ tellings of people, and especially women, where the main concern is to illuminate ‘suffering’. Here we are forced to tread the intellectually most murky, but also perhaps deepest, waters of narrativity—issues of power and ownership, agency and institutional control in Chapter 7; and notions of explanation, coincidence, enigma and the incomprehensibility of death and an end to our narratives, in Chapter 8. It is the fragility of our theorizing about, as well as through, narrative, that is the ironic theme of these last chapters. The final chapter of the work, ‘Narrative Sutras’, then attempts to knot together as many of the theoretical loose ends that the analogy of the Indian rope trick naturally suggests, using the format of a textual device nearly as ancient as the goddess Vac herself. The sutra is a brief gnomic summary of an entire thesis or argument which can be ‘unknotted’, or, alternatively, left bereft of any interpretation whatsoever, depending on an interlocutor’s interest. Looping back to the detailed and often tedious arguments presented in the book, is only one of the ways to unknot a sutra. There are several alternative Alexandrian methods of cutting the Gordian knot as well, which depend largely on the reader’s ingenuity. For a shot at unknotting a sutra, turn to page 347, but consider before then the following schematic representation of some of the positions on narrativity and the self that we have discussed so far. The Goddess Speaks Position I—The Authorless Narrator of Dennett—We are not singular selves, and our narrative texts do not really have the singular authors we take them to have. The fact is that we are machines. Sophisticated biological machines, it is true, but still machines, designed to endlessly produce the ‘multiple drafts’ of narrative from which we derive, fallaciously, our ‘singular’ self-representations. Consciousness within the Dennettian perspective is epiphenomenonal; we attribute ‘intentional stances’ to others, and to ourselves, because we postulate for each body a mental centre, but this is just a convenience. A self is a narrative congeries, so to speak, rather than a unity. Dennett’s anti-essentialist, and possibly anti-moralist arguments thus dissolve the part/whole system so central to the ‘thing-in-itself ’ structural analyses, not to mention the categorical moral dicta that Kant held were part of a ‘universal’ ethical order.16 Position II—The Searlean Performer—Strong opposition from this quarter to Dennett’s ‘anti-humanist’ anti-foundationalist stand. We have to be different from machines because we, unlike ‘them’, have intentions,
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
21
feelings, desires. We actually understand what words mean, rather than merely produce ‘correct’ responses as a machine, however complicated, might. We can tell fiction from non-fiction, truth from falsity, as no animal or machine can. Ergo, we cannot be machines. Short Reply from Dennett to Searle—Searle begs the question when he claims that we understand words while machines don’t. How can he ever know? Why not think of it this way? Machines are not (yet) us, but we are machines. It’s only that we are very special machines—meaningproducing machines, rationalizing and feeling machines; and the way we achieve these effects of feeling (excitement, happiness, sorrow, curiosity) is by extruding narratives. Our narratives make us the feeling, thinking, rational creatures we imagine ourselves to be. They teach us to handle both fact and fiction and they create the illusion of an intentional ‘Centre of Narrative Gravity’. Very Short Reply from Searle to Dennett —Not to nit-pick. But doesn’t ‘very special machine’ beg the question in much the same way as it was suggested ‘actually understand’ does? Position III—Nair’s Communicating Cog—Having, literally, by shameless recourse to the story-teller’s cloak of absolute licence, put words into the mouths of Dennett and Searle, it seems the guilty party must speak up. Assuming a mediatory role, Nair sees merit both in Searle’s emphasis on human performativity and Dennett’s focus on human design. She has no problem at all with Dennett’s idea that we are biological machines designed to produce narrative self-representations, but because the norms for such self-representations are initially learnt (as Dennett admits, even insists), she feels that our ‘own’ narratives strands are umbilically connected to those produced by ‘others’ within the community. We can only learn narrative performance from other humans in the first place, and not from either gods, animals or machines. This is not to suggest that we cannot teach a robot to tell stories, and then learn from it in turn, but rather that narrative activity, unlike language, is not, and very probably could not have developed as, a solitary pastime. It must always have required the presence of a specifically human community for narrative interaction to take place—given that other species show no great predilection either for 16Unless one were to argue that such moral injunctions were biologically programmed, just like language rules or the propensity to produce narratives. I’m not sure how Dennett would respond to this line of enquiry, as he does not address it in his book, but as a liberal thinker, he would sooner or later surely be drawn to take a position on it, especially as he is now committed to building an intelligent, ‘feeling’ robot .
22
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
lying, or for language, or for conceptualizing the passage of time. For Nair, narrative, somewhat like sex, is an interlocking device for selfperpetuation that has of necessity to involve at least two members of the human community before it can work. It evokes the same high affect (love, despair, agony, fear, curiosity, surprise) because it too relies on the dialogic, or even as Bakhtin might have it, a polyphonic imagination. Like the body, narrative, to be ‘creative’, needs interpretive listeners as well as active tellers. Nair therefore wants to replace Dennett’s ‘authorless narrative’ with the idea of a ‘co-authored narrative’. She wishes to suggest that those ‘multiple drafts’ of narrative that Dennett says are spun round a supposed singular ‘self’ actually have ‘multiple authors’ as well. That is, all our narratives have to be communally authored, and authorized, by listeners whose job it is to ‘correctly’ process tellers’ implicultural meanings. Even though the single authorships of selves is a convenient fiction, which, given our physical separation from each other, all societies must, in general, underwrite, Nair holds that narrative activity depends on tacit acceptance of the notion of multiple authorship in all human communities. The ‘paradox’ of the narrative function of language is that it both promotes the illusion of separateness, and at the same time, implicates us in inter-dependence. We may also infer something about the moral positions we could take towards ‘our’ narratives from this paradox. Since we cannot, in fact, ever manage to produce any narrative, simple or complex, entirely on our own, it follows that ‘care’ of narrative ‘selves’ should be a shared onus. The alternative to communal ‘multiple authorship’ is not single self-adducing ‘multiple drafts’, but the silence, or silencing, of the self. A consequence is that no single ‘author’ can ever be held solely responsible for the narratives he has ‘intentionally’ produced, since his stories could not have been performed at all without the cognitive input of the communit(ies) which produced him, and his particular illusion of an authorial ‘self’, in the first place. Every individual ‘self’, according to Nair, is thus a cog, big or little, in the wheel of community. Of course, this cog-in-the-wheel analogy may at first glance appear distasteful to those who see it as reductive, and a denial of individuality, insinuating that each one of us has our assigned ‘place’ in a fixed social system, and that’s that. However, I’d like to reiterate that the main feature of a cog is that it is designed to lock in with other cogs, its jagged edges fashioned to smoothly fit with other edges to produce motion and energy. Our boundaries of self are both defined and extended when we meet with others through our narratives. As I suggested earlier, we communicating cogs may
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
23
well have command over two basic kinds of narrative—narratives of the self and narratives to the other. Our centres may be created by the first kind of narratives, but our boundaries, our defences, are marked by the second kind. We are cogs whose business is to communicate—to perform intricate, interlocking narrative dances. That is what stimulates us most; this unavoidably cooperative creation of theories is what we are best at, even if they sometimes take outlandish, contestatory, and even painful forms. Not only because we make them for each other, but because we cannot make them without each other, our narratives in the last resort force on us a few unlikely lessons in tolerance and solidarity. One of the more paradoxical traits of narrative, as I emphasized in connection with the Indian rope trick, seems to be that it facilitates a reconciliation of conflicting sets of beliefs in our minds. It enables an audience to accept the ‘neither-dead-nor-aliveness’ of a magician’s victim, until such time as the performance comes to an end. And at another level narrative rests on a presumption of listeners’ or readers’ charity. Take, for example, the frequent changes of gender pronominals (sometimes my listener has been a ‘he’, sometimes a ‘she’, likewise my story-teller), with which I have burdened the reader throughout this chapter. Such licence comes from my belief that there is an astounding sense-making ability which all sophisticated interpreters of texts bring to a ‘telling’. From multiple settings and complex character changes, even contradictions and incongruities, adept listeners can extract a main logical thread, and may indeed enjoy such inferencing in proportion, the more knots you deliberately introduce. This is how they display both their skill and their cooperation as masters of narrative unravelling. Tolerance of confusions and mysteries, containment of fears and anxieties, leaps of inference and interpretation—these are what we might declare narrativity, as a species of theory, is all about. If so, it is about time to recall the enigmatic goddess Vac, now at the end of this chapter, as we did at the beginning. The beliefs we hold today would hardly allow us to give any credence at all to what poor Vac ‘said’ in her classic Rigvedic speech, because of course, not being human, she could not possibly have said anything at all! It had to be someone else, a mere mortal, one of ‘us’, speaking ‘through’ her, much as Dennett might speak in a few years’ time through his robot Cog. ‘But’, replies the goddess, ‘you’ve stolen my argument—mark my words’ : The one who eats food, who truly sees, who breathes, who hears what is said, does so through me.
24
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Who, then, is speaking ‘through’ whom? Well, to us in the twenty-first century, it seems indubitably the case that it is we humans who speak through, for and about, the goddess, since goddesses simply don’t exist. But did the person(s) who ‘put’ these words into the mouth of the goddess believe she did not exist? Given our beliefs about the history of early Aryanism, we would probably agree that it is quite likely that they believed in the existence of the goddess Speech, just as Dennett believes that one day Cog will have a ‘mind of his own’, and Searle believes equally vehemently that Cog will not. If we concede this much, however, we are mired in an argumentative impasse, even before this book, in struggling defiance of gravity, has got off the ground, let alone to regions ‘beyond the sky, beyond this earth’. Attributing speech to a goddess called Speech is impossible for two independent reasons—the first is our current belief that speech is restricted to humans, and the second is our conviction that goddesses are non-existent, anyway. However, not attributing speech to Vac privileges our beliefs over those people who originally ‘heard’ these words from a goddess they were sure could speak, and did exist. How may we get away from this relativistic conundrum? As we know well, there is still no solution to the primal etiological mysteries. What were the origins of speech? There can be neither a wholly logical nor empirical answer to this question since we can never ‘know’ what took place, but can at best tell stories about our origins, theorize our ancestry.17 Under the circumstances, Vac’s assertion carries the same weight and is as laden with gravity as ours, only we prefer to ‘give more weight’ to our own. The study of narrative thus prompts us to question our most privileged truths and to value the stirrings of doubt. Anything is possible in narrative, because in truth anything is possible once we are able to develop some tolerance towards theories that seemed to us a little fantastic to begin with. As communicating cogs, we are bound to exchange narratives with Vac, Dennett, Searle—however strange their stories may appear to us, unless we wish to be excluded from the human conversation altogether—surely, a fate worse than death! Death. The point has been made before that the end of a story anticipates death. The closing of the narrative sequence, its coda, marks a formal separation from all the other cogs still merrily spinning along. It metaphorically describes the final dissolution of the ‘self’. I have called 17This point about the unavailability of logical solutions to our puzzlement about our origins has often been made. See, for example, J. Hillis Miller’s article on narrative in Lentricchia and Mclaughlin Critical Terms for Literary Study, 1990, p.72, which is also discussed in Chapter 4.
I N T RO D U C T I O N : F I R S T C O N V E R S AT I O N A L S T E P S
25
this book Narrative Gravity partly because the phonology as well as the polysemy of the second word in the title seems to resonate well with the overwhelming sense of mortality which narrative drags with it. Gravity, locked in an onomatopoeic tackle with all those other groaning English words—grief, grind, gruesome, grumble, grovel, grunt, growl, grisly, grim, but also, to keep things in proportion, grin. Then, there is the semantics of gravity; cognate with the Sanskrit word ‘guru’ or teacher, whose words carry most ‘weight’ in the culture and who attracts all wisdom unto himself or herself (Vac?); gravity, also meaning seriousness; gravity, meaning a centrifugal force which attracts; and grave, shadowy half-homonym of gravity, meaning a place of burial, that space where gravity finally holds the ‘self’ down.18 ‘The grave’s a fine and private place, but none I think do there embrace’, wrote the poet Andrew Marvell once, with a fine flourish of irony. There is, however, perhaps one paradoxical instance in which the grave does turn into ‘a fine and public place’, ideally suited to ‘embraces’ of all kinds, even with death itself, because we know that, whether or not we live to tell the tale, the tale will live to tell us.19 As I hope the rest of this book will show, that vital centre is—narrative. 18Speaking of etymologies, not only is the Sanskrit word ‘guru’ cognate with ‘gravity’, as I have mentioned, but the word ‘narrative’ itself also has its origins in Sanskrit. See, for example, H. Porter Abbott: ‘Hayden White pointed out in his book The Content of the Form that the word “narrative” goes back to the ancient Sanskrit “gna”, a root that means “know” and that it comes to us through Latin words for both “knowing” (“gnarus”) as well as “telling” (“narro”). This etymology catches the two sides of narrative. It is a tool for knowing as well as telling, for absorbing knowledge as well as expressing it’ (The Cambridge Introduction to Narrative, 2002, p. 11). Abbott’s intervention thus fits in well with my own notion of narrative as a major theoretical tool that helps organize knowledge for the human species. 19 As an interesting coincidence, the Nobel prize-winning author Gabriel Garcia Marquez’s much-awaited autobiography, written under the danger-of-death shadow of lymphatic cancer—the first volume of which was published in 2002—is actually called Vivir Para Contaria or To Live To Tell It. In an article on the subject, Juan Forero comments: ‘To be sure, this is a writer famously obsessed with death … it is evident in all his books; nearly all start with death or a similar theme’. Forero then goes on to quote Gustavo Tatis from Cartagena, rich in oral story-telling traditions and the city where Marquez served his apprenticeship as a writer and reporter: ‘All his motivation is contained in that title, To Live To Tell It—it is the pleasure of telling the story. It is like saying life has been worth living’ (The New York Times, October 9, 2002). My contention in Narrative Gravity is very similar. The emotional ‘pleasure of telling the story’ and thus providing a ‘theoretical explanation’ of why ‘life is worth living’ seems to be a species characteristic that motivates the cultural production of narrative in every known human society and makes it perhaps the most widespread of ‘discourse universals’.
26
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
1
qQ STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES The Grammar and Context of Narrative (Guru: William Labov)
A. A violent order is disorder; and B. A great disorder is an order. These Two things are one. (Pages of illustrations.) After all the pretty contrast of life and death Proves that these opposite things partake of one, At least that was the theory, when bishops’ books Resolved the world. We cannot go back to that. The squirming facts exceed the squamous mind If one may say so. Now, A And B are not like statuary, posed For a vista in the Louvre. They are things chalked On the sidewalk so that the pensive man might see. The pensive man ... He sees that eagle float For which the intricate Alps are a single nest. Wallace Stevens, Connoisseur of Chaos My relation to Structuralism [is] against shutting oneself in the text. ... The resulting formalization and depersonalization: all relations are of a logical nature (in the broad sense of the term). I, on the other hand, hear voices everywhere, and dialogic relations among them. M. Bakhtin, Concerning Methodology in the Human Sciences
Structuralism spanned the early and middle decades of the twentieth century like a great cantilever bridge. Conceptually girded like an engineer’s marvel, it led the ‘pensive men’ (Ferdinand de Saussure,
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
27
Claude Levi-Strauss, Roman Jakobson) who set it up to think that its stretch might cover all those ‘squirming facts’ which Wallace Stevens found so hard to order. In their choice of primary materials, however, most structuralists seemed to prefer to study ‘the statuary in the Louvre’ rather than ‘the things chalked on the side walk’. So, Claude Levi-Strauss’s primary materials included the Greek myths, and Vladimir Propp’s morphology analysed the Russian folk-tale; but stories as a part of casual conversation seemed to evade that ‘eagle’s eye’ analysis which made of complex intricacies the ‘single nest’ demanded by high structuralism. But today, the doctrinal pages of the ‘bishops’ books’ of structuralism have been swept aside by the viewless winds of deconstruction and postmodernism. Why bother to resurrect them? Well, for a start, every member of the human species seems born a connoisseur of chaos. An escape from the structural paradigm, cognitively rather than culturally defined, hardly appears possible for the only species on the planet caught in the perceptual trap of linear time, which ‘hears voices everywhere’ and defines its sense of community through talk and language. As a historical production, structuralism may be passé but its mental sources run deep. The biologist’s impulse to dissect and label the body of Vac, to impose an order on the squirming facts, has always driven, and will continue to motivate, both our fascination with binaries—mirroring the alternating ABABAB structures of conversation—as well as our strong intuitions about linear sequencing—reflecting the temporal ‘and then’ ABCCDE structure of narrative. That is why it seems important, even as we accept the inevitability of a cognitive bondage to structural principles, occasionally to ponder over our pre-programmed and potentially ‘violent’—an adjective implied by Vac and used by Stevens—structuralist procedures of enquiry in the human sciences across cultures. In this first chapter, I return to the seventies and early eighties—the heyday of the ‘story-grammars’. These grammars all shared the premise that there is, out there in the world, a natural, linear structure of events. Our words, for the most part, follow and secure this powerful temporal order. That is to say, in a story-grammar, as in life, it would be distinctly odd for an Outcome or Resolution to precede an Action, such as in the following inversion presented by Harvey Sacks: The mommy picked it up. The baby cried.
Sacks points to the normal structure of our inferences. We expect that: If the baby cried, it ought to have started crying before the mother picked it up, and not after. Hearing it that way, the second sentence ‘The mommy picked it
28
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
up’ is explained by the first ‘The baby cried’. Hearing them as consecutive, or with the second preceding the first, some further explanation is needed.1
The psycholinguist J.M. Levelt makes the cognitive implications of Sacks’ remark clear: Linearization ... serves the main purpose of evoking certain inferences in the mind of the listener. Order is one determinant of implicature. ... Order of mention apparently implicates order of events ... The old principle in rhetoric corresponding to this is known as ordo naturalis. Natural order is, so to speak, the unmarked form of linearization. All other words, the so called artificial orders, are designed to create special attentional or aesthetic effects. A psycholinguistic consideration of linearization starts out most profitably with the unmarked case. ... The principle of natural order may have two related but still different, psychological sources. ... A first source is the organization of the speaker’s own pre-linguistic experience. An event-structure, for instance, is in our culture quite likely memorized in such a way that consecutive events are more closely associated than non-consecutive events. ... The other source of natural order is conversational [emphasis mine]. If the speaker intends the listener to derive certain implicatures from the order in which things are said, he should base his speech on mutual knowledge. There is general knowledge in our culture that causes precede effects, that means are sought before ends are achieved, that planning precedes execution, etc. By using unmarked order, the speaker can make sure that the listener will correctly apply such knowledge and come up with the intended implicature. ... Here the speaker’s and the listener’s interests are likely to coincide: if the speaker’s retrieval process is, in part, governed by what is stereotypic in the culture, the listener will be able to use the same stereotype to encode and store the information. The short answer, therefore, to what makes natural order so natural is that it allows for easy retrieval on the part of the speaker and for easy inference on the part of the listener, given shared general or more specific knowledge in the speech community.2
Levelt’s strategy of setting inference-making from such domains of discourse as stories within the context of a cooperative speech community means that the ‘two sources’ of ‘natural order’ with which I’m concerned in this book—the narrative and the conversation—are inevitably drawn together. Departures from this dominant combination of natural orders, as in the Sacks story, are also ‘naturally’ noticed, since they demand extra effort at sense-making. The ‘Paradox of the Indian 1H. Sacks, ‘On the Analysability of Stories by Children’ in Gumperz and Hymes (eds), 1972, pp. 330–1. 2J.M. Levelt, ‘The Speaker’s Linearization Problem’ in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Vol. 295, Number 1077, 2 October 1981, pp. 93–4.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
29
Rope Trick’, to which I return at the end of this chapter, focuses on these ‘so called artificial orders…designed to create special attentional or aesthetic effects’. The ordering of the world, in effect, is a cognitive process which requires us to rely on our intuitive understanding of linearization as temporal. If we were to imagine the ‘now’ universe of, say, chaffinches, or chimps, or very young babies, or even patients with Alzheimer’s, we would surely attribute to them a much fuzzier sense of time. This would imply that they are unable to process the world in narrative terms. Narrative requires, that is, a meta-theory of time. The deep illusion—if illusion it is—that we harbour about the unidirectionality of the arrow of time actually helps us to organize chaos. Because we hold fast to the belief that, despite Einstein’s equations, perceptual and physical time both flow always forwards, we are able to play narrative games with time— to cut it up, re-sequence and re-label parts of the body of Vac and then recombine them. Narrative is perhaps our most efficient way of packaging our perceptions of time, which in turn crucially promotes our sense of individual identity. Sorting events into a temporal format which enables easy storage, easy retrieval and easy cultural exchange confers a distinct evolutionary advantage. As several recent studies have shown, there is a clear time lag between the perception of an event and its recording by the brain.3 This suggests that what we ‘consciously’ see or hear is a sort of continuous ‘action replay’, split seconds after things happen. In other words, at the very moment we prove ourselves excellent narrators who can connect events with amazing facility, we are robbed of much agency or decision-making power over what we perceive. Yet this lost agency is then returned to us through another channel, since the ‘stereotypic’ expectations we have of an event invest it with structure before it takes place—allowing us to ‘predict’ how it will work out. That is why I called narrative a ‘species of natural theory’ in my Introduction; in this chapter, I shall try to show how the analysis of the structuralist story-grammarians in fact highlights this ‘theoretical’ nature of narrative. What does any theory accomplish? At its simplest, it describes observable phenomena, makes deductive generalizations about these, and creates a meta-vocabulary of statements that are in principle falsifiable and thus have non-trivial predictive power. A ‘good’ theory must also suggest replicable experiments which anybody with suitable skills can 3For a documentation of these experiments, see Chapters 12–13 of Paul Davies,
About Time, 1995.
30
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
carry out, experiments which reinforce its claims to have ‘explained’ the phenomena in question. Furthermore, we have to assume that it is a characteristic of a good theory that it keeps up a constant struggle to maintain its place against competing theories which could provide simpler, more elegant and more exciting explanations for the same phenomena. Now narratives, I submit, paradigmatically do all these things: they describe things and events in the world, generate meta-vocabularies such as those on display in the terminology of the structuralist storygrammars (Abstract, Orientation, Action, Cause, Evaluation, Resolution, Coda, etc.), make generalizations which may be falsified by a community of skilled listeners, predict events, are reproduced in a ‘formulaic’ mode; and, finally, offer explanations of both psychological and physical phenomena. A narrative, as ‘theory’, competes with other narratives that could displace it because they offer ‘better’ and more ‘universal’ explanations of a comparable range of phenomena. Conversational narrative thus functions as ‘theory in the round’, if not exactly ‘theatre in the round’, with several opportunities for listeners to present rival narrative accounts. Of course, a great deal of tedium is involved in ‘proving’ such a hypothesis about the purpose of narrative. One wishes that the ‘pages of illustrations’ that Stevens so neatly bracketed off in his poem were unnecessary. However, since we can assume no such thing, let’s start with as unobjectionable a set of observations as possible. A Thought Experiment Story-telling is an intuitively recognizable and frequently observed phenomenon in everyday conversation. Like the sentence, it is highly amenable to structural analysis, being linear and hierarchically organized. It possesses, too, the same capacity for infinite recursive embedding. One can imagine, if not process, a very long sentence that would include all the words in a given language, some more than once, and still have room left over. Such a sentence, if we were to change over to a ‘post-structuralist’ perspective for a moment, could be said to ‘drain’ language, to blanch it of its ‘potential meanings’, and convert them into ‘narrative meanings’. Throughout this book, I shall engage with the implications of this narrative takeover over meaning. A simple prediction follows: should anyone try the Gedankenexperimente of attempting to construct that mythical Indian rope trick of a sentence, she will end up before long with a compelling narrative turn to her production. Long sentences naturally tend to metamorphose into narrative.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
31
I begin, then, with the premise that narrative has the same psychological validity as the sentence. It is as central in cognitive processing. While the sentence is accepted, however, as perhaps the most significant of grammatical universals, the narrative has still to win its spurs as a discourse universal—an indispensable communicative and cognitive tool for selffashioning across cultures.4 Narrative differs from the sentence in that it tends constantly to break through the ‘upper bound’ of grammatical analysis and enter a different and less well-charted realm. The realm of ‘discourse’, peopled with speakers, hearers and enriched with context. My examination of ‘story-grammars’ in this first chapter is thus committed to teasing out the notion of context in relation to the grammatical units of a story described by structuralist researchers like Labov and Waletsky and Mandler and Johnson: Steps I and II, in fact, of the mad, methodological parabola described in my Introduction. Surprisingly, or perhaps not so surprisingly, given their historical genesis, the psycholinguistic story-grammars of the seventies, and the more literary structural analysis presented by Barthes, also in the seventies, resemble the Labovian schema (Abstract, Orientation, Complicating Action, Resolution, Coda and Evaluation) closely. It is possible to group together these variegated readings of narrative, because they all suffer from a problem common to structural analyses of social phenomena: they leave very little place for inter-subjectivity, for the ‘squamous mind’ to spill over. In the structural picture of narrative, both the external, political state of the world and the internal, plural state of mind, are factored out. There is a notorious absence of contextualizing conventions within structuralist accounts of narrative, even when these accounts deal, as in Labov and Waletsky’s case, with ‘spontaneous’, ‘oral’ narratives. Context, signifying both the physical setting in which a story is told, as well as conversational interventions by listeners and other participants, has of necessity to be reduced to a cipher whenever a distant eagle’s-eye vision that makes of ‘the intricate Alps a single nest’ is resorted to. It is one of my main criticisms of structuralism that it distorts significantly those intimate processes of twigged reception and arboreal interaction between tale, 4But see, for example, William Odlin’s impassioned plea for narrative as a ‘discourse universal’, which emphasizes those ‘formulaic characteristics that recur in the oral literature of many communities’ (Levi-Strauss 1955; Dundes 1964; Propp 1968). On the basis of some of these formulaic characteristics, scholars (Thorndyke 1977; Mandler et al. 1980) have developed ‘story-grammars; to suggest the role that linguistic organisation plays in signalling discourse. ... [Many] of the narratives characterized in story-grammars are quite common in story-telling traditions and have a number of recurrent properties.’
32
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
teller and audience that shape the ‘nest’ of narrative in the first place. Co-authored stories, so necessary to the resolution of the Indian Rope Trick of Narrative, because they yield the vital conversation resin (expressions of appreciation, ‘you knows’, ‘ums’, and ‘I means’) that could glue the sundered body of Vac together again, are rendered impossible. Despite the reassuringly ‘natural’ metaphor of the nested ‘tree’ that the structural paradigm makes use of, its terse, hierarchical trees in fact disallow any of the additional information that the teller has to assume the hearer contributes in order make sense of the story. This matter of how a listener construes or infers ‘additional meanings’ not present in any literal way in a teller’s narrative will occupy us for a considerable part of Narrative Gravity. Here, I discuss how some parts of the Labovian schema, such as the Abstract, Evaluation and Coda, particularly relate to the presence of an audience. Audience reactions, the twitters, chirps and trills of participation, are shown not just to influence a teller’s story but to be structurally a part of the story. Hence, the story begins to emerge not just as a teller’s show but rather as a joint production by narrators(s) and listeners(s), speaker(s) and hearer(s). Chapters 4–8 then carry this interactional approach further by showing how the shared cultural generalizations that function as premises for narrative tellings are often made explicit not by the narrator but by the listener. A more satisfactory route to an understanding of narrative coherence, or the singularity of narrative, therefore seems to place it, paradoxically, within a plural framework where ‘self’ and ‘other’ both contribute directly to the structure of narrative. This, in essence, is what I understand by a strong ‘communicative’ reading of narrative—no assumption of a prior context of conversation, no narrative activity. Pages of Illustrations I now provide some of those ‘pages of illustrations’ which might enable a reassessment of the ambitious goals of structuralist research on narrative, concentrating on one paradigmatic instance. This is a paper by William Labov and Josef Waletzky, acknowledged as a classic in sociolinguistic studies,5 which argued forcefully that stories told in spontaneous conversation could, and indeed should, be subject to formal analysis, 5William Labov and Josef Waletzky, ‘Narrative Analysis: Oral Versions of Personal Experience’, Essays in the Verbal and Visual Arts, 1966, p.12.
33
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
since the ‘fundamental structures of narrative are to be found in oral versions of personal experience’. Labov and Waletzky maintained that: By examining the actual narratives of large numbers of unsophisticated speakers, it will be possible to relate the formal properties of narrative to their functions. By studying the development of narrative technique from children to adults, and the range of narrative technique from lower-class to middle-class speakers, it will be possible to isolate the elements of narrative.6
The Labov and Waletzky theory of narrative could be represented thus:7 ANALYSIS OF NARRATIVE
FORMAL
FUNCTIONAL
[A formal analysis is based on ‘recurrent patterns characteristic of narrative from the clause level to the complete simple narrative’. The techniques used to establish such patterns are formal, linguistic ones, for example, the working out of a temporal sequence out of ‘displacement sets’ of clauses.]
[A functional analysis narrative is considered as ‘one verbal technique for recapitulating past experience’ which works by constructing narrative units that match the experience as it occurred.]
REFERENTIAL [The narrative refers to past experience.]
EVALUATIVE [The function of ‘personal interest is determined by a stimulus in the social context in which the narrative occurs’.]
Fig. 2.1 As the figure indicates, the ‘functions’ of narrative comprise the pragmatic aspects of story-telling. In contrast, Labov and Waletzky have in mind a specifically syntactic analysis for the ‘formal’ properties of narrative. Their formal structure of narrative is based on a definition of the ‘narrative 6See also the amendments suggested by Labov in his fuller paper of 1972, memorably entitled ‘The Tranformation of Experience in Narrative Syntax’. 7I choose to present Labov and Waletzky’s ideas schematically for two reasons: (a) they themselves adopt such a representation in their analysis of narrative; (b) a ‘treediagram’ helps when I compare their work to the psycholinguistic story-grammars. Roland Barthes’ structural schema for narrative in terms of ‘codes’ and ‘indices’, although applied mainly to literary texts, is also relevant here because of the striking representational similarity it bears to the Labovian design; see Chapter 5.
34
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
clause’, as opposed to other relative coordinate clauses in the narrative, having an ‘unordered displacement set’. In other words, ‘it is characteristic of a narrative clause that it cannot be displaced across a temporal juncture,8 without a change in the temporal sequence of the original semantic interpretation’. Thus, ‘any sequence of clauses which contains at least one temporal juncture is a narrative’ [italics mine].9 Labov and Waletzky admit that this definition of narrative which is a formalization of their functional characterization of it as ‘one method of recapitulating past experience in the same order as past events’ remains inadequate. To begin with, it cannot disambiguate ‘ambiguous’ cases where two distinct interpretations are possible. Thus, to quote Labov, and Waletzky’s own example—‘I punched him in the head and the mouth and the chest’—is normally a list which does not imply that the object of violence was punched in the head, then in the mouth, then in the chest, but a temporal interpretation is nevertheless possible, thus cognitively turning the set of clauses into a narrative. Now consider a) and b) below, which provide more complex instances of recorded data where sets of clauses containing impeccable sequences of temporal junctures do not seem to be interpreted by participants as narratives; and conversely, instances in conversation where participants display unmistakable signs of recognition that a narrative is in progress, despite the fact that the ‘story-teller’ has not offered them a sequence of clauses containing a temporal juncture. Example a)offers an example of the former kind, and example b) of the latter. a) Sequences of clauses with ‘temporal junctures’ apparently not recognized by participants as narrative: S1—My husband can’t talk at all. When we ... got married, he used to talk then. And then, of course, it was an old-fashioned marriage. I got married at ten. He was sixteen. Contracting typhoid and pneumonia in those days meant he lost both speech and hearing…which is why we [have to/try to] manage with the [sewing-] machine somehow. As far as the children are concerned, I collect [their] books, and I now fund their teaching in this way. If they ever grow to manhood, [with this education] they [should] be able to fend for themselves. S2—How much money did you get last time? 8Two clauses which are temporally ordered so that the displacement range of the one clause does not extend past the actual location of the other following clause, and conversely, the displacement range of the following clause does not extend past the actual location of the preceding clause, are said to be separated by a temporal juncture. 9Labov and Waletzky, p. 28.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
35
S1—Er, I got about a hundred rupees last time. This story is the succinct recapitulation of a lifetime of tragedy. It is about the loss of Vac, of speech, in a most fundamental sense. Structurally, the temporal deixis of ‘now’ preceded by ‘in those days’ leaves us in no doubt that S1 has just engaged in an extended ‘narrative’ of survival, yet S2 does not react in a conventionally appropriate fashion at all. Not only does he not display any signs through ‘backchannel’ utterances like ‘mm’ ‘aha’ and so on that he is listening to a story, but he is brutally detached in the first turn after its completion, even though he exercises his right to that turn as the main addressee.10 Moreover, if his turn following the completion of the story is a comment on the story, it is at first glance a peculiar one. Indeed, S2 manifests no overt signs of recognition at all in the course of this conversation that a devastating story has just been narrated. Despite this, his question at the end of the story is treated, surprisingly, as perfectly coherent by the teller of the story, who promptly answers it. Within the cultural bounds of this conversation, S2 has apparently produced a ‘correct’ response. Is a story in context then the same sort of object as a story in isolation? Were this ‘story’ removed from its conversational context and treated independently as Labov and Waletzky have treated their data, it would surely qualify as an authentic story. With context as background one might pose a different set of questions about it. In the course of my exploration of the paradoxes of narrativity, I will try and suggest the sorts of questions these might be. There are, of course, many ways in which S2’s response can be rationalized so that it is seen as perfectly coherent. For example, what Dell Hymes calls ‘setting’ constrains responses to stories: S2’s response to S1’s story is acceptable in an official situation where the ‘hard luck’ story is a prelude to a handout. At this stage, however, my purpose is only to establish that S2 does not recognize S1’s story qua story. That is, a sequence of clauses with several intervening temporal junctures does not seem to be regarded as a ‘story’, if we go by the story recipient’s response. Part of the difficulty stems simply from Labov and Waletzky’s ambiguous use of the word ‘context’ for it is never quite clear whether this refers to the broad social setting of the narrative or to its particular conversational environment, meaning the turns in conversation that precede and succeed the story. If the word ‘context’ 10I was present, and S1 was aware of my presence in the room but her appeal was directed wholly at S2.
36
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
is understood in this latter, more precise sense, then Labov and Waletzky exclude it almost entirely from their examples, in spite of their claim that the context in which a story is told is ‘a matter quite relevant to the functional analysis of the narrative’. In each of the fourteen examples presented by them, the story is abstracted from the conversation of which it must have formed an integral part. Hence, the elements postulated by Labov and Waletzky, as essential to a story do not emerge specifically and convincingly out of their enquiry into it as an oral version of events. With the possible exception of the category ‘Coda’, the other elements of Orientation, Complication, Evaluation and Resolution ironically apply more tellingly to a textual story than to a story told in conversation. Indeed, I would suggest that the structuralist approach adopted by Labov and Waletzky actually prevents a complete appreciation of the notion of ‘context’. Severe violence needs to be done to the alternating structure of conversational order in order to emphasize the linear sequence of narrative order. b) Here, participants display recognition within the conversation that a narrative is in progress, although the story-teller has not offered them a sequence of clauses containing a temporal juncture: d
921
c B 9
922 923 255 926 927 928 929 930 931 932 933 934 935 936 937 938 939
A B
A B
Tell Nancy your story about your professor. I don’t believe this at all. Are you ? Who is this Saul ? [m] he INSISTED that I and about four members of the STAFF and one senior POST GRADUATE go to his lectures on Pushtu LANGUAGES one would THINK given his AUDIENCE that he would be a LITTLE BETTER than exceedingly ELEMENTARY he came up with a gem TODAY (laughs) all about two WORDS in one of his LANGUAGES one of which began with—on a HIGH tone one of (laughs) which began with a ‘k’ on a LOW tone
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
940
c B ? All d B ? c B
c B A
B d B
941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 950 951 952 953 954 955 956 957 958 959 960 961 962 963 964 965
966 967 968 969 970 c 971 B 972 c 973 d 974 A 975 976 977 All 978
37
it being a basic point of phonetic theory that the ‘k’ can’t be distinguished TONALLY [m] and this is [b] by the way—this is (laugh) just by the WAY you can only DISTINGUISH these of course in DAYLIGHT because at night-time you can’t SEE [m] (laughs) and there’s a certain constriction in the JAW when he says the ‘k’ with a HIGH tone which you II don’t GET when he says the (—laughs) and he’s got an international REPUTATION as a bright MAN this is TRUE he HAS YES YES you know this is TRUE and then he came out and said [ddd] just before you go any further just give—fill in his historical background which seems rather odd oh YES he took his first DEGREE IN NECROMANCY then he became a MISSIONARY (giggles) then he took his (laughs) Ph.D. in LINGUISTICS and got a PROFESSORSHIP oh god so there’s hope you see— you KNOW [?:] we’re all LAUGHING aren’t we (laugh)
38
B
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
979 980 A 981 B 982 All 983 c 984
ABSOLUTELY YES you’ll be Mrs VICE CHANCELLOR, NANCY Tom Parkhurst’s younger than YOU, isn’t he Cedric? (laugh 3 to 4 sylls interspersed) well—(sighs) [THE TRANSCRIPT ENDS AT THIS POINT]11
If story a) was all about a world of struggle following upon the tragedy of a husband rendered dumb, b) is about a successful career where highspirited play with words is paramount. The cultural setting and the tone of the conversations are entirely different. Light and chatty replaces dull and official; England displaces India in the imagination of the analyst, and high educational status substitutes the theme of a desperate appeal for a basic education. Even character and power relations may be inferred differently from the way these conversations dovetail. Yet the structural patterns that we are examining are sensitive to few of these tacit presumptions about cultural context. If our focus is narrative structure, we learn from d’s utterance in line 921 that a ‘story’ is actually requested from B, who begins this story in the turn following c’s utterance. Yet, in all B’s turns from line 932 until line 964 there is not a single example of a temporal juncture even though each of the other three participants display signs that they understand a story to be in progress; for example, by their repeated appreciative laughter in lines 933, 939, 945, 951 and 956. Line 964 does have an example of temporal juncture—‘and then he came out and said’—but long before this, participants have already shown signs of ‘story’ recognition. How, we may ask, is such recognition possible if temporal sequencing is, as Labov and Waletzky have it, a ‘defining property’ of narrative, and this defining property is absent as a feature of B’s turns from lines 932 to 963? Labov and Waletzky explain their position with reference to one of their own recorded stories: In Narrative 5 we have four independent clauses which refer to four successive events or situations: a Well, this person has a little too much to drink, b and he attacked me, c and the friend came in, d and she stopped it. 11From Svartvik and Quirk, A Corpus of Conversational Interaction, 1980. This corpus
is a crucial source of spontaneous conversational data in Narrative Gravity, but precisely because of its omnipresence, individual examples from Svartvik and Quirk will not each be separately acknowledged from this point on. For copyright reasons, I have retained the numbering and transcription system of the original.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
39
The temporal sequence of narrative is an important defining property which proceeds from its referential function. Narrative is not the only method for referring to a sequence of events; all recapitulation of experience is not narrative. For example, the narrative of no. 5 might have been presented in the following way: c d a d
A friend of mine came in just in time to stop this person, who had a little too much to drink, from attacking me.
Though this second version of Narrative 5 is a ‘perfectly logical, orderly and acceptable way of representing a sequence of events’, it is, in Labov and Waletzky’s view, not a narrative, since it depends on what they call ‘syntactic embedding’.12 Now, let’s rewrite B’s lines 932–63: a he came up with a gem today, b about two words in one of his languages, one of which began with a ‘k’ on a high tone, one of which began with a ‘k’ on a low tone, it being a basic point of phonetic theory that the ‘k’ cannot be distinguished tonally, c and you can only distinguish these, of course, in daylight because at night-time you can’t see, d and there’s a certain constriction in the jaw when he says the ‘k’ with a high tone, which you don’t get when he says the ‘k’ with a low tone, e and he’s got an international reputation as a bright man, f this is true. We find that i) there are several embedded clauses in b; ii) c does not follow from these clauses in b; iii) d does follow from the clauses in b, in the natural order of events as they occur, which is the order that narrative recapitulates, according to Labov and Waletzky, but d is ‘displaced’ by c, and iv) e does not follow in temporal sequence from a, b, c or d. Hence, B’s utterances don’t strictly qualify as a ‘story’ under Labov and Waletzky’s definition. Yet, it is as a response to d’s request for a ‘story’ that this ‘sequence’ of utterances, which appears to be treated by recipients as a very satisfactory ‘story’ indeed, was produced. True, there is no reason to assume that laughter or any other expression of ‘appreciation’ by participants characterizes the telling of stories. In Chapter 4, I go on to present a case for making this assumption. At the 12Labov and Waletzky, p. 20.
40
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
moment, however, I shall rely on B’s ‘sequence’ of utterances 923–63 actually being produced in response to a request for a ‘story’, as sufficient preliminary evidence that a story is indeed being told. Let’s move on then to B’s utterances in lines 967–72, which are produced as a response to d’s request in line 965 to ‘fill in his historical background’: a b c d
he took his first degree in necromancy then he became a missionary then he took his Ph.D in linguistics and got a professorship
This sequence is marked by temporal junctures of the exact sort which Labov and Waletzky say are characteristic of narrative. It is also greeted by laughter by c in line 971, and an ‘appreciative’ remark ‘oh god’ by c in line 973. Yet the nagging question remains whether the sequence is more of a ‘story’ and less of a ‘list’ than B’s earlier lines 932–63. How are stories to be structurally separated from lists and catalogues? This is a Labovian question to which I return, but the initial evidence from ordinary conversation suggests that Labov and Waletzky’s ‘formal’ analysis, sanitized and detached from context, may not apply quite so snugly if context is included. Labov and Waletzky propose, after all, that their formal analysis captures the ‘fundamental structures’ of narrative, and yet these fundamental structures are apparently not recognized for what they are by participants in actual conversations. Labov and Waletzky recognize this themselves when they discuss a second limitation of their formal analysis, which is that ‘the upper bound of narrative is not set by this approach’. It is impossible in theory for such a formalism to decide when a narrative is completed, without involving other empirically-discovered ‘functional’ categories such as the ‘Coda’. These ‘functional’ categories constitute, in other words, a second set of criteria defining stories. Indeed, this functional arm has constantly to be called into action by Labov and Waletzky in order to fend off the criticism that their formal characterization of narrative is far too weak. There is an obvious circularity here. First, we are presented with an informal functional definition of narrative as a ‘verbal technique for recapitulating past experience’. This definition is then formalized in terms of displacement sets of clauses and the temporal junctures between these sets, but in order to explain and sustain the formal definition, subsidiary informal functional categories such as ‘Result’ and ‘Evaluation’ need again to be summoned up. It is clear that such a process of formalization can go on as long as further informal categories
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
41
are discovered. Thus it is a moot question whether it would not be more elegant simply to study the functional aspects of narrative, and then incorporate these functions themselves into a format of grammatical rewrite rules, such as for instance the ‘story-grammars’ of the psycholinguists. I shall, in a later section of this chapter, therefore discuss these grammars and also recast the functional analysis of Labov and Waletzky as a storygrammar. The functional categories listed by Labov and Waletzky are Abstract, Orientation, Complicating Action, Evaluation, Result or Resolution, and Coda, while the fully-developed, ‘normal-form’ of narrative looks like this: Evaluation Complicating Action
Result or Resolution
Orientation
Coda
Abstract
Fig. 2.2 The originating function of the narrative is applied at the base of the diamond; we proceed up and to the left with the orientation section, then up to the apex with the complication. Frequently, but not always, the evaluation suspends the action at this apex, as is represented by the circle. The resolution proceeds downwards to the right, and the coda is represented by the line which returns to the situation (point in time) at which the narrative was first elicited.13 Functional Categories of Narrativity Of the functional categories said to constitute the ‘normal form’ of narrative, three are of special interest. These are the Orientation or Abstract, Evaluation and Coda, which concern the ‘spontaneous’ aspects of storytelling in relation to: i. the nature of a reportable event in conversation, and the conversational means whereby an account of such an event can be elicited and presented. 13Labov and Waletzky, p. 41. There are also other, more sophisticated revisions of this ‘normal form’ discussed by Labov (see Labov, 1972a).
42
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
ii. the extent to which the notion of an evaluative function helps provide a theoretical answer to the story-recipient’s always immanent question to the story-teller: why is this particular story being told at this particular point in the conversation? iii. the ways in which the notion of a ‘coda’ can contribute to a characterization of the turns immediately following the completion of a story in conversation. Both the Orientation and Evaluation sections of a narrative serve the ‘function’ of establishing ‘why the events of the narrative are reportable’.14 Drawing on the same stories for data as in the 1966 paper, Labov (1972) states that it is not uncommon for narrators to begin with one or two clauses summarizing the story or ‘encapsulating the point of the story’.15 The Orientation or Abstract does not stand in place of the story; the story-teller has ‘no intention of stopping there, but goes on to give the full account. The Abstract is not an advertisement or a warning: the narrator does not wait for the listener to say “I’ve heard about that” or “Don’t tell me that now”.’16 What then is the function of the Abstract? If it covers the same ground as the story, what does it add to it? Labov makes an important suggestion: Most of the narratives cited here concern matters that are always reportable: the danger of death or of physical injury. These matters occupy a high place on an unspoken permanent agenda. Whenever people are speaking, it is relevant to say ‘I just saw a man killed on the street’. No one will answer such a remark with ‘So what?’ If on the other hand, someone says, ‘I skidded on the bridge and nearly went off’, someone else can say, ‘So what? That happens to me nearly every time I cross it’; it is no longer a violation of an expected rule of behaviour and it is not reportable. The narrators of these stories were under social pressure to show that the events involved were truly dangerous and unusual, or that someone else really broke the normal rules in an outrageous or reportable way.17
The primary function of the Abstract is, presumably, to establish that the story about to be told is ‘reportable’. Even in danger-of-death narratives which ‘concern matters that are always reportable’ ... ‘narrators…[are] under pressure to show that the events involved [are] truly dangerous’. 14Labov, ‘The Transformation of Experience in Narrative Syntax’, Language in the Inner
City, 1972a, pp. 370–1. In Chapter 6, I return to a fuller discussion of what is ‘storyable’ or ‘reportable’ in conversation within an ethnomethodological perspective. 15Ibid., p. 363. 16Ibid., p. 364. 17Ibid., pp. 370–1; n. 53
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
43
In other words, even ‘always reportable’ events have to be worked on by the narrator. This issue is taken up again in Chapter 6 when I consider the implications of Harvey Sacks’ comment that ‘disasters are merely things in the world’. To become the subjects of stories they have to be made into ‘something for us’ by the narrator. As Wallace Stevens reminds us, ‘the pretty contrast of life and death’ is merely an opposition beloved in theory. We cannot go back to that, despite the pressure of structuralist ‘bishops’’ doctrine. In fact, not only ‘disaster’ stories but all stories may in their ‘normal form’ have to be made into something-for-us. Stepping into the squishy puddles of emotional interaction from which the basic motives for story-telling spring but which structuralism avoids because of its obligatory messiness, thus seems an imperative. More simply, story-tellers often present Abstracts or Orientating clauses in such a way that other conversationalists do have a chance to say ‘I’ve heard about that’, or ‘Don’t tell me that now’. For instance: c) a C a
576 577 578
I’ll tell you a friend of yours I met recently… II you ‘TOLD me x oh
d) C
640 641 642 643 644 645 646
Ian was HORRIBLE ACTUALLY because I’d I’d just broken up with this BLOKE AND with this Martin YEAH (laughs) oh God don’t let’s go into that, Ann (laughs) and and and—you remember when we ‘went’ well— went (laughs)—we all went into this (laughs)—oh it’s all FORGIVEN NOW, don’t WORRY but (laughs) but you{WERE pretty}ROTTEN (laughs) actually—I know I was rotten I never heard—anything about this WELL well, you SEE we all went to this POETRY reading [+ STORY]
b C a C
a b C
647 648 649 650 651 652 653 654
Examples c) and d) are typical of Abstracts being greeted by the responses ‘I’ve heard about that’ in the first case, and ‘Don’t tell me that now’ in the second. In example c), a’s line 576 offering a potential story, followed by C’s emphatic turn in 577 ‘you told me’, effectively prevents an
44
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
anecdotal launching forth. Participants, it appears, routinely exercise their right to forestall a story if the Abstract which structurally precedes the story provides them with some clue that they might find the story objectionable. A frequent reason for objecting to a forthcoming story is that one or more of the participants have heard it before. In Chapter 6, I elaborate on this seemingly obvious point with reference to remarks made by John Searle and Harvey Sacks that all stories must observe a rule not to tell people what they already know. But here I confine myself to a critical examination of the function of the Abstract. Examples c) and d) , indicate that Abstracts can be greeted adversely by participants and a conflict of interests may ensue if this adverse assessment is not a shared one. Thus, in line 645 of example d), a protests against the story that is to follow from C’s Abstract in lines 640–2, but his line 645 is uttered concurrently with C’s line 646, and the story goes ahead when b’s line 651 ‘I never heard anything about this’ suggests that she, at any rate, is interested. In general, even the most adept tellers seem keen to elicit from participants a positive response to their Abstracts, ‘encapsulating the point of the story’, before they embark on the story. Witness e) through g): e) A
96
b A
97 98 99 100
f) A
941 942 943 944 945 946 947 948 949 950 951 952 953
I acquired an absolutely magnificent SEWINGMACHINE by foul MEANS did I TELL you about THAT No well when I was doing freelance ADVERTISING… [+ STORY] well NOW going back to Pete BASKERDON this is ANOTHER story— Pete BASKERDON is a SAD man he is NOT a very CLEVER boy x— he’s not REALLY— he’s never ANY further PROMOTION from the job that he was in when I met him in the WAR— he GOT that JOB— because there was a MAN— who was the head of the Celtic MUSEUM—
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
b A
954 955 956 957 958 959
g) B
c c&d B
1026 1027 1028 1029 1030 1031
45
I may remember HIS name in a MINUTE who was a German SPY oh fascination go on (coughs) and what is the WONDER—most biggest {SEND UP} of IRELAND— and all our prehistoric ARCHAEOLOGY— was that in… [+ STORY] one of the most AWFUL things Arthur did to me— was when I confused—confused macrobiotics with NECROPHILIACS— (laughs) (laugh) and I carried ON with this conversation about… [+ STORY]
In example e), A’s question in line 98 ‘did I tell you about that?’ could presumably be answered with ‘Yes, you did’, in which case her forthcoming story would be rendered redundant, yet A does wait for b’s response before producing her story. Clearly, A’s Abstract-cum-confession ‘I acquired an absolutely magnificent sewing-machine by foul means’ is crucially important whether she gets to tell a story or not. The Abstract does therefore function as ‘an advertisement or a warning’ here, though Labov denies that this has its function in the passage quoted earlier. Naturally, this prompts us to ask why a prospective story-teller should docilely present other conversationalists with the structural means to scotch his story. I shall show in Chapters 4–8 that an answer to this question may have to do with the strategies adopted by story-tellers to protect what Sacks calls the ‘fragile’ aspects of their stories. Examples f) and g), for instance, seem to be deliberately fashioned to evoke a positive response from participants like b’s line 956 ‘oh fascination go on’ in f), or c and d’s laughs in lines 1028 and 1029 in g); as a consequence, the stories which follow are rendered less ‘fragile’, since participants ‘asked for’ them after the ‘advertisements’ presented in the Abstracts. What counts as a ‘reportable’ event in conversation must logically depend on the fashioning of the Abstract if story-tellers resort to this strategy to present their material. Yet, the circularity inherent in Labov’s approach to his own brilliant notion of the Abstract not only stops him from considering any problematic counter-examples to his definition, such as the common ones above, but also prevents him from providing
46
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
satisfactory answers to the important queries he himself has about the function of the Abstract. The examples of Abstracts cited by Labov and Waletzky are of particular interest to me because of the ‘two distinct social contexts’18 in which the stories were told. The recurrent theme of ‘extreme danger’ in them could, as I show in Chapters 7 and 8, be compared profitably with my own data but I would still like to query whether these fourteen stories, at least as they are isolated and presented in the Labov and Waletzky paper, can serve as the basis for a formulation of the relationship between the formal and functional properties of narrative. When Labov and Waletzky formally define their Abstract or ‘Orientation Section’, which serves ‘the referential function of orienting, the hearer with reference to person, place, time and behavioural situation’, as ‘the group of free clauses which precede the first narrative clause’, they qualify this immediately by adding that some free clauses with these functions occur in other positions and that ‘the orientation function is often performed by phrases or lexical items contained in narrative clauses’. Hence, the formal definition of the Orientation Section is, as I have argued earlier, by no means self-supporting but needs to be propped up by the questionable assertion that ‘despite these limitations, the overall view of narrative shows that the Orientation Section is a structural feature of narrative structure’. While it is observably true that many narratives do orient their listeners with reference to person, place, time and behavioural situation, such reference need not be construed as an essential structural feature of narrative. The two enterprises of defining narrative formally and of defining it functionally seem, upon detailed examination, not to require to be ‘related’ but to be conducted separately, especially with regard to stories told in natural conversation. The formal analysis of Labov and Waletzky does not appear to be particularly suggested by the ‘spontaneous’ stories which are the object of their analysis. Their functional analysis, on the other hand, while generally appropriate, suffers from not being ‘functional’ to the extent of concerning itself with the origins and effects 18See p. 13, Labov and Waletzky’s statement: ‘We will be dealing with tape-recorded interviews taken from two distinct social contexts. One is a face-to-face interview where the narrator is speaking only to the interviewer; a person who is not a member of the narrator’s primary group. In the second situation, the narrator is recorded in interaction with his primary group; he is speaking in part to members of his group, and in part to an outsider on the margins of the group who provides only a part of the stimulus for the narrative’. These two social contexts outlined by Labov and Waletzky correspond closely to the contexts within which conversationalists talk, in my own data, about the disaster of floods.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
47
of the story in the conversation of which it is a part. This criticism, however, may be less valid when applied to the functional categories of Evaluation and Coda—to which I now turn. The Paradox of Evaluation Evaluative devices say to us: this was terrifying, dangerous, weird, wild, crazy or amusing, hilarious, wonderful; more generally, that it was strange, uncommon or unusual—that is, worth reporting. It was not ordinary, plain, humdrum, everyday or run-of-the-mill.19
Evaluative devices, which are ‘concentrated in the Evaluation Section but may be found in various forms throughout the narrative’20 serve the function of answering the ever present question, ‘Why are you telling me this story now?’ In the stories examined by Labov and Waletzky, the justification for telling a story is usually the intrinsic interest of the story material: ‘We find that most narratives are so designed as to emphasize the strange and unusual character of the situation.’ In Chapter 6, I contrast this observation with Sacks’ apparently diametrically opposed view that ‘it seems plain enough that people monitor the scenes they are in for their storyable characteristics. And yet the awesome overwhelming fact is that they come away with no storyable characteristics’.21 Sacks stresses that one of the most noteworthy features of story-telling in conversation is the way in which tellers strive to achieve ‘the nothing-happened sense of really catastrophic events’,22 that is to say, their ‘ordinariness’. Labov and Waletzky, however, are equally insistent that the Evaluation Section of a narrative underlines the unusualness of the events described. Without such a section, a narrative would lose its point. [We] suggested that a narrative which contains an orientation, complicating action and result is not a complete narrative. It may carry out the referential function perfectly and yet seem difficult to understand. Such a narrative lacks significance. It has no point.23
The Evaluation Section thus shares characteristics in common with the Abstract, which also ‘encapsulates the point of the story’. Like the Abstract or Orientation Section, the Evaluation Section is not sequentially 19Labov, pp. 370–1. 20Ibid. p. 369. 21Sacks, H. Lecture Notes, Spring, 1970, pagination inconsistent. 22Ibid. 23Labov and Waletzky, p. 33.
48
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
confined, and may perform its function ‘in various forms throughout the narrative’. In what respect does the Evaluative function then differ from the Orientation function, since both functions are directed towards acquainting listeners with the ‘point’ of the story? Within the terms of Labov and Waletzky’s own analysis, the maintenance of a qualitative distinction between the function of the Orientation Section, and the function of the Evaluative Section, seems to present some difficulties. As soon as a story is studied in the context of the conversation in which it occurs, the Orientation Section may however be defined as the turn(s) by the narrator seeking participants’ permission to tell a particular story, the essence of which he sets out in the turns prior to the turn in which he actually tells the story. Examples d)–g) already cited offer instances of such ‘orientating’ turns. The Evaluation Section is more problematic, since evaluations or ‘assessments’ are typically made in turns by other participants rather than in turns by the story-teller himself. In the following ‘confession’, B is the main narrator: h) B
c B c D
B c B
D
B
1072 1073 1074 1075 1076 1077 1078 1079 1080 1081 1082 1083 1084 1085 1086 1087 1088 1089 1090 1091 1092 1093 1094 1095
YOU KNOW she was a ‘poor ‘old THING after all— and mother went WILD with ME she thought this was TERRIBLE— oh gosh and that I couldn’t ‘see her ‘point of VIEW at ALL— oh God—no—> YES— siding with— the ENEMY YES— YES— YES— and of course I did see her point of VIEW— [m] oh Lord AND— but I—didn’t WANT— to ring her up and SAY— and do something FATAL— YES that’s RIGHT— and say anything AWFUL to her—
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
c B c B
c B c B
D B
c B
c B
1096 1097 1096 1098 1099 1100 1101 1102 1103 1104 1105 1106 1107 1108 1109 1110 1111 1112 1113 1114 1115 1116 1117 1118 1119 1120 1121 1122 1123 1124 1125 1126 1127 1128 1129 1130 1131 1132 1133 1134 1135
because she’s— yeah so ‘nice and’ kind and MILD— oh God SO this went on for WEEKS and— I thought I’d better ring [ ] my mother UP and pretend I’ve NEVER SAID it [m] I’d just ring up and ASK— how she’s getting ON and yeah SO on and [j ?a:] so I rang up— and my SISTER answered the PHONE— and she—really gave me a terrible HARANGUE— —SHARP YEAH— over the PHONE— going ON— and ON and ON all about how COULD I say such things oh God SAY anything— SO ANYWAY— by the time she’d finished sort of telling me OFF and me SAYING— now what’s the good of QUARRELLING it’s so TRIVIAL and— [m] . you KNOW— why make a lot of—sort of FUSS about it— it was NOTHING— I DIDN’T SAY anything— for a START— (laughs)
49
50
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
c B
c B c B
c B c D B c B D B c D B
c
1136 1137 1138 1139 1140 1141 1142 1143
1144 1145 1146 1147 1148 1149 1150 1151 1152 1153 1154 1155 1156 1157 1158 1159 1160 1161 1162
(laughs) oh God she—she finally SAID don’t argue with ME— if you ARGUE with me— I shall just put this PHONE down {she SAID} [m .m]— so I thought—well, sure enough she COULD— right but I thought I—can’t—just sort of let it go on and say oh well I don’t want to speak to you if that’s your ATTITUDE— no because I THOUGHT— she really NEEDS to have somebody {ring her UP AND}— course YES YES and besides—she always comes DOWN {in the SUMMER}— your sister—or your mother [ ] my sister and my—MOTHER— BOTH of them— YES— and I thought if they—don’t—if we {can’t ASK them}to come DOWN— —[m]— > YES it’s going to be—VERY ‘awkward— and my mother can’t get about on her OWN— so— family feuds are horrible
Here, B makes only one ‘evaluative’ comment during the telling of her story. This is the comment ‘really awful’ in line 1119; whereas D responds with a remarkable array of ‘Yes’s, and c with evaluative exclamations in lines 1076, 1087, 1098, 1123 and 1136, and with the evaluative comments ‘trivial’ in line 1118, ‘right’ in line 1142 and ‘I know family feuds are horrible’ in line 1162. The evaluation of the ‘point’ of the story is thus evident not in the story-teller’s turns but in the repeated turns by other participants. Moreover, as I shall demonstrate in Chapter 6, the contradiction between Labov and Waletzky’s view that story-tellers stress
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
51
the unusual nature of the events they are recounting, and Sacks’ opinion that story-tellers strive to render ordinary the event they are describing, may be resolved if the interactional context of a story is taken into account. Example f) provides some clues, pursued in Chapter 6, as to how such a resolution may be accomplished. Many of B’s utterances in her ‘story-telling’ turns, preceding c’s evaluative exclamations, it will be noticed, are not only relatively matterof-fact but still incomplete when c utters her exclamations. The fact that c’s ‘evaluations’ above often come before B has completed the story suggests that story-telling in conversation demands extremely active participation, from listeners, and that such participation is accommodated naturally within the activity of story-telling in conversation. Close cooperation can be observed between story-teller B and the participant c, to the extent that c’s comments are actually located in the interstices of B’s sentences. B tells her story by means of a series of flat statements such as ‘and of course I did see her point of view’, or ‘she’s nice and kind and mild’, and c responds with extreme deftness and sensitivity in evaluating their significance or ‘point’. And it is here that a resolution may be sought between the views of Labov and Waletzky and Sacks. It is possible for the story-teller to be deliberately ‘ordinary’ and matter-of-fact if other participants cooperate in the task of ‘evaluating’ or assigning significance to his narrative. The Evaluation section of narrative will therefore be reassessed in Chapter 6, which uses the methodology of conversational analysis to study stories told in natural conversation. Returning the Narrative Perspective to the Present: Labov on the Coda The coda can be seen as one means of solving the problem of indicating the end of a ‘turn’ at speaking. As Harvey Sacks has pointed out, a sentence is an optimal unit for utterance, in that the listener’s syntactic competence is employed in a double sense—to let him know when the sentence is complete and also when it is his turn to talk. Narrative requires other means for the narrator to signal the fact that he is beginning a long series of utterances which will form one ‘turn’, and to mark the end of that sequence. ... It can also be said that a good coda provides more than a mechanical solution for the sequencing problem: it leaves the listener with a feeling of satisfaction and completeness, that matters have been rounded off and accounted for.24
The Coda, in short, is an ‘interactional’ device, used within a conversation to end a narrative turn. Like the Abstract and Orientation, it is not an 24Labov, p. 365.
52
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
essential feature of the story format. It is merely ‘one of the many options open to the narrator for signalling that a narrative is finished’. As usual, it turns out that participants other than the story-teller can manipulate the Coda (‘Yes. I know. Family feuds are horrible’) Once again, therefore, some of the ‘defining’, if not essential, functional features of stories appear in the turns of other conversationalists. Though Labov does introduce a caveat in the passage on the Coda to the effect that certain ‘fixed formulas’ that mark the beginnings and ends of folk-tales ‘are not available for personal narrative’, he essentially views narrative as a simpler form of literary genres like the myth and fairy-tale. This is implicit in the first paragraphs of Labov and Waletsky’s paper— Myths, folk-tales, legends, histories, epics, toasts and sagas seem to be the results of the combination and evolution of simpler elements; they contain many cycles and re-cycles of basic narrative structures; in many cases, the evolution of a particular narrative has removed it so far from its originating function that it is difficult to say what its present function is. In our opinion, it will not be possible to make very much progress in the analysis and understanding of these complex narratives until the simplest and most fundamental narrative structures are analysed in direct connection with their originating functions. We suggest that such fundamental structures are to be found in oral versions of personal experiences; not the products of expert story-tellers that have been retold many times, but the original productions of a representative sample of the population.25
But it is surely not the case that myths and legends are just more ‘expert’ versions of stories in everyday conversation. The story-teller in a faceto-face situation has to be alert from moment to moment. She has to be a ‘cog’ spinning in perfect unison with other cogs in the freewheeling conversational wheel. At each stage, she has to attend to the ‘turn-taking structure’ of talk and manoeuvre her story in so that it relates sequentially to prior talk, unless the story ‘opens’ the conversation, in which case the teller has still to make it appropriate to this ‘slot’, ward off interruptions and uncooperative commentary, and strive to produce a ‘preferred response’26 at the end. Story-telling in conversation is thus both a hazardous and skilled pastime. It cannot be treated as merely a simple version of the literary narrative. On the contrary, it offers a 25Labov and Waletzky, p. 12. 26 In this chapter, I have used words and phrases such as ‘turn-taking’, ‘slot’, ‘move’,
‘repair’, and ‘preference’ in a non-technical manner. In Chapter 6, I provide, where necessary definitions and fuller discussions of these terms as they are used by conversational analysts.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
53
paradigm for the ways in which we might decode ruptures and cognitive detentes within the more conventionalized structures of literary narrative. As Labov and Waletzky themselves put it: ... it is essential to preserve the context of the narrative. Because such originating context is often missing and cannot be reconstructed in traditional folk-tales it is more difficult to relate analysis to the originating functions.27
By treating the stories in their tape-recorded data as ‘essentially similar’ to myth and folk-tale, however, Labov and Waletzky are both prevented from shedding some light on what this essential similarity is, and from using an appropriate methodology such as that provided by conversational analysis. This, I think, is the crux of my critique of Labov and Waletzky’s analysis of ‘spontaneous’ narrative. The story is robbed of its very spontaneity when the context within which the story occurs is deleted. Conversational participation constitutes an integral aspect of the story itself, and it is futile to attempt to analyse the story without reference to this ‘squirming’ surround of facts. Repetition, Labov and Waletzky tell us, is a salient feature of sophisticated accounts. So, to repeat a point I have made earlier, structuralists in the classical mould like Labov and Waletzky, are forced by certain of their own assumptions to actually erase a number of well-demarcated structural features. These features relate to the conversational context of turn-taking in which any story of the sort recorded by Labov and Waletzky occurs. Since all turns by other participants are wiped out in their analysis, there is here a blatant contradiction of their own dictum that ‘narrative structures must be analysed in direct connection with their originating functions’. As we have observed, at least four—the Abstract, Orientation, Evaluation and Coda—out of the six elements of narrative named by Labov and Waletzky can be supplied by other participants. Evaluation and Coda, in particular, are typically assigned to listeners. This leaves only Complicating Action and Resolution unambiguously to the teller. But then, we are no further on methodologically or logically from Aristotle who just required a story to have a beginning, a middle, and an end. Looking afresh at ‘spontaneous’ narratives in speech, which seemed so attractive an idea to begin with, has in the end left us at a standstill. The cogs do not turn, and the wheel of conversation has ground to a halt. According to Nair’s Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick, it is the ‘missing elements’—invisible to structuralists—that make the 27Labov and Waletzky, p. 32.
54
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
magic of narrative. In the foregoing sections, some of these elements corresponding to the structural components of Abstract, Evaluation and Coda, and produced by listeners rather than story-tellers, have been identified. I shall now move on, briefly, to another kind of structuralist paradigm. These are the ‘story-grammars’ designed by psycholinguists. Story Grammars and Natural Order Stevens’ poetic conversationalists A and B, quoted at the beginning of this chapter perspicaciously comment in tandem: A. A violent order is disorder; and B. A great disorder is an order. These Two things are one. (Pages of illustrations.)
How may we decode the enigma of these lines? Can order and disorder be ‘rewritten’ in terms of each other? So far, I have highlighted some of the ‘missing elements’ of structure that tend to get lost in a structural analysis. Now I return to an earlier suggestion I made in passing that Labov and Waletzky’s functional description of story structure could easily be expressed as the set of rewrite rules espoused by their near contemporaries—the psycholinguistic story-grammarians.28 Eleven years after their distinguished predecessors, Mandler and Johnson (1977) claimed that the rewrite rules they proposed ‘were found to be adequate to parse a fairly large set of stories, including both single and multi-episode stories of several types’.29 But it should not be forgotten that these grammars were clearly intended to apply to textual materials. A real danger in applying them willy-nilly to conversational stories does not envisage, for example, the psychological implications of the differences between an ‘ordered’ experimental situation in which a story is read out to and listened to by ‘subjects’, and a ‘disordered’ conversational situation in which a story is heard and interacted with 28Though several psycholinguists have contributed to the notion of story-schemata,
I have made no fine distinctions between theorists like Mandler and Johnson, for example, and R.C. Schank whose interest in stories stems from his interest in artificial intelligence, since I felt that it was important for the purposes of this book to derive some general insights from psycholinguistic research on stories without dwelling too obsessively on the differences of approach among the psycholinguists themselves. 29Mandler, J.M., ‘A Code in the Node: The Use of a Story Scheme in Retrieval’, Discourse Processes, I, 1978, p. 15 and Mandler and Johnson, ‘Remembrance of Things Parsed: Story Structure and Recall’, Cognitive Psychology. Vol. 9, 1977.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
55
by participants. Levelt, as we remember, related the kinds of narrative inferences which psycholinguists consider of interest to the implicatures deriving from culturally specific conversations. Indeed, what is interesting about the story-grammars is precisely that listeners’ expectations of the information in a story are a main focus of attention. I shall shortly show with a second series of ‘live’ illustrations that some valuable insights arise for the ‘Indian Rope’ paradox of narrative from this orientation towards listeners. All story-grammars consist of simple rewrite rules capable of generating well-formed stories or of breaking down a well-formed story into its constituent parts. For instance, Mandler and Johnson (1977), following work by Rumelhart (1975) and Colby (1973), characterize the underlying structure of simple stories as a set of basic nodes in a tree structure, each of which is either causally or temporally connected to other nodes in the tree. Several assumptions are made here concerning the analysis of stories. The first is that story material has some kind of internal structure much like sentences (see Rumelhart, 1975). The second assumption is that stories can be described in terms of a hierarchical network of categories and the logical relations that exist between these categories. Finally, it is assumed that this network corresponds to certain universal cognitive patterns that relate to the ways in which we all organize story-information. This assumption about organization, in particular, is directly connected to the preoccupations of the more ethnomethodologically-inclined conversational analysts. Harold Garfinkel, for example, writes: I use the term ethno-methodology to refer to various policies, methods, results ... with which to locate and accomplish the study of the rational properties. ... or organized, artful properties of everyday life.30
With their focus on the ‘rational’ inferences made by listeners during the process of a telling, story-grammars lead on, not just to the ethnomethodology and conversational analysis but also suggest that some model such as the Gricean one of conversational implicature may provide, as indeed I suggest in Chapter 4, a wider frame for analysing just how ‘order and disorder’ coexist in narrative. Indeed, it is to the structural capacity of stories to allow for a concurrence of rationality and irrationality, online belief and suspended disbelief, that my paradox of the Indian rope trick attributes the evolutionary durability of narrative as a cognitive structure among the human species. 30‘Remarks on Ethnomethodology’ in Gumperz and Hymes (eds), 1972.
56
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Expectations and Event Structures ‘Event-structure’ is a term used in psycholinguistic literature of storygrammars to refer to the ordering of incidents within a story. This ‘structural’ description of stories then offers a basis on which psycholinguists can found their investigations into the use people make of such structures in encoding and retrieving information in a story. The types and orders of inference which psycholinguists postulate follow from the abstract structural description which they assign to stories. Mandler and Johnson (1977) assume that the structure of a story influences comprehension— encoding and retrieving the information in a story—because of the operation of the story-schemata. That is, the grammatical rules which specify whether or not a story is well-formed are intended to represent sets of expectations, or which a listener has incorporated. ‘Story-schemata are acquired through experience with listening to stories as well as experience with typical kinds of causal and temporal event sequences in the world’ (see Mandler, 1978).31 The cognitive schemata reflected by the grammar serve several functions. They provide a limited set of frameworks within which the incoming material will be structured. They let a listener know which aspects of the material are important or relevant. They tell the listener when some part of the story is complete and can be ‘stored’, or that some proposition must be kept in memory because related material is yet to come. However, according to Mandler and Johnson (1977), ‘there are a number of places even in a well-structured story where a listener may go wrong’. It is also ‘perfectly possible for listeners to “change their minds” as the story proceeds, to decide they have gotten off on the wrong track and to revise their notions of what the story is about. Reorganization can occur even after a story is finished’ (Spiro, 1977, Mandler and Johnson, 1977). Mandler and Johnson’s characterization of stories is pertinent to conversational ‘story receipts’ because it delineates from the point of view of the listener, a set of rules which enable him to structure incoming propositions. That is, it suggests ‘how a listener knows when one [episodic] node is complete and another begun’. Similarly, Warren, Trabasso and Nicholas (1978) relate the point-of-view of the listener or story-recipient to the inferences he makes during the telling of a story. In order to model the process of a listener making inferences we place him at a moving point [italics mine] in an unfolding narrative. This point is termed the 31Mandler, 1978, p. 32.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
57
focal event in an event chain, at any given moment in the narrative. Definition of this focal event allows us to determine the information available to the listener for making inferences at that moment rather than assuming full retrospective knowledge. Inferences made from the focal event can be directed backward, linking it with previous events and/or forward, predicting subsequent events. These forward ... backward processes may be viewed as the listener interrogating the text on the basis of present information, asking: Who, What, When, How? etc., in order to relate/justify the focal event in relation to past events and, What next? in order to anticipate.32
Listeners’ Grammars and Rewrite Rules According to Mandler and Johnson, a typical story-schemata looks like this (with connections between nodes and details below the basic nodes omitted): STORY
SETTING
EVENT STRUCTURE Episode I
Beginning
Development
Reaction
II
..n
Ending
Goal Path
Attempt
Outcome
Fig. 2.3 A slightly more complex version of a story-grammar by Stein and Glenn (1978), with a simple story included as illustration, is reproduced below.33 Summary of Grammatical Rules 1. Story → ALLOW (Setting, Episode System) 2. Setting → State(s), Action(s) 32Warren, W.H., Nicholas, D.W. and Trabasso, T., ‘Event chains and Inferences in Understanding Narratives’, Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol. 2, 1978, pp. 23–51. 33Stein and Glenn, ‘Story Comprehension’ in Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol.2, 1978, pp. 53–119.
58
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
3. Episode System → AND THEN [Episode(s)] CAUSE 4. Episode → INITIATE (Initiating Event, Response) 5. Initiating Event → Natural Occurrence(s), Action(s) Internal Events(s) 6. Response → MOTIVATE (Internal Response, Plan Sequence) 7. Internal Response → Goal(s), Affect(s) Cognition(s) 8. Plan Sequence → INITIATE (Internal Plan, Plan Application) 9. Internal Plan → Cognition(s), Subgoal(s) 10. Plan Application → RESULT (Attempt, Resolution) 11. Attempt → Action(s) 12. Resolution → INITIATE (Direct Consequence, Reaction) 13. Direct Consequence → Natural Occurrence(s), Action(s), End State(s) 14. Reaction → Affect(s) Cognition(s) Action(s) Intra-category connectors: AND : includes simultaneous or a temporal relation. THEN : includes temporal but no direct causal relations. CAUSE : includes temporal relations which are causal in nature. These rules define ‘the internal representation of a story’. The way in which they apply to ‘the structure of a simple episode’, is shown in the tale of: Melvin, The Skinny Mouse Setting
Initiating Event Internal Response Internal Plan Attempt Direct Consequence Reaction
1. Once upon a time, there was a skinny little mouse named Melvin 2. who lived in a big red barn. 3. One day, Melvin found a box of rice crispies underneath a stack of hay. 4. Then he saw a small hole in the side of the box. 5. Melvin knew how good the cereal tasted 6. and wanted to eat just a little bit of the cereal. 7. He decided to get some sugar first 8. so that he could sweeten the cereal. 9. Then Melvin slipped through the hole in the box 10. and quickly filled his cereal bowl. 11. Soon Melvin had eaten every bit of the rice crispies 12. and had become very fat. 13. Melvin knew he had eaten too much. 14. and felt very sad.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
59
How do these schema compare with a Labov and Waletzky-type grammar describing the ‘function’ of stories? Consider the following mapping: NARRATIVE
ORIENTATION [i.e. Setting]
COMPLICATING ACTION [i.e. Event Structure] ○
○
○
○
○
○
○
○
Episode I
Beginning
○
○
○
○
II
..n
Development End
EVALUATION [i.e. Reaction]
Goal Path
Attempt
RESOLUTION [i.e. Outcome]
Fig. 2.4 Like Labov and Waletzky’s narrative analysis, story-grammars stress the functional aspects of story-telling, the motivations for telling a story, and the inferences that can be made from it, although we find that a representation in terms of the Mandler and Johnson tree-diagram necessitates the omission of one of Labov and Waletzky’s functions, the Coda, which I have already argued is really an ‘interactional device’ in conversation. The other interesting feature about such a representation is that Labov and Waletzky’s ‘Evaluation’ function appears to coincide with the internalized ‘Reaction’ node which Mandler and Johnson claim ‘is central to the formation of an episode’. Ambiguities seem to arise in listeners’ understanding of a story when the ‘Reaction’ node is omitted. This is exactly similar to Labov and Waletzky’s claim that a narrative without an Evaluation Section ‘... lacks significance; it has no point’. Again, I believe that this coincidence provides us with insights into the actual telling and reception of stories in conversation, as I suggest in the discussion of ‘evaluation inferencing’ later in this chapter. Inferences, Nodes and Slots It seems clear that a variety of structural descriptions of story-telling, whether framed by sociolinguists like Labov or psycholinguists like Stein
60
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
and Glenn, have much in common. We can therefore return to a version of Levelt’s basic question. Do the descriptions generated by the grammar correspond to the structure people perceive in stories? In order to answer this question psycholinguists have, predictably, attempted to show that the structure generated by a story-grammar is not only related but systematically related to the inferences necessary for proper story comprehension. Schank (1975) offers, for instance, what he calls a ‘functional definition of inference’.34 According to Schank’s description the listener of a narrative must, at every stage, make inferences. Such inferencing serves two main ‘functions’. First, it fills in missing ‘slots’ in the story-structure; second, it connects elementary events in the structure with other events in order to provide a higher level of organization. ‘Slot-filling’ occurs when, for example, an action is given but its motivation is unspecified and the listener attempts to fill in the missing information. ‘Story-connecting’ is done when two or more propositions in the story are linked together. The ‘structure’ of a story may be described in terms of the tree-system of ‘nodes and relationships’ suggested by Minsky (1975), in which the higher nodes are fixed and represent necessary elements in the storystructure, while ‘the lower nodes have many terminals—slots—that must be filled by specific instances of data. Each terminal can specify conditions its assignment must meet’.35 Thus ‘slot-filling’ inferences are made at the terminal or lower nodes of a hierarchical story-structure, whereas ‘connecting’ inferences are made with reference to the higher nodes of structure. The two operations are, of course, really quite similar. ‘Storyconnection’ becomes ‘slot-filling’ when alternatives are not explicitly stated in the story. Warren, Nicholas and Trabasso (1978) present another, not altogether different, classification of the inferences made during the telling of stories. This classification divides inferences into three main types of which I will consider only the last—value inferences—in some detail because they seem to correspond more or less to Schank’s ‘slotfilling’ inferences. The three types of inferences specified by Warren, Nicholas and Trabasso36 are: 1. Logical inferences: which stem from the logical relations between events in the story, and answer the questions Why? and/or How? 34Schank, R.C., ‘The Structure of Episodes in Memory’, in Bobrow and Collins (eds),
1975. 35Minsky, M., ‘Frame-system Theory’ in Johnson-Laird and Wason (eds), 1978, p. 355. 36Warren, W.H., Nicholas, D.W. and Trabasso, T. (1978).
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
61
Obviously, logical inferences would be related to the CAUSE and AND THEN nodes in a Stein and Glenn tree and the COMPLICATING ACTION and RESOLUTION units in a Labovian diamond story structure. 2. Informational inferences: which enable the listener ‘to understand who is doing what to whom, under what circumstances at what time and place, across propositions’. They do not indicate causes or consequences. Equally obviously, informational inferences correspond to the components SETTING, ORIENTATION and ABSTRACT in Labov and Waletzky. 3. Value inferences: which are evaluative. The ‘listeners’ judgements on the actions of the characters, the intention of the story-teller and the validity of the story-events are themselves value inferences. They involve ‘judgements of morality, convention and anomaly in characters’ thoughts and actions or in story-style and construction. They draw upon the listeners’ values and world-knowledge of the situations mentioned’. In other words, they involve listeners’ expectations of the story; and they also involve story-tellers’ expectations of listeners’ expectations of the story. For example, Tannen (1978) includes the following example from a story-telling session: S4—... I’m giving you also these details, I don’t know if you want them ... um ... the ... reason I’m giving you the details is ‘cause I don’t know what the point of the movie was. ... Okay? So maybe you can see something that I didn’t. ... Okay? ... [LAUGH] Tannen comments, ‘S4 apparently feels that when telling about a movie, she should know and communicate what “the point” was. Her inability to do this creates enough discomfort for her to mention it as a reason for telling details. Her statement about the interviewer’s ability to make sense of the details (note the modal ‘can’) indicates that she is operating on a cooperative model in which she assumes her purpose is to communicate to her hearer. This is somewhat different from the expectation of a purpose of furnishing data for an unidentified researcher’.37 ‘Evaluative’ inferences, as defined by the psycholinguists, are interesting not only because they obviously connect with Labov and Waletzky’s analysis of the ‘evaluative function’ of stories but because they assume a cooperative model of speaker-hearer interaction. Like the notion of ‘slot-filling’ inferences, ‘evaluative’ inferences contribute to an understanding of the reception of stories by a community of listeners. 37Tannen, D. ‘What is a Frame? Surface Evidence for Underlying Expectations’, Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol. 2, 1978, pp. 137–79.
62
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Finally, psycholinguists invoke the concept of ‘relevance’ in order to constrain the number of inferences made from a story, for otherwise ‘the interrogation’ of ‘a story could conceivably continue indefinitely’. Rieger (1974) suggested that all possible inferences are made before the next proposition in the story is considered, but Warren, Nicholas and Trabasso object that ‘this clearly cannot be the case. The listener would be stuck for hours on a line such as: “Once upon a time there lived a noble king”. Introspectively, it seems we make very few of the myriad possible inferences, and often hold the process completely in check until the important links become clear many propositions later. ... A distinction thus arises—how many inferences does he actually make when encountering a story?’38 On the basis of this distinction, these researchers then postulate a ‘relevancy hypothesis’. Formally, this hypothesis states that ‘in understanding a narrative a listener makes only those inferences relevant to the progress of the narrative’.39 Considering their previous classification of logical, informational and evaluative inferences, Warren, Nicholas and Trabasso ‘propose that the relevant inferences are those which establish the information necessary to determine what happened and why’. This is knowledge that, according to these psycholinguists, is essential for a listener to comprehend a story. Four degrees of inferential constraint are defined in this regard. Firstorder inferences are the most unconstrained. They are consistent with, but undetermined by information in the text. All elaborative inferences fall in this class, as do guesses at unindicated causes and motivations. They consist of straight additions of world-knowledge, hence they cannot be story-connectors. Second-order inferences obey a tighter constraint in that they are determined but irrelevant, that is, indicated by the text but still not relevant to the progress of the story. They consist of interpreting ‘given information on the basis of world-knowledge’ but are not important for determining what happened and why. Many logical and informational inferences fulfilling a slot-filling function fall into this category. Third-order inferences are both determined by the text of the story and relevant to its progress. They consist of interpreting ‘given information on the basis of world-knowledge’ to determine what happened and why. It is these inferences that the ‘relevancy-hypothesis’ proposes are 38Warren, Nicholas and Trabasso, pp. 43–4. 39Ibid., p. 44.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
63
necessary for story-comprehension and suggests listeners actually make in conversation. Fourth-order inferences might be called over-constrained or redundant. They duplicate information given in the story or inferred from it that was already adequate for comprehending the story. Hence, they do not add anything new and are irrelevant to the progress of the story. The types and orders of inferences postulated by psycholinguists of the seventies and early eighties are important in this book because I believe they can be brought to bear upon the discussion of the Gricean model of cooperative interaction in Chapter 4, and Sperber and Wilson’s subsequent theory of ‘cognitive relevance’ in Chapter 5. The Gricean model, which seeks to explicate in general terms inferences deriving from particular talk exchanges, offers a suitable framework for the practice of conversational analysis. Here I agree with Stephen Levinson (1979) that ‘there may in fact be some relation between Grice’s maxims of conversation and particular expectations associated with particular activities’.40 Levinson both poses a question and provides an answer—‘What exactly is the relation betwen the structure of an activity and the inferences special to it? Presumably exactly the same kind of relation that holds between Grice’s maxims and the inferences they generate’.41 In Chapter 4, I examine the relationship between the general inferences which arise from a violation of Gricean maxims and the particular constraints on the activity of storytelling observed by conversational analysts. The present chapter anticipates some of these particular inferences which, according to psycholinguists, are also derivable from the structure of a typical story-grammar. As early as in 1962, M.B. Arnold argued in her work on the Thematic Apperception Test (TAT) that the primary task of the psycholinguistic research was to infer the ‘import’ of ... each of a subject’s stories. If each story is an imaginative exploration of various problems and their possible solutions, we must try and isolate what it is the story-teller is trying to say. What he says about the picture [he is shown] will reveal his convictions: what could be called the ‘moral’ of the story. When this moral is applied to the story-teller’s subjective circumstances, we arrive at the import (the meaning or significance) of the story.42
Arnold’s purpose in proposing a set of ‘definite rules for abstracting the story import’ was the psychological one of arriving at the ‘motivational 40Levinson, S.C., ‘Activity Types and Language’, Linguistics 17, 1979, p. 374. 41Ibid., p. 376. 42M.B. Arnold, Story Sequence Analysis, 1962, p. 51.
64
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
pattern’ of the story-teller. Yet she suggested, interestingly enough, that the best and most unbiased way for the researcher to arrive at a motivational pattern was to ‘formulate the imports before too much is known about the story-teller’. There is only a minimum of factual information that is necessary: the storyteller’s sex, age, profession, marital status, domicile. Beyond that, the only thing that is necessary is to formulate the import so that it expresses what is implied in the story from the point of view of the story-teller. This means suspending judgement, foregoing interpretations based on some personality theory, however plausible, and simply listening to what the story-teller is saying [italics mine].43
The sort of ‘imports’ formulated by Arnold’s subjects are illustrated in the example below: Record # 4 (Good teacher, age 28, F, I.Q. 120) [Card I] Last night, for the last time, Jim heard Dad play his violin. Dad died early this morning. This violin he gave Jim as one last treasure. Now music grows to be a part of his life, as it was of his Dad’s. Jim uses his music as a stepping stone to friendliness and cheer, not in a great symphonic orchestra but in his home and in neighbourly circles. Import: If you use the talent you have you can achieve success, not necessarily in a big but in a simple way. Record # 5 (Poor teacher, age 30, F. I.Q. 124) [Card I] The boy in this picture is the only son of a musician. His father has lately returned from a concert tour and he left the instrument on the table. Sudden illness followed by unexpected death has left the boy’s mother upset and confined to her room. The child has come to gaze at the instrument his father made seem almost alive. It is a link to one he loved and as he is so absorbed in his dream, his one desire is to make the instrument live again. As he dreams, his loneliness fades and he sees his mother’s happy smile as he, in years to come, steps into the vacant place of his father. The dream comes true as a result of this moment’s searching thought and resolution. Import: Love for someone you admire may make you want to continue his work and take his place in the world. Your dream comes true as a result of this thought and resolution.44
Arnold’s rather straightforward methodology of getting subjects to write out stories based on ‘card pictures’ enables some equally straightforward distinctions. First, there is the well-worn distinction between 43Ibid. 44Ibid., pp. 67–8.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
65
written texts as data and spoken utterances. Though Arnold urges the researcher to ‘simply listen to what a story-teller is saying’, this phrase is not an indication of her interest in conversation. On the contrary, she insists that ‘it is desirable to have the stories short and to the point without the irrelevant elaboration and disorganization that is often the result of asking someone to tell a story’45 [italics Arnold’s]. Arnold’s subjects were therefore specifically invited to ‘write a story and not a piece of conversation’. Spontaneous stories, on the other hand, appear to be deliberately organized so as to allow for a considerable degree of conversational interplay, which casts into doubt Arnold’s basic premise that ‘disorganization’ is a necessary consequence of requesting someone to tell a story. Written stories are thus privileged by Arnold over spoken ones, as are storytellers over listeners. Arnold takes it for granted that ‘imports’ always derive from the point of view of the story-teller. More recent storygrammars such as those of Warren, Trabasso and Nicholas seek to explicate the inferences made by the listener. Yet, both strictly maintain a distinction of roles. I will argue, however, that story-teller and listener cannot possibly be the neat, cognitively separable, entities that the psycholinguistic analyses indicate. As some of the conversations recorded in this chapter already show, both story-teller and listener skilfully combine to fulfil what Labov and Waletzky define as the story-teller’s essential functional task of evaluating the narrative. They behave much like ‘Nair’s communicating cogs’ in my introduction to Narrative Gravity. It is this structurally interactional aspect of story-telling as it contributes to the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick to which I shall return at the end of this chapter, but now, on to a third distinction—between story-imports and the inferences deriving from a story-grammar. Story-imports are formulations of the intention of the story-teller. Inferences from stories are made, on the other hand, by the listener and are structurally derivable from the listeners’ knowledge of typical storyschemata. Most psycholinguistic story-grammars thus dispense even with the need for ‘minimum factual information’ about the story-teller’s age, sex and so on, since these grammars simply model the ‘universal’ structural knowledge required to interpret narrative. The person telling the story is no longer the focus of interest as ‘good’ versus ‘bad’ teachers were for Arnold. Somewhat like Labov and Waletzky, Arnold concentrates on the 45Ibid., p. 50.
66
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
significance or ‘point’ of the narrative captured in its ‘import’, since this is the key to an understanding of the personality of the story-teller. Personal ‘questionnaire’ details are therefore not in the end irrelevant in Arnold’s analysis. Labov and Waletzky similarly state that ‘the ultimate aims of our work will require close correlations of the narrator’s social characteristics with the structure of their communication’. Story-grammars, however, render such social correlations made by Labov and Waletzky and Arnold, in their different ways, redundant. Inferences deriving from story-grammars seem to be constrained in ways which do not obviously relate back to the narrator’s sociological background at all. In this respect, they anticipate in some respects the ‘analytic mentality’ of the ethnomethodological conversation analysts for whom the story or the data is the only source to which appeal can be legitimately made. If story-grammarians do refer to any sociological ‘principle’ at all, it is the principle of salience, which guides a narrator’s choice of story or elements within a story. Events are salient to a story-schema to the extent to which they depart from the banal routine experience that makes up the greater part of people’s lives. The things worth talking about are those which represent significant deviations from the baseline.46
In Chapter 6, I discuss whether such a notion of salience has any bearing upon what Labov and Waletzky call a ‘reportable’ event and Sacks a ‘storyable’ event in conversation, and in Chapter 6, I examine its relation to Sperber and Wilson’s concept of relevance. The Salient Paradox Nietzsche’s towering superman, I have always believed, is actually a fragile construct of subs, paras, metas, transes, alters, uns and semis. Much the same analogy holds in my mind for the ‘strong’ image of structuralism. Structural definitions tend to overwhelm us because their categories are so obvious, so definite, and their combinatorial properties so wellordered. It is only when a paradigmatic structural description such as the Labovian schema for stories is examined in detail that we come to realize with something of a shock that it eliminates the very idea of ‘context’ that it began by valorizing. Part of the argument of this book is that the materials neatly left out, excised, from structural analyses of 46Chafe, W., ‘Creativity in Verbalization’ in Freedle (ed.), Discourse Production and Comprehension, 1977, p. 44.
STRUCTURAL SIMPLICITIES
67
narrative, the Nietzsche subscripts as it were, turn out to be far more cognitively salient than one might ‘reasonably’ expect. Here is a fuller quote from Odlin, whom I mentioned at the beginning of this chapter: Appearing in most, and perhaps all, societies, narratives allow for many crosslinguistic comparisons of discourse form. ... Stories about the creation of the world, a flood, a return of a god or a hero, and so forth, have appeared in a remarkable number of communities. Moreover, traditional narratives are known to have formulaic characteristics that recur in the oral literature of many communities. ... Among such properties are chronological and causal order, as well as a sense of narrative tension. ... In many cultures, children are introduced to such stories at an early age, and adult listeners (or readers) are quite able to recognise and expect [these] patterns. ... Kintsch and Green (1978) have claimed that there are culturally specific patterns of narrative, and that cultural differences in narrative form have consequences for language comprehension.47
How might one recognize patterns of cultural salience in narrative? Structuralism tells us that the ‘point’ of a narrative can be inferred strictly from its logical connections; the core of narrative is its complicating action and resolution. Yet, as we have seen, listeners seem much more taken by precisely those aspects of narrative structure that are non-core—its evaluative and orientating functions, its coda. And herein lies the salience of the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick with regard to structuralism. Methodologically, structuralism is committed to breaking any ‘whole’ into a hierarchy of parts; the structure of the whole consists in the ordered relationship of its parts. If a story is conceived of as such a whole—as it obviously is in a story-grammar—then it would seem that inferences by the hearers actually end up subverting the carefully workedout order of its parts. Labovian ‘displacement sets of narrative clauses’ may fail signally to distinguish between true narratives and ‘lists’. Far more cognitively salient than the core elements of narrative, it turns out, are its peripheral accoutrements. In conversational narrative, the structure of a story is further fragmented so as to perversely give away some of the best performative parts to listeners! An observation of facts such as these suggests that the complete structure of a narrative unfolds only when teller and listeners share their knowledge of cultural background. Not through structure darkly, but face-to-face, speaker-to-listener and vice versa. The aesthetic of narrative, its cultural call for attention, as Levelt reminded us at the beginning of this chapter, is about a subversion of 47Odlin,1978, pp. 58–9.
68
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
the natural order of events. It is an often violent unsettling of the logic of expectation. It is in such piquant cases alone that there can be any ‘point’ in getting excited about inferring the ‘point’ of a narrative. In the following chapters, I consider how narrativity is handled within theories that claim to take context, culture, action and strong reaction into account. The goddess Vac, we recall, proudly declared that she spoke not directly but ‘through’ others, a host of cultural deputies. Who are these ‘selves’ that Vac deputizes, and how do they conduct their speech acts of narrative, in fiction and in fact? This is the subject of Searle’s paradox and also of the next chapter.
69
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
2
qQ FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY Narrative as a speech act (Gurus: J.L. Austin and John Searle)
Austin had to free the analysis of the performative from the authority of the value of truth... occasionally substituting for it the value of force, of difference of force (illocutionary or perlocutionary force). It is this, in a thought which is nothing less than Nietzschean, which seems to me to beckon towards Nietzsche, who often recognized in himself a certain affinity with a vein of English thought. Jacques Derrida It is good to express a matter in two ways simultaneously so as to give it both a right foot and a left. Truth can stand on one leg, to be sure; but with two it can walk and get about. Friedrich Nietzsche
Truth on one leg is a monument; on two, it is travelling theory. For this reason, it could be challenging to equip truth with that second leg, which is surely—fiction. Fiction has the licence to go anywhere it pleases; it is theory at its most untrammelled. In this chapter I argue that speech act theory too cursorily dismisses the revolutionary potential of fiction as a species of ‘theory’ by treating it merely as a case of ‘pretended assertion’. Classical speech act theory tells us that a fictional story is parasitic upon a more basic communicative act and can be analysed, satisfactorily and without any major snafu, in terms of the speech act of assertion (Searle, 1975). Yet anyone with the slightest predilection for those perambulatory truths we call ‘fictions’ might want to question this assertion. Why is it so crucial for speech act theory to deny narrative, and fictional narrative in particular, the status of an independent speech act? The answer to this
70
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
query turns, in large part, on the location of speech act theory within an area of research, namely pragmatics, that accommodates many quite disparate theories of language use. Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics The area itself has been variously described, but perhaps most generally by Rudolf Carnap in 1959, when he suggested that the realm of pragmatics extended across all those regions of study in which explicit reference was made to the user of a language.1 However, as Asa Kasher has pointed out,2 Carnap’s trick is to keep language and use separate. A linguistic system is defined by rules of syntactic formation and semantic interpretation without any reference to the use of language. This results, obviously, in a conception of pragmatic rules as governing only the relationships between linguistic behaviour and some non-linguistic practices in a particular speech community. Carnap’s separation of a language ‘system’ for its ‘users’ thus deliberately limits the scope of pragmatic theory. And in time, this ‘trick’ of his turns into something like the ‘act’ of speech act theory, as I shall try to show in this chapter. More recently, following work by Grice, Searle, Sperber and Wilson and others, there is widespread agreement that pragmatic rules have to specify the conditions for successful ‘conversation’, where conversation is understood to consist of interlocking communicative acts, involving such entities as Speakers, Hearers, inferences from utterances in context, and so on. Thus, Bach and Harnish (1979) set out a SAS (speech act schema), which codifies the inferences a Hearer has to make in any conversation: H’s Inference
Basis for making Inference
L1. S is uttering e(xpression) L2. S means such-and-such by e L3. S is saying that so-and-so L4. S is doing such-and-such
Hearing S utter e L1, MCBs (mutual contextual beliefs) L2, MCBs L3, MCBs3
The SAS, neatly set out as it is, calls our attention to a worrisome glitch in 1Carnap, R., Introduction to Semantics, 1959, Compare also Morris, who produces an almost identical version when he writes that ‘pragmatics is designated the science of the relation of signs to their interpreters’, p. 9. 2Kasher, A., Foundations of Philosophical Pragmatics in Butts and Hintikka (eds), 1977, p. 225. 3‘Linguistic Communication: A Schema for speech acts’, 1979, reproduced in S. Davis’ Pragmatics: A Reader, 1991, p. 233.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
71
the hitherto taut wave of speech act theory. Unlike Austin, who made a three-way distinction between locutions, illocutions and perlocutions, Bach and Harnish offer L1–L4. In this new format, L1 corresponds roughly to the Austinian locutionary act, but an extra ‘saying’ stage – L3 – is introduced within the illocutionary act proper in addition to ‘meaning’ and ‘doing’. This step is justified, they say, because a Hearer must be able to calculate those intended meaning(s) of a Speaker not conventionally entailed by the use of an explicit performative. Such meanings ensue from what is putatively ‘said’ rather what is performatively ‘done’ by a speech act. These meanings, called R-intentions, are reflexive intentions on the part of the Speaker to get the Hearer to recognize her intentions. R-intentions thus include intended perlocutionary effects (humiliating, insinuating, etc.), indirect speech acts (‘would you mind not sniggering?’ for example) and ‘non-literal meanings’ (metaphor, irony and so forth). Consider, in this connection, the following expansion of the SAS. Basis—Co-presence of Speaker and Hearer exchanging (e)xpressions. L1.uttering— e.g. L2.meaning— e.g. L3.saying— e.g. L4.doing— e.g.
phonetic form i promis to tel ju a stori phonetic form + sense and reference I promise to tell you a story phonetic form + sense and reference + R-intention ‘I promise to tell you a story’ phonetic form + sense and reference + R-intent + act ‘I PROMISE to tell a story’.
If we accept Bach and Harnish’s claim that the series L1–L4 consists of acts ‘intimately related’, then such an expansion shows that one can only distinguish the ‘doing’ stage from the previous three stages by arbitrarily highlighting the performative verb. But why is ‘doing’ not conventionally implicated at the ‘meaning’ stage, given the linguistic system and supporting MCBs? Furthermore, why should the Speaker, who produces the original locution after all, only come into her own at L3., when she has been around all along anyway? Perhaps an example may make these doubts more explicit. Imagine a Speaker X uttering the words, ‘I promise to tell you a story if you promise to eat your dinner’, craftily intending to get her recalcitrant son, Hearer Y, to eat his dinner rather than just promise to eat it. Since Y is a smart brat he immediately recognizes her intention and eats up his dinner, thereby getting his bedtime story. Note that he has not actually
72
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
fulfilled his part of the bargain, which was to promise to eat his dinner, but his non-compliance does not matter because he has demonstrated his understanding of his mother’s true intention, which was simply to get him to eat his dinner. Now, what’s interesting is that X’s intention is indicated not by her use of the performative verb ‘promise’, which gives her act the force of a promise, but by the verbal complement in the subordinate conditional clause—‘if you promise to EAT YOUR DINNER’. Surely it is this complement rather than the illocutionary PROMISE which should be the focus of L4, or at least a focus, since X is ‘doing’ getting Y to eat, which is her primary intention or goal, via this complement construction. Moreover, a crucial syntactio-semantic deletion is required at the ‘locutionary’ stages L1 and L2, namely, that the phrase ‘promise to’ be dropped from the subordinate clause, for Hearer Y to correctly compute X’s intention, which is not that he promises to, but that he actually eats his dinner. That is, his understanding (or mental representation or processing) of X’s original sentence should at some stage be modified to ‘I will read you a story if (and only if) you eat your dinner’. Forget about the promising! Given that MCBs and linguistic knowledge are already present at L2, it seems plausible that a Hearer may arrive at an R-intention before rather than, as Austin says, as a ‘consequence’, or sequential by-product, of the illocutionary act. In other words, if that famous line between ‘language’ and its ‘users’ is eliminated, by admitting ‘intimate’, not to say impossible to differentiate, connections within the SAS, then the centrality of the illocutionary act is also severely threatened. A Hearer may work out all sorts of R-intentions from a Speaker’s uttering an e, without the structure of the illocutionary act qua performative entering into his calculations at all. Instead, knowledge of ‘co-presence’ (the presence of the speaker from the perspective of the Hearer and vice-versa, including all the MCBs that mere, or sheer, presence evokes), could be the ground on which readings of R-intentions stand. It is this ground which forms a necessary though not sufficient condition for linguistic communication or ‘conversation’ to occur, whereas knowledge of illocutionary acts per se is neither necessary nor sufficient for computing R-intention, even though most R-intentions are, in fact, conventionally arrived at via our knowledge of appropriate illocutions. To my mind, the explosive charge carried by Bach and Harnish’s breakdown of the Austinian performative, tinder-dry though their commentary is, has to be attributed to the fact that their SAS allows R-intentions other than those conveyed by explicit illocutions to surface so
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
73
readily. As we shall see, it is these R-intentions that can become thoroughly insubordinate, threatening to destroy the whole SAS set-up when they attach to such entities as narrative fiction or metaphor. In general, pragmatic theories today (Relevance theory, Gricean theory, classical speech act theory, a Davidsonian theory of metaphor, Brown and Levinson’s theory of politeness, etc.) confront one crucial problem. How are R-intentions, or implicatures arising from (linguistic) communication to be restricted? What principles or norms do human beings use, socially and psychologically, to prevent an impossible proliferation of implicatures? Part of the problem arises from the assumption that the basic unit of pragmatic study is the ‘utterance’. The notion of the ‘utterance’, as it stands, seems too scattered, vague and impoverished to be analytically useful. Then add to utterances, the possible implicatures arising from each utterance, and one just has far too much on one’s plate (as the precocious Hearer Y might have said to his mother in our example). The focus on the utterance as a fundamental category results in pragmatists more or less depending on catch-all ‘lists’ to ostensively define pragmatic phenomena and principles (‘There goes something that looks like it may be pragmatic. Grab it!’). Thus Kasher (1991) concedes a little wearily that the ‘scope of what is called “pragmatics” will depend on one’s view of the nature of pragmatics’, and proceeds to detail six kinds of phenomena that are required for an ‘adequate’ pragmatic theory. They are—1) deixis; 2) lexical pragmatic presuppositions; 3) forces (of speech acts); 4) performatives; 5) conversational implicatures; and 6) politeness principles.4 But why these six and not some others like indirect speech acts, speaker reference, metaphor and irony, perlocutions and such? As Kasher tacitly grants, that’s because consensus on the issue is a distant hope, and meanwhile one gets on with it as best one can.5 Given the present state of art, therefore, it might be useful to reconsider, as much for heuristic reasons as anything else, an alternative unit which 4Kasher, in S. Davis (ed.), 1991. 5As with the phenomena, so with the principles. In the work of Leech (1983), Recanati,
etc. (1991), a variety of principles, often very suggestive, make their appearance. Recanati, for example, ‘enriches’ Grice’s super principle of cooperation by examining the claims of a Minimalist Principle, followed by an Availability Principle, followed by an Independence Principle, and then a Scope Principle. Again, the attempt is to restrict the R-implicatures that arise from the very process of enrichment. Recanati’s philosophical tools are wellhoned, but in the end the problem that Gricean theory faced, remains. There is no end to the making of principles until pragmatics is more severely defined.
74
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
pragmaticists could consider basic. I have already suggested, outrageously, that this unit should be the narrative, constituting both the upper bound and the main structure of pragmatic analysis, just as the sentence works as the largest unit or boundary structure as well as the central object of grammatical inquiry. Like the sentence, a narrative is a cognitively salient, universal, mnemonic unit of discourse, consisting of linear, hierarchical, and recursive patterns, which give it thew and sinew. What makes the narrative vitally different from the sentence, however, is precisely its pragmatic propensity. It is a structure devised to probe into context. Further, not only are the functional parts of narrative (abstract, setting, complicating action, etc. considered in the last chapter), designed to reflect on the relations of subjects to situations, the overall problematic of narrativity concerns contextual salience or relevance, fictionality, nonliteral meanings, implicatures, intentions, conventions, truth conditions, speaker-hearer interaction, and indeed all topics which have, according to Kasher and others, been the bread-and-butter of pragmaticists for the last half a-century. Narrative sets in motion complex processes of hypothesis formation, premise correction and reasoning among Hearer/Readers, whose task it is to deduce the point of the story from the evidence that Speakers/ Tellers present to them by attributing intentional stances to them. Grice’s idea that conversationalists display a remarkable degree of rationality in efficiently recovering non-natural meanings is thus tested in both gross and graceful ways by following through hearers’ interpretations of a narrative as it unfolds in its linearity. The Illocutionary Force of Fiction Fiction, I have rashly claimed, is a variety of theory. Why? Precisely because it encourages hypothesis formation and rational deduction from a given structure of premises and evidence. At the same time, there are certain kinds of latitude permitted in the genre of fiction which provide a subtle contrast to the conventions by which factual narrative evidence is judged by conversationalists in many cultures. There are five main reasons for this. First, fiction is always ‘false’ or ‘pretended’, and therefore the prototype of the ‘parasitic’ speech act, mimicking the ‘neither true nor false’ quality of real illocutionary acts while being patently and blatantly false—the shadow of a paradox here somewhere, a version of which Searle grapples with, as we shall shortly observe. Second, fiction is the most ‘performative’ of acts since its existence is typically predicated on its announcing itself as fiction, and that’s that,
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
75
in the same way as a promise is a promise. So, it should fall into the mould of an ‘explicit performative’ quite easily, enabling ‘felicity conditions’ to be formulated for it—an exercise duly undertaken later in this chapter. Third, fiction is conventionally associated with those leaky perlocutionary effects (curiosity, surprise, fear, wonder), which seem to indicate that the illocutionary boat is not so water-tight after all. Fourth, because fictions ‘make believe’, they are exploratory mechanisms in a way similar to scientific hypotheses. They enable us to investigate counterfactual worlds, lay out evidence, and offer plausible explanations for that evidence, without getting caught up in what Austin thought of as often tedious and irrelevant questions of ‘truth’ and ‘falsity’. All the four reasons listed so far, however, hinge on our acceptance of a fifth and final one, which concerns the form of fiction. Much of the speech act theory, I’ve suggested, concerns formal types, such as the types verditives, exercitives, commissives, behabitives and expositives discussed in How to Do Things with Words. Danger signals in speech act theory always have to do with instances when a word or a deed will not fit into a class—such intransigence being punished by Austin with a slew of fastidiously disapproving adjectives (‘impure’, ‘parasitic’, ‘etiolated’). The category ‘fiction’, then, so far as formless as the alternative categories ‘literature’ and ‘language’, could also run the risk of being found too chaotic to be taken seriously by Austinian speech act theorists—were it not for a happy coincidence. Fiction does for the most part come neatly packaged. It comes in a narrative pack. For, there is no denying that the easiest, perhaps the most natural way in many cultures to think about fiction is in terms of narrative. Our commonest access, even as children, to the subtle idea of fiction seems to be through the simple activity of story-telling. And stories are typically structures, as I’ve iterated, that convert conversation into ‘text’, where a‘text’ is not necessarily understood as written, but rather a mode which especially invites interpretation or ‘readings’ from the audience. If someone innocent of the speech act theory were to address us at the dinner table with that notorious sentence of the speech act theorist, ‘can you please pass the salt?’, we’d probably pass him the salt, no questions asked. Unless the circumstances were exceedingly strange, we would not waste much time trying to ‘read meaning’ into his utterance. But were the same person to tell us a story, we’d get straight-away into the business of interpretation, of hypothesis formation, of interrogating his tale for its plausibility. As we saw in the last chapter, we’d want to know what the ‘point’ of it all was. The point of course is that form, in this case the narrative form which
76
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
is the guise of fiction, is the primary and most reliable indicator of the ‘point’ of a speech act. Without this ‘explicit’ form it would be very difficult to endow fiction with illocutionary ‘force’. Even though, for the reasons of ancestry mentioned earlier, speech act theory has largely restricted itself to a formal classification of single sentence utterances, there are scattered assumptions throughout the literature that larger entities like stories, lectures and so on could be accommodated within the confines of the theory.6 Thus, Austin argues— At a more sophisticated level perhaps comes the use of the connecting particle; thus we may use the particle ‘still’ with the force of ‘I intend that’; we use ‘therefore’ with the force of ‘I conclude that’; we use ‘although’ with the force of ‘I concede that’. Note also the uses of ‘whereas’ and ‘hereby’ and ‘moreover’. A very similar purpose is served by the use of titles such as Manifesto, Act, Proclamation, or the sub-heading ‘A Novel’. ... [HTDTWW, 1962, 75]
Though Austin does not develop his section on ‘connecting particles’7 further, he definitely seems in this passage to envisage the possibility that the phrase ‘A Novel’ might precede a speech act of a specific kind, that of telling a story.8 That is, Austin’s suggestion appears to be that there is a conventional way in which such a phrase indicates that the utterances which follow it must be understood in connected sequence. It is therefore a connecting particle which conveys a particular illocutionary ‘force’, which is—‘I hereby narrate that’ ...9 Searle also discusses the problem raised by the consideration of fiction as a speech act. He writes: ... speaking or writing in a language consists of performing speech acts of a quite specific kind called ‘illocutionary acts’. These include making statements, 6Compare R. Bauman and J. Sherzer in Explorations in the Ethnography of Speaking, 1974, p. 163. One of the central concerns in the ethnography of speaking is the description of speech acts, events and situations. ... Most formal description within linguistics has been limited to units of sentence length. Within this limitation, insights have been achieved in the techniques and theory of linguistic formalization. Yet there is much more to language use than abstract, isolated sentences and such uses of language as greeting, leavetakings, conversation speeches, stories, insults, jokes, and puns also have a formal structure. 7Austin, p. 75. 8See Forster, E.M., Aspects of the Novel, 1974, where he reluctantly admits, ‘Yes, oh dear yes, the novel tells a story.’ 9Narrate, of course, is not a performative verb in English, but Searle’s arguments, alluded to later in this chapter, have shown conclusively that the lack of a particular illocutionary verb in a language does not mean that there is no corresponding illocutionary act in the language. Other illocutinary force indicating devices, such as ‘A Novel’, in this case might perform the function of the illocutionary verb.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
77
asking questions, giving orders, making promises, apologizing, thanking, and so on…there is also a sytematic set of relations between the meanings of the words or sentences that we utter and the illocutionary acts we perform in the utterance of these words and sentences. Now, for anybody who holds such a view, the existence of fictional discourse poses a difficult problem. We might put the question in the form of a paradox; how can it be both the case that words and elements in a fictional story have their ordinary meanings and yet the rules that attach to those words and other elements and determine their meaning are not complied with?10
I would now like to argue that this very influential definition of the crucial problem posed by thinking of fictional stories as a speech act is misleading in many ways. I therefore consider the essay on ‘the logic of fictional discourse’ at some length below.11 Here, Searle begins by setting out the quite specific semantic and pragmatic rule for an assertion, since he wishes to develop an argument to the effect that fictional stories are a special case of ‘pretended’ assertions. These rules are: 1. The essential rule: the maker of an assertion commits himself to the truth of the expressed proposition. 2. The preparatory rule: the speaker must be in a position to provide evidence or reasons for the truth of the expressed proposition. 3. The expressed proposition must not be obviously true to both the speaker and the hearer in the context of the utterance. 4. The sincerity rule: the speaker commits himself to a belief in the truth of the expressed proposition. Once the conditions on assertion are stated, Searle happily points out that the fictional story fails to meet these conditions; in fact, it exactly reverses them, as will become obvious if the words ‘falsity’ and ‘false’ are substituted for ‘truth’ and ‘true’ in all the rules above. This is the observation at the heart of Searle’s ‘paradox’, as he states it. In chapters 4–6, I consider a number of possible explanations for this characteristic ‘reversal’ in fictional discourses, but to stay with Searle’s argument for the moment, we must confront his paradox. If the meaning of the fictional sentence is determined by the linguistic rules that attach to the elements of the sentence, and if those rules determine that the 10Searle, J.R., ‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, New Literary History, Vol. 6,
1975, p. 233. 11See also Furberg, M., Saying and Meaning: A Main Theme in J.L. Austin’s Philosophy, 1971, ‘... a story-teller “states”, “advises” and “promises” when he, in spinning out his yarn, goes through the motions of stating, advising and promising’. p. 90.
78
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
literal utterance of the sentence is an assertion, and if there is a literal utterance of the sentence, then surely it must be an assertion: but it can’t be an assertion since it does not comply with those rules that are specific to and constitutive of assertions.12
Searle does not, in this essay, spell out the kind of rules he has in mind when he talks of the ‘linguistic’ rules’ that determine whether the literal utterance of a sentence is an assertion or not. Elsewhere,13 however, he argues that there is a typical syntactic form of the representative, namely I + verb (that) + S, or even I + verb + (NP), of which the assertion is a sub-class; so I take it that the ‘linguistic rules’ for an assertion comprise some such syntactic features. Still, something is remarkably amiss. For, while syntactic rules tell us how to identify sentences, NPs, ‘that’ clauses and so forth, they do not tell us how to identify ‘representatives’ or ‘assertions’ or ‘statements’. A grammarian is usually clueless about how these essentially pragmatic categories can be told apart on purely linguistic grounds. At the very most, grammars broadly classify sentence moods on the basis of, say, movement rules or deletions. What grammars, and on the whole, grammarians, are unable to do with conviction is to claim: ‘this sentence here asserts, while that one declares, and that other one narrates’, unless an explicit performative verb is used. In the case of narrative, as we know, no such explicit performative verb is available in English, and many other languages.14 Grammarians can, of course, tell simple from compound and complex sentences, and this may help sift narratives from assertions, but it is by no means a reliable linguistic heuristic, as I shall show in my analysis of minimal narratives in Chapter 6. Under these circumstances, therefore, it does not seem to make much sense to insist that ‘linguistic rules’ determine whether the ‘literal utterance’ is an assertion. Linguistic rules are silent on the matter. Grammar will certainly not help link assertions with ‘truthfulness’, which is essentially the fix Searle needs to make his ‘paradox’ stick. So we are left, it appears, not with a paradox engendered by the existence of a grammatical rule, but with the default pragmatic convention by which speakers in any conversational context are assumed to be speaking the 12Searle, ‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, p. 236. 13Searle, J.R., ‘A Classification of Illocutionary Acts’, in Hymes, 1976, pp. 17,20. 14 See Dennett, 1991, on story-telling; one implication of Dennett’s view of narrative
as a basic human activity is that the need for an explicit performative verb for story-telling may be redundant.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
79
truth, unless there is apparent evidence to the contrary. In this situation, there are two options. The first, favoured by Searle, with or without a paradoxical aura, is to allow fictional discourse to form a sub-class of the Declarative/Assertion, because it is grammatically indistinguishable from the assertion, but at the same time treat it as a ‘parasitic’ rather than a full-fledged member of the class because it animadverts a speaker’s belief in the falsity (not the truth) of her utterance. According to Searle, fictional discourse simply comprises a series of ‘pretended’ assertions in which the teller goes ‘through the motions of making an assertion or imitating the making of an assertion’.15 Why the teller of the tale should undertake such an elaborate and laborious ‘pretence’ is not a question to which Searle addresses himself in this essay, except to state that ‘it is in part a function of the contract between author and reader’.16 Since that mysterious ‘contract’ seems to be crucial to the definition of fiction as ‘pretence’, I shall however, unlike Searle, continue to search for its terms of reference. Speech acts are not unrelated to speech pacts between listeners and hearers, I shall argue a little later, in the case of story-telling especially, but also more generally. The second solution to the ‘problem’ raised by fictional discourse Searle rejects out of hand, which is that fiction does not perform the illocutionary act of making an assertion but that of telling a story. Searle finds this view unsatisfactory because— Anyone ... who wishes to claim that fiction contains different illocutionary acts from non-fiction is committed to the view that words do not have their normal meaning in works of fiction ... in order to have the ability to read any work of fiction, a speaker of a language would have to learn the language all over again since every sentence in the language would have both a fictional and a nonfictional meaning.17
Obviously, Searle is no Davidsonian. For Donald Davidson,18 metaphors and other fictional statements which have long been considered ‘patently false’ [italics in original]19 are literally true instead. So they do not entail the kind of punishing labour Searle has in mind for those unsuspecting 15Searle, ‘ The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, p. 237. 16Ibid., p. 241. 17Ibid., p. 236. 18Davidson, D., ‘What Metaphors Mean’, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 1984,
p. 258. 19Kripke, S., Naming and Necessity, 1972.
80
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
fools who believe that ‘fiction contains different illocutionary acts from non-fiction’. By this logic of Searle’s, we would have a different meaning for each individual word in ‘Can you pass the salt?’ as a request versus the same question as a genuine inquiry, since these are two distinct illocutionary acts. That it is hard to imagine a context for the second illocution should not obscure our main argument, which is that the meanings of words, or even sentences, are not at issue when we consider illocutionary acts that are grammatically equivalent or isomorphic but have distinct functions. Contextual conventions decree that ‘Can you pass the salt?’ functions holistically—just as a frozen metaphor does—as a request. We do not painfully have to work out new ‘meanings’ for each of its forms, but simply invoke such conventions of use as are relevant. As Kripke pointed out some time ago, it may take ‘expert knowledge’ to sort out ‘real’ gold from all that glitters, but this does not affect either our everyday transactions with the word or quantity ‘gold’, nor our belief that there can be different ‘kinds’ of gold ‘meant’ by speakers in different contexts. It is my argument that the ‘users’ of narrative similarly do not in general bother about ‘expert’ opinions that sift fiction from non-fiction. They know, and possibly care, as little about the ‘textual properties’ of these classes of narrative as the average person in a community which, say, values gold, and knows about the ‘chemical properties’ of this metal. Instead, speaker-hearers rely on sets of conventions that enable them to heuristically decide which senses/aspects of narrative (including the fiction/non-fiction ones) should be foregrounded in any particular discourse context. Going by Davidson’s elegant arguments, it would seem that fictions function like metaphors20 in that they have the same gross ‘meanings’ as in any other kind of talk, provided we dismiss the red herring of truth value. Following Davidson, there seems to be no good reason why any true-blue pragmatist need get into a pother about the truth or falsity of a speech act, as long as he can suggest ways in which a hearer or reader can in context gauge the use to which the speech act is being put. That, after all, is the main purpose of girding an illocution about with felicity conditions—it enables us to grasp at once that speech is, for the most part, performatively interpreted. Davidson is categorical: What makes a difference between a lie and a metaphor is not the difference in the works used, or what they mean (in any strict sense of meaning), but in how 20Davidson, D., ‘What Metaphors Mean’, p. 259.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
81
the words are used. Using a sentence to tell a lie and using it to make a metaphor are, of course, totally different uses, so different that they do not interfere with each other [italics mine]. ... What distinguishes metaphor is not meaning but use—in this it is like the assertion, hinting, lying, promising, or criticising.21
These arguments by Davidson, comparing metaphorical uses with the effects achieved by lies are obviously relevant to Searle’s ‘fiction’ versus ‘non-fiction’ division. I will argue in the following paragraphs that the two seemingly major objections raised by Searle against considering fiction as an independent speech act, are, in fact, specious because they focus on the formal distinctions between fiction and non-fiction, only to prove that there aren’t any such. Since these types can be formally identical, not much is gained from a pragmatic point of view by admitting that, as Davidson puts it, ‘it is sometimes hard to prove what intention lay behind the saying’.22 On this non-controversial yet apparently endlessly engaging point, Searle, Davidson and I are all agreed. We are also probably all agreed that in point of fact conversationalists are very seldom into the business of ‘proving’ their own or others’ intentions. I will now advance this line of enquiry by suggesting specifically that our attention should be directed, not at the fiction/non-fiction nexus at all, but at the more crucial dichotomy between the putatively intentional act of telling a story, either fictional or non-fictional, and the act of making an assertion. Otherwise, an important pattern of similarities between stories which are factual (such as the vast majority which occur in spoken conversation) and those which are fictional, is obscured. To recapitulate, Searle’s main contentions are a) that ‘it would be impossible for anyone to understand a work of fiction without learning a new set of meanings for all the words and elements of a language’,23 b) that ‘there is no textual property, syntactic or semantic, that will identify a text as a work of fiction’.24 Several reasons exist, as we have observed, including the arguments cited from Davidson, why a) is prima facie not acceptable as an argument against considering fiction as a independent speech act, with a set of uses pragmatically distinguishable from non-fiction. For, as I’ve pointed out, both fiction and non-fiction might come packaged as narratives, formally indistinguishable, but there are still likely to be several strategies 21Ibid., p. 259. 22Ibid., p. 258. 23Searle, ‘ The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, pp. 236–7. 24Ibid., p. 236.
82
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
which conversationalists use to discover which is which in any given situation. Hence, Searle’s contention b) that no strictly ‘textual property’ determines which narrative is fictional and which isn’t can readily be acceded to, without necessarily conceding that any predictive power25 is thereby lost by conversationalists. There is little doubt that the kinds of problem posed by fictional discourse differ significantly from the kind of difficulty raised by stories, both factual and fictional, within the bounds of speech act theory. Fictional discourse, Searle believes, results in an ‘abuse’ of the felicity condition on assertions ‘S believes that p’. Hence, he proposes the solution that fiction be treated as a special case of assertion in which this particular condition is ‘suspended’. Stories, on the other hand, present a problem that has to do with the question of whether speech act theory is designed to deal with ‘macro’ entities such as stories. They require a meta-critique of the limits of the theory as a whole, unlike Searle’s treatment of fiction which only necessitates a theory-internal adjustment of the felicity conditions on assertions. The passage from Austin quoted earlier demonstrates that the originator of speech act theory certainly showed some inclination towards considering even an unwieldy genre like the novel a possible speech act, where the phrase ‘A Novel’ indicates that a connected sequence is to follow. Austin’s potentially revolutionary instinct seems to have been that to treat various ‘macro’ entities as speech acts would involve pointing to some available constraints on connected sequencing, such as the illocutionary force indicating device ‘a novel’ in the case of stories. Searle, however, does not address himself to this question at all, though it is as much a problem for the fictional stories he considered in his paper as for factual stories. One reason for this, as I have already said, is that Searle concentrates exclusively on fictional discourse. A second more foundational reason, which has to do with Searle’s resistance to a meta-critique of speech act theory, is also postulated later in this chapter. In the chapters that follow, as well as this one, I propose, after Austin, that there are in fact constraints on sequencing stories and conditions on story-telling as a speech act which differ markedly from the conditions on assertions. These pragmatic conventions apply as much to fictional as to factual narration and 25Dennett’s ‘Paradox of the Authorless Narrator’ is indeed based on the insight that all our narratives ‘prepare’ us for the future, whatever the ‘intentional stances’ that we choose to adopt.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
83
therefore provide an alternative to Searle’s claim that ‘no textual property’ separates fiction from non-fiction. Textual properties like the phrases ‘once upon a time’, or ‘a novel’ are, I suggest, conventional, but their conventionality is governed by cultural norms rather than ‘purely linguistic’ grammatical rules. If, say, newspaper headlines or the ‘Contents’ page/cover of a volume of short fiction, or story-announcements in a conversation are understood to be part of the ‘text’, then it seems reasonable to assume that they count as ‘textual properties’, enabling readers/ listeners to assess the functional significance of the sequence they are currently processing. Competent reception of narrative entails that a hearer concentrate on semantic connections between elements in a sequence and not fritter away her energies on deciding whether each individual assertion she confronts in a fictional sequence is a ‘pretended assertion’ or not. Once in place, I argue that the ‘textual properties’ which have signalled the fictionality or factuality of a narrative work holistically work to structure listeners’ expectations and predictions about the rest of the text.26 In fact, one of the very valuable insights provided by Searle himself is that there is a whole set of such ‘extra-linguistic’ conventions which govern fictional discourse. These conventions ‘enable the speakers to use words with their literal meanings without undertaking the commitments normally required by those meanings’.27 What Searle calls ‘extra-linguistic’— meaning, presumably, ‘not linguistic at all’ rather than ‘extremely linguistic’!—I refer to as ‘textual’ conventions, meaning those cues which enable a listener to more or less reliably figure out the function of any act of speech. Thus, while I cannot not agree with Searle’s conclusion that the existence of such conventions makes ‘the language game’ of storytelling ‘parasitic’ on, by implication, more basic ‘illocutionary language games’, I do in the next chapter make a preliminary attempt to extend the work of Grice and Lewis on ‘maxims’ and ‘conventions’, to include those cultural norms associated with the act of telling a story. I also consider some of the ‘non-natural’ meaning implicatures that can be generated when certain Gricean maxims are flouted during stories told in conversation. Searle asks the pertinent questions himself, ‘What are the mechanisms 26See Dennett and Chapters 1, 5 on this issue. 27Searle, ‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, p. 238.
84
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
by which the author invokes; these ... conventions? What procedures does he follow?’28 In this chapter, I argue that the ‘procedures’ followed by a story-teller are typical of the speech act of story-telling, while in the next chapter on Gricean cooperative maxims, I plead that the ‘mechanisms’ whereby the teller invokes these conventions are available for use within the system of conversational implicature that Grice outlines. Felicity Conditions and Narrative Fit Austin’s theory of speech acts grew out of the seemingly simple observation that not all sensible utterances in a language could be classified as either true or false. Many utterances such as ‘I name this ship the Queen Elizabeth are not falsifiable in the sense that the proposition ‘I named this ship the Queen Elizabeth’ on the 9th of January 1999’ is falsifiable. These utterances can, however, go wrong in which case they are ‘infelicitous’ in at least one of three ways. They can be abused, which would mean that the utterer does not have intentions appropriate to the performance of some particular speech act; they can misfire, which would mean that the listener has not understood the utterer to have performed the particular speech act which the utterer intended to perform; and they can be null and void, which would mean that circumstances render the speech act abortive. Any set of felicity conditions we construct for stories must, therefore, also enable us to determine the sorts of misfires, abuses and nullities which result from non-conformity to these conditions. Searle’s systematization of Austin also vitally affects any formulation of felicity conditions on narrative since it provides a general model of the illocutionary act in its prototypical form f(p)29 A valuable contribution by Searle to contemporary speech act theory is that he eschews Austin’s reliance on the verbs of a language to define classes of speech act. This step makes Searle’s taxonomy more consistent and comprehensive than Austin’s; and it also underlines a point that is very important in my analysis of narrative, namely, that it is possible to have illocutionary acts in a given language even in the absence of specific lexical verbs which correspond with the speech act in question. Thus, there is no verb in 28Ibid., p. 238. 29 See Searle, in Searle, Kiefer and Bierwisch, 1980, where he is responsible for
formulating the typical logical form of the speech act whereby it has a proposition content (p), and this propositional content is presented with a certain illocutionary force F, giving the total act the structure F(p), based on the premises that ‘that basic unit of human linguistic communication is the illocutionary act’.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
85
English, Hindi or Bengali which can be conventionally uttered with the force of ‘I narrate that ...’ in order to kick-start the telling of a story.30 In the following formulation of felicity conditions for narrative, bearing in mind that in the languages I consider there is no illocutionary verb that conventionally indicates the activity of story-telling, I will rely heavily on Searle’s table of typical conditions on speech acts. These are the essential, preparatory, sincerity and propositional-content conditions which must obtain for the felicitous performance of any speech act. My procedure will be to a) extrapolate from Searle’s classification of illocutionary acts a set of felicity conditions for stories; b) show, if possible, that these conditions accurately describe the distinctive qualities attaching of the stories in my data, and c) that violations of these conditions result in obvious misfires, abuses and nullities. Speech act theory claims categorically to be a theory which offers an explanation of the phenomena of natural language use. Therefore, it must survive the test of confrontation with actual data. The failure of the felicity conditions that I construct for stories to apply to my ‘real’ data will thus force alternative conclusions— Either a) Felicity conditions may be necessary and sufficient to capture the distinctive properties of the act of story-telling, but this particular set of felicity conditions is insufficient in major ways. Or b) Felicity conditions are neither necessary nor sufficient to capture the distinctive features of the act of story-telling, from which it follows that story-telling cannot be an illocutionary act in the sense of following ‘an accepted conventional procedure having a certain conventional effect’. But even if story-telling is not an illocutionary act it may still be a perlocutionary speech act, in which case the problem, as Austin first pointed out, is to decide whether there are in fact conventions which specially attach to perlocutionary acts.31 If a) is the conclusion reached by the failure of the felicity condition to apply to stories in my data then it may prove futile to travel on the same track until some very different notion of ‘felicity’ for speech acts comes to be invented. If b) is the conclusion reached, however, it will be equally frustrating to work further on felicity conditions for story-telling as an illocutionary act; but since it may be a complex perlocutionary act, I shall consider this possibility after presenting, and testing, the felicity conditions on story-telling below:
30See Searle’s arguments against Austin’s taxonomy in Hymes, 1976, pp. 7–1. 31Austin, How to do Things with Words, p. 118.
86
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Felicity Conditions on the Putative Illocutionary Act on Narration Propositional Content Condition: A story is any sequence of clauses p1 ... pn such that p1 describes an event t1 which temporally precedes events in the following clauses. Preparatory Condition: The (S)peaker has reason to believe that the sequence of clauses p1 ... pn will interest the (H)earer, resulting in at least one or more perlocutionary effects upon the H, which the H is bound to evaluate and/or articulate. p ... pn It is obvious to both S and H that t ... tn form a composite unit such that it is incumbent on S to complete the sequence once he has uttered p1, and it is incumbent on H to let him complete it.32 It is not obvious to either H or S that H has heard this particular sequence of p1 ... pn clauses 1 ... n before. t t p1 ... pn Sincerity Condition: S wants H to hear the sequence of clauses t1 ... tn through, and S desires H to assess their ‘tellability’, i.e. evaluate them in terms of perlocutionary effect.33 Essential Condition: This counts as an undertaking by S to demonstrate to H that the succession of clauses p1 ... pn is of interest to H and will t1 ... tn satisfy H in terms of perlocutionary effect. Comment:34 I take it that the essential condition for any illocutionary act states in some wise the illocutionary point of that illocutionary act. In narrative, I suggest that the illocutionary point is to show, through the medium of the story, that the general point or moral of the story could not have been made otherwise. Thus, for example, in the numerous accounts of flood disasters that I have recorded and analysed in Chapters 7-8, the general point being made was almost always the same, and could be expressed by a simple assertion such as ‘These floods have affected us disastrously!’ Yet each individual account of the flood was 32Compare Sacks, ‘An Analysis of the Course of a Joke’s Telling in Conversation’,
1974, p. 344, also quoted from at length in Chapter 8, page 330 of this book. 33See Furberg, Saying and Meaning, 1971, ‘Never say anything than cannot be expected to interest your addressee; and when you have started on a topic which interests him, don’t omit parts that are important to him.’ p. 93. 34In Speech Acts (1969) Searle allows himself some remarks on the interesting features of types of illocutionary acts in his classification of the felicity conditions for these acts, even though these features do not come under the heading of any specific felicity condition. I adopt the same procedure for my proposed conditions on story-telling.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
87
fashioned so as to demonstrate that it was intrinsically interesting in its own right and could not have been substituted by a simple assertion. It may be useful to recall here Searle’s insistence that fictional stories are a type of Assertion or Representative. Earlier in this chapter I’d entertained, and then rejected, the possibility that fictional stories could be analysed as pretended assertions. But there is an obvious sense in which factual stories, such as those in recorded flood disaster accounts, are not pretences. The crucial similarity between fictional and factual stories is that they are both stories and understood as such by Speakers and Hearers. Therefore, in dealing only with fictional discourse, my argument has been that Searle could be bypassing a central issue, which is whether to consider story-telling as an illocutionary act in its own right or not. Having now constructed a set of felicity conditions for stories, both fictional and factual, to be tested against data, I can at this point perhaps begin to offer some explanation for Searle’s keenness to maintain the divide between fictional and factual stories. Unlike Austin, who was ‘not content to restrict’35 himself to statements of an ‘ideal simplicity’36, Searle makes a strong claim that ‘the five basic kinds of illocutionary acts are: representatives (or assertive), directives, commissive, expressive and declarations’.37 But while the simplicity of this taxonomy has enormous appeal, it also commits Searle to analysing any more complex but intuitively recognizable speech act such as storytelling in terms of the five types of acts listed above. To analyse narrative as an illocutionary act would thus undermine the very premises on which Searle bases his classification of illocutionary acts. This is one of the primary reasons, among others that I detail briefly towards the end of this chapter, why classical speech act theory in the form that it has settled into today does not offer a suitable explanation of such phenomena as story-telling in conversation. Classical speech act theory has moved a long way, it seems, from an Austinian elucidation of ‘the total speech act in the total speech situation’. My attempt in this chapter to actually build felicity conditions for story-telling is partly meant to restore to speech act theory something of this original version of Austin’s. One other feature which may be worthy of comment about stories illocutionary acts is their direction of fit, which according to Searle is one of the most important ‘dimensions of difference between illocutionary 35Austin, ‘Performative Constative’, 1969, p. 22. 36Ibid., p. 22. 37Searle, ‘A Classification of Illocutionary Acts’, in Hymes (ed.), 1976, p. 1.
88
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
acts’.38 ‘Fit’ could be taken to be in one direction in the case of fictional accounts and in another in the case of non-fictional or factual accounts. Thus, in a factual account words could be taken to conform to certain events and actions in the world but not in a fictional one. And it is here that one durable difference between fictional and factual stories could possibly be located. Searle states that ‘direction of fit is always a consequence of illocutionary point’.39 Nevertheless, he confesses that he is ‘unable to make it’ the basis of his taxonomy, presumably because there are cases where it is difficult to determine the direction of fit because it is ambiguous. Now, in the specific case of stories I have postulated that their illocutionary point is to sustain the interest of the H through a temporal succession of clauses, but this interest may be aroused and maintained under appropriate circumstances by either a fictional or a factual story since I hope to show that there are no other important differences between the two—the only difference being that the words of a factual story should plausibly correspond to the world, in order to sustain H’s interest in the story as a factual story, whereas in a fictional story there is no such overt requirement. An intuitive speculation is that the element of belief (B) alters according to the factual or fictional nature of the narrative. Hence, if the story is factual, the element of B must ideally = 1, whereas if the story is fictional, the element of B can be > 0. In other words the range of B in the case of any story could be represented as being between the ideal points of 0 and 1.40 Since the questions of cultural belief, memory and convention are explored at greater length in Chapters 4–8 of this book, however, I will not labour the point about degree of belief any more here, but go on to ‘test’ the conditions on story-telling I’ve just constructed against various examples, both felicitous and infelicitous, of oral narrative performance. The Preparatory Conditions for this act are illustrated with reference to actual examples from natural conversation; the Sincerity Conditions are illustrated with reference to hypothetical examples. I have chosen, however, not to illustrate the Propositional Content Condition at all, not only because it is not defined with regard to the interaction between Speaker and Hearer, but because it has in effect been discussed in detail in Chapter 1, in relation to Labov’s definition of basic narrative structure. The Propositional Content Condition suggested by me, in short, is little 38Searle, ‘A Classification of Illocutionary Acts’, p. 1. 39Ibid., p. 4. 40See Dennett, 1991, on the relationship between beliefs and the self as a centre of
narrative, pp. 452–55.
FORCE, FICTION, FIT AND FELICITY
89
different from Labov and Waletsky’s pioneering one. It might be illustrated by Forster’s41 brief but well-known example— The king died and then the queen died. (p1 t1) + (p2 t2) As shown in Chapter 1, such sequences of clauses separated by a ‘temporal juncture’ between them are sometimes not understood by participants in a conversation as conveying a narrative sequence, even though, taken in isolation, they would be considered a ‘story’. Thus the weakness of the propositional content condition as applicable to stories in conversation has already been exposed in Chapter 1. In terms of speech act theory, it could be said that utterances fully in accordance with the present Propositional Content Condition on stories may still be shown not to ‘count as’ the performance of the act of telling a story. Similarly, I do not consider it necessary to illustrate the Essential Condition since it is a ‘fail-safe’ rule. It simply states that a story is any utterance that counts as such for teller and hearer. Now consider illustrations of the Preparatory and Sincerity Conditions below: Checking Speech Act Conditions on Narrativity against Data i)
a
356
A
357
a A a A
361 362 363 364
a A
366 367
(—laughs) what about the doctor, guy. Jake was it. II YESx—358 II OOH I don’t KNOWx. 359 II we play SQUASHx 360 and—took me off to see Phaedra BRITANNICA that other NIGHTx— um? II WHICH was um? quite AMUSINGx— I don’t what’s that— II it’s ; :m?—an up’dated. RICHARD Harrison II PETER Harrison}x 365 II version of ’s—E QUIVALENTx— oh yeah i II rib ?. oII riginally ‘done by EU RIPIDES>x. 368 II it’s !m? set in. the pre-Indian MUTINYx.
41E.M. Forster, Aspects of the Novel, 1974, p. 60. As a matter of interest, this example of Forster’s could well have derived from his Indian repertoire. Evidence for this comes via a very common Hindustani nursery rhyme that Forster is likely to have known. It goes ‘ek tha raja/ek tha rani/dono mar gae. khatam kahani’, meaning ‘there was a king and a queen/Both died and that’s the end of the story’. See also the ‘expansion’ of this Forsterian example as a ‘danger of death story’ in Chapter 5.
90
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
a A A
369 370 370
a A a A
378 379 380 381
a
383
A
384
a A
388 389
a A
401 402 403 404
a A
406 407
a A
411 412
im? —371 the II WIFEx 372 the II SONx—373 >. II KINGx. 374 II SHAHx . 365 II KINGx—376 well you II KNOWx 377 the British. viceroy—im?— II iku?x— what i? i? imperial India *you mean* *IIYESx* 382 IM II PERIAL ‘India’ just be’ fore >— that’d be the. would it be the +viceroy then—yeah— yes+ +well it II OUGHT to be the VICEROYx 385 but I’m II sure that’s not what they CALLED himx + but 386 II ANYWAYx—387 II it was all rhyming COUPLETS BASICALLYx *oh yeah (—laughs)* *(—laughs)* and II some of them were .. REAL} GROANERSx II some of them were REALLY quite’ clever391 and the II rest you ‘just didn’t NOTICE’ you knowx—392 II it had. ii:?’ most—. II it was IN CREDIBLEx 393 II i. II I had cut OTx—394 II>x 395 II two of my brothers were sitting in the FLATx 396 when II I was IN VITED to itx 397 and II I de’cided it was time to find OUT a ‘bout it be’fore I WENTx—398 II ..m}x—399 they’d II brought a. Time OUTx—400 II i i:? WRITE-UP for it was. II absolutely ... utterly CON DEMNINGx— *(laughs)* *it was* II saying that you would sit THEREx youd be II yawning till you were bored STIFF andx. 405 it +was II really TERRIBLEx—+ +(—laughs) + so I IIMET ‘ Jake at the PUBx 408 and II I said OHx 409 > read THIS be’fore you GO to (CI)->(II)->(EI)->(CI) ... n (recursively) C(ausal) I(nference) -> X cause Y, Y cause Z ... n I(nformational) I(nference) -> A,B,C ... n connect X,Y,Z ... n E(valuative) I(nference) -> A,B,C, and/or X,Y,Z connote P,Q,R ... n
214
X,Y A,B,C, P,Q,R
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
-> any clause or phrase within the sequence of the candidate N -> any clause or phrase outside the candidate N
I have chosen the genres of ‘the short, short story’ and ‘the tall, tall tale’ in order to illustrate how my rewrite rules work. Minimal narratives, because of their generic and tantalizing brevity, require extensive inference-making on the part of listeners. Likewise, tall tales which are deliberately implausible, provoke inferences of a special sort by listeners. Together, tall, tall tales and short, short stories thus offer a useful group of formally contrastive narratives which facilitate the construction of a grammar, narrative based, not so much on a hypothesis about invariant elements of structure as on a postulate about the continuous processes of inferencing that systematize a story. As I’ve emphasized, a crucial difference between mine and the earlier story-grammars is that my inferential model does not simply assign propositions in a given story to nodes such as orientation, complication, resolution on a set tree. It allows for, indeed depends on, fresh inputs from the listener to keep the story moving. It is this adoption of such a listener’s or hearer’s perspective that helps incorporate narrative processing within a broader Gricean framework of communicative cooperation in general. Obviously, a schema which emphasizes the listener’s role in creating and ‘gluing together’ the parts of a narrative through her active inferences is also in keeping with Dennett’s idea of ‘authorlessness’. The onus is shifted here from the intentional narrator’s shoulders to those of the inferring listener. It is she who carries the burden of establishing narrative connectivity, of proving to herself that she has ‘got the point’, and the body of Vac is reconstituted. How does she achieve this? Inferring an evaluative judgement from the story, when it is not made explicit by the teller, as in minimal narratives, enables the listener to a) actively participate in the construction of the narrative. b) display her cultural knowledge and membership-status, her memeawareness. c) cooperate with the teller in resolving inherent textual enigmas. The means by which particular inferences follow from a particular narrative ordering—a classic problem in narrative studies12—will be the 12 Levelt (1981), we recall, made a point similar to Sacks (1972) that different
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
215
main focus of the discussion which follows the briefest of brief stories below: 1. The king died and [then] the queen died [of grief] (E.M. Forster). 2. aekta bagh, aekta shikari, aekta bagh (Bengali, traditional). a tiger, a hunter, a tiger. 3. John Donne, Anne Donne, Undone (John Donne). 4. Algy met a bear. The bear was bulgy. The bulge was Algy. 5. A GHOST STORY IN ONE SENTENCE. A man woke up in the dark, felt frightened, groped for his torch, and felt it put into his hand. 6. PI PU, PHI SHU. du jon alshi lok, agun ! aek jon bole PI PU BU BA, TU OV. Two lazy men. Fire ! One man says BU BA onno jon uttor dae: PHI SHU du jonei pure more. The other replies: TU OV. Both burn to death (Bengali, traditional). 7. A tree, a nest, two birds, three eggs, three fledglings, two birds again. 8. I’ll you a story, said Jack-a-Nory And now my story’s begun I’ll tell you another Of Jack and his brother And now my story is done. 9. It was a dark and stormy night The rain, it fell in loomps Tell me a tale the Captain said And the tale it ran as follows It was a dark and stormy night ... (and etc.). Suppose we were to expand the inferences in Story 1, taking it to be uncontroversially a narrative sequence, and not what Labov called a inferences followed from the different ordering of narrative propositions when he used ‘absurd’ sentences like ‘The Lone Rider rode off into the sunset and mounted his horse’, to demonstrate that there is a natural causal and psychological, as well as cultural, ordering of narrative. 13See in this connection Grice on ‘Indicative Conditionals’ in his 1967 William James Lectures in which he discusses possible ‘expansions’ of expressions like ‘and’ disallowed in formal logic but not uncommon in everyday talk. Sperber and Wilson also comment: ‘in his William James Lectures, Grice put forward an idea of fundamental importance: that the very act of communicating creates expectations which it then exploits. Grice himself first applied this idea and its elaboration in terms of the maxims to a rather limited problem of linguistic philosophy: do logical connectives (‘and’, ‘or’, ‘if ... then’) have the same meaning in natural languages as they do in logic? He argued that the richer meaning these connectives seem to have in natural languages can be explained in terms not of word meaning but of implicature.
216
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
‘list’, i.e., clauses simultaneously rather than temporally ordered with respect to one another, we would get: i. The king died and the queen died. ii. The king died and then the queen died.13 By Rule I: If there is no evidence to the contrary, assume all linear sequences are temporal sequences. iii. The king died and then, as a result, the queen died. By Rule II: If there is no evidence to the contrary, assume all temporal sequences are causal sequences. iv. The king died and then, as a result, the queen of grief. of loneliness. of merry-making(?!). of palace intrigues. of the same infection. By Rule III: If there is no evidence to the contrary, assume that a causal sequence can be reinforced by suitable informational evidence either from within the text, or from world knowledge. Thus, if Rule III holds, the addition of first and second order inferences (see feature c) of story-grammars, listed above, turn out not to be arbitrary but directed by a narrative rule that requires causal inferences to be supplemented/reinforced by informative ones. It is an interesting speculation that these choices of what Sperber and Wilson (1986) call ‘enriching’ inferences are constrained by their most information/least effort principle. This cognitive principle of relevance would decree, for example, that the inference ‘the queen died of grief’ is more plausible a conjecture than that ‘the queen died of over-indulgence, celebrating the king’s death’, an entirely possible but less likely event, given our real-world, encyclopaedic, knowledge of the conventional correlation of death and grief. In other words, Sperber and Wilson would argue that this inference is prima facie ruled out because it involves much more processing effort, many more inferential steps—a position which will be considered later in my discussuion of Story 2 or the ‘tiger’ story. At present, however, a final step in the development/ expansion of Story 1 follows from Rule IV, yielding something like: iv. The king died and [then, as a result] the queen died [of grief]: ubi sunt, sic transit gloria mundi.
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
217
By Rule IV: If there is no evidence to the contrary, assume that the choice of the most plausible informational inference(s) leads to some evaluative generalization that gives ‘point’ to the story. The generalizations ‘everything passes’ and/or ‘so passes the glory of the world’ reflect a recurrent theme in ‘Western’ ‘Christian’ culture relating to mortality and the impermanence of the earthly state. On the other hand, this sort of generalization may not be entirely appropriate in a culture where, for example, the idea of rebirth or re-incarnation was widely accepted. It is here that my additional idea of impliculture seeks to play a vital theoretical role (see next section). In all cases, however, implicit references to deep and ‘weighty’ cultural themes seem to help ward off the ‘so what?’ question which Labov claims every listener implicitly asks of every narrator. Almost every researcher on narrative from Aristotle through Labov to Bakhtin has noted that a narrative must have a ‘point’. Although it is not clear whether this is a culture-specific requirement or not, there seems to be a widespread norm that a story amounts to more than just a sequential enumeration of events. Particular evaluations and generalizations might, of course, differ from culture to culture. For instance, the anthropologist Edmund Leach recalls that the powerful biblical story of the Fall, when Adam and Eve felt shame for the first time at their nakedness, made no sense at all in the Nuer culture where people habitually went unclothed, until Adam and Eve were redescribed as brother and sister, and the theme of incest thus once again invested the motif of shame with point.14 In exploring the Bengali minimal narratives in Story 2, the ‘pointless’ Story 7 and Bauman’s ‘coon’ stories below, I return to this issue of cultural ballast, but at this juncture will merely reiterate that the normative needs of Rule 4, requiring evaluation, seem to hold very generally, despite the evaluations themselves requiring significantly different presuppositions in different cultures. Inferring an evaluation or ‘moral’ from the story appears to serve the pragmatic function of a Labovian coda by definitively resolving inherent textual enigmas and thus barricading the narrative for the time-being. At the point of the final listener’s evaluation the gnomon of narrative time closes in upon itself again. Application of the Inferential Model to Minimal Narratives The following assignment of nodes and terminals to Stories 1 through 5, as well as stories 8 and 9, on the inferential tree-structure I have suggested, 14Edmund Leach, Mythology, 1974, p. 9.
218
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
N
TS
x and then y...n. DOMAIN OF RULE I.
IS
CI x cause y (x) + y cause...n. DOMAIN OF RULE II.
II a, b...n connect x, y...n DOMAIN OF RULE III.
II
EI x, y...n; a, b...n connote p, q...n. DOMAIN OF RULE IV.
(... and so on, in theory, ad infinitum). Worked out in detail, stories 1–5 would appear to be structured: 1.
N
TS
IS
x {and then} y and z and...n. BY RULE I
CI {x cause y cause x, y...n} BY RULE II
II {a, b...n. connect z....n.} *1. BY RULE III.
the king. → died and then the queen died
the king → died and then therefore the queen died.
the king died and then, therefore the queen died of grief.
EI {x, y...n; a, b...n connote p, q, r} BY RULE IV. The king died, and then therefore the queen died of grief. Sic transit gloria mundi.
219
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
IS CI Since both king and queen were dead, an heir to the throne was was needed.
II Heirs to thrones in many cultures are sons, not daughters ...
EI Who would be heir? A mystery! *2 *1. x cause y, y cause z may be too strictly sequential since x and y can combine to cause inference z, and z can in turn combine with x and y to cause n, and so forth. Or x can cause y and z, without y having to cause z. Such minor modifications to my rewrite rules are, of course, possible to make in the analysis of a given narrative. *2. These additional inferences show how listeners can always ‘tag-on’ inferences at any stage during the narrative on the basis of information volunteered by the teller, using the categories of cause (since, therefore, because, etc.), information about the world, including cultural knowledge (as in the inference about male heirs), which they take to be relevant and evaluation (how mysterious, how sad! what will happen now? etc.). 2.
N TS ○
IS
○
○ ○
○ ○
○
○
x
y
a tiger
& then a hunter
○
z
CI & then a tiger
→
a tiger, → therefore a hunter.
II hunters shoot tigers; tigers eat hunters.
CI The story ends with → Goodness ‘a tiger’. Ergo the tiger ate the hunter, since it is economical to assume, given no evidence to the contrary, that the tiger at the end is identical to the tiger first mentioned. *3.
EI
gracious! The biter bit! A tale of irony.
*3. The appeal to a criterion of ‘economy’ is derivable from Grice’s Maxim of Quantity, as well as my own maxims of narrativity, discussed in more detail with reference to this particular story in the section on cooperative norms below:
220
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
3.
N TS
IS
○
○
○
○ ○ ○
○
○ ○ ○
○
x Anne Donne
y & then John Donne
○
z & then Undone
II John Donne, a poet, was tutor to Anne, whom he later married, despite severe opposition.
CI John Donne is undone because of Anne Donne; or vice versa; or both are mutually undone by each other, or by some other cause.
II ‘John’ and ‘Anne’ are conventionally male and female names. When men and women are ‘undone’ by each other, the cause is, again by convention, often attributed to an emotion called ‘love’.
CI Given all the information so far, it is economical to conclude that John and Anne were undone by love for each other, and not some other cause. We can also surmise that this story is probably autobiographical.
CI John Donne was a poet; therefore it is not unlikely that he wrote these lines. Furthermore, we can assume that he wrote them after he was married, given that ‘Anne’ has the surname ‘Donne’ in the story.
II Poems have rhyming lines.
II From the fact that John Donne was a poet, and poems have rhyming lines, we can assume this story is a ‘poem’, or at least ‘literary’.
CI Causes generally precede effects.
CI
II (continued on next page)
221
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
CI From all the information so far we can revise our original hypothesis that John and Anne Donne were mutually ‘undone’ by love for each other, to John Donne as the more likely focus of the undoing.
II ‘Undone’ means ‘smitten’, ‘conquered’, ‘left defenceless’. This imagery occurs quite often in John Donne’s poetry, which is of the seventeenth century metaphysical school, deeply intellectual and ‘ironic’.
II Poems and ‘literary texts’ usually display special qualities, like irony and rhythm. They also often have a didactic element or ‘moral’.
CI So, it is probable, that John Donne is being ironic at his own expense in this story-poem.
II There has been a tendency in many cultures, including Donne’s own, for poets to sing of the glories of love. This faith in the power of love is also evidenced in popular adages such as, for example: Amor vincit omnia!
EI Aha! Got it! Poetic devices, such as rhyme, are being humorously used by John Donne in this narrative to give us his own ironic version of a generalization like Amor vincit omnia!
4. Story 4. ‘Algy met a bear’, a traditional cautionary tale for children, is in many ways structurally similar to Donne’s more sophisticated and definitely adult tale, which may be indicative of the fact that inferential strategies can be shared across a wide spectrum of tales and tellers. ‘Algy met a bear’ requires far less recourse to encyclopaedic knowledge of a particular textual tradition than Donne’s minimal narrative. This makes it ‘suitable’ for children, but at the same time it is important not to lose sight of the quality of ‘dramatic irony’, or reversal of expectations, which pervades this story as much as it does Donne’s poem and Story 2 about the tiger eating the hunter. Like these stories, ‘Algy’ also makes use of the structural device of iteration analysed in a separate section below. One might in fact argue that it is exactly such an ‘expansion’ of a text that the whole enterprise of academic criticism undertakes when it ‘reads meanings into’ and offers new interpretations of a literary work.
222
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
5.
N
TS x→ a man woke in the dark
IS & then y→ & then z→ & then n felt groped [and] frightfor felt ened his it torch put into his hand
CI because the man woke up in the dark, therefore he felt frightened, therefore he groped, etc., and therefore a torch was placed in his hand
II being alone in the dark often frightens people; a torch lights up the dark *4.
CI we can therefore conclude that the man was alone when the torch was put into his hand, otherwise there would be nothing remarkable about the fact. Ergo, this is the ghostly happening implied in title of the story *5.
EI Who put the matches into the man’s hand? Wow! A ghost! *6. *4. & *5. There appears little reason to insist, within the inferential model that I’ve presented, that one and only one ‘piece of information’ (roughly equivalent, I suppose, to a single proposition) can attach to a single node (CI, II, or EI) in a given tree. Many psychologists have argued that information naturally comes in rough-cut ‘chunks’ instead. Thus, under the II node marked by *4, there are two pieces of information, working in conjunction, one, that being alone in the dark frightens people, and two, that torches light up the dark. Similarly, under the CI node marked by *5, two causal inferences are made, one, the man was alone, two, the torch being put into his hand was the ghostly happening to be identified. Nor is there any good reason in this model why such concatenations of inferences should stop at two at each terminal. Pragmatically, limitations of time would act as a natural constraints or the information summoned up, while psychologically memory would provide another sort of external constraint. *6. Evaluative inferences, consisting of (mental) queries, feelings of surprise, fear, etc., in this sort of schema, often seem to repeat information already inferred at a moment in the story’s processing. This happens, for example, in this story, where the ghostly event has
223
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
been identified at an earlier terminal. It happens in Story 3, when the final evaluative inference repeats some of the information in the adjoining information inference. Why evaluative inferences should typically repeat information is a question that will be raised in relation to Sperber and Wilson’s theory of ‘echoic mention’ in the section on repetition below: 8 & 9. N
TS I’ll tell you a story Of Jack and his brother And now my story’s begun + I’ll tell you another Of Jack and his brother And now my story is done.
IS CI 0
II 0
→
→ EI But I haven’t had a chance to infer anything!Huh, so where’s my story? I’m puzzled.
N
TS It was a dark and stormy night
IS It was a dark and stormy night
TI [when] The rain it fell in loomps [and then] Tell me a tale the Captain said [and then] The tale it ran as follows It was a dark and stormy night ... (and etc.).
CI [as result] The rain it fell in loomps
II Dark, stormy rainy nights are great occasions for story-telling
CI [as a result] Tell me a tale, the Captain said
II Someone agreed to tell the Captain a tale
CI [as a result] A tale was told The tale it ran as follows
II It was a dark and stormy night ....
EI Gosh! This sounds a lot like the beginning of our story! Are we going round in circles by any chance? That’s recursion. Funny, fun!
224
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
represent a preliminary attempt to observe these rules in action. An abstract tree in its simplest form, without the terminal nodes filled in, might look something like: Both stories 8 and 9 contain, as it were, ‘excluded middles’. The first consists of two commisive speech acts backed by declaratives, but there is no Labovian ‘complicating action’ or ‘resolution’, which were core elements in earlier story-grammars. In terms of my inferential grammar, the shock of surprise generated by these stories would be accounted for not by pointing out that a central pre-determined part is missing, but by suggesting that listeners are deprived of a psychological necessity. There is simply very little work in these stories for the usually active right-most IS arm of the narrative grammar to do. Perhaps there is a little more scope for evaluative inferencing in the story 9, partly because of the semantics of atmosphere conjured up by the first two lines. In this ‘tale’, the Captain remains a shadowy, Ancient Mariner-like figure until the end, and depending on one’s levels of literary sophistication, one could make further nautical connections or raise questions of basic narrative identity (is the present teller the original teller, for example?), but my focus here is on operation of structures of inference-making. I contend that these, rather than any pre-specified parts of a story structure, are what are essential to the grammar of narrative. Earlier story-grammars would simply have rejected as ungrammatical garbage the ‘trick’ stories above. However, this would hardly explain the mental states of pleasure, surprise, and so forth, that they arouse in us. On the contrary, a grammar based on a recursive inference-making system that combines real-world knowledge with story information would account for perlocutionary effects because it crucially depends on the reader/listener actively trying to ‘get’ the point of the narrative. In stories 8 and 9, it is precisely when the second inference-making arm finds itself flailing that the paradoxical ‘point’ of these story communicates itself, thus actually making space for the final satisfaction of an evaluative inference (EI) at the end. The importance of evaluative inferences as ‘codas’ produced by listeners is attended to in point 3 of the comments below. The detailed analyses of seven minimal narratives attempted above have a number of implications for any cognitively oriented model of narrative such as my own, which is intimately linked to the post-Gricean notion of impliculture that I will shortly present. Briefly, these comprise: 1. A Contrast between the functions of left-hand and right-hand nodes on the inferential tree—The parsing rules I have worked out above assign a relatively ‘static’ role to the left-most TS (temporal sequencing)
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
225
node. This first branching of the tree suggests that, apart from the conversion of all sequential ‘lists’ to ‘and then’ temporal structures, nothing much else gets done on this side of the tree. There is thus a qualitative difference between the left-most TS and subsequent rightbranching arms: the TS arm attends mainly to memory and storage, the left IS arm to ‘relevance’ requirements. An obvious metaphor would be to regard the left side as a vast mnemonic storage-bin where all and only the information directly forthcoming from the teller is stored in linear order. Hierarchical inferences from real-world knowledge added by the listener are all on the right-hand side. A possible prediction from this sort of model would then arise, for example, in the area of narrative acquisition. Young children could be expected to master the ‘and then’ TI structure on the left-hand side of the tree (i.e., the domain of Rule I), sooner than the more complex CI, II, EI structures, which are the domains of Rules II, III and IV. Skills at narrative recounting and reception would grow as children became able to add pieces of information relevant to interpretation, rather than merely memorizing the story under the right hand nodes. Anecdotal evidence indicates that very little children across cultures do, in fact, prefer simple rhythmic repetitions of a story before they grow confident enough to add to it or react to it on their own.15 Likewise, children with autism, who have difficulties with story-telling, owing to a possible problem with constructing theories of mind, seem to be able to master the repetitive or mnemonic aspects of narrative repetition without going on to a stage where they contribute their own inferences to a story.16 2. Default and contraction rules—When putative tree structures are assigned to narrative, as in Stories 1–7 above, certain corollaries to the Rules I– IV suggest themselves. It is logical, for example, to assume that narratives which can be enriched and expanded can also be contracted or closed off. A tree can be trimmed or pruned at various stages; that is, the listener can ‘decide’ (not necessarily consciously) to delete or disregard pieces of information provided by the teller as either unimportant to the progress of the narrative, inconsistent with 15 See in this connection, Bambi B. Schiefflin and Elinor Ochs (eds), Language Socialization Across Cultures, 1986. This work focuses on children’s story-telling routines. 16At present, I am working on autism and its possible socio-linguistic correlates, along with my Ph.D student, Rajesh Kumar. Kumar’s dissertation, entitled ‘A Psycholinguistic Analysis of Verbal Communication in Autism with Special Reference to Social Communication’ is the first of its kind in India.
226
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
previous narrative information, or simply untrue. The simple default Rules V and VI, covering cases where a move to the next node is indicated if there is nothing to be attached to the currently active terminal, takes care of these possibilities: Rule V—If no CI (causal inference) is necessary at a given point, move down the tree to a II (informational inference); if no II is necessary at a given terminal in the story’s progress, move on to an EI (evaluative inference); and if no EI is judged necessary, move on again to a CI, following the cause->connect-> connote route, until the teller’s narrative sequence comes to an end. Rule VI—If the information provided by the teller seems unlikely to contribute to a causal, informational or evaluative narrative inference (CI, II, EI), delete, discount or disregard it. One of the tricks in a detective story, for example, is to pass ‘clues’ on to the reader without fore-grounding them. These clues are often disguised as irrelevant detail that a listener ‘automatically’ deletes while processing incoming information. It is only at the story’s end that the significance of the ‘deleted’ fact suddenly becomes clear. Interestingly, such a ‘oh, I’d completely forgotten that!’ response typically tends to heighten the effect of the mandatory ‘evaluation’ in the closing sequence of a ‘whodunit’. In genres like the ‘tall story’, it might be imperative for listeners to discount or delete information provided by the tellers as not really ‘true’. This move would in fact, be essential for a tall story to work as a tall story. For example, in Bauman’s ‘coon’ stories16, a teller reveals his discovery that the ‘finest coon dog’ that he has just bought will actually never pursue raccoons and will only chase deer. So the teller gives away the useless dog, but just ‘five minutes later’, a guy, drives up and asks him where he can find ‘a deer dog for sale’! To take the emphatic ‘five minutes’ here as literally true would be to miss the point; its value is simply as rhetorical stratagem which brings home to the listener the chance so very narrowly missed by the teller. Any such selfdeprecating narrative relies on its sharp contrasts being taken ‘with a pinch of salt’—that is, at least partially discounted by the listener. If the listener failed to ‘cooperate’ by taking all the teller’s claims as literally true, then the story would hardly ‘count as’ a tall tale. That is precisely why cultural knowledge—what I have called ‘impliculture’, is so crucial in the interpretative or inferential processes of narrative. 3. The intuitive connection between evaluative inferences and story endings— A final rule that suggests itself concerns neither movement by default down a narrative tree nor certain terminals coinciding with certain
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
227
types of inference, but cognitive models themselves. Like cognitive models in general, a narrative grammar must attempt to account for speaker/hearer intuitions. And intuitively, it seems to be the case that evaluative inferences act like natural resting points in a story structure. Roland Barthes, in his structural analysis of narrative, for instance, proffers the idea that every story needs ‘areas of safety, rests, luxuries.’17 During descriptive passages in a story, the action dawdles to a standstill; it is possible relax, to meditate and evaluate ‘the story so far’. Like a park bench while taking a walk, these parts of a story enhance the overall appeal of the narrative by offering a space to the reader/listener, otherwise in danger of ‘opting out’ of the rest of the journey out of exhaustion. When a listener is persuaded to walk through a sufficient cultural repertoire of stories, she imbibes the knowledge that there is a significant correlation to be observed. The most evident ‘resting place’ in a story is its ending and there is almost always an ‘evaluation’ at this point. A rule which would take into account this phenomenon of the co-occurrence of a certain type of inference, and a certain point in a story structure would read something like the following: Rule VII—Whenever possible, a story ending should coincide with an evaluative inference (EI) rather than a causal (CI) or informational one (II); conversely, whenever an evaluative inference is made, there is the possibility of a structural ‘pause’ in the progress of the narrative, which sometimes may amount to a story(‘s) ending. 4. Listener’s perspective adopted and individual differences of interpretation represented—It hardly needs repeating that a crucial difference between this and the earlier story-grammars is that, unlike them, this model does not simply assign propositions in a story—say, ‘Melvin the Skinny Mouse’—to nodes such as orientation, or resolution on a set tree. It allows for, indeed depends on, fresh inputs from the listener to keep the story moving. Because the earlier grammars simply assigned parts of a given narrative to terminal nodes in a tree, our picture of narrative processing remained superficial. Once the last sentence or phrase of a narrative had been assigned, it was assumed that narrative processing was complete. Such models failed to show how information could be added to or deleted from a narrative, even while it was conceded listeners did in fact ‘reorganize’ narrative information continuously. This process of addition and reorganization by listeners is precisely what the current 17Barthes, 1977, p. 95.
228
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
model focuses on. Previous models were essentially left-handed, while this one is right-handed. Without these right-hand processes, as I’ve tried to show, a story cannot be adequately processed or understood. If anything is original in this chapter, it is this grammaticalized listener or hearer perspective, which sets narrative processing within a broader Gricean framework of communicative cooperation. Sperber and Wilson (1992) point out in their critique of previous models of communication in general, and Gricean theory in particular, that: different hearers with different background knowledge and different imaginations will follow different (inferential) routes. However, they are all encouraged and guided by the text, and they all proceed by exploring its analytic and contextual implications as relevantly as they can.
I would like to add to this observation of Sperber and Wilson’s that even the same listener can at different points of time interpret the text differently and bring somewhat different pieces of contextual information to bear on the text. Different routes to an evaluation of textual relevance by one or many listeners are, in fact, exactly what the right-hand side of my model makes it possible to represent. Insofar as their representations and applications of real-world knowledge matched, the model would therefore predict that different listeners or the same listener at a different time would have similar interpretations of the story; insofar as their use of real-world information to reorganize the story varied, listeners would actually be recipients of very different stories. In the example of the Nuer narrative cited earlier, it was the application of real-world, cultural knowledge that led recipients to first ‘misread’ and then re-interpret the story, to give it evaluative point. By incorporating the text of a story but no other material, previous story-grammars were disadvantaged; they were unable to cope with the vital aspect of narrative processing that allows the representation of individual interpretations. 5. Non-propositional attitudes privileged—Sperber and Wilson (1992) also criticize Grice’s ‘logico-pragmatic approach’ for under-emphasizing the ‘non-propositional’, non-deductive aspects of utterances. ‘An ironical utterance carries suggestions of attitude—and sometimes ... of images—which cannot be made entirely explicit in propositional form’. Although Sperber and Wilson’s remark is made with ironic utterances in mind, I think they would agree that it applies more generally. In the case of narrative, I have argued, and will argue further, that
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
229
non-propositional, emotive inferences or perlocutions play a very special role in giving a story its ‘point’ and fending off the ‘So what?’ enquiry from a listener. These attitudinal inferences are therefore assigned their own ‘evaluative’ node in my schema, but it is important to note that the re-write rules that I suggest require the evaluative node (EI) to be dominated by a causal or informational one (CI, II). This ensures that evaluations or non-propositional inferences of attitude are, in fact, deductively linked, a la Grice, to earlier propositional inferences. Narrative coherence is thereby maintained via a chain of reasoning. This brings us directly to Gricean Theory. Implicature, Explicature and Impliculture Grice’s Theory of Conversational Implicature, which has had an indelible effect on all speech act and performative models, suggests that communication is at its most cooperative, that is, rationally efficient, when it conforms to the sub-maxims of Quality, Quantity, Relevance, and Manner. As we know, Sperber and Wilson have since tried, with controversial success, to reduce these multiple commandments to the single psychological maxim of relevance, in order to eliminate Grice’s more social ‘cooperative principle’. But my argument here will be that a generalized theory of cooperative conversation is still required as background for a more particular theory of narrative inference. This is because a successful narrative seems to be one where tellers’ implicatures and listeners’ inferences dovetail; or, to express it differently, narrative competence is best attested in cases where tellers and listeners culturally cooperate—are able to cooperate—in their evaluations. This is not always possible in the absence of specific cultural knowledge, nor is it possible without recourse to specific maxims such as the Maxims of Quality and Quantity, as these appear to have a direct bearing on the manner in which narrative inferences are made, as I shall try to show below with reference to the genres of the short, short story and the tall, tall tale. The original appeal of Grice’s theory was that it showed how an apparently casual social activity like conversation, where ‘meanings’ were far from rigorously defined, was actually guided by norms of logical reasoning. The deductive apparatus used by conversationalists to retrieve implicatures from ordinary talk was little different from the ‘rational’ procedures used by philosophers to construe ‘meanings’ and construct ‘theories of meaning’. Like philosophers, conversationalists too—despite their natural disadvantages!—made reference to notions like ‘truth’, ‘economy of argument’ and ‘synthetic vs. analytic propositions’, in order
230
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
to make inferences; only the set of premises they relied on was rather large, including as it did contextual information. Grice’s frequent references to contextual information, presumably not excluding culturally specific aspects of knowledge, as a resource for working out implicatures, make his work particularly attractive to those interested in pragmatic explanations of linguistic functioning. Useful though the maxims are as overarching inferential norms, they must be supported, in the description of particular activities such as story-telling, or joke-recounting, or apologizing, or gossiping, by the rules of inferencing peculiar to those activities. The Maxims of Narrative Implicature presented in Chapter 4 are an example. Similarly, the Inferential Model of Narrative in this chapter emphasizes that cues to the structure of a story are derived from patterns of temporality, causality and evaluation typically associated with narrative forms, as distinct from conversational conventions, in any given culture. These patterns, it is suggested, are not fixed, like the six stable elements of earlier narrative grammar (setting, resolution, etc.), but allow for the fluid interplay of contextual and linguistic information in the creation of narrative meaning. To return, for example to Story 2—‘A tiger, a hunter, a tiger.’ In this particular story, the ‘facts’ to be explained are: a) that the proposition ‘the tiger ate the hunter’ is inferred by all competent hearers from this narrative sequence. b) that some competent hearers think this narrative amusing/ironic. Now, Gricean theory can deal very well with the first of these facts. As the connections between the three NP’s are not made explicit in the ‘tiger story’, we perceive in it a violation of Grice’s Quantity Maxim, which enjoins conversationalists to be ‘adequately informative’. Implicatures then follow by rule, via the following sort of reasoned steps: i) The narrator has violated the maxim of quantity. ii) From his violation + contextual knowledge (i.e., what I know about tigers and hunters, as well as the fact that the sequence is offered as a story), the narrator intends me to infer additional meanings not made explicit in his telling. iii) Since tigers eat people, and hunters are people, I can safely infer that the tiger ate the hunter. However, it is not quite clear from Grice’s steps how the second, nonpropositional, ‘perlocutionary effect’ b) is inferred, unless we know that
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
231
in some cultures, excessive brevity is regarded as droll, the soul of wit, etc. The fashioning of this story in its truncated form may then be seen as exploiting this cultural norm. A typical story in many cultures is typically prolix, as it has not only to narrate the ‘bare facts’ but indicate through ‘evaluative devices’ (asides, exclamations, intensifiers, etc.), and the significance of those facts. The ‘tiger’ story is slightly unusual in that it violates the maxim ‘be adequately informative’ in a way that runs counter to the usual run of narratives; it is less not more than adequately informative. But now imagine a culture where stories are standardly told through a staccato series of nominalizations. Consider, as an example from this hypothetical culture, story 7, quoted again below: A tree, a nest, two birds, three eggs, three fledglings, two birds again.
Here, it would be perfectly possible to infer the temporal->causal-> informational-> sequence of this narrative without finding it in the least funny or witty. If the ‘tiger’ story were recounted in this culture, it is reasonable to assume that it too would not be regarded as funny or witty, simply because it was in contravention of the Maxim of Quantity, as we interpret this maxim. In other words, we are now forced to ask: are the reasons for the ‘tiger’ story being regarded as ‘funny’ based on a violation of the quantity maxim alone? Or could it be that the culturespecific knowledge underlying this story—namely, that it is of the ironic ‘biter-bit’ variety—that contributes to the evaluative inference that it is funny ? Part of my thesis in Narrative Gravity is that innumerable stories across cultures are fashioned as explanations for generalizations such as ‘life is hard’ or adages such as ‘make hay while the sun shines’. Such general ‘truths’ are ‘known’ in particular societies, yet being general, they continually stand in need of supporting evidence from specific cultural products such as stories. The theoretical implications of considering stories as particularized evidence for general cultural beliefs is considered at greater length in Chapters 6 and 7. The answer to the question—why is the ‘tiger’ story funny, but not the equally laconic ‘bird’ story?—requires reference not only to Grice’s Quantity Maxim, but also to the fact that we are trained to regard ‘the biter being bitten’, agent-as-victim, subject-as-object, and other such sets of reversals as ironic in many cultures. No such reversal, ‘peripety’ in Aristotle’s idiom, falls out from the second story, and so it might be inferred that it is less rich in cultural ‘indices’ (Barthes), evaluation (Labov), dialogic imagination (Bakhtin, Todorov), and/or perlocutionary effect (Searle, Austin).
232
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Another cultural/pragmatic set of reasons which could influence a listener’s positive evaluation of the ‘tiger’ story is connected not with its being a kind of saturnine revenge comedy, but with its generic specification.18 This sort of story, as a genre, seems to be quite close to a riddle in its advertised uninformativeness.19 So when we ‘get’ the point of the story, as when we ‘get’ a riddle, part of the pleasure is in our our own cultural savvy. Cleverness pleases us, especially our own; conversely dullness frustrates, our own or anyone else’s. Story 7, for example, is likely in the end to be evaluated as boring and pointless, except perhaps in a diectic or learning context, because it offers so little interpretive scope to the listener, so little scope for that always agile right hand of narrative inferencing. Despite its riddle-like structure, it does not live up to its promise, thus provoking the ‘so what?’ question which Labov suggests deals a death blow to any story. Story 2, on the other hand, also shaped like a riddle, justifies this generic resemblance to a riddle; it challenges the listener to display her cultural ‘membershipping’20 by solving the puzzle in its sequencing (compare story 6 about Algy). As 18For the purposes of this chapter, I take genres to include such categories as jokes, riddles, novels, short stories, fairy tales, etc. Narrative, conversation, poetry, etc., are, in contrast, informally equated with ‘supergenres’, the intuitive idea being that they form umbrellas over the more precisely defined genres. Wittgenstein’s remarks about the difficulties of finding a satisfactory description of the word ‘game’, despite very clear rules about the constitution of particular games like chess or cricket, may be relevant here. 19I am indebted to Michael Toolan (personal communication) for the wonderful phrase ‘advertised uninformativeness’, and also for making explicit two assumptions underlying my formulation of the basic Rules 1–IV on narrative. First, that these rules embedding temporal->causal->informational->evaluative inferences work like generalized Gricean implicature for all narratives. Second, that the processing of the incoming inferences is usually done at the level of propositions. Thus, we mark boundaries, see chunk a as prior to chunk b by ‘filling out’ expressions until they are proposition-like (somewhat like Sperber and Wilson’s ‘thoughts’). In this task, each of us come up with slightly differing expansions. For example, in the tiger story: (There was) a tiger. (There was) a hunter (with the tiger?). (There was) a tiger (only?). On ‘bare’ propositions such as these, temporality, causality, more contextual information and evaluation can be—in most narratives must be—overlaid (given Rules A-D—yielding versions such as: Once there was a tiger in a forest. The tiger was pursued by a hunter, who intended to kill it. Unfortunately for the poor hunter, he got eaten by the tiger instead—end of story. 20Sacks (1972) p. 332, suggests that a ‘membership categorization device’ might resolve some of the difficulties which participants might have in making associations within the conversation. ‘Sex’, for example, is a categorization device with two members (male and female); if a concept does not clearly fit the categories imposed by the categorization device, cultural difficulties could arise. Similarly, riddles may also serve this function, and a listener’s competence be guaged by her ability at manipulating this device so that she arrives at a ‘correct’ or appropiate reponse, mediated, say, by Grice’s Maxim of Manner.
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
233
contended earlier, much needs to be internalized about social values and beliefs (encoded, for instance, in idiom and adages), as well as about the structure of genres, before such a solution can be capably offered. These arguments, deriving from the specific nature of cultural materials, are useful insofar as they enable a critique of some of the universal, and thus essentializing, assumptions of Gricean theory. They show that Grice’s theory of conversational implicature may be deemed inadequate because it does not account for the full expansion of this sort of minimal narrative. It explains, at most, how the additional proposition ‘the tiger ate the hunter’ is computed, but not the additional non-propositional inference of irony which is what gives this story its evaluative ‘point’. Sperber and Wilson’s theory of contextual relevance could be perhaps considered an improvement because it explains in more detail than Grice’s how causal, temporal, inferences may be arrived at by ‘enriching’ the linguistic context of the story with already stored background information etc. But Sperber and Wilson’s cognitivist emphasis is at odds with the fact that the generalization implicated in the telling of the story is a piece of culturally conceived information. By simply stating that it is stored in individual memories, they underemphasize the value of ongoing socially directed reasoning.To assert that every aspect of understanding is ‘in the mind’ is to speak a truism.21 Or to put it differently, Sperber and Wilson’s insistence that the processes of inferencing are similar in the case of both explicatures and implicatures makes them miss the qualitative distinction between the propositional inference, ‘the tiger ate the hunter’, which all competent hearer in all cultures would derive (if they understood the meanings of the words in the story, were following Grice’s cooperative principle, and had access to the rules of narrative inferencing postulated by me), and the non-propositional inference22 that 21See Mey and Talbot’s review of Relevance for an extended critique along these lines.
These pragmaticists point out that Sperber and Wilson’s references to real-world contexts are noticeably stilted. Despite gestures in the direction of contextualization, they seem to prefer their own constructed examples, drawn from a narrow cultural base. Hence, the extent to which Sperber and Wilson would admit the influence of social factors on judgements about plausible inferences remains unclear. For instance, although we may ‘know’ that in the real world people, especially kings and queens (!), don’t exactly keel over and die of grief on the death of spouses, our cultural acquaintance with narrative fictionalization still promotes the ‘grief ’ inference over the ‘intrigue’ or ‘disease’ inferences in the first Forsterian story that I analysed. Few, if any, of the utterances discussed by Sperber and Wilson, are ‘enriched’, even to this degree of complexity, making it difficult to assess how their theory would be extended in such cases. 22‘Perlocutionary effects’ , we recall, are by-products of illocutionary acts, in Austinian speech act theory. Frightening, amusing, amazing, provoking, etc., are perlocutionary effects, which may fall out as a consequence of illocutionary performatives such as
234
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
the story is funny because it belongs to the ironic ‘biter-bit’ mode, which inference can only be made if a hearer/reader has a particular set of cultural expectations to fall back on. Presumably, a hearer who did not have societal knowledge of the ‘biter-bit’ type of stories would still make the first Gricean inference, but fail to see the point of the story because she could not take that culturally-given step towards the crucial evaluative inference that would complete the story and enable her to understand its narrative tension Cultural norms of interpretation—which I refer to as Impliculture, as distinct from Implicature—thus seem not merely useful, but indispensable, during the process of narrative inferencing. For example, the mystery at the heart of Story 5 (PI PU, PHI SHU) remains impenetrable to readers from another culture, even in translation, until a Bengali speaker guides the English (or Turkish or Nuer) towards a satisfactory interpretation. But I will let the mystery stand since its very presence illustrates the importance of social factors in satisfactory narrative inferencing.23 From the Short, Short Story to the Tall, Tall Tale If we turn to the genre of the tall story now, a similar trend manifests itself. As Bauman,24 in his examination of the tall stories of coon-hunting from the American Midwest has shown, any assessment of a tall claim within a subculture, such as that of the coon-hunters, depends on a thorough knowledge of the conversational display rituals of this group. An outsider may not, with equal confidence, be able to decide which facts are ‘tall’ and which are perfectly plausible. Specialized in-group knowledge thus becomes essential to inferencing in this genre of the tall story. In my view, Bauman’s analysis of the ‘coon’ tall story is characterized by the following features: a) moral community ‘issue[s] of truthfulness and lying’ are addressed via the ‘tall’ tale. warnings, statements, promises and so on. However, there are difficulties with assimilating perlocutions to propositions, and assigning them propositional status, so that they can function as Gricean implicatures. This constitutes a genuine problem area in the inferential theory of narrative that I am proposing, since stories are verbal bundles especially rich in perlocutionary effect(s). 23Examples like this demonstrate almost perfectly the limits/limitations of translation, mired in conventions of spelling, pronunciation and, above all, cultural reception. While I would be more than happy to provide a longer gloss on the PI PU, PHI SHU Bengali story for any curious reader, there is little doubt in my mind that this procedure would almost certainly diminish the narrative text in question! 24Bauman, 1986. See Bibliography.
R AT I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E V A N C E
235
b) the tall tale ‘play[s] upon ... another genre of story which is ubiquitous among hound-dog men: narratives of personal experience about the special quality and hunting prowess of particular dogs. ... The more common story of personal experience, told straightforwardly as truth contextualizes the tall tale, it contributes to the latter’s humorous effect by establishing a set of generic expectations that the tall tale can bend exaggeratedly out of shape. ... Thus tall tales are lies, insofar as what they report as having happened either did not happen or could not have happened’ [italics mine]. c) tall tales are often told in the third person, but when they are told in the first person, moving closer to generic narratives of personal experience, the teller is understood to be not simply a humorous liar but a fabricator, a ‘con man’. d) the ‘creative exaggeration’ in the tall tale is an ‘instrument for identity building, for self-aggrandizement ... a means of enhancing one’s own image ... a tendency towards‘stretching the truth’ that has been widely reported in men’s sociable encounters’ [italics mine]. e) tall tales are often marked by formulaic iterative devices and a punchline, which indicate the culmination of events. f) the ‘expressive lying’ in the coon-hunting tall tales place them in an American folk tradition ‘in unbroken continuity with the generations of hunters, traders, and storytellers’ making the tales a ‘richly textured arena for the ethnographic investigation of, ... the negotiation of truthfulness and lying as action and evaluation in the conduct of social life’ [italics mine]. g) in narratives of personal experience attempts at ‘validation’ , stressing the plausibility of the narrative, are frequent, but in the tall tale these validating moves could be subverted or discarded, since here ‘lying is overwhelmingly licensed as part of the fundamental ethos of sociability ... to call another man a liar in this context, then, is to threaten his “face”, with some risk and no possible advantage to oneself; whereas to give apparent acceptance to his accounts is to store-up interactional credit towards the unchallenged acceptance of one’s own tales’ [italics mine]. In effect, Bauman pleads for a contextualized interpretation of the tall tale that sees it in relation to the cultural tradition within which it was generated. He stresses the interactional payoffs of this genre in an allmale, macho atmosphere where the tall tale becomes a variety of performance, and hence ‘lying’ gains social sanction. Speaking of performativity, the use of the tall tale at a pivotal moment in a recent popular film on the American Midwest, entitled Fried Green
236
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
Tomatoes (John Avnet, 1992), illustrates well a point I have stressed before. The ‘good’ story, I have argued, is distinguished by the fact that it travels through social space, passing from person to person as a durable bundle of perlocutionary effects binding the community together. Thus a tall story, embedded in the frame of another story, functions very much like the prototypical cognitive structure designed to convert ‘talk into text’, that I’ve suggested narrative is. It works as a metaphor of survival. To ask for a tall story in the face of imminent death constitutes an act of psychological self-preservation. Fried Green Tomatoes is a story told in flashback of the friendship between two feisty young women, Ruth and Idgie, who run a restaurant in remote Whistlestop, Alabama. During the course of the film, Ruth is stricken with cancer. An ominous clock ticks away in the dark interiors of the house, as the dying Ruth turns away a pastor and instead requests a story from Idgie—a tall story. Even the unconventional Idgie is embarrassed at the thought of delivering a tall story—virtually a lie, as Bauman points out—as a form of final absolution, but her love and grief overcome her inhibitions. And this is the story she tells: There was once a lake across from Ruth’s house. One day a gaggle of geese alighted on it just as the wintry lake was freezing over. When the geese then flew across to the neighbouring state of Georgia, they carried the lake with them, frozen on their webbed feet. Now, Georgia has that lake.
As the tale ends, Ruth passes on peacefully. Fiction, the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick asserts, thus reassures us, even as it lies or deludes. By making other worlds ‘real’—excitingly and dramatically real—stories persuade us that all may not be lost. In this case, the tall story Idgie tells Ruth certainly mirrors the sociological theme of rivalry between the Midwest states of Alabama and Georgia that is a constant leit-motif in the film, but it achieves more than this simple conversion of real life into reel life. It guarantees itself an ultimate relevance, in Sperber and Wilson’s terminology. Or, one could say that it transforms itself into a form of the Dennett/Dawkins meme—part of a cultural gene-pool. In keeping with the narrative paradigm of the Indian Rope Trick, it manages this by suggesting that dying and pain could themselves be illusions that can be substituted by other more entrancing illusions. Like the geese who fly off with a fictional lake as an icy, shimmering attachment, the essential ‘self’ is freed in a narrative universe; it can wander eternally where it pleases, and thus defy the ‘reality’ of death. One recalls here Virginia Woolf’s phrase about the ‘varied and wandering’ nature of self. If the self is itself an illusion, then a condemnation
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
237
of tall stories, or indeed any form of fiction, seems pointless. The human species as a whole may be said to answer the dread Labovian question—What’s the point of this story?—by making stories central to their being. That, at any rate, is Dennett’s idea. We spend our lives unifying our frangible selves through the cognitive activity of story-telling because constructing the illusion of a self is what we are born to do. From this anti-foundationalist perspective, then, an individual self is ‘really’ just a congeries of story. My own further suggestion in this chapter has been that such a notion of the self as a centre of narrative gravity can be further connected to Dennett and Dawkins’ other suggestion about humans as meme-generators. Since memes are culturally transmitted, narratives make ideal receptacles and/or formats for the transfer of durable memes, such as, for instance, the riddle-like short stories and tall tales examined in this chapter. Apart from their common susceptibility to cultural conditioning (implicultural constraints) are there, however, any other links between the tall tale and the minimal narrative? How are they both analytically (ob)served in terms of my grammar of narrative inferencing? And in what ways are those general issues of meme-formation, narrative coherence, iteration, tension, plausibility, chronology, causality, and relevance illuminated by this kind of data, or addressed in this sort of model? These complex questions are tackled in the penultimate and final sections of this chapter. Narrrative Fragility A possible route towards arriving at an integrated view of narrative discourse, which consists of so many sub-genres, only two of which find a place here, is via Sacks’ notion of ‘the fragility of stories’.25 Only briefly mentioned here, this notion is analysed in much greater detail in the next chapter. Stories are fragile, according to Sacks, to the extent that listeners can question their veracity and tellability. The first strategy enables listeners to arraign the implausibility of the narrative, the second strategy allows listeners to be critical of the boring qualities of the tale, its unexciting ordinariness. A psychological onus is thus automatically placed on all narrative tellers. In their production of a series of narrative clauses, it is incumbent upon tellers to ‘protect’ fragile aspects of their stories by ensuring that listeners do not make such causal, informational or evaluative inferences 25Lecture Notes, Fall 1971 (Sacks, ms. 1967–72).
238
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
as will lead them to conclude that the story offered is ‘fragile’, either on account of its implausibility or its ordinariness. Tellers accomplish such ‘protection’ in a variety of ways: i) by citing witnesses who have seen the events described or can reliably vouch for them ii) by including everyday details to contextualize extraordinary, and therefore implausible, tales iii) by including historical and social facts within their story which ‘everyone knows’, thereby making the rest of the story more ‘real’ iv) by prefacing their stories as Labovian ‘tellables’ v) by making tellables into ‘something for us’ through conventions such as ‘local occasioning’ described in Chapter 6 vi) by inviting listeners to actively join in the construction of the story vii) by telling a ‘third-person’ story as a ‘first-person’ narrative of personal experience, or vice-versa viii) by making a story so short that a listener has no opportunity to question its details, especially as she must busy herself filling in all the missing inferential details ix) by building a story round an embedded cultural generalization x) by frankly admitting the ‘falseness’ of the story, or making obvious its fictionality xi) by using iterative structures to reinforce the causal patterns and evaluative aspects of the story xii) by explicitly ‘leading’ the listener with tags like ‘as you know’, ‘don’t you think’, ‘that’s right’, etc. I offer this list of strategies for the protection of fragile narratives as a means of focusing on the complex interactive understanding—Gricean cooperation—achieved between teller and listener during the unfolding of a story. What inferential spaces does the teller make for the listener, and how does the listener take maximum advantage of these spaces? The extent to which these protective strategies, which Bauman calls ‘validation strategies’, can be culturally identified, and the facility with which tellers use them, afford a means of answering this question. The narrative inferences of temporality, causality, information, and evaluation, could crucially depend on how a community attends to the protection of its narratives. For example, manner of telling—attention to pauses, gaze, voice quality, register, medium, and so forth—would importantly focus and constrain the valid implicultural inferences a listener can make. Different genres—personal narratives, tall stories, disaster accounts,
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
239
riddles—would also be likely to attract different types of validation in given social contexts, being ‘fragile’ in diverse ways. Conversely, it might be possible to identify a range of similarities between superficially differing genres such as the short, short story and tall, tall tale. Since both types of story are fragile on account of their implausibility, departing as they do from the ‘generic expectations’ of truthfulness in the parallel ‘narrative of personal experience’, both arguably employ implicultural validations of a similar sort. First, both are typically told in the third person, so that the teller does not take personal, ‘moral’ responsibilty for the truth of the events he relates. Second, both are laconically told, leaving large inferential gaps, where the burden falls heavily on the teller to interpret the causal, informational and evaluative connections between the events narrated. In this way the listener becomes ‘an accessory after the fact’. She is implicated—or impliculturated—in the actual construction of the tale. Third, both make use of formal patterns of iteration (repeated phrases, e.g., a tiger; repeated syntactic patterns, or NP, NP, NP; repeated stresses, exclamatives, and even phonological repetitions—Anne Donne, John Donne, Undone). This last strategy underlines the fact that these stories have a formulaic, literary, performative orientation that relieves them from the burden of a pedestrian truthfulness. Fourth, both make use of the listener’s knowledge of cultural generalizations, and generic expectations, which structure their inferences and give ‘point’ to the narration—a strategy that may also be viewed as a special case of validating stories via social witness. Fifth, both are generally fashioned as frankly exaggerated narratives of counterfactual humour and/or ironic wit, which by their flagrant flouting of the usually prolix development of narrative, and the expectations of truthfulness in conversation, hold a heightened interest. Sixth, both offer a challenge to the listener because they unfold enigmatically, sustaining narrative tension until the very end, usually marked by a punchline. More generally, while the tall tale violates Grice’s Maxim of Quality advising truthful and the minimal narrative violates his Maxim of Quantity enjoining adequate informativeness, both deliberately subvert principles of communication, immediately setting in train processes of inferencing. It will be recalled that the Gricean Supermaxim for Narrative that I suggested in Chapter 4 is couched as the following injunction: ALWAYS PROTECT THE FRAGILITY OF YOUR NARRATIVES BECAUSE YOU ARE THEREBY PROTECTING YOUR VULNERABLE ‘SELF’. Following this imperative, any narrative can be graded by listeners along a cline of
240
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
fragility, ranging from the weakest narrative (most implausible and boring) to the strongest, most riveting narratives (neither implausible nor boring). In my ‘inferential’ grammar of narrative, it is possible to relate this cline of ‘fragility’ with the ‘degrees’ of inference postulated by the story-grammarians. These run from first order (least constrained) to fourth order (most constrained). Can these two gradations, then, be matched up? NARRATIVE FRAGILITY
INFERENTIAL CONSTRAINTS
Weakest Story: Boring and implausible Next Weakest: Boring but not implausible
4th Order Inferences: Duplicate information, overdetermined and unimportant 2nd Order Inferences: Relevant and determined, important to the progress of the story 3rd Order Inferences: Irrelevant, determined but not logically important 1st Order Inferences: Elaborative, underdetermined by the text of the story.
Somewhat Stronger: Implausible but not boring Strongest Story: Neither implausible nor boring
My speculative hunch is that, presented with a very weak story, overdetermined or too clearly explicated, listeners simply ‘shut off’, not bothering to make any effort; in other words, ‘lazy’ 4th order inferences are all they are willing to make. If a story is boring but credible, listeners put in some processing effort, but this effort is likely to be erratic, corresponding to 2nd order inferencing. Stories like Bauman’s ‘coon’ tale, exciting but highly implausible, require listeners to invest a great deal of cognitive effort; owing to the contextual expressiveness of the narrative, they produce quite ‘good’ 3rd order narratives. Elaborative, sustained readings, involving complex evaluative and informational inferences—implicultural reasoning—is the domain of 1st order inferences. Great literary masterpieces belong to this category. In Chapter 6, which presents illustrations of Sacks’ ethnomethodological concept of ‘narrative fragility’, I quote the novelist Margaret Drabble on why a story can fail because it is ‘too interesting to be interesting’. The teller gives away too much; in terms of my extension, Searle’s Principle of Expressibility, the explication by the teller is overdone, leaving nothing to the imagination of the hearer. It follows that if, for example, 1st order inferences dominate in a story, there is little for the right-hand arm of my narrative grammar to do, the truth maxim and conventions of narrativity are over-worked and memes are in short supply. A teller’s limitations as
In early storygrammars, these would mainly comprise the type: logical inference.
2nd Order → Inferences.
1st Order → Inferences:
STORY-GRAMMARS: DEGREES & TYPES OF INFERENCE
Over explicit →
Over-explicated
→
SEARLE’S PRINCIPLE EXPRESSIBILITY
The Quantity → Maxim for Narrative says: Be summary and explicit!
The Truth → or Quality Maxim for Narrative says:. Be plausible. Explicate!
GRICEAN MAXIMS EXTENDED TO STORY-TELLING
Provide abstracts, → or proverbial or didactic generalizations as needed, so that people ‘get the point’ of your story.
Provide orientations, → engage in being culturally ordinary, membershipped; make your stories ‘something for us.’
LEWISIAN CONVENTIONS EXTENDED TO NARRATIVE
Quantum of memes → somewhat increased. More implicultural— inferences required. The ‘bird’ story above as well as ordinary neighbourly exchanges would exemplify this category of story.
Relatively few memes → and correspondingly an attenuated sense of a Dennettian ‘self ’. Limited scope for implicultural exchanges of subjectivity. See Drabble’s story in Chapter 6 for this sort of narrative.
DAWKINS’ MEMES AND DENNETT’S NARRATIVE GRAVITY
(contd...)
Given no evidence to the contrary, treat all ‘and then’ conjuncts as causal, thus making plotoriented narrative connections.
Given no evidence to the contrary, treat all conjunctions with ‘and’ as ‘and then’ conjunctions, thus privileging temporality.
NAIR’S INFERENTIAL GRAMMAR OF NARRATIVE
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
241
In early storygrammar, these would mainly comprise the type: evaluative inference.
4th Order → Inferences
Super → Expressive
Over exciting →
3rd Order → Inference
In early storygrammars, these would mainly comprise the type: informational. inference.
SEARLE’S PRINCIPLE EXPRESSIBILITY
STORY-GRAMMARS: DEGREES & TYPES OF INFERENCE
The Manner → Maxim for Narrative says: Be expressive and Be memeconscious
The Relevance → Maxim for Narrative says: Be interesting and exciting!
GRICEAN MAXIMS EXTENDED TO STORY-TELLING
Produce culturally → appropriate stories, and attempt to use ‘literary’ and rhetorical skills at irony, metaphor etc. as self-reflexively as required for the purposes of the communicative exchange in progress.
Locally occasion → your stories; produce tellables, and include story-internal evaluations; encourage listener participation in turn-taking.
LEWISIAN CONVENTIONS EXTENDED TO NARRATIVE
Most meme-studded → narrative. Rich in possibilities for implicultural inferences. This sort of narrative is best suited to express the ‘self’ and welladapted to social survival and transfer. The Odyssey the Ramayana, and/or a modern classic would belong to this class.
Vastly improved → opportunities for meme creation, storage and transmission. These stories are told, repeated and appreciated by socially self-confident individuals who enjoy playing the implicultural game.
DAWKINS’ MEMES AND DENNETT’S NARRATIVE GRAVITY
Given no evidence to the contrary, go from an informational inference to an evaluative one and try to arrive at a strong evaluation to coincide with the end of the story.
Given no evidence to the contrary, ensure that all causal connectives are supported by realworld inferences that render the narrative culturally indexed and engaging.
NAIR’S INFERENTIAL GRAMMAR OF NARRATIVE
(contd...)
242 N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
243
a social agent would thus show up in such a narrative, with the eventual repercussion that bad listening strategies are followed by hearers. Likewise, a story can be unduly explicit, immoderately exciting, or unnecessarily expressive. To summarize, then, the complex set of relationships between the theories I’ve made use of so far in my analysis of narrativity: Even a cursory glance at the chart linking various perspective on narrative confirms one thesis. Not only do we seem to be narrative-extruding pastamachines in the Dennettian mould, but we appear to be incorrigible inference-making machines. My own argument in this connection has been that narrative studies sorely require a Theory of Impliculture to supplement, if not supplant, the existing scaffold of the Theory of Implicature developed by Grice. Our competence as ‘narrative speakerhearers’, as well as ‘native speaker-hearers’, is attested by the ingenuity and cultural skill with which we decode story inferences. Merely labelling narrative nodes as settings, complicating actions, resolutions, etc., although effective as description of many narratives, does not explain how we arrived at our schematic labelling in the first place. Such a post hoc method of enquiry leads inevitably to a conceptualization of narrative as inert product rather than vital process. Since it is widely realized that listeners continuously form and reject hypotheses about the coherence of a story as it is being told, not afterwards, it is this sort of ongoing competence-inperformance that must be accounted for by narratologists. Psycholinguistic models of narrative did indeed recognize that the schema they proposed had to be supported by some inferencing mechanism incorporating the types and orders of narrative implicatures that they postulated. However, they did not take the crucial theoretical step towards making inferences of temporality, causality and evaluation the pivots of narrative. This is the move that has been attempted, if not fully accomplished, in this chapter. Recursive inferences, on this view, are to be regarded not as the incidental by-products of a narrative system, but as constitutive of the system itself. In my final section below, I ask why recursion and its cousin, repetition, is such an important element in reasoning. Iteration and Narrative Tension Repetition plays an incalculable part in the inference-making process, as well as in structuring narrative. As we have observed in this chapter, iteration seems to be a feature of even the most minimal of narratives. The puzzle posed by the phenomenon of iteration is simple: since
244
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
repetition presents redundant information, why repeat? Why waste cognitive effort, both in producing and decoding information presented for a second or third time? Why violate the Gricean Maxim of Quantity? What is implied by the fact that, despite its apparent redundancy, iteration is ubiquitous in our speech, and occurs all over the place in our most sophisticated literary productions? Grice set the ball rolling by remaking that literary effects such as irony, metaphor, hyperbole and understatement, could perhaps be explained, not so much by the Quantity Maxim, as by the Quality or Truth Maxim, since all these tropes make some sort of ‘false’ statement. He then added in a further note that ‘irony is intimately connected with the expression of a feeling, attitude or evaluation.’26 Taking yet another leaf out of the Gricean book, Sperber and Wilson then redo irony, metaphor, etc., in terms of their own preferred principle of relevance. These forms, they suggest, form a continuum with ordinary linguistic usage rather than a special ‘literary class’ distinguished by some sort of maxim violation. Like any other form of words, irony for Sperber and Wilson typically involves three factors: cultural reference, an attitudinal stance—and repetition. In their own words, ‘standards or rules of behaviour are culturally defined, commonly known and frequently invoked; they are thus always available for echoic mention.’ ‘Echoic mention’ is, of course, Sperber and Wilson’s own term for repetition. This is how Sperber and Wilson explain their position: We would like to show that irony and a lot of related tropes (eg., meiosis, litotes,) fall together within a range of cases that would not normally be regarded as figurative at all. What unites these cases is the fact that the thought of the speaker... is an interpretation of a thought of someone other than the speaker (or of the speaker in the past). When interpretations achieve relevance in this way we will say they are echoic . ... From the pragmatic point of view, what is important is that a speaker can use an echoic utterance to convey a whole range of attitudes and emotions, ranging from outright acceptance and approval to outright rejection and disapproval, and that the recognition of these attitudes and emotions may be crucial to the interpretation process.27
Immediate problems arise with this explanation of echoic effects. For one thing, there are far too many counterexamples to the theory that repetition works as irony, metaphor and so forth because ‘the thought of the speaker ... is an interpretation of a thought of someone other than the speaker (or of the speaker in the past).’ Consider, for instance, 26Grice, 1990, p. 53. 27Sperber and Wilson, 1992, pp. 237–240.
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
245
Conrad’s famous exclamation in The Heart of Darkness: ‘the horror, the horror’, or somebody exclaiming after a winning a race, ‘I did it, I did it!’, or a person saying ‘Ha, ha!’ because he is sceptical of the claims being made by someone, or even a stammerer repeating phrases without intending to. These are all cases where the iteration does not require us to interpret the present utterance with reference to a previous occasion or another speaker. They are text-internal and refer to the present circumstances of the utterance alone. Indeed, I would maintain that most instances of repetition do not need us to go through the complicated set of manouevres that Sperber and Wilson advise. On the contrary, repetition forces us to reconsider first mention within the text rather than outside it. It thus calls for structure–internal reorganization of the conversation or ‘story’ as we have interpreted it so far, as well as, maybe, a contextual search. Sperber and Wilson go on to remark that ‘a speaker can use an echoic utterance to convey a whole range of attitudes and emotions’. They are right about this, of course, but such an obvious statement gives us no clue as to how we may distinguish irony as repetition from, for instance, metaphor or litotes as repetition. I would suggest that there are marked and unmarked cases of repetition, the distinction between these being culturally learnt, and requiring implicultural skills. Formally, we must recognize that all repetitions resemble 4th order inferences, which simply duplicate information already presented; as such, they are overdetermined and redundant. Yet many of the world languages have discovered grammatical advantages to reduplication; for example, they can be used to convey plurality (Malay), habitual action (Bengali), or continuous aspect (Hindi). These would, like an individual’s stammer, constitute unmarked repetition. Marked instances of repetition would occur most predictably in forms like narrative, which are culturally as well as cognitively designed to turn forgettable talk into memorable text. Repetition basically says ‘Look again! You may have missed something!’ It is a call to the listener to attend more closely and at once to the inferencemaking process. As such, the job it does within a text or a conversation is to force the inference-making process; it tugs at the listener or reader’s mental sleeve. For example, when in this chapter I refer to the ‘short, short story’, the repetition intensifies and draws attention to the very minimal narratives I present, but the phrase the ‘tall, tall tale’ has a different function; here the adjective is used for reasons of sheer alliterative balance, wordplay, and textuality are foregrounded, marked. By creating patterns within the text, repetition thus stimulates the
246
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
process of pattern-recognition—an activity the human brain is good at, and take great delight in. E.M. Forster in Aspects of the Novel commented long ago on these motifs which occur like fugues in a narrative, giving it unity and coherence. Different literary genres use repetition in different ways to highlight their own raison d’être. A detective story might use repetition as a red herring to mislead readers about the ‘true’ identity of a murderer, for example, while a romance may associate a certain metaphor, say a white shawl, with a heroine. This is what gives repetition its complexity and power as a literary device, or in the vocabulary of story-grammars, its potential as evaluation. To return to the special case of irony at this point. Both dramatic irony and everyday irony are distinguished by a process Aristotle called ‘reversal’, which could be characterized as a special case of repetition. Here, circumstances turn out exactly opposed to an expected pattern, as in Oedipus Rex, and words turn out to have a double entendre, a contrary meaning. Now, in a narrative, there are two basic reasons why speakers might want to indicate the opposite of what is said. First, as I’ve argued, it allows listeners much greater scope for interpretive play. By deliberately complicating the conversational situation, tellers heighten the interactional stakes. Talk is thereby turned into text—a possible meme structure that can subsequently be passed on by listeners as a joke, a witticism, a story, or some other ‘tellable’. The second reason is related to the first. Structures like narrative, I have suggested, take a certain pleasure in perverseness, in imaginatively reconstituting our workaday world. By doing so, they momentarily ‘challenge’ logic and enable both tellers and listeners, for a fragment of time, to hold contradictory beliefs in mind, to be ‘in two minds’ as it were. It is this capacity to evoke the thrill of the ‘in two minds’ cognitive state that the device of repetition, so common in stories, shares with narrative as a structure. To repeat, then. Acknowledged as a universal supergenre of discourse, narrativity has invited many attempts at description. Almost all these classifications have concentrated on tellable or culturally meme-studded varieties of narrative. Stories have been labelled as either fictional or factual (Searle 1975 ; Adams 1985), casually conversational or carefully rehearsed as ‘performances’ (Bauman 1986; Maclean 1988), oral or written (Tannen 1984, Street 1984), fragile or durable, plausible or boring (Sacks 1967–72, Bhaya Nair 1982) , tellable or ordinary (Labov 1972, Pratt 1975); authorless or authoritative (Dennett, 1991, Miller 1992). Narrative Gravity tries to take as many as possible of these multifarious distinctions into account in presenting its listener-oriented view of narrative
R A T I O N A L I T Y A N D R E L E VA N C E
247
structure as applied to two of the simplest subgenres of narrative—the tall tale and minimal narrative. Inferential moves—evaluation implicated in informational sequences, information indicated in causal sequences, causal sequences following from temporal assumptions, and then recursively, informational sequences generating causal ones, etc.—are vital to a narrative grammar. Degree of inference may also, as we have seen, be systematically related to the perceived fragility of stories. Grice’s theory, as well as Sperber and Wilson’s more detailed, contemporary and cognitivist version of it are important here for the links I make between the classical Gricean notion of deductive implicatures and my own ideas about impliculture as an inductive mode of inferencing. The minimal narrative and the tall tale, in particular, are genres which require a great deal inferencing on the part of the listener. Hence they offer an ideal body of data against which to test an inferential theory of narrative. Moreover, much of the knowledge they presuppose is culturespecific, so that the claim that an inferential model is predisposed towards the incorporation of socio-cultural context is also put to test by such data. Evaluative inferences in particular are influenced by cultural norms, without reference to which the point of many such stories might simply be lost.28 Narrative structure can be seen as the outcome of strategies of validation, or story-protection by tellers, combining with types and orders of inferencing by listeners to yield a completed object, as well a complete subjectivity. By making repeated temporal, causal, informational and evaluative inferences, listeners endow a raw narrative with coherence, as well as resolve textual mysteries and inconsistencies. Getting to know oneself, as the graffiti on the wall says, is the beginning of a life-long love affair. Self constantly meets and merges with others in this iterative narrative dance. A ‘good’ story is one where the listener is so completely hooked that he completely identifies with the imaginary characters and imaginary worlds that the teller conjures up. This is when memes are best transferred—and the Indian Rope Trick successfully completed. The attraction of an inferential model lies in its attempt to mimic precisely this flexibility which tellers, listeners and analysts display in their meme-sensitive interpretations of narrative. It allows for changeable hypotheses about the genre and ‘point’ of a particular narrative, and yet it presents/represents a systematic hierarchy consisting 28Labov (1972) has listed and explicated such evaluative devices at considerable length in this samples of New York Black English Vernacular [BEV].
248
N A R R AT I V E G R AV I T Y
of major nodes which consistently govern the expectations of listeners. A substantial part of my motivation in proposing such a model, not in isolation, but in conjunction with specific data, in fact, has been to show that accounts of narrative structure must be able to incorporate cultural intuitions about the relevance of narrative in context. In his essay on the tall tale, Bauman states that these narratives ... do not fall into clear-cut categories of factual and fictional, truthful and lying, believable and incredible, but rather interweave in a complex contextual web that leaves these issues constantly in doubt.29
The image of narrative projected herein is that even the most minimal of stories can be analysed with maximal complexity, given a theoretical approach that values inferential enrichment over interpretive economy, and partial indeterminacy over absolute predictability.
29Bauman, 1986, p. 32.
T U R N S A T TA L K
249
6
qQ T U R N S AT TA L K Ethnomethodological Analysis of Narrative
‘The time has come’, the Walrus said, ‘To talk of many things: Of shoes—and ships—and sealing-wax Of cabbages—and kings— And why the sea is boiling hot and whether pigs have wings’ ‘Tut, tut, child’ said the Duchess. ‘Everything’s got a moral, if only you can find it.’ Lewis Carroll, Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland and Through the Looking Glass If the story-tellers could ha’ got decency and good morals from true stories, who’d have troubled to invent parables? Thomas Hardy, Under the Greenwood Tree
Any study of story-telling, Hillis Miller has claimed, must respond to three questions. Why do we need stories at all? Why do we need the same story over and over? Why do we always need more stories? Miller’s answers to these questions are attractively brief. The first is tackled by saying that stories appeal to our innate sense of order and rhythm, and also ‘police’ our culture by telling us how we may ‘become more like our neighbours’. Stories prescribe cultural norms, while allowing space for a ‘relatively safe’ critique of the culture within which these norms operate. The second answer then reiterates the arguments of the first. We need order, and we need to read order into the meanderings of fiction— as structuralist work on narrative has decisively shown. Repeating basic
250
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
themes and metaphors via narrative is therefore ‘perhaps the most powerful of ways to assert the basic ideology of our culture’. But it is Miller’s third query that fetches the most interesting reaction. It could be that we always need stories because in some way they do not satisfy. ... Each story and each repetition or variation of it leaves some uncertainty or contains some loose-end unravelling its effect, according to some law that is not so much psychological or social as linguistic. This necessary incompletion means that no story fulfils perfectly, once and for all, its functions of ordering and confirming. And so we need another story, and then another and yet another, without ever coming to the end of our need for stories, or ever assuaging the hunger they are meant to satisfy.1
Miller admits that the third is the most difficult of his questions and examines a number of literary examples to demonstrate their ‘essential incompleteness’. This chapter seeks to connect my own interest in mundane non-literary stories with Miller’s analysis of culturally famous, highly regarded texts.2 Its aim is to provide the sort of ‘linguistic’ explanation of a story’s intrinsic incompleteness that Miller seems to want. This incompleteness derives from three sorts of physicality. Stories are indeed food—as Miller implies—for what Dennett has called the ‘epistemic hunger’ of our species. This metaphor of ‘hunger’ however appears incompatible with the notion of ‘perfect fulfillment’. Just as we cannot be ever satisfied with a single meal, or even multiple ones, even if they are absolute gourmet delights, but have to keep eating at regular intervals all our lives, so we cannot ever be fulfilled by binges of narrative activity. As a species, we are not meant to suffer from narrative bulimia, although some of us do. In the course of our everyday existence most of us are condemned to a lifetime of fulfilling our appetite for stories. As long as we have a ‘self’ to sustain and do not move into Alzheimer’s or other similar selfdeleting conditions, our ‘selfhood’ is sustained by narrative. It is in this context that the Millerian demand for ‘morals’ from our stories—those precepts by which we may ‘live’—seems explicable. Morals in a narrative are the mental equivalent of the nutritional value of a meal. Hence, the ideological task of narrative that Miller refers to cannot be over until a culture becomes quite moribund, because sustaining vital levels of 1Miller, in Lentricchia and McLaughlin, 1990, p. 72. 2Although some of the research in Narrative Gravity was first undertaken in the
nineteen eighties, I should note that the three basic questions asked by Miller in 1990 were anticipated to an extent in my thesis of 1982, partly because one could not avoid this sort of ‘naïve’ enquiry in that proto-era of narrative studies.
T U R N S A T TA L K
251
narrative interaction are the main means by which a culture made up of story-telling individuals renews itself. Or to change our metaphor slightly, we always need more stories just as, crudely speaking, we always need more babies each generation in any society if it is not to die out. Furthermore, that structural ‘open-endedness’ of all face-to-face talk, which forms the background, and often the ground, of most narrative interaction, seem designed to allow, indeed encourage, us to routinely fill our narrative stomachs—or make more babies, whichever analogy is preferable. Conversation, I had said in my Introduction, is somewhat like sex. It is an interlocking device for self-perpetuation. This structural openness—the potentially infinite ABABAB chain of conversation which any two people can open up at any time to exchange their stories—is the primary subject of this chapter. As for hunger and the life-sustaining properties of those materials we classify as ‘food for thought’, the alternating rhythm of the conversation-machine could be likened to the jaws of a perpetually famished shark—forever moving in an openshut-open-shut movement, always ready to take in more feed—‘shoes and ships and sealing wax, cabbages and kings’. There is no end to our appetite for talk, indeed there can be no end, structurally speaking. Talking into Tape-recorders Ethnomethodology was the soul-child of the America of the sixties and bears all the distinguishing marks of that era. Greatly influenced by the work of Erving Goffman and Harold Garfinkel, it turned the gaze, the ‘oyster eye’, of American sociology, inward upon the ‘self’ of ordinary Americans. By concentrating on the manner in which America, and especially California, organized its everyday life in shops, in neighbourhoods, in psychiatric clinics and in beauty parlours, the American ethnomethodologists hoped to learn more about ‘structures of social action’.3 A quick look at, let’s say, a dozen keywords in the ethnomethodological lexicon which might be of some help here. Twelve conceptuallyloaded terms in conversational analysis, an offshoot of ethnomethology, are ‘negotiation’, ‘participant’, ‘ratification’, ‘turn-taking mechanism’, ‘preference organization’, ‘repair’, ‘sequencing’, ‘pairs’, ‘trouble’, ‘strategy’, ‘observable’, and ‘transcription’. So, we could set up the ethnomethodological scenario like this. In most conversational situations, participants negotiate with each 3This is the title of a book on ethnomethodology, edited by J. Maxwell Atkinson and
John Heritage, 1984.
252
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
other, tell their troubles, and ratify, or not, as the case may be, previous turns at talk. The analyst’s task is to transcribe in minute detail a conversational fragment from which she can retrieve observables within the turn-taking mechanism. From these she can build up a theoretical picture of the strategies participants use to repair those turns at talk that they consider faulty. She can also study the preference organization of sequencing patterns characteristic of conversational pairs such as complimenting and thanking, questioning and answering, greeting and greeting, riddling and responding, offering and accepting. From their research, conversational analysts related this ‘local’ tendency towards sequencing in set pairs to the ‘over-arching’ pairing established in the abstract by the ABABAB structure of conversation itself. Conversation, as the conversational analysts saw it, was in this sense primarily a ‘machine’ with given structural properties which had to be skillfully ‘manipulated’ to solve participants’ problems or ‘troubles’, and help them achieve communicative goals. Depending on their managerial aptitude, some did much better than others at ‘using the system’ of conversation to get what they wanted. There is an obvious analogy here with my metaphor of human beings as communicating cogs in the factory of culture, turning out all sorts of memes to serve our ‘illusions’ of selfhood. Three implications of the conversational analytic perspective should be spelt out at this stage. First, the ethnomethodologists insisted that they came to their data with few preconceived notions about conversational structure. They simply pointed out ‘observables’ that were there. But how did they know what was ‘there’ in a conversation, and what wasn’t? Simple, said the ethnomethodologists, we can point out —or ostensively define as Sperber and Wilson might put it—the conversational feature to which we refer on a tape. And here we come to a truly interesting aspect of the ethnomethodologists’ contribution to an understanding of conversational structure. It offers a striking illustration of the manner in which a method as well as an ideology of analysis can be founded on a new technology. Not only do the human species constitute inferential machines themselves, but they also perceive themselves anew through the machines they invent. Cassette tape recorders in the sixties changed the way in which one could observe a conversation; it was no longer necessary to rely on individual or collective memory in order to reconstruct what had been said. Now every conversation could be replayed exactly as many times as necessary for analytic procedure. In a way, what the ‘ordinary’ tapes of the ethnomethodologists then revealed was to my mind almost as
T U R N S A T TA L K
253
theoretically shocking as Watergate was socially scandalous. For, the conversational analysts’ reams of tape showed the following—that precisely those parts of a speaker’s ‘turn at talk’ that we had naively imagined were dispensable are, in fact, crucial to sustaining its structure and momentum. The pauses, the ums and ers, wells and you knows, the lapses into silence, reformulations of utterances and the overlapping speech that we would automatically ‘erase’ from an ideal representation of our linguistic performance turn out to be really important in ‘holding a narrative together’, as well as in structuring the changeovers between speakers and hearers in a conversation. One could conjecture that these intervening bits and pieces make up that elusive and ‘invisible’ super glue with which the magician in the Indian Rope Trick of Narrative binds again the severed parts of the goddess Vac. They are the solution to that little mystery of re-incorporated structure—as I shall demonstrate in this, and the following chapters of this book. Such a solution is not as far-fetched as it would seem. Gail Jefferson, a leading ethnomethodologist, has called a story in conversation ‘an extended object’,4 meaning that it is distributed across several turns in a conversation, some of which belong to the teller and some, equally, to the listener(s). Hence, a story has to be controlled by all the participants in a conversation if it is to be properly organized. As I shall show, such organizational, and organic, control over the complex Vac ‘body’ of a narrative is indeed exercised by the small, and on the face of it irrelevant, interventions and ‘repairs’ produced by participants during the process of story-telling. A genuine problem with using conversational analytic methodology, however, is its undoubted tedium. It requires that stretches of talk be presented and studied in their entirety—yet this means the ‘data’ set out in its transcribed form is exasperatingly cumbersome. I can only hope that the surreptitious pleasures of eavesdropping, as well as the intrinsic interest of the danger-of-death, tall stories, and minimal narratives that I’ve presented here will do something to mitigate boredom. And then there is always the reader’s unilateral option of ‘skipping’ through or psychologically deleting chunks of tedious material—a choice which we have all have exercised with our texts at one time or another! Second, the ethnomethodologists did not just use a machine—namely, a tape-recorder—for their researches. They also suggested that the object of their studies—namely, conversation—was itself a machine. The properties of this mechanical turn-taking system of conversation were 4Jefferson G., ‘The Sequential Aspects of Story-telling in Conversation’, in Schenkein
(ed.), 1978, p. 219.
254
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
listed by Sacks, Schegloff and Jefferson in their pioneering paper of 1967 (see Chapter 4), which has since inspired a great many other papers. As far as we are concerned, that identification of conversation with a machine remains important because of Dennett’s rather more recent description of the human mind as a machine, and Searle’s arguments against Dennett’s position. Third, ethnomethodologists speak of participants as ‘doers’. Conversationalists cast in the ‘ethno’ mould do not invite, they ‘do inviting’; they do not question, they ‘do questioning’, they do not tell stories, they ‘do story-telling’. The point of this awkward terminology, apparently, is to draw attention to the labour-intensive nature of conversation. Talk does not amount merely to ‘saying’ but to ‘doing’. Obviously, such a rejection of the dichotomy between ‘mere talk’ and ‘active work’, echoes the heavy emphasis in speech act theory on language as action and performance. Conversational analytic maneouvres with tape-recorders—memorymachines—were meant to sustain their claims to manufacture a theoretical ‘apparatus’, not by ‘imagining’ it, but on the basis of recorded ‘facts’. These facts about the enjambment of sentences into a complicated conversational structure force us to reassess the manner in which we extricate theoretical concepts such as ‘sentence’ and ‘word’ from ‘evidence’. At the same time, we manage to confer very little power on parallel concepts such as ‘utterance’ and ‘turn’, although they seem to possess as much ‘factivity’—which in the conversational analytic perspective appears to mean something like brute observability. My argument is that ethnomethodological observations—reasonably serviceable as ‘facts’ about the interlocking structure of conversational communication—are difficult to accommodate within structuralist formalizations, Labovian or speech act, since each speech act is so self-contained, with its own, heavily speaker-oriented, and perhaps unavoidably ethno centric, set of ‘felicity conditions’. Conversational Generalizations Three African proverbs: ‘talking with one another is loving one another’; ‘he who begins a conversation does not foresee its end’ and ‘a proverb is the horse of conversation: when the conversation lags, a proverb revives it.’ In this section, I will concentrate on the pioneering work of Harvey Sacks. Sacks’ energetic and original but strangely disoriented writings still conspire to make him—more than twenty years after his early death
T U R N S A T TA L K
255
in a car accident—perhaps the single most charismatic thinker among the aficionados of the conversational analytic school. It so happens that Sacks raised some specific problems about stories in conversation, to which I offer possible solutions here. These solutions will not be unrelated to the ideas discussed in previous chapters, nor to Hillis Miller’s insights; the shrewd observations of the Yoruba and the Ndebele that I’ve just quoted will also walk alongside my theoretical gabble, forming a counterpoint to it and guiding it when it falters. In Chapter 4, I suggested that a model such as that constituted by the theories of Grice and Lewis was one from which the features of conversation noted by Sacks, Schegloff and Jefferson could be deduced. Lewisian conventions, I argued, could be used to define the regularities of behaviour displayed whenever a story was relayed among members of a community. Whether such ‘regularities’ as conversational analysts notice can properly be called ‘conventions’ according to the Lewisian definition requires a more detailed attention to the methodology used to observe them. The present chapter undertakes this task. Sacks states the ends of conversational analytic methodology succinctly: What one ought to seek to build is an apparatus which will provide for how it is that any activities, which members do in such a way as to be recognizable as such to members, are done, and done recognizably.5
Now, the building of ‘an apparatus’ appears to be a mechanical task, very different from Lewis’ aims of providing an analytic definition of convention. Yet Lewis’ description of convention, below, conforms strikingly to Sacks’ requirements for a talk-machine. A convention of language, according to Lewis— ... is a regularity restricting one’s production of, and response to verbal utterances and inscriptions. Linguistic competence consists in part of a disposition to conform to that restriction with ease; and in part of an expectation that one’s neighbours will be likewise disposed with a recognition of their conformity as a reason for one’s own.6
Though Lewis is writing of ‘grammatical’ conventions, his deposition could refer equally, or even more aptly to the interdependent regularities in a conversation. Lewisian conventions would apply as restrictions on ‘members’ production of and responses to’ conversational acts. They would 5Sacks, ‘On the Analysability of Stories by Children’ in Gumperz and Hymes (eds), 1972, p. 332. 6Lewis, Convention, 1972, p. 51.
256
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
provide ways of presenting an activity so that it was easily ‘recognizable as such to members’, and conversely, opaque to non-members. In Chapter 4, I suggested that turn-taking could itself be treated as a conventional regularity derivable from the rational principle that in cooperative talk it is, by and large, cognitively essential to observe what Schegloff calls ‘the basic rule for conversation: one party at a time [italics mine]’.7 This rule is necessary to ensure the physical processing of a speaker’s ‘meanings’ by hearers. Of course, such a physical ‘rule’ would only be the grossest of parameters, and there could be many socially sanctioned deviations from it.8 Most interesting, though, are the ways in which speakers and hearers contrive not so much to ‘violate’ as to meet the exhausting demands of conversational ‘love’ as the African proverb has it. Schegloff, drew attention to ‘the ways in which coordinated entry by two parties into an orderly sequence of conversational turns is managed ... given the convention of ABAB sequencing’.9 Who gets to speak first, without stepping clumsily on the conversational toes of the other party? How is the pact kept going, without too much damage to the concerned ‘selves’, and without too much offence? The trick, according to Schegloff, is use the pre-existing ABAB turntaking system precisely like a Lewisian convention—that is, as a pattern of behaviour so regular that it constrains the choice of ‘moves’ by conversationalists. When a ‘language-game’ such as story-telling is played out within its confines, turn-taking actually facilitates coordination. Lewis’ own definition of convention, we may recall, had as its source the theory of ‘games of coordination’. A very general convention such as turn-taking, would constrain the way in which participants coordinate every conversational activity; but then there are conventions special to the sub-games possible within the general ABAB system. Harvey Sacks kicks off the discussion by observing that in any conversation ‘certain activities can only be done at certain places in a sequence’; so, for instance, a greeting has regularly to be placed in the opening turns of a sequence, and so forth. He proposes, therefore, that a distinction be made in analysing conversation between a slot and the items which fill it ... certain activities [being] accomplished by a combination of some ‘slot’ and some ‘activity’. Engagement in particular 7Schegloff E., ‘Sequencing in Conversational Openings’, in Gumperz and Hymes
(eds), p. 350. 8For example, see Ochs, 1976. 9Schegloff, ‘Sequencing in Conversational Openings’, in Gumperz and Hymes (eds), p. 350.
T U R N S A T TA L K
257
language-games is, on this account, constrained by members’ knowledge that only particular ‘slots’ are appropriate to particular activities. Conversational ‘objects’ such as answers, greetings, and the like, have conventionally to be positioned in proper ‘slots’.10
Although Sacks uses the terms ‘item’ and ‘object’ interchangeably in his work; I will refer, in this chapter and hereafter, to the story itself as an ‘object’ and to announcements, prefaces and other associated turns by the prospective or current teller of the story as ‘items’.11 Since the languagegame of story-telling requires coordination of moves across several ‘slots’12 in a conversational sequence, and control over several items, it is prototypically cooperative talk in extenso. From the conversational analytic point of view, in what does cooperation consist? One could begin with a basic insight of Sacks about conversation—one he shared with Searle. Recall Searle’s third condition on assertions, set out in Chapter 2. The expressed proposition must not be obviously true to both the speaker and the hearer in the context of the utterance.13
Similarly, Sacks notes that— ... it is a general rule about conversation that it is your business not to tell people what you can suppose they know. If the rule were relaxed there would be no shortage of things to say; you could read from a physics text, you could announce the date, the weather, the time; you could say your name over and over again; you could point things out, ‘This is a chair, today is Saturday, tomorrow is 10Sacks, ‘On the Analysability of Stories by Children’, p. 341. 11 Schegloff has, for instance, pointed out that a turn may contain more than one
‘move’ (‘Sequencing in Conversational Openings’, p. 351). See also M. Owen (1979), ‘Units of Natural Conversation’ (Chapter 2 of Ph.D. dissertation on ‘Remedial Interchanges’), where turns and moves are analysed in relation to one another and to higher order units of natural conversation. Incidentally, the terminology of ‘natural conversation’ used by Owen and others may appear puzzling, but it seems to be ‘preferred’ for two reasons. One, ‘meanings’ in a natural language are thought to be much more variable (i.e., open to interpretation), and therefore more complex than words in an ‘artificial’ language (e.g., a computer language). Two, the phrases ‘natural language’ and ‘natural conversation’ can be related in a conversational analytic framework because the corpus consists of tape-recordings of conversations as they actually occur, although there is some irony in such ‘natural’ narratives being recorded on an ‘artificial’ instrument. 12The use of ‘slot’ in conversational analysis is not to be confused with slots in a story-grammar, but it is interesting that these two approaches to communication were being developed side-by-side in the America of the seventies. 13This is also a preparatory condition in the felicity-conditions constructed for stories in Chapter 2.
258
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Sunday, the next day is Monday’. So if one asserts a fact one can assume the listener knows one is obviously pointing to the relevance/significance of the fact, not telling him the fact itself. The listener then inspects it for—how far does this remark bear on what we have been talking about?14
And in a second lecture Sacks raises this question with regard to stories: The kind of lessons that stories often contain can be delivered perfectly well in the form of a lesson, a proverb, an idiom, a general expression, a general truth, like, ‘make hay while the sun shines’.15
Why then are stories told at such great length? My solution to Sacks’ puzzlement is simply this—since it is a maxim governing conversation that we do not tell people things they know already, story-tellers meet this conversational criterion by presenting general truths such as those expressed in idioms and proverbs—which they know their audience knows—in the form of specific accounts—the particulars of which are unknown. This ‘manoeuvre’ enables tellers to get their recipients to respond to the story by drawing out and stating the general ‘moral’ implied by the story, rather than announcing it themselves. They thus avoid moral responsibility for an overt violation of the maxim which enjoins us to eschew ‘redundancy’. We have seen in earlier chapters that story-recipients’ responses situated at the end of stories, often consist of generalized remarks like, ‘Yes, riots are terrible’, or ‘It’s wonderful to have some leisure!’, and so on. For example: a) i
-> a) ii ->
A 75
... she was IIabsolutely you II KNOWx 76 BLOTTO a’bout himx 77 it was II all FAN’ TASTICx 78 IN II CREDIBLEx—(LAST LINE OF STORY) B 79 oh well, things can go wrong. B 1159 +it’s II going to be VERY ‘awkwardx 1160 and my II mother ‘can’t+ ‘get a’bout ’on her OWNx 1161 **so** c 1162 ** **family** feuds are horrible
a) i below is the paradigm case of a generalization inferred from a story, while a)ii, from a story cited at length in Chapter 1 again brings out the fact that story-tellers leave it to recipients to make generalizations from their stories. Prolific instances of this sort in our everyday conversations illustrate the wisdom of the African sayings about ‘proverbs’ serving as 14H. Sacks, Lecture Notes, Fall, 1971. Also compare Sacks’ observation on the ‘relevance’ of facts in a conversation to Sperber and Wilson’s comments on much the same issue. 15Ibid.
T U R N S A T TA L K
259
the foundation of conversation, as cultural cornerstones and touchstones. To summarize, these instances show that: story-tellers tell particular stories in order to illustrate general truths which they expect their recipients to infer; story-tellers prefer to imply rather than baldly state the general truth they are illustrating since a direct violation of a conversational maxim is thereby avoided; story-tellers manoeuvre or adopt strategies so that they can get recipients to make appropriate generalizations. But what about cases in which story-tellers introduce their stories with generalizations? These narratives are conversationally challenging because they seem to go out of their way to provoke Labov’s ‘So what?’ question. Labov had argued that an important function of the ‘Abstract’ was to establish that the story the narrator was about to tell was ‘reportable’. A generalization at the beginning of a story works like an abstract, but because it presents known information, it provokes prospective recipients into asking for the significance of this information. We can establish this logically by presenting constructed data. b) i
b) ii
c) i
c) ii
c) iii
d) i
d) ii
S1. I must say, Mondays are about the worst days of the week. S2. Pretty bleak, I admit. What’s brought you to the sudden realization? S1. Well, last weekend I. ... [+ STORY] S1. I must say, Mondays are awful. S2. I know. The other days are pretty bad too! S1. But MONdays are the worst. S2. Why do you say that? S1. Well, last weekend I. ... [+ STORY] S1. Cyclists can’t be trusted on roads any more! S2. You just had an accident or something? S1. Very nearly. I was cycling along. ... [+ STORY] S1. Cyclists can’t be trusted on the roads! S2. That’s a fact of life in Cambridge. So what’s new? S1. I’m so glad you agree with me I just had the most horrid experience. I was. ... [+ STORY] S1. Cyclists positively are a menace! S2. I don’t agree with that. I’m on the side of cyclists. S2. Just wait till you hear about my experience. I was. ... [+ STORY] S1. Long live liberty! S2. Joined the SDP, have you? S2. No, but I went along to the meeting and. ... [+STORY] S1. Long live liberty!
260
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
S2. S1. S2. S1.
Liberty’s a corpse already. No, it isn’t. Of course, it is. Can’t wake the dead, can you? Yes, you can! Listen, I went along to. ... [+STORY]
The ‘design’ of these turns demonstrates that generalizations in the slot[s] prior to the intended story ensure that the prospective story-teller does ultimately get to tell his story, provided he is persistent enough, even if the prospective recipient does not immediately ask for an account of the events which prompted the teller’s generalization. In example b)ii, for instance, S2 treats S1’s generalization as simply a comment which does not ‘project’16 for following turns, but S1’s insistence that Mondays are the worst days of weeks, must lead to a story-engendering query sooner or later. Examples c)iii and d)ii similarly present generalizations which prospective story-recipients initially do not accept as ‘facts’, but even in these cases, story-tellers are finally able to produce their stories in ‘defence’ of their earlier generalizations. Though this strategy is an aggressive one in that it openly violates a maxim, making the teller’s slot ‘fragile’, it does avoid the danger associated with particularized story-prefaces of the type ‘I skidded on the bridge, and nearly went off’. For, as I have shown in Chapter 1, story-prefaces which offer specific details of the experience of tellers, give other participants the opportunity to say, ‘I’ve heard about that’, or even as Labov suggests, ‘That’s nothing new. It happens to me everyday.’ The manouevre of presenting a generalization as a story-preface forces prospective story-recipients into guessing at the story-teller’s implied meaning in violating the Maxim of Quantity. It thus ends up inviting further explanations or elaborations of this implied meaning in the form of a story by tellers. Of course, recipients can arraign a story which begins with a generalization as inadequately justifying the initial generalization, but this can only happen after the story-teller has held the floor. The strategic problems confronting tellers who initiate their stories with generalizations are therefore different from the problems which confront tellers striving to get recipients to make the ‘correct’ generalizations from these stories. Tellers who take the risk of beginning their stories with 16See Jefferson in Schenkein (ed.) ‘story-telling can involve a story-preface in which a teller projects a forthcoming story’, that is, story-telling, unlike commenting, is not typically a single-turn utterance but is understood to occupy a sequence of ‘slots’ projected by the teller’s initial prefacing utterance (p. 219).
T U R N S A T TA L K
261
generalizations must fend off possible attacks from recipients condemning the stories as unworthy of the generalization which engendered them. I support my constructed examples above with the tape-recorded instance below: e) i A
1
3 b → 4 A 5
b A
9 10
b A
12 13
but II then you see no more were SOLDIERS ‘wickedx 2 II seex because II they just WENT and DID it {DIDN’T theyx}x that’s a very unfashionable view I II knowx—6 II I keep thinking of my uncle ARTHUR 7 or II rather my GREAT ‘UNCLE ARTHURx— 8 II who what he do he II [f :?] II he ‘fought in [di:] in the SUDAN11 he II fought in ‘SOUTH AFRICAx [m] [STORY introduced]
Even if recipients object to the generalization which prefaces the story (‘that’s a very unfashionable view’), it seems to be the case that the strategy adopted by the teller sooner or later results in his being able to tell his story. This is not to argue that a generalization always engenders a story, since generalizations can typically result in the language games of ‘discussion’ or ‘argument’, but if prospective tellers do wish to ensure that a particular story gets told, one of the surest ways of doing so is to ‘preface’ the story with a generalization, precisely because it evokes questions in recipients mind about the story’s ‘fragility’. Generalizations, like metaphors and proverbs, encapsulate the collective wisdom and moral apprehensions of cultures. Sometimes they represent the store of experience that a senior member of the community has to offer (‘but then you see no more were SOLDIERS ‘wickedx 2 II seex 3 because II they just WENT and DID it {DIDN’T theyx}x’). What’s interesting here is the tentative manner in which the generalization is ‘glued’ into its conversational turn. There’s a ‘but’ connecting with the previous turn; a ‘you see’; a tag question, ‘didn’t they?’, which seeks listener approval for the non politically correct generalization on offer; and, finally, there’s the emphasis on the evocative key-word, ‘soldier’, as well on the commonsensical idea of just ‘going and doing’ things. Not just an opinion, but a whole ideological universe of a soldier’s morality—not to mention mortality—is thus in contention. ‘Theirs not to reason why, theirs but to do and die’. Yet, one can disagree with such
262
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
a Tennysonian perspective, absolving soldiers of ‘wickedness’, since all’s fair in war—and the listener is obviously aware of this. That is why the hedges around the teller’s utterance are not irrelevant; they reveal an awareness that a sharp ‘unhedged’ response might follow—as indeed it does. The hedges highlight this contrast of mental attitudes; they demonstrate that the dynamics of the conversation does not just consist of wooden generalizations and prepared responses, but is extremely flexible in its sensitivity to the cognitive states of participants. As we have observed, generalizations constitute a fairly sturdy means of opening or closing narratives, but they too are subject to what Miller identified as a fundamental weakness of narrativity. Stories obey a linguistic law of ‘necessary incompleteness’. I have argued that this is so because all discourse genres, of which narrative is arguably just the most prototypical example, are embedded in the cognitive context of conversation. Language may primarily be a tool of thought, but discourse genres—jokes, riddles, lectures, novels, poems, rap, tall tales, etc.—cannot but be at least ‘two-party’. They are specifically designed to turn talk into text—that is, to call up perlocutionary inferences. No audience, no narrative completion, as I stressed when I introduced the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick. Ethnomethodological studies of conversation, which visualize conversation as a machine for generating talk, constantly call to our attention the ‘technicalities’ of the turn-taking system and the constraints it imposes on talk. For example, there is a set order of ‘slots’ for the story as a ‘sequenced object’. If we return to Labov’s structural categories of narrative, and try to fit them into a conversational system, for example, we find that a) there exist a surprising number of slots for the insertion of generalizations, suggesting that this mode of opening and closing stories may be cognitively quite efficient or salient; and b) that ‘slots’ are more or less evenly distributed between teller and listener in terms of ‘turns’. Abstract (often consisting of a generalization): Orientation: Complicating Action: Resolution: (may involve a generalization) Evaluation: (may include generalizations and several turns) Coda: (often consisting of a generalization)
Typically a teller’s turn Often a shared turn Typically a teller’s turn Typically a teller’s turn Typically a listener’s turn Typically a listener’s turn
T U R N S A T TA L K
263
However, the openness of the ABABAB turn-taking system means, just as Miller suspects, that there remains a linguistic or structural problem with ever closing a narrative tightly enough in a conversational context, which in turn stands in for the cognitive context of communication at large. Even a meme-supported generalization—often the strongest of cultural means—cannot ensure that a narrative is safely completed and invulnerable to fragility. That is the lesson of the Indian Rope Trick: the body of Vac may be glued together for the time being by the cooperative endeavours of teller and listener, but there is reason to suspect that she might fall apart at the next performance! No theory is invulnerable to reanalysis or replacement. This follows from the ethnomethodologically ‘observed’ fact that it is built into the nature of all conversational interaction that it, literally and physically, distributes, segments and cuts up speech. He who begins a conversation, as the African saying put it, does not foresee its end. Human Frailty and Narrative Fragility A story, according to Sacks, is a version of events where ‘what may be involved is that you may present to your audience in some fashion materials which are more complicated than your story says, where they could, for example, focus off the proposed business of your story or the proposed upshot of your story, to suggest that you may not have it right.’17
The fragility of stories is, paradoxically, an ‘interactional’ or cooperative feature in conversations because the logic of conversation decrees that it is recipients who must play a crucial role in determining which aspects of a story a teller ‘may not have ... right’. Tellers therefore use a number of strategies to protect their narratives. One such method, Sacks suggests, is to compress their length and detail so that recipients have fewer opportunities to challenge them. f) i C
436
B
443
> I was IIon a ‘bus ‘just ‘going ‘down to the British MU SEUM ‘not so ‘long a’gox—437 and II there—were two ‘girls just GETTING ‘on the ‘busx 438 and II flirting with the CON DUCTORx—439 and IIone of them ‘said to the OTHERx . 440 IIyou’re a ‘dirty WHOREx 441 and IIshe said no I AIN’Tx 442 I’m a II CLEAN’ whorex II AHx 444 (—laughs) that’s IIrather NICEx 445 (— laughs)
17H. Sacks, Lecture Notes, Fall, 1971.
264
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
C
446
B
448
I II don’t know ‘whether she REALLY ‘meant itx 447 or IIwhether they were just TEASINGx— IIwhore IT SELF is a ‘euphemism ‘they SAYx
In example f)iii, C’s story in lines 436–42 is distinguished not only by its brevity. It is also unusual in that it has a clear punch-line which most everyday stories lack. This gives it the character of a joke rather than of a factual story, as B’s positive evaluation (laugh+ ‘that rather nice’ + laugh) in lines 444–5 shows. Noticeably, B does not question the authenticity of the story in any way, presumably because the story is both extremely brief and apposite (C has mentioned an interest of the word ‘whore’ before in the conversation to which remark B returns in lines 448 ). It is left to the narrator C to modify his story with an attitudinal comment (‘I don’t know if she really, meant it or whether they were just teasing’). Brevity therefore not only seems to sharpens the ‘wit’ or humour of the story, it offers a strategic advantage to the teller, who can then get to evaluate his own performance. Compressing a story, leaving out all but the most striking details, thus appears to ‘protect’ stories in that listeners are drawn away from questioning the story’s fragility. I shall now maintain, unlike Labov, that stories may be particularly ‘fragile’ when they are blatantly offered as stories about extraordinary rather than everyday events. Despite changes in cultural context, this rule seems to hold, as in the Bengali-cum-English conversation below: f) ii J H M N H N
1
He’ll never tell the story now. 2 He’ll think you’re taking ‘evidence. na: / hae/ oke ki: / 3 No.. [to N] 4 Yes, was she ...? shunte perecho / 5 Did you hear anything? she: amader/ she a:gekar/ she dorwan ashchilo na: 6 The—that old durwan of ours—the one who’d come ... hae / kon dorwan / 7 Yes, which durwan? she kedi eshechilo / kompani theke je eshechilo na / to or shonge khabar tabar nie ashto/ o:r basa / oke a:mi djigish korlam / o bollo a:mar bou a:chche/ 8 That K.D. who came—9 the one who came from the Company 10 he used to bring along his lunch from home—11 I asked him (about this)—12 he said, I have a wife ...
T U R N S A T TA L K
H 13 N 14 H 15 N 16 M 17 H 18 N
19
265
hu / oh to a:mio djani / sundaro djane / nandlal djane/ sobai dzane / So I know, Sundar knows, Nandlal knows, everybody knows ... Sobai dzane / Everybody knows? hu one:k di:n theke / Yes, [we’ve known] for a long time. achcha / Oh? tarpore ki holo / What happened then? tarpore bolchhe ki a:ge /mane taka paesa thik dichchilo / aekhuni bolche cho sa:t ma:sh dhore taka paesa ki:chu daena / [Long Pause] Then she claims that before ... 20 I mean, he used to give her money all right—now she says that for the last six or seven months he doesn’t give her anything. ... [and etc.]
To begin with, the cultural import of power relations cannot be underestimated in this story, where members of a well-to-do family are interrogating a family retainer about another employee who has taken a second ‘city wife’. Yet bigamy is only a secondary issue here; secrecy and loyalty are the primary motifs. Had the ‘wife’ not taken the bold step of coming to the employer’s house and complaining that she was no longer being supported by her ‘husband’, no one would have bothered about this fairly common private arrangement made by men who live away from their villages for long periods. As N points out, he knew about the second wife anyway because ‘K.D.’ used to bring a cooked lunch to work—a crucial clue. So ‘everybody knew’, but the matter only became a ‘tellable’ in this cultural context after the wife complained to the other ‘servants’. This means their loyalty was now divided (‘He’ll never tell the story now. He’ll think you’re taking evidence.’). N’s narrative gains its drama, its ‘extraordinariness’ from this ordinary ‘fact’ of divided loyalties, which might be completely missed by someone who foregrounds, say, bigamy, as the most scandalous ‘tellable’ in the story. The ability to deduce straightforward implicatures of the Gricean type is not enough in such a situation; implicultural ability is required. Given the ubiquitous employment of domestic servants in India, class is perhaps the most salient part of the interpretive context in this
266
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
narrative, and it directly influences the strategy adopted by the teller. Himself an employee, N’s audience consists of several of his employers. His ‘story’ is culturally vulnerable on this count. There is an obvious payoff in N’s being ‘loyal’ to his employers and coming clean about K.D.’s wife when he is questioned by them. At the same time, both audience and teller are aware that such a ‘payoff’ might influence the ‘outcome’ of the story, and they also share the knowledge that there is a social cost to ‘snitching’. In this complex cultural situation, N has no guarantee at all that his narrative will be accepted as plausible by his audience. That is what makes his choice of strategy so brilliant. N chose to cite his fellow employees as witnesses: in line 14 he claims that ‘Sundar knows, Nandlal knows, everybody knows ...,’ and in line 16 insists that not only do these witnesses know about the incident but they have been aware of it for a long time. Through lines 14 and 16, N is thus able to demonstrate both his solidarity with the other employees, and yet be the first to loyally tell a story that ‘everyone’ has known about for a long time, to his employers. The strategy of citing witnesses classically ‘ratifies’ N’s story, as conversational analysts would say. It protects the fragile fabric of the story from sceptical attacks by his powerful listeners by stressing common, shared knowledge. As a result of this strategy, two goals are concurrently achieved: N’s own conduct is rendered exemplary, and the ‘extraordinary’ conduct of K.D.’s city wife is made plausible. The example below also shows that no matter how extraordinary the events narrated, story-tellers contrive to present their stories as ordinary and everyday. This remains perhaps the most frequent and interesting strategy tellers use to maintain the convention of protecting the fragile aspects of their unusual stories. Since this story consists of a lengthier extract from the conversation of which e)i above formed a part, I will number this example e) i (b) A
893 895 897
but IIgoing ‘back to B SPECIALS you ‘knowx 894 *these* IIarmed. these *[m]* 894 IIarmed THUGS 896 the II PROTESTANT ‘lotx— and II I was thinking a’bout that Bright ‘Park BAYx— 898 a II {LOVELY} {BEAUTIFUL}—[ ].AMPITHEATRE {IIfull of ‘wild FLOWERSx}x—899 the IItime. when I was DEFENDING itx 900 and II I was ‘having to CUT ‘these things > IIcut [ ] SLIP ‘trenchesx 901 II here ‘there and EVERYWHERE
T U R N S A T TA L K
b A
903 904
b A
914 915
b A
917 918
b A
922 923
c b
931 932
A
933
b A
936 937
267
x 902IIso that the—‘people could. IIcould ‘not {LIVE} upon the BEACHES as it ‘were {BE II LOWx}x [m]— IIand I. I IIhad to ‘make my—I II asked well what sup’porting TROOPS there will bex 905 IIwe are MACHINE gunn>x 906 I must II have a ‘COUNTER-AT{TACK} FORCEx—907 I IIdon’t see any—infantry battalion within MILESx 908IINO {IIGWYNx}x909 II SORRYx 910 you II CAN’T we IIhaven’t GOT anyx—911 they’re II all ‘ready to ‘go and ‘do something ELSEx 912II you’ve got to do it YOUR SELVESx 913 with the IIhelp. ‘of. the CONSTABULARYx oh— II and—then I had to ‘go the ‘ ROUNDx—916 the II Orange ‘lodges and the ‘local FARMSx OH —. II every PROTESTANT FARMx—919 IIall the ‘able-’bodied MENx 920 from II sixty to— SEVENTEEN {or II SIXTEEN}x}—921 had IIgot— a most beautifully ‘kept Lee ‘Enfield RIFLEx oh and a IIvery ‘sharp BAYONETx—924IIand I said WELLx. 925 IIcan I I [? ?] I IIall I ‘want is to be SURE 926 that IImy ‘men are not ‘going to be stabbed in the {BACK} while they’re ‘firing their GUNSx 927 we could IIcope with what ‘comes from SEAx—928 IIyou could. IIyou can be abso lutely CERTAINx—929 we will have II done what is {NECESSARY} to all the ‘people of the other FAITHx—930*(—coughs)* (*—*—giggles) ooh Jesus—well how would the people of the other faith have received Germans from the sea—you must have thought *about that* *II I’ve [w ] II I’ve* no II I’ve never THOUGHT of THATx934 that’s II not a[na: n] it’s IInow that I I II think that it is NOWx 935 II a pertinent QUESTION I ask it IIand I IIyou ASK itx 938 and II I ‘think that if they {HADN’T} got the B SPECIALS on their
268
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
b A
940 941
b A
956 957
b A
967 968
b A
973 974
b
979
‘tailx. 939 II they would have ACCEPTED the ‘Germans [m] well II NOWx. 942IIgoing ‘back to Pete BASKERDONx 943 II this is ANOTHER ‘storyx— 944 II Pete BASKERDONx945 II is a SAD ‘manx 946 IIhe is NOT a ‘very CLEVER ‘boyx —947 he’s II not REALLYx 948IIup to his ‘PHDx—949 he’s II {NEVER had } ANY ‘further PROMOTION x 950 II from the job that ‘he was in when I ‘met him in the WARx— 951 he II GOT that JOBx—952 be II cause there was a MANx—953 who was the II head of the ‘Celtic MUSEUMx—945 I. IImay re’member HIS ‘name in a MINUTEx—955 IIwho was a German SPYx— oh fascination go on—(—coughs) and II what is the WONDER IImost II biggest {SEND-UP} of IRELAND 958 and II all ‘our prehistoric ‘ARCHAE OLOGYx—959 IIwas that in [ ] PRO {CEEDINGS of the } PREHISTORIC SOCIETYx—960 II you can READ in the II any ‘library you ‘wish to. CON SULT it ‘inx—961 be II tween nine’ teen THIRTYx 962 and II nineteen THIRTYNINEx—963 the IImost ‘ wonderfully ‘vivid ACCOUNTx. 964 of the DIS II COVERYx—965 comIIpletely {NEW} [ai] Irish ‘culture in’Northern ‘Ireland ‘called the ‘{BANN}CULTUREx 966 the II river BANNx oh. *—good God* *this is an enIItire ‘IN VENTIONx. 969II of that*. very GIFTEDx 970 IIvery’ clever ‘German SPYx—971 who was the II HEADx 972 of the [u] IIof the’ of the Celtic ‘[mju:] of the of of the II Celtic [ m ]. ‘National Mu’seum in DUBLINx— do you mean *he created it* *and II that ‘man* II what is so INTERESTING isx 975 that IInot only was this the CASEx. 976 II BUTx. 977 IIthat the ‘Irish ‘government ‘KNEW a’bout itx—978 II and the British the II ARCHAE OLOGISTS did ‘NOTx—. do you mean he created it as an excuse for being around I *don’t really know*
T U R N S A T TA L K
A
980
b A
982 983
b A
986 987
b A
989 990
b
992
A b A
993 994 995
b A b A
1007 1008 1009 1010
b
1018
269
*to II go into the* ‘north and. spy OUTx 981 where II all the AERODROMES ‘were and EVERYTHINGx— *good God* *IIand the* II Irish ‘[gav] IIsomebody SPLIT on himx. 984 and the II Irish ‘government kept it to them’selves and ‘didn’t ‘tell the BRITISHx. 985 and the II British ARCHAEOLOGIST—IIyou. SEEx— *idiots* *that’s II just* ‘what II just ‘shows what the academic ‘racket is ABOUTx 988 (sighs—)— *and was nobody. * *I’ll II think I’ll I think of his NAME in a MINUTEx*. 991 it’s II there in PRINTx extraordinary. are you saying that he was a German or an Irishman II I’m saying ‘he was a GERMANx [m] II and. Pete BASKERDONx—996 II TOLD me ‘thisx—997 IIwhen we ‘got to KNOW each ‘otherx— 998 he [?] II HE wanted to KNOWx 999 if II anybody in ‘our—. PRO FESSIONAL ‘ranksx 1000 IIsmelt a RATx—1001 IIand I SAIDx 1002 to II my best of my knowledge and BE LIEFx—1003 II OUR [pri] ‘prehis’torians in CAMBRIDGEx—1004 were II swallowing the whole ‘thing hook ‘line and SINKERx—. 1005 it was II CAUSED ‘byx 1006 a II geo olgical FAULTx oh. IIwhich. made ROCK SPLITx yeah IIkind of. SHALE of SOME ‘sortx.1011 and II if you ‘went A{LONG} poking a ‘long the ‘river. the rivers of ‘Northern IRELANDx 1012II you would FINDx 1013 at II various PLACESx. 1014IIyou’d find {BEAUTIFUL}what were ALLEGED to be ARTEFACTSx 1015 which which were II REALLYx 1016 II Dame ‘Nature of. II after a ‘little bit of FROSTx— 1017 had PRO II DUCED ‘these ‘thingsx— but if you were the first person to be told of this by Baskerdon did you spill the beans
270
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
A
1019
b A
1021 1022
b A
1025 1026
II I DIDN’Tx—1020 (—giggles) II wasn’t till ‘after the WARx but Gwyn God rot you really if I may say so (—giggles) II I was too BUSYx 1023 II doing OTHER ‘thingsx 1024 (—giggles) *[ ]* * ri*diculous— [ ] IIwhen I was [?]. down [?] at the very ‘corner ‘of—TYRONEx—1027 we IIdid an [a:] an EXCA VATIONx [START OF NEXT STORY]
It is hard to imagine a more extraordinary concatenation of tales than the ones related above by A! Yet A begins his account of the pre-war ‘troubles’ in Ireland with a deceptively charming description of ‘Bright Park Bay, a lovely beautiful amphitheatre full of wild flowers, the time I was defending it’. Such an inclusion of natural detail not only offers a ‘poetic’ contrast to the violence of the ‘armed thugs’ who are the actual protagonists of his story, it also provides an ordinary ‘picnic’ setting which recipients unfamiliar with guns and battle can recognize—the only ominous note being struck by A’s selection of the word ‘amphitheatre’ to describe the bay. A’s next utterance moves the story dramatically on from this idyllic setting to his confrontation with the B Specials. He uses direct speech to report the encounter, which further dramatizes the scene. At the same time, direct speech seems to make the story more plausible because the interchanges are so matter of fact (‘and I, I had to make my—I asked well—what supporting troops will there be—we are machine gunners, I must have a counterattack force, I don’t see any infantry battalion within miles—No Gwyn, sorry, you can’t, we haven’t got any. They’re all ready to go and do something else, you’ve got to do it yourselves, with the help of the constabulary’ (lines 904–13). Here a desolate, halffinished sentence at the start indicating the speaker’s doubts about the whole enterprise is suddenly abandoned in favour of a much more energetic approach which ‘repairs’ it. The casualness of, ‘No, Gwyn, sorry, you can’t, we haven’t got any ... you’ve got to do it yourselves’ shows the teller taking steps early in his ‘A Special’ narrative to make it convincing. Reported speech is employed again by A in his utterance in lines 923–9, where the last line, ‘you can be absolutely certain we will have done what is necessary to all the people of the other faith’, gains its definitive effect by laconic understatement.
T U R N S A T TA L K
271
Despite its startling subject matter, the first story told by A is as well planned as a war-exercise. It defends its terrain in at least two convincing ways; it is set in a scene that is pleasant and un-alarming, and it uses reported speech in a way that renders the violence A is engaged in immediate because it is so ordinary-sounding. That A ‘wins’ his ‘war’ is evident from the way in which his recipients are rendered almost speechless by the narrative of his exploits. One recipient, c, only manages a single nervous giggle during the entire conversation, while b, the main listener, is just able come up with ‘oh’ in her first three turns (lines 914, 917 and 922); then, c’s giggle appears to galvanize her and she does become quite a bit more assertive in the second half of A’s telling, but it is plain that she is mesmerized by A’s narrative skills, using her evaluative slots in the conversation to urge A to ‘go on’. At this point, ‘Gywn’ has clearly succeeded in quite disarming his listeners. Anything he does subsequently— such as forgetting the name of the main character in his second story ‘the German spy’ (see lines 945, 990), an omission he tries twice to ‘repair’ without success (lines 945, 990)—will be forgiven. The second story A tells also begins by introducing an unusual subject in a casual way. The story starts with some subdued comments about ‘Pete Baskerdon ... a sad man, he is not a very clever boy, he’s not really up to his Ph.D.’, and so forth; but these remarks lead on to the subject of ‘a man who was the head of the Celtic museum ... who was a German spy’. In the manner so typical of casual conversations, we hardly notice the subtlety of this strategy. The subject of the story is indirectly introduced through a reworking into the ‘talk-exchange’ of a known name, the name of a person who has evidently been discussed by the participants before (‘Well, now, going back to Pete Baskerdon. ...’) This prepares the ground so that the mention of ‘a German spy’ does not seem too abrupt or jarring. Similarly, A is careful in his next turn (lines 957–66) to use the by now familiar strategy of ‘ratification’. He stresses that his account of the ‘biggest send-up of Ireland and all our prehistoric archaeology’ can be read ‘in any library you wish to consult it in’. Corroborative evidence ‘in print’ is pretty convincing in the psychological context of the literate culture(s) of the twentieth century; so ‘Gwyn’ is on safe ground here, even though he cannot remember his ‘hero’s’ name. Given A’s heroic efforts to make his story both plausible and interesting, it is not therefore surprising that recipient b is entirely convinced, as well as captivated, by ‘the story so far’; b’s turns in lines 956 (‘oh fascination go on’) and 967 (‘oh ... good God’) clearly demonstrate this.
272
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
In A’s turns in lines 968-72, however, we hit an area of landmines, of narrative fragility, because A fails to clarify a pivotal point. His assertion ‘this is an entire invention of that very gifted and very clever German spy’ refers to the ‘Bann’ culture of Ireland and not to the ‘Celtic Museum’ in Dublin. The immediate result is that speaker b becomes a doubting Thomas in successive turns (see lines 973 ‘do you mean he created it’ and 979 ‘do you mean he created it as an excuse for being around, I don’t really know’). Now, the reason for b’s scepticism may be that while A has prepared the ground in his previous turns with talk about a German spy and ‘the biggest send-up in Ireland’, for the ‘Bann’ culture to turn out to be a hoax, he has not similarly prepared b for thinking of the Celtic Museum itself as a ‘invention’. Although he has mentioned twice that the German spy was head of the Celtic Museum, the linguistic ambiguity remains. The Bann culture was certainly a hoax, but was the Celtic Museum one too? A’s comments about the Irish government’s tacit support to the German spy (line 984) do nothing to clear up this confusion. The point is that skilful story-tellers like A can make the most bizarre stories sound credible. If, however, they make a wrong move—which becomes increasingly probable, the longer a story sequence extends— ‘co-ordination problems’ are bound to arise. Recipients retain the right to demur if story-tellers ask them to accept developments in the story which have not been sufficiently prepared for in earlier turns by the teller. In the present example, A does not seem to realize the import of b’s question, and simply picks up on the word ‘excuse’ (‘[excuse] ... to go into the north and spy out where all the aerodromes were and everything’, (lines 980–1), so that b’s question is never really answered. Still, b appears to accept this unwitting failure on the part of A (see b’s lines 982, 989 and 992)—partly because A has already created sufficient interest in his story, and partly perhaps out of politeness because A is pushing ahead with the story, unaware of the significance of b’s question. Nevertheless, A’s defences have been breached at this stage. The shining hero, who not only held his audience enthralled with his first story of facing the B Specials, but earned their moral respect, is revealed as a somewhat less perfect agent—a ‘naughty boy’ almost—after this closing interchange, and yet another story is needed to repair the damage (lines 1026–7). Consider the segment: b
1018
A
1019
but if you were the first person to be told of this by Baskerdon did you spill the beans II I DIDN’Tx—1020 (—giggles) II wasn’t till ‘after the WARx
T U R N S A T TA L K
b A
1021 1022
b
1025
273
but Gwyn God rot you really if I may say so (—giggles) II I was too BUSYx 1023 II doing OTHER ‘thingsx 1024 (—giggles) *[ ]* * ri*diculous—
A’s facetiousness invites spirited objections from b in lines 1021 and 1025—the more so because he seems to have merrily implicated himself in the ‘cover-up’ of the activities of the German spy. A’s explanation of the source of the hoax ‘what were alleged to be artefacts were really Dame Nature of—after a little bit of frost—had produced these things’ (lines 1015–17), is greeted by b with the uncompromising challenge, ‘but if you were the first person to be told of this by Baskerdon, did you spill the beans’ (line 1018). The question is a serious one because it implies A had some responsibility to expose the hoax since he was the first person to be told about it; however, A’s negative answer to this loaded question defuses the charge by simply refusing to take it seriously. The answer ‘I didn’t’, accompanied by a ‘giggle’ and an excuse, ‘It wasn’t until after the war’, is not designed to do much for A’s image, but it succeeds in making light of a very unusual event and treating it as routine—‘I was too busy doing other things (giggles)’. The implication seems to be that the episode was not worth taking the trouble to expose. And while b finds this attitude ‘ridiculous’, it is worth noting that she uses such a strong expression because she takes A’s story seriously, despite the fact that A himself underplays its gravity. Semantically, the latter part of A’s second story connects the words ‘hoax’, ‘racket’ and ‘invention’.18 Line 987, for example, uttered at a possible completion point for the story—‘that’s just what, just shows what the academic racket is about’—is a generalization that finds A again using the strategy of stressing the ordinary and recognizable aspects of his story. In lines 995–1004, A continues with this strategy (‘our prehistorians in Cambridge were swallowing the whole thing hook, line and sinker’). Thus, the extraordinary story of a major hoax by a German spy, involving the collusion of the Irish government, is deliberately linked to the world of academics which A has reason to suppose is familiar to b.19 To this extent, the various tactics A summons up to 18Following Sack’s notion of member-shipping categories, the concepts ‘racket, ‘hoax’,
and ‘invention’ might be classified as members of the same ‘category device’. 19Quirk and Svartvik in the ‘Corpus’ list teller A as a ‘male businessman’, and recipient B as a younger ‘female academic’. Presumably, then, A has reason to believe that B is familiar with academia, and academic ‘rackets’.
274
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
convert his unusual subject matter into ‘something for us’—everyday stuff—are admirably successful. He may have lost a narrative battle or two, but he emerges an undoubted winner in the conversational war. The observations made above accord well with Sacks’ comments on the ‘overwhelming banality of the stories we encounter’.20 It was his examination of a number of danger of death ‘earthquake’ stories that led Sacks to remark on a peculiarity of these stories. He noticed that one of the most frequent ways in which tellers seem to protect fragile aspects of their ‘danger-of-death’ narratives was to present their material as quite unremarkable. At first, this observation of Sacks’ seems to conflict with Labov’s claim that a narrative is always ‘tellable’ or reportable if it is constructed out of unusual materials. Yet disasters, classic ‘tellables’ in Labov’s sense, as Sacks pertinently remarks, are merely ‘things in the world’. Despite their immense potential as reportable events, they have to be worked on, fashioned into ‘something for us’, something that engages a teller’s particular audience. This means that reportable story material has to be rendered ‘ordinary’ (‘it could happen to you’) if it is not to be arraigned as ‘fragile’ on grounds of implausibility. Conversely, ordinary story material has to be made reportable if it is not to be criticized as boring (‘why are you telling me this?’). It is really remarkable to see people’s efforts to achieve the ‘nothing happened’ sense of really catastrophic events. ... It seems plain enough that people monitor the scenes they are in for their storyable characteristics. And yet the awesome, overwhelming fact is that they come away with no storyable characteristics.21
Why is this so? Sacks’ answer is that people ‘come away with no storyable characteristics’ from really amazing scenes because ordinary people work conversationally at being ordinary. ... they and the people around them may be co-ordinatively engaged in assuming that each of them are ordinary persons, and that can then be a job they undertake together, to achieve that each of them together are ordinary persons ... [this is] a specific feature [of conversations] which turns on a kind of attitude of working at being usual, which is perhaps central to the way our world is organized. There are enormous virtues in seeing the usual in a scene. It permits all kinds of ways of dealing with it.22 20Sacks, Lecture Notes, Spring, 1970. 21Ibid. 22Sacks, Lecture Notes, Spring, 1970.
T U R N S A T TA L K
275
In the last chapter, I suggested in relation to Dennett’s characterization of the ‘self as a centre of narrative gravity’ that there were likely to be at least two cognitive categories of narrativity—stories to the self and stories to the other, the daily and the daylight. Ordinarily, the routines of our day-to-day activities make up stories not worth telling to others, yet central to our sense of self or ‘the way our world is organized’. These ‘hidden’ narratives, I now want to suggest, form a cognitive substrate to the narratives that we do share with others. The task of ‘being ordinary’ is in fact one we engage in at all times, whether alone or with others, while ‘doing being ordinary’ involves the additional burden of interaction. In the next section, I develop the idea ‘plausibility’, ‘boredom’ and ‘narrative fragility’ being intrinsically interactional concepts. Plausibility and Boredom as Gauges of Narrative Fragility So far, I have used the term ‘plausible’ informally to describe stories or aspects of stories that are convincing and therefore acceptable to recipients. I shall now argue, contra Searle, that it is plausibility rather than truth that recipients look for in stories. The Oxford English Dictionary (O.E.D.)23 derives the word ‘plausibility’ from the Latin plaudere (‘to applaud’), so that the first sense of the word is given as ‘the quality of deserving applause or approval’. Some vestige of this sense is retained in the second, more usual, modern use of the word which conveys a ‘seeming worthiness of acceptance’ or ‘appearance of reasonableness’. The significance of this connection will, I hope, become more obvious as my argument progresses. For the moment, I will concentrate on distinguishing between ‘truth’ and ‘plausibility’. The distinction, it appears from the O.E.D., was made as early as in 1745 by Swift, who wrote, ‘The last excuse was allowed indeed to have more plausibility but less truth’; and in 1838, Thirlwall wrote, ‘According even to the avowed doctrines of Protagoras and Gorgias, no truth could claim any higher value than that of a plausible opinion.’24 Earlier, in 1598, Bernard maintained, ‘Nowadays, plausibleness gains friends, and truth gets foes’.25 There is therefore some etymological sanction or historical precedent for considering ‘truth’ and ‘plausibility’ distinctly different gauges of the acceptability of an utterance. My contention is that story-recipients 23The Oxford English Dictionary, Vol. VII (N-Poy), 1970, p. 972. 24Thirlwall, Greece, IV, xxxii, 1935. 25Bernard, Terence, Andria 1.i (translation), 1598.
276
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
in ordinary conversations standardly accept a story if it is plausible, even if they cannot verify its facts. Sacks points out: It is an interesting fact to consider that recipients can apparently decide that a story was correctly told without going out and checking the actual circumstances in which it occurred. ... That is to say, recipients do not feel at the mercy of the teller to decide what the world is about. And apparently tellers have ways, and need to employ ways, in order to produce a story that is recognizably correct or at least plausible.26
I have already analysed some of the ways in which tellers render a story ‘recognizably correct or at least plausible’; but Sacks’ opinion seems to be that producing a ‘plausible’ story is the next best thing to producing a story that is ‘recognizably correct’. My claim is a more parsimonious one. I suggest that a story that is ‘plausible’ is ‘recognizably correct’, and that recipients almost always use the gauge of ‘plausibility’ to assess tellers’ stories. A story is plausible insofar as it is credible, probable, likely, possible and/or convincing; it is true insofar as it is verifiable, factual, correct and/or demonstrable. And given that most recipients cannot ‘go out and check the actual circumstances’ in which a story occurred, it is the former set of criteria which are standardly used. Consider another extract with the same teller A as in the conversation in the previous section: e) i (c) A
828
c A
831 832
b A
837 838
b
845
->
we IIhadn’t ‘said anything. [ ] derogatory a’bout the I’rish. GOVERNMENTx 828 IIhe’s an Irish ‘civil SERVANTx . 830 and IIhe SUDDENLY. he II he SUDDENLYx (—coughs) A II DOPTED ‘usx 833 and we II found ourselves ‘going out to HIS little ‘housex—834 II in SORDSx 835 II IS itx 836 I II think it— sounds plausible— it’s II on the {SORDS} ROAD} ANYWAYx 839 I .I’m II not sure ‘which is what the ‘name of the little the II little VILLAGE ‘isx—840 II SANTRYx 841 II BEG your PARDONx 842 II SANTRYx 843 II opposite ‘Santry COURTx . 844 II Sords is just ‘further UPx yeah [A CONTINUES WITH HIS STORY]
26Sacks, Lecture Notes, Spring, 1970.
T U R N S A T TA L K
277
Here, listener b accepts that the house A is talking about in his story is in the village of Sords because this ‘sounds plausible’; and even though story-teller A corrects himself in his next turn—having made a factual error in confusing Sords with Santry—recipient b accepts the correction with a simple ‘yeah’, indicating that A should continue with his story. I wish to argue from this that what recipients are really concerned with is not so much the ‘facts’ of the story, but whether it appears credible. Note that had the story-teller confused ‘Sords’ with say ‘Sandringham’ or ‘Sanchi’ or ‘Sungchi’ recipient b’s credibility would have been subject to immensely greater strain, given that the conversational setting for A’s story is Ireland. In other words, ‘degrees of plausibility’ based on tacit world-knowledge and cultural connection are implicit in all conversations. Even where a story does not occur within a conversation, listeners or readers judge it on the basis of its plausibility. Here is a column from The Times newspaper, more or less contemporaneous with the Svartvik and Quirk recordings: Those of you who didn’t believe that Patty Hearst had been ‘brainwashed’ by the so-called Symbionese Liberation Army, when she took part in those robberies after her kidnap in the mid 1970s, will be vindicated when her own account of the ordeal, Every Secret Thing, is published by Methuen next February. Miss Hearst’s own version is that she had to participate to survive. She says in the book that she always thought the SLA were crazy and that she would be killed unless she played along—even to the point where she never tried to escape and provided covering fire for other SLA members during a raid on a sporting goods store. Is all this convincing? Those who have read the entire manuscript say it is ‘plausible’, given that she spent 57 days in a closet, blindfolded. [italics mine] Miss Hearst apparently still sleeps in a room lined with weapons, such is the long-term effect of her experiences. I wonder how much money she will make out of her plausible account.27
Apparently, it is the ‘plausible’ account which sells, and which readers bestow their approval on, not necessarily the ‘truthful’ one. Extraordinary stories like Miss Hearst’s, have primarily to sound credible. Once their tellers make their tales too unlikely or out-of-the-ordinary, they are open to the charge of being ‘fictional’. And this brings my argument into direct confrontation with Searle’s claim, examined in Chapter 2, that there is a sharp ‘logical’ distinction between fictional and factual discourse, for the newspaper report above is exactly the kind of material on which 27P. Watson, ‘ The Times Diary’, The Times, 8 December 1981.
278
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Searle based his distinction.28 From the evidence at hand, it seems that a story offered by the teller as a ‘factual’ one, can begin to sound and be taken as ‘fictional’, if the skill of the teller is not equal to making it sound plausible. The standard criticisms that recipients make of a story have to do with their finding a story unconvincing or implausible, not with their finding it untrue. Likewise, if a teller embarks on a story which is clearly intended to be fictional, such as a fairytale, he has still to organize his materials so that recipients cooperatively agree to ‘a willing suspension of disbelief’ in Coleridge’s famous phrase. The following passage from the novelist Margaret Drabble makes this point very engagingly: At first Anthony could not work out why he found Tim boring; it was not so much that he talked too much, although he did, it was more that one could not believe anything he said. His stories were too interesting to be interesting. ... Perhaps, thought Anthony at first, this is what life is really like in that particular kind of underworld: mad landladies, beneficent old Etonians, narrow escapes from the fuzz, wild weekends in country houses, propositions from famous film stars, betrayals, and little acts of violence. But if it was really like that, why did such strange narratives arouse in him so little curiosity? Why did he have to work so hard to bring himself to say, every now and then, over the yellow paella or the Greek salad, ‘How astonishing’, ‘Goodness me’, ‘He didn’t really, did he?’ It was astonishingly hard work responding to Tim. The explanation did not occur to him for some days.29
The ‘explanation’ is simply the one noted above. Tellers must weigh down their wild, flyaway stories with the ore of everyday fact, give it ‘gravity’ as it were, otherwise their stories are in danger of being stricken by an unbearable lightness of being. They become ‘too interesting to be interesting’. Over-emphasis on the extraordinary by story-tellers often has the paradoxical consequence that recipients are bored. Since stories typically put the ‘selves’ of teller and listener into conversational contact, they offer a series of glimpses into the organization of inner landscapes. Mental territories are opened out and we get to compare how weirdly similar our minds are—how extraordinarily ordinary. Conversation works, as Sacks says, by participants ‘coordinatively engaging’ in being ordinary, in following recognizable routines of thought and action—but if the teller constantly stresses the fantastic nature of the events or experience he is recounting, recipients’ responses, 28 In ‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, Searle considers a newspaper report by Eileen Shanahan, from The New York Times, 15 December 1972 (Searle, p. 235). 29 Drabble M., The Ice Age, 1977, pp.148–9.
T U R N S A T TA L K
279
deeply dependent on presumptions of ordinariness, are hampered. They lose interest in the language-game because their moves become limited, as Drabble’s character indicates in her novel, to gasping ‘how astonishing’ or ‘goodness me’ in every turn. The whole inference-making process is thereby wrecked and listeners can no longer participate actively in the telling. Complaints to this effect are in fact quite common in everyday talk, as demonstrated by the following extract, analysed at greater length in the section after this one—in which I return to the structural ‘conventions’ of story-telling. C
763 get {SO} fed UP in the ENDx 764 with IIthis sort of ‘FANTASY ‘thingx—765 II AND [ ]x. 766 II I just got BOREDx 767 with II listening to the STORIES {as II WELLx}x768 and II and. and II ALSOx 769 he was II sort of desperately ‘desperately KEENx 770 and II that. that II [?]always . puts me OFFx .
In this conversation, an affair with a boyfriend comes to naught because the speaker gets ‘fed up’ of his predilection for fantasizing through his boring stories. Those who think that stories are mere fluff without a real effect on the lives of people, and that analysing story-telling is ‘soft’ research, should take heed of hard evidence from conversations like the one above! Sperber and Wilson in Relevance make the acerbic comment, ‘as we know the world is full of bores’.30 Good adaptive self-preserving behaviour would, I guess, consist in running in the opposite direction when confronted with such conversationalists. At the same time, situations routinely arise when interaction is unavoidable. Ideally, the maxims and rules of communication should equip one with the cognitive wherewithal to protect oneself if pinned against the wall by a mega-bore, or even a minor one. They should also give each individual guidelines for how she herself ranks on the scale of bores. Academics, for instance, must be able to skim through loads of books and articles that go on and on and on and say very little. This is a basic survival skill in academia. How seldom does one come across something worth reading, but this does not warrant ‘opting out’, to use Grice’s phrase, of the reading process altogether. If one wants to remain fighting fit, there is no choice but to develop techniques which allow one to cope with intellectual boredom in order not to miss the truly stimulating thoughts—the great memes that come one’s way from time to time. 30Sperber and Wilson, 1986, p. 158.
280
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Analogously, one can simply ‘switch off’, making only the smallest effort at 4th order inferencing when served up with the ‘most fragile’ of stories (boring and implausible), as I pointed out in the last chapter and here one would be aided by the ambiguity inherent in turn-taking behaviour. As Sacks has remarked, silence during the course of a story’s telling may indicate recipients’ absorbed interest, but it may also simply be that the recipient has ceased to pay attention to the story.31 Mere ‘[m]’s and ‘aha’s are insufficient to establish, as far as the teller is concerned, whether he still holds recipients’ interest; these can at best be read by the teller as polite signals to continue with his story. Routine evaluative comments (‘How astonishing!’, ‘goodness me!’) may also be mechanically produced. The only really foolproof preventive against boredom is to provide ample space with the turn-taking system for genuine inferences—that is, to activate in listeners’ heads’ the right-hand arm of the inferential model of narrative that I presented in the last chapter. The best, ‘least fragile’ stories (interesting and plausible) leave plenty of ‘slots’ for recipients to make ‘elaborative’ inferences. The triad of concepts, ‘fragility’, ‘plausibility’, and ‘boredom’ are interactional in the basic sense that recipients are required—by the obverse corollary of the Super Maxim of Narrative I’ve postulated (commanding tellers to protect their stories against listeners’charges of implausiblity and/or boringness)—to identify the points of fragility in a story. Being a ‘good listener’ consists of having such excellent vigilance reflexes. The same continuum of reflexes that allows a listener to go into a ‘automatic’ story-appreciation mode when hit with a boring story, also alerts her possible violations of, say, the Maxim of Quality, when an over-ambitious story is placed on the conversational counter. Sacks himself characterizes ‘plausibility’ in terms of ‘what a teller presents as descriptor being used by recipients to assess the creditability of his story’.32 For example, if stories illustrate ‘general truths’ in the shape of particularized accounts of events, then ‘plausibility’ can specifically be analysed in terms of whether recipients recognize a ‘truth’ known to them in the course of the teller’s account. In contrast, if a particular story is told to illustrate a generalization already made in a previous turn, then recipients assess the story as ‘plausible’ or ‘implausible’ in accordance with the generalization already given to them by the teller. The great pleasure that ‘good’ narratives give listeners is that they can truly ‘get into’ a story. By monitoring its points of fragility, they thus ‘get’ the non-fragile core of the narrative—its ‘point’. 31Sacks, Lecture Notes, Spring, 1970. 32 Ibid.
T U R N S A T TA L K
281
Whereas a strong case can be made for the ‘truth’ of a story being independent of whether recipients believe it to be true or not, a story cannot be said to be ‘plausible’ unless recipients in particular conversational contexts judge it to be so. To return then, at the end of this section to the etymologies with which I began, one of the earliest senses of ‘plausible’ that is still retained in my interpretation of the word is that it is ultimately ‘pleasing’ or pleasurable for listeners to interrogate a narrative, and for tellers to be so interrogated. Like the cognitive state of ‘boredom’, conjectures about ‘plausibility’ are only induced when a narrative is closely attended to by listeners or readers. Such attention is in turn the reward that tellers claim. It is in this sense that all the three concepts of plausibility, boredom and fragility are, within the logic of conversation, null and void except in the cognitive context of communication between speaker and hearer. Conventions and Manoeuvres Sacks has remarked, ‘If you watch conversation at all you can see manoeuvering’.33 In the following paragraphs, I shall examine the relationship between participants’ manoeuvres in order to achieve their conversational goals and the constraints which the conventions peculiar to story-telling, place on these manoeuvres. Of the conventions I suggested in Chapter 4, I have dealt with convention 2) or PF at some length earlier in this chapter; 3) CS is treated in detail in my discussion of preparatory condition II on the speech act of story-telling in Chapter 2; and 4) or EC, is illustrated by several examples in Chapters 1 and 4. Instances of the remaining convention 1) of ‘local occasioning’ or LO are now presented below: g) i C
763
b C
771 772
get {SO} fed UP in the ENDx 764 with IIthis sort of ‘FANTASY ‘thingx—765 II AND [ ]x. 766 II I just got BOREDx 767 with II listening to the STORIES {as II WELLx}x768 and II and . and II ALSOx 769 he was II sort of desperately ‘desperately KEENx 770 and II that . that II [?]always . puts me OFFx . [m] II AND [ ] . I IIjust ‘couldn’t BEAR itx 773 II in the ENDx—774 IIhe IIhe . it was II funny how I MET HIMx—775 if IIthat’s the WORDx 776 IIhe [?] IIpicked me Upx 777 in Tra IIfalgar SQUAREx 778 *(—laughs)*
33Sacks, ‘Lecture Notes’, May, 1971.
282
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
b C
779 780
*(—laughs)*. IIand—and II I was going to the THEATREx 781 and [+ STORY]
Margaret Drabble’s fictional character and the ‘real’ speaker C in g)i above appear to share a very common cognitive stance. Being ‘desperately desperately keen’, and showing it by shoving fantastic stories down the throat of one’s prospective audience creates ‘trouble’. It arouses in listeners an instinct for self-preservation, when a teller’s stories overwhelm them to the extent that they can no longer ‘bear it’. The inferential system is simply overloaded. In the present case, the episode with the boring boyfriend is past history, and is ripe to be converted into the former victim’s ‘own’ story— ‘something for us’. C’s first turn from line’s 763 right through to line 773 works like an abstract or ‘story-preface’, as the conversational analysts call it; and b’s back-channel ‘mm’ indicates that she is willing to listen. Hence, when C finally begins her narrative in line 774, ‘... it was funny how I met him’, we can categorize it as a clear instance of LO. This is because the story is directly occasioned by the fact that C and b have been talking about the ‘him’ of C’s forthcoming story in several previous turns. Further, C’s revelation, ‘I just couldn’t bear it in the end’ [italics mine] strongly suggest a story to come about the start of C’s acquaintance with her ‘desperately keen’ suitor. Thus, the teller’s move here is typical; she is constrained by the convention of LO to produce her story in the ‘telling’ slot after it has been well prepared for over several former turns, as well as prefaced by a long ‘orientation’ or ‘abstract’. There are cases, however, where the convention of LO is not, on the face of it, obeyed as obviously. This happens usually when, as Jefferson points out, stories are ‘triggered’ by the ongoing talk, but where the connection between the stories and the ‘triggering’ word or phrase in some previous turn may not be apparent.34 Consider example g)ii: g) ii C
1289
b
1292
II and these people SMILEx 1290 and you [pu]—well you II don’t know how to REACT at FIRSTx1291 because it’s IIso *STRANGEx* *yes* I felt that in Scotland **—yes (—laughs)**
34See Jefferson ‘Sequential Aspects of Story-telling’ on ‘local occasioning’. ‘In general, the occurrence of an utterance at a given moment is accountable, and a basic account is that a next utterance is produced by reference to a prior, that is, is occasioned by it’ (p. 220).
T U R N S A T TA L K
C a b a
1293 1294 1295 1296
b
1297
C a b C b
1298 1299 1300 1301 1300
a b
1302 1303
ALL b C b
1304 1305 1306 1307
283
**(—laughs)** **yes** someone gave me a very nice smile in Dillon’s [m] she was waiting for the life—I just. up while I was writing and she gave me a great big smile . [m] . I [h] overheard a man in Barkers today . asking for a wok—and . I apparently was the only other person there who knew what a wok *was—(—laughs)* *(—laughs)* what is a wok a wok as a **[ ] one of those big** ** II FRYING —’PANx** Chinese frying-pans with rounded bottoms you know that they [swisul] swizzle *things around* in *oh I see* . oh yes— [ ] . and I was able to . call out over several counters . wok (—laugh) do you want a wok I can tell you where to get it (—laughs) and all the assistants talked to me and told me about the bombs and—how bad business was… [+ STORY]
The story b tells of ‘a man in Barkers asking for a wok’ does not at first glance appear consistent with prior talk which has been about participants’ reactions to strangers smiling at them; b being ‘apparently the only other person there who knew what a wok was’, seems to be an irrelevant contribution to the subject of discussion this stage in the conversation. Yet, a closer look at participant a’s earlier turn ‘yes— someone gave me a very nice smile in Dillon’s’ shows that b’s story is in fact locally occasioned (LO), the ‘trigger’ here being the word ‘Dillon’s’. Barker’s, like Dillon’s, is a large department store in London—this is the crucial semantic ‘hook’ on which LO hangs in this conversation. Ethnomethodological scrutiny thus reveals that even stories which do not seem to obey the convention of LO turn out to have been triggered by some previous utterance. In Chapter 8, I identify a few examples where stories do not seem locally occasioned at all and examine the reasons for this unusual failure. Continuing here with my analysis of participant’s manoeuvering and its relation to the conventions of story-telling, we find that the convention
284
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
of LO in this conversation is nicely linked with the convention of CS, namely, completing a story that has been begun.Line 1294, containing a’s utterance in ‘someone gave me a very nice smile in Dillon’s’, could very well be a story-preface, and b’s ‘[m]’ seems to indicate that as a prospective story-recipient she is prepared to listen to the story which is expected to follow. But now notice that a’s utterance 1296, which could at first be taken to be elaborately establishing the setting for the story, ‘she was waiting for the lift—I just up while I was writing’, ends abruptly ‘and she gave me a great big smile’. Hence, from the perspective of recipient b, it cannot but look as though the convention CS which says that there should be a completed story in this slot if a’s line 1294 was indeed intended as a story-preface, is in imminent danger of being violated. If a fails to tell a story in the slot assigned to her, b as the main story-recipient who have given the go-ahead with her listening cue ‘[m]’, has three main options open to her. She can 1. respond by treating a’s line 1296 as a brief but completed story. In other words, she can position a ‘story-appreciation’ generalization in her own slot; this, however, does not appear to be an attractive move in the context of this particular conversation, since many generalized remarks have already been made earlier by participants on the subject of strangers smiling at one. 2. continue with her previous strategy of responding simply with a ‘[m]’ in her next move as well, so that a is forced to continue and complete her story. 3. can offer an appropriate story of her own to fill this slot. Intriguingly, it is this third and last recipient b chooses. I have already pointed out how recipient b cleverly manages to locally occasion her story in this conversation by offering a story about Barkers instead of Dillon’s. I now wish to argue further than the story b finally tells is not, as might be suggested, an independent second story.35 Rather, it is a story offered in lieu of the full, completed story that a was expected to place in this slot. Hence, the story about Dillon’s is specifically replaced by a story about Barkers. Recipient b here takes over the story-teller’s responsibility as a moral agent in the language-game in order to obey the lawful constraint CS. Examples like this illustrate beautifully Sacks’ observation about manoeuvering to make sure, as far as possible, that conventions like LO and CS are obeyed, even in unusual cases where the teller does 35See A.L. Ryave ‘On the Achievement of a Series of Stories’ in Schenkein (ed.), in which he analyzes how second stories get told in conversation.
T U R N S A T TA L K
285
not fulfil her obligations herself. The significance of Sacks’ remark is that the sort of ‘manoeuvering’ we see in conversation is not just driven by conversationalists’ intentional goals but by the structure of conversation itself as well as the specific ‘activities’ that are locally ‘inserted’ into this mechanical ‘slot-and-filler’ turn-taking system. The convention of LO is obviously related, as I indicated in Chapter 4, to the Maxim of Relevance. If a story is locally occasioned, it is by definition related to prior turns, and this provides the teller’s initial rationale for presenting his story as ‘relevant’ to the current talk-exchange. Consequently, non-conformity to LO always results in a violation of the Relevance Maxim and heralds the kind of ‘trouble’ that conversationalists must then take the responsibility of resolving. The convention of CS is, likewise, systematically related to the Maxim of Quantity, which requires a conversationalist to be adequately informative. As with the connection between the Maxim of Quality and the convention of protecting a fragile story, the convention which requires a story-teller to complete a story paradoxically both recognizes the Maxim of Quantity and permits subtle violation of this maxim. That is, story-tellers often include a number of details in their stories when the information they are seeking to convey can easily be more briefly stated. This involves a violation of the Maxim of Quantity; at the same time, the Maxim states that the teller must be adequately informative, and a story cannot be adequately informative unless it is completed. Following the convention CS therefore means that a violation of the Maxim of Quantity becomes implicitly possible, as long as the several ‘redundant’ details that a teller might include are skilfully deployed so that they interest recipients in knowing the ‘end’ of the story. While such details might be considered ‘redundant’ information outside the language-game of story-telling, within the language-game they are crucially important because they engage recipients in the story until it is completed. The convention of protecting the ‘fragility’ of stories or PF is related to the maxim which enjoins conversationalists to be ‘truthful’, though obliquely. The Maxim of Quality is meant to be observed by all conversationalists at all times, but in the case of stories, tellers need not be ‘truthful’ if they can make their stories ‘credible’ to recipients, as I have argued in the section above. Tellers must manoeuvre so that recipients accept their stories as truthful. The convention of protecting a ‘fragile’ story is a necessary convention precisely because if a story were not so protected, then an overt clash with the Maxim of Quality would result, and cooperative engagement in the language-game of story-telling would become impossible.
286
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Given that story recipients are presented with a number of particular ‘facts, which are not immediately verifiable, the quality of ‘plausibility’ on the part of tellers is the only rational alternative to the quality of truthfulness’. This particular language-game can only be played if both recipients and tellers accept that to be ‘plausible’ is to be ‘truthful’ within the conventions of the game. The convention of protecting a ‘fragile’ story both recognizes the importance of the Maxim of Quality and allows tellers to subvert this maxim by substituting a truthful account with a plausible one. Or as Thomas Hardy, most beguiling of Wessex novelists, described the ‘natural logic’ of story-telling: ‘If the story-tellers could ha’ got decency and good morals from true stories, who’d have troubled to invent parables?’ Good stories are tagged with a culturally appropriate ‘moral’ or generalization because this renders them invariably more plausible, although by the same token, not necessarily more truthful. Finally, the convention of EC always observed by recipients is connected, in a relatively straightforward way, to the Maxim of Manner, which urges conversationalists to be polite, tactful, etc. For example, should a story-recipient not position a story appreciation or evaluation in the slot immediately after a story, an implicature of intentional ‘rudeness’ would almost certainly result, though this is an assertion I cannot support with data since recipients in the conversations I have studied have never failed to comply with the convention. But why attempt to spell out such prior connections in the first place, as I have done in painful detail both in Chapter 4 and this one? Well, it has long been a shibboleth of conversational analysis that its researchers work without references to ‘prefigured hypotheses’.36 They do not resort to preconceptions about the conversational objects that they are studying. The video-taperecorder is their god. Jefferson and Schenkein for instance, state that they are ‘in the end, examining the prospects of a “non-intuitive” analytic mentality’37 for the study of conversation. Yet I hope I have shown in this chapter that, just as schematic representations of narrative can gain enormously from a detailed study of the conversational structure into which stories are typically indexed, so ethnomethodological approaches need to be underpinned by more general theories of pragmatics like the Gricean and the Lewisian or my own inferential model of narrativity, which try to link structure to intuition, and conventions to intentions. 36This inspired phrase is Schenkein’s. See ‘Sketch of an Analytic Mentality for the
Study of Conversational Interaction’ in Schenkein (ed.), 1977, p. 2. 37Jefferson and Schenkein, quoted in Schenkein (ed.), p. 2.
T U R N S A T TA L K
287
The origins of ‘ethno’ from the Greek ethnos meaning ‘nation’ should also support me on this; ethnomethodology deals, in essence, with the methods which members of a culture use to work themselves into that culture from day to day, from moment to moment. Conversational analysts’ admirable emphasis on the ‘ordinariness’ of the human enterprises that they focus on should not, however, blind either them or us to the fact that the operative word in the previous sentence is the ‘selves’ in ‘themselves’. I would submit that even the most ‘non-intuitive’ of analytic mentalities requires considerable cognitive investment when their ‘object’ of study is, by definition, the linguistic formation of social selves. We cannot but depend on introspective understanding when dealing with reflexive concepts like’, ‘manoeuvre’, ‘narrative fragility’, ‘agency’, etc. However hard ethnomethodologists try, it is impossible, and perhaps undesirable to attempt to completely ‘de-cognitize’ and ‘de-moralize’ (!) these notions. Meanwhile, we can dwell upon the not altogether irrelevant wisdom of Lewis Carroll’s Duchess: ‘Tut, tut, my child. Everything’s got a moral, if only you can find it.’ In the next two chapters, I will look at some of the more directly ethical and even political questions that arise out of a consideration of narrative as a mode of cultural ‘manoeuvering’. Ill-founded though it might appear from the conversational analytic perspective, the search for moral explanations seems ubiquitious; it is indeed the most everyday of activities among human communities and should therefore directly interest the ethnomethodologists. I feel intuitively sure it would have interested Harvey Sacks at any rate. That is, as Dennett would insist, whether we consciously will it or not, our psychological propensity to turn our narratives into morality engines does seem to drive that troika of conversation, communication and culture, which is our subject in this book.
288
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
7
qQ S E L F, S TAT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y The Politics of Narrative
Narrativity constitutes ... an immanent structure of action. As H. Arendt has it, it is in stories that the ‘who of action’ can be said, i.e., has to be told. Historical narratives, in the sense of historiography and fictional narratives, are grafted on to this immanent narrativity, which equates a human life with one or many ‘life-stories’. ... The self, i.e., the ‘who of action’ does not merely consist in the self-designation of humans as the owners and authors of their deeds, it implies also self-interpretation in terms of the achievements and failures of what we call practices and plans of life ... the ethical evaluation of our actions. The phenomenon which deserves to be underscored here is that, by acting, someone exerts power over somebody else ... this asymmetry within action as interaction between agents and patients ... constitutes the basic occasion for using the other as an instrument, which is the beginning of violence, murder, and still more torture. ... My claim then is that it is violence and the process of victimization generated by violence which invite us to add a deontological dimension to the teleological dimension of ethics. Paul Ricoeur, ‘The Human Being as the Subject Matter of Philosophy’ Salman Rushdie: Would you like to say something now about the codes by which Palestinians recognize each other and about the idea of repetition and excess as a way of existing?. ... Doesn’t this need to go back again and again over the same story become tiring? Edward Said: It does, but you do it anyway. The interesting thing is that there seems to be nothing in the world which sustains the story: unless you go on telling it, it will just drop and disappear. Salman Rushdie: The need to be perpetually told. Edward Said: The other narratives have a kind of permanence of institutional existence. ...
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
289
Salman Rushdie: This is one of the things you criticize from within Palestinianness: the lack of any serious attempt to institutionalize the story, to give it objective existence. Salman Rushdie, ‘A Conversation with Edward Said’ in Imaginary Homelands
Here is dislocation now. The cool eddies of theory edge towards a storm, a flood, the wrath of the gods, and the terrible treason of the clerks. Steps III and IV of the methodological trajectory mentioned almost facetiously in my Introduction were completed—or as complete as I could make them—in the last chapter. This penultimate chapter now steps into deeper waters.1 For one thing, it flaunts a different cast of characters, as well as a change of theme. That theme is political violence. Has narrative theory any voice at all in such a fraught domain? Or is its theoretical ‘story’ too ‘fragile’ to withstand the assault of realpolitik? How do the ‘selves’ iterated in our stories gain an ‘objective existence’—to use, Salman Rushdie’s phrase—by entering the socio-political regimes of ‘institutionalization’? These are the questions to which I will address myself now. Violence, and more specifically, the violence inflicted by an alienated modern state on its powerless citizens, has been the focus of much recent sociological enquiry in India.2 On the basis of this sort of work and the research of the ‘Subaltern’ school of historians, it appears that the postcolonial Indian state has taken over intact many of the working presuppositions of its former rulers, both in its institutional discourses and its governmental praxis. A subalternist perspective on India’s colonial inheritance, when extended to a reading of the current political scenario in India, would seem to suggest that the notorious mai-bap mode of transaction between the homogenized entities, ‘the state’ and ‘the people’—in which the Government is hailed as both mother and father, an absolute donor—still persists from colonial times. Patronage figures in such a relationship, but not identification. Any dispassionate understanding of notions like ‘agency’, ‘subjectivity’ and ‘responsibility for suffering’, such as proffered by the structuralist and speech act theories discussed in my earlier chapters, is pulled up 1This chapter has appeared as an article in the Economic and Political Weekly, May 1997. 2See, for example, Science, Hegemony and Violence: A Requiem for Modernity, edited by Ashis Nandy, Oxford University Press, 1988; Mirrors of Violence: Communities, Riots and Survivors in South Asia, edited by Veena Das, Oxford University Press, 1990; Gyan Pandey, ‘In Defence of the Fragment’, Economic and Political Weekly, 1993.
290
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
short when we discover that the dismemberment of the body of Vac is often gruesomely real. In the wake of an influential historiography based on the belief that a postcolonial state is designed to disinherit, and possibly assault, the very people who are its supposed protegées, theorizing from a safe distance about ‘boring’ and ‘implausible’ stories may simply be inadequate. The high-falutin narratives of ‘fiction and historiography’, as Ricoeur and Arendt remind us, are always ‘grafted onto’ the ‘immanent narrative’ of ordinary ‘life stories’. It is these life-stories, which ethnomethodologists have always claimed as one of their primary objects of study, that come to the fore in this chapter. Earlier, I have suggested that a post-Dennettian analysis would probably postulate two basic categories of narrative— stories of the self and stories to the other. Both these categories merge in the kind of narratives that this chapter examines, as do certain other fundamental semantic categories. Writing as I do from a postcolonial location demands that I begin this chapter by accepting in full the ideological imperatives that drive a politically-informed historiography. At the same time, I will contend here that perhaps schools such as the Subalternist too sharply differentiate ‘natural’ from ‘man-made’ violence, focusing almost entirely on the latter. My argument, following on from the ‘inferential grammar’ of narrativity that I built up in Chapter 5, will proceed thus: if the marginalized narratives of the people who suffer the traumas of floods, earthquakes and fires are actually compared to those of the victims of communal riots, terrorism and police brutality, both sorts of events appear to share common premises. The inferential processes they set in motion are, consequently, similar: both natural-kind and nominal-kind disasters are treated by ‘the common man’ as ‘acts of god’, breaking inexplicably and terrifyingly upon peoples’ heads. God or government, in both cases, the violence these entities inflict has an unpredictable quality. The cultural repertoire on which ‘the people’ draw to cope with the effects of both categories of violence is shared. Strikingly similar also is the post-tragedy intervention of the governmental ‘higher-ups’, the gods. In each set of cases, for example, such intervention consists in the handing out of ex-gratia payments, verification of ‘claims’ by officials, the calling in of the Central Reserve Police, Army, and so forth. For these, and other reasons which I shall shortly outline, the argument is developed here that a subalternist reading of peoples’ suffering, the political virtues of which remain substantial, should nevertheless cease to rely so heavily on the classic philosophical distinction between nominal and natural kinds that underpins many of even our most radical postmodernist insights.
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
291
For a better historiography, it is important not only to recognize marginal discourses but also long-standing and deep cultural affinities between those discourses. In order to grasp the full force of the violence perpetrated today against large segments of the Indian people, it is crucial to concede the relationships that exist between seemingly independent categories of calamity—the ‘natural’ and the ‘denatured’. I will try to illustrate the extreme complexity of these connections by examining three levels of narrative—the official, the popular and the academic—each of which interprets an underlying nominal/natural kind of divide differently, and almost irreconcilably. Contemporary Political Stances Towards Disaster Towards the beginning of the last decade of the twentieth century, several newspapers the world over carried a small item which informed the public that the UN General Assembly had declared it an International Decade of Natural Disaster Reduction (IDNDR), beginning January 1, 1990. India—never a nation to lag behind in taking politically correct action on paper—immediately responded by setting up a National Advisory Council on the IDNDR, as well as, for good measure, a Cabinet Committee on National Calamities ‘to examine, direct and control programmes for reducing the adverse impact of natural calamities, direct and implement relief measures in the wake of a calamity, and supervise implementation of programmes to give effect to the objectives of the IDNDR’. The decision of the UN and the Indian state to arrange programmes that ‘control disaster’ exemplify attitudes that enlightened modern administrations must hold towards large-scale natural calamities. They put within the purview of official governmental responsibility the damage resulting from sources that conventionally have been regarded as ‘acts of God’—floods, earthquakes, droughts, fires, cyclones. Although no human agency can be blamed for the suffering inflicted by a natural disaster, insofar as these incidences are a) increasingly predictable, and thus preventable, and b) traumatic for large numbers of people, any modern government which does not work to ameliorate their effects becomes a morally indictable agent. More obviously, elected governments are held responsible when they fail to prevent, and sometimes promote, those cases of suffering where human instigation is involved, such as communal, race and language riots. Government intervention seems therefore a normative, Gricean, expectation in a modern state, whenever suffering assumes epidemic
292
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
proportions. However, the official management of disparate forms of violence in India today paradoxically seems to have extended, rather than eliminated, those colonial discourses which objectified calamity by homogenizing its causes. Very different kinds of agency are involved in ‘natural kind’ and ‘nominal kind’ disasters, yet the responses of a postcolonial state tend to reduce them to one narrative format, thereby strategically reaffirming its ‘impartiality’, while simultaneously absolving itself of guilt. Narrative Strands and The State of the Story-teller The goal of this chapter is to demonstrate how governmental narratives often exploit the ‘nominal kind/natural kind’ of distinction in the representation of disaster, but that is only part of its purpose. More generally, I want to understand how the philosophical categories, ‘nominal and natural kind’, in relation to three inter-related levels of narrative, in order to develop what might be thought of, rather grandly, I admit, as the beginnings of a ‘feminist critique of bureaucracy’.3 It is almost superfluous to add that the mammoth superstructure of the bureaucracy in India constitutes an almost perfect token of an Althusserian ISA (ideological state apparatus) concerned with the production and maintenance of a hegemonic—i.e., in the Gramscian sense of not merely repressive but necessarily collusive, conversationally enjambed—interdependence between the government and ‘the people’. My argument is that, given the conventional pietistic or ‘moral’ stances required in ‘disaster management’, the state is all of a sudden forced into patristic confrontation with its most distant victims (see example a) Chapter 1), with women as widows and mothers, or children as unclaimed orphans—categories of the dispossessed that it would normally never come into contact with. At least three sorts of narrative agency ‘tangle’ (another Althusserian word!) at such a time, severely complicating those questions of power and its embodiment as speech; gender and its marking of a subaltern status; as well as suffering and its historical representation, that are at the heart of any discussion of ‘self-hood’. The three intersecting levels of narrativity that I have in mind are: 3It was Michael Toolan who first described, only half seriously, I suspect, my enterprise in the current essay as ‘a feminist critique of the bureaucracy’. I thank him now, not merely for the phrase, but also for other vigorous and stimulating discussions over the years. See also my ‘Gender, Genre and Generative Grammar’ in Toolan (ed.) Essays in Contextualised Stylistics (Routledge, London, 1992).
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
293
i) The official or grand narrative of disaster, constructed in order to distance the state from the particularities of pain. Here, the main thematics spun out by the bureaucratic story-tellers concern power, and patronage and the allocation of resources. ii) The people’s own accounts, in the form of oral reports, poems, conclaves or emergency meetings, responses to the questions of activists, government officials, and so on, form counter-narratives to the received history. While such stories are often suppressed in the national context, the work of Subalternist historians has convincingly shown that they constitute a grave potential hazard to the health of official documentation. In this sort of narrative, the chief problematic, in my view, is for tellers to adapt the age-old and familiar cultural repertoires available in the community, to a description of calamities in a postcolonial context, where the idea of community itself has drastically changed. iii) The narrative of the concerned historian for whom such a period of crisis is arguably one where the ‘interpellation’ of the subaltern subject by the state, as Althusser would call it, appears most evident. At such times, that peremptory ‘Hey you!’ from a state official does not just summon the invisible subaltern onto the stage of history, giving her the mere illusion of individual agency, as Althusser implied. It does more. Disaster-time is that estranging time when history is forced to recognize the special character of those victims to whom the state is handing out its ‘aid’. Only true victims, after all, are to be granted aid; not all subalterns are in these special circumstances equally privileged. For the historian, seeking to determine the complex ways in which ‘truth’ is rendered when a community goes into crisis, the important question naturally is—how does one write history, especially the history of events as submerged in the currents of affective memory as, say, a communal riot or a flood? What counts as history, as historical material, and what can legitimately be excluded? Could some kinds of accounts, normally excised from a ‘historical’ representation, like poems written by riot victims, or fictions, be privileged when a historian seeks to describe ‘the moment of suffering’ with maximal accuracy? Is there a ‘deontology’, a robust ethics, on which a historian in his role of ‘recording angel’ can rely? Before I go on to examine how these three narrative strands: the official, the localized and the historical, plait, and then curl away from each other, a more detailed discussion of nominal and natural kinds is perhaps in order.
294
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Natural and Nominal Kinds, Expert Knowledge and the Story-tellers of the State Among philosophers, Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, Donald Davidson, S.G. Schwartz, Stephen Pulman, and Tyler Burge, have in recent times contributed to the discussion of a pair of concepts which seem to possess a certain intuitive simplicity. Natural kinds exist in the world independent of human creativity. They are entities like mountains, tigers, cactus plants and gold, or events like storms, fires, and earthquakes. Subjects of empirical investigation and inductive generalizations, natural kinds, as a rule of thumb, are discovered rather than invented. Nominal kinds are artifacts like monuments, thermos flasks, cold cream, governments, or processes like steel-smelting, story-telling or typing. Objects of deductive reasoning, nominal kinds can apparently be analytically reduced to the sum of their parts, being human creations. However, philosophical difficulties arise because there are several areas where the categories are not clear-cut. Kripke, for example, has suggested that since it is not ordinarily possible to tell simply by looking whether something is, say, truly gold or not, we need expert knowledge within a community to appeal to in ambiguous cases. But Kripke’s ‘expert knowledge’4 is not always a-political scientific know-how, and it is here that the problem begins to get knotty, tangled. In most real-life situations in a postcolonial state,‘expert-knowledge’ is not earned but assigned. It resides with ‘the authorities’—a faceless phrase Indians recognize only too well. Charged with handling, and handing down, expertise to ‘the masses’ are these institutional representatives of the state—clerks, judges, compounders, IAS officers, politicians. Especially, when large-scale calamities such as the Bhopal gas tragedy, or the Gujarat earthquake afflict a population, the authorities make their presence felt in no uncertain terms. They decide, more or less absolutely, who is a victim and to what extent, how much state compensation is owed; they arbitrate between ‘fake’ and ‘real’ suffering, and even on whether to declare incidences calamitous or not. Thus you can have a Laloo Yadav in Bihar brushing off reports of a Kala Azar epidemic in Bihar, or a Kalyan Singh in UP hushing up riots in his state, since political power enables ‘ministers’ to assert expert status in almost every matter relating to the people with whose well-being they are charged. This misappropriation of ‘expert knowledge’ is most apparent in the totalizing narratives that the state and the media put out on the effects of 4Kripke, Saul A., Naming and Necessity, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1980.
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
295
disaster. As the People’s Union for Democratic Rights (PUDR) and other records of, for example, the Bhagalpur riots reveal, there are many ways in which a biased press and a callous government can misrepresent ‘news’, but this chapter will concentrate on just one aspect of that wide spectrum. Whenever the Government is implicated in tragedies such as the 1990 Sura liquor poisoning, or the 1991 October fire in the Govindpuri slums, I will argue that it cunningly reduces the scope of its responsibility by representing such nominal kind of happenings where the agency is definitely human, as natural kind ‘acts of God’. For instance: GOVINDPURI JHUGGI FIRE TOLL 16. Police and fire servicemen extricated 16 bodies, mostly of children between one and ten years old. ... Sunday’s fire shook the city. Two Ministers of State, Mr M.M. Jacob (Home Affairs) and Mr Arunachalam (Urban Development), accompanied by the local M.P., Mr Sajjan Kumar, inspected the relief work personally. Mr Jacob had visited the spot last evening too, and instructed Delhi Administration officers to provide adequate relief and medical facilities to the displaced. Talking to reporters, Mr Jacob expressed concern at the deteriorating conditions of the Capital’s slums. He was non-commital on the demand of the local M.P. to provide 25-yard residential plots to each family. Mr Jacob, along with the Urban Development minister, assured the victims that adequate measures would be taken to ameliorate their condition. The Prime Minister is likely to visit the site today (Tuesday). According to reports, Mr Narasimha Rao had originally planned to visit Govindpuri on Monday afternoon, but could not due to some ‘pressing engagements’. Meanwhile, a joint team of the Central Forensic Science Laboratory, Hindustan Petroleum, and Delhi Fire Service were conducting an enquiry to determine what had caused the fire. The Hindustan Petroleum experts were called in to check reports that the fire was caused by a gas cylinder explosion. (The Statesman, 1 October 1991).
Several features of this report illustrate my thesis. Note that the fire, a natural kind, is the main agent, the ‘baddie’. Foregrounded is the presence of politicians and police, the goodies. In stark contrast, we do not hear the narrative voice of a single parent, yet it is their children who have died so terribly. The jhuggi is referred to as a ‘site’, and the ‘deteriorating condition of the Capital’s slums’ appears a self-perpetuating phenomenon, a natural growth with which it would be absurd to connect either Mr Jacob or the party he represents. The use of verbs like ‘instructed’ further emphasize the distance between Mr Jacob, who is just ‘visiting’, and the ‘victims’. The fact that Jacob, despite his ‘concern’ can be nonchalantly ‘non-committal’ when it comes to a specific ‘demand’, shows how the powers of decision rest entirely with some distanced administration that belongs elsewhere and has endless non-specified ‘pressing
296
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
engagements’. And then, of course, there is the routine presence of ‘experts’—the backbone of Kripke’s expert knowledge systems—who will act on behalf of the authorities, to trace the cause of the fire to a faulty gas-cylinder, or some such source. True, fire is a classic natural kind, but is a faulty cylinder the real cause of the Govindpuri fire? By under-playing human agency and emphasizing the physical aspects of the disaster, that is, deliberately using a bureaucratic discourse that blurs the natural/nominal kind distinction, the narrative of the state, as presented in the media, manages to erase ‘suffering’ from its text. And where suffering is so successfully deleted, questions of responsibility for this suffering no longer remain relevant. In the case of the Sura tragedy, similar reporting was actually supported by an earthquake epicentre-type map showing ‘places where Sura casualties were reported’. Again, Sura is the main agent, treated as a natural kind, which sends ‘shock-waves’ through the sensitive upper echelons of bureaucratic power. Excessive drinking of methyl alcohol was stated to be the cause of death. As doctors sought hard to save as many lives as possible, the mounting death toll sent shock waves through Raj Niwas and the Nirman Bhawan office of the Central Excise Ministry. The Excise Commissioner, Mr R. Narayanan, was reported to be huddled in a meeting with the Lieutenant Governor, Mr Markandey Singh, just as his police counterpart, Mr Arun Bhagat was. Officials at the directorate of health lamented that the Government’s policy to help, encourage and support traditional medicinal systems had paved the way for the production and sale of illicit liquor, ostensibly as sura. Officials blamed courts for taking away their enforcement rights by passing injunction orders to allow the sale of sura without a licence. (The Statesman, Friday, 8 November 1990).
Once more, disproportionate narrative attention is focused on officials who ‘lament’ that their good intentions have somehow, quite without their knowledge, been circumvented. The police and judiciary are again a felt presence on the front page, while the narratives of the bereaved are relegated to the back of the newspaper—protocols of reportage that make suffering a secondary issue, government activity primary, and sura or ‘country liqour’ the main criminal, rather than the complicity of the state agencies. And an uncanny resemblance to the subaltern historian David Arnold’s archival material on the late colonial response to the Indian Plague of 1896–1900 is accentuated when one reads in the newspaper reports of the sura deaths that: There were rows and acrimony when police moved in at the Anand Parbat and Adarsh Nagar Crematoriums to retrieve the bodies of victims from the fire as
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
297
warranted under the law in the case of unnatural death. Mortuaries at the Hindu Rao Hospital and the nearby old Sabzi Mandi in North Delhi remained clogged with scores of bodies, as doctors tried hard to conduct post-mortems. Heartrending scenes could be witnessed as grieving relatives wailed outside the mortuaries.
Arnold’s description of colonial procedures runs: In the Bombay Presidency it was decreed that bodies could not be buried or cremated until they had been inspected by a qualified doctor to ascertain whether plague had been the cause of death. With scores of deaths occuring daily in towns and cities, this might entail a delay of many hours before funeral rites could be proceeded with. ... The carrying out of post-mortems on plague victims was widely resented. Interference with customary funeral rites ... gave rise to several demonstrations of defiance (attack on plague camp at Hardwar, etc.)5
The point of Arnold’s subalternist argument is that during the plague years the human body became a metaphoric as well as physical site of conflict between the colonial state and a subject people. If this analysis seems plausible, then similar scenes in postcolonial India may warrant a similar interpretation of the relation between oppressive state agencies and the people affected in a disaster. Grief, resentment, sorrow—it appears that the state deals with the emotional residue of tragedy by simple ‘decree’ and the adoption of an agent-deleting passive voice which reinforces the impression of ‘grand narrative’. Such linguistic ploys still leave them, to be sure, with the administrative dirty job of cleaning up after a plague or fire have unaccountably ‘struck’, but consign effectively to amnesia any embarassing pre-disaster memories of official negligence. People’s Narratives, Gender and Cultural Repertoires It was the feminist Madhu Kishwar who made the point some years ago that cold waves do not kill people, what kills is not having adequate shelter or protection. That is, not a natural cause but a ‘denatured’ society must be held responsible for such deaths. Disasters, natural and nominal, seem to affect the same segments of Indians repeatedly—the economically deprived urban lower classes, often migrants from an India-wide hinterland, and the rural poor. Their narratives are the narratives of a brave and stubborn survival against great odds, and are structured 5Arnold, David, ‘Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900’, in Selected Subaltern Studies edited by Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakraborty Spivak, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford, 1988, p. 402.
298
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
entirely differently from official accounts, yet they too blur the nominal/ natural kind of dichotomy in accordance with yet another set of cultural norms. The Partition of 1947 was a man-made calamity that affected millions in Bengal; while the very severe floods of 1978 rendered thousands homeless in West Bengal. However, in archival accounts of both types of disaster, the people’s narrative seem to make use of a basic vocabulary, an arrangement of verbal structures that draws on a repertoire of stoic attitudes towards suffering, cultivated over time. These constitute a durable set of coping strategies that can, if called upon, also cleverly express resistance to external, i.e., official pressures. Another feminist, Urvashi Butalia, has extensively recorded, for example, women’s narratives of Partition.6 Her transcripts illustrate some of the strategic conversational moves possible in narrativizing memories of anguish.For example: Q: What is your memory of childhood from Barisal? Say just before you left Barisal. A: We stayed on. We meant to stay and stayed on. ... We were two poor sisters. People were asking us who was accompanying us; we told them we were with our brother who had just gone to fetch some food. We didn’t want to let them know that we were all alone. After the departure of three trains, we managed to get on to the fourth. After much trouble we arrived at Sealdah at 2 o’ clock at night. Where could we go at such an hour? We spread a blanket on the platform and waited. ... The police officer put us in a bus for Ballygunge. We went up to Ballygunge station. From the station we hired a rickshaw. We kept asking people for directions, and finally we found the place opposite the Triangular Park. And then we stayed there. It was a painful experience. We were very unwanted and they did not like our presence. There were also some ruffians who would pester us and insult us continuously. Young girls were at their mercy. A man used to follow me everyday when I got off the bus. I told my sister ... and one day she caught hold of him and accused him of following me. There was a big scuffle in the camp. Afterwards we moved to Naktala camp. It was only because we had ‘free rations’ that we managed to keep alive in that camp. I used to go to Howrah station godown in the morning to collect free rations. ... I had some special favours because the man in charge of the distribution held me in high esteem because I belonged to a high caste. I was given finer saris. I don’t know what 6I am very grateful to Urvashi Butalia for allowing me such generous access to the
conversational archive she has documented relating to survivors’ memories, and especially women’s recollections, of Partition.
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
299
you think of such things but I regard them to be destiny. Because of this good fortune we received those fine clothes which we shared among ourselves. Life in Naktala was very hard. After my brothers and sisters had eaten their meal I would have the leftovers—that is how I survived. There weren’t any more free rations. ... The majority have suffered for the benefit of a few. This is how I see it as an ordinary person. I never participated in any party politics. But I always stood in protest to what I considered bad. Leaving aside politics and parties, I strongly believe that Partition happened for a small section of society. ... But who they are? I understand well that it is for the benefit of a few and not of all. If it was for everybody, then we would not have suffered so much. Q: From your own experience what you consider to be the best lesson for the next generation? A: I have learnt from life that no struggle is in vain and no pain is a waste. ...
From this sort of primary material, an initial feature, so obvious as to go unnoticed, that must be registered about people’s recountings of disaster, is the fact that they are usually couched in the ephemeral, oral, resistant-to-inscription conversational medium. This is a chief source both of their on-the-record meekness and their off-the-record subversive potential. A brief example from my own recordings of flood narratives in the Midnapur district of West Bengal, treated more extensively in the next chapter, might help me elaborate this point.7 A: What you—um—feel worst about is ... those who’ve grown old ... for them. A neighbour of ours ... he went ... he was working there, [and] on the Kolaghat bridge stood an old—very old person—what happened to this person was—he stood a long while in the—um—he’s standing in the water— the rain (constantly) drips down on him from the roof to the shelter ... his whole back is covered with sores ... the water keeps dripping ... there’s no way one can move ... he’s hanging on by holding on to a stake ... what suffering! Things continued like this. ... B: What suffering people have to go through! A: It was like this for two whole days—that means he stood there for five days in this condition. His hands were covered with watery, watery ... sores. That’s exactly what was happening—destruction of the hands and feet.
No academic summation could do the tellers of these stories justice, especially within the conventions of a ‘historcizing’ academic discourse 7These disaster narratives were initially documented as a student attached to a party
of Government of West Bengal officials and CPM party cadre visiting villages in the aftermath of the extremely severe floods of 1978.
300
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
where one has perforce to select and dissect. The sheer physical suffering captured in my recordings and the great mental endurance shown by in the extract from Butalia’s corpus discourage any attempt at a glib and superior commentary. The description I offer now will focus on just a single aspect of a startlingly rich and resilient corpus. This aspect concerns the ways in which women’s narratives differ from men’s in their reconstruction of a lost world. As we know, the place of women in a subalternist history is currently contentious because while some critics like Spivak8 have critiqued the Subaltern project for a degree of insensitivity to the problematic of women, others like Chatterjee9 have optimistically contended that women’s writings, as well as their sheer presence, in (their own and others) letters, autobiographies and fictions—preserved a crucial place for traditional values during a period of embattled nationalism. Whereas Chatterjee focuses on the largely introspective struggle of middle-class Bengali women in the nineteenth century to make their hard-won literacy speak for them, however, I am concerned with the oral accounts of rural women in a postcolonial state, actors whose agency it is almost impossible to recover in the written medium because they are, and have always been, kept at a safe distance from any kind of even elementary literacy. Their subjectivity is narrativized around a thematics of survival rather than of self-expression. These voices seem to be heard only in times of dire calamity, when they are, as I have suggested earlier, ‘instantly’ historicized by a self-serving interpellation on the part of the state. In my understanding, the genderlect of women in contemporary rural Bengal confronting the kind of archetypal act of god that a flood is, exemplifies distinctive linguistic features. These characteristic linguistic markers, I argue, enable us to make connections between affect or emotivity in the causal structure of narrative and the cultural role that women’s narratives have, or may have, in controlling and conditioning others, including the state’s, attitudes towards suffering. My own extensive tape-recordings of women’s speech display, in contrast to men’s idiom, the following features: 8See, for instance, Spivak’s ‘Introduction’ to the volume mentioned in footnote 5, pp. 26–32 and several subsequent pieces, most famously in ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?’ in Marxism and the Interpretaion of Culture, edited by Cary Nelson and Larry Grossberg, University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1988, followed by a couple of essays in Outside in the Teaching Machine, Routledge, London, 1993, and Chapters Ten and Eleven of A Spivak Reader, Routledge, 1996. 9Chatterjee, Partha, The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories, Oxford University Press, Delhi, 1994; Chapters Six and Seven, ‘The Nation and its Women’, and ‘Women and the Nation’.
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
301
1. 2. 3. 4. 5.
more exclamatives (ore baba, ma go, ki bhishon, bap re bap); more comparators (khub, bhishon, boddo); more silences, breaks, reformulations; more interruptions resulting in more joint tellings; more politeness forms, address and agreement markers (ki didi, boshben naki, ektu jol khan) 6. more deictics (eta, ekane, eidje) Apart from having less of everything, I noted that men’s speech in the same fraught context showed a proneness to generalizations (‘disaster seems to strike us in nine-year cycles’, ‘no one knew where the next meal was coming from’) and the use of external place-names (Calcutta, Diamond Harbour, Delhi, Birbhum). It should perhaps be emphasized here that these linguistic features do not refer directly to ‘topic’; of course, the women talked about different things from the men as well, but the characteristic speech-markers that differentiated men from women were independent of the subject being discussed, in this case, the recent floods. This ‘independence of topic’ has the consequence that the bundle of conversational features identified here, given the fact that rural women have, with rare exceptions, always been denied access to literacy codes, make up a chief means of identifying women as social agents. They are a cultural guide to woman, and and the role she plays in narrativizing her community. How do you recover a lost past? Only through words, words that recall and sometimes enrich and amplify the memories of the possessions, emotional as well as physical, that one held in the antediluvian past. In the case of a flood or fire, the physical evidence has vanished forever. All has been devoured by calamity. In this tabula-rasa world, therefore, infinite imaginative possibilities are opened up—one can, so to speak, theoretically remake oneself through one’s narratives. Yet, the situation is far from being one of painless make-believe. The calamity itself is historically attested. State, institutions, news agencies all work it into their operations. Thus, when the bureaucracy descends to ‘assess’ the situation, it is most natural that the primary narrators, men and women, use deictic references to the devastated scene around them as gestures of witness. In the specific cases that I’m reporting on, the reality of the damage wrought by the floods was painfully apparent in visual terms. It spoke for itself. The urgent business at hand thus became not so much to ‘prove’ that the floods had caused damage as to ensure that the Government would provide substantial and speedy assistance. This resulted, often, in a shift of narrative focus and theme
302
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
from the emotional to the economic, from the personal to the pragmatic. Here is a fragment of an actual letter, written by a flood victim in Orissa, Nand Kishore Barik, to his employer in a metropolis, reproduced here with his permission: Sri sri charaneshu Respected Sir, You will take my namaskars I am very sorry due to the terrible evil. On the 26th May last a violent storm (cyclone) with showers of rain and its companions (thunder and lightening) had took place in our Area. As a result, many a house, many a tree, were destroyed by blowing of the cyclone. The roof of my house has blown away and a palm tree, a bamboo bush has broken on account of the blowing of heavy rain and wind. So, I have lost the amount of Rs.1500/- in my own wealth for the effect of the cyclone. Before it happened, I had already sown the seeds in my fields. Now, those have sunk in the flood water. I don’t know what to do. I think fifteen days I shall spend my time to repair it. ...
Although this letter is in the written rather than the spoken mode, it demonstrates aptly the shift from the almost poetic medium of personal turmoil to the hard facts of economic deprivation. Natural kind disaster (cyclone) shifts gear into nominal kind (loss of wealth). Part of the ‘poetic’ effect of this letter is no doubt because it has been translated from colloquial Oriya into a slightly archaic English (‘many a house, many a tree’, etc.) by the village scribe—English still being the language of official communication and this particular inheritance of colonial plantation having clearly ‘sown seeds’ deep. However, perhaps an even more striking aspect of the idiom employed by Nand Kishore Barik’s scribe is its derivation from a tradition of letter-writing that begins with a respectful invocation to a diety (sri sri charaneshu) and the folded-hand gesture of respect (namaskar). It is precisely because these inscriptional gestures impute to Barik’s employer not only a social but also a moral, deontological superiority, that they possess implications for a more general analysis of the relationship between disaster victims and the governmental elite who control state funds. Narrative accounts of both Partition and flood constitute a community’s fragile resources for recuperating historical agency—and they display one shared characteristic. Both ‘nominal kind’ and ‘natural kind’ narrators invariably treat the government, even when it has been elected by them, as a power as unpredictable and unknowable as God. For example, in 1978, as a student, I witnessed government officials from Calcutta being surrounded by villagers and importuned as if they had
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
303
descended from above, in many cases they were explicitly compared to devatas (literally translated as ‘gods’). In other words, the narrative vocabulary of disaster was flexibly adapted to both flatter the god-like representatives of the government who had kindly come down to rescue the people from their plight, and at the same time strip them of a common humanity. This strategy, which I will call the trope of deification10 recalls Ricoeur’s ‘claim’, quoted at the beginning of this chapter, that ‘it is violence and the process of victimization generated by violence which invite us to add a deontological dimension to the teleological dimension of ethics’. It is precisely that ‘deontological dimension’ or the call to duty, combined with other strategies of discourse where narrators loudly blame their own fate, or their sins in past lives for their current suffering, which enabled victims to launch a bitter verbal attack on a callous ‘system’, without offending those on whose whims they depended. The ‘simple’ narratives of the people thus turn out to be extremely sophisticated in their modes of subversion. They express anger, pain and frustration, while at the same time managing to contain and conceal these wrenching emotions. On this depends their precarious survival. The Wound in the Text Disasters are unpredictable, if not by definition, then at least by implication. They constitute a sudden violent disruption of the even tenor of existence. Textually, then, an event of disaster could be trivially matched in an essay like this one by some intervention that destroys the continuity of argument. In this section, there occurs such a textual event, which does not fall in docilely with what came before and will come after. First, a wrenching of style. It is a well-established convention in academic essays that they often eliminate an authorial persona, thus bolstering an impression of objectivity . The critic’s ‘who of action’, as Ricoeur puts it, is hardly ever the subject of critical ‘evaluation’, and it is this convention I begin by breaking with, not dramatically, but at least in subdued mutiny, changing initially just the background of the essay, so that academic complicity stands revealed. Scene-setting: no longer rural Bengal. Instead, I am in the University Bookstore in Seattle a few days after I have delivered a version of this 10A question by Raimonda Modiano prompted me to think of deification as a powerful trope in the conduct of conversations with officialdom. I am grateful to her for the insight.
304
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
chapter at the Jackson School of International Studies. Meandering aimlessly through the aisles, a book, glossily red, glistening with the preternatural significance of blood, catches my eye. It is called The Writing of the Disaster by Maurice Blanchot.11 I remember the name Blanchot because I have just walked over from an ‘installation’ at the University Museum, which has enigmatic quotations from Blanchot magnified a thousand-fold and projected onto the walls as a bemused audience passes from room to room. Quotations are therefore very much on my mind. Having seen them in so gigantic a form recently, I am struck by their power to humble the reader and to speak in the authoritative deificatory voice that I have been struggling to identify as the hallmark of superior bureaucratese. Blanchot’s book is devoted to understanding the horror of the inexplicable, namely the Nazi pogroms, actions which offer perhaps the most incontrovertible evidence in modern history of the terrors which result when the state plays uncompromisingly at being God. How exactly do Blanchot’s comments fit in with my own reading of disaster narratives in a postcolonial state? I confess I do not know. What I do know is that they had a powerful effect on my earlier interpretation of disaster—for whereas I’d so far thought in terms of a plurality of disasters, nominal and natural, Blanchot condensed all disasters, past and future, to this one event in history: The Disaster. Concentrated in this fashion, disasters seemed to be entirely a nominal kind, a cultural focal point for the analysis of the power of evil, human evil, institutionalized evil. I remembered again Nand Kishore Barik’s unselfconscious sentence at the beginning of his letter, ‘I am sorry due to this terrible evil’. For Barik ‘evil’ resided without, it was a cosmic quirk of nature. Ordinary humans were never meant to comprehend it. For Blanchot, on the contrary, evil lay within, a twist of conscience, explicable with reference neither to an all-powerful God nor to the laws of Nature. In short, inexplicability was differently assigned in the two cases. It was this difference in conceptualizing disaster that seemed to give Blanchot’s ‘writing of the disaster’ its peculiar force. Furthermore, in attempting to describe the incomprehensibility of the human soul, his words themselves seemed to resist easy assimilation; they would not alter to fit in with the relatively standard format of my chapter. In the event, the best I can do is to quote directly from Blanchot, without explanation, as the walls in Seattle’s museum did. This literal 11Blanchot, Maurice L’Écriture de Désastre, translated by Ann Smock, University of
Nebraska Press, Lincoln and London, 1986.
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
305
‘writing on the wall’ will, I hope, enable the reader make what connections she/he will between my argument and his. Here it occurs to me, ironically, that quotations, inserted forcefully into the body of a text, as in the present instance, can themselves be regarded as repeated metaphors of violence—both violating the text, as it were, and gendering it. If Althusser’s focus was on interpellation, then Blanchot’s might be said to be interpolation; Blanchot, a cultural stranger, thus enters my postcolonial narrative brandishing, as he himself phrases it, a ‘radical unquotability’: The disaster ruins everything, all the while leaving everything intact ... the gift that ... would liberate us from everything ... There is disaster only because, ceaselessly, it falls short of disaster. The end of nature, the end of culture. We are passive with respect to the disaster. ... The disaster does not allow us to entertain this question either: what have you done to gain knowledge of the disaster?. ... Not to answer is the rule—or not to receive any answer. If there is a relationship between writing and passivity, it is because both presuppose the effacement, the extenuation of the subject: both presuppose a change in time ... one can speak of an infinite passivity. ... We can evoke situations of passivity: affliction; the final crushing force of the totalitarian State, with its camps. ... In all these cases, we recognize even though it be with falsifying, approximating knowledge, common traits: anonymity, loss of self; loss of all sovereignty, but also of all subordination; utter uprootedness, exile, the impossibility of presence, dispersion (separation). Thus does the patience of the disaster lead us to expect nothing of the ‘cosmic’ ... if we succeed in disengaging it from the idea of order, of regularity guaranteed by law. For the ‘disaster’, a rip forever ripping apart, seems to say to us: there is not, to begin with, law, prohibition, and then transgression, but rather there is transgression in the absence of prohibition, which eventually freezes into Law, the Principle of Meaning. The disaster, unexperienced. It is what escapes the very possibility of experience—it is the limit of writing. This must be repeated: the disaster describes. ... Boneyard of names, never empty. ... The disaster is related to forgetfulness, forgetfulness without memory. ... The calm, the burn of the holocaust, the annhilation of noon—the calm of the disaster. Concentration camps, annhilation camps, emblems wherein the invisible has made itself visible forever. Learn to think with pain.
Fictionality and the Historian’s Dilemma Blanchot speaks of the disaster as ‘the ultimate experience’ because it is indescribable; it is beyond poetry, beyond words, beyond the power of
306
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
human agents to render except in tattered verbal fragments. Although his tone is vastly different from Blanchot’s, Gyan Pandey (1993) makes a similar point when he analyses the historiography of communalism in an article entitled, unsurprisingly, ‘In Defence of the Fragment’. Pandey argues that frameworks of academic analysis, such as Marxism, which show how riots, epidemics, etc., result from the play of larger economic and social forces, almost seem to rob ‘the people’ of ‘agency’, a hand in their own fate. In other words, it makes them precisely the subjects of what Blanchot calls ‘an infinite passivity’ perpetuated through writing. Yet if one were to direct Pandey’s critique of Marxism towards the role of the historian, it seems to me the academic historian cannot help but mimic in significant ways the stance of the Government official. That is, she/he is usually at a considerable distance from the pain and agony experienced by the victims of disaster and thus faces a challenge in attempting to provide an adequate representation of their suffering. In effect, can a historian in the pursuit of his profession ever manage to obey Blanchot’s italicized admonishment: Learn to think with pain? Moreover, if she/he does manage to somehow acquire such an apparently paradoxical mode of thought, will it put within the historian’s reach an ethics which logically eludes the bureaucratic scribe in the pursuit of his profession? Pandey thinks one solution to this problematic is for historians to include within their descriptions the marginalized narratives of individual victims, so as achieve a more textured ‘truth’. At least two difficulties immediately arise, however. First, the ‘people’s narratives’ are generally told to outsiders, to activists or officials, for obvious reasons. Within your own community, your suffering is already ‘known’, experienced; there is thus no explicit need to ‘tell’ shared pain. Or, to as Blanchot puts it, in their world ‘the invisible has made itself visible forever’. When a victim of disaster does tell her pain, to the activist or the official, the cultural repertoire on which she draws is intentionally fashioned, as I have tried to show, to minimize both pain and agency, and to give the personal a pragmatic ‘cover’, so that grief does not seem gratuitous but contributes to the ‘business at hand’—obtaining relief supplies expeditiously, for instance. The net effect of these strategies, inevitably, distances the teller from her tale, and the tale from the listener. Victims’ accounts, typically have the chill calm: ‘the burn ... the annihilation of noon—the calm of disaster’. No naive conception of the immediacy, and particularity of pain, will serve the historian well here. People supposedly robbed of agency by historical forces and by historians’ representations, can produce
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
307
subtle narratives which in their turn rob their oppressors of personhood and individualism, by, for instance, the ironic device of turning them into pseudo-gods. Such complex narrative strategies require that the cultural coding of disaster in a postcolonial society, and the uses to which traditional vocabulary is re-adapted, must first be understood (for example, the ‘emblematic’ part played by references to gods, fate, kinship paradigms, etc., in the discourse of suffering obviously does a lot of cultural ‘work’), before they serve the historian’s cause. The second difficulty has to do with extending the analytical domain of history to include poetry, as Pandey has suggested, in cases where affect is obviously an important part of circumstantial ‘truth’. However, it is often held, as we know, that the historian is unable by the very terms of his profession to attempt an account of this sort of ‘truth’. For, such a procedure would surely ‘transgress’ what Blanchot calls the ‘Law’ or the conventions of prohibition—in this case the disciplinary norms binding on historians. After all, if poetry is admitted as historical evidence, why not fictionalized history? Should short stories, novels, docu-dramas about the police blindings in Bhagalpur, the mass rape of women during Partition, the terrible scenes of the Latur and Gujarat earthquakes, be admitted as authentic ‘history’ because they describe affect, in a manner the historian cannot avail of? Most historians would protest that their discipline is committed to producing narratives where causality above all is emphasized. Academic histories are motivated by explanatory concerns12; representing suffering ‘artfully’, thus comes a poor second to marshalling evidence that establishes the agencies responsible for that suffering. This may be so, but the vexed—and decidedly postmodern—question that Gyan Pandey has raised remains vexed— how is the historian to give due weight to affect in his work? In another but related context, the philosopher Richard Rorty has discussed how philosophical writing might deal with affect. Rorty’s position is that concepts like freedom, solidarity and suffering are best 12On the issue of explanatory concerns, we might refer to Paul Ricoeur’s remarks on
narrative as ‘the keeper of human time’ that preface this essay. As Maria Villela Petit points out in her article on Ricoeur in the volume mentioned in footnote 1, one of his central themes is the relationship of the fictional narrative to the historical archive. Ricoeur shows a special awareness of the work of the Annales School of historians in France, who in turn have influenced the Subalternist historiographers of the subcontinent. Ricoeur writes: ‘... historians are not simply narrators, they give reasons why they consider a particular factor rather than some other to be the sufficient cause of a given course of events. ... Placed in the real or potential situation of a dispute, they attempt to prove that one explanation is better than another.’ (Time and Narrative,Vol. I, p.186 and p. 175).
308
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
understood not by philosophical works but by literary ones.13 With the best will in the world, the philosopher cannot ‘explain’ these notions. She/he can at best conduct a dialogue with the writers who are, so to speak, the Kripkean ‘experts’ in this field. Indeed it might be said that Rorty’s line on the matter is, ‘the statement shall wither away and be replaced by the subjunctive’. Or to put it in another way, ‘if-then’ clauses—the classic structures of causality—should yield to ‘ifs’—the classic structures of fiction when a discussion of emotion is involved. Now, this alleged ‘failure’ of the philosopher to produce satisfactory deductive generalizations about emotion, and that of the historian to produce empirical generalizations about ‘suffering’ are, in my view, comparable because they centre on the same paradox. The paradox has the following shape: fiction can and indeed must describe individual protagonists, if it is to move hearts. Dickens’ canvas is the French Revolution in his A Tale of Two Cities, Rabindranath Tagore’s subject in Gora is India’s relationship with the Empire, Bhisham Sahni’s theme the nobility and terror of Partition in Tamas, Tolstoy’s the immensity of War and Peace, but they all work through characters whom we meet face to face. Disaster assumes identity in a creative text, comes to have what Shakespeare called ‘a local habitation and a name’. History, on the other hand, necessarily involves numbers. It was E.H. Carr who said, in effect, in What is History? , that had Caesar crossed the Rubicon alone, the incident would have passed unnoticed. When he crossed it with an army of soldiers—that became a ‘fact of history’.14 Numbers make history, as every historian recognizes—so many hundred killed in an earthquake, so many murdered in a riot. But in order to render emotion, you need the individual mode, which can only be literary and artistic. That is the paradox. To be a player in the grand narrative of state, even as a lead actor, you need to be part of a larger whole. And huge numbers tend towards homogenization/hegemonies. It is for this reason that the historian can never, given the nature of his professional domain, individualize his 13Rorty, Richard, Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cambridge University Press, 1989. 14Carr, E.H., in What is History? Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1990, pp. 11 and
49–50. ‘It is the historian who has decided for his own reasons that Caesar’s crossing of that petty stream, the Rubicon, is a fact of history, whereas the crossing of the Rubicon by millions of other people before or since interests nobody at all. ... The historian will not in ordinary circumstances need to take cognizance of a single discontented peasant or discontented village. But millions of discontented peasants in thousands of villages are a factor which no historian will ignore.’
S E L F, S T AT E A N D S O L I D A R I T Y
309
narrative, narrow it down to the poignant story of one or two individuals from the inside. That interior, individual account would not then be history, even if it involved historical personages. It would tend towards fiction. The tension that exists between history and literature involves generic differences of scale, and of interiority. One is centrally concerned with the description of mammoth events, and the other with representation of individual emotion. Perhaps this is too simple a turn, but it does show why the dilemma of ‘the historian with a heart’, is inherent; it can never be completely resolved. I want to emphasize, however, that this use of a vocabulary which resonates with the emotional connotations of the word ‘heart’ should not be taken to imply that we are returning to the bad old subjective/objective division of labour between literary and historical depiction. Disasters, natural and nominal, by reason of their scale, are the stuff of history. Yet, of the three kinds of narrative that I have discussed in the paper it is historians alone who strictly keep these kinds apart, privileging nominal kind calamities over natural kinds in their writings, not only because they possess analytic minds, but because agency seems much more attributable in these cases. This could be a fallacious judgement. Given the distanced nature of the postcolonial state, and its agencyerasing narratives, as well as the fragmentary narratives of the people which also avoid, often with prescient wisdom, directly condemning anyone, historians have a greater duty than ever to analyse ‘agency’ thoroughly. It is clearly the case that agency is a slippery customer, going underground in most ‘on-record’ narratives. Further, as the blurring of nominal/natural kind categories in these narratives demonstrates, neither ‘the state’ nor ‘the people’—and certainly not women narrators— are so unsophisticated as to suppose that the one involves only the victims of viciousness and the other the victims of fate. Punishment is well deserved in both these cases, and in both the capacity and willingness of ‘the state’, to identify and judge the culpable is more than a little suspect. Hence, in the postcolony, it is the especial ‘burden’ of historians to reuse a word which Kipling and, latterly, Gayatri Spivak,15 have used, to expose the trahison des clercs. They must document ‘with calm’, as many nameless women narrators have shown they can do, the ways in which the agents of the state manage to hoist them themselves into a position of godlike control over all kinds of suffering—the natural as much as, 15Spivak, Gayatri Chakraborty, ‘The Burden of English’ in The Lie of the Land: English
Literary Studies in India, edited by Rajeshwari Sunder Rajan, Oxford University Press, 1992.
310
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
maybe even more than, the nominal. In order to pursue this goal, it may be important for postcolonial historians to first concede that while suffering is a palpable phenomenon where disasters are concerned, agency is neither palpable nor singular. It is, in my view, in filling out this concept that the skill of historians is most urgently needed. Everyone with any ‘voice’ at all weeps for ‘the suffering of the people’ in India, and it is hard to differentiate between the crocodile majority and the concerned minority in this area. Therefore it is my belief that, if there is any point at all in historians taking on board the idea that it is the ‘moment of suffering’ that they are charged with recording, then that point has to come from the recognition that a supposed ‘moment’ of suffering has complex causal antecedents, requiring a more nuanced analysis of moral agency equally in nominal and in natural kind narratives. Unlike the subalternists in this matter, I see a crucial problem for the historian, not in that ‘suffering’ is so refractory a phenomenon, but in that ‘agency’ is so hard to pin down. Perhaps handing out prescriptions is the least satisfactory of deontological strategies, yet I must risk articulating one last hunch here. Since most historians agree that tracking the ‘remote’ causes of historical events is their professional business, I’d say to them: identify the agents of violence as the protagonists of narrative and the classic problem of recording emotion or ‘suffering’ within the discipline of history may well take care of itself. This is a chief lesson to be drawn from the people’s, and particularly, women’s, handling of the life-line of narrative in times of disaster. We do not need thought police but true intellectuals who can, without malice, take the initiative in analysing and identifying agency, even when the trail leads up to the godlike doors of government. Until then, it remains the tragedy of our postcolonial inheritance that so-called ‘moments of suffering’—a phrase blithely utilized by postmodern historians, even though Wittgenstein argued very plausibly a long time ago that ‘momentary grief’ worked like a linguistic oxymoron precisely because it was a psychological impossibility16—stretch so far into narrative infinity.
16 ‘Grief’ describes a pattern which recurs, with different variations, in the weave of our lives. If a man’s bodily expression of sorrow and of joy alternated, say with the ticking of a clock, here we should not have the characteristic formation of the pattern of sorrow or of the pattern of joy. ‘For a second he felt violent pain’,—[but] why does it sound queer to say: ‘For a second he felt deep grief’? Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Philosophical Investigations, translated by G.E.M. Anscombe, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1976, p. 174.
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
8
qQ EXPLAINING ENIGMAS FROM EVIDENCE The Cause of Narrative
Certainly, those determining acts of her life were not ideally beautiful. They were the mixed result of ... noble impulse struggling amidst the conditions of an imperfect social state ... for there is no creature whose inward being is so strong that it is not greatly determined by what lies outside it. ... Her full nature like that river of which Cyrus broke the strength, spent itself in channels that had no great name on the earth, but the effect of her being on those around her was incalculably diffusive: for the growing good of the world is partly dependent on unhistoric acts; and that things are not so ill with you or me as they might have been, is half owing to the number who lived faithfully a hidden life, and rest in hidden tombs. George Eliot, Middlemarch For a visitor to the flood-affected areas of Balasore, Mayurbhanj and Cuttack in North Bihar and Orissa, it is a job to get at the truth. ... A villager speaks: ‘I have eleven children. Two I’ve left to the mercy of God. The rest are begging, somewhere’. ... I went to the village to find out the truth. All the houses had collapsed. Many were washed away ... but the villagers would not tell me anything until I convinced them I wasn’t a government official. Nissim Ezekiel, ‘The Truth About the Floods’
311
312
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
The collection of poems in which Ezekiel’s ‘The Truth about the Floods’ appears was published in 1976, two years before the 1978 floods of West Bengal, which are the subject of this chapter. Yet, there is an uncanny resemblance between the oral narratives of the Bengal floods and Ezekiel’s poem. Some part of the explanation for this coincidence is provided by Ezekiel himself when he glosses ‘The Truth About the Floods’ as a ‘found-poem’ based on a newspaper report.1 Historical Agency and Narrative Mysteries Ezekiel’s, in other words, is a narrative that relinquishes its claim to fictional status by frankly admitting its genealogy in a kind of ‘history’. At the very least, it could be construed as a factual ‘danger-of-death’ Labovian narrative—but it is more than that. For, if it does not qualify as ‘literary history’, it is at least ‘historized literature’, that is, a kind of literature that would not have come into being without a historical precedent. ‘The Truth About the Floods’ commemorates an ill-starred time (as the etymology of ‘disaster’ reminds us) when a whole community is caught in crisis. Furthermore, this time seems to have the marked feature of occurring not once, but repeatedly (1967, 1978, 1999 ad infinitum; see also Chapter 5 on the element of repetition in narrative). When the floods will happen again may not be entirely predictable, that they will is. From this fearful iteration of tense, the past recurrently predicting the future, comes the tension of flood narratives, their ancient place in the literature of most cultures. Ezekiel’s contemporary production is simply one more addition to the genre. The narrative focus of Ezekiel’s poem is thus a well-attested, traumatic public event that has always seemed, ‘down the ages’, as the phrase goes, to demand re-telling, a natural ‘tellable’. Yet, as ‘The Truth About the Floods’ implies, there remains something secret about this event, something that resists recounting in the presence of certain hearers. ... but the villagers would not tell me anything until I convinced them I wasn’t a government official.
Under what circumstances do witnesses to a community tragedy deliberately suppress ‘the truth’ as they have shared it, and shared it perhaps more than once? Why should they choose to deny their history? Why is it so hard for a ‘visitor’ to ‘get at the truth’ about the floods? In Chapter 7, I made a start at considering some of these questions, but in doing 1See V.K. Dixit in The Indian Express, Bombay, 25 September 1967.
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
313
so I had to veer sharply away from the concerns of the previous chapters towards a more historicized and politicized understanding of narrative ‘context’, particularly in the case of disaster narratives. This is clearly reflected in the anxious and bitter tone of my last chapter, which indicts colonialism and its lasting effect on the narrative of postcoloniality— as told by from differing points-of-view by state officials, by academic historians and by ‘the people’, when confronted with life-threatening fires and floods. The resentment I recorded is not, of course, mine alone; it is part of a widely shared perception of ‘history’ on the Indian subcontinent today. Here, for example, is the opening essay of a journal issue devoted in 1999 entirely to floods in India: It is important to underline that the transformation of the plains and deltas in the Indian subcontinent from a flood dependent to a flood vulnerable relationship needs to be examined in a historical perspective. ... The first coordinated attempt at insulating lands from inundating rivers began with colonial rule in the Bengal Delta in the latter half of the eighteenth century. The East India Company, upon drastically reordering the mode of revenue collection, property arrangements and social coordinates of administration, was compelled to jettison the far more flexible response towards deltaic inundation that had been in prior operation. This rigidity in the new practices of the colonial revenue administration soon shaped the official view on inundation. Instead of perceiving the annual and recurrent excesses of the riverine systems, hydrology as geomorphological processes intrinsic and essential to the delta’s ecology, the emphasis now veered towards treating the phenomenon as calamitous events. In other words, imperatives of rule and administration were decisive in coalescing and organizing an agenda for flood control.2
Passages like the one above shore up my argument Chapter 7 about the changes wrought in the ‘age-old’ meme-narrative of flood by a historical process such as colonization. ‘Geomorphological processes’ came under the control of government writ, with the result that they were reconstrued as ‘calamitous events’ or ‘acts of god’, which it was the duty of administrations to strenuously resist, not least because it was profitable to do so. Thus the building of embankments, etc. that made it easier for the East India Company to collect revenue in the short term turned out to have long-term tragic effects on the lives of ‘the people’. This last chapter of Narrative Gravity, structurally committed to effecting closure, seeks also to effect many kinds of reconciliation. One of these rapproachements is between the historical narrative and the ‘ordinary 2D’Souza, Rohan, in ‘Floods: A Symposium on Flood Control and Management’,
Seminar, Vol. 478, June 1999, p. 14.
314
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
conversational narratives’, or what George Eliot calls ‘unhistoric acts’, to which most of this book has been devoted. That is why it must circle again the matters of enigmatic refusal, of deferred, or at least concealed, narrative explanation referred to so poignantly by Ezekiel. On the face of it, flood narratives afford striking examples of the ways in which tellers contrive to illustrate through their individual and particular stories a general truth (see Chapters 5 and 6). This is a truth which they can assume is quite obvious to their audience. The evidence for it lies all around; the havoc wrought speaks for itself. For this reason, the ‘plausibility’ of these stories, understood as the way in which they use particular ‘facts’ to convince sceptical listeners from ‘outside’ that their tellers ‘speak the truth’, could very easily be judged in terms of my Maxims of Narrative Exchange. Judgement, however, is not the purpose of this chapter. Here, I wish, as it were, to complicate the position I attributed a little earlier to Ezekiel—that of a literateur who fashions poems from the contingencies of history. Such literary renditions, from the epic of Gilgamesh to the legend of the god Krishna, who held up Mount Govardhan to protect the inhabitants of Braj from the flood waters, seem to have a deontic teleology, an ethical purpose. The gentle satire of Ezekiel’s poem, those ironic digs at ‘govermment officials’, only become possible if a contrary and enigmatic pattern of behaviour is first attributed to Ezekiel’s main protagonists, the villagers. Why, after all, would anyone refuse to witness his own loss (‘All the houses had collapsed. Many were washed away’), especially to the officials whose job it is to help him? An enigma. To exaggerate one’s loss is a rational, Gricean violation in these circumstances (‘I have eleven children’), but Ezekiel quickly dismisses this as a superficial strategy. He is in search of a deeper explanation for the villagers’ recalcitrance—and his poem provides one by altering a contextual presupposition. The causal account that Ezekiel comes up with is one that I would describe, for want of a more precise word, as essentially political, in absolutely the non-pejorative sense of this word. Within the world of the poem, there is indeed a ‘truth’ intentionally ‘hidden’ by the villagers, who might consent to tell it to a sympathetic poet, or even perhaps an investigative reporter (Ezekiel’s real-life ‘source’), but never to a probing official. What ‘truly happened’, the historical ‘fact’ then becomes in the poem, a secret shared between poet and villager, an expression of solidarity. It offers evidence of what George Eliot implies is the heroism of ‘a hidden life’. On Ezekiel’s account, the reason for hiding the truth is revealed as a tacit resistance to bureaucratic interference, on the part of the villagers
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
315
and, by extension, on the part of the poet, who is on the same ‘side’. Now, such a reading of silence as resistance cannot but be attractive because it ‘makes sense’, good political sense, of the apparently perverse reactions which people often have to tragedy. There is a problem, though, because resistance may paradoxically be expressed as much through ‘keeping up’ a conversation as through silence. Conversational cooperation is not to be misread as ideological cooperation. The men and women of the Bengal villages, especially the women, whom I recorded in Chapter 7, for example, were neither inhibited, nor apparently suspicious, in their response to strangers. They, literally, produced floods of stories in response to requests for stories of floods.Their welcoming narrative gestures extended even to those like myself who had clearly gone there with a government team, crude taperecorder in hand, recognizably a type of vulture—perhaps not a particularly threatening one, but still one who appeared obviously interested in the pickings of tragedy. Why would such a despicable personage be allowed any conversational entry at all? One naive, but surely convincing response is: power and class position, the agent-patient asymmetry relation that exists between potential donors (urban, middle-class, university literate) and potential recipients of aid (rural, manual labouring, school literate or illiterate). Another slightly less naive response has to do with political process, because the ‘government officials’ in this case belonged to the Marxist state government in West Bengal, a government which had proven to a considerable extent its commitment to changing land-labour relations in West Bengal, and thus has been returned to power, on the strength of a massive rural vote, for the last thirty years. Insofar as any government official could be trusted, these officials had, in fact, won some rights to the people’s confidence. Both these ‘naive’ answers go some way towards reassuring us that the conversational cooperation of the villagers is explicable in terms of ‘care of the self ’, the motivations of self-interest and self-preservation, that pre-programmed survival instinct, so central to Dennett’s Paradox. Is that all, though? Is Ezekiel’s explanation of the villagers’ ‘refusal to speak’ as a stubborn resistance to bureaucratic invasion simply to be replaced by a pragmatic explanation of rational as well as instinctive selfinterest? I believe not. I believe that the role of the copious narrativization that surrounds disaster in all societies is not to be understood as merely instrumental—that is, as achieving straight-forward political or pragmatic ends. Rather, these narratives are primarily theoretical. What I mean by this is that meme-etic disaster-narratives are explanatory paradigms setting out the human consequences of disaster, and suggesting its causes. They
316
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
are not so much explained by their tellers intentions as explanations for them. This might appear to be semantic quibbling, but I would like to plead not. For there is the simple relation of logical contraries between the statements X explains Y and Y explains X; so, ‘teller’s intentions and (other) circumstances explain stories’ makes a truth-claim that is quite different from ‘stories explain teller’s intentions and (other) circumstances’. In this chapter, I shall be concerned with defending and elaborating the latter Denneltian proposition. Deixis and Evidence The extreme sophistication that marks the oral narratives of flood in the villages of West Bengal—an enduring sophistication that seems to me to mimic the myths of flood that characterize many early cultural accounts of creation itself—stems, in my view, from a basic impulse towards theory built into the ‘linear’ structure of narrative and supported by the ‘argumentative’ structure of conversation. And while we may infer ‘political resistance’ too in these narratives, I’d suggest that what is truly exciting about this resistance is that it is actually a resistance to other theories about the causes and consequences of the disaster being explained—the colonial theory or ‘narrative’ about the deltaic floods in Bengal described in the passage quoted earlier, for example. The following two conversations, presented by me, offer causal ‘theories’ for the floods. These confrontations between a government official, who is the main story recipient, and the villagers who have suffered, mark the clash of explanatory paradigms that I have just mentioned. Differing world-views are in contest here, as will become increasingly apparent as these long conversations progress. a) i A
B A
B A
MIDNAPORE 1 So this flood which has now—2 Everybody agrees that the engineers didn’t know about it. 3 They assumed that the river— 4 I mean—damming the river, would solve the problem. 5 Hm. 6 But this we [knew] five hundred years ago—7 we saw for ourselves that it wasn’t so 8 The river—here—imagine, it was another twelve or fourteen feet deep. 9 Hm. 10 But what happened here [pointing] 11 there is an anicut here, just on top, where there’s the Koshai Bridge—there—12 And since there is an anicut there, the water-flow comes to a standstill here. 13 Because of this, the sand [from the river
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
317
bed] forms a mud-flat—14 Automatically, the [quantity of] sand grows with the strength of the current—and if the river— er—if(they) dam up the water then the sandbank goes and builds up there. 15 When it falls there [the bank] grows higher. 16 And after it grows higher, obviously, both barriers break down. 17 This is how the river is filling up with mudflats. 18 There are mud-flats—er 19 However many mudflats there are, slow down the current of the river. 20 Because of this slowing down, the silt grows and deposits itself and the greater the amount of sand on the river bed the more the level of the river rises. 21 It rises because we have seen that— 22 I mean—er—the nullahs—er—made by the Government for releasing the water have closed up with sand—23 This means that—fifty-sixty years ago, those were—um—not flooded. 24 They were firm land. 25 Now they’ ve become sandy soil. 26 That’s why the overflooding. 27 However, they say that the dams—er—we will stop the floods. But we think this is not the case—28 If there is a twenty-foot flood, but we have erected only a ten-foot dam over this—[pointing] then the water will break through the dam and escape— Then, like the Hinglo dam—29 From the place where the water breaks through will stem a river. 30 That’s why we have—have held things up and if the flood is to be stopped in time, the main thing to do is to deepen the river bed—31 Not the whole— a little—the bed—32 Dig in four or five hundred feet deep— and if we pile up the sand on either bank—we can work through it and make mud-flats on either side. 33 This will deepen the river bed [Pause] 34 And the anicut is the biggest problem here these days. 35 At that time the anicut will have to be kept totally closed. 36 We will have to follow another system. 37 Only then can the flood be avoided. 38 Without these measures this land will have floods down through the ages. 39 And we will have to leave this village. 40 This—this will be the state of affairs—[Pause] 41 Here, don’t you see— 42 don’t you see that this little compression of the water has led to such a rise in the water level? 43 Almost level with the land—44 But fifty years ago all this was not s-sand—it was all firm land. 45 My house— B 46 And the river? C 47 By the river—there [pointing] 48 there were houses all along there—by the river bank. ...
318
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
A 49 Yes, the river was much narrower—almost the half of this— a half narrower— C 50 The river was in the middle. 51 Near that sand bank. ... A 52 These were all villages. 53 The advance [of the river] has swallowed them up. 54 This is a very frightening thing. 55 That is why we have only one plan to stop the flood; there isn’t any other way. 56 And I think that the other floods have been—the fault of the engineers. 57 We have had so many floods because of their various errors. B 58 Who will cut through this? A 59 Oh the Government will have to do that—um—with Central Government money. 60 The way the Centre has spent money—61 the money that has been spent for so long—no account of that—the engineers themselves 62 I mean, they’ve just wasted the money—used it badly. 63 It hasn’t been spent according to plan. B 64 Does our Government have facilities for cutting [through beds]? 65 Of course, we have mud-cutters—66 These dredgers—they— A 67 Yes, they can cut through banks of mud. 68 But they don’t have any [machines] now. 69 If the Central Government provides the money then the [State] Government will have to cut through the river banks. 70 That is the strategy our Kapil Dev is contemplating now—71 which we’d thought of five or even seven years ago! 72 Now even the big-shots who are heads of the Flood Control Committee are advocating the same thing, 73 and everybody wants the river bed to be made deeper now! B 74 Does our Government have a dredger? 75 These things? A 76 There are some dredgers. 77 Even if there aren’t, they’ ll have to be acquired from outside. 78 And all the foreign help we’re getting from UNICEF, etc., that can buy a dredger. 79 All that money. 80 Because UNICEF is doing quite a lot now. 81 If they can do a little, deepen the river in the middle—82 if the river is deepened in the middle, then the water which flows down the centre will deepen it further and the displaced mud will form banks on either side. 83 No matter how much water flows down here, however many cu.secs., the water will remain channelled. 84 Now the water here simply floods onto the bank. 85 This is the main problem. 86 I—[think] all the floods in West Bengal must be caused by this. 87 That’s what I think.
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
319
B 88 But dredging the river bed is quite a proposition! [Pause] 89 [if] the river bed is so high then cutting through it with a dredger will mean so much mud, where will you dump it all? A 90 They can be dumped on b-both sides of the river. B 91 You’ll get rid of it on both sides? A 92 Yes, and they’ll form mud-flats later. 93 And the deepening of the river will allow fertile flats to form mid-stream as well, without the water rising. 94 It’ll all form naturally. D 95 And if not it will have to be cemented in concrete. 96 No other way out. A 97 The sides [of the river] cannot be made concrete. D 98 Well— B 99 I will have a word about this—with the Department of Irrigation Engineer. A 100 Can a river be confined by concrete? D 101 That’s true, of course. A 102 Then the Government would spend its time doing nothing else! VAR 103 [laugh] B 104[Pause] I will discuss this [with somebody in the Government] a) ii [DIAMOND HARBOUR] S 1 Your field—um—is it—has it been submerged in salt water? H 2 Yes absolutely. 3 I mean, our circumstances this year—er— what [I don’t know] what will happen afterwards. 4 Maybe just at the moment somehow we’ll manage for these few months. 5 But what’ll happen afterwards, it pains me to think. S 6 All the land? H 7 All of it. 8 Whenever the flood goes anywhere. 9 At that moment before your eyes—10 For instance, this soil, there is so much [salt] water in it. S 11 Is there water still or has it gone down? H 12 There’s not much now of course. 13 Only then. 14 For three months we went—15 I mean—16 I mean we had to walk with our clothes lifted. 17 It was so severe some people’s houses fell down. 18 Nothing left in the fields. 19 Here, have you seen the other [fresh] soil that has been brought? S 20 But there’s no salt water now? H 21 Not now. 22 Whatever was fated to turn salt has turned salt. 23 [But] we have been unfortunate once. 24 Other places have been unlucky twice or thrice. 25 We have floods [only] once [a year]. 26 Whatever happens in this rainy season, you see.
320
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
S 27 Why doesn’t it happen at other times? H 28 Well, how can it happen at other times? 29 We haven’t had any canal installed. 30 Other places have deep tube wells but we haven’t got anything here. S 31 Why? H 32 Shallow [wells] in our land here are—I mean, they’re useless. 33 They’ll just be no use—34 The misfortune can affect the Ragi and Mustard crops at most. 35 If canals are dug here, they can help a little [more]. S 36 Here—why can’t there be shallow tube wells here? H 37 There can’t, I mean—because it’s known that there can’t. 38 We hope, of course. 39 First of all, it’s expensive here. 40 There have been [some], 41 once or twice [in the past] there have been [some], of course, 42 but it wasn’t possible to raise the water. S 43 First of all—the water ... why wasn’t it possible [to raise it?] H 44 There was a ditch near Diamond Harbour. 45 When they raised the water, they found that the water subsides, goes down a hole—[in the] tube well, and the level of the water is low again. 46 Whenever there is a problem the water level has to be raised. S 46 Well—are there—er [a:]only—shallow tube wells that you have, or [have you a] big tube well. 47 Those ... H 48 This will cost more, but at the moment we have to limit expenditure. 49 It will cost more here than in other places. S 50 Your water here is salty, is it not? H 51 Yeah, its salty. S 52 That’s why the pipes will be ruined in no time. H 53 That’s certain. 54 These tubewells that are dug here. 55 They are ruined after perhaps just five or six months. 56 Don’t last any longer. S 57 That’s why tube wells are no use here. 58 We have to dig lots of canals. 59 There’s no way out but this. Narrative, I have argued throughout th is book, is a species of natural theory; when it is embedded in a conversation, there is the added advantage that often we witness a critique of the explanation on offer. Recipients agree, via the turn-taking mechanisms of conversation, to give a particular ‘theory’ a hearing, but they may also exercise their rights to knock it down. Sometimes, the story-tellers themselves set up an opposing theory as a foil to their own. This is the strategy A adopts in the first of conversations
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
321
above. A’s ‘story-prefacing’ utterances in lines 1–7 make it clear that he is going to set up an opposition between the ignorance of the city engineers and the perspicacity of the villagers. The wisdom of the villagers is tried and tested (‘but this we knew five hundred years ago’), whereas by implication the engineers are city-slickers whose modern training fails the test of an actual trial. A’s superb eloquence and rhetorical gifts come through, I think, even in translation, for example in the marvellous irony of his question: ‘Can a river be confined by concrete?’ (line 100). One could draw attention to many aspects of A’s narrative, but I will focus here mainly on one methodological feature of his causal account of why the floods were so devastating—namely, deixis. My suggestion is that, in an environment where scenes of recent disaster are plainly to be seen by recipients, tellers do not always tell stories which simply outline the actual circumstances of the disaster, because this would, in Gricean terms, be redundant. Rather, they resourcefully use an unusual advantage that they happen to possess in these circumstances. They can actually point to the evidence. Deixis thus becomes an important explanatory aid. In the first example, A is a selfappointed spokesman for the village, B is a government official, and it emerges clearly from A’s story that his intention is a) to persuade B that the engineers sent by the Government have been responsible for the flood because they produced the wrong solutions to the villagers’ problems with riverine ‘overflooding’ (see A’s opening statement for the prosecution in lines 2–4, and then again one of several concluding gambits, for example, lines 56–7). b) to convince B that his own solution, which involves deepening the river bed is the correct one, a theoretical option which A supports with several arguments (see especially lines 11–44, replete with causal connectors such as ‘that’s why’, ‘because’, ‘since’, ‘this means that’, etc.). c) to get B to commit himself to doing something about the situation if he accepts A’s explanation, which it appears he is remarkably successful at because B does appear to accept his theory by the end of A’s story (see his line 99 ‘I will have a word about this—with the Department of Irrigation Engineer.’). A’s narrative, ‘but what happened here ... ’ (line 10), is fashioned as a counter-argument. His story is about the history of a river—a river which now floods regularly because of the impracticality of the Government engineers. ‘It [the river] rises because we have seen that—er—the nullah—er—made by the Government for releasing the water has closed
322
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
up with sand. This means that fifty-sixty years ago those were—um—not flooded. Now they’ve become sandy soil’ (lines 21–25). ‘They say—the dams—we will stop the flood with these. But we think this is not the case—(and etc., line 27)’. Not only is A’s indictment strong, it is extremely courageous. He is taking his fight, his faith in his theory, right up to the Government camp. Ironically the naïve ‘theory’ that A’s develops through his narrative is in keeping with the latest thinking on ecologically sustainable flood-control. Dinesh Kumar Mishra, an engineer, writes in the 1999 Seminar issue on the floods from which I quoted earlier: It is important to realize that when the river is embanked (or dammed?) the water which could have entered the river on its own gets stuck outside ... and causes water-logging. The river water contains a lot of silt which spreads over a large area if the river is free to spill. This silt gets trapped inside the embankments, continuously raising the bed-level of the area, thereby pressing for raising the height of the embankments. There is a practical limit to which an embankment can be raised. The trouble starts when a tributary joins the main river. The embankments on the main river block the entry of the tributary into the main river and a sluice-gate (Speaker A’s ‘anicut’) becomes necessary. When constructed, this sluice gate must be kept closed during the rainy season because any sudden rise in the flood level of the main river will push the flood waters into the protected area through the sluice gate. And if the sluice-gates are closed even for a short while ... the backwaters from the tributary will submerge the protected area on the countryside of the embankments. ... Consequently, the tributary is also embanked. ... This creates another problem. ... If any of the two embankments [now] breach, whether on the main river or on the tributary, the people living [in] between will meet a watery grave. This knowledge existed with Indian engineers much before embankments (and big dams?) were okayed by them in the post-Independence era. The political compulsions of the time forced them to toe the line of the politicians, and in their enthusiasm to do so, the engineers went out of their way to negate what they had argued against for over a hundred years. ... The colonial rulers were calculating and knew that if embankments were constructed ... costs would always exceed the benefits accrued over the years ... or the revenues collected by the government as flood protection levy. Their engineers rightly spoke the language of their masters, and so did the Indian engineers of independent India. To argue that technology is neutral and apolitical is hardly teneable.
All the main points made by A’s eye-witness narrative of 1978 are repeated in the academic article of 1999—the silting up of rivers because of damming and embankment, the part played by ‘anicuts’ or sluice-gates,
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
323
the historic guilt of the engineers, the actual and political costs of the technological changes wrought by government, and the price paid by the people for faults that are not theirs. Just as Mishra’s argument closes with a ‘coda’ politicizing technology, so A’s narrative ends with a bleak vision of the future which also contains a political ultimatum—‘We will have to follow another system. Only then can the flood be avoided. Without these measures this land will have flood down through the ages. And we will have to leave this village. This—this will be the state of affairs [Pause]’ (lines 36–40). That pause at the end is significant because this is where there could be a story-evaluation by recipient B. But B’s position is a difficult one; he is after all a representative of the Government which A is castigating; his move has therefore to be carefully planned so as to show a degree of neutrality. As I have suggested, the special environment in which these disaster stories are being told does not permit recipients to adopt a strategy whereby they question the teller’s story. B cannot and does not say, for instance, ‘I don’t accept what you’ve told me. I happen to know for a fact that the river was as prone to flooding fifty or sixty years ago as now and, anyhow, our engineers weren’t around then.’ Given that no such option exists, the problem he has to solve is that of appearing sympathetic, and at the same time, reserved. Notice that B makes no less than six moves after the story is told; each of these temporarily resolves his dilemma by the expedient of asking further ‘knowledgeable’ questions about, for example, dredgers (see lines 46–91). This places the onus back on the teller for the time being, but finally B is trapped both by the relentlessness of the turn-taking system and by A’s adroitness as a storyteller—the logic of narrative theme and of conversational structure combine to corner him. When B initially fails to come in at the end of his pause in line 40, A again resorts to the by now familiar strategy of pointing to the actual scene before him, ‘Here, don’t you see, that this little compression of water has led to such a rise in the water level? Almost level with the land. But fifty years ago all this was not sand, it was all firm land. My house ... ’ (lines 41–5) Indeed, his entire narrative is packed with ‘this’, ‘that’, ‘here’, ‘now’, and other deictic markers. It is also significant that B interrupts with his question at the point when A refers to his house, because if A had launched on a story about how his own house was destroyed in the floods, B would be forced to express sympathy for A and thereby forfeit his neutrality. As we have observed, B does ultimately commit himself to some action at the end, but his six questioning, questing, moves must
324
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
not be forgotten. It would be reasonable for us as analysts to infer from them that B would have preferred not to have made his concession in lines 98–9, but he seems to be left in the ongoing conversational exchange with no alternative moves, unless he pursues a strategy of endlessly asking further questions. In this sense, it would be correct to maintain that A has been uniquely successful in utilizing deictic coordinates to magnificent effect. A powerless ‘villager’, his narrative has got an powerful inspecting official from Calcutta to agree that something must be done. What is striking about A’s narrative is the way in which it combines an apocalyptic tone and moral indignation with a cool scientific argument The political sense of self, of a local and rooted identity, is supported by a causal account how the miserable present came into being through a series of historical ‘errors’. A’s prophesy or scientific ‘prediction’ is based on a theory supported by plenty of visible evidence. It cannot be gainsaid. In the second of the stories above, it is with invisible evidence that we are concerned. Story i)b was recorded in the district of Diamond Harbour, which was much less severely affected by flooding than Midnapore district, but had the special problem that it was near the sea and so prone to being inundated by sea water. We notice, to begin with, the hesitation that accompanies S’s first utterance, ‘Your field—er—um—is it—has it— been submerged in salt water? S is again an official who has to ascertain the extent of the damage caused by the floods, but asking the question the way he does, is almost bound to evoke the response that H predictably produces: ‘Yes, absolutely’, followed by a digression into the consequences of this for H’s family. But S’s second question, ‘Is there water still or has it gone down?’, follows a strategy that becomes transparent once his third question is taken into account. ‘But there’s no salt water now?’ This is a manoeuvre to get H to admit that his situation is not as bad as all that, if the water has already subsided. But, as I have been emphasizing, the circumstances in which these conversations are conducted often permit recipients to dispense with the convention which tellers must follow of making their stories plausible, so H can take the risk of answering S with ‘There’s not much [evidence? salt?] now of course. Only then. For three months we went—I mean—I mean, we had to walk with our clothes lifted up. It was so severe some people’s houses fell down. Nothing left in the fields’ (lines 13–18). The crucial contextual information needed to make the correct inference from the information H offers in lines 13–18 is the following, Diamond Harbour was not an area where the damage to property was severe, and at the time this recording was made, the floods were certainly
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
325
not ‘three months old’. Yet, curiously, in spite of these discrepencies, H is still using the strategy of pointing to visual evidence of disaster in a very subtle way to augment his case. This is because it is common knowledge among participants that damage caused by salt water flooding, though invisible, lasts a long time. Even minimum flooding, if the water is salt sea water, can kill crops. H exploits this particular fact to present his theory of flood damage, and then to offer his solution to it. Invisible evidence of long-term devastation can still be conversationally pointed at, and pointed up; thus there is, literally, more to H’s utterance than meets the eye. He can exaggerate about people’s houses falling down on the strength of this. The unusualness of salt water flooding thus offers H a very specialized conversational resource he can use. S’s purpose is to convince H, as A’s purpose was to convince the official B in a)i that deep and shallow tube wells are useless in his district because they tend to get contaminated with seeping salt water, and only canals that channel in fresh water are useful. He too has a premeditated solution to the logical problem posed by annual flooding in the district. That is the purpose of his brief, exaggerated story at the beginning, prefaced by line 10 ‘this soil there is so much [salt] water in it’, to which is S’s response, ‘Is there water still or has it gone down?’ The exchange makes it clear that it is not visually apparent to S whether there is still salt water in the soil or not. The rest of the conversation is concerned with establishing that canals are the logical solution and again, as in the last conversation, S concedes after a series of negotiations in line 57, ‘There’s no way out but this’. Conversations like the two we have just studied reveal how adaptable tellers are, how attuned to making the best use of environmental conditions. Rather than concentrate on the single aspect of the misery and damage caused by the floods, A and H show us how they can simply point to evident damage in order to corroborate, legitimize and sustain the logic of their narratives. Narrative, in short, helps us to survive and preserve our essential identities even at times of the gravest physical and mental danger by creating logical solutions to the problems presented by our surroundings. Thus, they conform to the contours of both Dennett’s paradox and mine in that they literally offer structural, logical and psychological lifelines to those in danger of drowning Narrative Sequencing in an Interruptive Culture The flood narratives that we have been discussing are certainly distinctive, as I hope I have demonstrated in the last section, in terms of their
326
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
immediate context. What about cultural context? In this section, I will try to show that cultural habits also have structural repercussions both for the theoretical design and performative strategies adopted by narrators so as to prevent their ‘alien’ recipients—government officials, research students—from questioning their ‘fragile’ stories. Our stories are a measure of exactly how fragile and how tough our ‘selves’ within a culture are. Plunging in at the deep end, then, here is another conversation recorded in Midnapore District, where the floods of 1978 had their most disastrous effects. b) i A
B
C B A B D A
C A
B A C B C A
1 [We] made a banana boat (kolar bhaela) and got the women and children into that. 2 Think of the [people in their] houses, we had to get in each time and push people out. 3 and the others were on their own. 4 I mean—the older people all climbed onto trees. 5 All climbed up on trees. 6 They had to be rescued too—from their heights! 7 Oh, goodness! 8 Everyone had climbed up on trees! 9 They themselves had a lot. ... 10 Apart from this, a lot. ... 11 Then we had to get them down from there and get them across in the banana boats. 12 They’ve [now] been taken to places wherever the land is higher. ... 13 ... wherever there were brick houses, those place where— whoever. ... 14 Lots of people have brick houses, you see 15 They were taken to these houses. 16 You’ve had a bad time, haven’t you? 17 Terrible. 18 Our elders tell us that in five (fifty?) years we haven’t had a flood here like this one. 19 This is the only time in our lives. 20 At eleven o’clock in the night we saw no water. 21 We haven’t seen a flood like this in our lives! 22 Yeah, yeah. 23 There we were sleeping in the night—24 At one o’clock we find, I mean—water in the house! 25 Oh, you didn’t even notice—26 didn’t think that it would turn out like this! 27 No, not at all. 28 That there would be this huge flood. ...
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
327
C 29 Yes, nobody could conceive of it! Really! A 30 It took us quite unawares! 31 And what was most frightening was that—whenever there was a current from any side, if we fell into the river there was no chance of our swimming. ... C 32 Hm, hm. A 33 ... if we got further and further away from the river bank. B 34 Many houses have floated* away on that side—[pointing] 35 Others on that side [pointing] 36 Many houses have been destroyed, people have been carried away, cows, bullocks, everything. C 37 Yes, no one could imagine it! D 38 Everything floated away down the river. A 39 The level of the river—the level of the river and the level of the dam, just notice the difference! D 40 Then the women and children started such a wailing when the flood covered Bhatra, then Lokonghat [Pause] during the day— A 41 Crying and— D 42 From about nine or ten o’clock. 43 Crying and wailing. 44 That was the problem. 45 Then we cut down the banana trees in all four directions and. ... C 46 Yeah. D 47 The houses. ... 48 The dams [broke down] like this [gesture]. A 49 It wasn’t a little flood which they could hold out against. C 50 Hm. A 51 They are still in the school [building]. 52 It is they who have suffered most. 53 We get so many floods here. C 54 Yeah, hm. A 55 This is happening all the time to the river now. 56 Every time the water increases a little, the water floods all over here. 57 This is the situation. 58 But no one was prepared for such a huge flood. D 59 Made boats. 60 Cut the tr—wood and made floats for the women, children, kids, everybody. C 61 Of course the women and children would be frightened. 62 This kind of. ... D 63 Everybody was taken across one by one. 64 There where— whenever—65 where there was [once] a brick house. ... C 66 And the women and children didn’t know how to swim? D 67 No, no, they’re quite—
328
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
C 68 The children, the children, don’t. ... D 69 They know [swimming] well. 70 The young people in banana boats, somehow they had all to be taken to those big—big houses. 71 Took them to one or two of these houses. 72 Thousands and thousands of people were rescued, you know. 73 All this somehow—er—um—74 I mean, it took until Monday. 75 Otherwise we couldn’t have rescued them. 76 Nobody was capable of anything. C 77 Oh. 78 Yes, yeah. 79 There’s obviously been a lot of damage. One of the most noticeable features of this conversation is the way in which several tellers combine to tell the same story. I will now argue that the cooperation displayed by tellers in b)i is both a fitting strategic response to immediate context and culturally sanctioned. Generally, from insider observation of conversations in the pan-Indian cultural context it seems to me that there is a high tolerance of interruptions and joint performances. This, in my view, constitutes a typical instance of specifically implicultural knowledge concerning how conversations may be structured given the norms of a particular society. Subcontinental speakers are, ceteris paribus, far less likely to assert their right to a turn by saying, ‘Let me finish, please!’ than speakers in, say, ‘Western culture’. Interruptions are read as signs of cooperative behaviour—i.e. helping the speaker along—rather than rude attempts to cut into someone else’s conversational space. Of course, in the absence of hard statistical data, this remains a speculation, but in my examination of the ‘joint-telling’ above, I will at least make a start by placing my ‘culturally biased’ notion of interruptions within the turntaking system of conversation alongside Sacks’. So far, we implicitly made the assumption, based on ethnomethodological studies of narrative sequencing by Sacks, Jefferson et al., that a prospective teller who successfully completes a ‘preface sequence’ is rewarded by a chance to occupy the ‘telling slot’. A preface sequence is enormously influential, according to Sacks, in deciding the reading by recipients of the subsequent story.3 But where is the preface sequence in the present story, which is launched upon abruptly by A, as the party is walking towards the home of one of the tellers? A’s opening sentence 3See also Jefferson G., ‘Sequential Aspects of Story-Telling in Conversation’, p. 270. Story prefaces follow a constraint which requires participants ‘to display a relationship between the story and prior talk, and thus account for and propose the appropriateness of the story’s telling’. Obeying the convention of local occasioning when prefacing their stories, enables tellers to coordinate this turn with prior talk; furthermore, if recipients assume that convention is being obeyed, they can more easily guess at the implications arising from the
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
329
states baldly, ‘We made a banana boat and got the women and children into that’. There is no background provided either for constructing such a ‘banana boat’, or for piling women and children into it. In discussing the convention of local occasioning in Chapter 6, it was assumed that tellers had first to work at rendering a story ‘relevant’ to other participants, but in this context, as I have suggested, it is taken for granted that the relevance of A’s utterance is self evident. No further justification is needed. Labov would argue that this is because the material out of which A’s story is produced, is durable story material, but I would maintain that these flood conversations presents us with a more subtle dilemma. If recipients have to respond to a corpus of danger-to-death stories that are as homogeneous as this one, their interest in the stories is likely to diminish exponentially if each story makes the same point over and over, however poignant. So we are back to Sacks’ insight that it is imperative that tellers use whatever resources they possess to make their stories into ‘something for us’ over and above their interest as dire firstperson narratives of disaster. My suggestion is that a study of stories such as the one above show that tellers use the structure of conversation as well as cultural resources in tandem to achieve this difficult task. To establish this claim, it might be useful to recall standard conversational analytic definitions of story-sequencing. A preface sequence ‘can take a minimum length of two turns, the first involving talk by the intending teller and the second by an intended recipient’.4 It is a slot that can only be filled by a prospective teller, and is the first part of a pair in a paired sequence that, if successfully completed, initiates the telling of a story. It usually, though not always, ‘self-selects’5 for the next but one turn; that is, if the preface sequence extends over a number of paired turns—ABAB, and so on—where the first turn ‘belongs’ to the intending teller, and the second turn in the pair to the intended recipient, then every third turn is the teller’s turn and can potentially be filled with a story if the recipient agrees in his previous turn to the telling of the story. Once the story is begun a fresh sequence is initiated. This is the ‘telling sequence’. story, since the presumption is that the story is also a contribution to ongoing talk. Sometimes, as Jefferson notes, a story preface ‘may not be topically coherent with the talk in progress’. It may simply have been ‘triggered’ by the turn-by-turn talk (see also example g) i in Chapter 6 and the subsequent discussion. 4Sacks, ‘An Analysis of the Course of a Joke’s Telling in Conversation’, p. 340. It will also be recalled that one of the Preparatory Conditions on stories I suggested in Chapter 2 was that a sequence of clauses p 1... pn should constitute a ‘completed sequence’. 5‘Self-selection’ is a term used by conversational analysts to define a move by a current speaker to choose himself as the next speaker in the next appropriate turn.
330
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
The telling sequence may consist of a single slot, which by definition ‘belongs’ to the teller of the story. Once a teller is in possession of the ‘telling’ slot, that is, it is incumbent upon him to ‘proceed to tell [the story] directly to its completion’, as Sacks puts it below. My suggestion in this book is that tellers are bound by a convention when they engage in the language-game of story-telling to complete a story once it has been ‘appropriately prefaced’. Sacks also writes: A joke’s or a story’s telling having been appropriately prefaced, its teller should proceed to tell it directly to its completion. In contrast with the organization of the preface sequence, place for the talk of recipients within the course of telling sequence need not be provided by the teller, and the telling can then take a minimum length of one teller turn.6
Although the telling sequence may occupy just one slot, Sacks notices that recipients ‘in fact ... do talk, and talk interrruptively, within the telling sequence’.7 By ‘interrruptive talk’ Sacks means talk that does not necessarily have a place within the sequence, but which is nevertheless sanctioned because it may be essential for recipients to, for example, clarify a point if they are to understand the full implications of a story. Given the nature of interruptive talk, Sacks further points out that ‘we [should be] prepared for noticing and appreciating the orderliness of some rather fine, ... co-occurrent features of recipients’ talk within the telling sequence’.8 And indeed, it is overwhelmingly apparent from the conversations studied in Narrative Gravity that recipients not only talk during the telling sequence but use their interruptive turns to display their understanding of the progress of the story. They deftly locate their own utterances in interstices of the teller’s story, anticipating many of teller’s moves and coordinating their own interruptive moves to accord with the tellers. An interruptive turn generally consists of a single move by a recipient, rather than of several moves within the one turn; this is apparently because recipients have to manage their moves rather delicately, since a teller need not, as Sacks maintains, provide them with any place at all within the telling sequence, but can proceed directly to a story’s completion once in possession of the telling slot. Most tellers do, however, ‘allow’ recipients to talk interruptively throughout their extended turn for the obvious reason that these interruptive moves within the telling sequence 6Sacks, ‘Analysis of the Course of a Joke’s Telling’, p. 344. 7Ibid. 8Ibid.
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
331
serve the function of demonstrating their continued participation in the conversation, and their interest in the story. Thus, interruptive moves, which function as evaluations of the story and articulate the perlocutionary effects of the story on recipients, are fairly important within the telling sequence; despite the fact that recipients often use these moves to arraign fragile aspects of a teller’s story. Yet these carefully gathered observations about story sequencing seems to be in need of a major ‘repair’ or revision, at least as far as ‘interruptive moves’ are concerned, if the flood story we have just encountered is taken as culturally typical. Not only does it dispense with a preface sequence, but its single recipient does not make any interruptive moves. There are several ‘interruptions’ within the telling sequence, but they are not by the recipient. My own hunch is that in an ‘interruptive culture’ such I have designated the ‘Indian’, the structural places in telling sequence which Sacks says story-recipients occupy, can non-problematically be reassigned to other tellers. Thus, in story b)i the telling slot is occupied not by a single teller, but by three. Sacks has suggested that if two tellers, such as a man and his wife, have both had the same experience which they wish to narrate to a third party, then one possible solution to ‘the co-ordination problem’ of conversing is for one of the partners to keep quiet while the other tells the story. In my recording, the three tellers obviously adopt a much more active strategy, belonging as they do to a putative ‘culture of interruptions’. Teller A begins the story and D completes it, with B playing a supportive role throughout. In the unusual circumstances that each teller here has a ‘valuable’ first-person account of events which Labov would label ‘always reportable’, this is a perfect example of the resourcefulness of tellers. A, B and D combine their move with such extreme skill that they achieve nearly perfect coordination, with a ‘minimum of gaps and overlaps’. B, for instance, simply carries on from A’s opening utterance by using an ‘and’ to extend A’s sentence in line 2. C’s task as the single recipient is also made less arduous by this strategy, since C need only come in after both A and B, and later A and D, have completed their combined turns. The ‘response-sequence’ rounds off the language-game of storytelling. In Labov and Waletzky’s terminology, the story-receipt fulfils the function of a ‘coda’, which signals that a narrative is completed. As the examples examined earlier illustrate, the story-receipt slot is usually filled with a generalization that recipients have derived as the implicature of the foregoing story, or with some token of story appreciation such as laughter, or the articulation of a perlocutionary effect such as ‘gosh!’,
332
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
‘gives me the shivers’, etc. Since this is the main slot belonging to recipients in the story-telling game, it is obviously the slot most constrained by the convention that recipients must produce some sort of evaluation as a story. Even if recipients are completely silent during the telling of a story, sequentially the next slot after the story has to be filled by recipients, and there is copious evidence from conversational data to show that recipients almost always produce an evaluative comment in this slot. In this particular conversation, story-recipient C is more or less ‘silent’ during the telling sequence and nowhere ‘questions’ the speakers’ joint production. Indeed, when C attempts to inquire whether the children in the village could swim (lines 66 and 68), there is an unspoken ‘snub’ in D’s reply (‘They know [swimming] well’ line 69); D does not add, ‘but that’s not the point’, but it is implicit in the way he continues with his narrative (‘The young people in banana boats, somehow they had all to be taken to those big—big houses. Took them to one or two of these houses.’ lines 70–1). The subtext clearly is that it is irrelevant whether one can swim or not in this context; the point is to find a safe harbour, a piece of high ground or a big house. That is where the heroism of the rescue effort manifests itself. Consider D’s line 72, for instance: ‘Thousands and thousands of people were rescued, you know’. There is surely a hyperbolic element here when it is taken into account that D is talking only about his own village and of rescue by means of banana boats and rafts. Yet C’s ‘story-receipt’ in response is not in the least aggressive (line 77, ‘Oh, yes, yeah, there’s obviously been a lot of damage’). I would contend that this is so because of the strong combination of contextual knowledge (there is causal evidence of flood damage all around and the narrator is recounting a personal danger-of-death narrative) with cultural factors (this is an interruptive culture which permits as much space for joint-tellers as for listeners). In such a situation, it is not surprising that listener’s turns are actually given over to tellers. The natural logic of the cultural and contextual circumstances demand this specific ‘interruptive’ adjustment of the standard turn-taking mechanism of conversation. Distance lends Enchantment Most of the stories in the present chapter consist of first-person narratives told by people themselves affected by calamity (see Appendix I). On the whole, they offer perhaps a more homogeneous corpus than the one examined by Labov and Waletzky because while these researchers elicited an entire range of incidents in response to their requests for danger-ofdeath accounts, the stories here are all ‘spontaneous’ responses concerning
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
333
a single event. I have begun by arguing that this uniqueness may have consequences for the presentation and ordering of the conversations in which these stories occur. They represent, as it were, a theoretical consensus within a community. Since these floods were the most severe in several decades, they were widely discussed in a variety of social settings. I therefore include in this chapter an example of a ‘metropolitan’ story of the flood recorded in Calcutta, by way of contrast. Then, by way of an even more egregious contrast, the chapter finally ends with a narrative about a flood recorded in the very different cultural environment of Cambridge, England—a tale which cannot under any circumstances be said to fall into the genre of danger-of-death narrative! We have observed how remarkable is the resourcefulness of storytellers, under circumstances which are so unusual that many of the conventions which constrain their everyday behaviour are temporarily ‘interrupted’. For instance, the narrative maxim commanding tellers to protect ‘fragile’ aspects of stories need not be binding on first-person stories told in a context where a disaster has actually taken place, since recipients are faced with massive evidence for much that a teller tells them. This is in marked contrast to more ‘removed’ stories of the flood, such as the following: c) i B
1 The other day, the boys were all standing on the banks of the Ganges, when they saw— S 2 On the Dunlop waterfront—in the Dunlop +area+ B 3 Yes—where Dunlop is—they say a refrigerator floated past ... VAR (laugh) B 4 Can a refrigerator float? ALL (laugh) S 5 Perhaps it can [with mild sarcasm]. B 6 Impossible [laughs]. 7A steel almirah floated past—do you hear?—[laughs]—8 The whole thing’s very amusing. S 9 Then, yesterday—yesterday, those boys said—10 I asked them, how did a steel almirah float—11 they said, it wasn’t a steel almirah—it was a kather (wooden) almirah, so for every question. ... R kather 12 kãcher (glass)? S kather 13 wooden.
334
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
R 14 B 15 S 17 B 19 S 20 B 21 22 S 23 B 24 25 26 27 M 28 S 29 B 30 H 31 S 32 B 33 S 34 B 35 S 36 B 37 S 38 c) ii
K S B K
1 4 5 6
S 8 R 9 S 10 R 11 M 12
kath er wooden kather 16 So. ... a steel almirah floats by, a refrigerator floats by ... Lots of people are [said to be] collecting+ things—18 beds, almirahs and so on, all these things. ... But yes, we did see ducks being collected next to our house. ... Many ducks Some—from some farm—perhaps the farm was flooded— So the ducks. that were in the farm, all of them floated down the Ganges. ... ˜ pæk, ˜ pæk, ˜ [imitating quacking] pæk, Pæk spirited imitations] ˜ pæk—pæk ˜ ˜ pæk ˜ pæk—[more ˜ ˜ pæk ˜ sound. When we got up in the morning, what pæk So they all caught them ... some with nets, some with nets— They came down to the edge. ... Came down to the edge, and ...? Yes—captured many ducks. Caught many ducks Were they rescuing them or did they want to eat them? No, no, no. No, no. They’re still there in the house next to ours. They’re there in the house next to ours, but the others who’ve caught them have eaten them They’ve eaten them up. [laughs] And what fish they’ve caught! [and, etc. ... ]. I see, 2 Yeah 3 S lost a lot of books and ... Yeah And hamsters What about the hamsters? 7 They must have been an irreplaceable loss Yeah Yes, one of the hamsters died off— Not as a result Not immediately but it was ill. They were floating around. 13 Those two hamsters— weren’t they—
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
335
14 There were those two hamsters floating around in their cage. K 15 Well, they weren’t prepared for a Noah’s Ark. 16 you see, they’d with the best of intentions! VAR 17 [Laugh] R 18 Yes, it was a long time afterwards, that S came downstairs, about three hours later. S 19 I came downstairs after there was about a foot of water in the—20 I mean I was sitting upstairs and working and there was some shouting in the street but I didn’t think anything of it—21 I just carried on and it was only when I came down there was much tailer than inside the room B 22 Oh dear! K 23 You thought it was your neighbours who had some trouble, didn’t you? S 24 Yeah, I thought it was my you know [.a.] that [a:] 25 because our neighbour thought C 26 [Laughs] K [Laughs] M 27 the reaction people have to this sort of thing S 28 Yes. R 29 Yes, it is. 30 They had—they were actually sitting downstairs and he was gesticulating to people on the road, and they saw him and started laughing. S 31 You see—because you see—I think— VAR 32 [Laugh] S 33 Yes, well it is—it is a bit funny. Here is this man who is afraid to open the door and get out of the house. R 34 It was absolutely terrible. B 35 Naturally S 36 Because the water level is higher outside—37 if he’d opened the door it’d all come rushing—38- it >39 so he sat on top of a table, or he stood up on a table inside the house and you know, drew his curtains back and tried to appeal to the passers-by. ... R 40 [Laughs] S 41 ... to do something, and they found that sight funny, of a man trapped [laughs] inside a house with the flood waters swirling around, gesticulating you know—and trying to say something they didn’t quite understand ... B 42 [Laughs]
336
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
S R S R
43 44 45 46
M K M B M B M
47 48 49 50 51 52 53
I would have laughed you know. [Laughs] Well, I’m sure it is a funny sight. Well, you would probably have laughed and then gone there and tried to help. Well, yes, you know as I said I wish I were there. [Laughs] You wish you were there? [Laughs] No, I wasn’t there. You weren’t [Pause] there but you had to go ... Hm? You had to go? Yes, I had to go shortly afterwards but what I meant was you—you couldn’t have done anything ... [and etc.]
The first of these narratives was recorded in Calcutta, but the tellers A and B are recounting their experience in their home town in the Hoogly District where the floods caused some disruption but no devastation. The second conversation is recorded in Cambridge. Both examples share the feature in common with story b)i, that they have joint tellers who are Indians, marking again that concession to telling conventions in an ‘interruptive culture’ that I have commented on in the previous section. Unlike b)i though, the telling of each of these stories is designed to provoke laughter. A story, Sacks has suggested, is a package of information; it is selectively packed with features which the teller works to make ‘storyable’.9 Tellers sometimes design their stories so that they have the character of jokes or laughables (see example g) ii in Chapter 6). Being whimsical or witty in rendering an account of events seems to have the consequence that recipients do not question the story for being implausible or boring. In the first instance, B does take measures to protect his story about the refrigerator floating past by citing an eye-witness account—‘they say a refrigerator floated past’, and then questioning it himself , ‘Can a refrigerator float?’, but his selection of particular details ensures that people will laugh at his story. The rhetorical question, ‘Can a refrigerator float?’ does the job of eliciting laughter by drawing attention to the absurdity of the claim that a refrigerator was found floating down the river. Speaker S also cooperates with B in suggesting that the eye witness account of the flood 9Sacks H., ‘Aspects of the Sequential Organization of Conversation’, unpublished draft manuscript of book, p. 11.
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
337
which they are repeating falls into the category of a ‘tall story’ (see S’s line 9, where she reports that she herself questioned the account given by ‘the boys’). This story is therefore presented so that S and B not only allow, but actively encourage recipients to laugh at their story, by pointing out the ridiculous features of the story. By taking over the task of questioning obviously implausible aspects of their own story, I would want to argue that tellers are again displaying their attentiveness to a cultural or implicultural constraint that privileges joint telling over recipient questioning. Recipients are then free to simply join the tellers in combined laughter, virtually smudging the difference between tellers’ and listeners’ turns—in my view a characteristic of the ‘interruptive culture’ that I have posited—a prototypically Vac culture as it were, in its propensity to recombine. While there are many bouts of laughter during this story, one feature of the sequencing strategy stands out. Except at one point where there is a concerted effort at linguistic coordination from one of the listeners, and a joint ‘correction’ by both tellers S and B (lines 11 to 15, where the words kather and kancher are confused), there are virtually no other questions or comments from recipients arraigning the story’s fragility during the telling of this first story. S and B’s joint second story about the ducks floating down the river is also designed to provoke laughter, though this time the technique employed is not the one of eliciting laughter by pointing to their story as a tall one. Instead S and B vigorously come together in successive turns to imitate the loud and distressed quacking of displaced ducks as they are carried willy-nilly down the river. Now, there is an obvious selfpreserving sense in which the distress of ducks is seen to be comical in a way that a massive displacement of human beings from their homes is not. Both events are ‘storyable’, but tellers’ techniques for presenting them as stories have to be very different. With first-person stories of a flood in an environment where a flood has actually occurred, I have shown that the stories were not only presented in a way that used the environment as a conversational resource, but also that the stories were constructed so that a particular point of view was put across to a particular recipient. That is, the stories in a)i and a)ii were addressed to government officials, and the tellers accordingly designed these stories so that they were specifically oriented to the officials’ concerns. Ordinary people, said Sacks, work conversationally at being ordinary. In the context we are discussing, this remark may be elucidated in the following fashion: participants in any conversation, however unusual the circumstances, assume that the cooperative principle
338
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
of rational communication is being obeyed. Where the conversationalists involved are a government official and a village spokesman, their contributions to the ongoing talk-exchange are rational insofar as both participants orient to this fact. Both teller and recipient in example a)i are being entirely ordinary in that both recognize that A’s telling of his story is not quite gratuitous, and that the strategy which B follows in responding to A’s story is also one which must take cognizance of his own role vis-à-vis the teller; in this respect, therefore, it is true that their conversation is ordinary, normal, even banal. Stories about floods which just disrupt normal life without causing serious distress seems to require efforts at establishing a different order of ‘ordinariness’, namely camaraderie. They call for ‘packaging’ that will amuse recipients, especially if tellers are themselves directly involved in some way. In the present example, we have tellers who also have a first person account of the flood to offer but unlike the tellers in examples a)i and ii and b)i, they are not in an environment where they can point to any evidence for their story, nor have they been badly affected by the floods. Their strategy, therefore, is to select those aspects of the flood which might engage the interest of recipients because they are put together simply as a funny story or ‘joke’, thus distancing the event and warding off sceptical questioning by recipients. Any event is storyable but tellers have to make special efforts to render it acceptable to recipients. Tellers’ techniques, that is, for making the story into ‘something-for-us’ out of the ‘things-in-the-world’ which are disasters, depends very much on who the ‘us’ are, and what kind of a ‘disaster’ it is that they are making storyable. In the final example d)ii presented above, tellers S and R combine to tell a flood story about a neighbour on a Cambridge street who is stranded in his house and can’t get out. They stress how funny the sight must have seemed to others— ‘and he was gesticulating to people on the road and they saw him and they started laughing’ (line 29), and that anybody would have found the sight funny (see S’s line 33, ‘Yes, well it is a bit funny. Here is this man who is afraid to open the door and get out of the house’, and line 43 ‘I would have laughed, you know’). The story seems to be designed so that the ludicrous aspects of distress are focused on, and though teller R does remark in line 39 that it was ‘terrible’, the remark is not a wholly serious one, as B’s laugh after her, ‘Naturally’; following on R’s remark shows. The whole bantering tone of this conversation offers a great contrast to the conversations earlier in this chapter, though it is strikingly similar to c)i which also selects the funny aspects of a flood as ‘storyable’. Tellers S in c)ii, for instance, could have told a story about the books he
E X P L A I N I N G E N I G M A S F RO M E V I D E N C E
339
had lost, since he was given a lead to tell such a story by participant K in line 3, but he simply responds to K’s prompting with a ‘Yeah’. The question K asks in line 23, however, does seem to evoke a much more favourable response from S, and the story about their neighbour finally gets told by R and S from R’s line 30 onwards. This last chapter, then, presents just a few of the many ways in which tellers and recipients can organize the activity of story-telling with extreme sensitivity to the environment, while at the same time being guided by the overarching principles of rational communication. It shows how resourcefully tellers utilize those aspects of an event, and their experience of it, which enable them to interact best with their recipients. In short, it appears that fine complexity of listener and teller coordination cannot be reduced to any simple schematic representation. Structural descriptions of narrative as a basic conversational genre or ‘discourse universal’ are useful because they hold the mirror up to narrative itself as a species of natural theory. However, the pragmatics of context puts constant pressure on our theories of the ‘self ’ as we articulate them in our ‘ordinary’ conversations, forcing moment-by-moment changes in the shape of the narratives we relate. That is why, in Miller’s words, we ‘always need more stories’. Maybe, the following cautionary Indian folk tale, which has an implicature requiring no elucidation, can act as a coda to bring us back to the issues of narrative paradox, which seem to have floated far away and almost out of sight in this chapter. A grammarian once embarked on a boat, turned to the boatman and inquired, ‘Have you studied the rules of grammar?’ ‘No’, replied the boatman. ‘Then half your life has been wasted’, declared the scholar. Meanwhile, the river grew very turbulent. The boatman shouted to the grammarian, ‘Hey, can you swim?’ ‘I never had time for that’, answered the grammarian, ‘O grammarian’, said the boatman, ‘then your whole life is naught, for this boat is about to sink!’
The communal boat of narrative is a leaky one and its planks are continually being replaced so that one is never sure whether one is in a new vessel or a very ancient one, or even whether one is going to sink or swim when one embarks on conversational seas. All the three paradoxes of narrative that I have dwelt on in this book make, in their own way, this point about the uncertain pragmatics of narrative. Starting out with Searle’s Paradox of Fictional Discourse, I suggested that Searle’s dilemma can be dissolved not by lifting the felicity condition on the ‘truth’ of assertions in fiction but by treating both fictional or factual discourse as narrative performatives. Dennett’s Paradox of the Authorless Narrator then puts a cognitive slant on the matter by arguing that we are genetically
340
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
programmed to produce narratives. Although we might believe that we are intentional ‘selves’ producing our own stories, these stories are, in fact, being cranked out by a narrative programme. Such a narrative programme does not distinguish between fictional and factual assertions but simply attends to cultural self-preservation. Finally, my own Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick brings together Dennett’s cognitive emphasis with Searle’s performative one by analysing narrative as a fragile structure, its fragility mimicking the uncertainty, fragility and disaster-susceptibility of our own lives. All narrative is fragile insofar as its audience can question or put in doubt, the version of events given by the teller. Like the body of the goddess Vac, narrative is continually subject to both annihilation and reconstruction. What this book has focused on are the actual processes and theories which characterize that relentless break-up and gluing together, that gravitational attraction and centripetal disintegration of narrative parts. Narrative Gravity, in effect, has tried to extend the early notion of fragility as articulated in the ethnomethodological work of Sacks, by ultimately connecting it, via speech act theory, Gricean maxims and Lewisian conventions, to Dennett’s idea of a ‘self’ which grows through narrative accretion and meme-generation. Conversation, cognition, culture: three alliterative words that gravely weigh down the title of this book. Of these, conversation augments our sense of community and cultural belonging, while cognition or the psychological routines of inference-making and perceptual theorizing enables our sense of self. Amongst the many discourse formats invented by human cultures, narrative is perhaps the best adapted to allow every member of the species relatively safe, easy and regular practice in dealing with often very complex emotional states. It is also the chief conversational means by which we manage to give ourselves a causal, evidential, rational—even if necessarily illusory and fictional—account of the enigmatic fact of our existence. That is why this book has followed Vac in espousing the cause of narrativity, which is also, in the end, a narrative of causality.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
341
8
qQ CONCLUSION Final Narratives Sutras
‘I dwell in many places and enter into many forms’, declared Vac in the Rigveda. Today, as we surf through internet sites and hold polyphonic conversations with hosts of strangers, these ancient words seem to echo with a new intensity. For identity, it turns out, is wonderfully unstable on the net—a mode of communication that offers its users the opportunity to forge fresh narratives of the self, almost from minute to minute. Observe how quick we are, especially among the young, to succumb to this temptation—and the meme-etic adaptability of narrative appears obvious. Little further evidence is needed of the exploratory reach of narrative in theorizing various categories of ‘selfhood’. Net inhabitants routinely juggle—one might say ‘rig’—name, age, gender and location as they negotiate the chat-rooms of the world. Anyone who has conversed for intimate hours with, let’s say, a hermaphrodite called Robin Snakeskin aged 81 from Borobodur and then, sadly, drawn a total blank when she sought to resume contact with this fascinating creature, knows this to her cost. In the virtual universe of the net, there’s no doubt that body of Vac is being radically reconstituted once again—and how! says Vac. Yet, if Vac took it upon herself to initiate and direct the text of Narrative Gravity up to this point, it is now the turn of another speaker, equally steeped in antiquity, to close off the book. In the Sanskrit critical tradition, the word sutradhar (literally, ‘one who holds the thread or rope’) is a generic term for the chronicler or bard. John Garrett describes this ubiquitous figure in his A Classical Dictionary of India as a person ‘attached to the state of all men of rank to chaunt their praises, celebrate their actions, and commemorate their ancestry.’ The sutradhar, in short is a
342
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
classical performer of the Indian Rope Trick, a cultural appointee whose job is to keep the narrative spirit alive by skillfully controlling the puppetstrings or sutras of narrative. And the word sutra itself has a double meaning here, as is evident in a more extended passage from Garrett: Sutra—‘(From the Sanscrit siv, to sew, literally, therefore, a thread or string) is, in Sanscrit Literature, the technical name of aphoristic rules, and of works consisting of such rules. The importance of the term will be understood from the fact that the ground works of the whole ritual, grammatical, metrical, and philosophical literature of India are written in such aphorisms ... The object of the Sutras is extreme brevity; and, especially in the oldest works of this class, this brevity is carried to such an excess, that even the most experienced would find it extremely difficult, and sometimes impossible, to understand these aphorisms without the aid of commentaries ... Though there is no positive evidence as to the cause or causes which gave rise to this peculiarity of Hindu composition, the method of teaching in ancient India ... renders it highly probable that these Sutras were intended as memorial sentences which the pupil had to learn by heart, in order better to retain the fuller oral explanation which his teacher appended to them .... The manner ... in which up to this day, the Hindus are in the habit of keeping the leaves of their books together seems to throw some light on the name given to this aphoristic literature. The leaves ... are piled up, and, according to the length of the leaves, pierced in one or two places, when, through the hole or holes, one or two long strings are passed to keep them together. The name Sutra was probably, therefore, applied to works, not because they represent a thread or string of rules, but on account of the manner in which these works were rendered fit for practical use; just as in German a volume is called Band, from its being ‘bound’. That a habit deeply rooted outlives its necessity, is probably also shown by these Sutra works; for while the oldest works of this class may be called Sutras by necessity, there are others which convey the suspicion that they merely imitated [my italics] the Sutra style after the necessity had passed away, more especially as they do not adhere to the original brevity of the oldest Sutra ... fixed by Max Müller from 600 to 200. BC ...1.
From Garrett’s description we learn that: a) the Sanskrit sutras were distinguished by their extreme brevity and were hard to explicate without the help of extended commentary; b) they consisted mainly of grammatical rules and are likely to have been mnemonic devices; c) a tradition of oral transmission ironically constituted the core of the written tradition of the sutra; d) the material culture of the sutra consisted in a ‘book’ of leaves piled up like an untidy Dennettian narrative of self and pierced through with a single ‘thread’ joining them together; and finally, e) the sutras had their share of ‘modern’ fake imitators.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
343
Surely, as Vac would not hesitate to point out, the parallel is obvious. As the grammar-obsessed sutradhar of Narrative Gravity, I do not just inherit and appropriate several traditions of learning, I also sneakily contrive to offer a commentary on these great masters. But, being a mere upstart, I seem to have got the whole story back to front. In this book, the commentary came first, spanning eight long chapters, only now to be followed by certain ersatz sutras. Before we come to these sutras, however, we must return for one last time to the gurus who headed the various sections of this book. Narrative Gravity explores the anti-foundationalist, anti-essentialist idea that our stories make us up, rather than we (make up) our stories. This idea derives from Daniel Dennett’s insight that our basic identities are conferred on us by the myriad tales we hear and narrate throughout our lifetimes. The ‘self’, in this sense, is a ‘center of narrative gravity’ created by each individual at the intersection(s) where story-telling lines of force meet. Presumably, when these story-lines are physically erased in the brain by diseases like Alzheimer’s, there occurs a resultant loss of self-hood and a much ‘lighter’, almost negligible, sense of identity. That we do find such ghost-people amongst us strengthens Dennett’s case although he does not himself discuss these instances. Yet, even if it is true that we are born to weave stories, why is it that we are so ‘programmed’? Narrative Gravity attempted to answer this question by carrying the important but embryonic notion that stories are obsessive self-constructions to its (socio-)logical conclusion. My suggestion was that narrative—a universal genre found in every known human culture— functions as proto-theory. It works by introducing us to ‘primitive’ but foundational versions of biological theory (how the leopard got its spots); political theory (Robin Hood was a revolutionary who challenged the oppressive class-structures of a feudal society); moral theory (Cordelia’s ‘sin’ was to plainly tell ‘the truth’ and Lear’s to stubbornly refuse to hear it); aesthetic theory (the mirror on the wall in ‘Snow-white’ proved itself a dispassionate judge of beauty)—and so forth. That these one-line summaries are crude reductions of exquisite myths is not the point; the point is that the stories to which they refer perform, in essence, a function not dissimilar to the cultural ‘work’ done by, say, Darwinian theory for biology or Marxist theory for political science or Christianity for ethics or Platonic theory for aesthetics. That is, they present particular hypotheses about phenomena in the world and present a paradigm to explain them. Cognitively, narrative seems to have been designed as a evolutionary mechanism to probe experience and create competing theories about
344
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
the world, especially the world of emotional experience, which is so crucial to cultural survival. What narratives do is provide us with relatively lowcost means of taking mental risks. Consider, for example, our physiological reactions when we read a ghost-story or adventure fiction. Our palms sweat, our pulse-rates shoot up and our throats go dry, even as we ‘know’ that the words on the page are pure make-believe. We don’t actually have to go and climb that cliff or love that bounder in order to realize the dangers and aches inherent in these situations. Just imagine, then, how infinitely useful the ‘lazy machine’1 of fiction is: it extracts intellectual labour from us while giving us the illusion of enjoying our leisure. In this book, I contend that the growth of narrative as a mental structure and of fiction as a form of the ‘lie’ provide tremendous selective advantages to our species. They tie in causal, logical explanations of actual concrete ‘events’ with emotional affect in a powerful way, so that the ‘lessons’ taught to us as children, and then throughout our lives through stories, lay the cornerstones for most of our crucial beliefs and reactions. The first step in this argument, of course, was to make the obvious claim that narrative capabilities and the unique specialization of language in humans are crucially linked. This is what I did in Chapter I. Language gives us the ‘gift’ which grammarians call ‘displacement’—the ability to summon up scenarios that do not exist in the here and now. It gives us access to memories, fantasies and the future. As symbol-using creatures, we possess, so to speak, two very effective mental tools that help us arrive at a sense of ‘self’: one, grammar; two, narrative. That is, a narrative embedded in a cultural conversation has the same psychological importance as the sentence in grammar, in the sense that, just as all language rely on sentences to ‘construct’ the world for them, they rely on narratives to ‘explain’ the world to them. Narrative, that is, is a structure that introduces the question ‘why?’ and the connective ‘because’ into the world. Time’s arrow may be a physical illusion but it is psychologically and experientially real and story ‘sequencing’ basically reinforces this ‘theory’ that we as a species hold about the nature of time and its interplay with causality. A chief theme in Narrative Gravity concerns the cognitive tensions that arise within cultures when the basic temporal, linear, monologic ABCDEF ... structure of narrative is sought to be incorporated into the a-temporal, alternating, dialogic ABABAB ... mechanism of conversation. In such a situation a story is, paradoxically co-authored by its listeners. 1This felicitous phrase is from Umberto Eco’s Six Walks Through the Fictional Woods,
1993, p 49. Narrative is called ‘lazy’ because its lets the listener/reader do most of the work of inference-making and knowledge-creating.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
345
That is why the book has as its subtitle the three inter-related words Conversation, Cognition, Culture. The ‘conversations’ conducted in the book are between contending theorists such as Searle, Dennett and, immodestly, myself. The various chapters of the book were thus linked for me via what I call the Three Paradoxes of Narrative—Searle’s (how do words in fiction both have and not have their ‘ordinary’ everyday meanings?); Dennett’s (can there be author-less narratives?) and mine (why are narratives so good at making us accept hypotheses that clearly challenge commonsense? why is it useful to hold ‘competing’ theories as they are presented to us through our narratives? what possible pay-offs could such a risky intellectual strategy have?). With respect to this third ‘paradox’, I would say that the core chapter of Narrative Gravity is probably Chapter 5, which presents my own attempt at producing a tentative cognitive grammar of narrative. Despite these efforts, though, the question remains: who is the reader of such a volume as this? Why should anyone, but especially literary critics, be tempted to ‘dialogue’ with the cognitively inclined thinkers whose thoughts are discussed in this book? In general, it appears to be the case that literary theorists and cognitive scientists are not on speaking terms, so that exciting debates in one area may go unheard in the other. Sociologists and literary people know all about Propp, Barthes, LeviStrauss, Bakhtin, structuralism and the dialogic imagination but very little about Labov, Searle, Grice, Dennett, speech acts or story-grammars, and vice-versa. Yet, as Victor Hugo once said, it is easier to stop invading armies than an idea whose time has come! I believe that the time has indeed come when textual theorists must talk to cognitive scientists, psycholinguists and philosophers who, in turn, need to be persuaded that their theories can be successfully propelled into the ‘soft’ areas of literature and cultural studies. Recent research in narratology suggests explicitly that ‘whereas narratology began as a sub-field within structuralist literary and cultural theory ... [it] should [now] be construed as [a] resource for cognitive science.’2 Conversely, specific findings in the cognitive sciences on, for 2See, for example, D. Harman (1999) who aims, in a survey article, to ‘sketch out some of the implications of recent work in the cognitive sciences for narrative theory [and] ... consider how, inversely, current modes of narrative-theoretical inquiry bear on the field of the cognitive sciences’. Using the entries in the MIT Enclyclopaedia of the Cognitive Sciences (MITECS) as his base, Harman shows how a number of the topics covered in MITECS (animal communication, folk psychology, theory of mind [TOM], evolutionary biology, social play, causal reasoning, etc.) might be illuminated by research in narrative theory—and vice-versa.
346
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
instance, ‘mirror neurons’ in the F5 area of the brains of monkeys— roughly corresponding to Broca’s speech area in humans—seem to reinforce the idea, explored via the third ‘paradox’ in Narrative Gravity, that story telling could be a means of ‘reading the minds of others’. Narrative, according to this view, affords an inexpensive, everyday means whereby we may gain emotional practice at empathizing with others, as well as build a theory which ‘explains’ the future consequences of our acts. The fact that, in the higher simian species, the ‘same’ brain cells are activated both in the actual performance of an act and in just watching the action being performed, thus has enormous and exciting consequences for narrative theory and its embedding in human linguistic ability.3 In this book, I have tried to develop some of the basic arguments that might serve to shore up these vital links between the fields of cognitive science and narratology. For example, when I sought to produce original arguments that extend the scope of the Gricean theory of implicature to one of impliculture or the Austinian theory of the speech act to felicity conditions on the activity of story-telling, my aim was to modify these theories so that they could include narrative in a manner that interests philosophers of mind but does not bore literary people to death because the language used is too colourless and technical. To submit ‘hard’ cognitivist positions to a kind of Walter Benjaminesque reverie that might make them accessible and attractive to literary thinkers has been one of my main goals for this book. I do not imagine, of course, that I have succeeded but I did take the precaution of trying the book out among one of the hardest groups to please in contemporary culture—my graduate students (see Appendix V)—and found them, to my amazement, enthusiastically receptive. Such is the hold that narrative exercises. As I have already mentioned, my assignment in this ultimate chapter remains to knot together the book’s theoretical loose ends, a metaphor that the paradox of the Indian Rope Trick naturally suggests. To 3See in this connection, Gallese, V. and Goldman, A. (1998) ‘Mirror Neurons and the Simulation Theory of Mind Reading’ and Rizzolatti , G and Arbib, M. (1998) ‘Language within our Grasp’. According to V.S. Ramachandran, another researcher in the area, mirror neuron studies lead to fundamental questions about the acquisition of culture in human communities—‘their emergence and further development in hominids was a decisive step’. The current hypothesis in the cognitive sciences seems to be that ‘mirror neurons’ provide the brain architecture that might help explain why we can ‘feel what others feel’, the sources of our empathy with others. My own conjecture would be that these abilities also enable us to construct mental representations of ourselves as ‘intentional agents’ via the complex linguistic device, primarily, of narrative. Such a conjecture is keeping with the idea that humans as a species happen to be linguistic, story-telling beings who forge their individual and communal senses of selfhood via narrative performance.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
347
accomplish this task, I have chosen to call upon the textual device of the sutra. Finally then, the bits-and-pieces below are culled from the whole of Narrative Gravity and simply strung together for readers like my students, and unknown others, who constitute the multiple co-authors of ‘my’ narrative. Of course, the objections to this strategy are also obvious. Why these particular sutras and not others? What about the ‘other’ gurus, those mentioned in the book, but not given nearly enough space: Barthes and Bakhtin, for example? And how about the fact that mimicking the sutra methodology in a book like this involves so much pointless repetition, made laughably easy by the cut-and-paste methods of modern wordprocessing? Such repetition merely amounts to using the sutras like a student’s highlighter pen, but shouldn’t this high-lighting be left to the reader? The author after all has already had her say—and so forth ... Yet, to these protests, one might offer the rejoinder that a reader is quite free to leave the sutras below untouched and confine his criticism to the preceding text, if he happens to prefer the linearity of the gnomon to random gaps in a gnomic string. And who is the reader, anyhow, in a text that claims, in essence, to be co-constructed? In either case, what matters is the interpretative skill and effort that’s always needed to make patterned sense out of potential gibberish. Below then, the body of Vac, always a puzzle, to be reassembled—or not—as one chooses ... 1. Structuralism: the impulse to dissect and label the body of Vac, to impose order on ‘squirming facts’, motivates both our fascination with binaries, mirroring the alternating ABABAB ... structures of conversation as well as our strong intuitions about linear sequencing, reflecting the temporal ‘and then’ ABCDEF ... structure of narrative. 2. Within the context of a cooperative speech community, ‘two sources’ of ‘natural order’—the narrative and the conversational—are pulled together. Both resources are structurally open-ended and infinite. Departures from these dominant orders are ‘naturally’ noticed, since they demand extra cognitive effort at sense-making. 3. Narrative requires a meta-theory of time. Because we hold fast to the belief that, despite Einstein’s equations, perceptual and physical time both flow always forwards, we are able to play games with time—to cut up, re-sequence and re-label parts of the body of Vac and then recombine them in a linear mode. 4. If psychological experiments seem to confirm that events can ‘happen’ for us milli-seconds before we actually perceive them via our senses, this is so because we are already in the grip of some powerful narrative ‘theory’; on the other hand, if events happen
348
5.
6.
7. 8.
9. 10.
11. 12. 13.
14.
15.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
to us seconds after, then the narrative theory we were operating with may have been too ‘weak’ to link the event-sequence we have experienced. Narrative is perhaps our most efficient way of packaging our perceptions of ‘selves’ as ‘strung together’ across time. Sorting events into the temporal format of stories enables easy storage, easy retrieval and easy cultural exchange thus confering a distinct evolutionary advantage. Should anyone try the Gedankenexperimente of attempting to construct that mythical Indian rope-trick of an extended sentence, she will end up before long, like it or not, with a compelling narrative turn to her sentence. This is a testable prediction. In the structural picture of narrative, both the external, political state of the world and the internal, plural state of mind, are factored out. Co-constructed stories are necessary to the resolution of the Indian Rope Trick Paradox of Narrative, because they yield the vital conversation resin (expressions of appreciation, you-knows, ums, and I means) that glue the sundered body of Vac together again Narratives are produced in multiple drafts but by multiple authors. Audience reactions, the twitters, chirps and trills of participation, do not just influence a teller’s story but are structurally a part of the story. Evaluative devices serve the function of answering the ever present question ‘Why are you telling me this story?’ The Labovian ‘Coda’ is an vital interactional device to return the narrative time to the ‘present’. ‘We find that most narratives are so designed as to emphasize the strange and unusual character of the situation’ (Labov and Waletzky). ‘It seems plain enough that people monitor the scenes they are in for their storyable characteristics. And yet the awesome overwhelming fact is that they come away with no storyable characteristics’ (Sacks). A conflict? Myths and legends cannot be just more ‘expert’ versions of stories in everyday talk. For, the story-teller in a face-to-face situation has to be alert from moment to moment. She has to be a ‘cog’ spinning in perfect unison with other cogs in the freewheeling conversational wheel. This requires extraordinary expertise. Story grammars cognitively reconstruct the point-of-view of the listener or story-recipient via the progressive inferences he makes during the telling of a story.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
349
16. Three types of inferences are made during the telling of a story— logical, informational and evaluative. 17. Nietzsche’s towering superman is actually a fragile construct of subs, paras, metas, transes, alters, uns and semis. Much the same analogy holds for the ‘strong’ image of structuralism. 18. Far more cognitively salient than the core elements of narrative, it turns out, are its peripheral accoutrements. In conversational narrative, the structure of a story is actually fragmented so as to perversely give away some of the best performative parts to listeners! 19. The aesthetic of narrative, its cultural call for attention, is about a subversion of the natural order of happenings. It is an often violent unsettling of the logic of expectation. 20. Truth on one leg is a monument; on two, it is travelling theory. For this reason, it could be challenging to equip truth with that second leg, which is surely—fiction. Fiction is theory at its most untrammelled. 21. In general, pragmatic theories today (Relevance Theory, Gricean Theory, Classical speech act theory, a Davidsonian Theory of Metaphor, Brown and Levinson’s Theory of Politeness etc.) confront one crucial problem. How are R-intentions, or implicatures arising from (linguistic) communication, to be restricted? What principles or norms do human beings use to prevent an impossible proliferation of implicatures? 22. The basic unit of pragmatic study is the ‘utterance’, yet the notion ‘utterance’ seems too scattered, vague and impoverished to be analytically useful. An alternative unit which pragmaticists could consider basic is the narrative, constituting both the upper bound and the main structure of pragmatic analysis, just as the sentence works as the largest unit or boundary structure as well as the central object of grammatical inquiry. 23. What makes the narrative vitally different from the sentence is precisely its pragmatic propensity. It is a structure devised to probe into context. 24. Narrative sets in motion processes of hypothesis formation, premise correction and reasoning among Hearer/Readers, whose task it is to deduce the point of the story from the evidence that Speakers/ Tellers present to them by attributing intentional stances to them. 25. Fictions come in neat narrative packages. 26. All narratives work as ‘emotion prompts’ but most especially fiction. Fiction is conventionally associated with those leaky perlocutionary
350
27. 28.
29.
30. 31.
32.
33.
34.
35. 36.
37.
38.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
effects (curiosity, surprise, fear wonder) which seem to indicate that illocutionary boat is not so water-tight after all. Fiction is always ‘false’ or ‘pretended’ and therefore the prototype of the ‘parasitic’ speech act. Fiction is the most ‘performative’ of acts since its existence is typically predicated on its announcing itself as fiction, and that’s that, in the same way as a promise is a promise. So it falls into the mould of an ‘explicit performative’ quite easily, enabling strict ‘felicity conditions’ to be formulated for it. Fictions ‘make believe’ and thus constitute exploratory mechanisms in a way similar to scientific hypotheses. They enable us to investigate counterfactual worlds, without getting caught up in what Austin described as tedious and irrelevant questions of ‘truth’ and ‘falsity’. Searle: Stories, fictional and factual, considered as illocutionary acts differ their direction of fit. Searle’s Paradox: If the meaning of the functional sentence is determined by the linguistic rules that attach to the elements of the sentence, and if those rules determine that the literal utterance of the sentence is an assertion and if there is a literal utterance of the sentence, then surely it must be an assertion: but it can’t be an assertion since it does not comply with those rules that are specific to and constitutive of, assertions. The true paradox of fictional discourse is the physical and psychological perlocultionary effects it has on us. Our hearts beat faster, our palms sweat, our feet beat a tattoo, while all the while we are fully aware that the experience we are going through is false. Our attention should be directed, not at the fiction/non-fiction nexus at all, but at the more crucial dichotomy between the act of telling a story, either fictional or non-fictional, and the act of making an assertion. Austin: Even an unwieldy genre like the novel can be a possible speech-act, where the phrase ‘A Novel’ indicates that a connected sequence is to follow. Narrative is a structure that converts talk into text. ‘Maximally effective’ communication in narrative routinely requires tellers to reflexively attend to a double goal of self revelation and self concealment; it would seem to be self-defeating to ‘tell all’. The keyword ‘interesting’ (as opposed to ‘boring’) in estimates of narrative is ‘interesting’ because of its very nebulousness. Sperber and Wilson: the world is full of bores. Narrative in conversation is always a spectator sport, where the
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
351
speaker is required at all times to show awareness of being watched, heard, and assessed. Any attempt to resolve the problem of speakers’ and hearers’ access to indirect meanings must involve us in the painstaking endeavour of considering not just isolated individual speech acts such as greetings, promises and assertions, but the nested contexts in which they occur. One such ‘nest’ for any individual speech act is the conversation within which it is placed. Another much larger, nest could be the sets of cultural and normative beliefs that speaker/ hearers bring to the telling of a story or any other speech act. That is why we need Nair’s concept of impliculture in addition to generalized Gricean implicature. In what seems like an anachronistic mockery of the Principle of Expressibility, Nietzsche said—‘What can be thought must certainly be a fiction.’ The act of sharing makes a fictional thought ‘real’ since a speaker changes from an epistemic to an ontological stance when articulating her thoughts. Ethically, we’re into dubious terrain with recorded conversations because we are ‘eavesdropping; here, as it were, on private conversations, on personal evaluations, and turning them into ‘data’— the fodder of ‘theory’. How do we reconcile the need to consider not just the abstract attempts of philosophers at reconstituting ‘natural’ communication but conversationalists’ own finely honed skills with the need to minimize the invasion of private stories, private selves? The hearer’s task is not simply to recognize but to respond to the speaker’s meaning by extending its implications and scope. It is this ‘engagement with the present’ aspect of conversation that no researcher can replicate when studying the transcript of a story. The teller is absent, as in a literary narrative, and this severely alters the conventions of interpretation. And yet, a researcher is as unavoidably committed to interpreting the transcript of a narrative as is the hearer of a story told in real time in a casual conversation. Expressibility as a capacity of language to match the resources of thought is not an issue in Gricean theory; interactive notions like explicitness, explicibility and expressiveness, however, may well be. Explicitness, a criterion I derive from the Quantity Maxim, would require that a hearer settles on an interpretation of a speaker’s ‘meaning’ which minimizes the incompleteness and vagueness inherent in that utterance. Explicability, which I derive from the Maxim of Quality, would require
352
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
52.
53.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
a hearer to infer from any utterance of the speaker which she prima facie gauges as metaphorical or untruthful, some additional meaning or gloss consistent with the speaker in fact having been truthful when she appeared to be lying. Expressiveness, deriving from the Maxim of Manner, involves those features which Wittgenstein christened ‘imponderables’. Tone, gestures, facial expressions, quality of voice, as well as appropriate choices in vocabulary and sentence patterning, would all affect a hearer’s patterns of inference in this regard. Interpretation involves explaining the (linguistic) actions of others in terms of a schema of attributed desires and beliefs; in this sense, interpretation is a guarantor of ‘autonomy of meaning’, since there can always be more than one intended use’, in fact myriad uses, for any utterance. The speaker always gets the benefit of the doubt when her crime, so to speak, is communicative incompetence. This is where Davidson’s ‘principle of charity’ comes into play. Nietzsche: ‘Desire and force between them are responsible for all our actions; desire causes our voluntary acts, force our involuntary.’ Austin’s inspired variation on this Pascalian theme is to close the gap between desire as self-motivated and force as other-initiated. In Austin’s analysis, desire is force; it is the spur to action. When the language game is narrative, the complexities of performativity and pleasure, fiction and fact, explicability and expressivity, desire and force, tend inevitably to overlay the more simplistic dichotomy between truth and falsity. Nietzsche recognized that the concept of truth becomes vital and interesting only when it is realized that there are at least two, and possibly several ways, of expressing a ‘truth’. My suggestion is that the form of narrative is felicitously adapted to exploring the multiple, often paradoxical, ways in which ‘truth’ is presented. Because narrative is the typical site of fiction, the ‘truths’ used by adults across cultures to socialize their children come encoded as narrative; and the ancient battle scars of communities, to which only fictions can do honour and justice, turn out almost always to be recorded in narrative form. Furthermore, the store of social wisdom— what we like to think of as wisdom rather than ‘knowledge’ or ‘reason’—is also made less dreary, more palatable, more plausible, through the intervention, specifically, of narrative fictions. Speech act theory is haunted by its Carnapian ancestry. The avenging
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
54.
55.
56
57.
58.
59. 60
61.
353
ghost of grammar shows up each time pragmatics seeks independently to resolve its to-be-or-not-to-be Hamletian placement. Cabin’d, cribbed, confined by its philosophical antecedents, the Austinian performative simply cannot contain the endless supplements of meaning that Derrida wishes to stuff into it; nor can it hold all the literary baggage that Paul de Man wants it to. Nair’s reformulation of Derrida’s objections to Austin: Every performative comes with quotation marks round it. That is how we recognize it. Only because there have been previous instances of performance, can we recognize that the present instance is ‘infelicitous’. In this respect, the felicitous infelicity of ‘original’ ‘poetic’ language is no different from ‘ordinary’ infelicity. Ergo, Derrida can come to the satisfying conclusion that, given Austin’s own premises, there exists no such item as a ‘pure’, ‘original’ performative. The essential performative feature of perlocutions is that they have to be indirectly achieved. The fact of the matter is: one cannot frighten, annoy, amuse, people simply by declaring: I frighten/ annoy/ amuse you ...’ Try it!. All the long lists of emotion verbs in every human language just lie heavy and inert—sleeping beauties—until activated by ‘the kiss’ of narrative. Herein lies the cognitive value of the ‘simple’ story across cultures. If ‘disguise’ is such an essential feature of pretending, can fiction which wears its falsehood on its sleeve, really qualify as pretended assertion? What is being hidden? Plagiarism is literary theft, and it involves passing off someone else’s words as one’s own. In this respect, it is related to pretence in the way that Austin suggests the acts of ‘impersonation’, ‘imposture’ and ‘posing’ are. Authorship is typically erased in the large majority of narratives that circulate in a society. Even if one were to pretend, to one’s children for instance, that the strange terror of Hansel and Gretel was entirely the product of one’s own unique genius, this would not constitute an act of plagiarism. That is so because: where there is oral transmission, a story does not strictly retain an ‘original’ linguistic format; and where no exactly replicable linguistic format exists, there can be no rights of ownership; and where there is no ownership of words, no possibility of plagiarism exists. Conversational conventions concerning rights over third and first narratives—and narrative points-of-view—act as natural safeguards
354
62.
63.
64.
65. 66. 67.
68.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
against plagiarism. The ‘I’ narrative can be said to have an ‘original’ linguistic format, but if it is reproduced by others, unless a wholly extraordinary memory for semantics, syntax and phonological surasegmentals is involved, there is no question of exact simulation. So in oral discourse, ‘authorship’, if any, can be said to attach only to the first articulation of a narrative, after which plagiarism, strictly speaking, is virtually impossible. And this in turn would strongly imply that each (re-) telling of a story is necessarily an ‘original’ act in and of itself. Anti-Derrida? The basic form of the illocutionary act is the simple F(p); and the five basic types of ‘illocutions’ or linguistic ‘acts’—directives, commissives, declaratives, exclamatives and representatives—make up the fundamental building blocks of intentional meaning across the languages of the world. If narrative qualifies as a speech act, its efficaciousness as a performative derives from its perlocutionary effects. As a conversational object, a story may be defined as a bundle of perlocutions. Narrative ‘power’ or ‘force’ comes, not from an ‘indirect’ imitation of the speech act of assertion, but from the special feature that it conventionally secures perlocutionary effects. Any narrative within a conversation could be viewed as a miniature three-act play, with a turn-taking sequence of three parts (preface or orientation, main turn or complicating action and resolution and/ or coda). And as with a play, applause is conventionally required, because the whole raison d’etre of this sort of performance is to gain the admiration of audience, for pulling off an unlikely, an almost magical stunt—that of showing, a la the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick, that communication for communication’s sake is a logical possibility in which we take delight. Granted our weakness for other versions of ‘the truth’, it is not then surprising that we all, as Nietsche suggests, ‘sometimes tell a lie’. Narratives and ‘imponderable’ gestures which characterize the telling of stories, rehearse ‘truth’ for us in ways that hold our attention. Unlike illocutionary acts, which are allegedly ‘performed’ just by virtue of being appropriately uttered, implicatures and perlocutionary acts both depend crucially on the notion of ‘interpretation’. If Grice’s theory of conversational implicature is read as one of perlocutionary effect, this immediately puts narrative perlocutions in the context of a ‘talk-exchange’ where implicatures arise from conversationalists’ structure of expectations.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
355
69. The ‘Speakers’ and ‘Hearers’ that are among the main props of speech act theory, are conspicuous for their genderlessness, their classlessness, their absolute lack of dialectal and regional specificity and the flawlessness of their ‘performances’. 70. We explain textual details by adducing narrators and explain narrators by adducing qualities of real people. What is the status of ‘real people’ within the explanatory framework of the speech act? 71. If we try to think ourselves into the minds of our pets, or of animals to whom we attribute high ‘intelligence’ (vervet monkeys, chimps, dolphins etc.) the only way to succeed in this enterprise is via anthropomorphism. In this sense, to universalize is to ‘get personal’, and inevitably to be ethnocentric. 72. Pitting speech act theory’ against ‘Rhetoric Language’ in a de Manian sense presents us with a metaphysics. Mere human notions of the moral and the rational, such as sincerity, cooperativeness trust, tolerance, etc. come up against an uncanny force that cannot be ‘read’ at all in terms of these notions. 73. Readings of literary texts, above all, demonstrate the fundamental ‘unreadability’ of language. They reveal the aporias between the textual creation of meaning and the destruction, or at any rate undoing, of this meaning in any attempt to ‘understand’ it. Herein lies the deep connection between ethics and aesthetics—language at its most beautiful and seductive it is also unstable, unreliable, unreadable. 74. Note that we cannot (or do not?) prosecute ‘language’ for the crimes of, let’s say, plagiarism or perjury; we only indict persons A or B for these offences. 75. Deconstruction reinforces the reader’s sense of a ‘battle’ to be fought out between ‘theory’ (speech act theory in particular) and ‘language’ (especially literary language); between human ‘personality and linguistic ‘patterns’; between anthropomorphic ‘morality’ and ‘rationality’ and non-human ‘tropologies’ and ‘senselessness’. 76. A ‘self’ is socially exhibited through a range of speech acts. The asymmetry between ‘real’ first-person, face-to-face communication and ‘unreal’ third person authorial presentations may call up, not just different interpretative norms but also different moral conventions. If all our acts are displays of the self, they all involve role-playing and ‘imitation’, but the here-and-now ephemerality of the nonliterary speech act imposes a great urgency on conversationalists born of their shared knowledge that the present is fly-away, not possessed of narrative gravity.
356
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
77. The non-preservability of our everyday speech acts, not excluding our narrative acts, dictates our attitudes to the ‘privacy’ of these acts. Precisely because their tellers and listeners were not aiming at public ‘display texts’, narratives privately exchanged can be said to reveal narrators at their most vulnerable, with their guards down and their personal preoccupations up front. Unlike the literary narrator, a conversationalist is not required, by convention, to ‘watch her words’. This is why the ‘right to privacy’ becomes a moot moral issue when analysing ‘real’ versus ‘literary’ narratives. 78. The ‘author’ of a literary text is, conventionally, not taken to be remembering and recreating, but creating and presenting (i.e. making ‘present’ to readers events not culled from the real past). Unlike the teller of a conversational story, she therefore cannot be indicted for her failure to remember the past ‘correctly’. As Roland Barthes puts it in another context, what distinguished a novel or a poem is that it is literally ‘about nothing’. Perhaps we could say—in literature everything is presented and nothing is remembered. 79. Exploring conversational narrative brings to the surface the submerged moral codes and judgements that underlie our everyday speech acts. Part of the function of story-telling is to unsettle, at least momentarily, some of our regulatory moral assumptions. It is in this connection that notions such as pretence, plagiarism, parasitic speech, equivocation, and dissimulation come up in relation to the fictional narrative act. 80. Argument from Burge: Since our explicational abilities do not exhaust the concepts they describe, we are always subject to social correction in our use of language to describe the world. In this respect, language is unquestionably social. 81. Looking to others to ‘set standards’ in language is a ‘psychological necessity’ for a species that has language as its chief means of presenting premises and drawing inferences for purposes of conceptualization. Without such social reliance, language would be a code whose meaningfulness remained vastly under-utilized, an ideal tool lying idle. Divested of its enormous communicative potential, language would also be pitifully reduced as a vehicle of thought. 82. Extending Searle’s Chinese Room argument: a programmed computer can manage to ‘tell’ a story but can it respond spontaneously and variably to listeners’ interventions, and extrapolations from its own text? Can it produce that magical binding glue of discourse required for any successful performance of the Indian Rope Trick?
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
357
83. If we lived in a world where we could read each other’s thoughts— had transparent screens across our chests, for example, Grice’s Maxims of Quality and Quantity, which enjoin us to be informative and truthful respectively, would be rendered redundant. The price we put on a piece of cheese may be arbitrary but there is a non-arbitrary, rational relationship between the price of the piece of cheese, its weight and taste, and the fact that we live in a world where lumps of cheese do suddenly grow or shrink. Similarly, there is in the language games of our ordinary communication a relationship between the ‘arbitrary’ rules attaching to particular cultural games that we establish, and the ‘rational’ rules of behaviour that are forced upon us by the kind of world we live in, between the Lewisian concept of socially agreed conventions and the Gricean notion of naturally determined maxims. 84. Lewis: Use of language belongs to a class of situations with a conspicuous common character: they involve coordination problems. Conventions help solve coordination problems in language games by reducing the imperfectness of information regarding any recurrent situation S’ among members of a population P. 85. What is the main difference between conventions and maxims? Maxims are a privileged subset of the myriad conventions by which a culture lives. Conventions are convenience rules guided by mutual self-interest, whereas norms or maxims have an altruistic element. 86. There are loads of conventions which do not, on the face of it, qualify as maxims: eating with knives and forks, wearing saris not skirts, using a white flag to signal peaceful intentions, not pointing at people etc.; yet every convention always aspires to the status of a maxim, which would confer on it more meme-survival value in a culture. 87. Nair, after Barthes: Barthes suggests that every narrative text possesses the conventional structural capacity to contain periods of ‘rest and luxury’. These, presumably, are areas of the text where the reader can doze or relax on a ’park bench’ as it were. She is temporarily relieved of the need to pay stringent attention to the textual ‘action’. Barthes’ terminology of ‘catalysers’ and ‘indices’ versus ‘cardinal functions’ and ‘nuclei’ (conceptually similar to Labov’s distinction between the formal and functional elements of a narrative) is meant to reflect these differences in the pacing of a text. How we place our park benches within a story or the uses to which we put them, depend, of course, on the ‘arbitrary’ literary conventions established within cultures.
358
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
88. Taken together, Gricean maxims and Lewisian conventions offer a model which characterizes most of the features of story-telling observed through conversational analytic methods. 89. Grice’s four Maxims are denoted by the pseudo-Kantian categories of Quantity, Quality, Relation and Manner: Searle’s suggestion is that Grice’s account can be amended by adding to it rules that make explicit the ‘literal’ meaning of an utterance as well as its non-natural meaning. 90. Levinson: Grice’s maxims do not on their own provide the ‘knowledge that is necessary to make the appropriate inferences’ from particular activities in talk, since these maxims ‘are supposed to hold across different types of activity’. 91. For Grice, the concept of rationality is itself deeply implicated in a code of social obligations. The pattern in the Gricean formula is: rationality implies cooperation; cooperation implies obedience to the reciprocal moral imperatives of the maxims; reciprocal obedience in turn implies that morality is to be understood as fundamentally social, rather than a matter of purely individual vision or choice; and, thus, finally, that the psychology of rationality, its mental status and moral hold over us, can be deduced from the social phenomenon of everyday conversation. 92. Dennett presents a paradoxical situation where it is possible for a tale to be produced without a teller who must take responsibility for it. Dennett’s clever scheme does, however, need an intelligent listener. And it is here that Grice comes in, with his emphasis on a smart listener who can ‘make sense’ of almost random information. 93. Corresponding to each of Grice’s four maxims, there are those peculiar to narrative. The Super-maxim for Narrative: ALWAYS PROTECT THE FRAGILITY OF YOUR NARRATIVES BECAUSE YOU ARE THEREBY PROTECTING YOUR VULNERABLE ‘SELF’. Corresponding to Grice’s Maxim of Quality or Truthfulness is the Narrative Maxim: BE PLAUSIBLE, EXPLICATE! (provide orientations, engage in ordinariness, make your stories ‘something for us’). Corresponding to Grice’s Maxim of Quantity is the Narrative Maxim: BE SUMMARY AND EXPLICIT (provide abstracts, didactic, proverbial or other generalizations as required, so that people ‘get the point’ of your story). Corresponding to Grice’s Maxim of Relevance is the Narrative Maxim: BE INTERESTING AND EXCITING (locally occasion your stories, produce tellables and include story-internal evaluators, allow listener participation in the turn-taking sequence).
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
359
Corresponding to Grice’s Maxim of Manner is the Narrative Maxim: BE MEME-CONSCIOUS AND EXPRESSIVE (produce culturally appropriate narratives, be as ironic, reflexive and ‘literary’ as required, so that your story, which is an extension of yourself, is as well adapted as you can make it for social survival and transmission). One way to conceptualize these Maxims of Narrative Exchange is to think of them in relation to a cline of hearer-judgements from least to most implausible, boring and irrelevant. 94. Impliculture versus implicature. What does the idea of ‘impliculture’ buy us? Briefly, it allows us to focus on the relations between: i) cultural specificities ii) those things left unsaid within a cultural community iii) the community as a holistic, meme-sharing conversational group.
95.
96. 97.
98.
Because the Gricean system encourages one to think in terms of universal deductive implicatures, it minimizes attention to social differences. My concept of impliculture, or cultural implicativeness, is one through which we can theorize particular cultural communities as groups engaged in a complex polyphonic conversation. A great deal depends on conveying the unstated, or the understated, in such an ongoing group conversation since insider status within the community would come from listeners’ picking up specific implicultural meanings, rather than simply deducing the general Gricean meaning implicatures. Implicature prevents outsider ‘freeloading’ and thus safeguards cultural wealth. Paradoxically, it appears that a study of ordinary narratives proves that ‘undesirable’ maxim violations and ‘desirable’ perlocutionary communication are inseparable. This is what gives narrative its double power and its durable complexity. The noun ‘narrative’ both contains, and is bounded by, the noun ‘native’. The ability to create and comprehend stories is a species-ability with enormous social consequences. How do stories confer identities on ‘selves’? And how do the ‘selves’ iterated in our stories contribute to the meme-status of stories, their cultural survival? A narrative grammar must explain issues of coherence, formulaic repetition, expectations of chronology, causality and affective tension among audiences, as well as culture-specific differences in semantic interpretation. Such a grammar—structuralist or speech act—stories the status of a specialized discourse.
360
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
99. Inferencing by listeners gives consists in active interrogation of tellers’ narrative strategies. The structure of a story is understood not so much as a retrospective given as a creative challenge to both listeners and tellers. 100. Implicatures are worked into conversations by tellers; inferences are worked out from conversations by listeners. This is a basic division of labour in all communicative activity. 101. Thinking about the notion of inference, we could begin by referring to an etymology suggested for another key word—cognition, deriving from the Greek ‘gnomon’ which means ‘sundial’. Reading time—whose linear structure we know to be of utmost importance in decoding any narrative—off a sundial means setting in motion a chain of inference. It means having to infer a quite abstract entity—time—from nothing more than a pole, its shadow and the positioning of the sun in the sky. 102. Every narrative has, so to speak, a gnomon coiled within it. As the narrative unwinds in its structural linearity, this gnomon of time lets loose dynamic implicatures which listeners must infer in order to derive pleasure and profit from the story. How do these inferences alter the structure of the world for human beings making their interlocking moves as ‘cogs’ communicating through the machinery of conversation? 103. Narratives offer a natural harbour, a kind of safe house for the memes of a culture. 104 Narrative is a fertile breeding ground for fictions, but of all the fictions that narrativity fosters the most persistent, according to Dennett, is the fiction of ‘the intentional stance’. The paradox of the authorless narrative that Dennett relates is specifically directed at defusing this fallacy. 105. Dennett: Whether we intentionally choose to tell stories or not, we end up telling them, because that is what we are genetically programmed to do. In this sense, all narratives are authorless. 107. Just as the spread of specific cultural memes mimic the laws of genetic behaviour, so story-telling by individuals only enacts a preset programme. 108. Unlike Chomsky on sentences, Dennett stresses the activity, or performativity, of story-telling, as much as its abstract structure He sees all classes of narrative as performing a psychological ‘trick’, not dissimilar to my own ‘paradox’ of the Indian Rope Trick. Narratives, according to Dennett, creates the illusion that there is an authoritative ‘self’, a ‘central meaner’ who is the ultimate pro-
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
361
ducer of the strings of narrative that each of us endlessly ‘extrude’. 109. Where there is no real centre of ‘selfhood’, our stories help us imagine a centre—of narrative gravity. 110. Nair’s model of narrativity suggests a shift towards a consideration of some main types of temporal, causal, evaluative and informative inferences themselves as constituting the central nodes of a narrative tree. This rather radical alteration permits the incorporation of elements of cultural differences in genre and allows for cognitive shifts in perceptions of semantic/pragmatic appropriateness, while retaining the advantages of a ‘grammar’. A set of inferential rewriterules for narrative might read: N(arrative) TS IS C(ausal) I(nference) I(nformational) I(nference) E(valuative) I(nference) X,Y A,B,C, P,Q,R
→ T(emporal) S(tructure) + I(nference) S(tructure) → X and then Y ... n → (CI)->(II)->(EI)->(CI) ... n (recursively) → X cause Y, Y cause Z ... n → A,B,C ... n connect X,Y,Z ... n → A,B,C, and/or X,Y,Z connote P,Q,R ... n → any clause or phrase within the sequence of the candidate N → any clause or phrase outside the candidate N
111. The genres of ‘the short, short story’ and ‘the tall, tall tale’ is a useful group of formally contrastive narratives with which to illustrate the theoretical speculations on offer. 112. Minimal narratives, because of their generic brevity, require extensive inference-making on the part of listeners. Likewise, tall tales which are deliberately implausible, require inferences of a special sort by listeners. 113. Inferring an evaluative judgement from the story, when it is not made explicit by the teller, enables the listener to: a) actively participate in the construction of the narrative b) display her cultural knowledge and membership-status, her meme-awareness c) cooperate with the teller in resolving inherent textual enigmas. 114. A crucial difference between Nair’s and the earlier story grammars is that it does not simply assign propositions in a given story to nodes such as Orientation, Complication, Resolution on a set tree.
362
115.
118.
116.
117.
119. 120.
121.
122.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
It allows for, indeed depends on, fresh inputs from the listener to keep the story moving. It is this adoption of a listener’s or hearer’s perspective that helps set narrative processing within a broader Gricean framework of communicative cooperation in general. A schema which emphasizes the listener’s role in creating and ‘gluing together’ the parts of a narrative through her active inferences is in keeping with Dennett’s idea of ‘authorlessness’. The onus is shifted here from the narrator’s shoulders to those of the listener. It is she who carries the burden of establishing narrative connectivity, of proving to herself that she has ‘got the point’ and the body of Vac is rendered whole again. Labov: The listener’s job is continually ask of the story-teller—what’s the point, why are you telling me this? The hearer’s job is to ward off this question. Herein, the import of ‘danger of death’ narratives. It’s always relevant to say: ‘I saw a man fall off a bridge today ...’ There is a qualitative contrast between the functions of left hand and right hand nodes on Nair’s inferential tree. The latter moves the story on, the former is a vast mnemonic storage bin. Iteration or repetition plays an incalculable part of the inferencemaking process, as well as in structuring narrative. The puzzle is simple: since repetition presents redundant information, why repeat? Why waste cognitive effort? Well, repetition basically says: ‘Look again. You may have missed something the last time!’ Repetition also forces us to reconsider first mention within the text rather than outside it. It thus calls for structure-internal reorganization of the conversation or ‘story’ as well as a contextual search when it occurs. There are two fundamental reasons why speakers might want to indicate the opposite of what is said. First, these strategies allow listeners much greater scope for interpretive play; by complicating the conversational situation, tellers heighten the interactional stakes. Talk is thereby turned into ‘text’—a possible meme-structure that can subsequently be passed on by listeners as a joke, a witticism, a story, or some other ‘tellable’. The second reason is that narrative imaginatively reconstitutes our workaday world. By doing so, it momentarily ‘challenges’ logic and enables both tellers and listeners, for a fragment of time, to hold contradictory beliefs in mind. It is this capacity to evoke the thrill of the ‘in two minds’ cognitive state that the device of repetition, so common in stories, shares with narrative as a structure.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
363
123. Repetition is an inference forcer, a tug at the listener or reader’s mental sleeve. This is what gives repetition its power as a literary device, or in the vocabulary of story-grammars, its potential as ‘evaluation’. 124. There are marked and unmarked instances of repetition. The distinction between these is culturally learnt. 125. Repetition formally looks like a 4th order inference which simply duplicates information already presented; as such, it is overdetermined and redundant. 126. A successful narrative is one where tellers’ implicatures and listeners’ inferences dovetail in obedience to the Maxims of Conversation. 127. Sperber and Wilson: context is a notion cognitively defined in terms of the knowledge a hearer already has and which she uses to interpret all utterances, not just those which ‘violate’ some conversational norm. The Principle of Relevance is always in operation and governs all our speech acts. 128. There could be a distinction between Grice’s cooperative principle which may well be psychologically motivated (or substituted by the even more psychologically rooted principle of relevance in an ‘improved’ version of Gricean theory, as Sperber and Wilson suggest), and the socially motivated maxims. 129. To ask for a tall story in the face of imminent death is an act of psychological self-preservation. 130. Fiction, as the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick asserts, perennially reassures us. By making other worlds dramatically ‘real’, stories persuade us that all may not be lost. Maybe, even dying and pain are illusions that can be substituted by other more entrancing illusions. The ‘self’ is free in a narrative universe; it can wander eternally where it pleases and thus defy death. 131. Stories are fragile, according to Sacks, to the extent that listeners can question their veracity and tellability. The first strategy enables listeners to arraign the implausibility of the narrative, the second strategy allows listeners to be critical of the boring qualities of the tale, its unexciting ordinariness. 132. Narrative can be graded by listeners along a cline of fragility, ranging from the weakest narrative (most implausible and boring) to the strongest, riveting narratives (neither implausible nor boring). In an ‘inferential’ grammar of narrative, it is possible to relate this cline of ‘fragility’ with the ‘degrees’ of inference postulated by the storygrammarians. These run from first order (least constrained) to fourth order (most constrained). Matching up these two gradations we get:
364
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
NARRATIVE FRAGILITY
INFERENTIAL CONSTRAINTS
Weakest Story: Boring and implausible
4th order inferences Duplicate information, overdetermined and unimportant 3rd order inferences: Irrelevant, determined but not logically important 2nd order inferences: Relevant and determined, important to the progress of the story Ist order inferences: Elaborative, underdetermined by the text of the story.
Next Weakest: Boring but not Implausible Somewhat Stronger: Implausible but not boring Strongest Story: Neither implausible nor boring
133. Inferential moves—evaluation implicated in informational sequences, information indicated in causal sequences, causal sequences following from temporal assumptions, and then recursively, informational sequences generating causal ones—are vital to a narrative grammar. 134. Our competence as ‘narrative speaker/hearers’ as well as ‘native speakers/hearers’is attested by the ingenuity and cultural skill with which we decode story inferences. Inferences, on this view, are to be regarded not as the incidental by-products of a narrative system, but as constitutive of the system itself. Not only are we narrativeextruding pasta-machines in the Dennettian mould, but we are also inference-making machines. 135. The attraction of an inferential model lies in its attempt to mimic the flexibility which tellers, listeners and analysts display in their interpretations of narrative form. The image of narrative projected by such a model is that even the most minimal of stories can be analysed with maximal complexity, given a theoretical approach that values inferential enrichment over interpretive economy and partial indeterminacy over absolute predictability. 136. Stories are food for the ‘epistemic hunger’ of our species. This metaphor is, however, obviously incompatible with the notion of ‘perfect fulfillment’. Just as we cannot be ever satisfied with a single meal, or even multiple ones, even if they are absolute gourmet delights, but have to keep eating at regular intervals all our lives, so we cannot ever be fulfilled by binges of narrative activity. 137. As a species, we are not meant to suffer from narrative bulimia, although some of us do. This is so as long as we have a ‘self’ to sustain and do not move into autism, Alzheimer’s or other similar selfdeleting conditions.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
365
138. If it true that our ‘selfhood’ is sustained by narrative, then the demand for ‘morals’ from our stories, those precepts by which we may ‘live’, seems more explicable. Morals in a narrative are the mental equivalent of the nutritional value of a meal. 139. Conversation somewhat like sex, is an interlocking device for selfperpetuation. Apropos of hunger and the life-sustaining properties of those materials we classify as ‘food for thought’, the alternating rhythm of the conversation-machine could be likened to the jaws of a perpetually famished shark—forever moving in an open-shutopen-shut, ABABAB ... movement, always ready to take in more feed. There is no end to our appetite for talk, indeed can be no end, structurally speaking. 140. Conversational analysis (CA) is essentially a methodology—an ethnomethodology. It consists of highly specialized techniques for exhibiting that conversational materials of practically any sort are ‘orderly’, that is, ‘methodically produced by members of a society for one another’. 141. Schegloff and Sacks: ‘A problem is proposed as a problem for conversationalists; we are not interested in it as a problem for analysts except insofar, and in the ways, it is a problem for participants.’ 142. The aim of CA is to develop methods analogous to those used by conversationalists themselves, as sensitive and methodical, so as to make explicit the ‘problems’ faced and tackled by conversationalists. 143. Conversational analysts relate the ‘local’ tendency towards sequencing in set pairs to the ‘overarching’ pairing established in the abstract by the ABABAB structure of conversation itself. 144. The ethnomethodological understanding of conversational structure offers a striking illustration of the manner in which a method, as well as an ideology, of analysis can be founded on the use of a new technology. It appears that, not only are the human species story-telling inferential machines, but they also perceived through their machines. 145. Conversely, the ethnomethodogists did not just use a machine— namely, a tape-recorder—for their researches. They also suggested that the object of their studies—namely, conversation—was itself a machine. 146. Note the analogy here with Nair’s metaphor of human beings as communicating cogs in the factory of culture, churning out all sorts of memes to serve our ‘illusions’ of selfhood. 147. Cassette tape recorders in the sixties changed the way in which one could observe a conversation; it was no longer necessary to
366
148.
149.
150.
151.
152.
153. 154.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
rely on individual or collective memory in order to reconstruct what had been said. Now every conversation could be replayed exactly, as many times as necessary for analytic procedure. The conversational analysts’ reams of tape showed that precisely those parts of a speaker’s ‘turn at talk’ that were naïvely imagined to be dispensable are in fact crucial to sustaining its structure and momentum. The pauses, the ums and ers, wells and you knows, lapses into silence, reformulations and overlapping speech that we would automatically ‘erase’ from an ideal representation of our linguistic performance turn out to be really important in ‘holding a narrative together’, as well as in structuring the changeovers between speakers and hearers in a conversation. One could conjecture that these intervening bits and pieces make up that elusive and ‘invisible’ magic glue with which the magician in the ‘Indian Rope Trick of Narrative’ binds again the severed parts of the goddess Vac. They are the solution to the mystery of reincorporated structure. A story in conversation is ‘an extended object’, meaning that it is distributed across several turns in a conversation, some of which belong to the teller and some, equally, to the listener(s). Hence, it logically has to be controlled by all the participants in a conversation. Conversational analytic manoeuvres with tape-recorders—memorymachines—were meant to sustain their claims to manufacture a theoretical ‘apparatus’ not by ‘imagining’ them, but on the basis of recorded ‘facts’. These facts about the enjambment of sentences into a complicated conversational structure force us to reassess the manner in which we extricate theoretical concepts such as ‘sentences’ and ‘words’ from evidence, while allowing concommitant concepts such ‘utterance’ and ‘turn’ very little power, although they seem to possess as much ‘factivity’. Three African proverbs: ‘Talking with one another is loving one another’; ‘He who begins a conversation does not foresee its end’ and ‘A proverb is the horse of conversation: when the conversation lags a proverb revives it’. Lewis again: ‘A convention of language is a regularity restricting one’s production of, and response to, verbal utterances and inscriptions.’ The trick is use the pre-existing ABABAB turn-taking system precisely like a Lewisian convention—that is, as a pattern of behaviour so regular that it constrains the choice of ‘moves’ by conversationalists when a ‘language-game’ such as story-telling is played out within its confines—and thus actually facilitates coordination.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
367
155. It is a general rule about conversation that it is your business not to tell people what you can suppose they know. So if one asserts a fact one can assume the listener knows one is obviously pointing to the relevance/significance of the fact, not telling him the fact itself. 156. Sacks: The kind of lessons that stories often contain can be delivered perfectly well in the form of a lesson, a proverb, an idiom, a general expression, a general truth, like, ‘make hay while the sun shines’. 157. Generalizations, like metaphors and proverbs, encapsulate the collective wisdom and moral apprehensions of cultures. They represent the store of experience that a senior member of the community may have to offer. 158. Hedges around the teller’s utterance are not irrelevant; they reveal an awareness that a sharp ‘unhedged’ response might follow. The hedges highlight this contrast of mental attitudes; they demonstrate that the dynamics of the conversation does not just consist of wooden generalizations and prepared responses but is extremely flexible in its sensitivity to the cognitive states of participants. 159. Stories are subject to a linguistic law of ‘necessary incompleteness’. This is so because all discourse genres, of which narrative is arguably just the most prototypical example, are embedded in the cognitive context of conversation. 160. Language may primarily be a tool of solitary thought but discourse genres—jokes, riddles, lectures, novels, poems, rap, tall tales etc.— cannot but be at least ‘two-party’. They are specifically designed to turn talk into text—that is, to call up perlocutionary inferences. No audience, no narrative completion, as the Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick stresses. Consider the following Abstract (often consisting of a generalization): Orientation: Complicating Action: Resolution: (may involve a generalization) Evaluation: (may include generalizations and several turns) Coda: (often consisting of a generalization)
Typically a teller’s turn Often a shared turn Typically a teller’s turn Typically a teller’s turn Typically a listener’s turn Typically a listener’s turn
161. If the ‘self is a centre of narrative gravity’ that there are likely to be at least two cognitive categories of narrativity—stories to the self and stories to the other, the daily and the daylight.
368
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
162. Ordinarily, the routines of our day to day activities make up stories not worth telling to others, yet central to our sense of self or ‘the way our world is organized’. These ‘hidden’ narratives form a cognitive substrate to the narratives that we do share with others. 163. Being ordinary is a normative, Lewisian concept. The task of ‘being ordinary’ is one we engage in at all times, whether alone or with others, while ‘doing being ordinary’ involves the additional burden of interaction. 164. Sacks: It is an interesting fact to consider that recipients can apparently decide that a story was correctly told without going out and checking the actual circumstances in which it occurred ... That is to say, recipients do not feel at the mercy of the teller to decide what the world is about. And apparently tellers have ways, and need to employ ways, in order to produce a story that is recognizably correct or at least plausible. 165. Nair: A story is plausible insofar as it is credible, probable, likely, possible and/or convincing; it is true insofar as it is verifiable, factual, correct and/or demonstrable. And given that most recipients cannot ‘go out and check the actual circumstances’ in which a story occurred, it is the former set of criteria which are standardly used to judge a story. 166. Whereas a strong case can be made for the ‘truth’ of a story being independent of whether recipients believe it to be true or not, a story cannot be said to be ‘plausible’ unless recipients in particular conversational contexts judge it to be so. 167. Tellers must weigh down their wild, flyaway stories with the ore of everyday fact, give it gravity as it were, otherwise their stories are in danger of being stricken by an unbearable lightness of being. They become ‘too interesting to be interesting’. 168. Over-emphasis on the extraordinary by story-tellers often has the paradoxical consequence that recipients are bored. 169 If the teller constantly stresses the fantastic nature of the events or experience he is recounting, recipients’ responses, deeply dependent on presumptions of ordinariness, are hampered. They lose interest in the language-game because their moves become limited to gasping ‘How astonishing’ or ‘goodness me’ in every turn; their whole inference-making process is wrecked and they can no longer participate actively in the telling. 170. Since stories typically put the ‘selves’ of teller and listener into conversational contact, they offer a series of glimpses into the
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
171.
172.
173.
174.
175.
176.
177.
178.
369
organization of inner landscapes. Mental territories are opened out and we get to compare how weirdly similar our minds are, how extraordinarily ordinary. Good adaptive self-preserving behaviour would consist in running in the opposite direction when confronted with a bore. At the same time, situations routinely arise when interaction is unavoidable. Ideally, the maxims and rules of communication should equip one with the cognitive wherewithal to protect oneself if pinned against the wall by a mega bore, or even a minor one. The only really foolproof preventive against boredom is to provide ample space with the turntaking system for genuine inferences— that is, to activate in listeners’ heads’ the right-hand arm of Nair’s inferential model of narrative. The best, ‘least fragile’ stories (interesting and plausible), leave plenty of ‘slots’ for recipients to make elaborative inferences. The triad of concepts, ‘fragility’, ‘plausibility’ and ‘boredom’ are interactional in the basic sense that recipients are required, by the obverse corollary of the Super Maxim of Narrative commanding tellers to protect their stories against listeners’ charges of implausiblity and/or boringness, to identify the points of fragility in a story. Being a ‘good listener’ consists in having excellent vigilance reflexes. The same continuum of reflexes that allows a listener to go into a ‘automatic’ story-appreciation mode when hit with a boring story, also alerts her to possible violations of, say, the Maxim of Quality, when an over-ambitious story is placed on the conversational counter. The great pleasure that ‘good’ narratives give listeners is that they can truly ‘get into’ the story. By monitoring its points of fragility, they can get to the non-fragile core of the narrative—its ‘point’. It is a common cognitive stance: to be ‘desperately desperately keen’ and show it by shoving fantastic stories down the throat of one’s prospective audience. This creates ‘trouble’. It arouses in listeners an instinct for self-preservation, when a teller’s stories overwhelm one to the extent that one can no longer ‘bear it’. The inferential system is simply overloaded. Given that story recipients are presented with a number of particular ‘facts’ which are not immediately verifiable, the quality of ‘plausibility’ on the part of tellers is the only rational alternative to the quality of ‘truthfulness’. The ethnomethodological analysis of narrative deals, in essence,
370
179.
180.
181.
182.
183 184.
185. 186.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
with the methods which members of a culture use to work themselves into that culture from day to day, from moment to moment. Whether we consciously will it or not, our psychological propensity to turn our narratives into morality engines is what in the end drives that troika of conversation, communication and culture which is our chosen vehicle in this book. Nair wants to replace Dennett’s multiple drafts by a single self to co-constructed drafts by multiple authors. These endow a ‘talk-text’ with multi-dimensionality and give to what Ochs calls the ‘rough drafts’ of an individual’s ‘story’ the ‘authority’ of community. Narratives of the self grow by accretion, accumulation. They enable us to rehearse what we learn about the world. These are the hundreds of narratives that we repeat daily to ourselves. They are easily forgotten and seldom consciously articulated. However, most of the explanatory and interpretive activities that we engage in are guided by the structure of expectations that self-narratives engender. Narratives to the other are collectibles, tellables. They are the coins of social exchange. As artful forms, they enable us to exploit, in subtle and powerful ways, the narratives to the self that we have already acquired. A corollary: had we no self-narratives, it would be extremely unlikely that we would have other-narratives. Self-narratives are hidden, meant for learning and storing patterns of experience, while other-narratives are manifest, ‘display texts’, meant to be appreciated by others. Both kinds of narrativity are crucial to the formation of a self, but they are not, in general, interchangeable. In other words, if one were to narrate one’s daily routines from brushing ones’ teeth in the morning to changing into a nightdress one would have a prescription for friendlessness! Self-narratives only become salient ‘insofar as they depart from the baseline of our ordinary experience’ (Chafe). It goes without saying that what constitutes ‘ordinary experience’ in one culture, may not be so in another. Nevertheless, if one were to generalize, one could maintain that the most obvious forms of narratives of the self are a) dream sequences and b) quotidien business like eating, sleeping, making love, talking to friends, smiling, being annoyed or in pain etc. A tempting hypothesis is that self-narratives of type a) correspond to the genre of the fictional; and those of type b) to the genre of the factual narrative.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
371
187. Narrative to the other are also either fictional or factual. If fictional they tend towards the ‘literary’, i.e. texts which exist for purposes of interpretation and hypothesis formation; if factual, they tend towards the ‘extra-ordinary’, i.e. texts which confirm that an unexpected event has occurred. 188. Narratives of the other often function as counter-examples to the store of experiences built up in narratives of the self. Danger-ofdeath narratives, which deal with a predicament that is finally to be experienced by all of us, but which is resistant to routinization, are therefore an excellent example of narratives to the other. 189. All talk or conversation can be defined as an interventionist structure wherein speakers’ intentions and hearers’ interpretations collide. A continual tension exists between the structure of conversation which has an alternating ABABAB ... interchange between speakers and hearers, and the structure of narrative which is linear and sequential, with a progressive ABCDEF ... concatenation of units. 190. The teleology of narrative and that of conversation are at odds; therefore, problems arise when narratives have to be ‘fitted’ into conversations, or vice-versa. Interpolation as well as interpellation are thus normative in a conversational narrative. 191. A narrative is a natural meme-holder and meme-generator. This is its evolutionary purpose. 192. Narrative fiction is a culturally legitimate form of the often stigmatized activity of lying. As basic human abilities, lying and pretence find their most elevated expression in narrative form. In cases where these abilities are impaired, as with autistic individuals, there is an accompanying loss of socio-cultural intimacy. The ‘self’ nurtured through narrative play and pretence, is typically isolated in autistics. 193. The cognitive value of narrative is that it performs ‘binding’ functions and ‘projects’ back and forth in time, as well as ‘spatially’ between an individual’s experiences and those of others, thus helping him to ‘read’ them correctly and develop a full-fledged theory of mind. 194. Narrative links the cognitive worlds of verbal and non-verbal experience; as an aide memoire, it provides logical templates for the storage and explanation of ‘illogical emotional reactions’. 195. Has narrative theory any voice at all within the fraught domain of politics? 196. The dismemberment of the body of Vac is often gruesomely real. In the wake of an influential historiography based on the belief
372
197.
198.
199.
200.
201.
202.
203.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
that a postcolonial state is designed to disinherit, and possibly assault, the very people who are its supposed protegées, theorizing from a safe distance about ‘boring’ and ‘implausible’ stories may simply be inadequate. For a better historiography, it is important not only to recognize marginal discourses but also long-standing and deep cultural affinities between those discourses. In order to grasp the full force of the violence perpetrated today against large sections of humankind, it is crucial to concede the relationships that exist between seemingly independent categories of calamity—the ‘natural’ and the ‘denatured’. Although no human agency can be blamed for the suffering inflicted by a natural disaster, insofar as these incidences are a) increasingly predictable and thus preventable, and b) traumatic for large numbers of people, any modern government which does not work to ameliorate their effects becomes a morally indictable agent. Very different kinds of agency are involved in ‘natural kind’ and ‘nominal kind’ disasters, yet the responses of a postcolonial state tend to reduce them to one narrative format, thereby strategically reaffirming its ‘impartiality’, while simultaneously absolving itself of guilt. The philosophical categories ‘nominal and natural kind’ direct inferences in relation to three inter-related levels of narrative. In disaster narratives, three strands of story: the official, the localized and the historical—plait, and then curl away from each other The official or grand narrative of disaster is deliberately constructed in order to distance the state from the particularities of pain. Disastertime is that estranging time when history is forced to recognize the special character of those victims to whom the state is handing out its ‘aid’. Only true victims are to be granted aid; not all subalterns are in these special circumstances equally privileged. The point of the subalternist argument is that during the plague years the human body became a metaphoric as well as physical site of conflict between the colonial state and a subject people. Disasters, natural and nominal, seem to affect the same segments of Indians repeatedly—the economically deprived urban lower classes, often migrants from an India-wide hinterland, and the rural poor. Their narratives are the narratives of a brave and stubborn survival against great odds, and are structured entirely differently from official accounts.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
373
204. Women’s subjectivity is narrativized around a thematics of survival rather than of self-expression. These voices seem to be heard only in times of dire calamity, when they are, ‘instantly’ historicized by a self-serving interpellation on the part of the state. 205. The genderlect of women in contemporary rural Bengal confronting the kind of archetypal ‘act of god’ that a flood is, exemplifies distinctive linguistic features. These characteristic linguistic markers enable us to make connections between affect or emotivity in the causal structure of narrative and the cultural role that women’s narratives may have in controlling and conditioning others’, including the state’s, attitudes towards suffering. 206. Nair’s tape-recordings show that women’s speech displays, in contrast to men’s idiom, the following features: 1) 2) 3) 4) 5)
more exclamatives (ore baba, ma go, ki bhishon, bap re bap); more comparators (khub, bhishon, boddo); more silences, breaks, reformulations; more interruptions, resulting in more joint tellings; more politeness forms, address and agreement markers (ki didi, boshben naki, ektu jol khan) 6) more deictics (eta,ekane,eidje)
207. In short, women have ‘more of everything’. This bundle of conversational features may be seen as a cultural guide to woman, and the role she plays in narrativizing her community. 208. How do you recover a lost past? Only through words, words that recall and sometimes enrich and amplify the memories of the possessions, emotional as well as physical, that one held in the antediluvian past. 209. Floods of stories are often produced in response to requests for stories of floods. 210. In the case of a flood or fire, the physical evidence has vanished forever. All has been devoured by calamity. In this tabula rasa world, therefore, infinite imaginative possibilities are opened up—one can, so to speak, theoretically remake oneself through one’s narratives. Yet, the situation is far from being one of painless makebelieve. The calamity itself is historically attested. State, institutions, news agencies, all work it into their operations. 211. Narratives accounts of both Partition and flood constitute a community’s fragile resources for recuperating historical agency— and they display one shared characteristic. Both ‘nominal kind’
374
212.
213.
214.
215. 216.
217.
218.
219. 220. 221.
222.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
and ‘natural kind’ narrators invariably treat the government, even when it has been elected by them, as a power as unpredictable and unknowable as God. The ‘simple’ narratives of the people turn out to be extremely sophisticated in their modes of subversion. They express anger, pain and frustration while at the same time managing to contain and conceal these wrenching emotions. On this depends their precarious survival. People supposedly robbed of agency by historical forces and by historians’ representations, can produce subtle narratives which in their turn rob their oppressors of person-hood and individualism, by, for instance, the ironic device of turning them into pseudo-gods. Disasters are unpredictable, if not by definition then at least by implication. They constitute a sudden violent disruption of the even tenor of existence, hence their status as enigmatic ‘tellables’. A plurality of disasters, all disasters—past and future nominal and natural—can be condensed into one event in history: The Disaster. Quotations, inserted forcefully into the body of a text can themselves be regarded as repeated metaphors of violence—both violating the text, as it were, and gendering it. If Althusser’s focus was on interpellation, then Blanchot’s might be said to be interpolation; Blanchot enters the postcolonial narrative brandishing, as he himself phrases it, a ‘radical unquotability’. The academic historian cannot help but mimic in significant ways the narrative stance of the government official. That is, he is usually at a considerable distance from the pain and agony experienced by the victims of disaster and thus faces a challenge in attempting to provide an adequate representation of their suffering. Can a historian in the pursuit of his profession ever manage to obey Blanchot’s italicized admonishment: Learn to think with pain? Within your own community, your suffering is already ‘known’, experienced; there is thus no explicit need to ‘tell’ shared pain. The paradox is that fiction can and indeed must describe individual protagonists, if it is to move hearts. Disaster assumes identity in a creative text, comes to have what Shakespeare called ‘a local habitation and a name’. History, on the other hand, necessarily involves numbers. Numbers make history, as every historian recognizes—so many hundred killed in an earthquake, so many murdered in a riot. But in order to render emotion, you need the individual mode, which can only be literary and artistic. That is the paradox.
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
375
223. The tension that exists between history and literature involves generic differences of scale, and of interiority. One is centrally concerned with the description of mammoth events, and the other with representation of individual emotion. Perhaps this is too simple a turn, but it does show why the dilemma of ‘the historian with a heart’, is inherent; it can never be completely resolved. 224. Disasters, natural and nominal, by reason of their scale, are the stuff of history. 225. Agency is a slippery customer, going underground in most ‘onrecord’ narratives. 226. When natural disasters will happen again may not be entirely predictable, that they will is. 227 From the fearful iteration of tense, the past recurrently predicting the future, comes the tension of flood narratives, their ancient place in the literature of most cultures. Literary renditions of disaster from the epic of Gilgamesh to the legend of the god Krishna who held up Mount Govardhan to protect the inhabitants of Braj from the flood waters, seem to have a teleology, a deontology, an ethical purpose. 228. The role of the copious narrativization that surrounds disaster in all societies is not to be understood as merely instrumental—that is, as achieving straight-forward political or pragmatic ends. Rather, these narratives are primarily theoretical. 229. Resistance may paradoxically be expressed as much through ‘keeping up’ a conversation as through silence. Conversational cooperation is never to be misread as ideological cooperation. 230. Conversational cooperation is often explicable in terms of ‘care of the self’, the motivations of self-interest and self-preservation, that pre-programmed survival instinct so central to Dennett’s Paradox. 231. Disaster-narratives can be seen as explanatory paradigms setting out the human consequences of disaster, and suggesting its causes. They are not so much explained by their tellers intentions as explanations for them. 232. The extreme sophistication that marks the oral narratives of flood produced in the villages of West Bengal—an enduring sophistication that seems to mimic the myths of flood that characterize many early cultural accounts of creation itself—stem from a basic impulse towards theory built into the ‘linear’ structure of narrative and supported by the ‘argumentative’ structure of conversation. 234. While we may infer ‘ political resistance’ in these narratives what is truly exciting about this resistance is that it is actually a resistance to other theories about the causes and consequences of the disaster
376
235. 236.
237.
238.
239.
240.
241.
242.
243.
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
being explained—the colonial theory or ‘narrative’ about the deltaic floods in Bengal for example. Narrative speech acts are also speech pacts. Narrative is a species of natural theory; when it is embedded in a conversation, there is the added advantage that often we witness a critique of the explanation in offer. Recipients agree, via the turntaking mechanisms of conversation, to give a particular ‘theory’ a hearing, so that they may exercise their rights to knock it down. In an environment where scenes of recent disaster are plainly to be seen by recipients, tellers do not always tell stories which simply outline the actual circumstances of the disaster, because this would, in Gricean terms, be redundant. Rather, they resourcefully use an unusual advantage that they happen to possess in these circumstances. They can actually point to the evidence. Deixis thus becomes an important explanatory aid. Invisible evidence of long term devastation can still be conversationally pointed at, and pointed up. There is, literally, more to such utterances than utterance than meets the eye. Conversations reveal how adaptable tellers are, how attuned to making the best use of environmental conditions. Rather than concentrate on the single aspect of the misery and damage caused by the floods, narrators can simply use gestures of witness in order to corroborate, legitimize and sustain the logic of their narratives. Narrative helps us to survive and preserve our essential identities at times of the gravest physical and mental danger by creating logical solutions to the problems presented by our surroundings. Thus they conform to the contours of both Dennett’s paradox and that of the Indian Rope Trick in that they literally offer structural, logical and psychological lifelines to those in danger of drowning. Naïve ‘theories’ developed through a ‘villagers’’ narrative can turn out to be exactly in keeping with the latest trends in academic thought. Cultural habits have structural repercussions both for the theoretical design and performative strategies adopted by narrators so as to prevent their ‘alien’ recipients—government officials, research students—from questioning their ‘fragile’ stories. Our stories are a measure of exactly how fragile and how tough our ‘selves’ within a culture are. Conversationally, there may exist ‘interruptive cultures’. For example, in the pan-Indian cultural context, there seems to be a high structural
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
377
tolerance of interruptions and joint performances. Subcontinental speakers are, ceteris paribus, less likely to assert their right to a turn by saying ‘Let me finish, please!’ than speakers in, say, ‘Western culture’. Interruptions are read as signs of cooperative behaviour—i.e. helping the speaker along—rather than rude attempts to cut into someone else’s conversational space in such societies. 244. Interest is likely to diminish exponentially if every danger-to-death story makes the same point over and over, however poignant. So we are back to the insight that it is imperative that tellers use whatever resources they possess to make their stories into ‘something for us’ over and above their interest as dire first person narratives of disaster. Tellers use the structure of conversation as well as cultural resources in tandem to achieve this difficult task. 245. Most tellers ‘allow’ recipients to talk interruptively throughout their extended turn for the obvious reason that these interruptive moves within the telling sequence serve the function of demonstrating their continued participation in the conversation, and their interest in the story. 246. Interruptive moves, which function as evaluations of the story and articulate the perlocutionary effects of the story on recipients, are thus fairly important within the ‘speaker’s’ telling sequence, despite the fact that recipients often use these moves to arraign fragile aspects of a teller’s story. 247. By taking over the task of questioning implausible aspects of their own story, tellers display their attentiveness to a cultural or implicultural constraint that privileges joint telling over recipient questioning in some societies. 248. Joint co-constructed and supportive witnessing by tellers help avoid both Labov’s ‘so what?’ question and indictments of the tale as possibly false; in story-telling as in life, there’s strength in numbers. 249. Recipients are free to simply join the tellers in combined laughter, virtually smudging the difference between tellers’ and listeners’ turns in an ‘interruptive culture’—a prototypically Vac culture as it were, in its propensity to recombine. 250. Communal narratives, jointly told, represent a theoretical consensus in a culture. 251. The narrative maxim commanding tellers to protect ‘fragile’ aspects of stories need not be binding on first-person stories told in a context where a disaster has actually taken place, since recipients are faced with massive evidence for much that a teller tells them.
378
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
252. Sacks: a story is a package of information, selectively packed with features which the teller works to make ‘storyable’. 253. Stories about floods which just disrupt normal life without causing serious distress seems to require efforts at establishing a different order of ‘ordinariness’, namely camaraderie. They call for ‘packaging’ that will amuse recipients, especially if tellers are themselves directly involved in some way. 254. Any event is storyable but tellers have to make special efforts to render it ‘an object of desire’ for recipients. Tellers’ techniques, for example making the story into ‘something-for-us’ out of the ‘thingsin-the-world’ which are disasters, depends on whom the ‘us’ are, and what kind of a ‘disaster’ it is that they are making storyable. 255. One of the most frequent ways in which tellers seem to protect fragile aspects of their ‘danger-of-death’ narratives is present their material as quite unremarkable. Another way is to compress length and detail so that recipients have fewer opportunities to challenge them. 256. The communal boat of narrative is a leaky one and its planks are continually being replaced so that one is never sure whether one is in a new vessel or a very ancient one, or even whether one is going to sink or swim when one embarks on the conversational seas. All the three paradoxes of narrative that I have dwelt on in this book make, in their own way, this point about the radically uncertain nature of narrative. 257. Searle’s dilemma in his Paradox of Fictional Discourse can possibly be resolved, not by lifting the felicity condition on the ‘truth’ of assertions in fiction, but by treating both fictional or factual discourse as narrative performatives. Dennett’s Paradox of the Authorless Narrator puts a cognitive slant on the matter by arguing that we are genetically programmed to produce narratives. Although we might believe that we are intentional ‘selves’ producing our own stories, these stories are in fact being cranked out by a narrative programme that does not distinguish between fictional and factual assertions but simply attends to cultural self-preservation. 258. The Paradox of the Indian Rope Trick connects Dennett’s ‘cognitive programme’ with Searle’s ‘performative hypothesis’ by analysing narrative as a fragile structure, its fragility mimicking the uncertainty, and susceptibility to disaster in our own lives. All narrative is fragile insofar as its audience can question or put in doubt, the version
C O N C L U S I O N : F I N A L N A R R AT I V E S S U T R A S
379
of events given by the teller. Like the body of the goddess Vac , it is continually subject to both annihilation and reconstruction. 259. Narrative is perhaps the chief conversational means by which we manage to give ourselves a causal, evidential, rational—even if necessarily illusory and fictional—account of the enigmatic fact of our existence. As Vac might put it—the cause of narrativity is also, finally, a narrative of causality. And here, at the odd number 259, the sutradhar tosses Vac once more up into thin air. Narrative Gravity ends; the Indian Rope Trick begins ....
380
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
8
qQ APPENDIX I The Flood
The following is a brief extract from the official description of the floods which form the chief topic of conversation in the data presented in the ‘guru-less’ Chapters VII–VIII: Floods in West Bengal—Statement by Chief Minister in the Legislative Assembly—20 November 1978 We have re-assembled in the shadow of the greatest natural calamity to befall this State in living memory. Honourable members will kindly remember that we decided to adjourn this House in the second week of September because we all felt the need to disperse into the countryside and participate in the work of relief and rehabilitation then going on in the wake of the floods which had affected five districts in the State since early August. Little did we then anticipate that a third spell of the floods would soon ensue, the devastation caused by which would be several times greater than what has taken place earlier. The memorandum, Floods in West Bengal: third phase, which we have submitted to the Government of India and which has been circulated among honourable Members, contains details of the havoc rendered by this phase of the floods. Even, so I am taking this opportunity to place before this House a short narration of the course of events since we adjourned—the measures we have adopted to cope with the situation and the problems which continue to confront us. With effect from the midnight of September 26–7, there was massive rainfall in the upper as well as lower catchment areas of the Mayurakshi, Ajoy, Damodar and Kangsabati rivers accompanied by a high tidal influx. In most of southern Bengal, as much as 30 inches of rain fell in
APPENDIX I
381
the course of 72 hours. This was responsible for devastating flooding in as many as nine districts of the state. The city of Calcutta too was not spared. As honourable Members will recall, during the first two phases of the floods, five districts had been affected. All told, nearly one and a half crores of people in twelve districts have thus suffered the ravages of floods and rains during the past three months. Unusually heavy discharges occurred from practically all the river basins in the southern districts during the last week of September. The maximum discharge from both the Durgapur and the Tilpara barrages approximated to 400,000 cusecs; the releases from the Kangsabati dam and the DVC system too were inordinately high. The discharge from Shilavati, Dwarakeswar, Ajoy, Siddheswari and a number of other rivers also surpassed past records; the smaller tributaries were equally affected. Numerous big and small breaches took place along river embankments, leading to the inundation of thousands of villages. The left afflux bund of the Tilpara barrage belonging to the Mayurakshi system was either washed away or heavily damaged over a considerable length; the left guide bund and the left flank wall too either totally collapsed or were severely breached at a number of places. The Hinglow dam similarly suffered heavy breaches. The Ajoy changed its course at several places and established links with the Kunur river. The protective embankment of the Bhagirathi at Kalna was badly affected. The devastation caused in the districts of Birbhum and Burdwan apart, the collapse of the Tilpara barrage system, coupled with the floods in the Banga and the Padma systems, contributed to extensive flooding in the district of Murshidabad. In the district of Midnapore, the flood water breached several river embankments including those of the Rupnarayan and the Shilavati, the embankments of all the main canals in the northern and central parts, as well as most of the protective circuit embankments. In the district of Howrah, the Rupnarayan left embankment was breached at numerous places. The Damodar right embankment was under deep water for a number of days. High tides breached the right embankment of the Hooghly; the embankments of the Dwarakeswar, Damodar and Mundeswari rivers were also breached. Heavy congestion in the Ghia, Kunti, Dankuni and Saraswati river basins resulted in extensive inundation of the industrial belt of Hooghly for a number of days. The district of 24paraganas was similarly effected by the high water levels of the Hoogly and Ichamati rivers, leading to overtopping of major embankments. In Nadia, each of the four rivers, namely, Bhagiurathi, Jalangi, Churni and Ichamati, was in spate, resulting in heavy flooding. In the district of Bankura, the Maliara drainage channel spilled over and breached the right efflux
382
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
bund of the Durgapur barrage. A cyclonic storm, ferocious in its intensity, added to the sufferings in the district. The major parts of the city of Calcutta and its suburbs were under deep water from the night of September 26–7 for a number of days. The entire metropolitan areas, including its industrial belt, was severely affected. The high tide on the Hooghly during October 4–5 further contributed to the difficulties. A large number of slum settlements in and around the city, particularly in the eastern parts, were inundated. The flooding of the Palta and the Tala pumping stations led to widespread disturbance in the supply of drinking water in the metropolitan area for one full day. Of the 17 sewage pumping stations in the city, 6 were completely submerged, resulting in serious damage to pumps and motors and consequent suspension of pumping operations for varying periods. City roads, including major arterial roads, suffered extensive damage. In the districts, close to 70 municipal areas have been affected by the floods, about half of them very severely: substantial damage has been caused to the water supply and the sewerage system as well as to roads and houses. With the abatement of the floods, the major problems that await us are those of reconstruction and rehabilitation. The overall loss to the State’s economy as a result of the floods has been colossal. According to confirmed figures, 918 lives have been lost: even now final checks are being made with regard to some persons who have been accompanied by wholesale destruction of dwelling units. On a rough reckoning, about two hundred thousand head of cattle have been lost; post flood diseases have disabled perhaps an equal number. According to preliminary estimates, close to 18 lakh huts of which at least 11 lakhs belong to the landless labourers and poorer farmers and artisans have been either destroyed or damaged. The aggregate loss of crop-field as well as orchard, over an affected area of 34 lakh acres, would exceed Rs. 200 crores, affecting the livelihood of nearly 15 lakh small and marginal farmers and 20 lakh landless labourers. Large-scale capital losses have occurred, including loss of personal capital, working equipment and implements of small artisans and cottage craftsmen. The economic infrastructure has been badly eroded, affecting particularly the irrigation and flood control works, the water supply system, roads and a wide variety of other public amenities. Thousands of tube-wells have gone out of order; many of them will need re-sinking. There has been damage to the lift irrigation and other minor irrigation systems, including to deep and shallow tube-wells. Installations belonging to the State Electricity Board have been similarly affected. Schools, colleges, hospitals and health centres have had their buildings submerged in hundreds of places and would need extensive repairs.
APPENDIX I
Breaches in Embankments: 1. 2. 3. 4.
Name of the districts Number of breaches due to flood Number of breaches repaired so far Remarks
Malda .. .. .. .. 13 – All works taken up and would be completed within a short time. Murshidabad .. .. .. 223 – Ditto. Midnapore* .. .. .. 5,535 4,788 Initial closing done. Irrigation started from Midnapore canal. Hooghly* .. .. .. 357 173 Burdwan .. .. .. 817 799 Nadia .. .. .. .. 36 – All works taken up and would be completed with in a short time. Birbhum .. .. .. .. 800 350 Howrah .. .. .. .. 1,008 640
383
384
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Bankura .. .. .. .. 303 272 Purulia .. .. .. .. 1 1 24-Parganas* .. .. .. 346 346 Calcutta* .. .. .. .. The four districts where I recorded flood narratives are marked with an*.
APPENDIX II
385
8
qQ APPENDIX II Transcription and Translation
In view of the fact that most of the stories told in English were taken from the volume A Corpus of English Conversation edited by Svartvik and Quirk, and that Svartvik and Quirk expressly state that their ‘audiotape cannot be made available’. I have adopted almost entirely their own very minute and detailed transcript notation myself, except for fall-rise patterns. Wherever I have used English data from sources other than Svartvik and Quirk’s corpus, I have acknowledged this clearly in footnotes. Below is a relevant list of the conventions used in the corpus. Speakers: A Speaker identity A,B A and b (example) VAR Various Speakers ? Speaker identity unknown a Non-surreptitious speaker (example)
386
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Transcription conventions: + yes + Simultaneous talk (laughs) Contextual comment > Incomprehensible words [?] Glottal stop TONE UNIT x End of tone unit (TU) || Onset {} Subordinate TU STRESS ‘yes Normal “yes Heavy PAUSE Yes. yes Brief pause (of one light syllable) Yes-yes Unit pause (of one stress unit of ‘foot’)
APPENDIX II
387
Simultaneous talk is indicated by pairs of asterisks or plus signs, and it occurs in various combinations: A *...* B *... A *... B *...* A...* A *... B *...* C...* A *... B *...* C...* D...*
)Everything from the first to the last )asterisk occurs simultaneously, i.e. )also C’s talk. )
A..*...*.. B *...+*....+ C +....+ ‘Contextual comment’ indicates non-linguistic activity, such as (laughs), (coughs), (enters), (telephone rings) or technical mishaps, e.g., (gap in recording), (10 seconds untranscribable). Note that ‘ . ’ and ‘-‘ here mean length of contextual comment, e.g. (.laughs), (-coughs), (--giggles), etc. The ‘tone unit’ (TU) is the basic prosodic unit in the analysis. The ‘onset’ is the first prominent syllable in a tone unit. It is possible for a speaker to complete another speaker’s TU. e.g. B ||and they ‘sort of ‘REINFORCE’ one {an||other’s [ :]. > D ∆EGOSx}x
(S.I. 12 TU 989–990)
The peak of greatest prominence in a tone unit is called ‘nucleus’. The nucleus symbol has been placed as follows. In words with a single vowel: YES, YES, YES; in digraphs: READ; in words with a mute vowel: GUESS; in words with a semivowel: BEAUTIFUL, EUROPE but QUITE, CHOIR.
388
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
A consonant can also take nucleus, e.g. OK, [m]. Throughout this book the word carrying the nuclear tone is printed in small capital letters except for ‘words’ appearing within square brackets. Bengali Transcription Although my transcriptions, with detailed phonetic notations, of the original Bengali data have not been included in Narative Gravity, owing to constraints of length and readability, these are available in my Cambridge thesis ‘The Story in Conversation: Towards an Integration of Speech Act Theory and Conversational Analysis’ (1982). For accuracy and readability on these transcriptions, I consulted Sutton–Page’s classic An Introduction to Colloquial Bengali; Dimock, Bhattacharji and Chatterjee’s ‘An Introduction to Spoken Bengali, as well as the I.P.A. guidelines. The thesis also contains details of the rise-fall patterns of speech from the Svartvik–Quirk Corpus which have not been included in the present work. Bengali Translation In translating from the Bengali, I have tried to keep as close as possible to the literal sense of speakers’ utterances without losing the colloquialness of the utterances. The English translations are numbered. Wherever Bengali speakers have used English words, for example ‘most’ and ‘make’, I originally transcribed these with pure vowels as they were actually said except when speakers emphasize the words, when they do use the diphthongs [ou] [ei]. As the I.P.A. points out ‘stress is not strong [in Bengali]’ and I have not included stress, but only marked by underlining words which are emphasized. Note that only translations and not transcriptions are included in Narrative Gravity, except in one illustrative instance to be found on pp. 264–265. List of Sources of Data in Cambridge Thesis (inclusive of the data in this book), other than my own transcriptions: Chapter I
p. 39, Example g) Svartvik and Quirk p. 84, S.1.3 p. 39, Example h) Svartvik and Quirk p. 369, S.1.14. p. 40, Example i) Svartvik and Quirk p. 639, S.2.10 p. 46, Example j) Svartvik and Quirk p. 322, S.1.12
Chapter II
p. 119, Example a)i Svartvik and Quirk p. 692, S.2.12 p. 121, Example a)ii Svartvik and Quirk p. 695, S.2.12 p. 124, Example a) iii Language Laboratory, Cambridge.
APPENDIX II
389
p. 125, Example a)iv from Sacks, in Bauman and Sherzer (eds) p. 126, Example a)v Svartvik and Quirk p. 358 S.I.14. p. 127, Example a)vi Svartvik and Quirk p. 362 S.I.14. p. 129, Example a)vii Language Laboratory, Cambridge. p. 130, Example a) viii Svartvik and Quirk p. 569. S. 2.7. p. 131, Example a) ix Svartvik and Quirk p. 223. S. 1.9 Chapter III p. 161, Example e) i Svartvik and Quirk p. 244. S. 1.9 p. 166, Example e) ii Svartvik and Quirk p. 242. S. 1.9 Chapter IV
p. 182, Example a) i Svartvik and Quirk p. 687. S. 2.12 p. 182, Example a) ii Svartvik and Quirk p. 323. S. 1.12 p. 183, Example a) iii Svartvik and Quirk p. 170. S. 1.6 p. 187, Example a) iv Language Laboratory, Cambridge. p. 197, Example e) ii Svartvik and Quirk p. 248 S.1.10 p. 203, Example e) ii Language Laboratory, Cambridge. p. 206, Example e) iv Svartvik and Quirk p. 638. S. 2.10. p. 213, Example f) i Svartvik and Quirk p. 370. S. 1.14 p. 218, Example f) iii Svartvik and Quirk p. 499. S. 2.5 p. 220, Example f) iv Svartvik and Quirk p. 647. S. 2.10 p. 235, Example g) Svartvik and Quirk p. 367. S. 1.14 p. 245, Example g) i Svartvik and Quirk p. 559. S. 2.7 p. 247, Example g) ii Svartvik and Quirk p. 569. S. 2.7. p. 256, Example h) i from Jefferson, in Schenkein (ed.)
390
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
8
qQ APPENDIX III Putative Emotive and Emotional Registers: An Evolutionary Perspective
A classic text recently republished—namely, Charles Darwin’s The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (1872)—calls attention to the way in which certain reflexes like, say, blushing—culturally categorized today as a coy reaction associated with love and modesty—reflect an interior emotional state. Darwin was convinced that at some stage in our evolutionary history, blushing functioned as a warning to other members of the community that the person who was blushing was not to be trusted; s/he lacked inner confidence and was unsure of her place within the community. In other words, Darwin surmised that blushing marks an insider/outsider, public/private social boundary. He also noted that the characteristic of blushing was apparently not found in the animal kingdom. But what has this long digression on blushing have to do with the concepts of language, emotions, lying and narativity which are the themes of this book? Well, the issue turns on the matter of trust. Liars, as we know from the spectacular Bill Clinton case amongst others, are in the popular imagination regarded at betrayers of trust, like the blushers of Darwin’s paradigm. And trust is important because it indicates bonding—in particular emotional bonding and the ability to survive and ‘hold one’s own’—within a community. Trust, in short, is an emotional barometer. How then do we read the barometer of emotions in a community? Largely, we do so linguistically and through narrative practice. In our heads, that is, we carry language-based experiential charts of, very, very roughly, the following kind.
391
APPENDIX III
TRAITS
FEELINGS
EMOTIONS
Patience Selfishness Stupidity Kindness Generosity
Love Affection Hatred Sorrow Friendship
Anger Jealousy Irritation Boredom Annoyance
MOODS
SENSATIONS
QUALIA
Depressed Energetic Worried Solemn Ecstatic
Pain Pleasure Ticklishness Warmth Thirst
Seeing red Hearing thunder Tasting sweetness Feeling water Smelling eucalyptus
INTUITIONS
IMPRESSIONS
INFERENCES
About danger About truth About grammaticality About logic About right & wrong
From art, films From music From the weather From expressions From the scenery
From linguistic usage From dress or appearence From professional conduct From gender or age From race or colour
NEEDS
DESIRES
For food For water For shelter For sleep For sex
For wealth For approval For progeny For immortality For consumer goods
INTENTIONS/ AMBITIONS To visit your aunt To be rich To be a cinema star To study management To solve an equation
Some combination of the features listed would inevitably yield what in folk-psychological terms might be called the ‘character and personality’ of an individual. Since the permutations and combinations thus engendered are endless, we can have very large or small variations of personality from individual to individual. Moreover, we can have extremely rich and teeming interior worlds or relatively limited and impoverished ones according to the specific ways in which we make inter-connections between all these cognitive parameters—moods, instincts, feelings, desires etc. in a narrative to the self and to the other. To the extent that we believe that animals do not share this—or even a similar—typology of feelings, nor that they have brains specialized for symbolic/ linguistic representations, their interior worlds must, in principle, be unimaginably different from ours. As the philosopher Ernest
392
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Nagel put it, we can never know what it is to feel like a bat, or for that matter a cheetah or a chimp. One absolutely fundamental way in which our internal representations differ from those of animals is that we constantly make connections between fictional worlds and the mental universe of the emotions. Animals do not, as far as we know, habitually lie or create fictions. And if they do not, it follows, animals do not use fictions as an important learning or cultural device, whereas humans consistently do. There is no society in the world which does not utilize the ‘literary’ format of story-telling as a basic communicative tool and no culture where children are not introduced to the world through the methodology Pablo Picasso referred to as ‘the truth of our lies’. As the ‘meme-carriers’ of culture, our ‘lying tales’ encapsulate, often in seductively emotional and exciting ways the ‘truths’ that the larger communities in which we live feel are necessary for cultural ‘survival’.Thus, unlocking the ‘black-box’ of the brain must involve at least the following four cognitive factors which make human beings unique as a species: A. Language in the left brain: Broca’s and Wernicke’s Areas. These levels of language are conventionally held to be: 1. 2. 3. 4.
Phonetics and Phonology (sound systems) Morphology (meanings of words) Syntax (sentence structures) Discourse (communicative language)
B. Complex emotions: the emotional range engendered by chemical/ electrical changes in the amygdala, cerebellum, hippocampus, limbic system and forebrain. C. The capacity to tell lies and to imagine scenarios not actually present—i.e. the ability called ‘displacement’ by linguists. D. The types of memories that we possess: these seem to enable us to store and bind together in our brains not just facts and perceptions but narrative fictions—in a way that other species do not. UNIVERSAL ELEMENTS OF ANY NARRATIVE ACCORDING TO LABOV: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6.
Abstract Orientation Complicating Action Evaluation Resolution Coda
APPENDIX III
393
UNIVERSAL GOAL OF ANY NARRATIVE ACCORDING TO ARISTOTLE: Catharsis: to arouse the emotions (pity, fear and awe are such protypical emotions) and then to purge them through the playing out of the narrative action. NAIR: THE JOURNEY FROM CATHARSIS TO CRISIS, MIMESIS TO MEMES IN NARRATIVE CULTURE Crisis: to perceive or ‘create’ a problem—and, by implication, to think of a solution. Narrative is an essentially emotive learning device in culture, contributing to the theory of mind (TOM).
394
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
8
qQ APPENDIX IV Placements
Narrative as a genre stands at the nexus of critical enquiry from several disciplines—psychology, literary studies, sociology (especially ethnomethodology), philosophy and linguistics. The following interdisciplinary typology, which can hardly help being both somewhat idiosyncratic and controversial, attempts to trace some of the main trends in narrative studies. A few of the several hundred terms which have proliferated in the field of ‘narratology’ are also listed, just in order to give a flavour of the scope of current inquiries into narrativity. Indeed, the swathes of metalanguage that narrative studies seem to generate so effortlessly adds weight to one of the main arguments of this book—that practice with the narrative genre trains the mind to be acutely self-reflexive, to drive those wedges between ‘world’ and ‘words’ which are the essence of self-consciousness. As the still nascent field of cognitive studies in narrativity develops, it will no doubt generate its own vocabulary, as well as borrow abundantly from previous theoretical endeavours. My own contribution is now added to the glimpses below of metalinguistic awareness in academia—though not without a sense of the gravest irony. Typology of Narrative Theories Narrative Syntagmatic (story-grammars)
Semiotic (semantic models)
Labov(1973)
Todorov(1966)
Speech Act (performance Aspects) Austin(1962) (contd. on next page)
395
APPENDIX IV
Rumelhart(1977) Prince(1973) Barthes(1977) Banfield(1981)
Levi Strauss(1968) Propp(1968) Greimas(1976) Fludernik (1996)
Forster(1974) Rimmon Keenan(1983) Kundera(1986)
Searle(1965) Sacks(1972) Pratt (1974) Maclean (1988)
Bakhtin(1973) Genette(1972) Toolan(1987)
Cognitive (mental representations) Dennett (1991) Ochs and Capps (1996, 2000) Nair (2002)
Terminology 1. orientation 2. setting 3. complicating action 4. resolution
genre analepsis/prolepsis closure
5. 6. 7. 8.
defamiliarization repetition/frequency implied reader super reader/ r-response focalization point of view/voice functions
degree of belief felicity conditions narrative fragility turn taking
transformations operations enchainment/ embedding deletion
side sequences membershipping ratified participants conversational floor
character
regulative conventions
reflexivity
communicative codes
evaluation coda rewrite rules nodes/nuclei
9. sets of expectations 10. temporality 11. inferences (causal, logical, etc.) 12. catalysers 13. indices 14. mimesis 15. free indirect discourse 16. speakerless narratives 17. histoire/
enigmas/lacunae/
speech act F(p) locutions implicatures/ intentions world to words fit
sequenced objects oral strategies pre-/post-sequences
396
story diegesis 18. recit/text 19. narration/ extradiegesis 20. homo/hetero/ hypodiegesis 21. narrative clauses 22. displacement sets 23. conversational historical present 24. episodic structure 25. scripts, plans, goals
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
rupture stasis
the dialogic principle textual polyphony
heterology
meta-/inter-/pre-text
linearity mediative interrogation actualization
chronotope enactment
seme agents/patient
illocutionary force perlocutionary effects
repairs
APPENDIX V
397
8
qQ APPENDIX V A Possible Course on Narrative Based on this Book
I have actually taught the course suggested below under the following rubric: HU 981N Elements of Narrative Art
IITD Pre Ph.D. Course/rbn2000
The aim of this course is to: a) familiarize ourselves with various theoretical perspectives on narrative; especially those relevant to current research in the area; b) analyse texts on the basis of such theories; c) develop an ability to intelligently critique and add to an already existing body of theory; d) have fun! 1. Introduction: The Search for Narrative Universals from Aristotle to Austin 2. Narrative Structure: Is there a basic structure common to all stories? How do we differentiate between form and function, structure and context and other binaries in analyzing stories? — — — —
Conversational Narratives (William Labov and Sociolinguistics) Mythic Narratives (Claude Levi-Strauss and Anthropological Studies) Literary Narratives (Roland Barthes and Textual Analysis) The Grammar and Semiotics of Narrative (Mandler, Johnson and Psycholinguistics/AI)
3. Narrative in Philosophical Discourse What is a speech act? Do stories qualify as speech acts? What logical differences exist between fictional and factual narratives? — Felicity Conditions on Narrative (J.L. Austin, Nair) — Logical Conditions on Fiction (John Searle)
398
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
— Implied Conditions on Narrativity (Paul Grice; D.K. Lewis, Nair) — Narrative Effects and Emotion: Aristotelian Poetics Revisited (Martha Nussbaum) 4. Narrative in Literary Theory: What is the deconstructionist position on narrative? Does the rhetoricity inherent in language pose a threat to narrativity through the processes of self-erasure? — — — —
The Purloined Letter and Literary Detection (Lacan and Derrida) The Treachery of Language and Rhetorical Aporias (Paul de Man) The Anthropomorphic Narrative of speech act theory (Jonathan Culler) The Ethics of Narrative Research and Theory (Jacques Derrida, Culler, Nair)
5. Narrative in Ethomethodological Research: What ‘glue’ binds bits of a narrative together? Why do we always need more stories? How do we systematically use the story-talk to ‘solve’ everyday problems in communication? — Narrative as Purposive Problem Solving through Turn-Taking (Harvey Sacks, Nair) — Narrative as a Telling of Jokes, Riddles and Other Genres (Gail Jefferson) — Narrative as a Solution to the Incompleteness of our Lives (Hillis Miller, Michel de Certeau) — Narrative as a Developmental Necessity in Child Language ( Michael Toolan; Alyssa McCabe) 6. Narrative in Cognitive Studies: Are we as a species defined by the compulsive need to ‘narrativize’ ourselves? — Narrative Gravity as an Anti-foundationalist Anchor of the ‘Self’ (Daniel C. Dennett, Nair) — Narrativity and Cognitive Relevance (Dan Sperber and Diedre Wilson) — Narratives as the Vehicle and Transmittor of Memes (Richard Dawkins) — Narratives as Generic, Stylistic and Biological Mechanisms (Tzevan Todorov, Paul Ricoeur, Nair) 7. Narrative within the Postcolonial Paradigm: How far is narrative a powerful instrument of exploitation and domination? Can the colonial narrative be rewritten? — — — —
Narrative and Orientalism (Edward Said) Narrative and Gender (Gayatri Spivak, Salman Rushdie, Nair) Narrative, Nation and Postmodernism (Homi Bhabha, Antony Appiah) Narrative, Postcolonial Fiction and Pre-colonial Folklore (A.K. Ramanujan, Nair)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
399
8
qQ BIBLIOGRAPHY
Abbott, H.P. (2002) The Cambridge Introduction to Narrative, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Adam, J.M. (1985) Le texte narratif, Paris: Nathan. Adams, J.K. (1985) Pragmatics and Fiction Series: Pragmatics and Beyond, Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company. Allwood, J. (1976) Linguistic Communication as Action and Co-operation: A Study in Pragmatics, Gothenburg Monographs in Linguistics, 2. Goteburg: University of Goteborg. Aristotle (1920) Poetics, trans. I. Bywater, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Arnold, M.B. (1962) Story Sequence Analysis: A New Method of Measuring Motivation and Predicting Achievement. New York and London: Columbia University Press. Arnold, D. (1988) ‘Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague. 1896– 1900’, In Selected Subaltern Studies (eds) Guha, R. and Spivak, G.C. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Atkinson, M. and Drew, P. (1979) Order in Court: The Organization of Verbal Interaction in Judicial Settings, London: Macmillan. Atkinson, M. J and Heritage, J. (1984) Structures of Social Action, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Austin, J.L. (1961) Philosophical Papers of J.L. Austin, (eds) J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (1962) How to Do Things with Words, Oxford: Oxford University Press (1969) ‘Performative Constative’, in Searle, (ed.) Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Avishur, Y. (1999) Studies in Biblical Narrative: Style, Structure, and the Ancient Near Eastern Literary Background, Tel Aviv: Archaeological Center. Bach, K. and Harnish, R.M. (1979): Linguistics, Communication and Speech Acts, New York: M.I.T. Press. Bal, M. (1985) Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, trans. C. van Boheemen, 2nd ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
400
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Bhabha, H. K. (ed.) (1990) Nation and Narration. London: Routledge. Bakhtin, M.M. (1986) Speech Genres and Other Late Essays (ed.) C. Emerson and M. Holquist, trans. V.W. McGee, Austin: Walter Benjamin University of Texas Press. Bamberg, M. (1987) Acquisition of Narratives, Berlin and New York: Mouton de Gruyter. (1997) Narrative Development. Mahwah, N.J: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. (2000)Narrative Identity. (Special Issue of Narrative Inquiry—Vol. 10, 1, 2000) Amsterdam: John, Benjamins. Banfield, Ann (1982) Unspeakable Sentences: Narration and Representation in the Language of Fiction, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. Barthes, R. (1972) Mythologies. Trans. A. Lavers, London: Jonathan Cape. (1975) S/Z Trans. Miller, R., London: Jonathan Cape. (1977) Image–Music–Text. Trans. S. Heath New York: Hill and Wang. Barwise, J. and Perry, J. (1983) Situations and Attitudes, New York: MIT Press. Bauman, R. (1986) Story, Performance and Event: Contextual Studies of Oral Narrative, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baudrillard, J. (1987) The Ecstasy of Communication. Trans. Bernard and Caroline Schutze, New York: Semiotext(e). Bauman, R. and Briggs, C.L. (1990) ‘Poetics and Performance as Critical Perspectives on Language and Social Life’, Annual Review of Anthropology. Bauman, R. and Sherzer, J. (1974) Exploration in the Ethnography of Speaking, London: Cambridge University Press. Beck, B.E.E., Claus, P.J., Goswami, P. and Handoo, P. (1989) Folktales of India, Foreword Ramanujan, A.K. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. Benjamin, W. (1968) Illuminations, New York: Harcourt, Brace and Jovanovich. Bennett, J. (1976) Linguistic Behaviour, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Berman, R.A. and Slobin D.I. (1994) Relating Events in Narrative: A Cross-linguistic Developmental Study, Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Earlbaum. Bhaya, R. (1982) ‘ The Story in Conversation: Towards an Integration of Speech Act Theory and Conversational Analysis’, Ph.D. Dissertation, Cambridge: University of Cambridge [See also Nair, Rukmini Bhaya below]. Blakemore, C. (1988) The Mind Machine, London: BBC Books. Blakemore, D. (1987) Semantic Constraints on Relevance, Oxford: Blackwell. (1992) Understanding Pragmatics: An Introduction to Pragmatics, Oxford: Blackwell. Blanchot, M. (1986) The Writing of the Disaster. Trans by Ann Smock, Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Bloomfield, L. (1933) Language, New York: Holt. [IB, UB] Blum-Kulka, S. and Snow, C. E. (1993) ‘Developing autonomy for Tellers, Tales and Telling in Family Narrative Events,’ Journal of Narrative and Life History 2. 187–217. Blum-Kulka, S. (1993) ‘You Gotta Know How to Tell a Story: Telling, Tales and Tellers in American and Israeli Narrative Events at Dinner,’ Language in Society 22. 361–402.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
401
Boden, M. (1992) The Creative Mind, London: Abacus. Bolinger, D. (1980) ‘Fire in a Wooden Stove: On Being Aware in Language’ in Michaels l. and Ricks, E. (eds) The State of the Language, Berkeley: University of California Press. (1982) Language, the Loaded Weapon: The Use and Abuse of Language Today, London: Longman. Booth, W. C. (1961/1983) The Rhetoric of Fiction, 2nd ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Boruah, B. H. (1988) Fiction and Emotion: A Study in Aesthetics and Philosophy of Mind, Delhi: Oxford University Press. Brand, G. (1979) The Central Texts of Wittgenstein, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Brooks, P. (1984) Reading for the Plot: Design and Intention in Narrative, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Brown, G. and Yule, G. (1983) Discourse Analysis, Cambridge: CUP. Brown, Penelope/Stephen C. Levinson. (1987) Politeness: Some Universals of Language Usage, Cambridge: CUP. Brown, P. and Levinson, S. (1978) Universals in Language Usage: Politeness Phenomena. Questions and Politeness, ed. E. N. Goody, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Reissued as: Politeness: Some universals in language usage, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987.] Bruner, J. (1991) ‘The Narrative Construction of Reality’, in Critical Inquiry 18. Bühler, K. (1965) Sprachtheorie, Stuttgart: Gustav Fischer Verlag. [especially §2 Das Organonmodell der Sprache, 24–33]. [UB] Butterworth, B. (1980) Language Production, Vol. I: Speech and Talk, ed., London: Academic Press. Butts, R.E. and Hintikka, J. (1977) Basic Problems in Methodology and Linguistics, Dodrecht: Reidel. Campbell, P.N. (1973) ‘A Rhetorical View of Locutionary, Illocutionary and Perlocutionary Acts’, Quarterly Journal of Speech 59, Number 3, October, 1973. Capps, L. and Ochs, E. (2001) Living Narrative: Creating Lives in Everyday Storytelling, London: Harvard University Press. Capps, Lisa and Ochs, E. (1995) Constructing Panic: The Discourse of Agoraphobia, London: Harvard University Press. Carnap, R. (1959) Introduction to Semantics, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Carr, E H. (1990) What is History?, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Chafe, W. (1977) ‘Creativity in Verbalisation’, in Discourse Production and Comprehension (ed. R. O. Freedle) Norwood, New Jersey: Ablex Publishing Corporation. (1980) The Pear Stories, ed., Norwood: Ablex. (1994) Discourse, Consciousness and Time. Chicago: Chicago University Press. (1998) ‘Things We Can Learn From Repeated Tellings of the Same Experience’, Narrative Inquiry, Vol. 8 (2). 269–85. Chambers, R. (1984) Story and Situation: Narrative Seduction and the Power
402
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
of Fiction, Theory and History of Literature Series, Vol. 12. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Chatman, S (1990) Coming to Terms: the Rhetoric of Narrative in Fiction and Film. Cornell: Cornell University Press. (1992) Reading Narrative Fiction, New York: Prentice Hall. (2000) New Perspectives on Narrative Perspective, New York: State University New York Press. Chatterjee, P. (1994) The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Post Colonial Histories, Delhi: Oxford University Press. Chomsky, N. (1959) ‘Review of Skinner (1957)’, Language 35: 26–58. (1964) ‘The Logical Basis of Linguistic Theory’, in H.G. Lunt (ed.) Proceedings of the Ninth International Congress of Linguists, Mouton, The Hague. (1983) Knowledge of Language, New York: Praeger. (2001) The Architecture of Language, eds Mukherjee, N, Patnaik, B.D. and Agnihotri, R. Delhi and New York: Oxford University Press. Cicourel, A.V. (1980) Three Models of Discourse Analysis: The Role of Social Structure, in Freedle R.O. (ed.) Discourse Processes: A Multidisciplinary Journal, Vol. 3, 1980, Cohn, D. (1978) Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for Presenting Consciousness in Fiction, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Cohen, T. (1973) ‘Illocutions and Perlocutions’, Foundations of Language, Vol. 9. Cole, P. and Morgan, J.L. (1975) Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 3, Speech Acts, New York: Academic Press. Cook, E. (1969) The Ordinary and the Fabulous, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Coulmas, F. (1986) Direct and Indirect Speech, Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. 1–45; 311–332. Coulthard, M. and Brazil, D. (1979) Exchange Structure: Discourse Analysis Monograph 5, English Language Research. Birmingham: University of Birmingham. Coulthard, M.C.H. (1977) An Introduction to Discourse Analysis, London: Longmans. Crick, F. (1994) The Astonishing Hypothesis, New York: Simon and Schuster. Crystal, D. and Derek, D. (1970) Investigating English style, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Culler, J. (1975) ‘Defining Narrative Units’, in: R. Fowler (ed.) Style and Structure in Literature, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 123–42. (1988) Framing the Sign: Criticism and its Institutions, Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd. Currie, M. (1998) Postmodern Narrative Theory, New York: St. Martin's Press. Damasio, A. R. (1994) Descartes’ Error: Emotion. Reason & the Human Brain, New York: Avon Books. (1999) The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the making of Consciousness, New York: Harcourt Brace. Das, V. ed. (1990) Mirrors of Violence: Communities, Riots and Survivors in South Asia, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
403
Davidson, D. (1984) Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford: Clarendon Press. (1980) Essays on Actions and Events, Oxford, Clarendon Press. Davies, P. (1995) About Time, London: Simon and Schuster. Davis, S. (1992) Pragmatics: A Reader, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dawkins, R. (1976) The Selfish Gene, New York: Oxford University Press. (1996) Science, Delusion and the Appetite for Wonder, BBC Richard Dimbleby Lecture. De Beaugrande, R. W. and Dressler, U. (1981) Introduction to Text Linguistics, London: Longman. de Certeau, M. (1984) The Practice of Everyday Life, trans. S. Rendall, Berkeley: University of California Press. de Man, P.(1971) Blindness and Insight: Essays in the Rhetoric of Contemporary Criticism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (1979) Allegories of Reading: Figural Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche, Rilke, and Proust, London: Yale University Press. De Sousa, R. (1979) ‘The Rationality of Emotions’, In Dialogue, Vol. XVIII. Dennett, D.C. (1987) The Intentional Stance, Cambridge, MA: MIT press. (1991) Consciousness Explained, Boston and New York: Little Brown. Dennett, D., and Kinsbourne, M. (1992) ‘Time and the Observer: The Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 183–247. Dennett, D. (1996) Kinds of Minds, New York: Basic Books. Dentith, S. (1995) Bakhtinian Thought: An Introductory Reader, London: Routledge. Derrida, J. (1986) A Derrida Reader, trans. and ed. Peggy Kamuf, New York: Alfred Knopf. Descartes, R. (1649/1984) The Passions of the Soul, in J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, D. Murdoch (eds) The Philosophical Works of Descartes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Dimock, E.C. (jr.), Bhattacharji, S. Chatterjee, S. (1964) An Introduction to Spoken Bengali, Honolulu: East West Centre Press. Drabble, M. (1977) The Ice Age, London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson. Dretske, F. (1995) Naturalizing the Mind, Cambridge: MIT Press. Drew, P. and Atkinson, M. (1979) Order in Court: The Organisation of Verbal Interaction in Judicial Settings, London: Macmillan. D’Souza, R. (1999) ‘Floods: A Symposium on Flood Control and Management’, in Seminar, Vol. 478. June 1999. Dunbar, R. (1996) Gossip, Grooming & the Evolution of Language, London: Faber. Duranti, A. (1986) The Audience as Co-author: An Introduction, Text 6, 3. 239–47. Eco, U. (1993) Six Walks in the Fictional Woods, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (1995) The Search for the Perfect Language, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. Eco, U. with Rorty, R., Culler, J. and Brooke-Rose, C. (1992) In Collini, S. (ed.) Interpretation and Overinterpretation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See also Review of this work by Nair, R.B. below].
404
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Edelman, G. (1992) Bright Air, Brilliant Fire: On the Matter of the Mind, London: Penguin Books. Elster, J. (1999) Alchemies of the Mind: Rationality and the Emotions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ekman, P. (1992) ‘Facial Expressions of Emotions: New Findings, New Questions’, Psychological Science, 3, 34–8. Ellis, Andrew W. and Beattie, G. (1986) The Psychology of Language and Communication, London: Weidenfeld. Falk, J. (1980) ‘The Conversational Duet’, in Berkeley Linguistic Society: Proceedings of the Sixth Annual Meeting, 507–14. Ferrara, K. (1992) ‘The Interactive Achievements of a Sentence: Joint Productions in Therapeutic Discourse’, Discourse Processes 15. 207–28. Firth, J.R. (1957) Papers in Linguistics: 1934–1951, London: Oxford University Press. Flagg, Fannie (1988) Fried Green Tomatoes at the Whistle-Stop Café, New York: McGraw-Hill. Fleischman, S. (1990) Tense and Narrativity: From Medieval Performance to Modern Fiction, Austin: University of Texas Press. Fludernik, M. (1993) The Fictions of Language and the Languages of Fiction: The Linguistic Representation of Speech and Consciousness, London: Routledge. (1996) Towards a ‘Natural’ Narratology, London: Routledge. Forster, E.M.(1974) Aspects of the Novel, London: The Abinger Press. Fowler, R. ed. (1975) Style and Structure in Literature, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Freedle, R.O. ed. (1980) Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol. I–XII, New Directions in Discourse Processing, Norwood, New Jersey: Ablex. Freud, S. (1960) Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious, New York: Norton. Frijda, N. (1986) The Emotions, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Furberg, M. (1971) Saying and Meaning: A Main Theme in the Philosophy of J.L. Austin, Basil Oxford: Blackwell. Gallese, V. and Goldman, A. (1998) ‘Mirror Neurons and the Stimulation Theory of Mind Reading’, in Trends in Cognitive Science, Vol. 2, 12:493–501. Garfinkel, H. (1972) ‘Remarks on Ethnomethodology’, in Gumperz, J. and Hymes, D. (eds) The Ethnography of Communication, Directions in Socio Linguistics, New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. 301–24. Garrett, J. A (1973) Classical Dictionary of India, Illustrative of the Mythology, Philosophy, Literarure, Antiquities, Arts, Manners, Customs of the Hindoos, New York: Burt Franklin. Gazzaniga, M.S. (1992) Nature’s Mind: The Biological Roots of Thinking, Emotion, Sexuality and Language, New York: HarperCollins (1997) Conversations in the Cognitive Neuro Sciences, Cambridge: MIT Press. George, A. (1989) Reflections on Chomsky, Oxford, New York: Basil Blackwell. Genette, G. (1980) Narrative Discourse, trans. Lewin, J.E., Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. (1993) Fiction and Diction, trans. Porter, K., Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
405
Gibson, A. (1996) Towards a Postmodern Theory of Narrative, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Goffman, E. (1955) On Face-work. Psychiatry 18, 3. 213–31. [Reprinted in: E. Goffmann, 1967, Interactive Ritual, Chicago: Aldine. 5–45.] (1959) The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, Garden City: Anchor Books. (1963) Stigma Englewoods, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. (1974) Frame Analysis, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Goodwin, C. (1986) ‘Audience Diversity, Participation and Interpretation,’ Text 6, 3. 283–316. Grandy, R.E. and Warner, R. eds (1986) Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends, Oxford: Clarendon press. Granta Magazine (1987) The Story Teller, ed. Buford, B., vol. 21, London: Viking Penguin. Green, G. M. (1996) Pragmatics and Natural Language Understanding, Hillsdale: Erlbaum. Greenblatt, S. (1996) Judge Starr’s Narrative, New York Review of Books. Gregory, R.L. ed. (1987) The Oxford Companion to the Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Grice, H.P. (1957) ‘Meaning’, Philosophical Review,66, number 3, July 1957. (1968) ‘Utterer’s Meaning, Sentence Meaning and Word Meaning’, Foundations of Language, 4. (1975) ‘Logic and Conversation’, in Syntax and Semantics, Vol. 3: Speech Acts, ed. Cole, P. and Morgan, J. New York: Academic. (1978) ‘Further Notes on Logic and Conversation’, in Cole, Peter (ed.), Syntax and Semantics 9: Pragmatics, New York, Academic Press. (1981) ‘Presupposition and Conversational Implicature’, in Cole, P. (ed.), Radical Pragmatics. New York, Academic Press. (1990) Studies In the Way of Words, Berkeley: University of California Press. Grimes, J. (1975) The Thread of Discourse, The Hague: Mouton. Grimshaw, A.D. (1974) ‘Data and Data Use in an Analysis of Communicative Events’, in Baumann and Sherzer (eds) Gumperz, J.J. (1971) Language in Social Groups, Stanford: Stanford University Press. (1982a) ‘ The Linguistic Bases of Communicative Competence,’ in Tannen, D. (ed.), Analyzing Discourse: Text and Talk (Georgetown University Roundtable on Languages and Linguistics 1981), Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press. 323–34. (1982b) Discourse Strategies, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Gumperz, J.J. and Hymes, D. eds (1972) Directions in Sociolinguistics: The Ethnography of Communication, New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Halliday, M.A.K. (1975) Learning How to Mean, London: Arnold. (1976) System and Function in Language, London: Oxford University Halvorsen, P. K. (1987) ‘Computer Applications of Linguistic Theory’, in F.J. Newmeyer (ed.) Linguistics: The Cambridge Survey—Vol. II, Cambridge,
406
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Cambridge University Press. Hanlfing, O. (1983) ‘Real Life Art and the Grammar of Feeling’, in Philosophy, Vol. LVIII. Haraway, D. (1989) Primate Visions, London: Routledge Harrison, G.B. (1979) An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language, London: Macmillan. Herman, D. (1997) ‘Scripts, Sequences and Stories: Elements of Postclassical Narratology’, in Publications of the Modern Languages Association (PMLA) 112. Herman, D. ed. (1999) Narratologies: New Perspectives on Narrative Analysis, Columbus: Ohio State University Press. Hoffman, M. and Murphy, P. ed. (1997) Essentials of the Theory of Fiction, Leicester: Leicester University Press, 1997. Hofstader, D. (1986) The Mind’s I, New York: Bantam Edition. Holdcroft, D. (1978) Words and Deeds: Problems in the Theory of Speech Acts, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hume, D. (1911; original 1739) A Treatise of Human Nature, Everyman’s Library Editions. Humphrey, N. (1992) A History of the Mind, New York: Chatto and Windus. Hutcheon, L. (1991) Narcissistic Narrative: The Metafictional Paradox, London: Routledge. Hymes, D. (1962) The Ethnology of Speaking: Anthropology and Human Behavior, (ed.) Thomas Gladwin and William C. Sturtevant, 13–53, Washington, D.C.: Anthropological Society of Washington. (1972) ‘Models of the Interaction of Language and Social Life’, in: J.J Gumperz and D. Hymes (eds) Directions in Sociolinguistics, New York: Holt. 35–71. Hymes, D. and Gumperz, J. J. eds (1972) Directions in Sociolinguistics, New York: Holt. Jackendoff, R. (1994) Patterns in the Mind: Language & Human Nature, New York: Harper Collins. Jackson, F. (1982) ‘Epiphenomenal Qualia,’ Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136. Jain, J. (1981) Prakrit Narrative Literature: Origin and Growth, Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers. Jakobson, R. (1960) Closing statement: Linguistics and Poetics, in T. Sebeok (ed.) Style in Language, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. James, W. (1884) ‘What is an emotion?’ Mind, 9, 188–205. Jefferson, G. (1972) ‘Side Sequences’, in Sudnow, D. (ed.) Studies in Social Interaction, New York: Free Press. (1978) Sequential Aspects of Storytelling in Conversation,’ in: J. Schenkein (ed.). Studies in the Organization of Conversational Interaction, New York: Academic Press. 219–48. Johnson-Laird, P.N. and Wason, P.C. ed. (1977) Thinking: Readings in the Cognitive Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Johnstone, B. (1993) ‘Community and Contest: Midwestern Men and Women Creating their Worlds in Conversational Storytelling’, in D. Tannen (ed.)
BIBLIOGRAPHY
407
Gender and Conversational Interaction, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Joos, M. (1961) The Five Clocks, New York: Harcourt, Brace and Jovanovich. Journal of Narrative and Life History 7. (1997) ‘Special issue: ‘Oral Versions of Personal Experience: Three decades of Narrative Analysis.’ Journal of Pragmatics 24. (1995) Special issue: ‘Literary Pragmatics’. Morny, J. ed. (1997) Paul Ricoeur and Narrative, Calgary: University of Calgary Press. Kasher, A. ed. (1976) Language in Focus: Foundation, Methods, and System, Dordrecht: Reidel. (1977) ‘Foundations of Philosophical Pragmatics’, in Butts and Hintikka (eds). Katz, J.J and Lagendoen, D.T. (1976) ‘Pragmatics and Presupposition’, Language 52, Number I, 1976. Katz, J.J. (1979) ‘What is a Theory of Use?’ in Margalit, A. (ed.) Meaning and Use, Dodrecht: Reidel. Katz, J.J.and Postal, R. (1964) An Integrated Theory of Linguistic Descriptions, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press. Kermode, F. (1967) The Sense of an Ending: Studies in the Theory of Fiction, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kirschenblatt–Gimblett, B. (1974) ‘The Concept and Varieties of Narrative Performance in East European Jewish Culture’, in Bauman, R. and Sherzer, J. (eds). Klammer, T. P. (1973) Foundation for a Theory of Dialogue Structure, Poetics, 27–64. Kripke, S, A. (1972) Naming and Necessity, in Davidson, D. and Harman, G. (ed.) Semantics of Natural Language, Dordrecht: Reidel. Kundera, M. (1984) The Unbearable Lightness of Being trans. Heim, M.H, New York: Harper & Row. [see also Review by R.B. Nair, below]. (1988) The Art of the Novel, trans. Ashev, L. Grove Press Inc. Labov, W. and Waletzky, J. (1966) ‘Narrative Analysis: Oral Versions of Personal Experience’, in J. Helm (ed.) Essays on the Verbal and Visual Arts, in Seattle: University of Washington Press. 12–24. Labov, W. (1972a) ‘The Transformation of Experience in Narrative Syntax’, in Language in the Inner City: Studies in the Black English Vernacular, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. (1972b) Language in the Inner City, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. (1972c) Sociolinguistic Patterns, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Labov, W. and Fanshel, D. (1977) Therapeutic Discourse, New York: Academic Press. Lakoff, G. (1987) Women, Fire and Dangerous Things, Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. [UB]. Lakoff, G. and Johnson, M. (1980) Metaphors We Live By, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
408
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Lakoff, R. (1973) ‘Language and Women’s Place’, Language in Society 2. 45–80. Lamarque, P. (1996) Fictional Points of View, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Lanigan, R.L. (1977) Speech Act Phenomenology, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Lazarus, R. (1991) Emotion and Adaptation, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Le Doux, J. (1996) The Emotional Brain, New York: Simon and Schuster. Leech, E. (1974) Mythology, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Leech, G. (1983) Principles of Pragmatics, London: Longman Linguistic Library No. 30. Levelt, W.J.M. (1981) ‘The Speaker’s Linerization Problem’, in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London Vol. 295, Number 1077, October. Levinson, S.C. (1979) ‘Activity Types and Language’, Linguistics 17. (1980) ‘Speech Act Theory: The State of the Art’, Survey Article, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. (1983) Pragmatics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Levinson, Stephen C. (1987) ‘Minimization and Conversational Inference’, in Verschueren, J. and Bertucelli-Papi, M. (eds), The Pragmatic Perspective, Amsterdam, John Benjamins, 61–129. Lewis, D.K. (1969) Convention: A Philosophical Study, Harvard: Harvard University Press. Linde, C. (1993) Life Stories, New York: Oxford University Press. Lodge, D. (1990) After Bakhtin: Essays in Fiction and Criticism, London: Routledge. (1992) The Art of Fiction, London: Penguin. Lycan, W.G. ed. (1991:) Mind and Cognition: A Reader, Oxford: Blackwell Lyotard, J. F. (1984) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, Trans. Bennington, G. and Massumi, B., Manchester: Manchester University Press. (1991) The Inhuman, New York: Polity Press. Maclean, M. (1988) Narrative as Performance: the Baudelairean Experiment, London: Routledge. Majumdar, B. (1991) A Sociological Study of Toto Folk-tales, Calcutta: The Asiatic Society Monograph Series No. 29. Malinowski, B. (1923) The Problem of Meaning in Primitive Languages, London: Routledge. [Supplement I to C.K.Ogden and I.A. Richards, The Meaning of Meaning.] Mandler, J.M. and Johnson, N.S (1977) ‘Remembrance of Things Parsed: Story Structure and Recall,’ Cognitive Psychology. 9. 111–151. Mandler, J.M. (1978) ‘A Code in the Node: The Use of a Strong Schema in Retrieval’, in Freedle, R.O. (ed.) Discourse Processes a Multidisciplinary Journal, Vol. 3. (1984) Stories, Scripts and Scenes: Aspects of Schema Theory, London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Martin, W. (1986) Recent Theories of Narrative, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. McCabe, A. and Peterson, C. (1984) ‘What Makes A Good Story?’ Journal of Psycholinguistic Research Vol. 13, Number 6. McDonald, J. (1950) Strategy in Poker, Business and War, New York: The Norton Library.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
409
McGuinness, B. ed. (1979) Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations recorded by Friedrich Waismann, translated by J. Schutte and B. McGuinness, London: Basil Blackwell. Mey, J.L. and Talbot, M. (1988) ‘Computation and the Soul’, in Journal of Pragmatics 12. Mey, J. L. (1993) Pragmatics: An Introduction, Oxford: Blackwell. Michaels, S. and Cook-Gumperz, J. (1979) ‘A Study of Sharing Time with First Grade Students: Discourse Narratives in the Classroom,’ Berkeley Linguistics Society: Proceedings of the 5th annual meeting. 647–60. Miller, H. (1990) ‘Narrative, in Lentricchia and McLaughlin’, in Critical Terms For Literary Study, Duke: Duke University Press. Millikan, R. (1984) Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, Cambridge: MIT Press. Minsky, M. (1977) ‘Frame System Theory’, in Johnson-Laird and Wason (eds) Thinking: Readings in Cognitive Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 355–76. Mitchell, W.J.T. ed. (1981) On Narrative, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Nandy, A. ed. (1988) Science, Hegemony, and Violence: A Requiem for Modernity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nair, R.B. (1984) ‘Fictional Selves, Empire’s Fictions: The Poets of John Company’, in C.E. Nicholson and R. Chatterjee Tropic Crucible: Self and Theory in Language and Literature, Singapore: Singapore University Press. (1986) ‘ Telling Lies: Some Literary and Other Violations of Grice’s Maxim of Quality’, Nottingham Linguistic Circular 14, Special Issue on Pragmatics. (1989) ‘ Text and Pre-text: History as Gossip in Rushdie’s Novels’, Economic and Political Weekly, May. (1990) ‘Pre-linguistic Similarity and Post-linguistic Difference: Some Observations on Children’s Conceptualization in a Cross-cultural Context,’ in A. Kwan-Terry (ed.), Child Language Development in Singapore and Malaysia, Singapore: Singapore University Press. Nair, R. B. with Ron Carter and Michael J. Toolan (1988) ‘Rewarding Risks: Clines of Metaphoricity’, Journal of Literary Semantics, April. Nair, R. B. with Rimli Bhattacharya (1990) ‘Salman Rushdie: The Migrant in the Metropolis’, in The Third Text—Special Issue on the Rushdie Affair, Summer. (1991a) ‘Dissimilar Twins: Language and Literature’, in R. Sundar Rajan (ed.) The Lie of the Land: English Literary Studies in India, Delhi: Oxford University Press. (1991b) ‘Expressing Doubt and Certainty: The Tag Question and the ‘to’ Particle in Indian Languages’, in Studies in the Language Sciences, Oxford: Oxford University Press. (1991c) ‘From Freud to Rushdie: Notes on the Interpretation of Dreams’, in Seminar, July. (1992a) Gender, Genre and Generative Grammar: Deconstructing the Matrimonial Column, in M. Toolan (ed.) Text and Context: Essays in Stylistics, London: Routledge.
410
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
(1992b: guest-edited, with an introductory essay) ‘The Linguistic Landscape in India’, Seminar, March. (1992c) ‘All About Searches: Review Article on Theatre and the World: Essays on Performance and the Politics of Culture by Rustom Bharucha and Contingency Irony and Solidarity by Richard Rorty’, in the Book Review, May-June. Nair, R.B. ‘Smoke Signals: Review of Interpretation and Overinterpretation by Umberto Eco et al.’, in The Times of India, August. (1992d) ‘Monosyllabic English or Disyllabic Hindi: Language Acquisition in a Bilingual Child’, in The Indian Journal of Linguistics. (1992e) The Hyoid Bone: Poems, India: Viking Penguin. (1993a) ‘The Very Short Story and the Very Tall Tale: Towards an Inferential Model of Narrative Structure’, in Critical Spectrum: Responses to Contemporary Literary Theories, B. Chandrika (ed.), Calcutta: Papyrus Press. (1993b) ‘Unlike the Cat i’ the Adage’, Article on the Horror Story in Special Issue of Mysticism and the Occult. Hindu Literary Supplement, April. (1993c) ‘Double Talk: Reduplication: An Areal, Semantic, Typological and Historical Study by Anvita Abbi, Special Article on Linguistics’, in The Book Review, September. (1994) ‘Out of Practice: Review Article of In Theory by Aijaz Ahmad and Indian Responses to Theory, Bhalla, A. and Chandra. S. (ed.)’, in The Book Review, February-March. (1995a) ‘ The Sacred Thread of Theory: Review Article on Outside in the Teaching Machine by Gayatri Chakraborty Spivak and The Location of Culture by Homi K. Bhabha’, in The Book Review, December. (1995b) ‘The Pedigree of the White Stallion: Postcoloniality and Literary History’, in The Uses of Literary History Marshall Brown (ed.), Duke: Duke University Press. (1995c) ‘The Book of Cries and Reminders: Review of Testaments Betrayed by Milan Kundera’, in The Times of India Sunday Review, December. (1995d) ‘Why Does Rushdie Offend?’, in Seminar, Annual Issue, December. (1996) ‘Heaney’s Sense of History at Work and History’s Sense of Heaney at Work’, in Literature Alive Vol. 2. June. (1997a) ‘Acts of Agency and Acts of God: The Discourse of Disaster’, Economic and Political Weekly, March. (1997b) ‘Twins and Lovers: Review Essay on The God of Small Things by Arundhati Roy’, Biblio, May. (1997c) ‘Postcoloniality: The Literature of the Trace: Review Article based on Contemporary Postcolonial Theory: A Reader, Padmini Mongia (ed.)’, in The Book Review, September. (1998a) ‘What is it like to be a Bot? Review Essay on Language Behaviour and Evolutionary Biology by R. Narasimhan’, The Hindu, October, 1998. (1998b) ‘The Life and Death of Salman Rushdie’, American Review of Books, July-August. (1999a) ‘Postcoloniality and the Matrix of Indifference’—Lead Paper in the India International Centre Quarterly, May-June.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
411
(1999b) The Ayodhya Cantos: Poems, India: Viking Penguin. (1999c) ‘Sense and Insensibility: Review Essay on The Fate of Culture by Geoffrey Hartman’, in The Book Review, October. (2000a) ‘High Noon for Midnight’s Children and Pottermania’, The Times of India, April and June. (2000b) ‘Poetry in a Civil Society’, in The Hindu Literary Supplement, August. (2000c) ‘A Question of Answers’, in The Express Magazine, Gallery 5, September. (2000d) ‘Brainchildren: Review Article on Advances in Human Cognition’, Biblio, Vol. V Nos. 11–12, November-December. (2001a) ‘Surrogate Tongues: The Magical E-Scripts of Tomorrow’, Twentyone Ideas for the Twenty-First Century: Millennium Issue, Telegraph, January, 2000. (2001b) ‘ The e-Writing on the Wall’, Angle, Inaugural Issue, Spring. (2001c) ‘Singing a Nation into Being’, in Seminar, Annual Issue Vol. 497, January. (2001d) ‘The Testament of the Tenth Muse: A Perspective on Feminine Sensibility and Sexuality among Indian Women Poets in English’, in Satchidanandan, K. (ed.) Indian Poetry: Modernism and After, Delhi: Sahitya Akademi Publications. (2002: ed.) Translation, Text and Theory: the Paradigm of India, New Delhi; Thousand Oaks; London. Sage Publications. (2002: forthcoming Spring) Lying on the Post colonial Couch: the Idea of Indifference, Minnesota: Minnesota University Press. Nair, R. B., Bajaj, R. and Meattle, A. (1997) Technobrat: Culture in a Cybernetic Classroom, Delhi: Harper Collins. Narasimhan, R.(1998) Language Behaviour, India: Sage Publications. [See also R.B. Nair, Review above] Norrick, N. R. (1997) ‘ Twice-told tales: Collaborative Narration of Familiar Stories’, Language and Society 26. 199–220. (1998) ‘Retelling Stories in Spontaneous Conversations’, Discourse Processes 25, Vol. 1. 75–97. O’Flaherty, W.D. (1981) The Rig Veda, Penguin Classics, London: Penguin. Ochs, E. (1973) ‘A Sliding Sense of Obligatoriness: the Polystructure of Malagasy Oratory’, Language in Society 2. (1976) ‘On the Universality of Conversational Implicature’, Language in Society 5. Ochs, E. (2001) Living Narrative, Harvard: Harvard University Press. Ochs, Elinor; Smith R. and Taylor, C. (1989) ‘Detective Stories at Dinner-time: Problem Solving through Co-narration’, Cultural Dynamics 2. 238–56. Ochs, E. and Taylor, C. (1992) ‘Family Narrative as Political Activity’, Discourse and Society (3). 301–40. Ochs, E., Smith R., Rudolph, D. and Taylor, C. (1992) ‘Storytelling as a Theorybuilding Activity’, Discourse Processes 15. 37–72. Odlin, T. (1989) Language Transfer: Cross Linguistic Influence In Language Learning, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
412
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Ogden, C.K. and I.A. Richards. (1969) The Meaning of Meaning, London: Routledge. Olson, David. R and Nancy Torrance, eds (1996) Modes of Thought: Explorations in Culture and Cognition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. O’Neill, P. (1994) Fictions of Discourse: Reading Narrative Theory, Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Owen M.L (1979) ‘Remedial Interchanges; A Study of Language Use in Social Interaction’ Ph.D. Dissertation, Cambridge: University of Cambridge. Oxford English Dictionary (1970): Vol. VII, Oxford: The Clarendon Press. Palmer, G. (1996) Towards a Theory of Cultural Linguistics, Texas: University of Texas Press. Palmer, P. (1989)Contemporary Women’s Fiction: Narrative Practice and Feminist Theory, New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Pandey, Gyan. (1991) ‘In Defense of the Fragment’, Economic and Political Weekly, 1991. Papez, J.W. (1937) ‘A Proposed Mechanism of Emotion’, Archives of Neurology and Psychiatry, 79, 217–24. Pateman, T. (1987) Language in Mind and Language in Society: Studies in Linguistic Reproduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Penrose, R. (1994) Shadows of the Mind, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pinker, S. (1994) The Language Instinct, New York: Morrow. (1997) How the Mind Works, New York: Penguin. Pitcher, E. G. and Prelinger E. (1969) Children Tell Stories: An Analysis of Fantasy, New York: International University Press, Inc. Plato (1898) Dialogues of Plato, trans. B. Jowett, New York: D Appleton and Company. Polanyi, L. (1979) ‘So what’s the point?’, Semiotica 25. 207–41. (1981) ‘Telling the Same Story Twice’, Text 1: 315–36. (1985) Telling the American Story: From the Structure of Linguistic Texts to the Grammar of a Culture, Norwood, New Jersey: Ablex Publishing. Polkinghorne, D. E. (1988) Narrative Knowing and the Human Sciences, New York: State University of New York Press. Pollock, J. (1989) How to Build a Person, Massachussetts: MIT Press. Pratt, M. L. (1977) Toward a Speech Act Theory of Literary Discourse, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Prince, G. (1973) A Grammar of Stories, The Hague: Mouton. (1982) Narratology. The Form and Functioning of Narrative, The Hague: Mouton. Propp, V. (1977) Morphology of the Folktale, Austin: University of Texas Press. Psathas, G. ed. (1971) Everyday Language: Studies in Ethnomethodology, New York: Irvington Publishers. Ramachandran, V.S. (1998) Phantoms in the Brain, New York: William Morrow and Company. Recanati, F. (2000) Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta,Massachusetts: MIT Press. Reinhart, T. (1986) ‘Principes de perception des formes et organisation temporelle des textes narratifs’, Recherches Linguistiques 14/15, 45–92.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
413
Ricoeur, Paul (1984–8) Time and Narrative, trans. McLauglin, K. and Pellauer, D., 3 Volumes, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (1989) The Narrative Path: the Later Works of Paul Ricoeur, ed. Kemp, T.P. and Rasmussen, D., Cambridge, Massachusetts: M.I.T. Press Riessman, C. K. (1993) Narrative Analysis, Boston: Sage Publications. Rimmon-Kenan, S.(1983) Narrative Fiction: Contemporary Poetics, London: Methuen. Ritvo, H. (1990) The English and the Other Creatures in the Victorian Age, London: Penguin Books. Rizzolatti, G. and Arbib, M. (1998) Language Within Our Grasp, in Trends in Neurosciences Vol. 21. Rorty, A. ed. (1980) Explaining Emotions, Berkeley, Los Angeles and London: University of California Press. Rorty, R. (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See also Review Article by R.B. Nair above] Rosenberg, D. (1994) World Mythology, 2nd ed., Lincolnwood, Chicago: NTC Publishing Group. Rumelhart, D. E. (1975) ‘Notes on a Schema for Stories’, in: Bobrow, D. B. and Collins A. (eds), Representation and Understanding, New York: Academic Press. 211–36. Rushdie, S. (1992) Imaginary Homelands: Essays and Criticism 1981–1991, London and New York: Penguin. (1989) The Satanic Verses, New York: Penguin. Ryave, A. L. (1978) ‘On the Achievement of a Series of Stories’, in: J. Schenkein (ed.). Studies in the Organization of Conversational Interaction, New York: Academic Press. 113–32. Sacks, H. (1972) ‘On the Analyzability of Stories by Children’, in Gumperz, J.J. and Hymes, D. (eds). (1972) ‘Notes on police assessment of moral character’, in Sudnow, D. (ed.) Studies in Social Interaction, New York: The Free Press. (1972) ‘An Initial Investigation of the Usability of Conversational Data for Doing Sociology’, in Sudnow, D. (ed.) 31–74. Sacks, H. Schegloff, E. and Jefferson, G. (1974) ‘A Simplest Systematic for the Organization of Turn-taking in Conversation’, Language, 50, Number 4, 1974. Sacks, H. (1975) ‘Everyone has to Lie’, in Sanches, M. and Blount, B., Sociocultural Dimensions of Language Use 57–79, New York: Academic Press. (1979) ‘Hotrodder: A revolutionary category’, in Psathas, G. (ed.) Everyday Language: Studies in Ethnomethodology 7–14, New York: Irvington Publishers. (1984) ‘Notes on Methodology’, in Atkinson, J.M. and Heritage, J. (eds) 21–7. (1984) ‘On doing “being ordinary” ’, in Atkinson, J.M. and Heritage, J. (eds) 413–29. (n.d.) Aspects of the Sequential Organization of Conversation, Unpublished MS. (1967–72): Lecture Notes, Transcripts of Unpublished Lectures, School of Social Sciences, University of California at Irvine.
414
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
(1974) ‘An Analysis of the Course of a Joke’s Telling,’ in: Bauman, R. and J. Sherzer, J. (ed.) 337–53. (1992) ed. Jefferson, G. Lectures on Conversation I and II, Oxford: Blackwell. Sacks, O. (1987) The Man who Mistook his Wife for a Hat and Other Stories, New York: Harper and Row. (1995) An Anthropologist on Mars, London: Picador. Sahitya Akademi (1957/1981) Contemporary Indian Literature: A Symposium, Fourth ed., Delhi: Sahitya Akademi Publications. Said, E. (1993) Culture and Imperialism, London: Chatto and Windus. Sapir, Edward. (1949) Selected Writings of Edward Sapir in Language Culture and Personality, Berkley, Los Angeles: University of California Press. Sartre, J. P. (1962) Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions, trans. P. Mariot, London: Methuen. Scarry, E. (1999) Dreaming By the Book, New York: Strauss and Giroux. Schank, R.C. (1975) ‘The Structure of Episodes in Memory’, in Bobrow D.G. and Collins, A. Representation and Understanding: Studies in the Cognitive Sciences, New York: Academic Press. Schank, R. C. and Abelson, R. P. (1977) Scripts, Plans, Goals, and Understanding, Hillsdale: Erlbaum. Schegloff, E. A. (1972) ‘Sequencing in Conversational Openings’, in Gumperz, J.J. and Hymes, D. (eds). (1976) ‘On Some Questions and Ambiguities in Conversation’, Pragmatics Microfiche 2:2. Department of Linguistics, Cambridge: University of Cambridge. Schegloff, E.A. (1987) ‘Between Micro and Macro: Contexts and Other Connections’, in: Alexander, J.C. et al. (ed.) The Micro-Macro Link, Berkeley: University of California Press. 207–34. Schegloff, E. (1992) in another context In Duranti, A. & Goodwin. C (ed.) Rethinking Context, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 191–227. Schegloff, E. A. and Sacks, H. (1973) ‘Opening up Closings’, Semiotica, VIII, 4, pg. 290. Schegloff, E.A., Jefferson, G. and Sacks, H. (1977) ‘ The Preference for Self-correction in the Organization of Repair in Conversation’, Language 53. 361–82. Schenkein, J. ed. (1978) Studies in the Organization of Conversational Interaction, New York: Academic Press. Schiefflin B.B. and Ochs, E. ed. (1986) Language Socialisation Across Cultures, Cambridge Cambridge University Press. Schiffer, S.R. (1972) Meaning, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schiffrin, D. (1981) ‘Tense Variation in Narrative’, Language 57. 45–62. (1984) ‘How a Story Says What it Means and Does’, Text 4. 313–46. (1987) Discourse Markers: Semantic Resourse for the Construction of Conversation, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1994) Approaches to Discourse, Oxford: Blackwell. Scholes, R. (1974) Structuralism in Literature, New Haven: Yale University Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
415
Scholes, R. E. (1979) Fabulation and Metafiction, Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Scollon, R. and Scollon S. B. K. (1984) ‘Cooking it up and Boiling it Down: Abstracts in Athabaskan Children’s Story Retellings, in: Tannen, D. (ed.). Coherence in Spoken and Written Discourse, Norwood: Ablex. 173–97. Searle, J.R. (1969) Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1975) ‘The Logical Basis of Fictional Discourse’, New Literary History, Vol. 6. (1976) ‘A Classification of Illocutionary Acts’, in Hymes, D. (ed.) Language in Society, 1976. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1979) Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1983) Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (1992) The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge: MIT Press. (1998) Mind, Language, and Society, New York: Basic Books. (1984) Minds, Brains and Science, Harvard: Harvard University Press. Searle, J.R., Kiefer, F. and Bierwisch, M. (eds) (1980) Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics, Dodrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company. Sebeok, T. ed. (1960) Style in Language, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Sell, R. D. ed. (1991) Literary Pragmatics, London: Routledge. Shaffer, J. (1983) ‘An Assessment of Emotions’, in American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. XX. Shuman, A. (1986) Storytelling Rights, New York: Cambridge University Press. Siegel, L. (1991) Net of Magic: Wonders and Deceptions in India, Berkeley and Los Angeles (University of California Press). Sinclair, J.M. and Coulthard, M. (1975) Towards an Analysis of Discourse, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sinha, Chris (1988) Language and Representation: A Socio-naturalistic Approach to Human Development, Hampstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf Press. Smyth, E. J. ed. (1991) Postmodernism and Contemporary Fiction, London: Batsford. Sperber, D. and Wilson D.(1986) Relevance: Communication and Cognition, Harvard: Harvard University Press. Spielman, Roger W. (1987) ‘Collateral Information in Narrative Discourse’, Journal of Literary Semantics 16, 3. 200–26. Spivak, G.C. (1988) ‘Can the Subaltern Speak’, in Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture (ed.) by Nelson, Cary and Larry Grossberg, Urbana: University of Illinois Press. (1993) Outside in the Teaching Machine, London: Routledge. [See also review article by Nair, R.B. above] Stanzel, Franz K. (1984) A Theory of Narrative, trans. Goedscho, C., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stein, N.L. and Glenn, C.G. (1978) ‘An Analysis of Story Comprehension in Elementary School Children’, in Freedle, R.O. (ed.) Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol. II, New Directions in Discourse Processing.
416
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Stich, S.P. ed. (1975) Innate Ideas, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Strawson P.F. (1964) ‘Intention and Convention in Speech Acts’, Philosophical Review, 73, Number 4, October. (1974) ‘Imagination and Perception’, in Strawson Freedom and Resentment and Other Essays, London: Methuen. Streeck, J. (1980) ‘Speech Acts in Interaction: A Critique of Searle’, in Freedle, R.O. (ed.) Discourse Processes: A Multidisciplinary Journal, Vol. III, 1980. Street, B.V. (1984) Literacy in Theory and Practice, Cambridge Studies in Oral and Literate Culture, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Stubbs, M. (1983) Discourse Analysis: The Sociolinguistic Analysis of Natural Language, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sudnow, D. ed. (1972): Studies in Social Interaction, New York: The Free Press. Sutton-Page, W. (1934): An Introduction to Colloquial Bengali, Cambridge: W. Heffer and Sons. Sturgess, P. J. M. (1992) Narrativity: Theory and Practice, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Svartvik, J. and Quirk, R. ed. (1980) A Corpus of English Conversational Interaction, London-Lund: Liber Laromedel. Tannen, D. ed. (1984) Coherence in Spoken and Written Discourse: Advances in Discourse Processes (R.O. Freedle, series ed.) (1978) ‘What’s in a Frame ? Surface Evidence for Underlying Expectations’, in Advances in Discourse Processes Vol. II. (R.O. Freedle, series ed.) (1978) ‘The Effect of Expectations on Conversation’, Discourse Processes 1: 203–9, Norwood: Ablex. (1980) ‘A Comparative Analysis of Oral Narrative Strategies: Athenian Greek and American English’, in: W. Chafe (ed.), The Pear Stories, Norwood: Ablex. 51–87. (1984) Conversational Style, Norwood: Ablex. (1989) Talking Voices: Repetition, Dialogue, and Imagery in Conversational Discourse, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Taylor, J.R. (1989) Linguistic Categorization, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Taylor, C. (1991)The Sources of the Self, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Thorndyke, P.W. (1977) ‘Cognitive Structure in Comprehension and Memory of Narrative Discourse’, Cognitive Psychology, 9, 1977. Todorov, T. (1984) Mikhail Bakhtin: The Dialogic Principle, trans. Godzich W., Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press (1974) The Poetics of Prose, Ithaca: Cornell University. (1981) Introduction to Poetics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota. Toolan, M (1988) Narrative: A Critical Linguistic Introduction, London: Routledge. (ed.). (1993) Language, Text and Context, London: Routledge. (1990) The Stylistics of Fiction: A Literary-Lingusitic Approach, London: Routledge. Traugott, E.C. and M.L. Pratt. (1980) Linguistics for Students of Literature, New York: Harcourt. Turner, R. (1975) ‘Speech Act Theory and Natural Language Use’, Pragmatics
BIBLIOGRAPHY
417
Microfiche 1.1. Department of Linguistics, Cambridge: Cambridge University. Urmson, J.O. (1976) ‘Fiction’, in American Philosophical Quarterly Vol. XIII. Van Dijk, T. A. (1977) Text and Context. Explorations in the Semantics and Pragmatics of Discourse, London: Longman. Vasu, S.C. ed. (1962) Pannini Ashtadhyai, Delhi: Motilal Banarasidas. Vendler, Z. (1967) Linguistics in Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. von Neuman, J. and Morgenstern, O. (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Waismann, F. (1967) Wittgenstein under wiener Kreis, London: Basil Blackwell. Warren, W.H., Nicholas, D.W. and Trabasso, T. (1978) ‘Event Chains and Inferences in Understanding Narratives’, in Freedle, R.O. (ed.), Advances in Discourse Processes, Vol. 2, New Directions in Discourse Processing. Watson, P. (1981) ‘The Times Diary’, The Times, London. Waugh, P. (1984) Metafiction: The Theory and Practice of Self-Conscious Fiction, London: Methuen. Weitzman, S. (1997) Song and Story in Biblical Narrative: The History of a Literary Convention in Ancient Israel, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Wertsch, J.V. (1985) Culture, Communication and Cognition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Winograd, T. and Flores, F. (1986) Understanding Computers and Communication, Norwood, New Jersey.: Ablex Books. Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical Investigations, New York: Macmillan. (1958) The Blue and the Brown Books, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (1961) Notebooks 1914–16, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (1961) Tractates Logicus Philosophicus, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (1974) Philosophical Grammar, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (1975) Philosophical Remarks, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. White, H. (1987) The Content of the Form: Narrative Discourse and Historical Representation, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Wolfson, N. (1982) The Conversational Historical Present in American English Narrative, Mouton de Gruyter: Foris. Wollheim, R. (1973) On Art and the Mind, London: Allen Lane. Young, K.G. (1987) Taleworlds and Storyrealms: The Phenomenology of Narrative, Martinus Nijhoff, Dodrecht. Zurbuchen, M. S. (1987) The Language of Balinese Shadow Theatre, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
418
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
8
qQ INDEX
Abbott, H.P. 25 Abstract, function of 42–7, 51, 53–4, 367 Adams, Jean-Michel 246 Althusser 293, 305, 374 Appiah, Antony 398 Arendt, H. 288, 290 Aristotle 147, 217, 231, 246, 393 Arnold, David, 296–7 Arnold, M.B. 63–6 Aspects of the Novel 246 Assessments 48 Augustine, Saint 16 Austin, J.L. 4, 9, 69–70, 72, 75–6, 82, 84, 87, 112–15, 122, 126–7, 130–41, 145, 148, 152–4, 157, 161, 165, 179, 231, 350, 352–3, 394, 397 Authorless narrative 6, 179 Authorless narrator of Dennett 20–1 Avnet, John 236 Bach, K. 70–2, 186 Baker 168 Bakhtin, M. 6, 22, 26, 217, 231, 345, 347, 395 Banfield, Ann 395 Barthes, Roland 3, 31, 163, 227, 231, 345, 347, 356–7, 395, 397
Bauman, R. 207, 234–5, 238, 240, 246, 248 Bengali transcription and translation 388–9 Bennett, Jonathan 113 Berger, John 13–14 Bernard 275 Bhabha, Homi 398 Bhattacharji, S. 388 Blackemore, D. 207 Blanchot, Maurice 304–7, 374 Bolinger, Dwight 129 Boredom, narrative fragility and 275– 81, 369 Bosanquet 167 Briggs, C.L. 207 Broca 392 Brown 349 Brown Book 172 Burge, Tyler 169–70, 294, 356 Butalia, Urvashi 298 Calamity narrative, see, Disaster narrative Calvino, Italo 8 Campbell, P.N. 152 Capps, L. 395 Carnap, Rudolf 70, 130, 132, 136–7
INDEX
Carr, E.H. 308 Carroll, Lewis 122, 249, 287 Chafe, W. 207 Chatterjee, Partha 300 Chatterjee, S. 388 Chatwin, Bruce 13 Chinese Room argument 356 Chomsky, Noam 1, 110, 130, 205, 360 Classical Dictionary of India 341 Classical speech act theory 73, 87, 349 Clauses, sequence of and narrative 34– 6, 39, 89, 91 Clinton, Bill 390 Co-authored stories 32 Coda, concept of 40–2, 47, 51–4, 59 Labov on 51–4 Colby, Rumelhart 55 Coleridge 11, 108, 151, 278 Communicating cogs 21, 65 Communication, concept and theory 3–5 Conrad 245 Contemporary political stances, towards disaster 291–2 Contrast narrative 5 Conventions 175–9, 193–4, 255, 281–7, 366 Conversation, concept and theory 3–6 Conversational analysis (CA) 365–6 Conversational generalization 254–63 Conversational implicature, theory of 209, 229 Conversational impliculture, theory of 182–3, 187–8 Conversational narrative 36–9 Cooperative principle 116–28, 175–9, 189–90, 229, 337, 363 Coulthard, M. 190 Culler, Jonathan 12, 155–62, 398 Cultural repertoires 297–303 Danger-of-death narratives 42, 312, 329, 333, 362, 378 Danger-of-death stories 97–9, 116, 142, 151, 274
419
Darwin, Charles 390 Davidson, Donald 79–81, 125, 138, 149–50, 294, 352 Davidsonian theory 73, 79–81 Davis, Steven 153 Dawkins, Richard 204, 237, 241–2, 398 De Certeau, Michel 398 De Man, Paul 10, 12, 129, 131–6, 155, 158, 398 Deconstruction, and narrative speech act 129–66, 355 Default and contraction rules 225–6 Deixis, and evidence 316–25 Dennett, Daniel C. 6–8, 18, 20–24, 122, 169, 179–80, 183, 201, 204–5, 212, 214, 236–7, 241–2, 246, 250, 254, 275, 287, 315, 325, 339–40, 343, 345, 358, 360, 362, 370, 375–6, 378, 395, 398 Derrida, Jacques 1, 12, 69, 109, 126, 131–3, 136, 158, 353, 398 Dickens 308 Dimock, E.C. 388 Disaster, contemporary political stances towards 291–2 narratives 17–20, 106, 294–310, 313, 372–6 Drabble, Margaret 240, 278–9, 282 Dummett 168 Eco, Umberto 8, 202, 207 Einstein 29, 347 Eliot, George 311, 314 Eliot, T.S. 104 Emotional registers 390–3 Enchantment in narratives 332–40 Epistemic hunger 364 Ergo 133, 353 Ethics, and speech act theory 155–66 Ethnomethodological analysis, of narrative 249–87, 365, 369 Euripides 93
420
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Evaluation, paradox of 42, 47–51, 53–4 Evaluative inferences, and story endings 226–7 Event structures 56–7 Evidence, enigmas from 311–40 Expectations 56–7 Explicature 229–34 Explicit performative 136–7 Expressibility, principle of 93, 116–28, 184, 240–2, 351 Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals 390 Ezekiel, Nissim 311–12, 314 Fairy-tale and myths 52–3 Felicity conditions, narrative fit 84–5, 185 on putative illocutionary act on narration 85–112 Fiction, expressibility and cooperative principle 116–28 felicity conditions and narrative fit 84–112 form of 75–6 historian’s dilemma and 305–10 illocutionary force of 74–84, 151 pragmatics 70–4 pretence, plagiarism and narration 137–47 putative illocutionary act 85–112 speech act theory 70–4, 112–16, 350 Fictional discourse authorless narrative 6–12 logic of 77–80 paradox 179, 339, 378 searle’s paradox 8, 137 Floods, narrative about 316–28, 333– 40, 380–4 Fludernik M. 395 Forster, E.M. 89, 246, 395 Foucault’s Pendulum 203
Fragile narratives 237–43, 263–81, 285–6, 363–4, 369, 376, 378 Framing the Sign 155 Fried Green Tomatoes 235–6 Garfinkel, Harold 55, 251 Garrett, John 341–2 Generalizations 254–63, 367 Genette, G. 395 Glenn, C.G. 57, 60–1 Gnomons, 203–6 Goddess speaks, paradox of 20–5 Goffman, Erving 251 Gora 308 Gorgias doctrine 275 Govindpuri jhuggi fire narrative 295– 7 Grammar, and context of narrative 26– 8 Grammatical rules 57–8 Granta Magazine 13–14 Green, G.M. 67 Greimas 395 Grice, H.P. 4, 7, 63, 70, 74, 83–4, 101, 111–14, 120–2, 152–4, 165, 167–9, 173, 175–85, 189–91, 198–9, 206, 209, 211, 228–31, 233, 239, 243–4, 247, 255, 279, 345, 354, 358–9, 363, 398 Gricean concept of implicature 19 Gricean cooperative maxims 55, 63, 83 Gricean theory 5, 73, 111–12, 120–2, 124–5, 152–3, 165, 176–8, 180, 228–31, 233, 346, 349, 351, 363 Grimshaw, A.D. 110–11 Hardy, Thomas 249, 286 Harmish, R.M. 70–2, 186 Harrison, Bernard 112 Heart of Darkness 245 Hedges 367 Hippolytus 93
INDEX
Historian’s dilemma and fictionality 305–10 Historical agency, and narrative mysteries 312–16 How to do Things with Words 133, 135, 137, 148 Hugo, Victor 345 Human frailty, and narrative fragility 263–75 Hunting Down a Theory of Communication 4 Hymes, Dell 35, 111 Illocutionary act 85–112, 115, 134–6, 145–6, 151 perlocutions and 134–6 Illocutionary force, of fiction 74–84 Implicature 188–200, 229–34, 359–60 turn-taking rules and regularities 188–200 Impliculture 179–88, 224–34, 359 maxims for 179–88 notions of 224–9 Indian Rope Trick, paradox of narrative 12–16, 23, 28–9, 53, 55, 65, 67, 147, 171, 179, 205, 209, 236, 247, 253, 262–3, 340, 342, 346, 348, 354, 356, 360, 363, 366– 7, 376 Inferences 59–66, 203–6, 361–3 Inferential grammar, of narrative 241–2 Inferential model of narrative 211–30 application of 217–29 Inferential tree 224–5 Informational inferences 61 International Decade of Natural Disaster Reduction (IDNDR) 291 Interpretation, and speech and theory 155–66 Interruptive culture, narrative sequence in 325–32 Introduction to Colloquial Bengali 388 Introduction to Spoken Bengali 388 Iteration and narrative tension 243– 38
421
Jakobson, Roman 26–7 James, William 114 Jefferson, Gail 96, 102, 178, 188, 190– 1, 253–5, 282, 286, 328, 398 Johnson, N.S. 31, 54–7, 59, 397 Joyce, James 181 Kant 165, 180, 183 Kapucinski, Rysard 13–14 Kasher, Asha 70, 73–4, 112 Katz, J.J. 130 Keenan, Ochs 4 Keenan, Rimmon 395 Kinder und Hausmärchen 142 Kintsch 67 Kipling 309 Kishwar, Madhu 297 Kripke, Saul A. 80, 294, 296 Kundera, Milan 8, 395 Labov, William 19–20, 26, 31–4, 42, 45–8, 50–4, 59, 61, 65–6, 88– 9, 95, 116, 163, 185, 207, 213, 215, 217, 231, 246, 259–60, 262, 264, 274, 329, 331–2, 345, 348, 357, 362, 377, 392, 397 Labovian schema 31–2, 66 Labovian story grammar 18 Lacan 398 Language, concept of 168 conventions 175–9 cooperative principle 175–9 functional psychology 170–2 game 172–6, 179, 190, 194, 257, 331, 352, 357, 366 mind, social context and 168–72 philosophy of 2 rules and rationality 173–5 transcription and translation 385– 9 Lanigan, R. 151–2 Lanser, Susan 161 Leach, Edmund 217 Levelt, J.M. 28, 55, 67, 206
422
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Levinson, S.C. 63, 178–9, 349, 358 theory of politeness 73 Levi-Strauss, Claude 26–7, 345, 395, 397 Lewis, David K. 4, 7, 83, 113, 127, 173– 9, 187, 190–2, 198, 255–6, 357, 366, 398 Linearization concept of 28–9 Listeners grammars 57–9 Logical inferences 60–1 Maclean, M. 207, 246, 395 Mandler, J.M. 31, 54–7, 59, 397 Manoeuvres 281–7 Marvell, Andrew 25 Maxims for narrative and implicature 179–88 Maxims of quality, quantity etc. 173, 177–8, 182, 184, 190, 192, 194, 198–9, 229–31, 239, 244, 260, 280, 285–6, 351–2, 357–9 McCabe, Alyssa 398 Memes 203–6 Metaphore, Davidsonian theory of 73, 79–81, 349 Midnight’s Children 120 Miller, Hills 246, 249–50, 255, 262– 3, 339, 398 Mind, and social context of language 168–72 Minksy, M. 60 Mishra, Dinesh Kumar 322–3 Morgenstern 176 Morris 136–7 Mysteries narratives 312–16 Myths, and fairy tale 52–3 Nair, Bhaya 246 Nair, R.B. 21–2, 53, 65, 211, 241–2, 351, 353, 357, 361, 365, 368– 9, 393, 395, 397–8 Nair’s communicating cog 21 Narrative analysis 32–41 authorless 6–8, 20–2
care of self through 19 cause of 311–40 clause 34–6, 39, 89, 91 co-authored 22 cognitive implications of 28–9 contrast narrative 5–6 conversation and 28 course of 397–8 cultural memes in 201–48 definition of 34, 40 of disaster 17–20, 294–305 dynamic structure 5 ethnomethodological analysis of 249–87 evaluative analysis 33 fictional discourse and 6–12 floods 316–28, 333–40, 380–4 formal analysis 33 fragility 237–42, 263–81 functional analysis 33, 41–7 gender and 297–303 grammar and context of 26–68 implied meaning of 167–200 Indian Rope Trick Paradox of 12– 16, 23, 28–9, 32, 53, 55, 65, 67, 147, 171, 179, 205, 209, 236, 247, 253, 262–3, 340, 342, 346, 348, 354, 356, 360, 363, 366– 7, 376 inferential model of 211–17 as instrument of self-protection 18 interactional concept 10 as linguistic structure 14 maxims for 179–88 mental codes in 201–48 as mode of self-creation 18 morals in 250 mysteries 312–16 paradoxes of 6–12 perceived self images in 18 as perlocutionary act 147–54 politics of 288–310 pretence, plagiarism and 137–47 psychological validity 31 referential analysis 33
INDEX
sequencing 325–32 as speech act 69–128 strands and state of story teller 292–3 structural simplicities in 26–68 sutras 3, 20, 79, 341–79 takeover over meaning implications of 30 tension and iteration 243–8 theory of 18–19, 29–30, 33, 394–5 theory typology 394–5 thought experiment 30–2 universal elements of 392 Narrative Gravity 7–12, 17, 19, 32, 65, 110, 183, 231, 246, 313, 330, 340–1, 343–7, 379, 388–9 Natural order, story grammers and 54– 5 Nicholas, D.W. 56, 60, 62, 65, 206, 213 Nietzsche, Friedrich 66–7, 69, 119, 127, 132, 147, 349, 351–2 Nodes 59–66 Non-propositional attitudes 228–9, 233 Nussbaum, Martha 398 Ochs, E. 395 Odlin, T. 67, 202 Oedipus Rex 246 Oral narratives 31 Orientation 42–3, 46–8, 51, 53 Ostensive inferential communication 206–11 Pandey, Gyan 306–7 Pascal, Blaise 126 Pateman, T. 169 Penrose, Roger 209 People’s narratives 297–303, 306 People’s Union for Democratic Rights (PUDR) 295 Performativity 130–7, 205 deconstructive critique of 132–7 Perlocution, definition of 153
423
illocution and 134–6, 145–7, 151 narrative as 147–54 Perlocutionary acts, conditions for 153 as narrative 147–54 Phaedra 92–4, 96 Philosophical Investigations 168, 172 Picasso, Pablo 392 Pitting speech act thory 355 Placements 394–6 Plagiarism 137–47 Plausibility, and fragile narrative 275– 81, 286, 314, 369 Polanyi, L. 4 Politeness, Levinson’s theory of 73, 349 Pragmatics, phenomena required for 73 speech act theory and 70–4, 112 Pratt, Mary Louise 163, 207, 246, 395 Pretence 137–47 Prince, G. 395 Propositional content, condition for 85–6, 88–9 Propositional inference 233 Propp, Vladimir 27, 345, 395 Protagoras doctrine 275 Psycholinguistic story grammar 18, 31 Pulman, Stephen 294 Putnam, Hilary 294 Quirk, R. 181, 385, 389 Racine 93 Ramanujan, A.K. 398 Rationality, of language 173–5 Recanati, F. 4 Regularities and implicatures 188–200 Relevance Ostensive inferential communication and 206–11 theory 73, 349 Relevance 206, 209, 279 Rewrite rules 57–9 Ricoeur, Paul 288, 290, 303, 398 Rieger 62
424
N A R R AT I V E G R A V I T Y
Right of privacy 162–6 Rigveda 1 Ritvo, Harriet 18 Rorty, Richard 307–8 Rules of language 173–5 Rumelhart, D.E. 55, 395 Rushdie, Salman 15, 120, 288–9, 298 Sacks, Harvey 27–8, 43–5, 47, 51, 66, 99, 188, 190–1, 207, 240, 246, 254–8, 262, 274, 276, 278, 280– 1, 284–5, 287, 328, 330–1, 336, 340, 348, 365, 367–8, 378, 395, 398 Sahni, Bhisham 308 Said, Edward 288, 398 Salience, principle of 66 Salient paradox 66–8 Saussure, Ferdinand de 26 Schank, R.C. 60 Schegloff, E.A. 102, 188, 190–1, 254– 5, 365 Scheherazade 14 Schenkein, J. 286 Schiffer, S.R. 4 Schwartz, S.G. 294 Searle, J.R. 1, 4, 8–12, 21, 24, 44, 69– 70, 74, 76–85, 87–8, 93, 101– 2, 113–20, 122, 130–2, 137–40, 144–5, 147, 149–50, 152, 157, 168, 171–2, 177–9, 181, 184– 5, 231, 240–2, 246, 254, 257, 275, 278, 339–40, 345, 350, 356, 358, 378, 395, 397 Searle paradox of fictional discourse 8–12 Searlean performer 21 Self-narratives 370 Shadows of the Mind 209 Shakespeare, WIlliam 129, 161, 308 Short story 234–7 Simple episode, structure of 58 Sinclair, J.M. 190 Slots 59–66 Snakeskin Robin 341
Songlines 16–20 Speech act conditions of narrativity 89–91 Speech act scheme (SAS) 70–2 Speech act theory 9–10, 69–75, 82, 84– 5, 87, 101, 112–16, 118, 129–31, 144–5, 155–66, 181, 349, 352 interpretation and ethics 155–66 pragmatics and 70–4 scope and interpretation of 112–16 scope and use 155–6 Sperber, Dan 4, 7, 9, 63, 66, 70, 113, 122, 129–30, 169, 180, 204, 206, 209, 211–12, 216, 228–9, 233, 236, 244–5, 247, 252, 279, 350, 363, 398 Spiro 56 Spivak, Gayatri 300, 309, 398 Spontaneous narratives 31 Spontaneous stories 65 Stark 168 Stein, N.L. 57, 59, 61 Stevens, Wallace 26–7, 30, 43 Story-grammars 27–31, 41, 213–14, 241–2, 348 Story-imports 65 Story-schemata 56 Storytalk 3–6 Storyteller, expert knowledge 294–7 myths 16–17 narrative strands and states of 292–3 natural and nominal kind 294–7 Street, B.V. 246 Structural simplicities, in narratives 26–68 illustrations on 32–41 story grammars 27–30 thought experiment 30–3 Structuralism 26, 347 Sutton-Page, W. 388 Svartvik, J. 181, 385, 389 Swift, Jonathan 167 Syntactic embedding 39
INDEX
Tagore, Rabindranath 308 Tale of Two Cities 308 Talk-exchange, Grice’s analysis of 120 Talking into tape recorders 251–4 Tall tale 234–7 Tamas 308 Tannen, D. 61, 207, 246 Tape-recorders, talking into 251–4 Tempest 160–1 Temporal sequence 36, 39 Thematic Apperception Test (TAT) 63 Thirwall 275 Thought experiment 30–2 Todorov, Tzevan 231, 394, 398 Tolstoy 308 Toolan, Michael 395, 398 Trabasso, T. 56, 60, 62, 65, 206, 213 Transcription and translation 385–9 Turing, Alan 207–8 Turing test 208 Turn taking rules and implicatures 188–200 Turner, Roy 199
425
Ulysses 181 Value inferences 61 Von Neumann, J. 176 Waletzky, Joseph 19, 31–4, 46–8, 50, 52–4, 59, 61, 65–6, 89, 185, 331–2, 348 War and Peace 308 Warren, W.H. 56, 60, 62, 65, 206, 213 Wedding Guest 11 Wernicke 392 What is History? 308 Wilson, Diedre 4, 7, 9, 63, 66, 70, 113, 122, 129, 169, 180, 204, 206, 209, 211–12, 216, 228–9, 233, 236, 244–5, 247, 252, 279, 350, 363, 398 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 133, 147–8, 167–74, 310, 352 Wollaston 167 Woolf, Virginia 201–2, 205–6, 236 Writing of the Disaster 304