THE EDINBURGH COMPANION TO CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
General Editor Mark Evans
Edinburgh University Press
The Edinburg...
15 downloads
809 Views
28MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
THE EDINBURGH COMPANION TO CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
General Editor Mark Evans
Edinburgh University Press
The Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism
This page intentionally left blank
The Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism
General Editor Mark Evans
Edinburgh University Press
#
in this edition Edinburgh University Press, 2001.
Copyright in the individual contributions is retained by the authors. Edinburgh University Press 22 George Square, Edinburgh Typeset in Goudy by Hewer Text Ltd, Edinburgh, and printed and bound in Great Britain by Bookcraft Ltd A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 0 7486 1359 5 (hardback) The right of the contributors to be identified as authors of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
CONTENTS
Acknowledgements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vii List of Contributors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
ix
Part One: The Liberal Trajectory
1. Issues and Trends in Contemporary Liberalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Mark Evans
2. Twentieth-Century Liberal Thought: Development or Transformation? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21 Michael Freeden
Part Two: Citizenship: Universalism and Particularism
3. Human Rights and Ethnocultural Justice . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Will Kymlicka
4. Liberalism and Citizenship . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51 Andrew Vincent
5. The Sword of Faith and the Shield of Fear: Liberalism and the Power of the Nation. . . . . . . . . . 63 Margaret Canovan
6. Liberal Citizenship and Feminism. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 75 Andrea Baumeister
Part Three: Justice: Identity and Distribution
7. Liberalism and the Politics of Recognition. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 89 Jonathan Seglow
8. The Essential Indeterminacy of Rawls's Difference Principle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101 Rex Martin
9. Rawlsian Theory, Contemporary Marxism and the Difference Principle . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113 Rodney G. Peffer
Part Four: Problems of Liberal Justification
10. Disenchantment and the Liberalism of Fear . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135 Peter Lassman
11. Pragmatist Liberalism and the Evasion of Politics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 148 Mark Evans
CONTENTS
12. Liberalism and Contingency . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 162 Bruce Haddock
Part Five: Liberalism versus Republicanism?
13. Back to the Future: Pluralism and the Republican Alternative to Liberalism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175 Richard Bellamy
14. Accommodating Republicanism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 188 David Rasmussen
Part Six: The `Autonomous Individual': Feminist Critiques and Liberal Replies
15. Liberalism, Feminism, Enlightenment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 197 Kate Soper
16. Feminism and Women's Autonomy: The Challenge of Female Genital Cutting . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208 Diana Tietjens Meyers
Part Seven: Liberalism Beyond the Nation-State
17. Civil Association: The European Union as a Supranational Liberal Legal Order . . . . . . . . . . . . 225 Robert Bideleux
18. The Idea of a Liberal-Democratic Peace. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 241 Howard Williams
19. Constructing International Community: Liberal Theory, Developmental Communitarianism and International Ethics . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 Peter Sutch
Part Eight: New Directions for Liberal Thinking
20. Liberalism and Post-communism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 269 Richard Sakwa
21. Liberalism, Ecocentrism and Persons . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 287 Brian Baxter
22. Prolegomenon to a Liberal Theory of the Good Life . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 299 Mark Evans
Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 312 Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 323
vi
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
I would like to thank the University of Wales Academic Support Fund for a generous grant that financed several conferences and seminar sessions at which early versions of most of these chapters were aired and discussed. Thanks are also due to the following for permission to include revised versions of articles they have published: to the editor of the Review of Constitutional Studies, published by the Centre for Constitutional Studies at the University of Alberta, for Chapter 3; to the editor of Journal of Political Ideologies for Chapter 5; to Kluwer Academic Publishers and Larry May and Marilyn Friedman, editors of Rights and Reason, for Chapter 8; and to the editor of Environmental Values for Chapter 21. My colleagues in the Department of Political Theory and Government at the University of Wales, Swansea have been very supportive of this project, not least in relieving me of teaching and administration at a crucial time in its gestation. I would particularly like to thank David Boucher, Bruce Haddock and Rex Martin for their advice and encouragement. Nicola Carr and the staff of Edinburgh University Press have been patient, cheerful and immensely helpful. Having taken on such a large volume as my first collaborative project, I could hardly have wished for a better team. My family, as ever, has been immensely supportive, too, and Anne in particular has never flagged in her encouragement during my many distractions and absences throughout the production of this book.
vii
This page intentionally left blank
LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
Andrea Baumeister is Lecturer in Politics at the
Rex Martin is Professor of Philosophy at the Uni-
University of Stirling.
versity of Kansas and was, until 2000, Professor of Political Theory at the University of Wales, Swansea.
Brian Baxter is Lecturer in Politics at the Uni-
Diana Tietjens Meyers is Professor of Philosophy
versity of Dundee.
at the University of Connecticut.
Richard Bellamy is Professor of Politics at the
Rodney G. Peffer is Professor of Philosophy at the
University of Reading.
University of San Diego.
Robert Bideleux is Reader in Politics at the Uni-
David Rasmussen is Professor of Philosophy at
versity of Wales, Swansea.
Boston College, Massachusetts.
Margaret Canovan is Professor of Politics at the
Richard Sakwa is Professor of Politics at the Uni-
University of Keele.
versity of Kent at Canterbury.
Mark Evans is Lecturer in Political Theory at the
Jonathan Seglow is Lecturer in Politics at Royal
University of Wales, Swansea.
Holloway and Bedford New College.
Michael Freeden is Professor of Politics at the
University of Oxford and a Fellow of Mansfield
Kate Soper is Professor of Philosophy at the Uni-
College.
versity of North London.
Bruce Haddock is Reader in Politics at the Uni-
Peter Sutch is a Tutorial Fellow in the School of
versity of Wales, Swansea.
European Studies at the University of Wales, Cardiff.
Will
Kymlicka
is
Professor
of
Philosophy
Andrew Vincent is Professor of Politics in the
at
School of European Studies at the University of
Queen's University, Ontario.
Wales, Cardiff.
Peter Lassman is Senior Lecturer in Politics at the
Howard Williams is Professor of Politics at the
University of Birmingham.
University of Wales, Aberystwyth.
ix
This page intentionally left blank
Part One THE LIBERAL TRAJECTORY
This page intentionally left blank
1
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM Mark Evans
literature. Although it would be an exaggeration to
Introduction
say that the `Rawls industry' has swamped all other
For most contemporary liberal political theorists, it is
dimensions of liberal academic argument, it is never-
a defining tenet of their historical self-consciousness
theless obvious that liberalism's theoretical revival in
that political theory was `reborn' in 1971 with the
the last quarter of the twentieth century was largely
publication of John Rawls's magisterially weighty A
powered by the critical response to Theory. Even
1
After many years in which the grip
non-liberals have found it difficult to address the
of linguistic analysis reduced it to the supposedly
central questions of political theory without being
impartial role of clarifying the meaning of political
expected to orient themselves with respect to `the
concepts (and which led one commentator to de-
Rawlsian position'. The influence of Rawlsianism ± if
clare the more substantive activity of normative
only as a critical springboard ± can be detected in
position-taking in political philosophising to be
most breaths of the resurrected tradition of political
Theory of Justice.
2
theorising.
`dead' ), this book triumphantly demonstrated to liberals that intellectual validity could, after all, be
For anyone working in this tradition, it is thus
claimed for a philosophical theory that proposed
profoundly disturbing to encounter the charge that
what the content of political morality should be
the `revitalisation' of liberal political theory as any-
and how it might be justified. No longer need the
thing more than an `academic' preoccupation (in-
grand theorising of the just or good political society
cluding the pejorative sense of that term) is actually
be taken up only by liberalism's enemies ± particu-
illusory. In a series of excoriating critiques, John
larly, in the years immediately before Theory's ap-
Gray charges that contemporary liberal theorising
pearance, those to its left whose thinking shared
`has done little more than articulate the prejudices of
none of its hesitation over position-taking (a point
an Anglo-American academic class that lacks any
which demonstrates the overly parochial nature of
understanding of political life in our age.'
liberals' `death of political theory' claims).
contemporary philosophical guise liberalism lamen-
3
In its
Rawls's importance lies not only in his restoration
tably mistakes its own parochial, historical and cul-
to liberals of a confidence that they were indeed
tural specificity for an ahistorically and universally
justified in using philosophical argument for the
applicable mode of political discourse and analysis.
substantive end of defending the liberal order. It lies
Further, its concepts and concerns ± indeed, the very
also in the way in which both the specific principles
methods by which it conducts its theorising and the
of his theory and the way in which he defends them
forums in which it takes place ± are peculiarly
have generated a truly enormous debate and a vast
divorced from the actual politics even of those
3
MARK EVANS
western societies in which liberalism is said to be the
than does the academic study of it. Moreover, pol-
dominant political tradition. So for all of their
itics is hardly alone in being a concern whose full
hubristic pretensions to speak to the pressing poli-
comprehension is beyond all bar those few who have
tical problems of our times, liberal theorists ± who
the time, resources and aptitude to master its detail
have encouraged a wholly delusive perception that
even when it impacts greatly upon everyone. So
these can be all addressed within liberal terms of
when liberal political theorists decide to take, say,
reference
4
± `are reduced to talking with each other,
a Kantian approach to a concrete political problem ±
and to no one else, about topics of interest to no one
the selection and justification of basic constitutional
else, least of all in the liberal democracies they are
principles, for example ± they are obviously not
supposed to be addressing.'
5
Rather than a `rebirth'
political theory suffered a tragic `still birth' in 1971.
immediately vulnerable to the charges of unworldli-
6
ness and irrelevance simply by virtue of using ideas
Given this conclusion, Gray proposes that perhaps
unknown to, and probably not fully appreciable by,
political theory is not suited to substantive norma-
those to whom the problem nevertheless applies.
tive position-taking after all. Maybe it would be best
We might, of course, justifiably challenge the
for it humbly to retreat once again to the insular
appropriateness of the approach taken and/or the
world of the ivory tower and engage, if not in the
proposed solutions to it. Certainly, this is what Gray
dextrous niceties of linguistic philosophy, then to the
attempts to do and there is obviously a serious debate
`modest exegesis of texts ± like Mill's Liberty, say ±
to be had about the applicability of contemporary
whose charm is in their distance from the world, or
liberalism's methodology and recommendations. But
any world we are likely to find ourselves in.'
7
to reach any conclusion on this question substantive
Now such a devastating critique is hardly likely to
engagement with such theory is required; its rele-
be accepted with alacrity in the massed ranks of
vance to the practical problem at stake must be put
contemporary liberal political theorists, who are
to the test rather than denied straight away. And
much more likely than some of their linguistic-
even if the results of such assessment are ultimately
philosophical predecessors to be wounded by the
negative, it is still possible that the approach has
charge of `practical irrelevance'. Doubtless there is
thrown valuable light upon the concrete problem.
a temptation to treat it with an instantly dismissive
There is no argument here, then, for abandoning
contempt. Yet despite the critique's intemperance,
contemporary liberal political theory's normative
there may be a lurking fear that there is something to
ambitions.
its claims. For example, liberal thinkers who deal
Gray's critique, however, amounts to much more
with what they regard as issues that affect all of their
than just the ineffective charge that liberalism's
fellow citizens (and are therefore concerned to keep
theoretical approaches are remote from the `real
in view the `relevance' of their ideas to the wider
world of politics'. It urges that the very problems
world) need little perceptiveness to sense that, out-
taken up by liberal theorists and those critics who
side of the academic community, their work may be
debate with them in the same philosophical tradi-
8
Whatever their intentions
tions are simply not the problems (or at least the
to the contrary, they are indeed effectively talking
prime or only problems) of the real world, either of
only to each other.
liberal-democratic societies or of human commu-
completely inaccessible.
9
nities more widely. Gray finds it deeply absurd that,
If `inaccessibility' is simply a question of the technical difficulty of their writings, then there
for example, the journal Ethics ± which is one of the
may be no great cause for concern. After all, political
foremost vehicles for contemporary liberal academic
problems do tend to be extremely complex. We
moral and political theory ± should devote an entire
should not necessarily expect there to be any easy,
issue to a discussion of the merits and drawbacks of
publicly comprehensible ways of theorising them and
market socialism.
their possible resolution. The actual business of
have done better to discuss the prospects of the
politics requires no less technical understanding
restoration of monarchy in Russia ± far less of an
and expertise, unavailable to the citizenry as a whole,
exercise in anachronism, and just conceivably a topic
4
10
The contributors, he says, `might
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
it as nothing other than the genteel exchanges of
of some interest to those whose fates it might affect.'
11
philosophical
In more measured moments, Gray is happy
claims
between
professional
aca-
to grant that some of liberal theory's concerns do
demics. By highlighting the issues, we can see di-
connect with the practice of liberalism. But he still
rectly how liberalism engages with the problems of
wants to insist that there is much more to humanity's
practical political life today. And with the emphasis
political condition than liberal theory has allowed.
upon agenda-setting ± the topics that can and should
The purpose of the Edinburgh Companion to Con-
be addressed as well as what are currently being
temporary Liberalism is to demonstrate just how far
addressed ± contemporary liberalism can be seen
liberal theory can stand from the kind of abstract,
to be live: relevant, proactive, continuously engaged
unworldly,
and adaptable.
trivial
philosophical
navel-gazing
de-
picted in this caricaturising critique. I do not wish
If the Companion does not ultimately address all
to deny that the Rawls-inspired strand of liberal
the issues that Gray thinks to be so strikingly absent
theorising in particular has perhaps tended towards
from contemporary western political theory, it may
narrowness, both in terms of the issues discussed and
not be for want of space alone. Despite the claim
the range of authors who have engaged with them.
favoured by some that liberalism is becoming a global
Without in any way wishing to belittle the value and
doctrine and despite, too, the fact that its theorising
importance of this body of thought, it has probably
of international relations touches matters of concern
become all too easy to mistake its prominence as
for everyone in the world, many contemporary lib-
meaning that it signifies all that to which liberalism
erals are very wary (much more so than their pre-
necessarily amounts today. `Contemporary liberal-
decessors typically were) of any hubristic idea that all
ism' is often reduced to what Rawls and a select band
of their concerns are matters for humanity in its
of thinkers ± such as Dworkin, Nagel, Scanlon and
entirety. They recognise that `politics' may not be
Raz ± have to say. This phenomenon may well have
exhausted by their account of it alone, so that some
softened liberalism up in the face of the kind of
of the (sometimes rather bizarre) issues whose ab-
critique rehearsed above. Yet not only is it still unfair
sence Gray observes (such as theism, theocracy,
to say that Rawls, his interlocutors and their con-
`Byzantinism' and monarchism) are indeed best left
cerns are divorced from what really matters in po-
to other traditions of political thought to address.
litical practice, it is simply wrong to think that
Nor need it be thought that the `contemporary
contemporary liberalism does not and cannot range
agenda', wide-ranging though I believe it should
far beyond the `Rawlsian ambit'. This Companion,
be, is completely exhaustive of the issues that could
then, will certainly engage with liberal theory's `usual
legitimately warrant liberals' concern now and in the
suspects', but it will also show how liberalism can
future. Some issues in practice come to matter more
tackle issues that Gray's critique might fool us into
than others at certain times (a feature which will be
thinking are somehow out of its reach.
evident in the selection of themes covered in this
To this end, the book does not simply present
volume). But precisely because its fluidity and flex-
`contemporary liberalism' in terms of a survey of what
ibility is emphasised, we need not think ± as many of
its main protagonists have said over the past thirty
its critics seem implicitly prone to believe ± that
years or so. Instead, its guiding principle is to con-
liberalism is somehow conceptually and/or morally
ceptualise it as a set of issues and approaches that
incapable of addressing the topics with which it is
might be said to constitute liberalism's current prac-
not currently engaging.
tical challenges and hence its current research agen-
In short, the Companion hopes to present what will
da. After all, the importance of any one theorist
hopefully be compelling evidence that contemporary
ultimately rests upon the importance of the political
liberalism has not misidentified the relevant political
problem she or he is addressing; only once that is
concerns and that its approaches to their analysis are
recognised, perhaps, is the value of their work fully
not naõÈvely misguided. Even if debates about such
assessable. An `issue-led' account of contemporary
concerns may still rage and even if ± as some of the
liberalism shows how unilluminating it is to think of
chapters will show ± it may be justifiably doubted
5
MARK EVANS
whether liberal theory is always the best-equipped to
The other tendency is a product of Rawls's pro-
deal with them, there is still much theoretically and
minence in contemporary debates and has already
practically useful insight to be gained from it.
been alluded to. It identifies liberalism with the specifically anti-perfectionist politics of constitutional-democratic justice that his work has popu-
Contesting the Nature of `Liberalism'
larised and which has subsequently engaged so many
One feature that the discussion thus far might seem to
in liberal political theory. Thus, it has become very
share with much contemporary political theory is the
easy to think it axiomatic that liberalism is about the
apparent assumption that `liberalism' needs no expli-
`neutrality of the state', `the priority of the right over
cit definition, as if it is enough simply to name it to
the good', `the politics of public reason' and other
convey what kind of politics is intended. Those who
leitmotifs of Rawlsian theory. Now we have already
accept any version of Francis Fukuyama's belief that
conceded that Rawls has inspired a very influential
liberalism's ideals have morally triumphed over all
and perhaps attractive conception of liberalism. And
others and that ideological conflict in the realm of
I will shortly sketch how it frames many of the
ideas is now over may be particularly inclined to hold
predominant themes in liberalism's `post-Rawls' re-
12
Perhaps in earlier times, when this
search agenda. But as Michael Freeden forcefully
battle was still being fought, it was always necessary for
demonstrates in Chapter 2, it offers a very histori-
liberals to be explicit and detailed about that for which
cally and culturally specific interpretation of liberal-
they were fighting. When positions no longer need
ism (and one whose Kantianism is, moreover, not
defending, they may no longer need demarcating.
nearly as faithful to its cultural roots as it likes to
this assumption.
think).
In fact, of course, liberalism's meaning has always been contested by liberals themselves and even if we
One consequence of this narrowing of liberalism's
accept some version of Fukuyama's controversial
definition has been to render it vulnerable to criti-
claim we should not delude ourselves into thinking
cisms that would comfortably bypass other members
that this particular contest is also over. We should be
of the liberal tradition. Indeed, it often gives the
especially wary of two opposing tendencies in con-
impression of being blind to the existence of such a
temporary political theory's definitional handling of
diverse tradition behind it. Chapter 2 therefore
`liberalism'. One, which may be particularly encour-
serves to remind contemporary liberals of its exis-
aged if one accepts that it now has no serious
tence. In doing so, it suggests that one research task
competition in the Enlightenment tradition of pro-
of liberal theory now is to open up possibilities of
gressive politics (as socialism, say, once provided),
redefinition and perhaps retrieval of certain liberal
equates liberalism with a few very general Enlight-
self-images and commitments, lost from sight in the
enment moral commitments centring around some
fog of Rawlsianism, which may be valuable resources
notion of `equal individual freedom'. On this ac-
for the doctrine's defence and development.
count, if it is going too far to say that we are `all
Neither tendency serves us well, then, in trying to
liberals now', then it is still the case that non-liberal-
characterise liberalism. But this claim does not rest
ism ends up being defined very narrowly in terms of
upon any assumption that we can describe an ade-
doctrines such as fascism, ethnic nationalism and
quate, generally acceptable typology for it that is at
certain types of religious fundamentalism. In other
once sufficiently expansive to cover all liberalisms
words, `liberalism' is little more than a label to cover
but also sufficiently detailed not to become indis-
all adherents to the general progressive standpoint
tinguishable from related but distinct political doc-
opposed to these. From this perspective, it might
trines. In fact, it is probably best to treat liberalism as
therefore be thought difficult for any `reasonable'
in essence internally contested. The `liberal label'
person to argue against it. But with such a capacious
denotes a political identity to be regarded as one
definition `liberalism' would no longer be able to
that is not permissively open-ended but which oper-
stake specific political standpoints within the broad
ates within certain conceptual and historical con-
range of `progressivism'.
straints, yet whose diversity within these boundaries
6
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
should be celebrated rather than regretted. As most
dependence and strong ties of mutually supportive
of the chapters implicitly demonstrate, `liberalism'
obligations between people. Given the accelerating
remains an invaluable shorthand term. But, while its
spread of what Richard Rorty calls the `human rights
various usages cannot be totally antithetical to each
culture', however,
other without at least one of them being a misuse, we
general have increasingly employed the notion of
should not make the mistake of thinking there must
`individual human rights' as the conceptual device by
be any thoroughgoing identity of views and commit-
which to express at least part of their moral commit-
ments behind them all.
13
15
it is fair to say that liberals in
ment. They are not, however, conceptually bound to do so; there are other ways of formulating the general
Leaving it, then, to the individual contributors to use the term as they wish, I will here confine myself
commitment
to the identification of a few general themes and
should it be thought that liberal individual rights
tendencies in definitions of liberalism, to preface the
are necessarily characterised and prioritised in a
arguments in the rest of this introduction.
14
to
equal
individual
freedom.
Nor
manner that would negate or trump any official
It is
support for social justice.
important to note that the term can be used to characterise quite distinct topics or areas of concern
Area (2) concerns how liberalism's moral commit-
in particular ways and that confusion between them
ments are cashed out in terms of political institutions
may contribute to the vagaries of debating liberal-
and practices. As we might expect given the ob-
ism's nature. Three areas in particular are worthy of
servations above, the liberal tradition has ranged
note: (1) liberalism as a political morality; (2) lib-
from support for minimal or `night-watchman' states
eralism as a form of political regime; (3) liberalism as
presiding over loosely regulated free-market capitalist
a form of culture, or social order.
economies (sometimes now grouped under the heading of `libertarianism'
Under (1), liberalism posits the individual as the
16
) to the kind of economically
fundamental unit of moral and political concern.
interventionist welfarist politics sometimes thought
Although this need not be incompatible with a
to be the preserve of socialism or social democracy.
strong commitment to a notion of community and
Once again, though, we can identify certain wide-
the common good (and should not be thought to
spread tendencies across the liberal spectrum. For
imply an unavoidable reliance upon an atomistic
example, liberals tend to support some version of
methodological individualism at the heart of its
representative democracy as being (a) the most ideal
social-explanatory
does
and/or efficient way in which citizens can be given a
not deliberately subsume the individual in, or totally
say in how they are ruled; (b) the most ideal and/or
subordinate it to, any collective unit. The liberal
efficient way in which power can be held accoun-
individual is held to be `equally free' and the purpose
table by those over whom it is exercised; (c) the best
of liberal moral and political society is, in the first
means by which the state's power can be limited to
instance, to protect and promote the interests of
those specific areas of social life in which liberal
individuals as equally free beings. This is at the heart
politics is deemed to be rightfully concerned.
theory),
liberal
morality
17
of the justifications for whatever constraints such a
The argument for liberalism's equal individual
society will wish to place upon its members. How
moral freedoms is reinforced by the commitment
precisely this notion of equal freedom is to be inter-
to democracy, for it emphasises how the exercise
preted is part of what fuels the ongoing contest over
of political choice requires freedoms of expression
liberalism's nature. The concept of `justice' is often
and association (for example) to be rendered mean-
used nowadays as the peg upon which to hang this
ingful. The idea that politics is also a limited activity,
debate. And in their accounts of what justice de-
with realms of life being left free from direct political
mands of people to facilitate the equal freedom of all,
regulation, is a further consequence of the liberal
liberals can range from very individualistic moral-
account of freedom. Though the extent to which it is
ities, which emphasise political `non-interference', to
to be regulated is significantly variable within liberal
highly proactive theories of redistributive social jus-
thinking, liberals tend to support the general idea of
tice that posit substantial degrees of individual inter-
a market economy in which private property is
7
MARK EVANS
allowable (if not necessarily to the exclusion of any
individual identities and projects. But, again, they
form of public ownership). The capitalist character
tend to want to resist the possibilities of such iden-
of the liberal order will obviously inform the nature
tities swallowing up individual opportunities not to
of area (3), in which we can isolate two prominent
conform to them, and certainly to oppose any iden-
features of liberal society.
tity that fundamentally compromises the commitments of liberal citizenship.
The first feature is civil society, the recognition that a significant part of public social life should be left
The above is not meant to be an exhaustive
free from direct state control, instead being the realm
description; it merely indicates some of liberalism's
in which people may freely associate themselves for
prominent general characteristics. But this is enough
their various ends. This includes not just (significant
to orient the rest of this introduction. For next, I first
parts of) economic life, but other institutional asso-
identify the main research interests in liberal think-
ciations, some perhaps devoted to providing services
ing that followed in Rawls's wake. We will then be in
(private health-care providers, for example), others
a position to see how the chapters of this volume
tied
commitments
might build upon that legacy and address the kinds of
(churches, charities, working people's associations,
concerns that Gray's critique would have us regard as
and so on).
alien to it. Finally, I suggest a further line of argu-
to
particular
projects
or
ment in support of the claim that there are still
The second feature consists of the cultural charThis
crucial issues with which contemporary liberal poli-
phrase is designed to capture two aspects of the
tical theory may substantively engage. Liberals, I
character-ideal that liberalism tends to hope, expli-
contend, have nothing to be complacent about.
acteristics
of
`liberal-democratic
individuality' .
citly or implicitly, will flourish among citizens.
18
There are good reasons to think hard about the
First
longer-term viability of the liberal order.
is the disposition to act towards others in ways that uphold the institutions and the ethos of liberal society: to be, for example, respectful, tolerant of
Issues for a
disagreement and alternative lifestyles, prepared to
Contemporary Liberal Research Agenda
cooperate with others to live under mutually acceptable terms of social and political accommodation.
In outlining the main themes in contemporary lib-
Second is the idea that the interests of the individual
eral political theory to date, I don't pretend to be
are (within terms laid down by justice) to be cele-
offering an exhaustive account of liberal scholarship
brated. The fact that `people's lives are their own to
in the years since Theory's publication. I hope instead
lead' is something that liberal politics is designed to
simply to offer a sketch to place in context the
facilitate, proactively and/or through non-interfer-
directions in which this book suggests liberal thought
ence. Many liberals (including Rawls, his `anti-per-
may run hereafter. Bearing in mind the caveat that
fectionism' notwithstanding) favour the idea that
not everything even in today's liberalism is reducible
individuals should freely develop their own, unique
to `Rawls and his critics', it is nevertheless easy for a
characteristics and capacities as the central project in
schematic account such as this to tease out these
the pursuit of the good life.
themes in terms of debates raised by and generated
This is not to say that liberalism's `cult of the
from Rawls's work. Two in particular can be traced in
individual' in principle favours egoism at the expense
their current form back to Theory. The first concerns
of other-directed social concerns. As contemporary
the content of justice: what is it that a just state
liberals have arguably become more sensitive to what
should seek to secure for its citizens and by what
they regard as the expanding range of permissible
principles does it distribute what G. A. Cohen has
differences in human forms of life, cultural pluralism
called justice's `currency'?
has come to play a more prominent role in their
tion of distributive social justice, Rawls's answers to
thinking. Hence, liberals now tend to attach great
these two questions were that `social primary goods'
significance to cultural (that is, collective) identities
were the raw material of justice, and that they should
as crucial social resources in the constitution of
be distributed within the institutions and relation-
8
19
In defending a concep-
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
ships of society's `basic structure' according to his `two principles of justice'.
have already observed how Rawls propagated the
20
image of liberalism as committed to a politics of
Perhaps the most politically resonant attack on his
impartiality or neutralism. For him, liberal politics
theory came from Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State and
was fundamentally about justice alone. Justice em-
Utopia.
Capturing the ethos of the New Right
bodied principles of `right', to be justified largely
(which
in
the
upon the basis that they were acceptable by all to
1970s and 1980s electorally eclipsed the kind of
whom they applied. These were distinguishable from
politics many believed Rawls to be defending), No-
`conceptions of the good', the various forms of life-
zick attacked the very concept of distributive justice
style from which individuals should be allowed to
and defended a rights-based, purely procedural ac-
choose and which were not therefore the proper
count of the just state that largely served to protect
objects of political favouritism.
numerous
western
states
during
individual property holdings from redistributive po21
licies.
Much interest was generated over Rawls's revival
At the same time, there was also renewed
of contractarianism as a method of derivation and
interest in the work of F. A. Hayek, who provided a
justification. His use of the `original position' and its
far more intellectually rigorous defence of procedural
assumptions about individual rationality and moral
against distributive social justice.
22
Together, these
motivation generated an extensive literature, seeking
authors contributed much to the revival of what
to test the plausibility of the general idea that
many thought was harking back to a `classical liberal'
political principles could be derived from idealised
political theory (as we have already noted, people on
bargaining between equally free, rational indivi-
both sides of the debate felt sufficiently embarrassed
duals.
by this family connection to parcel off this revanchist
came known as the `communitarian' critique of
classical liberalism under the heading of `libertarian-
liberalism developed in reaction against this whole
ism').
tendency, epitomised by Michael Sandel's attack on
It is a measure of where many academics' sympa-
24
From the early 1980s, however, what be-
Theory in his Liberalism and the Limits of Justice .
25
thies tended to lie that there was more extensive and
Communitarians argued that contractarianism fun-
innovative intellectual work done on the other side
damentally
of the political spectrum. This embraced rather than
agency given its tendency to use `abstractive' meth-
jettisoned the notion of distributive social justice,
odologies, attempting to generate moral and political
and sought to contest Rawls's specific characterisa-
principles from hypothetical conceptions of `rational
tion of it. Indeed, it was precisely because of the fact
moral agents' drawn in abstraction from any parti-
that political ideas to the centre and left of the
cular identities, commitments and social contexts.
political spectrum were in electoral retreat that many
By ignoring the crucial fact that individuals were
thinkers became particularly concerned to bolster
essentially social creatures, with their identities and
their philosophical credibility. Here, then, the de-
moralities being the products of particular cultures,
bate was posed around how best to pattern the
such theories were predestined to fail to generate
distribution of whatever it was that justice demanded
conceptually and substantively adequate moralities.
should be equalised. Amartya Sen's seminal 1979
Hence, as exemplified by Michael Walzer's Spheres of
Tanner Lecture `Equality of What?' set the tone for
Justice, communitarians argued for what amounted to
the debate, and helped to generate a plethora of
a hermeneutic political theory, deriving its moral
rivals for Rawls's claim that social primary goods
principles from an interpretive analysis of concrete
were the proper focus for egalitarian policy.
23
misunderstood
the
nature
of
moral
social understandings. Acknowledging the diversity
The second issue raised by Theory concerned the
of societies and social meanings, this approach con-
justification of political principles: how are they to
sequently leant towards (even if it often wished to
be derived and what reasons could be given for
resist a total capitulation to) a normative as well as
accepting them? Committed to the idea that political
an epistemological relativism.
26
principles should respect all citizens as equals and be
The debate between liberals and communitarians
at least the potential object of their agreement, we
also broke off into separable questions about the
9
MARK EVANS
content and justification of political morality.
27
Part
manner that, on the one hand, doesn't rest upon
of the communitarian argument over political mor-
dubious claims about actual universal consensus in
ality's
cham-
liberal societies on liberal principles yet, on the other
pioned by Rawls, denying that the `right' can be
hand, still holds out as plausible the possibility of
conceptually separated from the `good'. One sub-
genuine agreement. Particularly in so far as many
stantive consequence of this was to give politics
(though emphatically not all) liberals have accepted
responsibility for promoting rather than avoiding
the need for a Rawlsian `communitarian turn', this
the `good' and, in some versions, communitarism
debate has partially substituted for the more abstract
was happy to bring into political thinking a direct
notions of rational calculation favoured in the earlier
concern with, for example, cultivating virtues of
contractarian debate.
content
character.
28
attacked
the
impartialism
30
Although many communitarians did
One of the possible limitations of the `commu-
not reject liberal morality in toto, they tended to
nitarian' school is that, ironically enough, some of its
criticise the narrowness of what they perceived to be
exponents have tended to use abstractly unspecific
liberalism's overly individualistic moral stance, con-
conceptions of `community' which are, in fact, im-
tending that it is ill-equipped to accommodate the
plicitly homogenising. They suppress full recognition
importance of group identities and collective goods
of diversity and conflict over values and practices,
to political morality.
overly simplifying the project of hermeneutically
Much liberal writing in recent times has thus been
obtaining a singular political morality for a commu-
devoted to showing that liberalism is not as blind to
nity. Many liberals have therefore paid close atten-
such concerns as the communitarians believe. The
tion to theorising this diversity and the relevant
complaints that it is insufficiently responsive to the
sense of `community' for the politics of a pluralistic
demands of community have led, for example, to an
society. Often, they now raise their concerns within
increasing interest in what is often called `civic
the terms set by `multiculturalism' and `the politics of
liberalism'. This frequently draws upon republican
difference.' Feminist thinkers have been at the fore-
traditions of thought to postulate interdependence
front of the project to expose and jettison from
between liberal individuality and `good citizenship',
political theory concepts that they argue to be
which rests upon the willingness and ability of
`difference-blind' to the extent that they utterly fail
citizens to participate in and uphold certain shared
to spot their own partiality. (Iris Marion Young's
practices in liberal-democratic society.
29
Justice and the Politics of Difference is representative of
And, as his
31
contribution to this volume shows, Will Kymlicka
this trend.
has been at the forefront of the attempt to establish
regard tend to argue that the whole Enlightenment
the coherence and desirability of `group-based' con-
heritage, which liberalism is held to exemplify, un-
cerns in liberal politics.
successfully masks its own particularity (western and/
) Many of liberalism's critics in this
Liberals have also been prompted to respond to
or masculine and/or bourgeois) in a cloak of cosmo-
the communitarian assault on their favoured justifi-
politan universalism. They want to displace from
catory strategies. Rawls himself has led liberalism's
political thinking any abstractly conceptualised mor-
response; in his Political Liberalism he effectively
al concerns with `humanity' (those which treat
localises his political theory in that he now believes
objects of moral concern only as `equal rational
that political justifications for liberalism need to be
moral agents', for example) and any other concepts
drawn from the shared ideas in the public political
which in fact represent a very particular, partial way
culture of a constitutional democracy (a strategy
of seeing the moral and political world.
sometimes called `liberal communitarianism', pro-
In reaction, we find a greater engagement by
posing the dissolution of the antithesis). His recent
liberals with other cultures, seeking to understand
work has given much prominence to the theme of
and appreciate their differences in a quest to con-
`public reason' as the source of justifications for
ceptualise what might be necessary to establish a
liberal principles. Strenuous efforts are now made
political order that can justly accommodate `differ-
to explicate its notion of `reasonable agreement' in a
ence'. As the chapters by Will Kymlicka, Andrea
10
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
Baumeister, Jonathan Seglow and Kate Soper show,
essential diversity. It contends that the Anglo-Amer-
for example, this has resulted in liberal arguments
ican philosophical liberalism, whose pre-eminence
which are much more sympathetically responsive to
in contemporary liberalism has already been identi-
the kinds of concerns that critics may rightly have
fied, has not displaced the myriad other forms of
complained to have gone unrecognised in certain
liberal thought and discourse. Future research on
strands of liberalism but who wrongly charged lib-
liberalism would do well to bear this in mind.
eralism in general to be incapable of addressing. We
Next, Will Kymlicka demonstrates how liberalism
also find a rejection of the apparent normative
is capable of addressing many of the concerns raised
localisation of some communitarians and `difference
by those critics who contended that it was concep-
theorists' in the recent upsurge of interest in norma-
tually incapable of catering for group- rather than
tive international relations theory.
individual-centred demands. He develops a case for
Concluding this brief summary, we should note
`group rights' as the centrepiece of an account of
how the heightened sensitivity to diversity contri-
what he calls `ethnocultural justice'. The following
butes to a further problematisation of liberalism's
four chapters analyse issues of the nature of liberal
justificatory project. Where, not so long ago, con-
community and citizenship, and the particular un-
tractarianism and `morals by rational and reasonable
derstanding of `justice', that emerges from his dis-
agreement' seemed to be predominant themes, the
cussion. Andrew Vincent argues that liberalism's
debate has widened and fragmented as the `fact of
account of citizenship ± the centrepiece of many
pluralism' (itself variably interpreted) has suggested
liberals' arguments against the communitarian cri-
to some that only a Hobbesian politics of modus
tique ± sits extremely uneasily astride two contra-
vivendi is possible and, to others (the postmoder-
dictory
nists), that the whole philosophical project of liberal
which underpins liberalism's moral principles and
justification is redundant. Here again, there is a
a highly particularist nationalism which actually
tendency to question liberalism's supposedly Enlight-
grounds the criteria for citizenship in liberal states.
enment-bound conceptions of morality and moral
By explaining the nature and implications of these
justification.
currents, he puts this issue firmly on liberalism's
currents:
a
universalist
cosmopolitanism
research agenda as requiring urgent attention. Mar-
From this overview, the following seem to emerge
garet Canovan's chapter throws light on this pro-
as contemporary liberalism's main preoccupations:
blem from a different angle. She identifies two 1. the content of `justice';
ostensibly very different liberalisms: the `Crusaders'
2. the justification of liberal political principles;
(those liberals who prioritise a universalist human
3. the conception of `citizenship' and its relation-
rights agenda) and the `Sceptics' (much more con-
ship to individual freedom, civic virtue and the
tent with the conduct of a limited politics inside
requirements of civil order;
their own national boundaries). She argues that,
4. the conception of a liberal political commu-
their highly distinctive commitments notwithstand-
nity as applicable to a pluralistic, multicultural
ing, both rely tacitly but crucially upon notions of
society;
nationhood. The suspicion that they share of `na-
5. the defence of liberal (`Enlightenment') poli-
tionality' in politics may therefore be misplaced;
tical concepts and concerns in the wake of the
again, it is shown that there is an intimate yet
challenge posed by pluralism and `difference'.
contentious
relationship
between
liberalism
and
`the nation', the nature of which requires much closer analysis than has been hitherto given.
We are now in a position to summarise the con-
Andrea Baumeister then presents a comprehen-
tributions to this volume, seeing how they pick up,
sive discussion of various feminist critiques that have
advance and supplement these themes. As already indicated, Michael Freeden's opening
condemned liberal conceptions of citizenship for
chapter takes us through numerous academic char-
their apparent blindness to the political significance
acterisations of liberalism's nature to confirm its
of difference. She argues, however, that Kantian
11
MARK EVANS
liberalism may not fall foul of this deficiency and
which, for liberals in particular, is compounded at
that, hence, feminist politics may not need to aban-
the heart by controversy over how to understand `the
don paradigmatic liberal ideas. Jonathan Seglow's
fact of pluralism' in the first place. His suggestion is
chapter provides an account of one of the newer
that the project of liberal justification may best be
additions to liberalism's reflections upon justice,
advanced by the argument Judith Shklar puts for-
which is implicit in Will Kymlicka's notion of
ward for an apparently modest `liberalism of fear'. In
`ethnocultural' justice: the idea that `recognition'
`Pragmatist Liberalism and the Evasion of Politics', I
of one's identity as well as `redistribution' of resources
evaluate Richard Rorty's rather more laid-back and
is part of what justice requires.
sanguine approach to the project, which is prepared
Having raised the question of `justice', the follow-
to dispense with philosophical argument in support
ing two chapters take us back to its distributive
of liberal principles altogether. I argue that the
aspect. Their analyses are crucially informed by
`Rortyean view' can and should be elaborated more
Rawls's `difference principle', but they draw notice-
fully than Rorty himself musters, to grasp just what
ably divergent conclusions over its import. Rex
consequences his notion of `contingency' might have
Martin agrees that it has been absolutely pivotal
for liberal theory and politics. Bruce Haddock con-
in liberalism's debates about justice. He offers a
tends, however, that the Enlightenment-inspired
rigorous account of how it is intended to work
aspiration of achieving a universal morality justified
and then seeks to demonstrate that it is critically
by reason, challenged in the previous two chapters,
indeterminate in specifying particular institutional
can be kept alive. He proposes that a neo-Kantian
and policy recommendations. To the extent that it
practical reason can come into play whenever people
still takes the difference principle as one of its
are faced with moral dilemmas. It is upon this basis
benchmarks, this conclusion indicates that liberal
that we may be able to construct a case at least for
discourse about justice may have reached a theore-
some of liberalism's fundamental principles. The
tical logjam through which it is urgent for liberals to
perturbing uncertainties of `contingency' in morals
think. Rodney Peffer, on the other hand, is happy to
± principles ungrounded by reason ± can be avoided.
argue that Rawlsian theory ± with only a few mod-
Pluralism, of course, poses practical problems of
ifications ± can lead us in a definite political direc-
political organisation as well as theoretical ones of
tion.
philosophical justification. For
However,
he
believes
it
is
one
that
can
Richard
Bellamy,
justifiably be called Marxist and he sets out to defend
liberal theory and practice as it stands is not well
the application of this label to his Rawlsian theory.
suited to resolve them. He forwards a robust case for a
He would stridently disagree with Gray's claim,
more participatory form of governance that draws
noted earlier, that reflections upon market socialism
upon the venerable republican political tradition. In
and the like are exercises in irrelevance and fantasy.
light of this proposed revival of `republicanism',
But the striking point is the argument that this is
David Rasmussen comments upon the recent debate
where liberal justice may well lead us: reason enough
between John Rawls and Ju È rgen Habermas, which
for radicals not to be dismissive of it.
can be seen as an exploration of the possible accommodation by Rawlsian liberalism of republican po-
The following three chapters turn us to the debate
litical insights.
about the justification of liberal values. It is not
As described earlier, many feminists have shared
implausible to suggest that the increased interest in, and perplexity of, the justification debate reflects
with
a wider cultural anxiety about the status of moral and
spired' critique of the Enlightenment and hence
political principles, in a world of such plural values
the forms of moral and political thinking informed
and moral outlooks that scepticism seems to be the
by it, of which liberalism is a paradigm. To combat
irresistible conclusion even when one would so
some of the more drastic conclusions drawn from
desperately wish otherwise. Peter Lassman's chapter
this, Kate Soper argues against a wholesale rejection
confirms that pluralism constitutes the distinctive
of the Enlightenment tradition. She shows that it
problem of modern politics. But the problem is one
was a good deal more sensitive to feminist causes
12
postmodernists
a
pluralistic,
`difference-in-
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
than many contemporary postmodernists in particu-
lighting some issues fairly new to liberal research but
lar allow. To persist with an `anti-Enlightenment'
which may become established preoccupations. In
theme in championing such causes today may there-
another example of new seams for liberals to mine,
fore be to do violence to what is valuably progressive
Richard Sakwa shows how strikingly varied liberal
in that tradition. This is not to deny that cultural
discourse has become in post-communist states, as
diversity, among other considerations, should rightly
the doctrine attempts to define and orient itself in a
prompt liberals into a re-evaluation of some of their
social and political context deeply unfamiliar to
concepts. Diana Tietjens Meyers's chapter is pre-
those which provide the backdrop of much liberal
sented as an example of how this critical self-analysis
thought to date. Brian Baxter takes up the charge
may proceed. She provides a powerful, innovative
that liberalism is ill-equipped to face the challenges
argument for the need to rethink many standard
of ecologism and environmental politics. He con-
conceptions of autonomy. She deals with exactly the
tends that `ecocentric' theories are indeed likely to
kind of question upon which so many liberals stum-
be inimical to liberal concepts and politics, but
ble: how to conceptualise `autonomy' in light of the
argues that these are not in fact desirable as they
fact that women in some cultures appear autono-
stand. He then presents a `personcentric' argument
mously to affirm the practice of female circumcision,
which shows how liberalism may be reconciled to
which western liberals usually cannot imagine being
ecologist concerns. Finally, in the last chapter I
supported at all by anybody in a genuinely autono-
address a question that many liberals once had no
mous way. Drawing upon material rarely utilised in
qualms in tackling but which the `Rawlsian ten-
liberal debate, this chapter indicates some of the new
dency' has tried to push out of liberalism's concerns:
directions to be taken and sources to be pursued in
the articulation of personal ideals of how it is good to
liberal research.
live, with a view to sanctioning their promotion by a
In the post-Cold War world, many traditional
liberal state under certain conditions. I note that this
understandings of politics are becoming redundant
`perfectionist' liberalism has been rehabilitated in
as power increasingly slips from nation-states to
Rawls's wake, but it remains peculiarly reluctant
regional and global sites. As an example of how
to articulate any particular ideal of the good, an
political theory must innovate conceptually to keep
abstinence which I claim is neither necessary nor
pace, Robert Bideleux substantially adapts the liberal
always desirable for liberals. Accordingly, I begin to
conception of civil association to characterise the
sketch some of what I call `candidate conceptions of
institutional form being taken by the European
the good' in an effort to reconnect liberal politics and
Union, still very much in the process of evolution.
the classical practice of ethical reflection on the
Provocatively, he argues that in the context of
nature of the good life.
European politics we must recognise that liberalism
Amid all this it is difficult, I think, to spot too
is decisively shedding its connections with democ-
much `irrelevance' and `triviality' in the subjects
racy. Howard Williams's chapter switches our atten-
covered, as we might be led to expect given Gray's
tion to the question of the global order and the
critique. They engage with real issues concerning the
normative goal of securing principles by which states
defence and promotion of the kind of politics that,
may live together in peace. He assesses the utility of
after all, most people in the West ± and, increasingly,
Kant's thinking in this regard as a classical and
beyond ± wish to support. The argument that this
quintessentially liberal starting-point from which
Companion wishes to promote is that political theory
contemporary reflections may proceed. A flavour
is a vital component of the political project to defend
of the latter is provided in Peter Sutch's contribu-
or contest the liberal order. This claim is based upon
tion, which goes on to articulate the concept of
the idea that the problems faced by the liberal order
`developmental communitarianism' as the justifica-
are sufficiently complex and perplexing to demand
tory strategy that a liberal `law of peoples' (to borrow
serious, rigorous philosophical reflection. That is
Rawls's phrase) may usefully adopt.
what contemporary liberal political theory attempts to deliver.
The Companion ends with three chapters high-
13
MARK EVANS
To end this introductory chapter and to supple-
proceed too far without indulging in the speculative
ment the research agenda already mapped out above,
realm of crystal ball-gazing. (It would also obviously
I propose a further demonstration of the potential for
be perverse to persevere with contemporary liberal-
relevant, serious-minded analysis in liberal political
ism, as many chapters in this book argue we might, if
theory. This is designed to test its capacity for critical
one believed it to be so pitifully doomed.) But
self-reflection and to put on its own menu the most
forcing liberals to analyse such negative arguments
fundamental challenges that liberal practice could
could strengthen their thinking and convictions,
actually face. It will outline yet more avenues for
perturbing to the liberal imagination though they
liberal theory to take, dispelling even more vigor-
may be. Here, at the beginning of the twenty-first century,
ously the illusion that it is complacently trivial.
it is particularly apposite to ponder the permanence of the liberal achievement. Confidence in liberal-
Prospects for Liberalism
ism's ability to adapt in the face of modernity's
and the Liberal Order
problems, or at least to be able to cope with them
Many of the contributions to this volume suggest or
better than any possible alternative, doubtless re-
imply that, though the challenges it faces may indeed
flects the widespread belief (epitomised in Fukuya-
be perplexing, it is conceivable that liberalism has
ma's work) that it represents the pinnacle of a
the resources to address them not only theoretically
successful struggle by humanity to work out the most
but also practically. That is to say, the challenges can
commodious form of political system. But I urge that
be understood from within a recognisably liberal
contemporary liberal theory should not begin with
conceptual framework and the institutions and prac-
this belief as an automatic presumption. Instead, it
tices of a liberal social and political order need not
should commit itself at most to a continuous testing
have to undergo a revolutionary transformation for
of such a proposition; it can never be taken for
them to be tackled adequately. On this view some
granted, for circumstances are too fluid to have blind
may argue that, though liberalism may not have all
faith in the `historical vindication' of liberalism.
the answers to every problem or even the best answer
So let us consider the argument that, though it
in certain instances, it informs what is, on balance,
may have beaten off many rivals to date, liberalism
the best standpoint from which to engage with
remains fundamentally flawed. There is no guaran-
politics in the modern world.
tee, it says, that liberalism's intellectual apparatus
It is hoped that this Companion will help readers to
will be able to help us cope with all of the practical
draw their own conclusions about the validity of this
problems that the liberal political order may face.
claim, ranging as it does across many of the issues by
And those problems could threaten to overwhelm
which liberalism should be judged. However, the test
liberal practice. Note that this scenario can be
or thought-experiment I wish to sketch hypothesises
imagined without believing that there is an alter-
deep internal tensions within the liberal `settlement',
native doctrine that, all things considered, will cope
which might plausibly threaten to destroy the very
any better with liberalism's predicament. For who
coherence of liberalism's commitments. My proposal
can say whether the victor in the `battle of the
is that there is no reason why liberals themselves
ideologies' will not still be torn apart as its panoply
cannot describe such scenarios, which are not ne-
of moral ideals and political prescriptions founder in
cessarily exercises in fantasy but which point to real
this deeply suboptimal social world of contradictions,
potentialities. If they can face up to such possibilities
complexities and antagonisms?
and think hard about how to address them, then it is
To substantiate this idea, we can reflect upon how
difficult to think of anything more serious for them to
a historical awareness should jolt us out of any
tackle. I hasten to note that I emphatically do not
sanguine
support the gloomily anti-Panglossian view that I
might now think we can forever harvest from liberal
shall construct to show how this test might be
society. A hundred years ago, the optimistic faith in
conducted, not least because no such exercise could
the direction of rational human development had yet
14
complacency
concerning
the
fruits
we
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
to be darkened by the slaughter of the Somme, the
be blithely ignorant of the problems these political
bureaucratically managed genocide of Stalin's purges
currents
and the Nazis' Final Solution, and the spectre of
democracies (as manifest, for example, in the per-
global nuclear destruction. No such underestimation
sistence of racism and other forms of violent `hate
of the human capacity for evil is now likely to be
politics'). But let us for the sake of argument deny
accepted without grave reservation. Moreover, glo-
that they constitute ± or are likely in the foreseeable
bal capitalism is producing such profound institu-
future to constitute ± genuine systemic threats to
tional and cultural changes at an ever-accelerating
the latter.
rate that it is increasingly difficult to think of many
strength to destroy liberal democracy as did fascism
of the norms, artefacts and `certainties' of our civi-
in many European states did during the inter-war
lisation as settled. Change is too dizzying, too dis-
years.
cause
33
within
actually-existing
liberal
They alone do not appear to have the
orientating for us to feel `at home' for long in any one
A more relevant and hence perplexing theoretical
manifestation of modernity; as Marx and Engels so
challenge is this. Even if we grant the argument that
presciently put it, `all that is solid melts into air.'
32
liberalism does not now seem to have seriously
Given all this, with what reason, exactly, could we
credible, morally and practically superior rivals, it
hold firm to the beliefs that, whatever happens,
is possible that liberal commitments and practices
liberalism's ideals will be capable of remaining our
may be torn apart from within. There are two ways in
moral inspiration? What follows is a selection of
which this might happen:
perhaps numerous ways in which `anti-liberal' pos1. At the level of ideals, some of its moral goals
sibilities might be postulated. Where once the liberals' `bogeymen' were primar-
may be realisable only at the expense of some
ily fascists and communists of various hues (and they
of its others. All of the goals may be thought to
may still threaten them in places, of course), it is
be valuable and we might have hoped that the
nowadays more often the figures of the authoritarian
victor in the battle of the ideologies might
nationalist and the religious fundamentalist who are
have been able to preserve them together. But
seen as either the main threats to established liberal
our destiny is not so rosy; we cannot but
orders or as the actually-existing obstacles to the
endure significant moral loss because of the
spread of liberalism in, say, post-communist societies.
practical uncombinability of liberalism's aims.
The basic themes of their anti-liberalism, however,
Whatever doctrine emerges from the choices
have largely remained the same as their predecessors
we will ultimately have to make may not deserve the name of `liberal'.
in liberalism's gallery of rogues: the denial of basic liberties as the prime political concern, the prepa-
2. At the level of practice, the kind of society that
redness to subordinate individual interests to (illu-
liberal doctrine supports ends up inadvertently
sory)
discrimination
subverting at least some of its aspirations.
between groups of people in a shameless abandon-
There is no way to fit the latter with the
ment of equal respect, and a willingness to prefer
socio-economic order that the doctrine sup-
coercion over persuasion in pursuit of such repressive
ports. Again, in crude terms, something will
political ends.
have to give way and what results may not
`common
goods',
an
overt
warrant the liberal label at all.
It is obviously right to confront the challenges that movements such as nationalism and religious fundamentalism pose to the liberal order. A recog-
To illustrate just a few of the ways we might render
nition that liberalism may not be appropriate in all
vivid this conclusion in our thought-experiment, we
four corners of the world should not necessarily
can return to our division of liberal concerns into (1)
mean that we should automatically forego the mak-
a moral theory; (2) an account of the ideal political
ing of the case for liberalism in at least some parts of
regime; (3) an account of the ideal social culture. In
the globe where anti-liberal nationalisms and fun-
so doing, we can see how on this account some of the
damentalisms currently hold sway. Nor should we
faults of which, it was argued above, liberalism's
15
MARK EVANS
principles are incorrectly convicted may yet emerge
moralities of individual freedom and social justice
as unintended consequences of its practice.
may not be sustainable in the kind of world in which we find ourselves. Perhaps liberalism's notions of `individuality' and
Challenges to the Morality of Liberalism
`individual projects' can be preserved in the face of
Although I have already indicated that liberalism is
justice so conceived only if we in the rich nations
by no means incompatible with the robust concep-
undergo a radical reconceptualisation of our pre-
tions of community favoured by `communitarians'
ferred or ideal individual modes of good living. If
(loosely defined), its central moral focus remains the
liberals become more prepared to lead lives that are
individual and some notion of the interests of in-
much less exorbitant in their use of resources, they
dividuality. And the more pluralistic one's concep-
may be more capable of reconciling themselves to
tion of human nature, the more individualistic (that
justice. I raise this point in the final chapter to
is, less communitarian) that notion may turn out to
indicate a possible twist in my argument about
be. It could be argued (as I will suggest below) that
perfectionist liberalism's theorisation of the good
modern capitalist society further `individualises' its
life. There I link it to the second concern that
subjects by undermining the culture and indeed the
can be raised under the present heading: what needs
physical
communities
to be done to preserve the global natural environ-
while creating no new `community' in their places.
ment. It may be the case that Brian Baxter's inge-
Liberalism, it might then be contended, tends to
nious melding of liberal and ecological concerns will
reinforce such developments by favouring the inter-
ultimately not demand enough of individuals (in
ests of individual freedom over human collectives.
fundamentally changing the way they live and the
Here, I shall mention just two moral issues that could
resources they use to do so) to do what is necessary to
place this doctrine ± and its reinforcement of `in-
stave off the destruction of the precarious ecological
dividualisation' ± under intolerable strain.
balance between humanity and the earth. The con-
constitution
of
traditional
The first is the ongoing scandal of international
sequences of this catastrophe (even from the most
distributive injustice: the billions who live in the
`personcentric' point of view) would be much more
most desperate, degrading poverty, a tragedy that
difficult to ignore in the way that many in the rich
seems to render them all the more prone to the other
world are presently capable of physically and psy-
terrible catastrophes brought by war, weather and
chologically isolating themselves from the demands
disease. We need not believe that redistribution of
of distributive justice.
35
wealth from the rich nations alone would be enough to solve these problems altogether to recognise that
Challenges to the Political Principles
they could be substantially alleviated if such redis-
and Institutions of Liberal Democracy
tribution were to take place. But to the extent that liberalism seeks not to swallow up all individual
It is as close as one gets to received wisdom in
projects and concerns is the extent to which it
political
may not be sufficiently responsive.
34
science
that
the
`formal'
constitutional
It may be that,
paraphernalia of modern liberal democracy do not
to meet even fairly minimal demands of justice (such
house the only, or even the main, sites of power.
as satisfying basic needs), the richer nations would
These are located instead in state and party bureau-
have to transfer such enormous amounts of resources
cracies, organised interest groups and other socio-
that many of the kinds of lifestyle that liberalism is
economic elites. Socialists in particular have always
valued for accommodating would not be sustainable.
attacked liberalism for a blindness with regard to the
Maybe justice would then require far more than the
power that capitalists wield over the liberal-demo-
voluntary acts of charity, necessitating a coercive
cratic state. In contemporary politics, this charge has
limitation upon people's freedoms to live such com-
taken on a heightened perspicacity with the phe-
paratively expensive lives. Here, then, is the possi-
nomenon of `globalisation'. Alongside the develop-
bility that liberalism's accommodation between the
ment of regional and genuinely global institutions,
16
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
there is a growing realisation that the nation-state's
democracy). Democratic institutions thus begin to
increasing dependence upon the support of capital is
wither. Further, as social unrest intensifies (through
undermining its very existence as a meaningful
industrial militancy and/or extra-systemic political
political entity in so far as that capital is acquiring
protest and/or increases in crime rates due to the
an increasingly multinational character.
widening gaps between rich and poor, and the
Now we could agree that a liberalism which is
destruction of meaningful economic and social op-
wholly ignorant of these facts, stubbornly clinging to
portunities for the latter), the state becomes more
the obvious fiction that real power rests solely with
authoritarian, undermining civil liberties as it at-
the `superficial' structures of the nation-state, should
tempts to impose civil order (or at least contain the
not be entertained at all seriously. But the mistake
effects of disorder).
37
which liberalism's critics may continue to make is to
In light of this, my suggestion is that in western
believe that liberals necessarily peddle such naõÈvety.
states it is likely that the biggest threat to liberal
In the same way that the defence of liberal politics
democracy does not come from liberal theory's tradi-
need not be based upon the kind of philosophical
tional nemeses of `fascism' or `religious fundament-
beliefs that the communitarians rightly argue to be
alism'.
discreditable, so it need imply no ignorance of the
authoritarian form of economic libertarianism, as
realities of power and the limitations imposed upon
the competitive pressures of globalising capitalism
its favoured institutions. Max Weber's `competitive
increasingly subordinate politics to the satisfaction of
elitism' offers one, albeit noticeably unenthusiastic,
its own exacting needs. (It might be suggested that
defence of liberal-democratic politics while conced-
certain South-East Asian capitalist states provide the
ing many such limitations.
36
It
lies
instead
in
the
drift
towards
an
none-too-enticing models for this.) As David Held
However, it is always possible that these limita-
points out, the New Right's rise from the mid-1970s
tions will profoundly undercut the possibility of
was a direct response to precisely the kinds of
liberal politics. The economic and institutional con-
intractable pressures from which liberalism in its
straints of the contemporary capitalist world may
Keynesian welfare-state form suffered.
place too much strain upon it to keep its aspirations
as observed above, an earlier form of classical liberal-
alive. Take, for example, its commitments to uphold
ism as its inspiration, cutting away at least part of its
an extensive range of civil liberties and to promote
later connections to democracy and certainly its
social justice for its citizens. We could envisage
commitments to social justice. The paradox of this,
something like a `legitimation crisis' crippling its
of course, was that it sanctioned a politics that also
ability to meet them. Sketching this thesis briefly:
threatened the commitments even to its more mini-
the capitalist state is ever more beholden to the need
mal conceptions of equal freedom, as the inequities
to attract rather than repel multinational capital
of power in capitalism were exacerbated by economic
which can roam the world in search of the most
`deregulation'
profitable sites to invest. Forced into ever more
Á -vis the basic civil liberties of instrengthened vis-a
exclusively `business-friendly' policies and progres-
dividuals. It is, then, hard to suggest that even
sively sapped by capitalism's economic cycles of
classical liberalism was being fully realised in this
`boom and bust', the state finds itself increasingly
situation.
unable to fund its other commitments adequately,
The
idea
and
of
the
power
`legitimation
of
38
It retrieved,
the
crisis'
state
prompts
was
the
primarily those most directly demanded by citizens in
thought that this drift to authoritarian economic
the form of public services and welfare provisions.
libertarianism may not be entirely led `from the
The citizens thus become disenchanted and embit-
top', either. If citizens become frustrated at the
tered. As part of its increasingly frantic attempts to
perceived failings of the liberal-democratic system
control expenditure by reducing the number of in-
and, in particular, disturbed by its inability to control
stitutions with the authority to spend at their own
rising crime rates and the other objects of the `moral
discretion, the state is forced to centralise political
panics' that periodically seize such societies, they
control (even where it promises the extension of
themselves may be tempted to support altogether
17
MARK EVANS
more illiberal politics in the name of law and order.
what is thought to be the traditional liberal idea of it
This fear, whose origins can be traced as far back as
as a (political) capacity to influence others. They
Plato's critique of democracy in The Republic, finds its
contend that power is the effect of all manner of
most disturbing expression in the spectre of the
social practices and relationships, `disciplining' or
Weimar Republic's fall and the willingness among
even constituting subjects in society. As critics of
many German citizens to accept (at least in its early
capitalist society, they attack the forms of subjectiv-
stages) the Nazi dictatorship.
ity produced by the social practices that liberalism
The ultimate crisis of progressive politics on this
upholds.
40
view, though, may lie in an inability plausibly to
Others, perhaps not always as prepared to give off
recommend any of the radical alternatives to capit-
the scent of cultural elitism that attaches to some
alism that might be necessary to secure and build
versions of the previous argument, nevertheless urge
upon the values that the present critique suggests
that there is something about the way in which social
liberal democracy might hope in vain to uphold in its
space and time is nowadays constructed that turns
midst. Socialism, for example, may just not be
individuals into withdrawn, privatised selves. Such
thought to be practicable. If some form of capitalism
people are increasingly unwilling and unable to reap
is regarded as unavoidable, and liberalism remains
those fruits of genuinely communal relationships
the progressive's best `match' for it, then progressi-
that once were so central to ideas of the good life.
vism has nowhere else to turn ± and yet even a
Fukuyama
shrunken neoclassical liberalism may not be able to
Nietzschean `last man' as the ominously possible
withstand the intensification of capitalist practices.
paradigmatic character of modern liberal capitalist
The relationship of liberal-democratic politics to the
society, content with mediocrity now that funda-
exigencies of capitalism will, I suspect, become one
mental social struggles for improvement are over.
of liberal theory's most urgent concerns in the years
But this development need not be due simply to a
ahead.
lack of character and lazy contentment with every-
himself
resurrects
the
image
of
the
41
day life in capitalist consumer society. Such are the pressures of this life that the hedonistic retreat into
Challenges to the Culture
the private realm becomes a perfectly understandable
of Liberal-Democratic Individuality
and, perhaps for some, existentially necessary reac-
The economic realities of capitalism impact as much
tion.
upon culture as they do upon political institutions.
As republican thinkers remind us, the privatisa-
The third category suggests, then, that liberalism's
tion of the self may have direct political conse-
support for capitalism ± which, as indicated in the
quences too. As Tocqueville influentially noted,
previous section may be far from unalloyed enthu-
democracy depends upon a culture of participation.
siasm even though there is no more preferable
If individuals are not prepared in significant numbers
alternative ± undermines its cultural ideals.
to engage in public political life at least to some
For example, there are those who think that
degree, then the practices of liberal democracy will
capitalist commodification tends to turn the project
wither, leaving a vacuum to be filled, if only by
of `individual conceptions of the good' into shallow
default, by non-democratic institutions. In modern
simulacra of flourishing individuality, reducing it to
times, the phenomenon of power slipping to une-
mere hedonism and the shaping of one's identity
lected bureaucratic `quangos' may well be testimony
purely with respect to the fashions that are just
to this (as well as to the anti-democratic tendencies
insidious ways of manipulating the tastes of indivi-
cited in the previous section).
duals as consumers.
39
42
If it is not almost a new kind of
More widely, such privatisation contributes to an
slavery, these critics would certainly regard it as a
increasing unwillingness to embrace social obliga-
travesty of liberalism's ideal of free human develop-
tions, narrowing if not individualising altogether our
ment. Many who argue in these general terms sup-
sense of to whom our responsibilities lie.
port a conception of power that ranges well beyond
tioned above in indicating how liberalism has re-
18
43
As men-
ISSUES AND TRENDS IN CONTEMPORARY LIBERALISM
sponded to the communitarian critique, there has
case. In so doing, I think this can orient liberal
been a renewed interest in ideas of `civic liberalism'
thinking towards a maximisation of its own depth,
which are designed to address such fears. But there
strength and self-confidence.
may be forces at work that would entirely undermine
In setting an agenda for contemporary liberal
the stability of any such ideal in practice. Within
research, this Companion is a contribution towards
civil society, therefore, an egoistic mentality is fos-
that orientation. Even those liberals who already feel
tered that causes the decline of many social institu-
confident enough to accept a Fukuyama-style verdict
tions and practices which formerly encouraged co-
on liberalism's moral superiority should not, then,
operation and mutual support. Given the obvious
regard this book as a final, definitive pronouncement
unwillingness of many major liberal-democratic po-
of that victory. Liberal political theory does not
litical parties to advocate an increased acceptance by
come to an end even if one thinks that `history'
the state of this social burden, this trend means that
in Fukuyama's sense has. There are always vexing
more and more social obligations go unfulfilled.
issues to be addressed, some of which may move to the fore and supplant some of those emphasised here. And we must constantly remain alert to the possi-
Conclusion
bility that liberalism does not constitute the end of our ideational and institutional development.
It is not perverse to end this introduction to a further twenty-one chapters on liberalism with such dire
Conversely, however, awareness of liberalism's
anti-liberal possibilities. As I have insisted, painting
problems ± both actual and potential ± need not
such dystopian pictures does not commit one to
commit one to the belief that continued support for
affirming them. But by taking full measure of the
liberalism necessarily represents some failure of ima-
problems it may face, I believe that liberalism can
gination by today's political thinkers. If any of the
become more emboldened to analyse its own con-
anti-liberal possibilities described above do threaten
dition honestly, and articulate, defend and refine
us, it may take great effort to sustain liberal ideas and
itself as robustly as possible. As much as anything,
practices ± and this is no small, meek undertaking.
this exposes the limitations of Gray's critique: unless
For liberalism's morality and politics has inspired and
we are blithely indifferent to the fate of liberal
sustained much hope through even the darkest
civilisation it is surely strange to think of these
periods of recent human history. Critical but con-
questions as somehow divorced from our real-life
structive engagement with its problems is vital to the
political concerns. Taking them as seriously as they
preservation of its legacy ± and that is the project this
are stated in the hypotheses above may be overly
book aims to keep alive.
melodramatic ± but it is up to liberalism to argue that
Notes
theoretical complexity and public comprehension in
1. Note that many wish to distinguish `political theory'
contemporary political theory.
and `political philosophy' and would doubtless stress
9. Gray (1995a), pp. 3±4, 11±13.
that it is the fate specifically of the latter which such claims announce. For my purposes in this discussion,
10. See Ethics, 102 (April 1992).
nothing significant hangs upon the distinction, which
11. Gray (1995a), p. 4.
is far from universally recognised.
12. See Fukuyama (1989), (1992). 13. For a comprehensive discussion of how to characterise
2. P. Laslett, `Introduction', in Laslett (ed.) (1956), pp.
liberalism illuminatingly and substantively while at
vii, xiii. Cf. Berlin (1969), pp. 118±19.
the same time doing justice to its diversity, see Freeden
3. Gray (1995a), p. 1.
(1996), parts I and II.
4. Ibid., p. 16. 5. Ibid., p. 3.
14. By `general themes' and `tendencies' I refer to features
6. Ibid., p. 2.
which occur in some form to a greater or lesser extent
7. Gray (1995a), p. 17.
in most versions of liberalism; I intend nothing more
8. See Bertram (1997) for a discussion of the problems of
specific than that.
19
MARK EVANS
15. Rorty (1998), p. 170.
29. For an example, see Dagger (1997).
16. See Freeden (1996), chapter 7.
30. See Rawls (1996) and, for commentary on this type of liberalism, Evans (1999).
17. For examples of this type of liberalism, see ibid.,
31. Young (1990).
chapter 5 and pp. 456±80.
32. Quoted in Kamenka (ed.) (1983), p. 207.
18. A `character-ideal' specifies certain dispositions, aptitudes and tastes which constitute what is deemed to
33. Having warned against complacency, I don't wish this
be the ideal form that a person's character could take.
point to be taken as ignorance of the activities of neo-
Anti-perfectionist liberals may be thought to eschew
Nazi movements and suchlike in contemporary wes-
such notions, but in fact they tend not to: Rawls, for
tern democracies. Certainly, liberals should steadfastly
example, has no qualms over talking about the ideal
resist them in theory and practice, for this is what will
characteristics of citizens. However, he attempts to
help to resist any future slide into fascist barbarism. I
avoid idealising forms of character outside of the
maintain that the latter is indeed unlikely, but I am
political realm. Perfectionist liberals, as is evident
primarily concerned here to divert attention to other possible anti-liberal trends.
in Chapter 22 of this book, do not accept this
34. Nagel phrases this problem in terms of balancing the
restriction. 19. See Cohen (1989).
impartial demands of morality with the partial con-
20. See Rawls (1972), especially part one.
cerns of particular relationships and projects; see Nagel (1991).
21. Nozick (1974).
35. See Singer (1993) for a cautiously optimistic assess-
22. See Hayek (1993).
ment about our ability to change our lives to meet
23. A. Sen, `Equality of What?', in Sen (1982), pp. 353±
such moral and ecological challenges.
73. Representative pivotal works in this debate in-
36. See Held (1996), pp. 157±77 for a discussion of
clude Dworkin (1981a) and (1981b), Cohen (1989)
Weber's political views.
and Arneson (1989). 24. Other
representative
contractarian
works
37. For a summary of `legitimation crisis' theory, see ibid.,
include
pp. 240±53.
Scanlon (1986) and, for a more libertarian position,
38. Ibid., pp. 253±63.
Gauthier (1986).
39. Classic statements of this kulturkritik, which blames
25. Sandel (1982). 26. See Walzer (1986) and, for a comprehensive discus-
the processes that liberal society has historically en-
sion of the liberal-communitarian debate, Mulhall and
couraged, are found in Marcuse (1964) and `The
Swift (1996).
Culture Industry: Enlightenment as Mass Deception', in Adorno and Horkheimer (1986), pp. 120±67.
27. As Charles Taylor has argued, `the liberal-communitarian debate' was often presented in a manner which
40. See Hindess (1996) for a discussion of the concept of
conflated the distinguishable questions of `ontology'
`power' in liberal political theory. I suggest in Chapter
(such as those on the nature of the self and its
22 that a Foucauldian rethinking of `power' may benefit the concept of a perfectionist liberalism.
relationship to society), which were centrally relevant to the justification debate, and `advocacy', which
41. Fukuyama (1992), part V.
specifically contested the content of political morality.
42. For illuminating discussion of Tocqueville in this regard, see Macedo (1989).
See his `Cross-Purposes: The Liberal-Communitarian
43. See Singer (1993), chapter 1 and passim, for discussion
Debate', in Taylor (1995), pp. 181±203.
of this claim.
28. See, for example, MacIntyre (1985).
20
2
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT: DEVELOPMENT OR TRANSFORMATION? Michael Freeden
In this chapter I seek to investigate how liberalism
liberalism in time-honoured conventional manner
was portrayed throughout the twentieth century in
on a unidimensional sequence, we need to draw
dedicated liberal literature, that is works primarily
conclusions from the variable presentation of histor-
devoted to an exposition of the basic tenets of
ical liberal narratives, or from their juxtaposition
liberalism. On the surface many, though not all,
with non-narrative justifications of liberalism. The
of these works present themselves as `second-order'
history of liberalism in the last century, and indeed in
overviews of liberal theory and ideology. Sometimes,
previous centuries, is not merely the reflection of its
as with the Rawlsian family of arguments, they
development, or evolution, or change, or perchance
intend both to offer a novel interpretation of liberal
regression. It is not a single story to be told. We now
principles and, in parallel, to reflect given cultural
recognise that all current theories are located in time
understandings unconsciously and unintentionally.
as well as in space. But when we say that, we are not
On the whole, though, writers about liberalism have
engaging in the simplistic assertion that `context
tended to elucidate a tradition rather than depart
counts'. Contexts are multi-temporal and multi-spa-
from it. But this raises a fundamental methodological
tial even with respect to one family of beliefs such as
problem: when does a `secondary' text become a
liberalism, and they generate both deliberate and
`primary' one? The response to that is: when we
unintentional meta-assumptions quite irrespective of
interpret it as itself an act of interpretation; and
whether liberalism itself contains views on univers-
when we acknowledge that the role of the political
alism or relativism or, as we have now come to
theorist incorporates not only prescription and its
appreciate, multiculturalism. Moreover, individual
investigation but also interpretation and its investi-
liberals, and conventional social norms concerning
gation. The analysts, chroniclers and popularisers of
what liberalism is, exercise choice over what con-
liberalism
understanding
stitutes a context and over which contexts to select
when we query its status as a transcendent moral
among the many contexts ± existing or yet to be
position and explore it instead as a diverse and
discovered or invented ± in which liberalism may be
flexible set of readings concerning the epistemology
located. A context, like a historical narrative, is not a
of the political.
reflection of events out there. It is an act of private or
become
pivotal
to
our
Whatever else liberalism is, it is a cultural artefact,
public imagination superimposed upon a set of per-
consciously intended to be adopted by large social
ceived, if fragmented, facts. This chapter will at-
groups. But rather than explore the Ideengeschichte of
tempt to identify more precisely not why and when
21
MICHAEL FREEDEN
liberalism changes in terms of objective contexts, but
intellectual history. Behind it stands a broader agen-
what it is that has changed in the imaginative
da, whose task it is to provide an analysis of a family
presentation of liberalism, and how different em-
of political theories and ideologies. To do so we
phases on various aspects of liberalism reflect and
ought to come to terms with liberalism as a complex
transform the political understandings of some of its
and elusive tradition of thinking about politics, and
more salient, or representative, purveyors.
we may gain from locating the analysis on offer here squarely among the activities in which political
Far too often, recent scholars of liberalism have
theorists engage.
confidently and stipulatively approached it as if that theory or ideology represents a clear and unitary moral position encompassing knowable and objec-
Liberal Movement: Evolution and Energy
tive, or at least reasonable, standards of justice and human rights: a homogeneous model which could
The twentieth century has witnessed three main
then be incisively contrasted with alternative `mono-
modes of writing about liberalism: as a development
lithic' theories such as communitarianism. This is
of political thought over time; as a political mani-
not the issue under discussion here; nor is it the most
festo against extremism, authoritarianism or conser-
challenging and rewarding question when examining
vative complacency; and as a philosophical view of
liberalism. Rather, liberalism is that semantic field in
the rational and moral relationship between the
which the political understandings of people who
individually unique and the socially common. In
regard themselves as liberals, or whom others regard
intricate and concrete argumentation, these modes
as liberals, may be investigated. It is a plastic, chan-
often overlap. When in 1911 L. T. Hobhouse wrote
ging thing, shaped and reshaped by the thought-
his famous volume entitled Liberalism, he was writing
practices of individuals and groups, and though it
a tract for the times, forged out of the successful
needs to have a roughly identifiable pattern for us to
battles fought by the new liberals, but it was a tract
call it consistently by the same name, `liberalism', it
with a moral purpose: that of consolidating the
also presents myriad variations which reflect the
reforms liberalism had undertaken from within. He
questions posed, and positions adopted, by various
did so by emphasising above all one aspect of liberal-
liberals.
ism, offering it as an evolutionary body of thought
In the space available, some samples will be
which not only advocated progress as a social ideal,
provided of the conceptualisations of liberalism dur-
but was itself controlled by that same evolutionary
ing this century, through examining a number of
law. This was not a particular liberal view of history,
books on liberalism which were written as central
such as the much-mooted Whig interpretation of
textbooks, introductions, surveys, statements, or cri-
history, but rather a particular historical view of
tiques. The assumption adhered to is that these
liberalism, which regarded it as a set of beliefs itself,
books mirrored, moulded and disseminated broad
crucially, subject to historical processes. In other
understandings of what liberalism was, as well as
words, one defining feature of liberalism, in sharp
carrying some unintentional baggage which has been
contrast to current philosophical liberalism, was that
left for us to unpack. Ultimately, in order for liberal-
its theorists held to a specific interpretation of time
ism to be comprehended we must observe it `at
as a central conceptual component of liberal ideol-
thought' by exploring the mind-sets of some of its
ogy. Time was not strictly sequential in its trajectory
typical agents. The result, one would hope, would be
of human and social improvement, nor totally open-
an enriched and rather more subtle view than can be
ended in accompanying human and social matura-
provided by attempting to construct a philosophi-
tion, but it nevertheless dictated that liberalism itself
cally `ideal' or `best-practice' liberal moral theory.
had to undergo steady transformation. In the past
Those philosophical approaches necessarily lose in
liberalism had experienced a process of growth which
breadth and political applicability what they gain in
was now reaching its apotheosis by aligning itself
internal cohesion and ethical persuasiveness. Nor is
with the development of a newly emerging social
this chapter about `mere' history, nor even `mere'
rationality, embodied in an integrated and organic
22
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT
7
society and regulated by a benevolent and empha-
the modern world'.
tically non-neutral agency ± the state.
`an effective historical force', is sustained by move-
Movement in the first sense, as
Like Mill, and many previous liberals, Hobhouse's
ment in this second animated, living sense. Liberal-
story about liberalism begins as a historical-anthro-
ism is the release of dynamic biological and spiritual
pological narrative. It is one of social harmony and
energy, a view reiterated by Guido de Ruggiero in his
community undermined by later authoritarian poli-
seminal The History of European Liberalism, when he
tical arrangements. Liberalism dawns as a `destruc-
identified liberalism as concerned with the free play
tive criticism', a project of release in order to enable
of individual forces which have `vital importance and
free, and natural, order and progress. Here are some
energising power'.
of the recognisable liberal core concepts of the
vigorous and liberalism is above all an instrument for
nineteenth and twentieth centuries. But there is a
freeing this flowing human essence. This is no mere
deeper and ulterior ontology of liberalism in opera-
`exercise concept' in Charles Taylor's phrase,
tion. Hobhouse endows the idea of release with a
the setting free of organic, non-static, life which will
specific complexion: `a movement of liberation, a
otherwise be suppressed. Unsurprisingly, well-being
clearance of obstructions . . . for the flow of free,
is for Hobhouse as important as liberty. Moreover,
1
8
The world is naturally active and
9
but
vital, spontaneous activity'. The idea of `movement'
the identification of processes as natural indicates
is subtly and only half-consciously recruited to un-
the typical ideological device of insulating funda-
derpin this specific understanding of liberalism. First,
mental ontological claims from the sphere of debate
liberalism is a movement, to be sure: it is an organised
and contention. In adhering to that thought-practice
body with, in J. A. Hobson's words, an `active
liberalism is no different from other ideological
2
mission' directed towards the attainment of political
families. Furthermore, although an understanding
objectives. Second, however, liberalism is a carrier of
of twentieth-century liberalism should not be deter-
truth, which moves for Hobhouse in `an expanding
mined merely through the yardstick of some of its
3
When in Chapter II Hobhouse lists
later manifestations, the contrast with Rawls here is
the types of liberty embraced by liberals, he con-
striking. For if liberalism is `all-penetrating', it pro-
ceives them as spatial, embracing parallel activities
vides both the common element enabling the ex-
such as civil, fiscal, economic and social, and located
pression of all human cooperative activity, a function
in arenas such as the personal, domestic, local,
allocated by Rawls to narrow political liberalism, and
circle of ideas'.
4
national and international. Similarly, Hobson could
the comprehensive liberalism which Rawls firmly
assert that `liberalism will come more definitely to
detaches from the political.
concern itself with the liberation and utilisation of the faculties and potencies of a nation and a muni-
Liberal Emotionalism
cipality, as well as with those of individuals and 5
voluntary groups of citizens.' The liberty at the core
Hobhouse unequivocally relates liberalism to human
of liberalism is hence conceptualised as undergoing
emotion on two levels. On the one he observes that
movement both through space and through time, and is aligned with the concept of spreading and
the philosophies that have driving force behind
contagious progress. Thus it contains seeds of uni-
them are those that arise . . . out of the practical
versalism, not in an analytical or intrinsic sense, but
demands of human feeling. The philosophies that
a historically and spatially contingent universalism,
remain ineffectual and academic are those that
called forth `by the special circumstances of Western
are formed by abstract reflection without relation
Europe'.
6
to the thirsty souls of human kind.
10
Third, as the initial quotation suggests, movement suggests vital activity. We arrive now at the semantic
Liberalism opens the door by means of the rational
kernel.
method `to the appeal of reason, of imagination, of
Hobhouse
instructs
us
that
`the
Liberal
11
movement . . . is coextensive with life'; `Liberalism
social feeling'.
is an all-penetrating element of the life-structure of
have emotions and imagination that demand respect
23
It is not only that human beings
MICHAEL FREEDEN
in social arrangements, but that expressivism and
relations between rulers and ruled; and is able
spontaneity are defining features of life, and hence of
to turn this experience to the ends of the eleva-
the liberalism that enables life. Liberalism contains
tion of human society.
17
core rational attributes, but is nonetheless irreducible to the contemplative faculty. Reason and emotion
The liberal spirit is possessed of a `lofty impartial-
coexist and support each other in a manner ruled out
ity'.
of court by most current manifestations of philoso-
refers to the liberal who `likes to preen himself on the
phical liberalism. Hence Hobhouse's support for
triumphs of human intelligence and virtue', and to
forms of nationalism, for
the liberal tradition as a `call to adventure: the
18
A mid-century American review of liberalism
adventure of growing up, becoming autonomous, inasmuch as the true social harmony rests on
living spontaneously' (and note, incidentally, the
feeling and makes use of all the natural ties of
constructive tension between development, freedom
kinship, of neighbourliness, of congruity of char-
and unreflectiveness).
acter and belief, and of language and mode of life,
mood, Laski identified a `flavour of romanticism' in
the best, healthiest and most vigorous political
its temper. It tended to be `zealous' for individual
unit is that to which men are by their own feelings
action, `subjective and anarchist, to be eager for the
strongly drawn.
12
19
In describing liberalism as a
change which comes from individual initiative, to be insistent that this initiative contains within itself 20
In addition, if `rational' may be contrasted with
some necessary seed of social good.'
`emotional', it may also be contrasted with `unre-
insistence ± these features of liberalism are necessa-
flective'. Hobhouse also drew attention to these
rily the attributes of an ideology whose reforming,
latter components of liberalism when he contended
even revolutionary, ardour is part and parcel of its
that `human progress, on whatever side we consider
appeal. For the over-critical Laski, the energising
it, is found to be in the main social progress, the work
power of liberalism had become exhausted.
of conscious or unconscious co-operation.'
13
Zeal, eagerness,
21
It may
Indeed,
be the case that the fervour of liberalism diminished
in his later work Hobhouse was to associate the
upon attaining many of its initial goals, though the
emergence of the ethical precepts of liberalism with
emotional aspects of its beliefs have never quite
fundamental psychological processes.
14
disappeared.
Similar views
on the evolution of liberalism were expressed by Laski, for whom it was `never direct and rarely conscious.'
Liberal Coherence and Liberal Diversity
15
From another perspective, most twentieth-century
Throughout the twentieth century there has been a
liberals adopt an emotive idiom when addressing
curious tension between the static and dynamic
liberalism. For Hobhouse, liberalism aims at `a spirit
facets of liberalism. This problematic of liberalism
of comradeship'; its vision of justice `kindles a pas-
may be redefined by asking whether it is a pliable
sion that may not flare up into moments of dramatic
structure or heavily rule-bound. The editors of The
scintillation, but burns with the enduring glow of the
Liberal Tradition, published in 1956, stated that `at
16
± hardly the predominant phraseology
first sight, the most striking thing about the Liberal
of current Anglo-American philosophy. De Ruggiero
tradition is its intellectual incoherence . . . This is
put this similarly:
the strongest argument in favour of treating Liberal-
central heat'
ism historically'. Considering liberalism as developLiberalism possesses that kind of tact or flair . . .
ing and changing allows such differences to fall into
which in its highest manifestations is true poli-
place.
tical sensitiveness, and serves to recognise every-
narrative alone, because invented narratives are
thing that is human ± human strength and human
contingent and selective. It is importantly the pro-
weakness, human reason and human passion,
duct either of the formulation of directive rules or
human interest and human morality ± in the
the discovery of unintended patterns (a discovery
24
22
Coherence, however, is not the product of a
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT
which itself may then be fashioned into a set of
liberal concepts of liberty, rationality, progress, in-
directive rules). If liberal history is not accidental or
dividuality, sociability, a common good, limited and
contingent, if liberalism is not a mathematical ag-
responsible power ± in other words, a theory that,
gregate of its historical parts, that is because history is
according to Hobhouse, undergirds every version of
understood as constituting the ineluctable design of
liberalism.
liberalism. To write about liberalism is for Hobhouse,
De Ruggiero's notion of history rested on similar
and no less so for de Ruggiero, always and necessarily
conceptions of liberal movement, but his Hegelian
to write about its history. They both conceptualise
historical scheme reshaped the liberal time-space
liberalism as the vehicle best encompassing the
relationship into a different pattern of coherence.
dynamic of individual and social life. Liberalism is
His comparative treatment of liberalism permitted
a process and it evokes an activity, the activity of
the postulation of multiple, interacting liberalisms,
being self-directively spontaneous, inventive and
but his reading of the logic of liberalism was not, as
imaginative. Process entails history; history is the
with Hobhouse, through its diffusion in ever-expand-
intellectual coherence of liberalism, rather than
ing circles but through convergence and conciliation
being superimposed to account for it. By contrast,
of opposite liberal currents. Liberalism has to be
the liberal projects of Rawls or Ronald Dworkin
understood `in the diversity of its national forms
prioritise rules as stasis, equilibrium and consensus
and the unity of its historical organism'.
over rules of change. The idea of a liberal constitu-
progress which is liberalism's lifeblood is not Hob-
tion, to which they are wedded, is precisely such a
house's non-teleological `onward course'. For Hob-
device, creating inviolable space, such as a Bill of
house, a release of energy is not necessarily self-
Rights or the two principles of justice, removed from
realisation. For de Ruggiero, `a more comprehensive
the ravages of social time. From a slightly different
Liberalism would recognise the dialectical ground of
perspective, the liberalism of foundational rules pri-
the antithesis and would see resistance and move-
vileges mechanics, whereas the liberalism of creative
ment, conservation and progress, justified and vali-
expressivism privileges organics, both as growth and
dated in a higher synthesis which is political life in its
as human interrelationship. Hobhouse summed up
concreteness'.
his position as follows:
thus a single liberalism which can be retrospectively
25
24
The
The end-result for de Ruggiero is
accounted for as the diachronic emergence of a The heart of liberalism is the understanding that
civilising strain in modern societies, the `irresistible
progress is not a matter of mechanical contri-
operation of civil society'.
vance, but of the liberation of living spiritual
ness crowds out rival arguments and secures victory
energy. Good mechanism is that which provides
in a multi-ideational world of really-existing compet-
the channels wherein such energy can flow un-
ing viewpoints.
26
Its political persuasive-
impeded, unobstructed by its own exuberance of output, vivifying the social structure, expanding and ennobling the life of mind.
The study of the historical forms of European
23
Liberalism has shown us, through all the differences of the various national minds, a process of
Current philosophical liberals tend to concentrate
mutual assimilation, gradually building up a Eur-
on the channels while professing to have no view on
opean Liberal consciousness pervading its parti-
the consequences of providing them, other than the
cular
tautological attainment of justice which has already
differences.
manifestations
without
destroying
their
27
been furnished by the very construction of the mechanical channels themselves. Hobhouse's agen-
Without such reconciliation, the liberal enterprise
da consisted rather in attaching liberalism to an idea-
would be undermined by the damaging potential of
environment formed through concepts such as re-
its disparate currents.
lease, movement, energy and vitality. That is his
That argument was taken even further by Bene-
`thin' theory of the good, which informs the core
detto Croce. In a chapter revealingly titled `Liberal-
25
MICHAEL FREEDEN
ism as a Concept of Life' he, too, combined devel-
As Hobson noted, reviewing de Ruggiero's book, `in
opmentalism with a view of liberalism as coinciding
each country the spirit of liberalism was largely
`with a complete idea of the world and of reality,'
formed by the practical tasks which the needs and
beginning in the world but going `beyond the formal
interests of the dominant classes incited them to
theory of politics'. The very tolerance built into
undertake'.
32
liberalism located it as the framework doctrine with-
Both Hobhouse and de Ruggiero subscribed to a
in which a dialectic competition among ideas could
concrete spatial universalism which is a function of
be resolved. It was characterised above all by this
time (as of course does Marxism) rather than a
immanent
the
transcendental and spaceless universalism which is
authoritarian fiat of otherworldly, externally im-
a function of atemporal reason. But de Ruggiero
posed, transcendental beliefs. History as struggle
removed internal pluralism and unstructured open-
was endemic to liberalism, and struggle encompassed
endedness from liberalism as it emerged as a tele-
process
which
impulse and spontaneity.
28
removed
it
from
Nevertheless Croce was
ological world-view in a very real, and irreversible,
drawn into joining to that profoundly secular doc-
sense. Hobhouse, to the contrary, voiced an increas-
trine an extra-rational, quasi-religious understanding
ing postwar despair concerning the future of liberal-
of liberty, attached to human `vocations' and `mis-
ism when he identified `arrest, retrogression or decay'
sions'. He believed that `the liberal mind regards the
as part of the historic course of change and con-
withdrawing of liberty and the times of reaction as
cluded: `Hence if progress means the gradual realisa-
illnesses and critical stages of growth, as incidents
tion of an ethical ideal no continuous progress is
and steps in the eternal life of liberty.' As with Hegel,
revealed by the course of history.'
timelessness engulfed and superseded time in the last
that pessimism concerning the evolution of the hu-
resort; moreover, this afforded a standpoint from
man mind in de Ruggiero's 1927 deluded prognosis
which history manifested pathologies as well as
that `one may conclude that the omens are favour-
normalities. The transcendental status of liberty
able towards the capacity of the German people to
returned to do the work of faith and underlying
win for itself that liberal education in politics which
essential meaning, justifying the course taken by a
the old regime denied it'.
non-transcendental history. That such liberal his-
giero was epistemologically unable to criticise liberal
tories attained impartiality, as Croce claimed, is
practices and beliefs in their current form because of
hardly borne out by the language in which that
liberalism's inherent evolutionary capacity of self-
claim is expressed.
29
34
33
There is none of
Consequently, de Rug-
development and improvement. These distinctions
A similar viewpoint, with different conclusions, is
aside, the liberalism of Hobhouse and de Ruggiero is
evident in Louis Hartz's modern classic The Liberal
primarily about individual and social expression and
Tradition In America. Liberalism has multiple facets,
development, and only secondarily about pluralism
crucially situated not above politics but in it: `we
and difference, especially in view of its allegiance to
know the European liberal, as it were, by the enemies
the nation-state. By contrast, current liberal plural-
30
Whereas European liberals experi-
ism, in some of its multicultural forms, applies a pre-
enced social diversity and conflict, the American
formed, ahistorical, singular liberal morality to con-
variant
invisibility
crete societies comprised of many components. It
through a cultural and ideological uniformity, `on
regards structural variety as a service concept for
the basis of a submerged and absolute liberal faith'.
autonomy, rather than regarding temporal develop-
Hartz identified a central ideological feature at work
ment as a service concept for individuality, socia-
in the manner American liberalism decontested its
bility or welfare. What de Ruggiero noted about
basic premises, one involving `silent omissions as
liberty and liberties ought to be said about the
he has made.'
acquired
non-contentious
31
Hence while American
tension between liberalism conceived of as universal
liberalism pre-empted political and ideational com-
philosophy and as situated ideology. The one is `an
petition, European liberalism had to fight its ground
abstraction, a concept intended to express the es-
within a culturally and historically disputed space.
sence of human personality, exalted above all his-
well as explicit inclusions'.
26
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT
torical and empirical contingency', the other a com-
dignity of human personality, and the construction
plex of features `acquired one by one as circum-
of impenetrable boundaries which the state may not
stances
pervade. Liberal principles are, or ought to be, un-
dictate'.
Each
on
its
own
is,
totally dispossessed of the Liberal spirit.
tellingly,
35
touched by history, even by the experimental reason which many liberals see fit to encourage in people. Instead, they are to be secured to transcendental
The Renewed Search for Certainty
standards and eternal truths, beyond the contami-
The experience of totalitarianism in the 1930s and
nating reach of untrustworthy human judgement.
1940s dramatically changed some interpretative lib-
Hallowell occupies a strange position in relation
eral paradigms. One of the most striking reformula-
to the liberal epistemology of this century, both
tions of liberalism to emerge from the Second World
regressive and progressive. The notion of progress,
War was John Hallowell's The Decline of Liberalism as
so central to liberal values,
an Ideology. His analysis constitutes a watershed in
attached to a theory of evolution which, when
twentieth-century
had in his view become
self-conceptualisation
applied to liberalism itself, undermined the absolute
mainly through its disentangling and counterposing
moral value of the individual. It did so by legitimat-
of the historical and the ahistorical mode of liberal-
ing humanly directed change, especially through the
ism. If for Hobhouse and de Ruggiero liberalism
German construct of the Rechtsstaat, which estab-
embodies a vital growth impetus, Hallowell reversed
lished positive law ± a law that was made and not
this historical tendency to identify a move from
found ± as the guarantor of equality. One of Hallo-
something live and vigorous to something decadent
well's inputs into the liberal debate was to re-em-
and degenerate. Growth may also imply regression,
phasise not its polysemic but its static character.
especially once de Ruggiero's Hegelian dialectic of
Another was to distinguish between liberalism as
progress is abandoned. `As a political ideology born
philosophy and as ideology, a move of importance
of a particular historical period in a specific socio-
associated with the mid-century decline in prestige of
logical environment [liberalism] is subject, like all
the concept of ideology. However, the decline of
such systems of ideas, to development, decline, and
ideology is not articulated in terms of the postwar
death.'
36
liberal
38
debate
Significantly, and in contradistinction to
over
undesirable
dogmatism
versus
com-
Hobhouse's anxieties concerning external impedi-
mended pragmatism, but in terms of undesirable
ments to liberalism, Hallowell attributed the death
pragmatism versus incontrovertible truth. Hallowell
of liberal ideology to liberals themselves, for a man-
approvingly quoted C. E. M. Joad, for whom prag-
made belief system is subject to human fallibility.
matism ministered
That fallibility has revealed itself in the forsaking of a parallel but morally and intellectually superior lib-
to human complacency by assuring human beings
eralism, `integral' liberalism, couched in the language
that right and wrong, beauty and ugliness, reality
of absolutes which would have prevented the in-
and unreality, are not external facts, features of
tellectual perversion of liberalism, particularly by
the universe to which human beings must in the
Nazism. Hallowell's version of liberalism embodied
long run subject themselves, but are the products
the typical disillusionment of postwar scholars with
of human consciousness and, therefore, amenable
the fickle impermanence of legal systems, unless
to human desires.
39
anchored in dictates of objective reason. The rediscovery of normative foundationalism became promi-
Hallowell proposed the following ideational com-
nent in the American legal tradition, in its renewed
pound as liberalism's epistemological base: first, a
anti-positivist appeal to natural law and its conse-
humanist doctrine that relinquishes anthropocentr-
quent revival of the notion of universal human rights
ism and rejects intuitive judgement; second, a theory
during the 1940s and 1950s.
37
Liberal ontology
of human freedom that dismisses the view of indi-
therefore sought refuge in invoking new variants
viduals as autonomously capable of exercising their
of traditional certitudes: the absolute value and
subjectively free wills; third, a conception of ration-
27
MICHAEL FREEDEN
ality that subjugates individuals to the `dictates of
factual thought experiments which translate the
reason' and the external criteria of justice as obliga-
requirements of coherence and procedure, rather
tion to transcendental law, accessed through an
than growth and energy, into structural fundamen-
inner conscience. For a liberal, Hallowell imposed
tals of liberalism. Is this, intriguingly, a parallel
a particularly stringent limitation on value pluralism,
tendency to what Orton describes as `the queer
for liberalism relies on `a common knowledge, or
double
recognition, of values transcending individuals.'
40
strain
in
nineteenth
century
liberalism.
The rationalistic, system-making tradition in lais-
Nevertheless all this is a `theory of political order
sez-faire theory never found common ground with
based upon individualism', and it is identified as a
the personalistic and humanitarian impulse' ± an
`comprehensive Weltanschauung'.
41
Contrast this
inspirational, empathetic and energy-liberating hu43
with the Rawlsian view of rationality emerging
manism?
volitionally from individuals and expressed in a
cidity of purpose belong essentially to Liberalism',
reasonable, overlapping and public consensus over
rather than `organic purpose' and `free enthusiasm'.
Hobson denied that `coldness and pla44
principles of justice, and moreover a view that now
Is it also the case that what some feminists term
relegates individualism to a feature of comprehensive
the colder philosophical liberalism is a product of the
liberalism, a liberalism which is no longer specifically
Cold War that never got round to thawing? Not for
endorsed as necessary to a just social order. And
nothing has the end of the Cold War witnessed a
contrast this with the Hobhousian faith in the
reheating of liberalism under the impact of nation-
evolution of social understandings of valued prac-
alism and the accompanying revalorisation of the
tices which release the potential and sustain the
emotional resonances that have always existed with-
well-being of a community as well as those of its
in liberal discourse: the language of bonds, alle-
members.
giance, sympathy. What nonetheless sustains the current philosophical variant is the predominant and overwhelmingly shared image of the American
Ontological Minimalism
constitution as mediating between the presumption
and the Supra-Political
of the reasonableness emanating from human beings
Works such as Hallowell's which began as manifestos
and the requirement of permanent, supra-political
against totalitarianism have been transformed into a
standards. This avoids the language of transcendent-
richer and deeper philosophical position. The heri-
alism while attaining some of its ends. It is hence
tage and motivation are plainly visible in late twen-
unsurprising to find Rawls describing the Supreme
tieth-century
Court as `the exemplar of public reason'.
liberal
theorising,
but
so
are
the
45
Is that
epistemological and conceptual modifications. One
another way of asserting, as Hartz did, that `the
of the residues of this mode of thinking has been to
absence of ``opposing principles,'' the fact that be-
reduce liberalism once again to a form of ontological
neath its political heroics the nation was of the
minimalism, captured in the loose use of the inde-
``same mind'' on the liberal formula, settled in ad-
terminate word `thin'. But one of the modifications it
vance the philosophic question'?
has undergone is the rediscovery of a Kantian-in-
the nation are we not referring to the academic
spired autonomy, an autonomy unavailable or de-
community, sustained by its Justices with their pre-
centred in early and mid-century liberal thought.
sumption of expressing the vox populi? Indeed, Hartz
The two have combined in the revival of the private-
had given the role of the Supreme Court, and the
public dichotomy as a moral statement about the
liberalism it sustained, a totally different and more
inherent but socially indifferent good sense of in-
persuasive gloss: `the Supreme Court had always
dividuals, detached from the impact of sustaining
been the Hebraic expositor of the American general
groups, the latter now perceived as more dangerous
will, building on the irrational acceptance of Locke
than formative.
42
46
Only instead of
the Talmudic rationality involved in his application
In addition liberalism has been
47
absorbed into the dominant Anglo-American phi-
to specific cases.'
losophical practice of model-building and counter-
cognisant of the emotive aspect of concrete liberal-
28
Moreover, Hartz was deeply
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT
isms. The American version, he argued, possessed
reasonable yet incompatible comprehensive doc-
`the ideologic power of the national irrational liberal-
trines is the normal result of the exercise of human
ism' which, in the case of the New Deal, `was
reason within the framework of the free institutions
responsible for its whole pragmatic orientation, for
of a constitutional regime' ± a philosophical anthro-
its whole aversion to systematic social thought.'
48
pology diametrically opposed to Hobhouse's. Rawls's
In view of the above, Croce's reaction to critics of
overriding aim is for a political liberalism which
liberalism, who labelled it as `formalistic', `empty',
provides not only justice but also unity in what
`sceptical' and `antagonistic', is edifying. Rather than
would otherwise be a fissiparous, even Hobbesian,
see these terms as referring to foundational categories
society. The difficulty with the core liberal concept
whose generality enables the integration of all rea-
of non-necessitarian development was that it had to
sonable ways of life, Croce saw them as embodying
allow for a choice which could include error. The
the essence of non-dogmatism in the spirit of modern
risky model of development, even riskier when `ir-
philosophy. The liberal conception thus denied `first
reconcilable conflict' is assumed to be socially la-
place to laws, casuistry and charts of duties and
tent,
virtues, and places the moral conscience at its cen-
of justice, stability and autonomy, which would
tre.' This was `like modern aesthetics, which refuses
eliminate
models, categories and rules, and places at its centre
too, had attempted to eliminate choice on a grander,
the genius that is good taste, both sensitive and very
supra-individual scale by positing a Hegelian neces-
strict.' That approach was formalistic only in the
sitarianism, but that variety had been extinguished as
sense that it shied away from imposing philosophical
a fashionable archetype under onslaughts such as
formulae and principles. The end result was strongly
Karl Popper's.
50
was replaced with a more advantageous model unpredictable
choice.
51
De
Ruggiero,
emotive and parti pris: `the liberal conception is not
Nor was Hallowell's transcendentalism acceptable
meant for the timid, the indolent and the pacifist,
to 1960s and 1970s Anglo-American philosophy.
but wishes to interpret the aspirations and the works
Hence the foundational assumptions of Rawls's sys-
of courageous and patient, of belligerent and gener-
tem were couched in anthropocentric terms of em-
ous spirits.' No wonder that Croce could refer to
pirically attainable reasonableness, even though the
Hobhouse's opus as `a beautiful English eulogy and
outcome of this process was to all effects and pur-
apology for liberalism' ± language more apposite for a
poses equally invariable. Like the contract model,
work of art than for the mechanics of a system of
Rawls's theory simulated open-ended liberal choice
rules.
49
without, of course, offering it, through assuming both a pre-discursive rationality (the veil of ignorance) and a convergent reasonableness (the overlapping
The Rawlsian Project: A Paradigmatic Shift
consensus). Rawls's political liberalism was presented
Looking back at liberalism from our vantage point,
as a western paradigm, but one whose rightness would
the unity of the Rawlsian project is conspicuous. In
gain it universal recognition, moving from historicity
the early years of the twentieth century, as in much
to ahistoricity. Its universal appeal would not be
of the nineteenth, the growth model central to
forged out of competition over legitimacy with other
liberal conceptions of human nature was applied
ideological arrangements, as most liberals have mea-
to liberalism itself. The development of liberalism
sured their successes, earning their spurs on the
was tantamount to the development of civilisation.
battlefield of ideas, but as a non-pluralist procedural
After the Second World War that very capacity for
and moral necessity.
change, with its newly highlighted contingency, lost
Put differently, this liberalism employed a second-
its attractiveness, and was increasingly replaced with
order argument not over substantive goods, but over
an
standards.
justifiable rules. Justification depended not on the
Rawls himself commenced his argument in Political
nature of the political benefits available, but ± and
Liberalism with that problematic: `political liberalism
here lay its novelty ± on the shared acceptance of
assumes that, for political purposes, a plurality of
those rules by all the members of the polity.
appeal
to
independent
immutable
29
52
Locke's
MICHAEL FREEDEN
liberalism by contrast, had sought a limited general
Modern: `liberal education is the necessary endeavour
acceptability only as a prior arrangement to estab-
to found an aristocracy within democratic mass
lishing relations of mutual and substantive trust,
society.' The point, however, as Mill recognised,
anchored in the norms of natural rights. Late twen-
was that liberalism was shaped by a few and then
tieth-century liberalism has, however, been charac-
disseminated to the many. Some of its substantive
terised as being that system of ideas which requires
values might precede the full evolution of demo-
and attains general acceptance, even prior to the
cratic consent and might not be entirely sustained by
political implementation of those ideas. The only
that evolution. As is the case with all ideologies,
ideas which comply with this scheme are those
liberals wish to protect the values they most cherish.
concerning the public rules of moral engagement
The problem with liberalism is that some of those
and interaction. In earlier versions of liberalism,
values (such as self-determination or participation)
acceptance had to be won through the substantive
are intrinsically dependent on the exercise of choice
benefits that would accrue from the liberal way of life
by all, and may be catered to instantly, and some
in the struggle with other political options.
(such as individuality or progress) are dependent on
Moreover,
the
Rawlsian
procedure
was
con-
the exercise of good choices by as many as possible,
structed to create boundaries and hence moral spaces
but by less than all if unavoidable, and are time-
in which individuals were responsibly reflective.
sensitive.
Intentionally or otherwise, that accomplished three
Third, it disposed of change in the arena of
ends. First, it restored liberalism's emphasis on the
political liberalism. Gone was the experimental at-
inviolability of individual space, rather than on the
titude of Hobhouse and his colleague J. A. Hobson
controlled permeability of space which organicist,
towards some of the decontestations of liberal va-
communitarian liberals had encouraged. This was
lues.
closely linked to a thinning of the sociability com-
tiveness. `We may', he writes, `reaffirm our more
ponent of liberalism and a resurrection of individu-
particular judgements and decide instead to modify
alism as an attribute of separate personal existence.
53
55
Rawls assumed coherence rather than tenta-
the proposed conception of justice until judgements at all levels of generality are at last in line on due
Second, it focused on equality ± a concept to
56
which evolutionary liberal traditions could not fully
reflection.'
subscribe because of the unpredictable dynamics of
to iron out kinks in the overlapping public reason-
human relationships. The a priori rule-following of
ableness of political liberalism, not experimentation
Rawlsian liberalism had to assume not only temporal
that can provide different and contrasting views of
stasis but relational stasis: equality as the participa-
liberalism's values. Compare this with another mid-
tion of each and every member in decision-making
century appraisal of liberalism: `as a form of social
and hence in justifiable and responsible action.
thought Liberalism has been empirical, scientific,
Strikingly, this limited notion of equality was a
mundane, and more or less skeptical-minded.'
non-voluntarist view of participation. Participation
The sense of paradigmatic shift is palpable.
and sharing in responsibility had become the be-all
If there is experimentation, it is in order
57
Gone also were Hobhouse's and Hobson's anxi58
and end-all of liberalism, rather than adjacent con-
eties concerning an unknown liberal future.
cepts that could be put into practice by those who
lsian liberalism is curiously unperturbed, not only
wished to participate.
54
Raw-
As an ethical exercise, this
because logic, procedure and coherence are by defi-
liberalism offers no space to opt out or to refrain from
nition emotionally neutered (though their outcomes
opting in. Obtaining the considered and uncon-
are hardly value-neutral) but because moral conflicts
strained consent of all ± a mechanical view of politics
are politically soluble. Certainty allows one to dis-
± becomes the heart of the liberal process rather than
pense with some of the affective language in which
the attainment of a package of values. The extreme
liberalism has usually indulged. How can that non-
view of this position, outside current exemplars of
transcendental certainty be sustained? Because the
the liberal family, was expressed by non-liberals such
precarious nature of progress based on human rea-
as Leo Strauss in his book Liberalism Ancient and
son
30
59
is eliminated at a stroke by removing liberalism
TWENTIETH-CENTURY LIBERAL THOUGHT
from the impact of a temporal perspective.
± as a comprehensive doctrine, and hence bereft of
One pre-eminent consequence of this paradig-
the reasonable pluralism that a narrower political
matic change has been the drastic contraction of
liberalism requires.
the natural habitat of liberalism, the political arena.
60
63
Other theorists, as we have seen, have distin-
The bulk of the liberal conceptual configura-
guished between good and bad forms of liberalism,
tion now spills over into a politics-free area, as
but no one prior to Rawls proposed to regard liberal-
61
and individuals are
ism as a two-tier edifice. What has this done to
literally abandoned to their own fates in the names
liberalism? It has injected into it a spurious neutrality
of autonomy and self-determination. The result is a
and dissociated it from gathering the fruits of the
political liberalism that claims to be compatible with
political process, hitherto a central aim of the liberal
an indeterminate variety of reasonable comprehen-
agenda. It has upset the delicate balance between
sive social and political beliefs, as long as they accept
essence and contingency so typical of liberal argu-
the procedural `minimum-kit' of democratic consti-
ment. And it has emaciated liberalism by relegating
tutionalism. This has significant repercussions for
its comprehensive values to the status of equal
liberalism. For in universalising political liberalism,
contenders with other socio-political doctrines, thus
the specific appeal of other doctrines is undercut
undercutting the specific ideological appeal of lib-
either by excluding them as unreasonable or by
eralism which its other proponents have been so
reducing them ± through revealing them as congru-
eager to advance. That is another way of arguing that
ous with political liberalism. Political liberalism thus
what are now termed the liberal virtues are excluded
becomes a particularly potent weapon that can out-
from the static preconditions concerning justice and
bid the attractions of other doctrines/ideologies by
pluralism. Maybe we should take Rawls at his word
subsuming aspects of them into itself. The shrinkage
and stop calling his project liberal in a doctrinal
of the political is thus both very modest and highly
sense altogether?
Dworkin has reminded us,
ambitious. To judge this enterprise as successful
Of course, liberalism continues to exist as a devel-
depends on whether one thinks such formulae work,
opmental and humanist theory. While universities
or on whether one can demonstrate that such phi-
have over the past two decades sent liberalism on a
losophical liberals are unaware, or in denial, of their
confusing trajectory, the ideology called liberalism is
own surpluses of meaning. As I have argued else-
still a comprehensive and culture-bound set of con-
where, Rawls's political liberalism contains almost all
ceptual decontestations that operates, like any ideol-
of the crucial attributions of meaning that typify the
ogy, to compete over the legitimate meanings of
family of liberal concepts. His political liberalism has
political language. Philosophical notions of liberal-
gone so far down the road towards a comprehensive
ism have not replaced historical, concrete, polysemic
liberalism that there is no turning back, no fork in
and hence ideological understandings. The former
the road that could lead on to a comprehensive
too may be seen in that latter light and simply serve
socialism, conservatism or reasonable religious doc-
as further evidence of the contingent and manifold
trine.
62
guises liberalism adopts within the broad constraints
It is therefore edifying to find Rawls's most
of shared family resemblances.
recent utterances redefining his theory of justice as fairness ± hitherto understood to be a general theory
Notes
1. Hobhouse (1964), p. 28.
8. De Ruggiero (1927), p. 359.
2. Hobson (1909), p. 91.
9. See C. Taylor, `What's Wrong With Negative Liberty?', in Ryan (ed.) (1979), pp. 175±93.
3. Hobhouse (1964), p. 60. 4. Ibid., pp. 16±29.
10. Hobhouse (1964), p. 30.
5. Hobson (1909), p. 95.
11. Ibid., p. 66.
6. Hobhouse (1964), p. 15.
12. Ibid., p. 72.
7. Ibid., pp. 28.
13. Ibid., p. 71. See also Freeden (1998).
31
MICHAEL FREEDEN
14. See Freeden (1986), pp. 234±7.
46. Hartz (1955), p. 141.
15. Laski (1936), p. 11.
47. Ibid., pp. 208±9.
16. Hobhouse (1964), pp. 90, 127.
48. Ibid., pp. 249, 307.
17. De Ruggiero (1927), p. 390.
49. Croce (1946), pp. 87, 106.
18. Ibid., p. 437.
50. Rawls (1996), p. xxvi.
19. Orton (1945), pp. 78, 303.
51. Rawls (ibid., pp. 72±8) attempts to distinguish be-
20. Laski (1936), p. 14.
tween various types of autonomy in a discussion that is
21. Ibid., p. 171.
highly contentious. Suffice it to observe that his
22. Bullock and Shock (1956), p. xix.
notions of rational and political autonomy, as distinct
23. Hobhouse (1964), p. 73.
from full ethical autonomy, are posited on an unten-
24. De Ruggiero (1927), p. 90.
able divide between political and comprehensive lib-
25. Ibid., p. 361.
eralism, and on a blindness to the thickness of his
26. Ibid., p. 437.
notion of an autonomous person in the space occupied by political liberalism.
27. Ibid., p. 347. 28. Croce (1946), pp. 79±81.
52. See Evans (1999).
29. Ibid., pp. 84±5.
53. See M. Freeden, `Liberal Community: An Exercise in
30. Hartz (1955), p. 16.
Retrieval', in A. Simhony and D. Weinstein (eds),
31. Ibid., pp. 7, 10.
Non-Individualist
32. Hobson (1928).
University Press, forthcoming).
Liberalism
(Cambridge: Cambridge
54. This is notably the case for Locke, who in a little-noted
33. Hobhouse (1924), p. 30. 34. De Ruggiero (1927), p. 274.
comment on the transition from the state of nature to
35. Ibid., p. 348.
civil society notes: `This any number of Men may do,
36. Hallowell (1946), p. 1.
because it injures not the Freedom of the rest; they are
37. For a discussion of these developments within the
left as they were in the Liberty of the State of Nature'
American legal profession, see Primus (1999), pp.
(Locke, 1991, section 96). This historically astute nonuniversalism is inconceivable in the Rawlsian project.
177±97.
55. See J.A. Hobson, `Character and Society', in Parker
38. In the extreme case, progress is seen as the central
(ed.) (1912), p. 96.
structural principle of liberalism: `Progressivism is indeed a better term than liberalism for the opposition to
56. Rawls (1996), p. 45.
conservatism. For if conservatism is, as its name in-
57. Neill (1953), p. 18.
dicates, aversion to change or distrust of change, its
58. Hobhouse (1964), pp. 115±17; Hobson (1909), passim.
opposite should be identified with the opposite posture toward change, and not with something substantive
59. Neill (1953), p. 21.
like liberty or liberality' (Strauss, 1968, p. vii).
60. Contrast this with Laski's complaint that liberalism
39. Hallowell (1946), p. 88.
has been far too political, in the sense of espousing the
40. Ibid., p. 109.
ends of political, but not economic, democracy. For
41. Ibid., pp. 21, 108±9.
Laski, `it was inherent in the Liberal idea that men
42. Kymlicka attempts to attach the (cultural) properties
should use their political power for the improvement of their material position' (Laski, 1936, pp. 158±9).
of groups to the promotion of individual identity-cum-
61. R. Dworkin, `Liberalism', in Dworkin (1985), pp.
autonomy alone. See Kymlicka (1995).
181±204.
43. Orton (1945), p. 308. 44. Hobson (1909), p. 92.
62. See Freeden (1996), chapter 6.
45. Rawls (1996), pp. 231±40.
63. Rawls (1999), p. 614.
32
Part Two CITIZENSHIP: UNIVERSALISM AND PARTICULARISM
This page intentionally left blank
3
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE Will Kymlicka
issue for anyone who wishes to defend and promote
I Introduction
the liberal project in the twenty-first century. But what exactly is the challenge which ethnocultural
It is an honour for me to be giving this Lecture in the 1
whose influential book on
diversity raises for human rights? We can distinguish
John Stuart Mill helped to clarify my understanding
two separate challenges. The first is foundational.
memory of John Rees,
2
Liberal democ-
Some critics argue that the conception of human
racy rests on principles of freedom and equality, but
personhood and human needs underlying the doc-
as Rees noted, it is not easy to specify or define these
trine of human rights is culturally biased. More
principles. He suggested, however, that these prin-
specifically, it is `Eurocentric', and in particular it
ciples are perhaps best illustrated or reflected in the
exhibits a European commitment to individualism,
doctrine of human rights ± that is, the doctrine that
whereas other non-western cultures have a more
each person has an intrinsic moral worth; that each
collectivist or communitarian understanding of hu-
person's interests must be taken into consideration
man identity. On this view, given the depth of
by the state; and that each person should receive
cultural differences around the world, the very idea
certain inviolable protections against mistreatment,
of developing a single set of universal human rights is
of liberalism and liberal democracy.
abuse and oppression.
3
inherently ethnocentric, and involves imposing one culture's view of human personality and human
The articulation and diffusion of the doctrine of
identity on other cultures.
human rights is indeed one of the great achievements of postwar liberalism. This year represents the fiftieth
The second challenge is more modest. Some
anniversary of the Universal Declaration of Human
critics say that the idea of universal human rights
Rights, and it is impressive how far we have come in
is acceptable in principle, but that the current list of
those fifty years in ensuring the protection of human
human rights is radically incomplete. In particular, it
dignity and human rights. Yet amid the anniversary
fails to protect minority cultures from various forms
celebrations there are an increasing number of scep-
of injustice, and so needs to be supplemented with an
tics and critics who attack the doctrine of human
additional set of what are sometimes called `collec-
rights for neglecting the realities of ethnocultural
tive rights' (or `group rights', `minority rights' or
diversity, and for being unable to deal with the
`cultural rights'). Most discussions of cultural diversity and human
conflicts which arise from this diversity, either with-
rights have focused on the first, foundational, chal-
in a society or between societies. This is an issue which Rees did not foresee, and
lenge. Here, however, I will focus on the second,
perhaps could not have foreseen. But it is an urgent
since it is less explored. Many commentators tend to
35
WILL KYMLICKA
confuse and conflate the two challenges; they assume
Individual Rights and Group Rights
that any group which is demanding `collective rights' must be doing so because they are `collectivist' in
According to many commentators, human rights are
their cultural outlook and attitudes, and so are,
paradigmatically individual rights, as befits the in-
implicitly at least, raising the foundationalist chal-
dividualism of western societies, whereas non-Eur-
lenge to the very idea of universal human rights. If
opean societies are more interested in `group' or
we conflate the two debates in this way, it will seem
`collective' rights, as befits their communalist tradi-
that we need to revisit the foundationalist issue every
tions. I think this way of framing the debate is quite
time an ethnocultural group demands collective
misleading. For one thing, individual rights have
rights. This tendency to conflate the two debates is, I
typically been defended within the Western tradi-
think, profoundly unhelpful. It is a source not only of
tion precisely on the grounds that they enable
philosophical misunderstanding, but also, and per-
various group-oriented activities. Consider the para-
haps more importantly, of political confusion which
digmatic liberal right ± namely, freedom of religion ±
has prevented liberals from understanding and effec-
which Rawls argues is the origin and foundation for
tively responding to ethnocultural conflicts around
all other liberal rights. The point of endowing in-
the world. So my aim is to discuss the second issue on
dividuals with rights to freedom of conscience and
its own terms. I will try to show why current con-
freedom of worship is to enable religious groups to
ceptions of human rights leave serious issues of
form and maintain themselves, and to recruit new
ethnocultural injustice unaddressed, and why these
members. And indeed according individuals rights to
issues of injustice are not reducible or dependent on
religious freedom has proven very successful in en-
the foundationalist challenge to human rights. I
abling a wide range of religious groups ± including
hope to show that these claims of injustice are
many non-western religions ± to survive and flourish
relevant and urgent even for those of us who reject
in western societies.
the foundationalist critique of human rights. Indeed,
Based partly on this example of religious toler-
I think that we will only be in a position to effec-
ance, many commentators have argued that indivi-
tively address the foundationalist critique of human
dual rights provide a firm foundation for justice for
rights if we have first made sure that our conception
all groups, including ethnocultural minorities. In-
of human rights deals satisfactorily with these issues
deed, this was explicitly the argument given after
of ethnocultural injustice.
the Second World War for replacing the League of
The discussion is divided into two main sections.
Nations' `minorities protection' scheme ± which
In the first section, I discuss why human rights are
accorded collective rights to specific groups ± with
insufficient for ethnocultural justice and may even
the UN's regime of universal human rights. Rather
exacerbate certain injustices, and hence why human
than protecting vulnerable groups directly, through
rights standards must be supplemented with various
special rights for the members of designated groups,
minority rights. In the second section, I ask whether,
cultural minorities would be protected indirectly, by
if human rights are supplemented with minority
guaranteeing basic civil and political rights to all
rights, we can hope or expect to get greater agree-
individuals regardless of group membership. Basic
ment on the transnational application of human
human rights such as freedom of speech, association
rights. I argue that we can indeed hope for greater
and conscience, while attributed to individuals, are
agreement on the principles of human rights, but that
typically exercised in community with others, and
there will still be very difficult issues remaining about
so provide protection for group life. Where these
appropriate institutions for the enforcement of these
individual rights are firmly protected, liberals as-
rights. I will conclude with some broader reflections
sumed, no further rights needed to be attributed to
on the relationship between cultural diversity and
the members of specific ethnic or national mino-
human rights.
rities:
36
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
The general tendency of the postwar movements
Âbe  cois in North America, the CatRicans and Que
for the promotion of human rights has been to
alans and Basques in Spain, the Flemish in Belgium,
subsume the problem of national minorities under
the Sami in Norway, and so on. Most countries
the broader problem of ensuring basic individual
around the world contain such national minorities,
rights to all human beings, without reference to
and most of these national minorities were involun-
membership in ethnic groups. The leading as-
tarily incorporated into their current state ± a testa-
sumption has been that members of national
ment to the role of imperialism and violence in the
minorities do not need, are not entitled to, or
formation of the current system of `nation-states'.
cannot be granted rights of a special character.
Very few if any of these national minorities are
The doctrine of human rights has been put for-
satisfied merely with respect for their individual
ward as a substitute for the concept of minority
human rights, and it is easy to see why. I will discuss
rights, with the strong implication that minorities
three examples where individual rights do not ade-
whose members enjoy individual equality of treat-
quately protect their interests: decisions about inter-
ment cannot legitimately demand facilities for the
nal migration/settlement policies, decisions about
maintenance of their ethnic particularism.
4
the boundaries and powers of internal political units, and decisions about official languages.
Guided by this philosophy, the United Nations
In each of these examples, and throughout the
deleted all references to the rights of ethnic and
analysis, I will be using the term `human rights' in an
national minorities in its Universal Declaration of
imprecise way. I am not referring to any particular
Human Rights.
canonical statement or declaration of international
There is of course much truth in this claim that
human rights, but rather to the constellation of
individual rights protect group life. Freedom of as-
individual civil and political rights which are for-
sociation, religion, speech, mobility and political
mulated in western democratic constitutions, and
organisation enables individuals to form and main-
which many advocates of human rights would like to
tain the various groups and associations which con-
see entrenched and enforced as transnational stan-
stitute
to
dards of human rights. Some of these rights are
changing circumstances, and to promote their views
included in the original Declaration, others in sub-
and interests to the wider population. The protec-
sequent conventions (such as the 1966 Covenant on
tion afforded by these common rights of citizenship is
Civil and Political Rights), others are still being
sufficient for many of the legitimate forms of group
debated. In short, I am referring more to a particular
diversity in society.
public and political discourse of `human rights', than
civil
society,
to
adapt
these
groups
to the actual list of human rights in any particular
However, it is increasingly clear that the list of
document.
common individual rights guaranteed in western democratic constitutions, or in the UN Declaration, is not sufficient to ensure ethnocultural justice,
5
Internal Migration/Settlement Policies
particularly in states with national minorities. By national minorities, I mean groups which formed
National governments have often encouraged people
functioning societies, with their own institutions,
from one part of the country (or new immigrants) to
culture and language, concentrated in a particular
move into the historical territory of the national
territory, prior to being incorporated into a larger
minority. Such large-scale settlement policies are
state. The incorporation of such national minorities
often deliberately used as a weapon against the
is usually involuntary, as a result of colonisation,
national minority, both to break open access to their
conquest or the ceding of territory from one imperial
territory's natural resources and to disempower them
power to another, but may also occur voluntarily,
politically by turning them into a minority even
through some treaty or other federative agreement.
within their own traditional territory.
Examples
of
national
minorities
within
6
western
This process is occurring around the world, in
democracies include the indigenous peoples, Puerto
Bangladesh, Israel, Tibet, Indonesia, Brazil, for ex-
37
WILL KYMLICKA
7
ample. It has also happened in North America. The
Chinese citizens have a basic human right to settle
nineteenth-century Canadian Prime Minister, Sir
there.
Âtis that `these John A. MacDonald, said of the Me
To protect against these unjust settlement poli-
impulsive half-breeds . . . must be kept down by a
cies, national minorities need and demand a variety
strong hand until they are swamped by the influx of
of measures. For example, they may make certain
8
And the same process occurred in the
land claims ± insisting that certain lands be reserved
American Southwest, where immigration was used
for their exclusive use and benefit. Or they may
to disempower the indigenous peoples and Chicano
demand that certain disincentives be placed on
populations who were living on that territory when it
in-migration. For example, migrants may need to
was incorporated into the United States in 1848.
pass lengthy residency requirements before they can
settlers.'
This is not only a source of grave injustice, but is
vote in local or regional elections. Or they may not
also the most common source of violent conflict in
be able to bring their language rights with them ±
the world. Indigenous peoples and other homeland
that is, they may be required to attend schools in the
minorities typically resist such massive settlement
local language, rather than having publicly funded
9
One would
education in their own language. Similarly, the
hope, therefore, that human rights doctrines would
courts and public services may be conducted in
provide us with the tools to challenge such policies.
the local language. These measures are all intended
Unfortunately, there is nothing in human rights
to reduce the number of migrants into the homeland
doctrine which precludes such settlement policies
of the national minority, and to ensure that those
(so long as individual members of the minority are
who do come are willing to integrate into the local
not deprived of their civil and political rights). There
culture.
policies, even with force, if necessary.
are other elements of international law which might
These are often cited as examples of the sort of
be of some help, in exceptional circumstances. For
`group rights' which conflict with western individu-
example, UN Resolution Number 2189, adopted in
alism. They are said to reflect the minority's `com-
December 1967, condemns attempts by colonial
munal' attachment to their land and culture. But in
powers systematically to promote the influx of im-
fact these demands have little if anything to do with
migrants into their colonised possessions. But this
the contrast between `individualist' and `commun-
only applies to overseas colonies or to newly con-
alist' societies. Western `individualists societies also
quered territories, not to already incorporated na-
seek protections against in-migration. Take any wes-
tional minorities and indigenous peoples. So it is of
tern democracy. While the majority believes in
Âtis or Tibetans. no help to the Me
maximising their individual mobility throughout
Human rights doctrines are not only silent on this
the country, they do not support the right of in-
question, but in fact may exacerbate the injustice,
dividuals outside the country to enter and settle. On
since the UN Charter guarantees the right to free
the contrary, western democracies are typically very
mobility within the territory of a state. Indeed,
restrictive about accepting new immigrants into their
ethnic Russians in the Baltics defended their settle-
society. None has accepted the idea that transna-
ment policies precisely on the grounds that they had
tional mobility is a basic human right. And those few
a human right to move freely throughout the territory
immigrants who are allowed in are pressured to
of the former Soviet Union. It is important to
integrate into the majority culture. For example,
remember that most countries recognised the bound-
learning the majority language is a condition of
aries of the Soviet Union, and so the UN Charter
gaining citizenship, and publicly funded education
does indeed imply that ethnic Russians had a basic
is typically provided only in the majority's language.
right to settle freely in any of the Soviet republics,
Western democracies impose these restrictions on
even to the point where the indigenous inhabitants
immigration into their country for precisely the same
were becoming a minority in their own homeland.
reason that national minorities seek to restrict in-
Similarly, human rights doctrines, far from prohibit-
migration into their territory ± namely, massive
ing ethnic Han settlement in Tibet, imply that
settlement would threaten their society and culture.
38
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
The majority, like the minority, has no desire to be
with the territory of a national minority, the degree
overrun and outnumbered by settlers from another
of meaningful autonomy may be undermined if the
culture.
central government usurps most or all of the sub-
To say that the desire of national minorities to
unit's powers and eliminates the group's traditional
limit in-migration reflects some sort of illiberal com-
mechanisms of self-government. And indeed, we can
munalism is therefore quite hypocritical. When the
find many such instances in which a minority nom-
majority says that mobility within a country is a basic
inally controls a political subunit but has no sub-
human right, but that mobility across borders is not,
stantive power, since the central government has (1)
they are not preferring individual mobility over
removed the traditional institutions and procedures
collective security. They are simply saying that their
of group self-government; and (2) arrogated all im-
collective security will be protected (by limits on
portant powers, even those affecting the very cultural
immigration), but that once their collective security
survival of the group ± for example, jurisdiction over
is protected, then individual mobility will be max-
economic development, education, language. (Con-
imised, regardless of the consequences for the col-
sider the plenary power of the American Congress
lective
over Indian tribes in the United States.)
security
of
minorities.
This
is
obviously
hypocritical and unjust, but it is an injustice which
This usurpation of power is, I believe, a clear
human rights doctrines do not prevent and may even
injustice, particularly when it involves seizing powers
exacerbate.
10
or undermining institutions which were guaranteed to the minority in treaties or federating agreements. Yet here again, it seems that human rights doctrines
The Boundaries and
are inadequate to prevent such injustice. So long as
Powers of Internal Political Subunits
individual members maintain the right to vote and
In states with territorially concentrated national
run for office, then human rights principles pose no
minorities, the boundaries of internal political sub-
obstacle to the majority's efforts to gerrymander the
units
Since
boundaries or powers of internal political subunits in
national minorities are usually territorially concen-
such a way as to disempower the national minority.
trated, these boundaries can be drawn in such a way
This is true even if the arrogation of power violates
as to empower them ± that is, to create political
an earlier treaty or federative agreement, since such
subunits within which the national minority forms a
internal treaties are not considered `international'
local majority, and which can therefore be used as a
agreements (the minority which signed the treaty is
vehicle for meaningful autonomy and self-govern-
not seen under international law as a sovereign state,
ment.
and so its treaties with the majority are seen as
raise
fundamental
issues
of
justice.
In many countries, however, boundaries have
matters of domestic politics, not international law).
been drawn so as to disempower national minorities.
Not only do human rights doctrines not help
For example, a minority's territory may be broken up
prevent this injustice, but they may exacerbate it.
into several units so as to make cohesive political
Historically, the majority's decisions to ignore the
action
of
traditional leadership of minority communities and
France into 83 `departments' after the Revolution
to destroy their traditional political institutions have
which intentionally subdivided the historical regions
been justified on the grounds that these traditional
of the Basques, Bretons and other linguistic mino-
leaders and institutions were not `democratic': they
rities, or the division of nineteenth-century Catalo-
did not involve the same process of periodic elec-
nia);
tions as majority political institutions. The tradi-
impossible
conversely,
(for
a
example,
minority's
the
division
territory
may
be
absorbed into a larger political subunit so as to ensure
tional
that they are outnumbered within the subunit as a
consensus and decision-making may well have pro-
whole (such as the Hispanics in nineteenth-century
vided every member of the minority community with
Florida).
11
mechanisms
of
group
consultation,
meaningful rights to political participation and influence. However, they were swept away by the
Even where the boundaries coincide more or less
39
WILL KYMLICKA
majority in the name of `democracy' ± that is, the
long in the modern world unless they are used in
right to vote in an electoral process within which
public life, and so government decisions about offi-
minorities had no real influence, conducted in a
cial languages are, in effect, decisions about which
foreign language and in foreign institutions, and
languages will thrive, and which will die out.
14
within which they were destined to become a per-
Just as the traditional political institutions of
manent minority. Thus the rhetoric of human rights
minorities have been shut down by the majority,
has provided an excuse and smokescreen for the
so too have the pre-existing educational institutions.
subjugation of a previously self-governing minor-
For example, Spanish schools in the American
ity.
12
Southwest were closed after 1848, and replaced with English-language
To avoid this sort of injustice, national minorities
schools.
Similarly,
French-lan-
need guaranteed rights to such things as self-govern-
guage schools in Western Canada were closed once
ment,
English-speakers achieved political dominance.
group-based
political
representation,
veto
rights over issues that directly affect their cultural
This can be an obvious source of injustice. Yet
survival, and so on. Again, these demands are often
here again, principles of human rights do not prevent
seen as conflicting with western individualism and as
this injustice (even when, as in the Southwest, there
proof of the minority's `collectivism'. But in reality,
were treaties guaranteeing Hispanics the right to
these demands simply help to redress clear political
their own Spanish-language schools). Human rights
inequalities. After all, the majority would equally
doctrines do preclude any attempt by the state to
reject any attempt by foreign powers to unilaterally
suppress the use of a minority language in private,
change its boundaries, institutions or self-govern-
and may even require state toleration of privately
ment powers. So why shouldn't national minorities
funded schools which operate in the minority lan-
also seek guarantees of their boundaries, institutions
guage. But human rights doctrines say nothing about
and powers?
rights to the use of one's language in government.
15
In a recent paper, Avigail Eisenberg details how
On some interpretations of more recent interna-
the debate over Aboriginal political rights in the
tional conventions which include minority rights,
Canadian north has been seriously distorted by the
public funding for mother-tongue classes at elemen-
focus on western `individualism' versus Aboriginal
tary level may under some circumstances be seen as a
`collectivism'. This way of framing the debate misses
`human right'. But this remains a controversial de-
the real issues, which are the ongoing effects of
velopment.
colonisation ± the political subordination of one
the elementary level is clearly insufficient if all jobs
people to another, through the majority's unilateral
in a modern economy require education at higher
efforts to undermine the minority's institutions and
levels conducted in the majority language. Indeed,
powers of self-government.
13
16
Moreover, mother-tongue education at
the requirement that education at senior levels be in the majority language creates a disincentive for minority parents to enrol their children in minor-
Official Language Policy
ity-language elementary schools in the first place.
17
In most democratic states, governments have typi-
To redress the injustice created by majority at-
cally adopted the majority's language as the one
tempts to impose linguistic homogeneity, national
`official language' ± that is, as the language of gov-
minorities may need broad-ranging language poli-
ernment, bureaucracy, courts, schools, and so on. All
cies. There is evidence that language communities
citizens are then forced to learn this language in
can only survive intergenerationally if they are nu-
school, and fluency in it is required to work for, or
merically dominant within a particular territory, and
deal with, government. While this policy is often
if their language is the language of opportunity in
defended in the name of `efficiency', it is also
that territory. But it is difficult to sustain such a
adopted to ensure the eventual assimilation of the
predominant status for a minority language, particu-
national minority into the majority group. There is
larly if newcomers to the minority's territory are able
strong evidence that languages cannot survive for
to become educated and employed in the majority
40
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
language (for example, if newcomers to Quebec are
common language have been important tools in
able to learn and work in English). It may not be
these nation-building efforts. There is no evidence
enough, therefore, for the minority simply to have
that states intended to relinquish these tools when
the right to use its language in public. It may also be
they accepted human rights conventions, and indeed
necessary that the minority language be the only
no evidence that states would have accepted a
official language in their territory.
18
If immigrants, or
conception of human rights which would preclude
migrants from the majority group, are able to use the
such nation-building programmes.
majority language in public life, this may eventually
Of course, human rights standards do set limits on
undermine the predominant status, and hence via-
this process of nation-building. States cannot kill or
bility, of the minority's language.
19
In other words,
expel minorities, or strip them of citizenship or deny
minorities may need not personal bilingualism (in
them the vote. But human rights standards do not
which individuals carry their language rights with
preclude less extreme forms of nation-building. And
them throughout the entire country), but rather
if these nation-building measures are successful, then
territorial bilingualism (in which people who choose
it is not necessary to restrict the individual civil and
to move to the minority's territory accept that the
political rights of the minority. Where nation-build-
minority's language will be the only official language
ing programmes have succeeded in turning the in-
in that territory). Yet this sort of territorial bilingu-
corporated group into a minority even within its own
alism ± which denies official language status to the
homeland, and in stripping it of its self-governing
majority language on the minority's territory ± is
institutions and language rights, then the group will
often seen as discriminatory by the majority, and
not pose any serious threat to the power or interests
indeed as a violation of their `human rights'.
of the majority. At this point, there is no need to
These demands for extensive language rights and
strip minority members of their individual rights.
territorial bilingualism are often described as evi-
This is not necessary in order to gain and maintain
dence of the minority's `collectivism'. But here again
effective political control over them.
the minority is just seeking the same opportunity to
In short, human rights standards are insufficient to
live and work in their own language that the ma-
prevent ethnocultural injustice, and may actually
jority takes for granted. There is no evidence that the
makes things worse. The majority can invoke human
majority attaches any less weight to their ability to
rights principles to demand access to the minority's
use their language in public life.
20
homeland, to scrap traditional political mechanisms of consultation and accommodation, and to reject
One could mention other issues where human rights
linguistic policies which try to protect the territorial
are insufficient for ensuring ethnocultural justice
viability of minority communities.
(public holidays, school curriculum, national sym-
In these and other ways, human rights have in-
bols, dress-codes and so on). But enough has been
directly served as an instrument of colonisation, as
said, I hope, to make the general point. Moreover, it
various critics have argued. However, I would not
is important to note that the three issues I have
agree with those critics who view this solely as a
examined ± migration, internal political subunits
problem of `western imperialism' against non-Eur-
and language policy ± are all connected. These are
opean peoples. After all, these processes of unjust
all key components in the `nation-building' pro-
subjugation have occurred between European groups
grammes which every western state has engaged
(such as the treatment of national minorities by the
21
Every democratic state has, at one time or
majority in France, Spain, Russia), and between
another, attempted to create a single `national iden-
African or Asian groups (such as the treatment of
tity' among its citizens, and so has tried to undermine
the Yao minority by the Chewa majority in Malawi,
any competing national identities, of the sort which
or the treatment of the Tibetan minority by the Han
in.
22
Policies designed
majority in China), as well as in the context of
to settle minority homelands, undermine their poli-
western colonisation of non-western peoples. These
tical and educational institutions and impose a single
processes have occurred in virtually every state with
national minorities often possess.
41
WILL KYMLICKA
national minorities, and to ascribe it to western
equally serious mistake to privilege minority rights
individualism is to seriously underestimate the scope
over human rights. In questioning the priority of
of the problem.
traditional human rights over minority rights, I am
If human rights are not to be an instrument of
not disputing the potential for serious rights viola-
unjust subjugation then they must be supplemented
tions within many minority groups, or the need to
with various minority rights ± language rights, self-
have some institutional checks on the power of local
government rights, representation rights, federalism
or minority political leaders. On the contrary, all
and so on. Moreover, these minority rights should
political authorities should be held accountable for
not, I think, be seen as in any way secondary to
respecting the basic rights of the people they govern,
traditional human rights. Even those who are sym-
and this applies as much to the exercise of self-
pathetic to the need for minority rights often say that
government powers by national minorities as to
we should at least begin with human rights. That is,
the actions of the larger state. The individual mem-
we should first secure respect for individual human
bers of national minorities can be just as badly
rights, and then, having secured the conditions for a
mistreated and oppressed by the leaders of their
free and democratic debate, move on to questions of
own group as by the majority government, and so
minority rights. When national minorities oppose
any system of minority self-government should in-
this assumption, they are often labelled as illiberal or
clude some institutional provisions for enforcing
anti-democratic. But as I've tried to show, we cannot
traditional human rights within the minority com-
assume that human rights will have their desired
munity.
consequences without attending to the larger con-
It is not a question of choosing between minority
text within which they operate. Unless supplemen-
rights and human rights, or of giving priority to one
ted by minority rights, majoritarian democracy and
over the other, but rather of treating them together
individual mobility rights may simply lead to min-
as equally important components of justice in eth-
ority oppression. As we've seen, various forms of
noculturally plural countries. We need a conception
oppression can occur while still respecting the in-
of justice that integrates fairness between different
dividual rights of minorities. As a result, the longer
ethnocultural groups (via minority rights) with the
we defer discussing minority rights, the more likely it
protection of individual rights within majority and
is that the minority will become increasingly wea-
minority political communities (via traditional hu-
kened and outnumbered. Indeed, it may over time
man rights).
23
become so weakened that it will become unable even to demand or exercise meaningful minority rights
The Enforcement of Human Rights
(for example, it may lose the local predominance or territorial concentration needed to sustain its lan-
Assuming that we can come up with some new
guage or to exercise local self-government). It is no
theory which combines human rights and minority
accident, therefore, that members of the majority are
rights, would the existing level of opposition to
often loudest in their support for giving priority to
transnational
democracy and human rights over issues of minority
Would we then get consensus on the enforcement
rights. They know that the longer issues of minority
of international standards of human rights?
human
rights
standards
diminish?
rights are deferred, the more time it provides for the
We can expect, I think, that the elites of some
majority to disempower and dispossess the minority
groups will continue to say human rights principles
of its land, schools and political institutions to the
contradict their cultural `traditions'. I will return to
point where the minority is in no position to sustain
this possibility in my conclusion. But my guess is that
itself as a thriving culture or to exercise meaningful
much of the current opposition to human rights
self-government.
would fade away. As I noted earlier, human rights
This is why human rights and minority rights must
are not inherently `individualistic' and do not pre-
be treated together, as equally important compo-
clude group life. They simply ensure that traditions
nents of a just society. Of course, it would be an
are voluntarily maintained, and that dissent is not
42
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
forcibly suppressed. To be sure, self-serving political
majorities are not going to give all groups the max-
elites who want to suppress challenges to their
imal rights demanded by the largest and most mo-
authority from within the community will continue
bilised groups (which may include secession).
to denounce human rights as a violation of their
I see no way to overcome this problem. While
`traditions'. This explains the recent criticisms of
minority rights are indeed essential, the solution is
human rights doctrines by the Indonesian and Chi-
not to add a detailed list of minority rights to human
nese governments. But my guess is that if human
rights declarations in international law. Instead, we
rights doctrines are no longer seen as a tool for
must accept that traditional human rights are in-
subordinating one people to another, but rather as
sufficient to ensure ethnocultural justice, and then
a tool for protecting vulnerable individuals from
recognise the need to supplement them within each
abuse by their political leaders, then such opposition
country with the specific minority rights which are
to human rights will increasingly be seen simply as a
appropriate for that country. As I will discuss later,
self-serving defence of elite power and privilege.
24
international bodies can play a useful role in adju-
So I would hope that we could gain greater
dicating minority rights conflicts, but this role is
international consensus on the principles of human
unlikely to take the form of adjudicating or enforcing
rights. But this is not to say that we are likely to get
a single codified international list of minority rights.
consensus on the appropriate enforcement mechan-
This then leads to the second problem. If human
isms of human rights/minority rights, either at the
rights and minority rights must be integrated at the
international level or even in the domestic setting.
domestic level rather than through a single interna-
There are at least two major difficulties here. First, it
tional code, can we find an impartial body to ad-
is difficult to see how minority rights can be codified
judicate and enforce these rights at the domestic
at the international level. Minorities come in many
level? Many people will naturally assume that these
different shapes and sizes. There are `national' mino-
rights should be listed in a single national constitu-
rities,
tion which is then adjudicated and enforced by a
indigenous
guestworkers,
peoples,
single supreme court. Certainly most liberals have
religious
assumed that the supreme court in each country
groups, and so on. All of these groups have different
should have final jurisdiction regarding both human
or
indentured
settlers,
refugees, of
slaves
colonising
immigrants,
labourers,
descendants Roma,
needs, aspirations and institutional capacities.
25
rights and minority rights.
Ter-
ritorial autonomy will not work for widely dispersed
But in fact we find strong resistance to this idea
groups, and even territorially concentrated groups
among some minority groups, even if they share the
differ dramatically in the sort of self-government
principles underlying the set of human rights and
they aspire to or are capable of. Similarly, language
minority rights listed in the national constitution.
rights (beyond the right to private speech) will not
Consider the situation of Indian tribes in the United
be the same in India or Malaysia (which contain
States. American constitutional law protects both
hundreds of indigenous languages) as in France or
certain minority rights for Indian tribes (they are
Britain.
recognised as `domestic dependent nations' with
This is why international declarations of minority
treaty-based rights of self-government) and also a
rights tend to waver between trivialities like the
general set of individual human rights (in the Bill of
`right to maintain one's culture' (which could simply
Rights). This could be seen as at least the beginnings
mean that respect for freedom of expression and
of an attempt to fairly integrate minority rights and
association, and hence add nothing to existing de-
human rights at the domestic level.
27
clarations of human rights) and vague generalities
But who should have the power to enforce these
like the `right to self-determination' (which could
constitutional provisions regarding individual and
mean anything from token representation to full-
minority rights? American liberals typically assume
blown secession).
26
Minorities are not going to
that the federal Supreme Court should have this
accept the lowest common denominator, which even
power. But many American Indians oppose this idea.
the smallest or most dispersed group seeks, but
They do not want the Supreme Court to be able to
43
WILL KYMLICKA
And why should they trust this court to act impar-
review their internal decisions to assess whether they 28
And they would
tially in considering their minority and treaty rights?
prefer to have some international body monitor the
For all these reasons, to assume that supreme courts
extent to which the American government respects
at the national level should have the ultimate
their treaty-based minority rights. So they do not
authority over all issues of individual and minority
want the federal Supreme Court to be the ultimate
rights within a country may be inappropriate in the
protector either of the individual rights of their
case of indigenous peoples and other incorporated
members or of their minority rights.
national minorities.
comply with the Bill of Rights.
29
There are good reasons why
Needless to say, Indian demands to reduce the
American Indians do not trust federal courts either
authority of the federal Supreme Court have met
to uphold the minority rights needed for ethnocul-
with
has
tural justice between majority and minority, or to
shown no desire to accept international monitoring
fairly determine whether the minority is respecting
of the extent to which the treaty rights of Indians are
human rights internally.
resistance.
The
American
government
respected. Indeed, the American government has
It is quite understandable, therefore, that many
jealously guarded its sovereignty in these matters,
Indian leaders seek to reduce the role of federal
and so refused to give any international body jur-
judicial review. But at the same time they affirm
isdiction to review and overturn the way it respects
their commitment to the basic package of human
the treaty rights, land claims or self-government
rights and minority rights which is contained in the
rights of indigenous peoples.
US constitution. They endorse the principles, but
And the demand to have internal tribal decisions
object to the particular institutions and procedures
exempted from scrutiny under the Bill of Rights is
that the larger society has established to enforce
widely opposed by liberals, since it raises the concern
these principles. As Joseph Carens puts it, `people
in many people's minds that individuals or subgroups
are supposed to experience the realisation of prin-
(such as women) within American Indian commu-
ciples of justice through various concrete institu-
nities could be oppressed in the name of group
tions, but they may actually experience a lot of
solidarity or cultural purity. They argue that any
the institution and very little of the principle.'
acceptable package of individual rights and minority
This is exactly how many indigenous peoples per-
rights must include judicial review of tribal decisions
ceive the Supreme Court in both Canada and the
by the American Supreme Court to ensure their
United States. What they experience is not the
compliance with the Bill of Rights.
principles of human dignity and equality, but rather
Before jumping to this conclusion, however, we
30
a social institution which has historically justified
should consider the reasons why certain groups are
their conquest and dispossession.
distrustful of federal judicial review. In the case of
What we need to do, therefore, is to find impartial
American Indians, these reasons are, I think, ob-
bodies to monitor compliance with both human
vious. After all, the federal Supreme Court has
rights and minority rights. We need to think crea-
historically legitimised the acts of colonisation and
tively about new mechanisms for enforcing human
conquest which dispossessed Indians of their prop-
rights and minority rights that will avoid the legit-
erty and political power. It has historically denied
imate objections which indigenous peoples and na-
both the individual rights and treaty rights of Indians
tional minorities have to federal courts.
on the basis of racist and ethnocentric assumptions.
What would these alternative mechanisms look
Moreover, Indians have had no representation on
like? To begin with, many Indian tribes have sought
the Supreme Court, and there is reason to fear that
to create or maintain their own procedures for
white judges on the Supreme Court may interpret
protecting human rights within their community,
certain rights in culturally biased ways (such as
specified in tribal constitutions, some of which are
democratic rights). Why should Indians agree to
based on the provisions of international protocols on
have their internal decisions reviewed by a body
human rights. It is important to distinguish Indian
which is, in effect, the court of their conquerors?
tribes, who have their own internal constitution and
44
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
courts which prevent the arbitrary exercise of poli-
of their conquerors). But they want this sort of
tical power, from ethnocultural groups which have
external monitoring to examine how well their
no formal constitutions or courts, and which there-
minority rights are upheld by the larger society,
fore provide no effective check on the exercise of
not just to focus on the extent to which their
arbitrary power by powerful individuals or traditional
own decisions respect individual human rights. This
elites. We should take these internal checks on the
seems like a reasonable demand to me.
misuse of power seriously. Indeed, to automatically
These international mechanisms could arise at the
assume that the federal courts should replace or
regional as well as global level. European countries
supersede the institutions which Indians have them-
have agreed to establish their own multilateral hu-
selves evolved to prevent injustice is evidence of an
man rights tribunals. Perhaps North American gov-
ethnocentric bias ± an implicit belief that `our'
ernments and Indian tribes could agree to establish a
institutions are superior to theirs.
31
similar multilateral tribunal, on which both sides are fairly represented.
Indian tribes have also sought to create new transnational or international procedures to help
My aim here is not to defend any particular
monitor the protection of their minority rights.
proposal for a new impartial body to monitor the
The international community can play an important
protection of individual rights and minority rights.
role, not so much by formulating a single list of
Rather, it is to stress again the necessity of treating
minority rights that applies to all countries (for that
individual rights and minority rights together when
is impossible), but rather by providing an impartial
thinking about appropriate enforcement mechan-
adjudicator to monitor the extent to which domestic
isms. On the one hand, we need to think about
provisions regarding minority rights are fairly nego-
effective mechanisms which can hold minority gov-
tiated and implemented.
ernments accountable for the way individual mem-
From the point of view of ethnocultural justice,
bers are treated. I see no justification for exempting
these proposals might be preferable to the current
minority self-government from the principles of hu-
reliance on the federal Supreme Court. But it would
man rights ± I believe that any exercise of political
be even better, I think, to establish international
power should be subject to these principles. But we
mechanisms which would monitor both the indivi-
need to simultaneously think about effective me-
dual rights and minority rights of Indian peoples.
chanisms for holding the larger society accountable
While the internal courts and constitutions of tribal
for respecting the minority rights of these groups. As
governments are worthy of respect, they ± like the
I argued in the previous section, minority rights are
courts and constitutions of nation-states ± are im-
equally important as individual human rights in
perfect in their protection of human rights. So it
ensuring ethnocultural justice, and so should be
would be preferable if all governments ± majority and
subject to equal scrutiny. Moreover, focusing exclu-
minority ± are subject to some form of international
sively on the latter while neglecting the former
scrutiny.
is
counter-productive
and
hypocritical.
Minority
Many Indian leaders have expressed a willingness
groups will not agree to greater external scrutiny
to accept some form of international monitoring of
of their internal decisions unless they achieve greater
their internal human rights record. They are willing
protection of their minority rights. And since exist-
to abide by international declarations of human
ing institutional mechanisms are typically unable to
rights, and to answer to international tribunals for
meet this twin test of accountability, we need to
complaints of rights violations within their commu-
think creatively about new mechanisms that can
nities. But they would only accept this if and when it
deal impartially with both individual human rights
is accompanied by international monitoring of how
and minority rights.
well the larger state respects their treaty rights. They
I should emphasise again that in questioning the
accept the idea that their tribal governments, like all
role of federal courts in reviewing the internal de-
governments, should be accountable to international
cisions of tribal governments I am not trying to
human rights norms (so long as this isn't in the court
diminish the significance of human rights. On the
45
WILL KYMLICKA
contrary, my goal is to find fairer and more effective
suggests a number of new avenues for future research
ways to promote human rights, by separating them
± avenues which would depart dramatically from the
from the historical and cultural baggage which makes
existing patterns of research and debate. At the
federal courts suspect in the eyes of incorporated
moment, wherever there is a conflict between `local
peoples. History has shown the value of holding
practices' and `transnational human rights standards',
governments
human
commentators tend to locate the source of the con-
rights, and this applies equally to Indian tribal
flict in the `culture' or `traditions' of the group, and
governments. But the appropriate forums for review-
then look for ways in which this culture differs from
ing the actions of self-governing indigenous peoples
`western' culture. This tendency is exacerbated by
may skip the federal level, as it were. Many indi-
the rhetoric of a `politics of difference' or a `politics of
genous groups would endorse a system in which their
identity' which encourages groups to press their
self-governing decisions are reviewed in the first
demands in the language of respect for cultural
instance by their own courts, and then by an inter-
`difference'.
accountable
for
respecting
national court, which would also monitor respect for
My suggestion, however, is that we should not
minority rights. Federal courts, dominated by the
jump to the conclusion that cultural differences are
majority, would not be the ultimate adjudicator of
the real source of the problem. Rather, in each case
either the individual or minority rights of Indian
where a group is objecting to the domestic or trans-
peoples.
national enforcement of human rights principles, we should ask the following questions:
The human rights movement has always set itself against the idea of unlimited sovereignty and pushed for limitations on the power of governments to
1. Has the majority society failed to recognise
mistreat their citizens. But we need to do this in
legitimate minority rights? If so, has this cre-
an even-handed manner. We should hold the min-
ated a situation in which the implementation
ority accountable for respecting the human rights of
of human rights standards contributes to the
its members, but we need also to hold the majority
unjust disempowerment of the minority? I
accountable for respecting minority rights, and we
have discussed three contexts or issues where
need to find impartial enforcement mechanisms
human rights standards can exacerbate ethno-
which can do both of these together.
cultural injustice if they are unaccompanied by minority rights, but it would be interesting to come up with a more systematic list of such
Conclusion
issues.
I have argued that our aims should be twofold: (1) to
2. Is there any reason to think that the existing or
supplement individual human rights with minority
proposed judicial mechanisms for adjudicating
rights, recognising that the specific combination will
or enforcing human rights are biased against
vary from country to country; and (2) to find new
the minority group? Have these judicial me-
domestic,
mechanisms
chanisms treated minorities fairly historically?
which will hold governments accountable for re-
Is the minority group fairly represented on the
specting both human rights and minority rights.
judicial bodies? Were these judicial mechan-
regional
or
transnational
If we manage to solve these two (enormous) tasks,
isms consensually accepted by the minority
then I believe that the commitment to universal
when it was incorporated into the country,
human rights need not be culturally biased. Indeed, if
or is the imposition of these judicial mechan-
we resolve these issues satisfactorily, then the idea of
isms a denial of historical agreements or trea-
human rights can become what it was always in-
ties which protected the autonomy of the
tended to be ± namely, a shield for the weak against
group's own judicial institutions?
the abuse of political power, not a weapon of the My guess is that in many cases where minority
majority in subjugating minorities.
groups object to transnational human rights stan-
If the present arguments are at all valid, then it
46
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
dards, it will be for one of these reasons, rather any
restrictions on its members, we should first make
inherent conflict between their traditional practices
sure we are respecting all of its legitimate minority
and human rights standards. Where these problems
rights. In short, the current conflict between local
are addressed, I expect that many minority groups
practices and transnational standards may not be the
will be more than willing to subscribe to human
result of a deep attachment to some long-standing
rights standards.
`tradition' in the local community, but rather the
I don't mean to deny the existence of illiberal or
(regretted) result of some new vulnerability which
anti-democratic practices within minority commu-
has arisen from the denial of their minority rights.
nities or non-western societies. But it's important to
To be sure, there will be some cases where mem-
note that at least in some cases the existence of such
bers of a group really do object to the very content of
practices is itself the consequence of some prior
the human rights standard on the grounds that it is
ethnocultural injustice. That is, many minorities feel
inconsistent with their cultural traditions. Even if we
compelled to restrict the liberties of their own mem-
solve the problem of minority rights and enforce-
bers because the larger society has denied their
ment mechanisms, we will still find some people
Âaume has legitimate minority rights. As Denise Re
rejecting `western' notions of human rights. They
noted, part of the `demonisation' of other cultures is
will say that restricting the liberty of women or
the assumption that these groups are naturally in-
suppressing political dissent is part of their `tradition',
clined to use coercion against their members. But in
and that human rights theories reflect a biased `euro-
so far as some groups seem regrettably willing to use
centric' and `individualistic' standard.
coercion to preserve group practices, this may be due,
may come from minority groups, or indeed from large
not to any innate illiberalism, but to the fact that the
and powerful majority groups or governments, as in
larger society has failed to respect their minority
Indonesia or China.
33
These claims
rights. Unable to get justice from the larger society
I do not want to enter into that debate and the
in terms of protection for its lands and institutions,
issues of cultural relativism which it raises. As I said
the minority turns its attention to the only people it
earlier, we are all familiar with that debate and I have
does have some control over, namely its own mem-
little to add to it. My aim, rather, is to insist that this
bers.
32
is not the only debate we need to have. On the
This tendency does not justify the violation of the
contrary, we may find that such conflicts are fewer
human rights of group members, but it suggests that
once we have properly dealt with the issues of
before we criticise a minority for imposing such
ethnocultural justice.
Notes
2. Rees (1985).
1. I'd like to thank David Boucher for inviting me to give the Rees Memorial Lecture and for his hospi-
3. Rees (1971), p. x.
tality during my stay in Wales. I'd also like to thank
4. Claude (1955), p. 211.
David Schneiderman for encouraging me to write this
5. There are now several attempts to define a theory of
paper, and for his helpful comments. Thanks also to
ethnocultural justice in the literature, for example
John McGarry for his comments, and to Thomas
Minow (1990), Young (1990), Kymlicka (1995). It
Nagel and Ronald Dworkin for inviting me to discuss
would take a separate paper to explain or defend any
this paper in their Colloquium in Law, Philosophy
particular one. But for the purposes of this paper we
and Political Theory at New York University in
can use a minimalist definition of ethnocultural justice
September 1997. (Editor's note: Professor Kymlicka's
as the absence of relations of oppression and humilia-
chapter was delivered as the J. C. Rees Memorial
tion between different ethnocultural groups. A more
Lecture, commemorating the founding professor of
robust conception of ethnocultural justice could be
the Department of Political Theory and Govern-
developed by asking what terms of coexistence would
ment, on 23 February 1998 at the University of
be freely consented to by the members of different
Wales Swansea. The opening remarks of that occa-
ethnocultural groups in a Habermasian/Rawlsian set-
sion have been preserved.)
ting where inequalities in bargaining power have been
47
WILL KYMLICKA
neutralised. For example, a Rawlsian approach to
(a process they had no real hope of influencing), they
ethnocultural justice would ask what terms of coex-
had to relinquish any claims to participate in long-
istence would be agreed to by people behind a `veil of
standing
ignorance', who didn't know whether they were going
This transparent attempt to undermine Aboriginal
to be born into a majority or minority ethnocultural
political institutions was justified in the name of
Aboriginal
processes
of
self-government.
promoting `democracy'.
group. Such a Rawlsian approach is likely to produce a more demanding conception of ethnocultural justice
13. Avigail Eisenberg, `Individualism and Collectivism in
than the mere absence of oppression and humiliation,
the Politics of Canada's North', paper presented at the
but the main claim of this chapter is that human rights
annual meeting of the Canadian Political Science
are insufficient even to ensure this minimal compo-
Association, May 1995. A revised version of this paper
nent of ethnocultural justice.
will appear in Painting the Maple: Essays on Race,
6. See McGarry (1998).
Gender and the Construction of Canada, edited by Joan
7. See Penz (1992) and (1993). I discuss these cases in
Anderson, Avigail Eisenberg, Sherril Grace and Veronica Strong-Boag (Vancouver: UBC Press, forthcom-
Kymlicka (1996).
ing).
8. MacDonald, quoted in Stanley (1961), p. 95.
14. On the necessity of extensive language rights for the
9. Gurr (1993).
survival and flourishing of linguistic minorities, see
10. It would not be hypocritical to criticise minority
Kymlicka (1995), chapter 6.
demands to limit in-migration if one also criticised state policies to limit immigration ± that is, if one
15. The view that language rights are not part of human
defended a policy of open borders. But such a policy
rights was explicitly affirmed by the Canadian Su-
has virtually no public support, and is certainly not
preme Court in MacDonald v. City of Montreal [1986] 1
endorsed by most of the people who criticise minority
 te  des acadiens du Nouveau-Brunswick v. SCR 460; Socie
demands. However, this raises an important limita-
Minority Language School Board no. 50 [1986] 1 SCR
549.
tion on my argument. I am discussing what justice requires for minorities in the world as we know it ±
16. For a comprehensive review of the current status of
that is, a world of nation-states which retain signifi-
language rights in international human rights law, see de Varennes (1996).
cant control over issues of migration, internal political structures and language policies. One could
17. Low enrolment is then often (perversely) cited by
(with difficulty) imagine a very different world ± a
majority politicians as evidence that most members of
world without states, or with just one world govern-
the minority are not interested in preserving their
ment. The
be
language and culture, and that it is only a few ex-
different in such a hypothetical world, since the
tremists in the minority group who are the cause of
rights
of minorities
would
clearly
ethnic conflict.
power of majorities would be dramatically reduced, including their ability to impose relations of oppres-
18. This is called the `territorial imperative', and the trend
sion and humiliation. My focus, however, is on what
towards territorial concentration of language groups is
ethnocultural justice requires in our world. See also
a widely-noted phenomenon in multilingual western
note 20.
countries. For a more general theoretical account of the `territorial imperative' in multilingual societies, see
11. Cf. Kymlicka (1998). In cases where national mino-
Laponce (1987) and (1993).
rities are not territorially concentrated different meinvoked.
19. This is obviously the rationale given for requiring
During the period of devolved rule in Northern Ire-
immigrants to Quebec to send their children to
chanisms
of
disempowerment
are
often
French-language schools.
land (1920±72), for example, the Catholics were disempowered not so much by the gerrymandering
20. Here again, it would not be hypocritical to criticise
of boundaries (although this occurred), but by the
minority demands regarding self-government rights
adoption of an electoral system (with single-member
and language rights if one applied the same standard
constituencies and plurality rules) designed to ensure
to majorities. For example, one could imagine letting
unity within the Protestant majority while ensuring an
the United Nations determine the boundaries and
ineffective Catholic opposition. This is another ex-
language policies of each state. Imagine that the
ample of how a rhetorical commitment to democracy
UN, in a free and democratic vote, decided to merge
and human rights can coexist alongside the oppression
all countries in the Americas (North, South and
of a national minority.
Central) into a single Spanish-speaking state. If the
12. A related example is the law which existed in Canada
anglophone majority in Canada or the United States
prior to 1960 which granted Indians the vote only if
would accept such a decision ± that is, if they were
they renounced their Indian status, and so abandoned
willing to abandon their own self-government powers
any claim to Aboriginal political or cultural rights. In
and language rights ± then it would not be hypocritical
order to gain a vote in the Canadian political process
to criticise the demands of Francophone, Hispanic or
48
HUMAN RIGHTS AND ETHNOCULTURAL JUSTICE
Aboriginal minorities in North America. But I don't
declarations, see Donald Horowitz, `Self-Determina-
know any English-speaking Canadians or Americans
tion: Politics, Philosophy and Law', in Kymlicka and Shapiro (eds) (1997), pp. 421±63.
who would agree to amalgamate into a single Spanishspeaking state, even if this merger was supported by
27. It is, at best, an imperfect beginning, in large part due
most countries in the Americas (and/or by most people
to the Plenary Power which Congress arbitrarily asserts over Indian tribes. See Kronowitz (1987).
living in the Americas). In reality, the anglophone majorities in both the United States and Canada
28. Indeed, tribal councils in the United States have
zealously guard their right to live in a state where
historically been exempted from having to comply
they form a majority, and their right to have English
with the federal Bill of Rights, and their internal
recognised as a language of public life. This defence of
decisions have not been subject to Supreme Court
the boundaries and linguistic policies of existing na-
review. Various efforts have been made by federal
tion-states is as `collectivist' as the demands of mino-
legislators to change this, most recently the 1968
rities for protection of their self-government and
Indian Civil Rights Act, which was passed by Con-
language rights.
gress despite vociferous opposition from most Indian
21. And, in a different way, in the Communist bloc. See
groups. American Indian groups remain strongly op-
Walker Connor's (1984) account of how Communist
posed to the 1968 Act, just as First Nations in Canada
leaders dealt with the issues of settlement policy,
have argued that their self-governing band councils
gerrymandering and linguistic policies, all of which
should not be subject to judicial review by the Ca-
were key policy tools in the Communist approach to
nadian Supreme Court under the Canadian Charter of
national minorities.
Rights and Freedoms. They do not want their members to be able to challenge band decisions in the
22. For the ubiquity of this process, see Gellner (1983).
courts of the mainstream society.
23. See the related analysis in de Sousa Santos (1996). He argues that attention to the claims of indigenous
29. See also the analysis in David Schneiderman, `Human
peoples and ethnic minorities can help develop a
Rights, Fundamental Differences? Multiple Charters
new `non-hegemonic' conception of human rights
in a Partnership Frame', in Beyond the Impasse, edited
which would retain its commitment to protecting
by Guy Laforest and Roger Gibbins (Montreal, In-
the
weak
and
vulnerable
without
serving
as
stitute for Research on Public Policy, forthcoming).
an
30. Joseph Carens, `Citizenship and Aboriginal Self-Gov-
instrument of western colonialism (for example on
ernment' (paper prepared for the Royal Commission
p. 353).
on Aboriginal Peoples, Ottawa, 1994).
24. As a general rule, we should be wary about the claims of elite members of a group to speak authoritatively
31. To be sure, some Indian tribal constitutions are not
about the group's `traditions'. Some individuals may
fully liberal or democratic, and so are inadequate from
claim to speak for the group as a whole, and may say
a human rights point of view, but they are forms of
that the group is united against the imposition of
constitutional government, and so should not be
`alien' ideas of human rights. But in reality, these
equated with mob rule or despotism. As Graham
people may simply be protecting their privileged
Walker notes, it is a mistake to conflate the ideas
position from internal challenges to their interpreta-
of liberalism and constitutionalism. There is a genuine
tion of the group's culture and traditions. In other
category of non-liberal constitutionalism which pro-
words, debates over the legitimacy of human rights
vides meaningful checks on political authority and
should
over
preserves the basic elements of natural justice, and
whether to subordinate local cultural traditions to
which thereby helps ensure that governments main-
transnational human rights standards, although this is
tain their legitimacy in the eyes of their subjects. See
how conservative members of the group may put it.
Walker, `The Idea of Non-Liberal Constitutionalism',
not
necessarily
be
seen
as
debates
in Kymlicka and Shapiro (eds.) (1997), pp. 154±84.
Instead, debates over human rights are often debates over who within the community should have the
Âaume (1995). 32. Re
authority to influence or determine the interpretation
33. As I said earlier, I do not think that the substantive
of the community's traditions and culture. When
interests protected by human rights doctrines are
individual members of the group demand their `hu-
either
man rights', they often do so in order to be able to
may well be that to talk of these interests in terms
participate in the community's process of interpreting
of `rights' is a specifically European invention which
its traditions.
does not fit comfortably with the discourse or self-
individualistic
or
Eurocentric.
However,
it
Minority
understandings of many cultures. I don't think we
Groups', in Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, edited by
should get hung up on `rights talk'. What matters,
Ruth Chadwick, (San Diego, CA: Academic Press,
morally speaking, is that people's substantive interests
forthcoming).
in life and liberty are protected, but we should be
25. For
a
typology,
see
my
`Ethnocultural
open-minded about what institutional mechanisms
26. For an acute criticism of existing minority rights
49
WILL KYMLICKA
best provide this protection. There is no reason to
of the language of rights as Eurocentric, see Turpel
assume that the best way to reliably protect people's
(1990). On ways to protect the substantive human
basic interests will always take the form of a judicially
interests underlying human rights without using the
enforceable constitutional list of `rights'. For a critique
language of `rights', see Pogge (1995).
50
4
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP Andrew Vincent
The central argument of this chapter is that liberal-
sically committed to agency and individualism, then
ism has a strong conceptual relationship with `citi-
liberalism is the most succinct modern bearer of
zenship' yet citizenship, in turn, has an ambiguous
citizenship claims. This argument is problematic,
conceptual relationship with nationalism. `Liberal
as we shall see. If, however, we can accept the
citizenship' is thus at the interstice between two
compound `liberal citizenship', then there are further
potentially contradictory forces.
implications which follow from the intrinsic logic of both citizenship and liberal beliefs.
There are two theses implicit in the issue of liberalism and citizenship, which need to be exam-
These can be summed up in the concept of
ined. The first concerns the cosmopolitan implica-
`cosmopolitanism'. The argument for this claim is
tion of liberal citizenship; the second concerns the
as follows: the core values of liberal citizenship ±
criteria for citizenship in liberal states.
autonomy, agency, individualism, liberty, rights,
First, intuitively, we tend to see a close conceptual
equality, justice and so forth ± are universalising
relation between liberalism and citizenship. This
values. They contain an intrinsic logic which shows
relation has deep philosophical roots, bound up with
that when dealing with the justice, rights or free-
ideas of self-determination, autonomy and individu-
doms of human beings there are no rational grounds
alism. The citizen is conceived as markedly different
to stop at state boundaries. In other words, to think
from the subject by dint of possessing, intrinsically,
within the ontology of liberal citizenship is to think
agency. Citizenship denotes choice, an opportunity
oneself into cosmopolitanism. This logic would
or space to act. It thus links conceptually with
account for the stress often laid on human rights,
freedom and agency. This intrinsic connection also
international justice, cosmopolitan democracy and
combines with other fundamental ideas in liberal
the like by many liberal theories. Boundaries be-
thought ± conscience, rights, equality, free speech
come morally arbitrary in this context, since we are
and so forth. Thus, there is a more than fortuitous
dealing with humanity as a single moral category.
connection between citizenship and liberalism. In
This consideration leads to the concept of `inter-
the last two centuries, citizenship has been integrally
national' or `global citizenship'. Now there are
part of a web of liberal values and beliefs.
many problems here, not least the legal, moral,
Second, citizenship has a complex and diverse
political and social implications of this concept.
etymological history which will be analysed here.
However, my central claim is that it is `concep-
In light of this chapter's critical focus upon the link
tually' natural for us (`natural' in the sense that it
with liberalism, it might nevertheless be claimed that
appears to be an unforced implication of the con-
since liberalism, above all other social and political
cepts we use) to read cosmopolitanism into liberal
theories, embodies a belief in moral and political
citizenship. The impact of Kant's thought upon the
individualism and agency, and citizenship is intrin-
modern western intellectual psyche has been pro-
51
ANDREW VINCENT
1
found here. It is, therefore, a short step from being a
universe.'
good liberal citizen to being a good member of
tractive to Christian thinkers like St Augustine. For
Amnesty International or being a proponent of
Stoics, we dwell both in the community of our birth
international human rights.
and the community of human argument, reason and
This argument alone made Stoicism at-
My own response to this is deeply ambivalent. The
aspiration. Our decisive moral values come from the
core intuition concerning cosmopolitanism is im-
latter, which is a moral, not a legal community. This
mensely compelling, but it also contains some quite
does not deny the separateness of peoples, but it
fundamental problems. The deepest problem relates
argues that such `separateness' is relatively unimpor-
to the link between nationality and citizenship.
tant in comparison with the wider moral community.
My discussion will first flesh out the cosmopolitan
Thus, world citizenship should be our ultimate moral
intuition. Secondly, it will examine the ambiguity of
focus.
liberalism itself. Thirdly, it will review the diverse
The cosmopolitan view, developed under the
senses of citizenship and the ambiguous relation with
aegis of Christianised natural law thinking, surfaces
nationalism. Overall, the chapter draws attention to
again most significantly (for the last century) in the
a complex of ideas which form an unresolved subtext
work of Kant.
to much current, legal, moral and political thought.
Pogge, most cosmopolitan arguments contain, firstly,
Hence it seeks to illuminate the dimensions of the
a commitment to individualism as against commu-
problem and indicate an important topic for further
nities or tribes; secondly, a belief in universalism,
research, one which liberals have tended to overlook
namely that all humans are valued equally; and,
but which exposes considerable tensions at the heart
thirdly, a sense of generality, that is that cosmopo-
of their political thinking.
litan concerns are not limited to specific regimes.
2
For a modern Kantian, like Thomas
Persons are of concern to everyone, wherever they are. Our fellow countrymen are no more or less
A Cosmopolitan Intuition
important than anyone else in the world. Pogge also
As suggested, the central premise of this argument is
distinguishes types of cosmopolitanism. `Legal' cos-
that citizenship embodies a strong conception of
mopolitanism is committed to a concrete juridical or
agency which is, in turn, a central value for liberal-
governmental order under which people will have
ism. Citizenship ± although a concept with a broader
equal basic rights, as in international courts on hu-
ambit ± can therefore be seen as a very important
man rights or international codes and covenants.
element of the liberal perspective, a characteristic
Most commentators see the central problem here of
liberal motif. The `citizen' can literally (and for-
jurisdiction, namely, will the courts be able to en-
mally) denote the individual person (agent) with
force their rulings? `Moral' cosmopolitanism, on the
basic legal or moral rights to life, freedom, con-
other hand, holds that all persons stand in certain
science and association.
moral relations to each other ± mutual concern or
However, the central purpose of this section is to
respect is incumbent upon us. Every human being is 3
substantiate the argument that liberalism embodies,
therefore an ultimate unit of moral concern.
in turn, an underlying cosmopolitan impetus and
cosmopolitanism can, however, vary in its content
that the logic of liberal citizenship would appear to
with different moral positions. It can thus require
be directed towards a global perspective. One of the
simply leaving individuals alone and not harming
first western philosophies to expound this cosmopo-
them (which might equate with a more passive sense
litan perspective was Stoicism. It involved a quite
of civil citizenship), or taking a definite responsi-
conscious rejection of the singularity and bounded
bility for others, even distant individuals (which
citizenship of the Greek city-state. The citizen/bar-
might entail strong civic duties).
barian
distinction,
common
to
such
Moral
Hellenic
The basic `logic of citizenship' argument would be
thought, was anathema to Stoics. As Marcus Aur-
this: citizenship, historically, has been used within
elius put it, `my city and my country, so far as I am
states to equalise, generalise and regularise treat-
Antonius, is Rome; but so far as I am a man, it is the
ment, thus preventing exclusionary practices within
52
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP
states. If citizenship, within the state, is used against
Nussbaum
therefore
contends
that
we should
exclusionary practices, why not extend it to `exclu-
automatically educate ourselves and our children
sionary practices' beyond state boundaries? An ex-
in a cosmopolitan mode of thought. In so doing,
clusionary practice remains an exclusionary practice
first, we will learn more about ourselves. Education
wherever it appears. What is so significant about
which
state boundaries?
courages irrationality. To be ignorant of humanity
focuses
within
national
boundaries
en-
Citizenship is thus embroiled in the logic of a
is to be ignorant about ourselves. Second, we can
universalising ethics which does not necessarily have
only make headway solving international problems if
to stop at the national boundary. Rights before the
we acknowledge global issues. The air that citizens
law, rights of participation and freedom, justice, the
breathe and the water they drink, for example, are
requirement for consent, and duties to promote a
not confined by national boundaries. Third, we
social good (all implicit within citizenship), are all
should be troubled by the fact that our high living
potentially universalisable. Thus, for Andrew Link-
standards are not more widely available. We should
later, recent theorists like Charles Beitz and Ju È rgen
therefore train children in a basic universalising
Habermas who appear to be engaging in this kind of
`Kantian awareness', otherwise we will nurture only
reasoning `universalise ideas about consent and dia-
hypocrites. Nussbaum remarks that if `we do believe
logue which are intrinsic to citizenship in the domes-
that all human beings are created equal and endowed
tic domain' and `enlarge the meaning of citizenship by
with certain inalienable rights, we are morally re-
conferring rights of participation on every member of
quired to think about what that conception requires
the species.'
4
Moral universalism thus arises automa-
us to do.'
tically out of domestic liberal citizenship.
7
We should work to acquire knowledge
that will enable us to consider these rights seriously.
One comparatively recent example of the above
Fourth, nationalist writers often seek to encourage
argument is deployed by Martha Nussbaum. Using a
nationals to join hands across racial or economic
Stoic analogy, she contends that we should think of
divisions; why, asks Nussbaum, stop at the arbitrary
ourselves as surrounded by concentric circles: the
boundary of the nation ± `what is it about the
self, the family, the neighbourhood, the city, the
national boundary that magically converts people
country and humanity. We cannot ignore our lo-
towards whom we are both incurious and indifferent
cality, but we must work to make all humans part of
into people to whom we have duties of mutual
our community, drawing all the circles to the centre.
respect?' Multicultural respect within a nation must
For
Nussbaum,
we
should
`recognise
lead to wider world respect. The `respect argument',
humanity wherever it occurs, and give its funda-
in nationalist writers, must carry us in this direction.
mental ingredients, reason and moral capacity, our
These arguments of Nussbaum's clearly illustrate the
first allegiance as respect.'
5
therefore
8
logic-of-citizenship argument, which Linklater as-
She puts the point well
sociates also with Beitz, Pogge and Habermas.
when she states that
Some of these cosmopolitan ideas have been I believe that . . . [the] emphasis on patriotic
translated into deeply practical concerns. The liberal
pride is both morally dangerous and, ultimately,
rights of the citizen to freedom, conscience, proce-
subversive of some of the worthy goals patriotism
dural justice, speech, or to dissent, can also be seen as
sets out to serve . . . These goals . . . would be
universal `human' rights. Although there are pro-
better served by an ideal that is any case more
blems
adequate to our situation in the contemporary
rights have also been codified and translated into
world, namely the very old idea of the cosmopo-
positive legal rights. So far the main obstacle to the
litan, the person whose allegiance is to the world-
full realisation of such rights has been persuading
wide community.
6
with
ratification
and
application,
human
states to agree and work with the United Nations and International Courts. The global citizen is there-
Even good nationalism ultimately subverts the values
fore one who simply acknowledges universal human
it upholds.
rights and believes, either on a personal level or on
53
ANDREW VINCENT
9
the institutional level of international courts and
and must take precedence over collective goals.
conventions, that he or she should accept the duties
Michael Walzer characterises this procedural liberal-
correlative to such rights.
ism as
There is a major problem here, namely that statebased citizens have a rich panoply of well-established
committed in the strongest possible way to in-
positive rights, whereas the global citizen's rights are,
dividual rights and, almost as a deduction from
in comparison, thin. One way out of this dilemma for
this, to a rigorously neutral state, that is, a state
some theorists would be to argue for an extension of
without cultural or religious projects or, indeed,
international legal organisations, expanded interna-
any sorts of collective goals beyond freedom and
tional courts of human rights and at the most ex-
physical security.'
10
treme end, an elected parliament at the United Nations. In the latter scenario, states which recog-
This is a view that one finds, according to Charles
nised cosmopolitan citizenship would provide full
Taylor, in writers like Rawls, Dworkin and Acker-
diplomatic and economic support to the UN, pro-
man.
mote arms control, uphold human rights, and pro-
substantive view about the ends of human life.
vide
generous
foreign
aid.
These
ideas
11
This conception of liberal society has no
are
Rather, society is united behind an idea of equal
speculative, although not overly so. The fact that
respect. For Taylor, the roots to this procedural view
we have international commissions, like that on
are very deep. Kant is probably the single most
Global Governance with their report Our Global
important figure articulating this perspective. Hu-
Neighbourhood, indicates that many take such ideas
man dignity focuses on autonomy and the ability of
very seriously. As such the logic of global citizenship
the individual to determine their own notion of the
certainly shows little sign of diminishing in world
good life. Taylor has his own thoughts on the
politics.
problems that this notion of liberalism has caused
The discussion now turns to three crucial, over-
in the Canadian situation. For him, procedural
lapping ambiguities, which are often glossed over, in
liberalism enshrines a politics of equal respect which
the above arguments. These are, first, the ambiguity
is hostile or indifferent to difference, because it
of liberalism itself; second, the ambiguity of citizen-
insists on the uniform application of rights and is
ship qua liberalism; and thirdly, the ambiguous rela-
thus suspicious of any collective goal.
tion of nationalism, liberalism and citizenship. By
Second, social or `new' liberalism appeared in
explaining and analysing each, the nature of liberal-
Britain in the 1880s and 1890s, although variants
ism's problem here will become more fully apparent.
also developed in America with John Dewey, in Italy with writers such as Guido de Ruggiero, and in Germany in the writings of Albert Lange and Karl
Liberalism
Ènder. Social liberal thought was committed to Vorla
Is liberalism a clear doctrine such that we could
collective welfare goals pursued through the state. It
postulate a particular understanding of a potentially
was thus statist, but not overtly nationalist. Essen-
cosmopolitan citizenship, as outlined in the previous
tially, social liberals were reacting to certain themes
section? The quickest response is `no': differing
present within classical liberalism, notions like ato-
conceptions
re-
mised individualism, the negative conception of
sponses to the question. There have been many
liberty, the radically free market economy and mini-
typologies of liberalism and so, to survey such re-
mal state theory. They wished to replace these with a
sponses, the following argument draws a distinction
more socialised, holistic and developmental under-
between three types of liberalism: classical liberalism,
standing of the individual, a more `positive' concep-
social liberalism and cultural liberalism.
tion of liberty linked to notions like self-realisation
of
liberalism
provide
divergent
First, the classical view (a predominantly proce-
and self-development, a conception of a mixed
dural view, certainly in its modern guise), which
economy and a more responsive, collectivised and
insists that individual rights must always come first
ethical conception of the state. State intervention
54
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP
was premised upon the common good and the full
might not share beliefs with social liberals about, say,
realisation of human personalities. It implied a de-
the market. It only affirms that culture is immensely
licate balance between self-government and corpo-
important for choice and that groups, as well as
rate government action. The new liberals were, in
individuals, have rights. There is therefore nothing
effect, developing the embryonic form of the Wol-
inherently to stop cultural liberalism from being
fartstaat. Their arguments were rooted in evolution-
assimilated with either an older variant of classical
ary theory, social utilitarianism and philosophical
liberalism (one less overtly procedural, like J. S.
idealism.
12
Mill's liberalism) or, alternatively, social liberalism.
Thirdly, cultural liberalism, which developed in
Cultural liberalism might thus legitimately share a
reaction particularly to procedural liberalism. Cul-
classical liberal antipathy to distributive justice and
tural liberals promote the conception of collective
the welfare state ± especially if the existent cultures
cultural goods, such as the French language for the
embody that antipathy. It therefore seems to have no
Quebeckers. This view of liberalism has been devel-
specific economic or political content.
oped by Will Kymlicka, among others and it claims
Secondly, cultural liberalism arrests, but does not
that classical, procedural liberalism overemphasises
undermine, the argument for citizenship leading to
individual rights against collective goals. For classical
cosmopolitanism. Because cultural liberalism tends
liberals, communities (and cultural goals) have no
to be more sympathetic to liberal nationalism, its
moral existence. For Kymlicka, however, group and
universalising appeal is stunted. Thirdly, because
individual rights are not necessarily opposed. He thus
social liberalism is statist and centralist in content,
tries to defend group rights within the framework of
it is ideologically antipathetic to classical liberalism.
cultural liberalism. The crux of his move is to suggest
It would also have little sympathy with cultural goods
that when we exercise our liberty it `is determined by
and group rights. Further and crucially, because it
13
Agency requires culture.
sees citizenship in the context of the state, it would
Culture provides the content of choice, its norms
also inhibit the force of any cosmopolitan argument.
and historical heritage. Thus, `the primary good
Fourthly, classical liberalism is intrinsically critical of
being recognised is the cultural community as a
the statism of social liberalism. It also feels deep
our cultural heritage.'
14
Contrary to his perception of
unease with the cultural goods and group rights being
communitarians, Kymlicka thinks that we can ab-
pursued at the expense of individual rights and
stract ourselves from ways of life and criticise them.
procedural justice.
context of choice.'
We can be thus `unencumbered'. We do not just
Thus classical liberalism is, oddly, most susceptible
discover views and we are not haplessly trapped by
to the cosmopolitan thesis outlined in the previous
them. Cultural liberalism, therefore, distinguishes
section. It is, literally, much easier to universalise the
fundamental liberties from privileges and immu-
generic negative individual rights of classical liberal-
nities. Provided the exponents of collective goals
ism ± life, liberty, property. Yet, at the same time,
and cultural goods respect the fundamental rights of
most recent postcolonial writers see classical liberal-
minorities and individuals, they can still be consid-
ism as the expression, par excellence, of a particular
ered liberal. This liberalism is seen as more sensitive
historically oppressive community. In this latter
to `cultural survivals' and, for Taylor, is the most
scenario, minimal generic rights are no longer con-
relevant model for contemporary porous and cultu-
sidered through the lens of cosmopolitanism, but
rally diverse societies. Liberalism has to do more than
rather through imperialism. This critical argument
let differences exist. It has to recognise the `worth' of
has, paradoxically, been applied to the treatment of
different cultures.
internal minorities, even within the USA, by Iris
Some very general claims can be made concerning
Marion Young. Rights-talk and notions of neutrality
liberalism and cosmopolitanism from this brief sur-
are conceived of as modes of group and cultural
vey. First, cultural liberalism is the least politically
domination.
distinctive of the three in that it tells us little about the nature of the state or welfare. Thus, it might or
55
ANDREW VINCENT
Ás's use of the term `active citizen'. on aspects of Sieye
Citizenship
However, the active sense of the citizen also refers
The upshot of the previous section is the suggestion
(in my use) to a more rigorous conception of political
that, given the profoundly contestable character of
involvement, which was revealed at certain mo-
liberalism, the initial intuition concerning cosmo-
ments during the French revolution, and harks back
politan citizenship looks less secure. Indeed, some
to an older civic tradition. In my usage, the active
senses of liberalism might be at odds with cosmopo-
conception conceives of the citizen as politically
litanism. The same observation also applies to citi-
involved and identified with the wider community.
zenship itself, as this section will now demonstrate by
Such an idea can be found ± in differing formats ± in
surveying examples of both its theory and empirical
the doctrines of Aristotelianism, some civic repub-
practice.
licanism and the later Rousseauist and Hegelian
On the theoretical level, there are certain con-
traditions. It can also be found implicitly in some
ceptual parameters which reveal the dimensions of
recent expressions in communitarian thought. The
the concept. These parameters are active and passive
active/passive divide bears some conceptual parallels
notions of the citizen, the character of rights and
with the distinction, made by Benjamin Constant,
duties and their correlativity. The origin of the terms
between ancient and modern liberty. Another way of
`active' and `passive' is debatable, but they can be
formulating it is in terms of `civic citizenship' and
 Sieye Ás. (Sieye Ás's found in the writings of the Abbe
`civil citizenship'. The civic idea corresponds with
use is not quite my present usage, although there are
the activist vision and the civil with the more passive
sufficient parallels to warrant discussion here.) For
tradition.
Ás, passive citizenship referred essentially to the Sieye
The category of civic or active citizenship is the
natural and civil rights of individuals. Such rights
oldest view. The good of the individual citizen was
concern the protection of all persons equally in their
seen as closely tied to the common good of the polis.
Ás, despite the fact that liberty and property. For Sieye
It implied, say, for Aristotle, minimally, membership
all persons within a state possess passive rights, not
of a city-state, the possession of certain claims and
all can take part in the `formation of public power'.
duties, the duty to participate in the adjudication
Passive citizenship is thus available to all. Active
processes of the polis (at least in Athens) and, finally,
citizens, on the other hand, are those who `contri-
an inner capacity for rational virtue, entailing the
bute to the public establishment' and can be likened
internalisation of communal norms ± an art of both
to `true shareholders in the great social enterprise'.
ruling and being ruled. The themes of political self-
At the time, active citizenship excluded women,
discipline, public spirit, a conception of the common
foreigners and children, who were all regarded as
good, unease with private gain and self-interest, and
`passive citizens'. However, within the class or group
a belief in simplicity and piety of life were reasserted
of `active citizens' no one has more rights than
in the later civic republican tradition. Again, the
anyone else.
active citizen was one who (mythically or not) gladly
It is worth noting here that active citizens are not
and intelligently participated in the promotion of
Ás primarily in the context of rights. discussed by Sieye
the public good. The civic world of the small city-
Active citizenship, although it incorporated concep-
state was more overtly small-scale and defensive in its
tions of political voting rights, also included a sense
stance. Its citizenry, despite being mobilised to a
of higher vocation. Taking part in the `great public
common task were, nonetheless, premised upon a
Ás in terms of the enterprises' is seen more by Sieye
large body of non-citizen slaves and foreign workers.
performance of public duties. He thus remarks that,
The spectre of civic citizenship developed once more
`it is a major error to envisage the exercise of public
with the rise of nationalism in the nineteenth cen-
power as a right; it is . . . a duty. The officers of the
tury. Its ethos, though, was `more creative and
nation are distinguished from other citizens only in
protective,
having more duties.'
15
fence.'
In terms of the present discussion I wish to pick up
stressing
liberation
rather
than
de-
16
However it is couched, one major criticism of
56
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP
`civic citizenship' is that, at its extreme, the citizen
it also incorporates political rights to vote or stand
will be asked to participate continuously in every
for office. The argument about political rights de-
aspect of political life. The public realm would
pends upon how significant one regards them; it is
totally absorb the private realm of the individual.
arguable that such rights can still be viewed as quasi-
Liberals, from Constant to Isaiah Berlin, have been
passive notions. As one recent writer has noted, `the
profoundly worried by such arguments as potentially
occasional visit to the polling booth has seemed to
undermining the value of individual liberty and
many a pathetically inadequate definition of citizen-
privacy. Ralf Dahrendorf has referred to this com-
ship.'
munal conception as the `total citizen'.
17
18
Some writers, like Schumpeter, have of
The total
course made a virtue of this quasi-passivity. How-
citizen and the total state would be seen, in this
ever, the intuition to grasp here is the point that
argument, as two sides of the same coin.
political citizenship, as it has been conventionally
The civil citizen, on the other hand, is a product of
understood, can be viewed as constrained, passive
the era of developing individualism and embryonic
and perfectly in accord with classical liberal theory.
liberal thought. The citizen is understood as separate
In sum, citizenship in classical liberal thought is
and, at least partially preformed, with desires, inter-
generally confined to a relatively narrow field, being
ests and often basic (natural) rights. The function of
defined in terms of constrained political rights to
a constitutional legal order is to protect and uphold
political involvement, combined with legal or civil
these fundamental interests or rights. Citizenship is
rights of persons, their liberty and their property,
thus conceived more negatively in terms of the legal
which prohibit mutual coercion. Classical liberal
protection of pre-existing rights to life, liberty and
thought on citizenship
property. The private moralities of the individual are
and entitlements to economic and social resources.
generally
excludes rights
distinct from the formal but minimal public ethics of
A well-established criticism of civil citizenship is
citizenship. For classical liberal theorists, although
that it is too minimalist. It ignores the socially and
individuals may have lost some of the benefits of
historically embedded (or encumbered) character of
close communal life, nonetheless they gained from
individuals and abandons any clear sense of perfec-
the privacy, modern liberty and new-found prosper-
tionism, community and nationality. This is a char-
ity of commercial liberal society. Later nineteenth-
acteristic
and twentieth-century versions of this understanding
consequentialist liberal individualism, to the present
of citizenship extends further into features like po-
day, by communitarians. The citizen of deontological
litical representation.
liberal individualism could be described as a `mini-
criticism
made
of
deontological
and
mal citizen', essentially being the other side of the
Civil citizenship, in my usage, is thus more con-
minimal state.
ventionally associated with classical liberalism, implying negative rights (understood largely as `side-
Turning now to the parameters of rights and
constraints') to protection of one's person, property
duties, the older tradition of civic or active citizen-
and liberty. The classical liberal view of citizenship
ship did not have such a rich vocabulary of rights at
thus favours limited political rule, a framework of
its disposal. Aristotelian-influenced proponents of
laws and minimal welfare. Markets are the preferred
active citizenship tended to speak more in terms
technique for allocation of resources. Essentially, this
of the duties of the citizen or what was due to the
is a more procedural view of politics. Politics does
citizen. The assertion of the importance for citizens
not pursue any particular social or moral goals. The
to perform their civic duty was not therefore neces-
consequences of this for citizenship are that indivi-
sarily premised on any correlative right, rather what
duals secure maximum negative liberty. They are left
was due to and from the common good. Later ex-
alone and free from coercion. The good citizen
ponents of a more active vision of citizenship, like T.
therefore upholds the rule of law and equal liberty
H. Green, transformed this form of argument into
for all. This is the conventional liberal Rechtstaat.
the vocabulary of rights, although, characteristically,
However, this is not a purely passive conception
it was usually the vocabulary of social (ethicised)
within classical liberal thought. In my own reading,
rights, not natural or human rights. Such socio-legal
57
ANDREW VINCENT
rights were also usually conceptually tied ± in the
lective goals and claims to collective resources.
case of Idealist thinkers ± to a conception of the
Social citizenship, as it developed in the twentieth
common good.
century, was more characteristic of a different species
The civic citizenship tradition also embodied a
of liberalism ± social liberalism. In many ways social
strong correlativity thesis. Rights were premised on
liberalism was a hybrid of the civic and civil forms of
the common good. Such rights implied that the
citizenship. The social liberal case is essentially that
citizen had correlative duties to that good. Citizen-
individual citizens are morally justified in claiming a
ship was not just a juridical category or an indication
particular economic status and a right to resources,
of nationality. It implied rather the consciousness of
via the welfare state and social justice. The social
the ends of human life as embodied in the institu-
liberal theorist therefore wants to extend arguments
tional forms of the public life. It was thus an ethical
beyond civil and political rights to social rights.
disposition, where the individual developed to a
Marshall recognised that this created immense pro-
level of self-consciousness and ethical awareness
blems and strains for a liberal capitalist society ±
inclusive enough to be identified with the public
problems which he never claimed to resolve. The more empirical approach to the citizenship
sphere of the whole community. The conception of definite individualistic rights
issue raises a different range of problems. First,
was more characteristic of civil citizenship. Rights
citizenship ± despite all that has been said earlier
expressed, ontologically, the separate or independent
± empirically is a technique of exclusion. The state is
identity of individuals. They were claims asserted
a state of a bounded citizenry. It is about closure.
against other individuals, groups or states. The more
Citizenship creates the concept of a foreigner, an
general of such rights ± natural and human rights ±
alien. Second, the character of citizenship changes
were fundamental claims to life, liberty, happiness,
between state traditions, even liberal-democratic
property, speech, opinion, association and so forth.
states. This change is one that crucially cross-cuts
Such rights correlated loosely with duties of forbear-
the civic/civil distinction outlined above.
ance or non-interference, usually with the proviso
The two best-known ways of conceiving the citi-
that such rights did not overtly injure or harm others.
zen has been the jus soli and the jus sanguinis con-
They did not, characteristically, demand positive
ceptions. Jus sanguinis associates citizenship with
public action by any individual ± except in the duty
direct descent and blood relations. If one can trace
to discharge one's debts and fulfil contracts. They
direct blood or birthright descent then citizenship is
were usually more negatively protective rights, im-
automatic. In jus soli citizenship follows prolonged
plying passive and relatively costless duties. This
residence or birth within a territory. There are
latter conception of rights is, to some extent, en-
usually combinations of these in most countries.
capsulated in the categories of civil and political
Thus, in the UK since 1981, where one parent must
citizenship, discussed by T. H. Marshall in his locus
be lawfully resident and settled, then birth in the
classicus account of citizenship, Citizenship and Social
territory gives citizenship. France and Germany offer
Class. For Marshall, civil citizenship, which he saw
purer examples of the two conceptions.
developing from the early eighteenth century, im-
Two phenomena affected the German case ± the
plied a comprehensive equality of rights to civil
Prussian state and romanticism. The Prussian state
freedoms, which might broadly be called `constitu-
view of the citizen was a corollary of the absolutist
tional' freedoms. Political citizenship, which devel-
state in intrinsic conflict with the older, medieval
oped
century,
Standestaat. Territorial residence took precedence in
concerned the extension of suffrage rights, namely
the Prussian conception. The romantic movement
the right to participate in the political process which
provided more of a background `pattern of thought'.
determines the condition of one's life.
The aesthetic socio-historical idiom of romanticism
gradually
over
the
nineteenth
The problematic category in the Marshall schema
was ideally suited for the misty formulations of
is `social citizenship'. It was still deeply individualis-
ethnocultural ideas, namely conceptions of unique-
tic and rights-orientated, but it also embodied col-
ness, inwardness, feeling over reason and organic
58
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP
growth over conscious artifice. These latter ideas
would be the bad citizen. Self-determination (in
provided a frame for jus sanguinis, developing be-
individuals or nations) was conceived in terms of
tween 1871 and 1913. Before 1913, German citizen-
the universal demand for liberty. The doctrine of the
ship was a partly contradictory affair. The older
`citizen' and the `citizen-nation' moved hand-in-
Prussian absolutist model of the citizen ± as member
hand. Republican ideology usually emphasised mili-
of territorial community ± jostled with the ethno-
tary service as a key factor here. Schools and the
cultural `community of descent' idea. It was the latter
army were engines of assimilation. Second- and
which won out, largely in 1913 with citizenship
third-generation immigrants in France became citi-
legislation which established the concept of Aus-
zens and were expected to save the nation militarily.
landsdeutsche. This legislation aimed at the preserva-
National purpose and assimilation were reinforced in
tion of the pure German Volkstum. Citizenship was
the Third Republic by the civilising mission of the
severed from questions of residence. Blood and des-
French nation. French citizenship was therefore al-
cent now became critical.
ways a peculiar brand of chauvinism and universal-
The difference between the Wilhelmine and the
ism. Before the 1870s it was very much a liberal and
National Socialist ideas of citizenship was that in the
radical push; after the 1870s it migrated to the right,
latter there was a definite ideology of ethnocultural
reaching an ascendancy in the Dreyfus Affair. The
dominance, coupled with the desire to deprive groups
left still, however, promulgated universalism through
of citizenship. In the Wilhelmine case, the ideology
imperialism.
was not so well-developed and the desire was rather
Ethnocultural criteria did appear in France in the 20
to prevent immigrants acquiring citizenship. As Ro-
mid-1800s.
gers Brubaker comments, `remarkably, German citi-
the citizen lost some of its universalising aspect. In
zenship today remains governed by a law of the
Arthur de Gobineau's work citizenship and nation-
Wilhelmine period.' He continues:
alism began to take on racial dimensions, a theme
As they developed, the French idea of
reflected in Taine, Renan and Thierry, particularly As a result of this continuity across two world
after the Franco-Prussian war. Still, the issue of
wars, three regime changes, and the division and
citizenship has exercised the French Republican
reunification of the country, the marked restric-
tradition, even to the present day. Whereas the
tiveness of citizenship law towards non-German
Dreyfusard ethnocultural line of thought is still
immigrants was carried over from the Wilhelmine
represented
Germany into the Federal Republic and, in 1990,
thought remains motivated by an underlying, if
into the new German nation-state. The 1913
semi-dormant, cosmopolitanism.
in
the
Front
Nationale,
republican
system of jus sanguinis, with no trace of jus soli continues to determine the citizenship status of immigrants and their descendants today.
Nationality, Liberalism and Citizenship
19
How does citizenship link up liberalism and nationIt is important to note here (in my reading) that we
ality? The French case is particularly instructive here.
are still looking at a liberal state in Germany, but its
French citizenship traditionally involved a core of
citizenship is deeply exclusive and measured by blood
universal human or natural rights. The declaration of
descent. Something does not seem to be quite right
1789 speaks stridently of the rights of `man' and
here.
`citizen'. The rights involved are `imprescriptible'
The French case is more interesting yet for my
and `inalienable', and governments are instituted
purpose, namely the question concerning the uni-
to uphold them. Thus, `the end of all political
versalising aspect of citizenship. In the French case,
associations, is the preservation of the natural and
jus soli is predominant. The drive for citizenship was
imprescriptible rights of man'. The French National
always state-centred and assimilationist. It was part
Assembly `recognises such ``sacred'' rights. It does not
of a revolutionary republican tradition. In its purest
create them. All men are all born free and equal, with
universalist reading, the only foreigner in France
respect to these rights'; thus `civil distinctions can be
59
ANDREW VINCENT
founded only on public utility.' Yet, at the same time
fore, a central motif within liberalism, and liberalism
as these assertions, the nation is also conceived of as
has always believed in equality of individual rights,
sovereign. Thus, no individual or group are `entitled
regardless of race, gender, class or birth. In the
to any authority which is not expressly derived from
French Republican tradition particularly, in the
it.'
classical liberal tradition, there has been a strong
So what is the relation between the nation and the
leaning to some form of cosmopolitanism. Yet, co-
universal cosmopolitan rights of man? The pro-
existing with this universalising dialectic is the na-
foundly direct (but also equivocal) answer is that
tion ± usually read through the state. As Rogers
the nation is the will of the whole community of
Brubaker has put it:
citizens and it embodies the imprescriptible rights of humanity within its own prescriptions. Law and
Almost all [states] claim to derive state power
government, as an expression of the national will,
from and exercise it for (and not simply over) a
are only there to give `security to the rights of man
nation . . . A state is a nation-state in this
and of citizens'. Thus, `the acts of the legislative and
minimal sense insofar as it claims (and is under-
executive powers of government, [can be] . . . every
stood) to be a nation's state: the state `of' and `for'
moment compared with the ends of political institu-
a particular, distinctive, bounded nation . . .
tions.'
21
How the state-bearing and state-justifying nation
is culturally or legally bounded is irrelevant; that it
The above forms the substance of my analysis of
is bounded is what matters.
this question and my key theme. Particularistic
22
nationalism and cosmopolitanism coexist, simultaneously, in liberal citizenship. Strikingly, it is actu-
One has only to think of the commonplace usage of
ally possible to assert simultaneously an extreme
`citizenship law', as directly synonymous with `na-
chauvinism and an extreme cosmopolitanism. In
tionality law', to see the truth of this point.
the case of jus sanguinis, the particularism and inclu-
The above observation creates an oddity in the
siveness comes to the fore unproblematically. Eth-
liberal argument outlined above. In the context of
nocultural
racism,
the nation, the citizen has rights which are premised
nationalism and cultural liberalism. The liberal ci-
citizenship
links
easily
with
on the natural arbitrariness of birth, even in the jus
tizenship/nationalism connection is thus more ob-
soli and liberal settings. In one sense, closure is
vious here. However, jus soli, particularly in the
pragmatically necessary, for the purposes of military
French republican tradition, reveals more clearly
service, taxation and public administration. Yet the
the intrinsic ambiguity of liberal citizenship, namely
nation, birth, citizen relation is stronger than simple
its continual alternation between cosmopolitanism
pragmatism. Given the history that liberalism re-
and particularism.
lates,
Liberalism, generically, often represents itself as a
and
given
its
lurking
cosmopolitanism,
something strange is taking place. As Brubaker
form of historical emancipation from older political
comments:
traditions ± the conventional portrayal of status to contract or the release from the medieval Standestaat.
[Citizenship] represents a striking exception to
Liberal citizenship sees itself as removing feudal
the secular trend away from ascribed statuses. And
shackles. It casts off the `subjecthood' status of in-
it is difficult to reconcile with a central claim ±
dividuals under absolute monarchy or feudalism.
perhaps the central claim of liberal political the-
Liberal rights theory thus rejects conceptions of
ory: the idea that political membership ought to
status based upon birth or position. There is, there-
be founded on individual consent.
23
fore, an insistent `progressive Whig' logic or dialectic to ideas of equality and freedom. Such ideas, it is
The ascription of rights based on birth or blood
suggested, cannot be checked by any hierarchical
descent is at odds with the panoply of liberal rights
regime. Liberal citizenship identified equal rights
and liberal agency, in general, and yet they all
with individuals as individuals. Citizenship is, there-
coexist within liberal citizenship.
60
LIBERALISM AND CITIZENSHIP
more cynical appraisal of this would be Gray's nicely
Conclusion
sour observation of `Kantianism in one country'. For
We can now appreciate exactly how liberal citizen-
Ackerman, the poor Europeans would, however, be
ship is at the interstice between contradictory forces,
condemned to be `rootless cosmopolitans'.
incorporating both an embracing cosmopolitanism
But note the problem in Ackerman's view of the
and an exclusive nationalism. There are, though, a
precise character of the national mission and liberal
number of forms of exclusion and some are more
universalism. There are a number of liberal states
problematic than others. But still the exclusions of
where global citizenship can be seen as an extension
citizenship do not rest easily with the cosmopolitan
of their own rights structures. Yet, different inter-
dialectic. The nationalist/birth connection of citi-
pretations of both liberalism and cosmopolitanism
zenship does not readily conjoin with the liberal
are inevitably involved. North Americans might
narrative. The two theses discussed in this chapter ±
well embrace generic liberal rights (on a civil level)
the cosmopolitan implication of liberal citizenship
but not widespread distributive justice (social and
and the potentially illiberal criteria for liberal citizen-
social-democratic rights) let alone specific cultural
ship ± present us with a dilemma. Another, possibly
rights. Social rights and demands for widespread
simpler, way of framing the unease here is through
redistribution would be a universalisation of civil
Veit Bader's recent reflections on transnational ci-
citizenship. Others might see distributive justice and
tizenship. Bader, reflecting procedural and cultural
social rights as a logical extension of human rights to
liberalism, remarks that procedural liberalism `has
life. If this happened, it would imply large transfers of
underestimated the importance of communities and
wealth across the globe. However, since this latter
cultures.' But cultural liberalism, which he describes
conception has been to date reliant upon social
as `communitarian liberalism', has actively taken
liberal or social-democratic sovereign states, it is
culture and nation on board, but to Bader has
an unlikely international scenario. France, on the
`not yet fully addressed the exclusionary effects of
other hand, would give full legal rights within its
communities and cultures.'
24
I would add to this the
Republican notion of citizenship. These would in-
point that even procedural liberalism subsists with
clude civil, political and social rights. But this would
radical exclusion.
not necessarily allow any special or cultural rights and would also imply an unacceptable level of im-
A number of thinkers appear to want to address
perial control.
this dilemma. Bruce Ackerman, for example, has 25
Lib-
Thus the implications of `liberalism' and `citizen-
eral universalism is seen to be virtually implicit
ship' seem to be inevitably linked ± but the tensions
within
described himself as a `rooted cosmopolitan'.
Conse-
and countervailing currents exposed here show just
quently, Ackerman is therefore provisionally per-
how the nature of this common fate remains pro-
suaded to `embrace the American Constitution'. A
foundly unclear.
the
United
States
Constitution.
Notes
1. Heater (1990), p. 12.
tional cosmopolitanism assigns moral responsibility
2. Kant argued for the moral autonomy of states within a
(for example, maintaining and promoting human
voluntary league of states committed to maintain peace.
rights) to institutional schemes. It is dependent upon
A liberal constitutional republic would thus be inclined,
the
in his view, to international peace. Liberal theory, qua
through institutions. Some argue, in this scenario,
Kant, conceives of citizenship in terms of contract and
for supranational state-like institutions to be set up.
consent. The citizen comes to the state ideally or actually
Interactional cosmopolitanism is `ethical' in the sense
with entitlements. The citizen will agree to limitations
that it assigns moral responsibility to individual or
for the common good. Liberal citizenship is thus a bearer
collective agencies. Each person is equally a subject of
or vehicle of rights within the state.
moral concern. Note that there is no necessary link
existence
and
maintenance
of
human
rights
3. Thomas Pogge proposes two forms of moral cosmo-
here between the institutional and interactional/ethi-
politanism: `institutional' and `interactional'. Institu-
cal types. One could therefore believe in the institu-
61
ANDREW VINCENT
accounts of the new liberalism can be found in
tional conception and not adhere to the ethical.
Vincent (1990).
Equally, one could be an ethical cosmopolitan and not believe in an institutional setting or, at least, a
13. Kymlicka (1989), p. 165.
central world state. Therefore, even if one rejects
14. Ibid., p. 172.
world government, it does not lead to a rejection of
15. Quoted in Forsyth (1987), pp. 117±19.
moral cosmopolitanism. See T. Pogge, `Cosmopolitan-
16. Kelley (1995), p. 91.
ism and Sovereignty', in Brown (ed.) (1994), pp. 89±
17. Dahrendorf (1974).
122.
18. Heater (1990), p. 96.
4. Linklater (1992), p. 32.
19. Brubaker (1994), p. 165.
5. M. Nussbaum, `Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism', in
20. Ibid., p. 99: `The legal nationality conferred by the state and the ethnocultural nationality invoked by the
Cohen (ed.) (1996), pp. 2±17, at p. 7. 6. Ibid., p. 4.
``principle
7. Ibid., p. 13.
things; the former may be conferred in utter disregard
8. Ibid., p. 14.
of the latter. Yet the thrust of the principle of nation-
9. This is close to Michael Sandel's use of the term
ality
was
of
nationality''
precisely
to
are
of
connect
course
the
two
different
±
not
`procedural republic' for this liberalism. See Sandel
directly . . . but indirectly via the redrawing of po-
(1984).
litical boundaries so as to make legal and ethnocultural nationality converge.'
10. Walzer, `Comment,' in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp.
21. Tom Paine's translation of the `Declaration of the
99±103, at p. 99; see also Habermas in the same
Rights of Man and of Citizens' by the National
volume, p. 123ff.
Assembly of France (1789), in Ritchie (ed.) (1954),
11. For Taylor, the `procedural' view is best encapsulated
pp. 291±2.
in Dworkin's early paper on `Liberalism'; see Taylor
22. Brubaker (1994), p. 28. Debates about both nation-
`The Politics of Recognition', in ibid., p. 56. 12. The term `new liberal' is immensely complex and
ality and citizenship are also closely associated with
contested. I have not attempted to examine it, but
distinct state traditions, although this is an even bigger issue.
have largely taken for granted in this chapter that we can speak of its ideology and social theory. This is by
23. Ibid., pp. 31±2.
no means an uncontroversial position. My own at-
24. See Bader (1997), p. 772.
tempt to summarise and assess some of the diverse
25. Ackerman (1994).
62
5
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR: LIBERALISM AND THE POWER OF THE NATION Margaret Canovan
When the terms `Liberal' and `Liberalism' first ar-
former is cosmopolitan in its appeal as well as its
rived in English politics in the early nineteenth
aspirations, though it is particularly well represented
century, they indicated support for national libera-
among political thinkers in the USA. The latter has
tion in Greece and South America.
1
The struggle of
always had a narrower academic base. On this side of
oppressed nations for freedom continued to be a
the Atlantic it is particularly (though not exclu-
liberal cause, so much so that liberalism has over
sively) associated with a school of political thinkers
the past two centuries been as closely associated with
influenced by Michael Oakeshott.
nationalism as internationalism.
2
4
To provide a
Revulsion against
frame for these two different sorts of liberalism, I
fascism after the Second World War weakened this
shall begin with some of Oakeshott's own reflections
association except in the case of anti-colonial move-
on two contrasted styles of politics, which corre-
ments; liberals became more wary of nationalism,
spond neatly to the versions of liberalism with which
and the dominant strand in liberal political thinking
we shall be concerned.
during the past half-century has been cosmopolitan. Even so, we have recently seen a revival of liberal
The Politics of Faith
nationalism among philosophers who argue that
and the Politics of Scepticism
liberal respect for individuals and their rights entails
Oakeshott was fond of dichotomous analyses of
respect for the national identities those individuals value.
3
political styles. His celebrated contrast between `rationalism in politics' and the practical activity of
Despite obvious tensions, therefore, liberalism and
5
nationalism do have affinities. I shall argue that the
`attending to the arrangements' of a society
connections go deeper than one might suppose and
followed by the more elaborate analysis in On Hu-
that even versions of liberalism that are explicitly
man Conduct of two opposed understandings of the
hostile to nationalism rely for much of their plausi-
modern state, as an `enterprise association' (universi-
bility on tacit assumptions about the presence and
tas) and in terms of `civil association' (societas).
efficacy of nationhood. I shall try to show that this is
Each of these contrasts carried the message that
equally true of two sharply opposed contemporary
the former of the two types of politics was dominant
versions of liberalism: on the one hand, the crusading
in the modern world but that the latter was to be
liberalism of universal human rights, and on the other
preferred. The contrast that concerns us here is a
the sceptical liberalism of limited government. The
third variant on the same theme, elaborated in an
63
was
6
MARGARET CANOVAN
essay (published posthumously) on `The Politics of
may seem unglamorous, `the sceptic understands
Faith and the Politics of Scepticism'. For the past five
order as a great and difficult achievement never
hundred years (according to Oakeshott), European
beyond the reach of decay and dissolution,'
politics has been marked by a tension between the
a political system that can properly carry out these
two
modest tasks is doing very well.
opposed
styles
named
in
the
essay's
title.
Although the two have mingled in practice, they
11
so that
Although these two styles of politics can be pre-
7
can in principle be characterised as opposites. These
sented in ideal-typical form, Oakeshott maintains
two ideal types bear obvious resemblances to Oake-
that they have been continuously intermingled with-
shott's more familiar pair of antagonists, but the
in European political traditions, and he even suggests
characterisation is more vivid than in the case of
that neither is sufficient without some infusion of the
universitas and societas and the treatment consider-
other.
ably more even-handed than in the case of political
own preference for the politics of scepticism is clear.
`rationalism' and its rival.
He preserves impartiality by arguing that in a poli-
12
Despite this formal even-handedness his
Those who practice `the politics of faith' (so
tical climate dominated by the politics of faith, a
Oakeshott would have us believe) approach the
modern `trimmer' will add his intellectual weight to
business of government with ambition and confi-
the beleaguered cause of scepticism.
13
dence, for within this style `the activity of governing
Following this long tug-of-war, our political vo-
is understood to be in the service of the perfection of
cabulary is systematically ambiguous because it has
mankind.'
8
Political
action
(it
is
assumed)
been `obliged for nearly five centuries to serve two
can
14
achieve such perfection in this world, though Oake-
masters.'
shott stresses that the `perfection' aimed at can be
styles and capable of being plausibly used for opposite
understood in many different ways. Seventeenth-
purposes. Oakeshott himself chooses to focus on the
century projects for using the state to establish a
ambiguities of democratic discourse to illustrate his
godly commonwealth stand alongside the secular
point,
projects of the last two hundred years under the
I believe, identify two sharply contrasted versions
banner of the politics of faith.
9
15
We inherit terminology marked by both
but if we now turn back to liberalism we can,
Interestingly, the
(both current within contemporary political thought
projects Oakeshott had earlier called `rationalist' fall
and each boasting a proud liberal ancestry) which
within this category: `faith' should be seen as the
vividly illustrate Oakeshott's contrasted styles. These
opposite not of reason but of scepticism. The most
are not the only sorts of liberalism there are, and I do
important political implication of this faith in the
not wish to imply that the rest could be fitted onto a
capacity of government to save mankind is that it
spectrum of which these two are the ends. But I hope
justifies great increases in power. No legalistic re-
it will be agreed that both sceptical liberalism and the
strictions can be allowed to stand in the way of such a
liberalism of faith ± which I shall call crusading
crusade, with the result that government becomes an
liberalism ± are familiar presences not only in the
`unlimited activity' and even a `godlike adventure.'
10
liberal tradition but within the complex contempor-
The `politics of scepticism' differs from this in ways
ary discourse of liberalism. My characterisations of
that any reader of Oakeshott might expect. Political
the two will verge on the ideal-typical, though
sceptics have lower expectations of government,
illustrated with examples from specific thinkers.
together with greater suspicion of power. Instead of looking to power to save the world, they deny
Crusading Liberalism
that it has any single overriding purpose. Rather, it is a matter of maintaining order, moderating the con-
A large proportion of all those who have ever
flicts that continually arise in human affairs and
thought of themselves as `liberal' could without
trying to minimise concentrations of arbitrary power.
undue distortion be assigned to this camp, and its
Rule according to settled law is crucial, as is the
roots are older than the term itself. But the first true
gradual development and maintenance of institu-
manifesto of crusading liberalism was the Declaration
tions that check power. Although such concerns
of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, approved by
64
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR
the French National Assembly in 1789, and its most
Whereas the academic representatives of crusading
characteristic twentieth-century document is the
liberalism are linked more or less closely to politi-
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, adopted
cians, campaigners, UN agencies and NGOs, scep-
by the United Nations in 1948. Although there is
tical liberalism is much less conspicuous within the
more to crusading liberalism than the discourse of
contemporary political arena and owes its continuing
human rights, that discourse vividly illustrates the
significance to the intellectual stature of its expo-
salient features of this kind of liberalism. In the first
nents. Oakeshott himself, Hayek, Shklar and others
place, crusading liberalism is a political project.
16
stand in a distinguished line of sceptics that runs
However abstract discussions of human rights may
back through Tocqueville and Constant to Mon-
at times become, they are more or less closely linked
tesquieu.
to a movement with practical political aims. The
cerned with limits: limits on power and on ambition
liberalism of human rights is a crusade today, just as it
in the uses of power. Mindful of the long history of
was in the days of the nineteenth-century campaign
misuse of political power, it is concerned (as Judith
against slavery.
Shklar says) with `damage control.'
Secondly, crusading liberalism is a
19
This sort of liberalism is essentially con-
20
Whatever their
universalist
views on the universality or relativity of moral and
creed. The notion of human rights clearly expresses
political principles, sceptical liberals share the view
the conviction that liberal principles do not lose
that the liberal institutions of civil society are a fragile
their relevance at the borders of states or at the
achievement, one that can be easily endangered by
fringes of cultures. Despite the worries about cultural
hubristic political projects. Like Oakeshott himself,
variation provoked by such claims,
17
the dominant
they see themselves swimming against a political tide
assumption is that a single moral and political order
fed by torrents of crusading enthusiasm and trying to
is right for all human beings: for those suspected of
maintain the crumbling dikes that hold it in check.
crimes in Sweden or in Saudi Arabia; for religious
In doing so they lay particular emphasis upon the
minorities in Ireland or in Iran; for political dissi-
rule of law (according to Hayek, liberalism is `the
dents in Canada or in China; for women in Australia
same as the demand for the rule of law'; similarly for
or in Afghanistan. Thirdly, besides being a univers-
Shklar, `the rule of law' is `the original first principle
alist project, crusading liberalism is radical in its
of liberalism'
confidence that the world must and can be changed
temporaries that it cannot be taken for granted.
21
) and they seek to remind their con-
to conform to this universal order. Institutions and
There is little love lost between crusaders and
practices that contravene human rights have no
sceptics within the liberal camp. To the former, the
justification, whatever the weight of established
latter seem mere conservatives,
tradition and cultural sanctity supporting them. If
that their cherished heritage of liberal institutions is
the institutional traditions and culture of the US
put at risk by the hubris of crusaders.
armed forces contravene the rights of women and
however, there is one topic on which they are agreed:
gays, then they must be changed, and if the entire
nationalism is anathema to both of them. Should a
historic culture of China or of Islam clashes with
crusader and a sceptic find themselves stranded
human rights, then they must all be changed as well.
together in a snowstorm, they could generate a warm
It is clear enough that crusading liberalism manifests
glow of mutual solidarity by denouncing the perni-
the ambition and confidence described in Oake-
cious political influence of national feeling. True,
shott's account of the `politics of faith',
18
22
while sceptics fear 23
Interestingly,
and (as
their hostility has different grounds, but on both
we shall see later) it also harbours the quest for power
sides the hostility is pronounced. Crusading liberals
that he found there.
object to the particularity of nations, which builds
To shift one's focus from crusading liberalism to
barriers against the universality of human rights. This
sceptical liberalism is to enter a different (and very
is in a sense an argument against any kind of political
much smaller) world. Unlike the former, sceptical
demarcation, but non-national boundaries may at
liberalism has never been a vast political movement
least be regarded as temporary matters of practical
but
convenience. National boundaries are more formid-
the
business
of
a
handful
of
intellectuals.
65
MARGARET CANOVAN
able obstacles, buttressed by the widespread belief
be, and in each case the nation has to be smuggled in
that they have moral significance, so that our fellow
to stuff the gap. With convenient symmetry, the way
nationals have special claims that trump the claims
this is done illustrates Oakeshott's observation that
of other human beings.
24
Similarly, the notion that
neither of his two styles of politics is self-sufficient,
national cultures and traditions have value in them-
for we shall see that sceptics need nationhood to
selves often seems (from the crusading point of view)
provide an infusion of enthusiasm, while crusaders
like an excuse to deny the universal rights of those
need it to give them a stiffening of realpolitik.
traditionally victimised.
25
Sceptical liberals have quite different reasons for
Sceptical Liberals and the Power Deficit
disliking nationalism, which they associate with the populist enthusiasm and `ideologies of solidarity'
26
Sceptical liberals are deeply suspicious of power and
that put liberal institutions at risk. In their view, it is
of grand political schemes that rely on expanding the
a fundamental mistake to expect political institu-
role of government and mobilising the people be-
tions to express the `identity' of their subjects.
27
By
hind a common cause. But that concern with the
chasing the mirage of `self-government' for members
dangers of excessive power leads them to overlook a
of a nation, nationalism undermines established
power deficit within their own style of politics. They
political systems that may in themselves have been
tend to underestimate the power that a limited
relatively benign, and replaces them at great political
government needs and to overlook the problem of
cost with others that exercise arbitrary power in the
where such power might be found. At first sight their
name of the nation. For the sake of national self-
political ambitions seem modest ± deplorably so to
determination, many people who had enjoyed a
those whose politics is concerned with righting
relatively high degree of liberty under law as subjects
wrongs
of the Habsburg or of the British Empire, found
schemes and do not expect perfection. Virtually
themselves `liberated' into subjection to local tyr-
all they ask is that arbitrary power should be re-
ants. In any case, the mixed societies of the late
strained by known rules, and that established rights
twentieth century are inappropriate sites for nation-
to person and property should be protected by an
alist fantasies. To quote John Gray:
impartial judiciary and by fair and effective enforce-
across
the
world.
They
have
no
grand
ment of the law. In the words of John Gray, what The aspiration to make states correspond to com-
they look for is a state that is `strong but small'.
29
munities cannot be other than a dangerous illu-
This may not seem much to ask. In criticising the
sion. Where moral solidarity is lacking, where (as
excessive ambitions of crusaders, sceptics often imply
in all modern societies) there is cultural diversity
that their own aims are much less demanding, some-
rather than seamless community, the role of
times even that they are really quite easy to attain.
government is first and last that of preserving
(Hayek says, for example, that his kind of liberalism
liberty in civil association under the rule of law.
28
is `an essentially modest creed'.
30
) But this is an
illusion. The crucial point to bear in mind is that So far I have been attempting to establish two
(despite their proximity to the more sceptical ver-
contrasted ideal types of liberalism corresponding to
sions of conservatism) our sceptics are liberals and it is
Oakeshott's `politics of faith' and `politics of scepti-
their liberal commitments that expose the power
cism', and to show that one of the few areas of
deficit in their thinking. If they were simply Hobbe-
common ground between them is that both are
sian conservatives, asking nothing from politics but
(for different reasons) hostile to nationalism. The
peace and order, then that `strong but small' state
remainder of the chapter will try to show that despite
might be easier to come by. Peace and order have on
this hostility, crusaders and sceptics are both much
occasion been achieved by a wide variety of regimes
more dependent on national attachments than they
in many different kinds of society: by traditional
would like to admit. Each version of liberalism has a
monarchies and military juntas, by oligarchic repub-
hole at its centre where a theory of power ought to
lics, and even by communism in its phase of Brezh-
66
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR
nevite immobilism. Neither social cohesion nor
grave difficulties in providing the rule of law in
democratic politics is required. Indeed, if peace
particular regions where that legitimacy is not gen-
and order are really what you are looking for, then
erally recognised, as the sorry history of British rule in
the power to enforce them may in some circum-
Ireland demonstrates. This is not to say that regimes
stances be more effectively achieved by non-demo-
enjoying this recognition will necessarily provide
cratic
by
equal justice ± far from it. But to have even a sporting
coercion, by traditional authority, or through a
chance of enjoying the rule of law, we do need a
negotiated
government with legitimate power.
tions.
than
by
democratic
modus
vivendi
means,
between
whether powerful
fac-
31
Followers of Hayek or Oakeshott will object that
But although sceptical liberals may be tempted by
the authority of the law should not be confused with
the Hobbesian politics of peace, in so far as they
popular support for the regime; all that is required is
remain liberals they cannot accept such solutions,
recognition of the authority of a system of rules and
simply because most ways of establishing peace and
of judicial decisions in accordance with it.
order are not compatible with the rule of equal law.
shott himself might cite as an analogue the authority
John Gray was deluding himself when, daringly
to adjudicate on the rules of cricket gradually ac-
dismissing the notion that democracy is necessary
quired by the MCC.
to `the practice of liberty', he claimed that the `civil
acceptance of the system of rules and, crucially, trust
condition' so much valued by sceptical liberals `is
in the judicial processes by which they are adminis-
fully compatible with a variety of political regimes',
tered and enforced. And that begs a vital question:
although it `presupposes always the rule of law and
under what political conditions is that impartial rule
equality before the law.'
32
34
33
Oake-
But this implies popular
Very few kinds of political
of law most likely? For this is the Holy Grail sought
regime and political society are in fact compatible
by republican thinkers from Cicero to Rousseau, who
with that `civil condition', because the equal rule of
wanted `the government of laws, not men', and who
law implies two very demanding conditions. The first
knew that such a government required a strong sense
is that the state enjoys a fund of consensual power,
of shared, inherited public good and its accompany-
enabling it to enforce the law without employing a
ing public spirit. Under modern conditions that
degree of coercion which would be inconsistent with
public spirit, like legitimacy and consensual power,
the civil condition. The second is that it presides
is most likely (though far from certain) where the
over a society sufficiently united to allow it to
polity is supported by a strong sense of collective
enforce equal law across the whole country. What
identity ± where it belongs to a people. Much as
this amounts to is a high level of identification of the
sceptical liberals may deplore populism, they can
polity with the population and vice versa, which in
hardly deny that impartial law enforcement with
the condition of modern politics normally means
minimum coercion is normally easier where the state
nationhood. Let us look more closely at these two
enjoys the legitimacy of being generally regarded as
conditions.
our state.
35
It may still be objected that my argument confuses a contingent historical cause with a necessary con-
Consensual Power
dition: that although as a matter of historical fact the
For the `strong but small' state to generate its
establishment of the rule of law in England owed a
strength in a manner compatible with the rule of
lot to collective national attachment to `the laws of
law, it must be recognised as legitimate by the mass of
England',
its subjects. Without that support the minimal liberal
that could be freely transferred elsewhere. In other
state is impossible; impartial justice is scarcely to be
words, while a strident national pride may have been
expected from rulers who have seized power in a
crucial in enabling Coke, Hampden and their heirs
military coup, or from a conquering army sitting on
to defend law and limited government against the
rifle butts. Even a state that is recognised by most of
Stuarts, the system has since become self-sustaining:
its subjects as their legitimate representative may find
wherever a state does provide the benefits of impar-
67
36
once established it became a practice
MARGARET CANOVAN
tial justice, then popular consent will follow. Bhikhu
obstacles a plural society poses to the achievement
Parekh argues, for example, that nothing by way of
of impartial judicial treatment of (say) felonies.
national cohesion is required because `the modern
Sceptics like to claim that the minimalist state they
state is a self-sufficient institution. It has a commonly
favour is particularly suited to ethnically divided
accepted structure of public authority, a set of pro-
societies, because its modest ambitions allow con-
cedures for taking collectively binding decisions, and
tentious issues to be depoliticised.
a body of widely shared politico-legal values', notably
implausible claim, perhaps betraying the confusion
`the rule of law, equality before the law, respect for
we noticed earlier between the conservative insis-
human dignity and common citizenship.' Although
tence on peace as the political goal and the more
this `self-sufficient state' is a contingent product of
demanding aims of liberals. A sceptical conservative
history, it does not now need the support of national
could argue that, where a political entity (such as
sentiment. Being a member means recognising its
Bosnia) is sharply divided between hostile commu-
`politico-legal values' and abiding by the laws. `Noth-
nities, then the best that can be hoped for is a
ing more is required of its members in order for it to
minimal state based on negotiation between leaders
remain united and stable.'
37
of
the
contending
factions,
38
But this is an
themselves
holding
power within their own patches as best they can.
For the increasing number of cosmopolitan individuals who move easily between different western
But that is not a solution any liberal could be content
liberal democratic countries, expecting much the
with, for it would certainly not imply equality before
same legal protections and offering the same minimal
the law, especially for minorities in the various
allegiance in each, this account may seem reasonable
enclaves.
enough, and the national identity of the local po-
divided, the Hobbesian concern for peace and order
pulation may seem irrelevant. But we should not be
may well clash with the rule of law. For despite the
misled by talk of `the modern state' into supposing
sceptics' image of the law as an umpire presiding
that there is something about the advent of the
impartially over communal divisions, in such cir-
millennium that makes such `modernity' easy to
cumstances everything to do with the legal process
achieve without a background of nationhood. Most
becomes politicised. Apart from the problems of
modern states (in the sense of states actually in
staffing juries and making judicial appointments,
existence today) are not `modern' in this sense. As
the outcome of every contentious trial becomes a
a matter of empirical observation, most UN members
victory or defeat for different sections of society. The
do not provide anything near enough to the rule of
tensions surrounding the trial of O. J. Simpson in the
law to earn the consent of a sceptical liberal. Cor-
USA is perhaps sufficient comment on the notion
ruption, violence and arbitrary power are common-
that the rule of equal law can comfortably coexist
place, even in many of the states that have formally
with communal divisions, even in a deeply legalistic
liberal constitutions. Evidently a properly `modern'
polity. For the equal rule of law to function, it is vital
state as understood by Parekh is one that does provide
that the apparatus of justice should not be seen by its
equal law, but we need to consider the role of
recipients as their law rather than ours.
nationhood or the lack of it in making that more
39
Even in societies that are less radically
The notion of the law as impartial umpire above
or less likely.
the fray may in some cases be a piece of unconscious post-imperial nostalgia, a regretful glance back to the days when relatively upright British officials admi-
Equal Law
nistered justice between the castes and religious
If taken seriously, the sceptic requirement of equality
groups of India, or when relatively professional im-
before the law seems to demand a substantial degree
perial bureaucrats dealt with the multifarious nation-
of social unity. This is the case even if we leave aside
alities
all the problems of equal justice between rich and
observations are apposite. In the first place, imperial
poor and men and women that would take us into
systems have never been models of impartial justice,
crusading liberal territory, and consider only the
as anyone who fell foul of the imperial authorities
68
of
the
Habsburg
Empire.
If
so,
two
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR
quickly discovered. Secondly, imperial regimes have
the product of a much more strident history. There is
in this century proved quite unable to attract enough
a good deal to be said for Michael Ignatieff's distinc-
popular consent to maintain peace and order, let
tion between `hungry' and `sated' nations,
alone the rule of law.
caveat that even the satisfied nations sometimes
In other words (as John Stuart Mill pointed out long ago
40
45
with the
wake up feeling peckish. Sceptical Liberal distrust
) the ideal venue for the kind of politics
of nationalism is reinforced by the fear that even
favoured by liberals is actually a polity belonging to a
apparently innocuous forms of the virus are liable to
people bound together by the mutual sympathies of
flare up if given the slightest encouragement.
nationhood. A state in which there is a long-estab-
Nevertheless, if the argument of this section holds,
lished sense of collective identification with the
sceptical liberals cannot afford to be so fastidious, for
polity, and in which state, government and laws
they cannot easily do without some measure of
are seen as ours rather than an alien imposition,
national feeling to underpin the rule of law with
provides a particularly favourable basis for strong but
the power of popular legitimation. Instead of dream-
consensual government, a sense of public interest
ing of a polity untroubled by any such emotional
and support for the fair and impartial rule of law.
41
stirrings,
the
far-sighted
sceptical
liberals
would
This is an ideal never fully realised in practice, like
choose a polity that belongs to a `sated' nation where
the republican ideal of the polity of virtuous citizens
the `pathologies of national sentiment' are buried
united in their devotion to the patria. But the
several generations deep in the past, and where the
historical connection between liberalism and nation-
rule of law is cherished as a national heritage.
hood is not accidental. Sceptical liberals are inclined to take this background of nationhood for granted
Crusading Liberalism and the Power Deficit
without reflecting upon its contribution to the in-
If sceptical liberals find it hard to do without political
stitutions they value. Some critics might concede this last point but
faith in nationhood to support the power needed by
object that I am ignoring a vital distinction between
their minimal state, a complementary point can be
nationhood and nationalism. They would argue that
made about crusading liberalism. For crusaders can-
one can acknowledge a debt to nationhood while
not find salvation through faith alone, and their
deploring
movements.
good works take them into a world of realpolitik in
This is (for example) the position that John Gray
which they find themselves relying to a degree not
attributes to Isaiah Berlin. Unlike most other liberals
normally acknowledged on the power generated by
of his time, according to Gray, `Berlin perceives that
nationhood. Power is not something that crusading
a liberal civil society cannot rest upon abstract
liberal political theorists like to think about; as their
principles or common rules alone, but needs a com-
critics (including sceptics) have observed, their pre-
mon national culture if it is to be stable and com-
occupations often seem more moral than political,
mand allegiance.' But (he continues) `in common
and questions about the sources, limits and costs of
with
the
power are rarely raised in their writings. But liberal-
This position
ism of this kind is more than a set of moral injunc-
is attractive but simplistic. It may seem easy in
tions addressed to individuals; it is a political project.
principle to affirm nationhood while condemning
Crusaders want to see human rights recognised and
`the pathology of nationalism', but the line is not so
protected across the world, and questions of political
easy to draw in particular cases (including Zionism,
agency inevitably follow.
all
nationalist
liberal
ideologies
thinkers,
and
Berlin
pathology of nationalist sentiment.'
which Berlin supported).
43
repudiates 42
46
Seeking to make the
It is significant that the
Marxist political project effective, Lenin hit on
word `nationalism' can itself refer not only to move-
the notion of the powerful party: what collective
ments and an ideology but also to the sense of
actor or actors can (by analogy) bear the project of
nationhood itself, perhaps indicating the difficulty
human rights?
44
In practice, where a strong
Having as little instinctive trust in professional
but civilised national sentiment exists it is normally
politicians as sceptical liberals have in popular move-
of distinguishing them.
69
MARGARET CANOVAN
ments, crusading liberals might be inclined to look
sponsibility to act in defence of rights across the
first to the non-governmental organisations that
world.
have to such an extraordinary degree furthered hu-
The experience that supports this claim goes back
manitarian projects across the world since the Sec-
nearly three hundred years. The role of global stan-
ond World War. But however good they may be at
dard-bearer for what later came to be called liberal
famine relief, NGOs are not well suited to protect
principles was first played by Britain, in a secularisa-
the human rights of individuals under threat from
tion of the responsibilities borne since the sixteenth
tyrannical regimes or ethnic militias. The former can
century by the Protestant English as God's chosen
simply refuse to admit them, while in the times of
people.
civil war and anarchy that breed the latter, NGOs
out of its more religious precursor in the poems of
themselves need protection, as events in Bosnia and
Thomas Tickell, who wrote in the days of Queen
elsewhere have shown. It is clear that political power
Anne:
is
required.
tion',
47
Calling
for
`humanitarian
50
We can see the political mission evolving
intervenHer guiltless glory just Britannia draws
crusaders will turn next to international
From pure religion and impartial laws
organisations that sprung up (like NGOs) in the second half of the twentieth century. Organisations of this kind (established by the more liberal nation-
Her labours are to plead the Almighty's cause
states) have indeed transformed the conduct of
Her pride to teach the untamed Barbarian laws.
51
international politics, and the ways in which they have modified older notions of state sovereignty should not be underestimated.
48
During the French Revolution Britain's mission as
Nevertheless, their
the universal shield of liberty was challenged by
inability (so far) to take the sort of decisive action
France. In the consciousness of the revolutionaries
crusaders often want has been cruelly exposed by
who carried the banner of the Rights of Man across
recent events. If action is to be taken to guard human
Europe, their universal mission of liberation became
rights where they are most seriously under threat, it
inextricably entangled with national pride. Interest-
can be taken only by a political agent able to project
ingly, this entanglement was not a foregone conclu-
power effectively, which means a powerful state or
sion, for at the start of the Revolution no one could
alliance of such states.
49
have been more critical of nationalism than the
It seems, then, that crusaders must compromise
Jacobins. Istvan Hont has shown, however, that
with political reality to the extent of calling on the
despite Robespierre's insistence that the Republic
power of states to further their cause. What is more
`was acting only on behalf of the peoples of the
interesting for our present purposes, though, is that
world . . . nothing was more striking than the
only certain sorts of state will do. Power alone is not
turning of Jacobin republicanism into the most dra-
enough; it must be power of a certain kind, based not
matic form of national patriotism.'
on the coercion of its own subjects but their support.
similar fusion of power, patriotism and messianic
So the state in question will need to enjoy popular
fervour has made the USA the favoured agent for
consent (with the implications already indicated in
the projects of crusading liberalism from Woodrow
relation to sceptical liberalism), and will need to be
Wilson to the present.
52
In our century a
53
one in which public opinion supports the cause of
Some may argue that the USA is peculiarly suited
international human rights to the point of being
to the task of defending universal human rights
willing to send `our boys' to fight for them. Under
precisely because it is not a nation, but instead a
what circumstances are these conditions most likely
polity united by subscription to universal liberal
to be fulfilled? History offers an answer: the kind of
principles. This case has been eloquently stated by
state most likely to function as the secular arm of
John Schaar, who defends American patriotism as
crusading liberalism is one in which liberalism of that
something quite different from the `parochial and
kind is perceived as a national mission, implying that
primitive fraternities of blood and race'. It is instead a
the state and people concerned have a special re-
`covenanted patriotism', which is ethically superior
70
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR
to nationalism because it is `guided by and directed
even take a possessive national pride in overcoming
toward the mission established in the founding
the limitations of nationalism, like the ingenious
covenant' of the Republic. Being committed to
nineteenth-century Frenchman who congratulated
universal principles of liberty, equality and self-gov-
his fellow countrymen on their cosmopolitanism: `it
ernment, this kind of patriotism `is compatible with
is we who taught the nations of Europe to detach
the most generous humanism' and indeed `assigns
themselves from a narrowly national ideal and to
America a teaching mission among the nations.'
54
march resolutely towards a human ideal.'
58
A less
But this is a red herring. Nations vary a great deal
strident example of the same phenomenon is the
and are by no means exclusively defined in terms of
national pride Swedes feel in being (collectively) a
55
What is much more crucial is the
shining example of internationalism. While this is
collective consciousness that enables a nation to act
(from a liberal point of view) an enormous improve-
as a single body and, for all its internal divisions, the
ment on more obviously chauvinistic versions, it
sense of being American is something that the USA
remains a form of nationalism.
ethnic unity.
has in abundance. That collective identity gives the
To sum up this section, then, in so far as crusading
country a unique capacity to act on the world stage
liberals leave the realms of pure faith and consider
and to mobilise power proportionate to its size and
the conditions of political effectiveness, they must
resources. It is true that the USA's peculiar suit-
realise that despite the real difficulty of reconciling
ability as a vehicle for the projects of crusading
universalist humanitarianism with the exclusiveness
liberalism comes from the conjunction of national
of national attachments, liberal nations with a strong
power with a universal mission. It may even be true,
sense of their national mission as representatives of
as Schaar implies, that belief in human rights is part
the `world community' are their most useful allies.
of what it means to be an American. But crusaders inclined to argue that this is a redeeming feature
Conclusion
should take note of the other side of the coin, which is a proprietary attitude towards such beliefs. Liberal
I have argued that liberals are a great deal closer to
principles tend to be experienced as American prin-
national enthusiasms than most of them like to
ciples ± seen by Americans as our principles, a
think, and that even those who are actively hostile
legitimate source of national pride. Reflecting on
to the nation and all its works find it hard to do
the ideological quality of American identity, Benja-
without the political power it can offer. Nationhood
min Barber remarks that `the American trick was to
offers sceptical liberals their best chance of a polity
use the fierce attachments of patriotic sentiment to
able to conduct its affairs according to the rule of law,
bond a people to high ideals. Our ``tribal'' sources
while the most effective support crusading liberals
from which we derive our sense of national identity
can summon up in defence of human rights around
are the Declaration of Independence, the Constitu-
the world is a sense of national mission ± the US
tion and the Bill of Rights.' He admits, however, that
Cavalry, in a manner of speaking. It might perhaps
`cosmopolitanism too has its pathologies and can also
be thought that this conclusion adds weight to the
breed its own antiseptic version of imperialism.'
56
arguments of the new `liberal nationalists' I men-
The dilemma for those who favour `humanitarian
tioned at the beginning of the chapter, and that
intervention' by the `international community' is
liberals of all kinds should join them in celebration of
that nations cast as the representatives of humanity
(some versions of) nationalism. But that would be
always have their own axes to grind.
57
too hasty an inference, for the argument I have been
The unpalatable truth facing crusading liberals, in
presenting is of a quite different kind. One way of
other words, is that their universal mission gains
highlighting the difference is to say that the present
maximum political clout when it is in effect captured
argument is concerned with contingent political
by a powerful nation and becomes part of that
considerations to do with power and feasibility,
nation's own identity and national pride. Such are
whereas defenders of liberal nationalism normally
the contortions of national identity that nations may
argue their case on moral and philosophical grounds.
71
MARGARET CANOVAN
The standard arguments for liberal nationalism try
dilemmas that nations pose for liberals in the con-
to show that liberalism and nationalism are morally
temporary world is not the whole story. There is a
compatible, and even that liberal principles entail
second reason for bearing in mind the tension as well
rights to national self-determination. These are not
as the link between nationhood and liberalism.
positions defended here. On the contrary, the reluc-
I have argued that sceptics and crusaders alike rely
tance of so many liberals to acknowledge their debts to
on the nation's capacity to mobilise and institutio-
nationhood is entirely understandable, for the nation
nalise consensual power:
makes an uncomfortable bedfellow for either of the
equal laws at home and provide a launching pad for
versions we have been looking at. Many nationalisms
universalist projects. But although this dependence
are, after all, explicitly hostile to liberalism in any of its
on national power is important and too little no-
forms; more crucially, even the most liberal version of
ticed, it is a matter of political contingency rather
nationalism is too irrational and populist really to suit
than philosophical necessity. In principle, it may
the fastidious sceptics, and too narrow in its identity
some day turn out to be the case that consensual
and commitments for the visions of crusaders. Re-
power can be mobilised and institutionalised in other
membering the tensions (as well as the links) between
ways. It may be significant that some of the inter-
liberalism and nationalism is important, for two rea-
national institutions launched from national bases in
sons. Fittingly, one of these reasons recalls Oakeshott's
the past half-century are showing signs of acquiring a
`politics of scepticism', the other his `politics of faith'.
legitimacy that enables them to some extent to
The first is that both kinds of liberals need to come
mobilise power of their own. While deeply depen-
to terms with the political cost of their aspirations.
dent on nation-states (and especially on a few states
The cost of the liberal freedoms valued by sceptics is
with strong national identities and political and
a greater or lesser degree of the nationalist enthu-
economic clout to match), these institutions are
siasm they deplore. For crusaders, the costs of effec-
already far from negligible, since they constrain
tiveness under present conditions are considerably
the activities of those same states. In the long term
higher, amounting (if crusading aspirations were to
(who knows?) crusading liberalism may free itself
be seriously pursued) to a new imperialism to be
from its national launching pad and build a home of
undertaken not by the `world community' but by the
its own, a political space station able to circle the
United States. Whether or not the goal is worth such
globe in serene detachment from the blood and soil
a price is another matter, but the question deserves
of nationality.
more attention than it currently gets.
59
61
60
power that can support
At any rate, as crusaders look for-
ward in faith to that day, sceptics are in no position
But sceptical
to declare it impossible.
`realism' about the genuine and serious political
62
Notes
8. Ibid., p. 23.
1. Blease (1913), p. 12.
9. Ibid., p. 59.
2. On mid-Victorian liberal enthusiasm for national selfdetermination (and on tensions between this and the
10. Ibid., pp. 27±9.
Cobdenite tradition of a non-interventionist foreign
11. Ibid., p. 32.
policy), see Bradley (1980), pp. 97±104, 133.
12. Ibid., p. 91. 13. Ibid., p. 128.
3. See, for example, Miller (1995), Tamir (1993), N. MacCormick, `What Place for Nationalism?', in Ca-
14. Ibid., p. 21.
ney, George and Jones (eds) (1996).
15. Ibid., pp. 130±1. I have pursued some of the intimations of that discussion in Canovan (1999).
4. Friedrich Hayek's `Anglo-American' as opposed to `continental' liberalism belongs to the wider family
16. Judith Shklar acutely observes that, whereas her own
of sceptical liberalism, as does Judith Shklar's `liberal-
`liberalism of fear' is prompted by `memory' ± memory
ism of fear'.
of the awful things that people have done to one another ± the `liberalism of natural rights' is prompted
5. Oakeshott (1962), pp. 1±36, 123±7.
by `hope'; Shklar (1989), pp. 26±7.
6. Oakeshott (1975a), pp. 200±6, 313±16.
17. See, for example, Renteln (1990).
7. Oakeshott (1996), p. 21.
72
THE SWORD OF FAITH AND THE SHIELD OF FEAR
18. Cf. Donnelly (1989), Waldron (1993), pp. 23±4;
82. Though strong, the connection is historically
Bobbio (1996), pp. 12±14, 30, 61±70. The volume
contingent. Bruce Haddock has drawn my attention
edited by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (Nuss-
to the counter-example of contemporary Italy, where
baum and Sen (eds), 1993) forms a particularly inter-
long-standing dissatisfaction with the performance of
esting illustration because its contributors are acutely
the Italian state expresses itself in a popular support for
aware of many of the objections to which this sort of
EU institutions that seems to indicate a wish not to be
project is open, but nevertheless mostly endorse it.
ruled by one's `own' state. Might this be a harbinger of a new form of empire-by-consent?
19. The most conspicuous recent British defender of
36. Helgerson (1992), p. 65, 81; Pocock (1957), pp. 30±
sceptical liberalism has been John Gray; see, for ex-
55.
ample, Gray (1993), especially pp. 314±20 (though, as we shall see below, in his most recent work Gray seems
37. Parekh (1995), pp. 139±40.
to have gone beyond liberalism altogether). See also
38. Gray (1993), p. 265; O'Sullivan (1997), p. 753.
O'Sullivan (1989) and (1997), especially pp. 748±54.
39. John Gray seems recently to have recognised this
20. Shklar (1989), p. 27.
point, and has taken to describing his position as
21. Hayek (1967), p. 165; Shklar (1989), p. 37.
`pluralist rather than liberal', seeing the appropriate
22. Sceptical liberalism does indeed share a border with
arrangement for deeply plural societies not as a suppo-
the more sceptical versions of conservatism, with a
sedly impartial legalism but as a kind of millet system
number of notable political theorists (including Mon-
with different laws for different communities related to
tesquieu and Tocqueville) inhabiting the disputed
one another by a process of political bargaining; Gray (1995a), pp. 126, 136±7.
territory. Even Hayek, who actually wrote an essay entitled, `Why I am Not a Conservative', can be
40. Mill (1972), pp. 391±4.
plausibly treated as one in some contexts. See, for
41. Scruton (1990), p. 322; Miller (1995), pp. 90±3.
example, Devigne (1994), p. 33. Oakeshott himself is
42. Gray (1995b), pp. 99±100.
most often categorised as a conservative, which is
43. Ibid., p. 117.
justified, but only with the qualification that he is
44. Hutchinson and Smith (eds) (1994), p. 4.
an unusual kind of `sceptical liberal conservative,
45. Ignatieff (1994), p. 189.
lacking both the emotional attachments of Burkean
46. Consider, for example, Robert Goodin's assertion that
conservatives and the faith in capitalism of the ``New
since we all have `general duties' to all other people,
Right''.' Cf. Gray (1989), p. 199; Franco (1990). As
regardless of nationhood or citizenship, `if some states
we shall later see, however, where nationalism is
prove incapable of discharging their responsibilities
concerned, there is a test that can distinguish between
effectively, then they should either be reconstituted or
the more liberal and the more conservative aspects.
assisted.' The choice of passive verbs conveniently dodges the tricky question of who is to do the `recon-
23. For example, Gray (1993), pp. 326±7.
stituting'; Goodin (1988), p. 685.
24. For a classic critique of this last belief, see Goodin
47. Cf. Ramsbotham and Woodhouse (eds) (1996), Har-
(1988).
riss (ed.) (1995).
25. See Donnelly (1989), pp. 119±20.
48. For example, states that desire acceptance by Western
26. Shklar (1989), p. 36. 27. On the dangers of atavistic `tribal' loyalties, see Hayek
clubs such as the Council of Europe or the EU find
(1993), volume II, p. 143. In Hayek's view, nation-
themselves under pressure to respect minority rights.
alism shares with socialism the dubious distinction of
This point was drawn to my attention by Richard Sakwa.
being one of `the two greatest threats to a free civilisa-
49. Bhikhu Parekh suggests that `morally concerned citi-
tion,'; ibid., volume III, p. 111.
zens' from around the world might move into such
28. John Gray, `The Politics of Cultural Diversity', in Gray
situations and
(1993), pp. 253±71.
`stage well-publicised and carefully
29. Ibid., p. 270.
planned acts of a Gandhian type of non-violent
30. Hayek (1967), p. 161.
resistance', such as placing themselves between the warring parties in an ethnic conflict. This is a heroic
31. The classic view of nationalism from a sceptical conKedourie
idea, but could be effective only if it mobilised public
(1993); see, for example, Kedourie's comments on
opinion inside powerful states to pressure those states
servative
perspective
can
be
found
in
themselves to take action; Parekh (1997).
Mazzini at p. 92. 32. Gray (1993), p. 318.
50. Greenfeld (1992), pp. 60±6.
33. Hayek (1993), volume I, chapter 4.
51. `On the Prospects of Peace', in Tickell (1822), pp. 135±6.
34. Oakeshott (1975a), p. 154.
52. Hont (1994), pp. 207, 219, 222.
35. Cf. Beetham (1991), p. 127. On the relation between national identity and the `generalised trust' required by
53. See, for example, Shue (1980).
modern civil society, see Seligman (1992), pp. 147±
54. Schaar (1981), p. 293.
73
MARGARET CANOVAN
59. Cf. Miller (1995), pp. 77±8.
55. On the nature and variability of nations, see Canovan
60. So successfully, indeed, that such power has come to
(1996), pp. 50±80. 56. B. Barber, `Constitutional Faith', in Cohen (ed.)
be taken for granted in nation-states, as if it existed by
(1996), pp. 30±7, at pp. 32±3. Cf. C. Taylor, `Alter-
nature. This point is more extensively discussed in Canovan (1996).
native Futures: Legitimacy, Identity and Alienation in Late Twentieth Century Canada', in Cairns and Wil-
61. For a vision of this kind, see Linklater (1998).
liams (eds) (1985), p. 215. As in the British and
62. I have benefited from the criticisms and observations
French cases, secular American universalist national-
of the other participants at the `Liberalism at the
ism owes a lot to a pre-existing sense of religious
Millennium' conference organised by the Department
mission. See O'Brien (1988).
of Political Theory and Government in the University
57. Parekh (1997), p. 58.
of Wales Swansea. I am also indebted to John Horton
58. Quoted in Newman (1987), p. 49. For a more sophis-
for his characteristically incisive and helpful comments.
ticated contemporary restatement of similar sentiments, see Schnapper (1994).
74
6
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM Andrea Baumeister
differences, which are also more fluid than fixed in
Introduction
character, an appeal to a unified women's politics is
One of the most striking features of contemporary
liable to prove just as exclusionary as the traditional
feminist discourse has been the increasing disen-
liberal preoccupation with universality. Yet, while
chantment with traditional liberal conceptions of
the dangers of exclusion are widely acknowledged, a
citizenship. Whereas early reforming feminists ap-
number of feminists have recently expressed concern
pealed to the liberal principles of equality and uni-
about the implications of such a rejection of all
versality in their attempts to include women in the
universal claims and norms. Not only does the
realm of citizenship, many contemporary feminists
anti-essentialist commitment to `radical otherness'
have criticised liberalism for failing to acknowledge
potentially undermine the idea of an effective fem-
the significance of difference and particularity. In the
inist politics, it also fails to recognise the important
eyes of critics such as Pateman and Young,
1
the
role appeals to universality and formal equality have
traditional emphasis upon formal equality and uni-
historically played in the struggle by oppressed groups
versality encourages liberals to ignore the extent to
to be included in the realm of citizenship. In the light
which our identities are irrevocably shaped by the
of these concerns feminists like Susan Moller Okin
particularities and contingencies of our existence.
and Martha Nussbaum have reasserted the impor-
Thus, whereas liberal conceptions of citizenship
tance of women's shared experiences and the con-
typically relegate difference, particularity and affec-
tinued
tivity to the non-political private sphere, many
struggle for equality for women worldwide.
relevance
of
universal
standards
in
the
3
contemporary feminists have sought to undermine
Faced with this lively debate among feminists, a
this liberal public/private distinction in their attempt
number of writers have attempted to strike a balance
to assert the political significance of our unique and
between the claims of difference and the concerns
particular characteristics.
which have traditionally given rise to the liberal
This regard for difference and particularity has led
emphasis on universality. One of the most influential
some feminists to be sceptical of all universal claims.
examples of such an approach is Iris Marion Young's
Thus writers such as Spelman, Harris, hooks and Flax
model of a `heterogeneous public'. Although Young
not only reject liberal universalism but also question
stresses that each social group has its own unique
the validity of a general, unified women's politics.
4
2
experiences, histories and social life, which can
For these feminist anti-essentialists gender is intrin-
never be entirely understood or adequately repre-
sically bound up with other aspects of identity such
sented by outsiders, she nonetheless recognises the
as class and race. In the face of such multifaceted
potential appeal of liberalism's commitment to uni-
75
ANDREA BAUMEISTER
versality and the equality as a justification for the
and marginalised women. If, due to their capacity for
inclusion of all in moral and social life. Yet, while
rational thought, all human beings deserve equal
Young's model of a heterogeneous public overcomes
rights and respect, then women, as beings capable of
many of the problems associated with earlier feminist
reason, are surely entitled to the same rights and
reconceptualisations of citizenship, this chapter will
privileges as men. Thus first-wave feminists, such as
argue that her model of group representation remains
Macaulay and Wollstonecraft,
at odds with both her dynamic conception of the
tions of universal reason and formal equality to show
social collective and her commitment to deliberative
that sexual differences should be seen as merely
democracy.
which
contingent and, in the final analysis, inconsequen-
Young combines an emphasis on universality at
tial. Ultimately men and women shared the same
the point of participation with the recognition of
faculties and capacities. Women's apparent failure to
the claims of difference in the allocation of rights and
develop their rational faculties did not rest upon
resources is, from a feminist perspective, rather at-
deep-seated biological differences between men and
tractive.
women but simply reflected the social norms and
Nonetheless,
the
manner
in
7
employed liberal no-
However, an attempt to strike such a balance need
pressures placed upon them. Not surprisingly, early
not imply a rejection of the liberal tradition. It is a
feminists regarded education as a vital stepping stone
rich and complex body of thought and practice
in the campaign for the enfranchisement of women.
which, in the final analysis, may not be as hostile
If granted access to equal education, women would
to diversity as is frequently assumed. Indeed, careful
realise their rational faculties and develop the capa-
reading reveals that questions of difference and
city for autonomous action. Once these goals had
particularity play a significant role in the Kantian
been attained women could not reasonably be de-
strand of liberalism. The distinction Kant draws
nied the vote. After all if the notion of self-sover-
between perfect and imperfect obligations and the
eignty is to be meaningful it must surely include the
open-ended, context-responsive manner in which a
right to self-governance in the political sphere. Yet,
Kantian approach determines specific obligations
while many first-wave feminists actively advocated
allows for the recognition of the complex relation-
liberal ideals and endorsed the liberal vision of a
ship between the public and the private and is
common citizenship, the attainment of equal legal
sensitive to the demands for more effective repre-
and political rights did not bring about the radical
sentation on the part of traditionally marginalised
improvement in the position of women first-wave
groups.
5
These traditional Kantian concerns have
feminists had so confidently anticipated. In the light
continued to inform the work of contemporary
of this failure many second-wave feminists have
6
This strand of
questioned the values which underpin the liberal
liberalism, therefore, can provide a framework for
notion of individual rights in general and the liberal
citizenship which potentially enables feminists to
conception of citizenship in particular. They have
resolve one of the most troubling tensions at the
argued that these commitments blind liberals to the
heart of contemporary feminist theorising.
significance of difference in their conception of both
Kantians such as Ju È rgen Habermas.
individual and citizen. At the level of the self, feminist theorists such as
Women and Liberal Citizenship
Pateman have drawn attention to the manner in
In their battle for equal rights for women many early
which liberals have attempted to abstract the in-
feminists were clearly inspired by the liberal Enlight-
dividual from all social, economic and biological
enment ideals of reason, progress, individual freedom
contingencies.
and equal rights. For example, the notion of uni-
comes disembedded and disembodied, giving rise
versal reason, central to the thought of liberal En-
to a unitary vision of the self ± a self that is the
lightenment philosophers such as Kant, provided
same for all humanity. Hence morality is equated
early feminist thinkers with powerful arguments to
with impartiality, with recognising the claims of the
challenge those social conventions which excluded
other who is just like oneself. Thus, we are invited to
76
8
Subsequently,
the individual
be-
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM
view one another as abstract, autonomous beings,
women's experiences, feminists fear that the liberal
unencumbered by the particularities of our existence.
appeal to `generality' and the subsequent public/
To act morally is to follow the norm of formal
private distinction denies women an effective voice
equality enshrined in a system of justice based on
within the political arena. In this context they have
a network of formal rights and duties. However, for
drawn attention not only to the fact that historically
many feminists such an account of the individual
women have been assigned to the private sphere, but
ignores the extent to which our identity is irrevoc-
also to the point that this genderisation of the public/
ably shaped by the particularities and contingencies
private distinction formed for many centuries the
of our existence. Here, a number of feminists have
basis for excluding women from citizenship. Women
highlighted the impact our physical being has on our
were identified with the sphere of the particular and
identity. As Pateman notes, if the individual is to be
the affective, with nurture, reproduction, love and
a universal figure, liberalism must ignore that `hu-
care, and, consequently, were seen as lacking in the
mankind has two bodies, female and male.'
9
This,
qualities required for public life. Yet, if particularity is
however, glosses over the political implications of
assigned to the non-political private sphere, then
women's bodily capacities and passions. For feminists
once women enter the `male' public sphere the way
such as Pateman, the tendency to regard the ato-
in which they differ from men is seen as deviating
mised individual as the norm has led liberal theorists
from the norm. As Susan Mendus points out,
either to view women and children as `deviant' cases
equality then becomes defined in terms of the re-
or to ignore or deny the interdependence between
moval of women's `disadvantage' or `disability', with
women and children.
10
12
`disadvantage' being determined by a model which is
To many feminists, liberal-
intrinsically male.
ism's failure to acknowledge women's experiences has given rise to a discourse in which what consti-
In the eyes of critics such as Young, this margin-
tutes a proper person, a true individual, is represen-
alisation of women's voices in the public realm is
tative of men's experience and reasoning specifically,
indicative of the limitations of the very ideal of
not women's. Paradigmatically, the liberal individual
`generality'. Given that different groups have differ-
becomes synonymous with the independent, proper-
ent experiences, histories and perspectives on social
tied male head of a household.
life, no one group can entirely understand the ex-
Since this conception of the individual shapes
periences of another. Hence no one group can speak
liberal notions of citizenship, the exclusion of the
for another. To adopt, in the face of such profound
perspective of all but one group has important
diversity, a conception of citizenship based upon
political consequences, not only for women, but also
formal equality and impartiality is merely to privilege
for marginalised groups in general. Just as liberals
the dominant group. If all are given equal rights, but
seek to abstract the individual from all social, eco-
no one can speak for the other, the interests of the
nomic and biological contingencies, traditional lib-
dominant group will prevail as the members of the
eral conceptions of democratic citizenship require
dominant group will be able `to assert their experi-
the exclusion of particularity. For Young, liberal
ences of and perspectives on social events as im-
citizenship is therefore characterised by an appeal
partial and objective.'
to an ideal of `generality'.
11
13
So not only does the denial
Citizens are expected to
of difference allow privileged groups to ignore their
transcend their differences and act on the basis of the
own group specificity, it also disadvantages groups
common good or the `general will'. This appeal to
whose experience, culture and socialised capacities
generality entails a sharp distinction between the
differ from this allegedly neutral standard. Given
public and the private sphere. Here the public realm
that, on Young's analysis, the ostensibly neutral
is identified with normative reason and the pursuit of
standards of the liberal public sphere merely reflect
shared interests, whereas difference, particularity and
the experiences of the dominant group ± white,
affectivity are firmly relegated to the private non-
middle-class, western males ± the liberal appeal to
political sphere. Yet, just as the liberal notion of an
formal equality and impartiality prevents the mem-
abstract, disembedded, disembodied self excludes
bers of groups such as women, whose experiences and
77
ANDREA BAUMEISTER
perspectives differ significantly from those of the
unitary self that is relatively stable and unchanging
dominant group, from effectively participating in
and the belief that, although there are significant
the public sphere.
differences between men and women, this self is the same for all women and for all men regardless of class, race or sexual orientation. For anti-essentialists such
Radical Diversity
feminist essentialism is as unsustainable as earlier
and the Dangers of Fragmentation
liberal claims to universality: just as liberalism's fail-
In order to remedy this marginalistion of women's
ure to acknowledge the significance of gender differ-
perspective many feminists have attempted to dis-
ences led theorists to presume that the experience of
place the traditional liberal emphasis upon univers-
male adults can be taken as normative for humanity
ality and formal equality with a notion of citizenship
at large, so the focus on `women as women' has given
which recognises the political significance of differ-
rise to a discourse in which the experiences of
ence and particularity. Initially this led them to focus
western, white, middle-class women have been con-
on the differences between men and women in an
flated with the experiences of all women. Conse-
attempt to highlight the political significance of
quently, just as liberal universalism defines difference
women's traditional experiences as mothers and
in terms of a deviation from a standard that is
carers. Writers such as Elshtain, Dinnerstein and
essentially male, so feminist essentialism views dif-
Ruddick
14
argued that the virtues of love, empathy,
compassion
and
emotional
sensitivity
ferences among women as a divergence from a
associated
with women's traditional role as mothers and carers
standard that is defined by the experiences of Wes-
15
tern, white, middle-class women. Hence in Spel-
have potentially important political implications and
man's opinion `the phrase ``as a woman'' is the
are indeed capable of laying the foundations for a
Trojan horse of feminist ethnocentrism.'
better society. However, while such attempts to stress
eyes of these writers, feminist essentialism treats the
the political consequences of women's experiences
experiences of women who are subject to multiple
provide a forceful critique of liberal universalism and
forms of oppression as merely `addition' problems:
the liberal public/private distinction, an increasing
black women suffer from sexism plus racism, while
number of contemporary feminists have argued that
working-class women are oppressed by sexism plus
such attempts to formulate a `women's politics' con-
class structures. For Spelman and Harris such an
tinue to endorse a unitary vision of individual iden-
approach not only forcibly fragments the experiences
tity
of black, poor and lesbian women, but also leads
and
ultimately
still
fail
to
take
difference
seriously.
19
In the
feminists to presume that the oppression women face
This regard for the wider implications of difference
`as women' is best identified by studying the position
is informed not only by an increasing awareness of
of women who are not subject to other forms of
the experiences
and other
oppression. This privileges the experiences of wes-
minority feminists, but reflects the general scepticism
tern, white, middle-class women. For example, char-
regarding all universal claims typical of postmodern
acterisations of the dominant feminine stereotype as
thought. For writers like Spelman, Harris, hooks and
passive and dependent failed to recognise the ex-
Flax,
16
of African-American
concepts such as `gender' and `woman' are
periences of black women who have struggled against
profoundly problematic unless they are `qualified by
images of matriarchy and sexual permissiveness. In a
and seen in the context of race, class, ethnicity and
similar vein the claim by many second-wave femin-
17
From this perspective the em-
ists that the solution to women's oppression was to be
phasis a `women's politics' places on the experience
found in work outside the home ignored the experi-
and identity of `women as such' implies an unsus-
ences of millions of women who had always worked
tainable essentialism. As Harris notes, the claim that
outside the home, but for whom work had been a far
the `biological and social implications of mother-
from `liberating' experience.
other differences'.
18
rests
Spelman and Harris conclude that instead of
upon two key assumptions: the supposition of a deep
holding onto unsustainable notions of a deep, uni-
hood shape the selfhood of all or most women'
78
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM
tary and stable women's self, feminists must recognise
fragmentation which may not only threaten the
that women are enmeshed in many and often contra-
viability of a wider feminist politics, but may ulti-
dictory discourses of sexuality, race and class. There-
mately undermine the very notion of democratic
fore, in place of the objective, rational and universal
citizenship. As Young notes,
standpoint central to the liberal disembedded and
as Spelman have tended to regard the categories of
disembodied self, Spelman and Harris posit a vision
class, race and nationality as relatively fixed, the
of a radically embedded, subjective self. From such a
stability of these categories is just as doubtful as the
perspective identities are seen as multiplicitous, con-
appropriateness of the category of `women'. One
tingent and context-bound. Differences are always
possible response to this complex interaction be-
relational not inherent. Thus `the social agent is
tween race, class, nationality and gender is to dis-
constituted by an assembly of subject positions that
tinguish further between subcategories. Thus one
can never be totally fixed in a closed system of
could, for example, subdivide working-class women
differences.'
20
23
whereas theorists such
further according to race, religion, nationality, eth-
Since identity is always defined in a gender
nicity, region and sexuality, or distinguish between
should not only be viewed as a relational concept,
the different attributes of an African-American gen-
whose characteristics and attributes can only be
der in relation to African-American men on the one
identified by comparing the situation of women with
hand and white men on the other. However, given
that of men. The construction of gender attributes
that `any category can be considered an arbitrary
will also vary according to race, class and nationality.
unity', such a strategy ultimately gives rise to an
The task of feminist theorising is not to attempt to
infinite regress which dissolves all `groups into in-
construct essences, but to explore these contingent
dividuals'.
relationships. Such an approach clearly has far-
fragmentation is liable to undermine the wider sym-
reaching implications with regard to the political
pathies essential to a shared sense of citizenship.
sphere. Given that what constitutes a woman differs
While cooperation for the common good and gen-
across cultural and social contexts, a common wo-
eral solidarity are widely regarded as important ele-
men's perspective cannot simply be regarded as a
ments of democratic citizenship, a commitment to
metaphysical given. On the contrary, `while some
`radical otherness' is liable to give rise to a focus on
women share some common interests and face some
sectional interests.
common enemies, such commonalties are by no
norms and standards, understanding and cooperation
means universal; rather they are interlaced with
across group lines is likely to prove difficult, if not
specific
context
Á -vis vis-a
specific
differences, even with conflict.'
21
others,
24
In the eyes of critics such a process of
25
Indeed, in the absence of shared
Feminism, there-
impossible. From the perspective of traditionally
fore, constitutes a complex network of different
marginalised groups this failure to generate wider
strands, which link discourses of gender to those
sympathies is potentially rather worrying. In the
of
orientation.
absence of a general sense of solidarity, not only
Rather than a unitary political movement, it is
may we lose any reason to hope that the dominant
therefore best regarded as the product of a complex,
groups within society could cultivate feelings of
shifting and often difficult `patchwork of overlapping
obligation to take into account the perspective
class,
alliances'.
race,
ethnicity
and
sexual
22
and needs of less powerful groups, but the possibility
While this vision of deep and radical diversity has
of solidarity between the latter may also recede.
been highly influential, not all second-wave femin-
Indeed, the process of differentiation could lead to
ists have endorsed such an outright rejection of
the fragmentation of wider political movements such
liberal principles. Indeed a number of feminists have
as feminism.
expressed profound disquiet about the political im-
In the light of these fears a number of feminists
plications of a commitment to `radical otherness'.
have reasserted the importance of women's shared
The basic worry here is that in the absence of any
experiences and the continued relevance of universal
appeal to universally shared standards, an emphasis
standards. In contrast to the anti-essentialist denial
upon radical diversity will give rise to a process of
of
79
a
`generalisable,
identifiable
and
collectively
ANDREA BAUMEISTER
shared experience of womanhood',
26
feminists such
influential contemporary feminist conceptions of
as Okin assert that sexism does constitute `an iden-
citizenship. For example, in Iris Marion Young's
tifiable form of oppression many of whose effects are
model of `the heterogeneous public' the commitment
felt by women regardless of race and class.'
27
Thus,
to difference and diversity is tempered by a recogni-
she claims that, if the findings of Anglo-American
tion of the appeal of liberal values and preoccupa-
feminists about justice within the household are
tions.
compared with the burdens and benefits in poor
group has its own unique experiences, histories and
households, the injustices of gender are revealed
perspectives on social life, which can never be
to be quite similar: `in both situations, women's
entirely understood or adequately represented by
access to paid work is constrained both by sex
outsiders, she nonetheless retains a commitment to
segregation in the workplace and the assumption
universality and the equality of moral worth of all
that women are ``naturally'' responsible for all or
persons. While the principle of equal moral worth
most of the unpaid work of the household.'
28
32
Although Young stresses that each social
Not
provides a powerful argument in favour of the in-
only does feminist anti-essentialism fail to recognise
clusion of all members of society in social and
the significance of women's shared experiences, it
political life, the liberal commitment to formal pro-
also underestimates the potential appeal of the lib-
cedural rules and basic rights safeguards minorities
eral
ob-
against the whim of the majority by setting limits to
historically the standards of impartiality
democratic deliberation and outcomes. However,
implied by the liberal notion of a common humanity
although Young appeals to the value of universality
have been employed by many oppressed groups,
at the point of inclusion, she stresses that `univers-
including women, in their struggle for equality. Thus
ality in the sense of the participation and inclusion of
liberal notions of universality and formal equality
everyone in moral and social life does not imply
have enabled oppressed groups to show that the
universality in the sense of the adoption of a general
manner in which they differ from the dominant
point of view that leaves behind particular affilia-
group ± be it in terms of gender, race or religion ±
tions, feelings, commitments and desires.'
does not constitute a legitimate ground for excluding
the liberal ideal of `impartial reason' (the `general
them from citizenship. For Okin and Martha Nuss-
point of view') fails to recognise the significance of
universalist
serves,
baum,
29
30
project.
As
Anne
Phillips
33
For her,
such an appeal to universal standards is
difference and particularity on at least three counts:
today still likely to be the most effective tool for
it insists that all situations are treated according to
31
A crucial
the same moral rule and thus `denies the particularity
problem is that the victims of oppression and dom-
of situations'; it tries to `master or eliminate hetero-
ination frequently not only lack the intellectual and
geneity in the form of feeling' by abstracting the
economic resources to challenge these injustices, but
individual from the needs, inclinations and feelings
have often internalised the very values which op-
which accompany particular situations; and, most
press them. According to Nussbaum and Okin, then,
importantly, it reduces the `plurality of moral judge-
such deeply entrenched discrimination can only be
ments to one subjectivity' by abstracting the subject
challenged effectively by an appeal to universal
from the particularities which individualise her.
standards. These can be employed to hold local
Thus, while acknowledging the potential appeal of
government,
international
liberal values and preoccupations, Young contends
bodies such as the UN to account for their failure
that the scope and nature of these values must be
to improve the position of women.
reconceptualised to account for the political claims
securing equality for women worldwide.
aid
organisations
and
34
of difference and particularity. Since each group differs with regard to its experiences, history and
The `Heterogeneous Public'
perspective on social life, equality in terms of the
This awareness of the potential strength of the
participation and inclusion of all groups requires a
traditional liberal emphasis upon universality and
specific set of rights for each group and for some
equality has been reflected in some of the most
groups a more comprehensive system than for others.
80
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM
In place of the liberal emphasis upon formal equality,
unified passively by the objects around which their
Young proposes a differentiated citizenship which
actions are orientated or by the material effects of the
guarantees `the effective recognition and representa-
actions of the other.'
tion of the distinct voices and perspectives of those
do not see themselves engaged in a common en-
of its constituent groups that are oppressed or dis-
terprise and hence do not identify with one another,
advantaged.'
35
37
While the members of a series
Since dominant groups within society
their actions are constrained by the same set of
will always attempt to shape the public sphere in the
material objects and collective habits which provide
light of their experiences and perspective, tradition-
the background for the actions of each member of
ally marginalised groups, such as women, the poor,
the series. For Young, the series of `women' is con-
ethnic minorities and the old, should be granted
stituted by the `rules, practices and assumptions of
additional rights to group-specific representation at
institutionalised heterosexuality' and the accompa-
the various levels of government, thereby increasing
nying sexual division of labour.
their opportunities for political participation. Op-
structures both enable and constrain action, they do
pressed groups should be provided with the resources
not define it and different individuals may adopt a
to organise themselves, should be invited to analyse
whole range of strategies to deal with gender struc-
and formulate social policy proposals and should
tures.
have the right to veto specific policies which affect
identity . . . will escape the markings of gender . . .
groups directly. Young contends that, given the
how gender marks her life is her own.'
different
experiences
and
perspectives
of
Hence,
although
38
`no
While these gender
individual
woman's
39
social
On Young's account, it is this serialised existence
groups, such measures are vital to promote justice.
which provides the basis for women's collective
Thus group-specific representation for traditionally
action. Groups of women are formed when women
marginalised groups ensures greater procedural fair-
take up and reconstruct `the gendered structures that
ness in the setting of the public agenda, allows for the
have passively unified them'.
recognition of all needs and interests in democratic
unlikely to incorporate all women, but are usually
deliberations and adds to democratic accountability
socially, historically and culturally specific. Here she
by providing an `antidote to self-deceiving interest
is careful to distinguish her conception of a social
masked as an impartial or general interest.'
36
40
Such groups are
group from both interest and identity groups. Thus social groups are neither merely an `aggregate or
Young's heterogeneous public clearly offers a so-
41
phisticated model for a feminist reconceptualisation
association of persons who seek a particular goal',
of citizenship which combines a recognition of the
nor are they the expression of an essential set of
political significance of difference and particularity
characteristics. Rather, social groups define them-
with a commitment to universality and equality of
selves in relation to one another. Since group iden-
moral worth at the point of inclusion. Yet, despite its
tities
apparent strength, her model of group representation
differentiation, they are fluid and often shifting.
remains at odds with both her dynamic conception
Group membership, therefore, does not signify a
of social collectives and her commitment to delib-
shared set of attributes; it is the product of a sense
erative democracy.
of identification and affinity. But, while social groups
are
the
product
of
this
process
of
Young offers a fluid and multi-layered conception
are partially constitutive of their members' identities,
of social collectives, which seek to acknowledge the
an individual is not wholly determined by her group
worries expressed by feminist anti-essentialists while
membership. In many ways she remains independent
safeguarding the possibility of a women's politics
from the group's identity and can transcend and
based upon collective action. Women should not,
reject group membership. In a complex, plural so-
in the first instance, be conceived of as a unified
ciety this sense of fluidity is further reinforced by
social group but are best viewed as a series. While
multiple group
groups are self-conscious, mutually acknowledging
every social group has group differences cutting
collectives with a shared sense of purpose, a `series'
across it.
refers to `a social collective whose members are
membership, which ensures that
However, while Young's fluid, multi-layered con-
81
ANDREA BAUMEISTER
ception of social collectives may allay many of the
principles which are not merely local. She herself
fears of anti-essentialists, her sophisticated under-
appears to recognise this when she maintains that
standing of collective identity and action does ap-
only those claims `are normatively valid which are
pear
group
generalisable in the sense that they can be recognised
representation. The notion of a guaranteed right
without violating the rights of others or subjecting
to group representation implies that groups can be
them to domination.'
readily identified, have a stable membership and are
dards by which such claims are to be assessed are not
sufficiently homogeneous to be able to formulate a
merely local. Yet, although such an emphasis upon
group response. A system which guaranteed op-
`generalisability' would offer an effective route for the
pressed groups the right to representation would
resolution of group conflict, it entails a commitment
hardly encourage them to recognise the contextual
to impartiality that is at odds with the regard for
nature and fluidity of their boundaries. On the
particularity and partiality central to the notion of
contrary, it would be in the interests of groups to
group representation. While Young could potentially
remain distinct and to attempt to build a loyal, fixed
overcome this tension by basing her defence of group
membership. Therefore, group representation may
representation upon an appeal to impartiality, this
not only be divisive, but it could also encourage
would place her conception of a `differentiated citi-
precisely the `essentialism' Young is so keen to avoid.
zenship' back within the liberal tradition she rejects.
to
be
at
odds
with
her
notion
of
45
This suggests that the stan-
The degree of division associated with group
However, such a return to liberal ideas should
representation will in part depend on the wider
arguably neither alarm nor surprise feminists. Liberal-
mechanisms for democratic decision-making.
42
In
ism is a rich and complex tradition which in the final
this context Young is keen to distinguish her model
analysis may not be as hostile to diversity as feminists
of communicative democracy from interest-group
frequently assume. Here, the distinction Kant draws
pluralism. Rather than simply assert their predeter-
between perfect and imperfect obligations and the
mined interests, democratic deliberation requires
open-ended, context-responsive manner in which a
that `participants discuss together the issues and
Kantian approach determines specific obligations are
come to a decision according to principles of jus-
of particular interest. These traditional Kantian con-
43
Therefore the participants in democratic
cerns have continued to inform the work of con-
discourse must express their demands not as wants
temporary Kantians such as Habermas. His context-
but as entitlements of justice. However, given the
responsive conception of impartiality allows for the
specificity of group experience, the various partici-
recognition of the complex relationship between the
pants will not always be able to recognise the claims
public and the private and is sensitive to the de-
of others and a certain amount of conflict is inevi-
mands for more effective representation on the part
table. The manner in which such conflicts are to be
of traditionally marginalised groups.
tice.'
resolved will largely depend upon the nature and character of the public standards that govern demo-
Liberal Citizenship,
cratic deliberation. Yet here Young remains vague.
Difference and Particularity
At times she suggests that these standards are local and do not entail an appeal to impartiality and the
From a Kantian perspective the imperative to treat
`general point of view'. Thus she contends that `the
humanity as an `end' and never merely as a `means'
rationality of norms can be grounded only by under-
requires of us not only to abstain from infringing the
standing them as the outcome of discussion includ-
rights of others, but also to take, as far as possible, an
44
But, if
active interest in the well-being of others. This
these standards are strictly local, then once negotia-
concern is central to the Kantian conception of
tion has broken down the decision-making process
imperfect duties. Therefore, while perfect obligations,
comes to a standstill. However, Young's own appeal
such as non-coercion and non-deceit, address ques-
to universality at the level of participation indicates
tions of justice, imperfect duties, like benevolence
that such conflicts should be resolved by an appeal to
and charity, focus upon the specific circumstances of
ing all those who will be bound by them.'
82
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM
particular individuals. For Kant,
46
important to ensure de facto rather than mere de jure
such imperfect
48
obligations are not supererogatory; they constitute
equality.
a vital aspect of a balanced moral approach. How-
citizens formal equality, equal rights and liberties can
ever, whereas perfect obligations can be discharged by
be used differently and may impact upon citizens
simply abstaining from certain actions, such as, for
differentially depending upon their circumstances.
instance, coercion or deceit and are, therefore, uni-
Thus genuine equality can only be guaranteed if the
versally
require
specific needs and circumstances of particular others
time, presence, resources and an understanding of
are taken into account. These considerations are
the particular situation and circumstances of the
akin to the concerns Kant addresses via the notion
other. Consequently, imperfect obligations are con-
of imperfect duties. Furthermore, just as a context-
text-specific. Once the principle of universalisability
responsive reading of the categorical imperative
is combined with the recognition of particularity,
differentiates between ancillary and fundamental
indifference to the specific circumstances and needs
principles of action, Habermas stresses the need to
of others is not permissible since it may constitute a
distinguish between the formulation and the appli-
threat to the agency of the other.
cation of norms. While norms can be justified by
applicable,
imperfect
obligations
While a formal system of rights may grant
This regard for difference and particularity is
reference to universal principles, the impartial jus-
further underlined by the context-responsive reading
tification of a norm requires careful attention to the
of the categorical imperative advocated by modern
specific circumstances of a given situation. To apply
Kantians such as O'Neill and Herman.
47
While the
a norm impartially we must determine whether, in
categorical imperative aims to rule out fundamental
the light of all relevant facts, a specific norm is the
principles of action which could not consistently be
most appropriate one in these circumstances.
adopted by all, it does not apply to ancillary prin-
Within the context of citizenship the sensitivity of
ciples. After all since the particular considerations
the Kantian tradition to specific circumstances and
which inform our actions in particular circumstances
particular needs provides a potentially powerful the-
vary widely, the more specific principles upon which
oretical framework for voicing the concerns that have
human beings may act cannot be universally acted
preoccupied many contemporary feminists. For in-
upon. While the categorical imperative rules out
stance, the distinction between perfect and imperfect
certain fundamental principles, it cannot, by itself,
duties enables a Kantian approach to be sensitive to the
discriminate among more specific principles of ac-
problems highlighted by feminists such as Young.
tion. Consequently, the adoption of ancillary mo-
While the emphasis on our common humanity which
tives which could not be consistently adopted by all
informs the Kantian notion of perfect duties provides a
is not prohibited. Thus the categorical imperative
powerful justification for the extension of citizenship
merely provides us with a criterion against which to
to all members of society and offers a clear set of
measure principles. It does not tell us which princi-
standards for resolving potential conflicts between
ples to select in specific situations and how to
the demands of various citizens, the idea of imperfect
implement them. To work out what an obligation
duties ensures that a Kantian conception of citizenship
entails in a specific situation requires careful evalua-
will be sensitive to the specific needs and circum-
tion of the various elements which influence the
stances of particular citizens. From a Kantian perspec-
situation. The main purpose of the categorical im-
tive citizenship is not merely a question of granting
perative, therefore, is to provide a starting-point for
everyone the same formal rights. It also implies an
this process of critical reflection.
obligation to ensure that all individuals are in a posi-
Kant's concern with the specific circumstances of
tion to effectively fulfil their role as citizens. In the light
particular others and context sensitivity in the ap-
of these considerations Habermas (and other contem-
plication of norms have continued to inform the
porary Kantians) have stressed the need for greater
work of contemporary Kantians. Thus, for example,
political participation on the part of traditionally
in his recent work Ju È rgen Habermas has argued that
marginalised or socially disadvantaged groups.
if the autonomy of all citizens is to be protected, it is
as imperfect obligations highlight human vulnerability
83
49
Just
ANDREA BAUMEISTER
and particularity, Habermas highlights the complex
Rather than placing the burden on marginalised
relationship between the public and the private
groups to claim their rights, the language of obliga-
sphere. Given that persons are individuated through
tions reminds the powerful of the moral requirement
the processes of socialisation, personal autonomy can
to fulfil their duties. Consequently the powerful
only be safeguarded if the life-context within which an
cannot simply ignore the needs and aspirations of
individual's identity is formulated is also protected.
traditionally marginalised groups. Furthermore, the
This can only be achieved if all citizens participate in
open-ended manner in which an obligation-based
the formulation and interpretation of the rights and
approach establishes specific obligations is well-sui-
norms that safeguard individual autonomy. After all,
ted to capture the emphasis contemporary feminists
unless all citizens participate in public debate and
have placed on the complex and multiplicitous
express their specific needs, there is a real danger that
nature of women's identities. Whereas a rights per-
the specific needs of socially disadvantaged groups will
spective requires the prior establishment of a set of
be misunderstood. This in turn may undermine the
rights in order to function, an obligation-based
capacity of such groups to pursue effectively their own
approach can allow for obligations to be established
conception of the good life. Thus for Habermas gen-
as situations arise. All an obligation-based approach
uine equality between men and women cannot be
needs is a formula, such as the categorical imperative,
achieved unless women take part in the formulation of
which can be applied to specific situations in order to
the criteria which determine what kind of treatment is
establish which obligations flow from these situa-
to count as equal. Yet, since traditionally marginalised
tions. A Kantian perspective therefore recognises
groups may require support to organise themselves and
that the nature and extent of the obligation to ensure
to effectively participate in the political process, Ha-
the effective exercise of citizenship can only be
bermas acknowledges that some citizens may require
established in response to the particular needs and
special cultural and social rights. However, in contrast
circumstances of given individuals.
to Young, Habermas not only conceptualises such
The regard for particularity and human vulner-
cultural and social rights as individual rights, he clearly
ability already evident in Kant's work suggests that
grounds them in a liberal appeal to impartiality. There-
this strand of liberal thought is potentially capable of
fore while, like Young, Habermas advocates a discur-
providing a framework for a richer and more ba-
sive model of democracy, his approach avoids the
lanced account of citizenship. Undoubtedly the re-
tensions inherent in Young's `heterogeneous public'.
sponses to the claims of difference and diversity
Although modern Kantians such as Habermas
advocated by contemporary Kantians remain proble-
invoke the language of rights, feminists, in their
matic. Habermas, for example, has quite rightly been
struggle to secure greater participation for women,
criticised for advocating a model of communication
may find it advantageous to formulate their demands
which places an undue emphasis upon critical, ra-
in Kant's language of obligations. Since on Kant's
tional argumentation, marginalising the speech pat-
account those in power have a clear duty to assist
terns of traditionally disadvantaged groups such as
those less fortunate, an obligation-based approach
women.
which firmly places the onus on those in positions of
an approach tempers its commitment to `universal-
influence to take all steps in their power to ensure
ity' with a recognition of `diversity' suggests that such
that every citizen is capable of effectively exercising
an account of liberal citizenship may enable feminists
her citizenship is liable to strengthen the position of
to resolve one of the most troubling tensions at the
traditionally marginalised groups such as women.
heart of contemporary feminist theorising.
50
Nonetheless, the manner in which such
Notes
1. Pateman (1988); Young (1990).
3. Okin (1994); M. Nussbaum, `Human Capabilities,
2. Spelman (1988); Harris (1990); hooks (1981); Flax
Female Human Beings', in Nussbaum and Glover
(1995).
(eds) (1995), pp. 61±104.
84
LIBERAL CITIZENSHIP AND FEMINISM
4. Young (1990).
31. For Nussbaum the commitment to the `radical other-
5. Kant (1963b).
ness' of different cultures has led some theorists to
6. Habermas (1993).
defend or at least condone many traditional cultural
7. Ferguson (1985); Wollstonecraft (1989). See, also, Kate
practices which systematically discriminate against
Soper's chapter in the present volume for a close analysis
women. Here Nussbaum cites two vivid examples of
of early feminism's relationship with the Enlightenment.
the approaches to which she objects. The first one
8. Pateman (1988).
refers to an American economist who cites the ex-
9. Ibid., p. 8.
tension of the idea that menstruating women pollute
10. Frazer (1996).
the kitchen to the workplace as an instance of the
11. Young (1989).
integration of the values that prevail in the workplace
12. Mendus (1992).
with those that shape home life, an integration which
13. Young (1989), p. 259.
he regards as lacking in Western countries. The
14. Elshtain (1981); Dinnerstein (1976); Ruddick (1989).
second one refers to a French anthropologist who
15. Many of these early attempts to formulate a `politics of
`expresses regret that the introduction of smallpox
maternal thinking' were influenced by Carol Gilligan's
vaccination in India by the British eradicated the cult
work on moral development (Gilligan, 1982). For
of Sittala Devi, the goddess to whom one used to pray
Gilligan not only the self but also the other person
in order to prevent smallpox,' (Nussbaum, `Human
towards whom one is acting has to be viewed as
Capabilities, Female Human Beings', in Nussbaum and Glover (eds) (1995), p. 65).
radically situated and particularised. Thus, the generalised other of liberal theory is replaced by the
32. Young (1990).
notion of the concrete other.
33. Ibid., p. 105. 34. Ibid., p. 100.
16. Spelman (1988); Harris (1990); hooks (1981); Flax
35. Ibid., p. 184.
(1995). 17. Okin (1994), p 6.
36. Ibid., p.185.
18. Harris (1990), p. 603.
37. Young (1995), p. 199.
19. Spelman (1988), p. 13.
38. Ibid., p. 204.
20. Mouffe (1992), p. 28.
39. Ibid., p. 209.
21. Fraser and Nicholson (1988), p. 391.
40. Ibid., p. 210.
22. Ibid.
41. Young (1990), p. 186.
23. Young (1995). As Young notes, it is, for example,
42. For an interesting discussion of the relationship be-
simply misleading to assume that a working-class
tween Young's commitment to group representation
woman's gendered experiences can only be properly
and her model of communicative democracy see J.
identified by comparing her situation to that of work-
Squires, `Group Representation, Deliberation and the
ing-class men. After all, gendered experiences such as
Displacement of Dichotomies', in M. Saward (ed.),
sexual harassment cut across class lines.
Innovations in Democratic Theory (London: Routledge,
forthcoming).
24. Ibid., p. 195.
43. Young (1990), p. 190.
25. See, S. Mendus, `Time and Chance: Kantian Ethics and Feminist Philosophy', Morrell Discussion Paper
44. Ibid., p 116.
(York: Department of Politics, University of York,
45. Ibid., p 107.
1990).
46. Kant (1963b). 47. O'Neill (1986); Herman (1985).
26. S. Benhabib and D. Cornell, cited in Okin (1994), p.
48. Habermas (1993).
9. 27. Ibid., p. 7.
49. Ibid.
28. Ibid., p. 9.
50. See I. M. Young, `Communication and the Other:
29. Phillips (1993).
Beyond Deliberative Democracy', in Benhabib (ed.)
30. S. Okin, `Inequalities Between the Sexes in Different
(1996), pp. 120±35. Feminists such as Warnke have
Cultural Contexts', in Nussbaum and Glover (eds)
also questioned whether it is possible to draw a sharp
(1995), pp. 275±97; M. Nussbaum, `Human Capabil-
a distinction between the application and formula-
ities, Female Human Beings', in Nussbaum and Glover
tion of norms as Habermas advocates (see Warnke,
(eds) (1995), pp. 61±104.
1995).
85
This page intentionally left blank
Part Three JUSTICE: IDENTITY AND DISTRIBUTION
This page intentionally left blank
7
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION Jonathan Seglow
automatically be resolved in favour of the latter.
I
Rather, there must be some interpretive compromise
Liberals, it is said nowadays, are having trouble com-
on both sides so that recognition can be incorporated
ing to terms with the concept of recognition. They are
into the liberal canon.
not sure what it is and hence do not know how to evaluate it, whether to incorporate it into the liberal
II
canon or eschew it altogether. And this is odd because recognition is always familiar to us. Or at any rate, less
We should begin by acquainting ourselves with the
glibly, the concept of recognition is not a difficult one.
kinds of claims to recognition actually made by
It is the universal human need to have one's identity
minorities, of different sorts, in a liberal society.
esteemed and valued by others. It is a vital need
The sorts of cases I have in mind include the
because in order to be an effective agent in a liberal
following:
society, with a secure sense of one's own identity, you
.
require recognition ± positive affirmation ± from
Should the children of recent immigrants be
others. Politically speaking, recognition is the need
entitled to schooling in their mother tongue on
to have one's group identity publicly appraised and
the grounds that without it their language
affirmed. But political recognition is in short supply
would swiftly die away, depriving the second
among some groups in liberal societies. Many mem-
generation of an important sense of orientation and identity?
bers of minority cultures, in particular, do not receive
.
the public recognition they deserve. And one reason
Should racist (`hate') speech against specific
for that is a lacuna in liberal theory itself: it does not
minorities be outlawed on the grounds that it is
recognise the importance of recognition in forming
not just offensive but threatens their fairly
individual and social identities. In this chapter, then, I
fragile public presence in a wider community not of their making?
will argue for an agenda: that recognition should enter
.
the normative constellation of liberalism (of some
Should a gay couple be entitled to a legally
sort). I say `of some sort' because there are certainly
recognised same-sex marriage on the grounds
conflicts between recognition and orthodox liberal
that they should enjoy public recognition of
values such as freedom, opportunity and impartiality.
their mutual commitment just like a mixed couple?
But, as this volume amply demonstrates, the liberal
.
identity is itself contested so there is no reason that
Should religious minorities enjoy exemptions and privileges with respect to dress codes at
conflicts between recognition and these values should
89
JONATHAN SEGLOW
work (for example, Sikh policemen who wear
.
.
.
I mentioned just now that recognition
place of a conventional school uniform)?
disadvantage and this idea is crucial to the liberal
Should public resources be directed towards
account of social justice. The crucial distinction is
measures which benefit minority communities
between unchosen circumstances, which people are
and only them (such as building cultural or
not responsible for, and their own freely made
religious centres)?
choices, which they are. While we quite properly
Should there be quotas which make it easier for
must bear the cost of our choices, we are not
under-represented groups such as ethnic mino-
responsible for the unchosen circumstances which
rities and women to gain university places and
diminish our capacity to choose in the first place.
certain jobs?
Some people in society ± the poor, the ill, the
Should curricula in state schools be revised to
handicapped, the unemployed, for example ± la-
promote a positive image of minority commu-
bour under disadvantages which other members of
nities' history and cultural achievements?
1
suffer
from
some
those who claim
turbans or Muslim girls who wear the chador in
sort
of
unchosen
society do not face and which prevent them from choosing how to live their lives. The basic principle
These cases are all quite different, and involve
of
the
liberal
theory
of
social
justice
is,
`cultures' in the very broadest sense of the term to
therefore, that unchosen circumstantial disadvan-
include ethnic groups, religions and genders. None-
tages should be compensated for, and in a way that
theless, at the risk of distorting some particular cases I
enables each person to determine for herself how
shall consider them all together as claims for recog-
she should live her life.
nition made by `collectives' or `groups', or cultures in
Two critical normative assumptions are made by
this broad sense. Now all these recognition claims are
this liberal account. First, all human beings are
claims for justice too because each group suffers from
regarded (for the purposes of justice) as morally
some sort of unchosen disadvantage and that is what
identical choice-making agents. Looking beyond
social justice aims to correct. They are not mere
the fact that someone is confined to a wheelchair,
wants as when, for example, I demand that you
for example, we see that she is a person who wants to
recognise my `need' for a million pounds. However,
be able to determine how she lives her life. It is just
as claims of justice, they are all highly contentious
the bad luck of being disabled which prevents her
from a liberal perspective. For they are claims for
from doing this. The second assumption is that the
special treatment, for something extra in the way of
circumstantial disadvantages which people face ±
rights or resources which other people do not have.
such as illness, handicap and poverty ± are all
This goes against the central liberal idea that the
contingent and not essential aspects of a person's
state should be impartial among different citizens
identity. By this I mean that people regard them-
whatever their particular identities and allegiances.
selves fundamentally as choice-making agents. Very
The impartial liberal state does offer respect for each
often, this is evidenced by the fact that a person
person's abstract moral worth, but for it to recognise
would much rather be without the disabling aspect of
particular concrete identities appears to be a viola-
her identity. Hence the compensation individuals
tion of impartiality. Put another way, the liberal state
receive in order to overcome their disadvantage has,
allows people to be different, but why should it
whatever its specific form, the same generic purpose:
actively sponsor such difference?
to enable them to regain the capacity for being a choice-making agent.
To address these questions we need first to examine the theory of social justice of which liberal
Can this account of social justice address the
political theory typically avails itself. I shall sketch a
claims for recognition I listed earlier? There are good
simplified version of the account of equal opportu-
reasons for thinking it cannot. To begin with, the
nities developed by John Rawls and Ronald Dwor-
kinds of people who make claims for recognition do
kin, and then we can assess whether it can address
not regard themselves first and foremost as choice-
these sorts of claims to recognition.
2
making agents. Rather it is a particular identity they
90
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION
want recognised. Immigrant ethnic groups who de-
looking at Charles Taylor's essay, `The Politics of
mand a more positive public evaluation of their
Recognition'.
3
culture, for example, want the culture to be recognised, not their choice-making capacity. While they
III
are in a disadvantaged position because of their cultural membership, they do not regard their culture
The notion of recognition takes as central a person's
as a disabling circumstance which merits compensa-
own view of what she is about, her identity. Identity
tion like the wheelchair-bound person. On the
involves taking a normative attitude towards one's
contrary, they want their culture positively affirmed
own substantive traits and abilities, what following
and promoted. More generally, the liberal theory of
Taylor I will call an agent's self-interpretations.
social justice seems ill-equipped to deal with what we
These self-interpretations are basic and constitutive
might call `ideational' issues that relate to ethnicity
of who I am: there is no prior autonomous self that
and culture, gender and sexual orientation, religion
can assess and revise them. To assume otherwise just
and language, and so on. It seems better suited to
pushes the question back a stage of what this auton-
addressing material disadvantages such as poverty,
omous self is. Thus as Taylor puts it, `to ask what a
illness and handicap. Indeed, many ideational in-
person is, in abstraction from his or her self-inter-
justices may not appear to be injustices at all for the
pretations, is to ask a fundamentally misguided ques-
liberal theory. Is it an injustice for the children of
tion, one to which there couldn't in principle be an
recent immigrants not to be entitled to schooling in
answer.'
their mother tongue, for example? Is it unjust (as
fundamental way, formed by others. I have the
opposed to unfortunate) to have overwhelmingly
self-interpretations that I do because I have inter-
negative images of some minority ethnic group dis-
nalised how others see me. The basic idea is that only
played in the media? It is hard to see how the liberal
through others' recognition can one acquire an
theory can view these as injustices.
identity. But of course if that were the only way
4
Now one's self-interpretations are, in a
This leads us naturally to ask whether the idea-
of acquiring an identity the individual person would
tional realms of culture, ethnicity and so on are really
merely be a locus for external social forces. So we
fit subjects for justice at all. If they were not, there
must add a second, more individual, moment to
would be no need to extend liberal social justice to
personal identity which appropriates the internalised
accommodate them. But I think there are two very
attitudes of others for its own purposes, and, no less
good reasons which show that ideational issues are
critical, looks outwards and takes attitudes towards
injustices which liberalism must address. The first
others. These two moments ± self and others ±
reason, which I discuss in the next section, hinges on
synthesise in the identity of a psychologically fully
the phenomenon of self-esteem. Drawing on Axel
formed person. Hence identity is fundamentally a
Honneth's theory of recognition, I will argue that it
negotiated achievement. There is no pure self-making
is only through having one's substantive traits and
(that ignores the need for others' recognition), but
attributes positively appraised by others, that one can
neither are persons constituted by external social
esteem them oneself, and only yet only through self-
forms.
esteem that one can become a properly functioning
pretations, but at the same time I can revise them
agent. I then discuss in section IV how the public
myself and project them outwards in the form of
culture in a liberal society systematically privileges
attitudes to others which in turn help to shape them
certain peoples' identities and derogates others. We
and so on. From this complex and ever-shifting
simply do live in societies that appraise some people's
matrix, different persons' identities are formed.
5
Others' attitudes shape my very self-inter-
identities more positively than others. This gives
In his important recent book on recognition Axel
some groups much greater collective esteem than
Honneth argues that there are three distinct dimen-
others which, since esteem is necessary for identity
sions to the phenomenon: love, rights and solidar-
and agency, is an injustice. In the final sections of the
ity.
chapter I will ask how liberalism might address this,
develops basic self-confidence; she has faith in her
91
6
The human infant who is loved by her parents
JONATHAN SEGLOW
ability to express her needs and desires without being
This quotation highlights the fact that we cannot
abandoned as a result. This capacity to trust one's
disassociate recognition as respect from the more
needs and desires is, Honneth argues, a precondition
substantive recognition which brings self-esteem.
for self-realisation in any human community. I shall
Both aspects (along with self-confidence) are neces-
not discuss it here. When a person is recognised by
sary to produce a person with a fully formed identity.
her community as a bearer of rights, by contrast, she
Substantive recognition of one's traits and abilities is
is recognised to share those universal features of
not simply a welcome endorsement of what you
personhood, such as agency, rationality and respon-
think you are about. It is fundamentally necessary
sibility, which make her able to assert claims upon
to become a properly functioning agent capable of
others. Others' recognition help enable people to
forming intentions and pursuing projects in the first
become claimers of their own rights. Honneth calls
place. It is not an intrusion upon one's autonomy,
this self-respect. Finally, self-esteem connotes a posi-
but rather a precondition of it.
tive relation to one's own substantive, concrete traits
Let us consider the idea of self-esteem more
and abilities. Against the background of a shared, yet
closely. It is a central self-interpretive attitude and
open and plural, value horizon, individuals recognise
takes as its object the substantive empirical traits that
each other as beings with positive traits and abilities
a person has. Someone with a healthy sense of self-
which enable them to contribute to the common
esteem regards her concrete identity as morally valu-
good. This final form of recognition enables indivi-
able, as something worth having and developing. As
duals, operating in a nexus of approving others, to
a precondition for pursuing one's ends, an adequate
realise their own concrete identities.
sense of self-esteem is a universal human need. Of
Honneth's central insight is that to become a
course, a crucial source of self-esteem is success in
person with a fully formed, integrated, fulfilled iden-
one's own projects. If I do well as a painter or a
tity requires recognition by others and this must
footballer, developing certain skills and attributes in
include respect, esteem and love. As he summarises
the process, I generally significantly raise my self-
it:
esteem. But here I want to focus on the converse, the way that self-esteem is a precondition, as much as a It is only due to the cumulative acquisition of
result, of engagement in projects. For a person will
basic self-confidence, of self-respect, and of self-
only engage in her own projects, developing her
esteem ± provided, one after another, by those
traits and abilities, if she thinks they are things worth
three forms of recognition ± that a person can
developing, in other words if she has a degree of self-
come to see himself or herself, unconditionally, as
esteem to begin with. As Honneth shows, this is not
both an autonomous and an individuated being,
the same as self-respect which liberal theory is more
and to identify with his or her goals and desires.
7
familiar with.
9
Self-respect involves recognition of
one's general capacity to make claims upon other These three forms of recognition are not an extra
people. An agent with self-respect is confident that
bonus for agents who are already autonomous any-
she is entitled to pursue her own projects when
way. Rather, they help create the self-interpretations
others disagree that she should do so. But this
which constitute any person's identity. Thus:
confidence in one's abstract moral worth is quite distinct from the value one places on one's own traits
The connection between the experience of re-
and abilities, and projects as externalisations of those
cognition and one's relation-to-self stems from
abilities. Self-esteem involves a positive self-evalua-
the intersubjective structure of personal identity.
tion of the particular person one is, self-respect that
The only way in which individuals are constituted
one shares the inherent dignity of all rights-bearing
as persons is by learning to refer to themselves as,
persons.
from the perspective of an approving or encoura-
When we claim that a person with self-esteem
ging other, beings with certain positive traits or
believes her own traits, abilities and projects are
abilities.
8
valuable and worth having we are making a claim
92
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION
about the prior and independent value of those traits,
they will suffer a deficit in their practical capacity to
abilities and projects. The more immediate and less
be agents in the public realm. In sum, the public
significant decisions an agent takes are genuinely
evaluative status of collective identities has a crucial
matters of taste where we can say of a person that,
bearing on their members' self-esteem and in turn on
because she wills it, a goal is valuable for her. But in
their ability to become properly functioning agents.
order to summon the motivation to pursue longerterm projects and goals, which are externalisations of
IV
her particular abilities, a person must perceive that they have independent value. I could not esteem
I now want to consider the role of the public culture
myself as a good parent or a good doctor, for example,
in providing an orientating medium within which
unless I believed that parenting and medicine were
citizens conduct their lives. Sometimes liberals write
morally valuable goals.
as if individual choice and agency takes place merely
Some putatively valuable features of persons that
within a thin `framework' of rights and liberties with
are significant sources of self-esteem are individual,
no further relevant values. This may be an ideal
such as a talent at music or the virtue of generosity,
inspired by the `fact of pluralism', but as a descriptive
but many others have an irreducible collective di-
claim it is certainly incorrect. Even the most liberal
mension which refers to (for example) gender and
societies contain thick, substantive public cultures
sexuality, ethnicity and religion, and linguistic and
which articulate a great many normative values and
national aspects of one's identity. These are all
ideals. Notwithstanding the fact of pluralism, liberal
features of persons who belong to the relevant group
citizens live by a set of shared ideas and values about
and from which they take pride or, in our terms,
how to live that help bind and integrate their
10
Of course, like other largely unchosen
community and serve as points of reference for
aspects of identity these collective memberships
individual members making their own choices about
may be more or less salient in a person's life. But
how to live. Because this culture is implicit and in
for many people a thriving culture or religion, say, is
the background we do not always realise its great
an important aspect of their self-interpreted identity
power in orientating our ethical identities. But con-
and will contribute significantly to their self-esteem.
sider the attitudes in this country to, say, the role of
On Honneth's view, that self-esteem will in turn
the Christian religion in public life (including its
help fulfil an individual's own identity and develop
implications for free speech), the value and status of
her capacity for agency. It follows, therefore, that if
the family compared to other modes of human
people need recognition in order to develop their
relationship,
identity and capacity for agency, they require it of
health care, our history of Empire and conquest,
these collective aspects as well as of their more
the place of languages other than English in public
individual traits and abilities. In other words, for
life, and more broadly the degree to which immi-
people who do identify with these collective groups,
grants must adapt themselves to our way of life. I
a positive evaluation of them by others enables them
hope that even this (almost) random list reveals the
better to be agents, that is effective pursuers of their
extent to which our public life is substantially nor-
own projects. This is true even where people are
matively
respected as rights-bearing citizens by the rest of the
transmitted through many sorts of social relation-
community. If ethnic minority X is generally re-
ships and amplified by the media, help maintain a
garded to be an uncivilised, backward tribal group,
nation as an `imagined community'. Like all com-
for example, then members of X who identify with it
munities, it takes a stand in moral space. The point is
will suffer a lack of self-esteem and have demeaned
that whatever scope people have for individual
individual identities. If the general view of women is
choice in liberal societies they cannot but take their
that they should do nothing but raise children and
bearings from the public moral consciousness ± the
(to use Mill's phrase) `beautify and adorn the home'
public culture ± of the nation. Of course, this public
then, independent of their legal status as citizens,
culture is not some hypostatic entity standing over
esteem.
93
the
importance
encoded.
Shared
of
publicly
values
and
funded
attitudes,
JONATHAN SEGLOW
and above individual agents. It is woven from the
personal agency. A theory of justice which addresses
fabric of our own attitudes. My claim is simply that
the problem of misrecognition, then, instead of
its normative encoding means that a huge number of
merely respecting people's abstract moral worth,
values and attitudes are privileged from the start and
should focus directly on the public evaluative status
this unfailingly structures whatever choices people
of significant collective identities. Policies of recog-
are formally free to make. Political societies which
nition which raise that status should improve the
are conscious of themselves as such are integrated by
collective self-esteem of members by legal means and
shared norms and values which cannot but have a
by gradually shifting the attitudes of the public
certain moral mass.
culture.
Public cultures are, of course, revisable and re-
As part of a liberal theory of justice, policies of
vised. They change in an evolutionary way. But the
recognition must of course be justifiable not only to
relevant
conservative,
the minority community which benefits from them
theistic or nationalistic society where the public
but also to the majority of citizens who do not. The
culture is seen to be an objective and unchangeable
problem is that policies of recognition will very often
moral system and a liberal society where individuals
involve a redistribution of freedom and opportunity
can participate in the progressive redefinition of
between different groups, and those who lose out will
their public culture. (I will return to the latter
demand some justification. The sorts of redistribu-
ideal.)
between
tions I have in mind include affirmative action
the former ultra-communitarian ideal and a purely
policies which reduce the opportunity for those
procedural republic constituted merely by abstract
who do not benefit from them to gain jobs and
values of freedom and equality in which individuals
places in education; restricting property ownership
can choose to be whatever they like with no moral
in a territory to those whose ethnic homeland it is
`externalities'. A perfectly competitive free market
(which erodes others' rights of movement); abridging
for values and ways of life is an ideal not yet realised
freedom of speech in order not to offend minority
and perhaps unrealisable. (Analogously, consider
religions; and more general redirections of resources
how supposedly value-neutral natural and social
to fund minority activities (their own schools, cul-
scientific research works through dominant para-
tural events, etc.) which of course take away from
digms which orientate practitioners' questions and
resources that could be spent on everyone.
distinction
The
relevant
is
between
distinction
a
is
not
The basic justification undergirding all these mea-
findings.) In sum, a liberal public culture is subor
sures of recognition is an ideal of equality which aims
values are not fixed and immutable but nonetheless
to achieve a rough parity of the social bases of self-
they seep into the crevices within which individuals
esteem, as expressed in law and the public culture, for
exercise freedom of choice.
different social groups. Rather than set out and
stantive
though
revisable
over
time.
Norms
defend how that justification would work in full, which is beyond the scope of this chapter, I would
V
like here merely to explore one aspect of it, and that
When the theory of recognition is linked to the
is the issue of moral value. As I argued above, what
sociological truth about the normative encoding of
disadvantaged groups want recognised is the moral
the public culture we can more clearly see that
value of their collective identities. And the majority
members of certain collectivities have a case in
who do not benefit from the kinds of policies of
justice for political recognition, and more specifically
recognition I've just listed would be more willing to
the kinds of measures I sketched at the beginning.
assent to them if they too appreciate the value of the
The public culture contains a negative appraisal of
way of life the policy is designed to benefit. Hence
certain religious, ethnic, cultural and sexual identi-
the value question is at the heart of the justification
ties which can lower the self-esteem of those for
of a recognition-sensitive liberalism.
whom that collective identity is important. That in
We might argue that only objectively valuable
turn has a negative impact on their own capacity for
collective identities merit official recognition. On
94
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION
this view, collective ways of life that bear great moral
is encapsulated in the notion of authenticity and we
value but which, nonetheless, are systematically
would do well to analyse this first.
devalued by the public culture should be recognised
Authenticity is `the idea that each of us has an
in the ways I've catalogued. Well, we might, but it
original way of being human: each person has his or
isn't promising because whatever moral consensus
her own ``measure'' '.
exists in a political community about the value of
particular, original accent on the human condition.
different ways of life is expressed by the public
Taylor encapsulates the idea of authenticity thus:
13
Each person has their own
culture and yet this, as we've seen, denigrates them. The objective view would have to appeal to a more
There is a certain way of being human that is my
abstract, ideal account of values in order to generate
way. I am called upon to live my life in this way
the moral authority for recognition. But even sup-
and not in imitation of anyone else's life. But this
posing this could be done ± which I doubt ± it would
notion gives a new importance to being true to
suffer from a further drawback: it would begin to lose
myself. If I am not, I miss the point of my life; I
touch with the self-interpretations of those groups
miss what being human is for me.
14
who it seeks to benefit. For it is only by positively evaluating their identity as they perceive it that the
The authentic person tries to construct for herself
self-esteem of demeaned groups is raised; their self-
a unique yet coherent and narratable life-project
interpreted account of the value of their identity may
rather than being an unthinking social conformist.
or may not have any connection with the objective
She will of course internalise others' normative
one. Conversely, then, we could embrace a subjec-
attitudes as her identity cannot but be part-formed
tive account. In this instance any collective whose
by them. But rather than being captive to these
members believed that their way of life was insuffi-
attitudes she will use them as symbolic material to
ciently valued by the public culture would merit
construct an identity that is her own.
official recognition.
11
15
This account has the advan-
As a value claim, authenticity is the idea that
tage that it perfectly tracks the normative self-inter-
particular identities have value just because of their
pretations of collectives. Indeed, the justification for
particularity. They have objective value, but not
policies of recognition is assimilated precisely to their
because they can be subsumed by a moral universal
subjective feeling. But the subjective account would
(as when we claim that all persons have equal moral
no longer be a justification for recognition: it would
worth). Rather, authentic identities possess exemp-
commit the state positively to recognise debased,
lary validity; they are valuable just because of their
harmful and valueless ways of life and would remove
authentic originality.
the evolutionary power of what Kymlicka calls the
moral value from the singular experience of the
`cultural marketplace' in helping them to wither
subject.
away.
12
16
Authenticity, in sum, wrests
Of course, Taylor's main concern is with cultural authenticity and cultural recognition. Straight after introducing the idea of personal authenticity, he goes
VI
on to claim that collective identities such as cultures
What we need is an account of the value of collec-
also have their own particular way of worth or
tive identities that does justice to their self-inter-
measure.
pretations while at the same time provides a firm
authenticity, Taylor writes, `Herder applied his con-
moral basis for justifying policies of recognition.
ception of originality at two levels, not only to the
With these criteria in mind I want in the remainder
individual person . . . but also to the culture-bearing
of this chapter to examine Charles Taylor's influen-
people . . . Just like individuals, a Volk should be
tial essay `The Politics of Recognition'. Although he
true to itself, that is, its own culture.'
does not use the term, Taylor presents a theory of the
Taylor says little more to defend cultural authenticity
justice of recognition grounded in a particular ac-
than this. The value of cultural authenticity is a
count of the value of collective identities. That value
simple deduction from personal authenticity.
95
Commenting
on
Herder's
notion
17
of
However,
18
The
JONATHAN SEGLOW
main reason for this, I think, is that Taylor sees the
We (white Europeans) simply lack the perspective
central constituent of cultures as language. People
from which distortion-free judgements of the worth
who share a culture speak the same language and
of alien cultures can be made. For Taylor, no purely
thus language defines and demarcates different cul-
impartial perspective exists, and the solution instead
tures. Cultures, then, as formed and maintained by
is to construct a shared cross-cultural language from
different languages, have their own authentic col-
which comparative judgements of the worth of
lective identities.
19
different cultures can be made.
22
By entering into
The norms and values of the public culture provide
dialogue with alien cultures, he argues, we enlarge
the medium by which cultural members evaluate their
the moral horizon from which we make judgements
own collective identities. If the public culture system-
of worth and a more perspicuous understanding of
atically denigrates a minority culture then this de-
the other culture becomes available to us. For both
means its identity internally. Unfortunately, this is
cultures, orientating beliefs which were deep yet
20
The example of
implicit are suddenly brought to consciousness as
misrecognition which especially exercises Taylor is
they face the challenge of other values. What was
his native province of Quebec. His question is how
previously strange and unfamiliar becomes clearer as
Âbe  cois maintain their own authentic can the Que
new values reconfigure old attitudes and beliefs. The
very often just what happens.
21
Taylor catalogues how the Quebec
result is a `fusion of horizons' where both sides
government introduced various policies of recogni-
develop a new vocabulary of comparison from which
tion the most important of which was the requirement
to make moral judgements of cultural worth.
cultural identity?
23
that French-speaking parents send their children to
In approaching other cultures we presume that,
French-speaking schools. The reason for this was the
unfamiliar though they are, their values have some
overriding good of survivance of the authentic cultural
objective status. `As a presumption the claim is that
identity of Quebec, constitutively defined by its being
all human cultures that have animated whole socie-
French-speaking. Taylor does not himself employ the
ties over some considerable stretch of time have
concept of self-esteem which I borrowed from Hon-
something important to say to human beings.'
24
For
neth. But we can certainly translate his politics of recognition into those terms and say that the rationale
It is reasonable to suppose that cultures that have
for promoting Quebec culture is precisely that it gives
provided the horizon of meaning for large num-
Âbe  cois a secure sense of self-esteem, and in the Que
bers of human beings, of diverse characters and
turn identity and agency.
temperaments, over a long period of time ± that
The question is whether Quebec culture does have
have, in their words, articulated their sense of the
authentic moral value such that its claim for recog-
good, the holy, the admirable ± are almost certain
nition is justified when, clearly, members of other
to have something that deserves our admiration
collective identities (Anglophone Canadians, for
and respect even if it is accompanied by much
example) may not recognise the exemplary moral
that we have to abhor and reject.
25
value of Quebec culture. This takes us to Taylor's larger concern which is when and how different
This, then, is the `starting hypothesis with which
cultures should recognise each other's moral value
we ought to approach the study of any other cul-
in general. And this is our concern too for we saw
ture.'
how public cultures are normatively encoded so as to
from our more enlightened perspective we see that a
privilege certain cultural identity. The problem is a
culture does possess authentic moral value, its claim
particularly acute one when the `cultural gap' be-
to recognition is then justified.
26
If the starting hypothesis is redeemed, so that
tween two groups is large ± as it can be, for example with black and Asian cultures (whether immigrants
VII
or indigenous peoples) who demand the recognition from the white majority in Europe and North Amer-
Taylor's essay has aroused much comment. The two
ica when it is the latter's identity that is privileged.
main arguments made against him are, first, that
96
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION
there is no such thing as an authentic cultural
a politics of recognition seeks to achieve a rough
identity since cultures are in fact internally plural
parity of the social bases of self-esteem for different
and diverse, and second, that the state promotion of
social groups (where self-esteem is crucially depen-
a particular cultural identity entailed by recognition
dent on how one's collective identity is appraised by
is unfair since it privileges one form of life at the
the public culture). Since a positive evaluation of
expense of others and hence derogates individual
people's concrete collective identities affects their
freedom and opportunity.
27
These two objections
very capacity for agency (the linkage we drew from
are, of course, related. If there are no authentic
Honneth), the former merit recognition to bolster
cultural essences then there is certainly no justifica-
their appraisive status in the public culture, provided
tion for politically recognising one culture at the
that, as we have been exploring, the collective
expense of others.
identity possesses exemplary moral value ± a judge-
I think Taylor can be rescued from these objec-
ment that can only be made post facto after a dialogic
tions, although not without modifying his position
encounter. It is worth recalling too that the liberal
somewhat. I shall address the second problem and
theory of social justice, which I sketched at the
then the first, but, before doing so, let me mention
beginning of this essay, also redistributes freedom
briefly a particularly acute version of the second
and opportunity, as when for example better off
argument made by K. Anthony Appiah in his com-
people disproportionately finance the welfare state.
mentary on the essay. Appiah agrees that many
The justification there is that the state should pro-
collective identities such as members of minority
vide roughly equal opportunity for each person to
ethnic cultures do suffer from systematic low collec-
exercise their capacities for choice and agency. The
tive esteem. Hence `one form of healing the self that
justification for political recognition is very similar,
those who have these identities participate in is
only that the primary focus is on the constitution and
learning to see these collective identities not as
maintenance of the capacity for personal agency in
sources of limitation and insult but as a valuable
the first place, and that the beneficiaries of recogni-
part of what they centrally are.'
28
But, he goes on,
tion are people who esteem their own culture rather
some recipients of recognition might object that it is
than people whose self-identities are primarily as free
not they who are receiving it, but just some attribute
choosers. If we follow Honneth we should not see a
of theirs ± first language, skin colour ± which they
morally great distinction between `free choosers' and
invest with no special significance. There are many
`culturally-encumbered peoples', but whether that is
people whose self-interpretations do not have a
so must await a full justification of liberal recogni-
central place for an authentic collective identity.
tion.
`It is at this point that someone who takes autonomy
I'm not sure the misrecognition of those who
seriously will ask whether we have not replaced one
regard themselves primarily as free agents as cul-
kind of tyranny with another.'
29
ture-bearing ones is really a kind of `tyranny', as
The second ± `freedom' ± objection to Taylor
Appiah claims. For it is arguable that a measure of
appears to take, therefore, two separate forms. One
misrecognition ± as when, for example, ethnic min-
is that other people's (non-beneficiaries) freedom
ority citizens complain that policies of affirmative
and opportunity is limited by policies of recognition;
action denude them of the opportunity to compete
the other is Appiah's subtle point that the benefi-
for jobs or university places on their own merits ± is
ciaries of political recognition have their identity as
simply a price worth paying for the undoubted
autonomous agents misrecognised by being viewed
benefits which recognition brings to those who do
through a cultural lens when their fundamental self-
identify with their collective cultural identity. Ap-
interpretation is simply as free agents.
piah's critique might also be put in terms of the
I have already sketched the general justification
public/private division so that the distinction is
for policies of recognition which very often redis-
between those who wish publicly to assert their
tribute freedom and opportunity. Beginning from a
collective identity (the gay pride movement, for
fundamental commitment to the equality of persons
example) and those who regard their identity (for
97
JONATHAN SEGLOW
consistent with the truths that (1) people want to be
example, their sexual identity) as essentially a pri30
But again, is it really
recognised not just through their culture but often in
tyrannical to have ± to continue the example ± the
other ways besides, and (2) that there is disagreement
right to a same-sex marriage, or is it rather an
among cultural members about the proper interpre-
opportunity which gay couples can take advantage
tation of their collective cultural identity. Problem
of if they wish? I have written all along of `claims' for
instances of (1) occur when a person is politically
recognition so perhaps the solution here is a kind of
recognised as being black, for example, when what
consent test which would prevent the introduction
she regards as much more central to her identity is
of policies of recognition which a majority of mem-
that she is a doctor. This problem is a version of
bers of the collective identity in question did not
Appiah's critique above, but it is worth pointing out
themselves desire. Finally, it is also worth recording,
here that there is no obvious inconsistency or in-
against Appiah's critique, that there are already
justice for the state to recognise doctors (some of
many other ways that the state misrecognises our
whom are black) for the purposes of collective pay-
self-interpreted identities which arise from less con-
bargaining and to recognise, say, a black arts group
troversial principles of justice. Unemployment or
which receives government money (and of which
disability benefit, for example, was sometimes said
our doctor is not a member). Issue (2) is a problem
vate, non-political matter.
because it seems to militate against the authenticity of
(by the New Right) to demean its recipients by labelling
them
with
a
negative
stereotype.
31
cultures. Perhaps authenticity is the wrong term here
Although the argument was over-inflated ± since
for we need only really say that cultures are real and
the positive relief brought by these benefits vastly
embody morally valuable human possibilities. In any
outweighs the negative stereotype ± the point re-
case, we must be careful not to go too far in the other
mains a valid one. And if that is true then cultural
direction and implicitly contrast the inauthenticity
recognition of the kind Taylor commends does not
of minority cultures with the authenticity of the
uniquely misidentify its subjects: Appiah's tyrannical
public culture in a way that denies the justice of
effects may be an unfortunate by-product of all
claims to recognition. The latter is the hegemonic
progressive policies of justice.
strategy of cultural conservatives. In reality, neither
It remains true nonetheless that if there are no
the public nor minority cultural identities are more
authentic collective cultural identities then there is
authentic or real than the other. Each borrows from
no case in justice to recognise them. This is the first
the other and both are constantly reformed and
objection made against Taylor. And it is also true
revised. Demands for recognition made by members
that, compared to the brute facticity of being poor or
of minority cultures are best understood as challenges
disabled or unemployed (all collective identities),
to the current self-interpretations of the public cul-
cultures are always amalgams, mongrel entities, the
ture. For these reasons, I think Taylor's dialogue
products of internal compromise and contestation
between different cultures is best understood as
and, indeed, prevailing legal norms. There are no
one about the best ± authentic ± self-understanding
pure, crystalline cultural identities waiting to be
of the public culture. This is given a recognition on
recognised by the public culture. There are few (if
all sides that no group of citizens possesses the
any) people in liberal societies who construct their
authoritative and final interpretation of what their
social role from a homogeneous cultural script and
public culture is about and that minority groups have
nothing else. But in reply to this objection, we
the right to participate in the progressive redefinition
should ask, simply: what needs to be true in order
of the public culture just like everyone else.
that cultural identities merit recognition? The an-
view dialogue is about reaching a public consensus
swer is that, first, there are people who recognise
on the self-interpretation of the political community
each other as members of a shared cultural identity,
and the value of cultural identities as part of that
and second, that that cultural identity is disadvan-
political community. The moral challenges which
taged with respect to the public culture. The second
minority cultures inevitably bring to the public
answer I have already argued for. The first answer is
culture will always provide a rationale for dialogue
98
32
On this
LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF RECOGNITION
and I am suggesting that this process should be
become part of what a liberal theory of social justice
formalised and institutionalised.
tries to accommodate. A full justification of liberal
This more deliberative-democratic interpretation
recognition needs to elaborate further the key con-
of intercultural dialogue in fact supplies two rather
cepts of recognition, identity, self-esteem, and the
different justifications for rights to recognition. The
public and minority cultures. I shall conclude briefly
first says that official recognition is justified when
by signalling three further issues which liberal re-
there is an appraisive consensus on cultural value.
cognition needs to address. First, I have said nothing
But since, in a complex, plural society, where the
about illiberal cultures which deny their members
public culture is ever-revisable, such a consensus can
freedom and choice. Illiberal cultures are especially
only ever be regarded as the ideal aim not the
problematic because they may be significant sources
concrete result of public deliberation, this first jus-
of self-esteem for (at least some of) their members.
tification has its limits. The second justification
Should they, then, merit political recognition? I
explicitly links claims for recognition with public
have argued only that the value of a culture is an
deliberation by regarding the rights granted to min-
emergent property of dialogic interchange and that
ority cultures as participatory rights which enable
harmful cultures do not merit recognition. But this
them to enter into collective deliberation with their
takes us to the second problem which is separatist
fellow citizens about the proper understanding of the
cultures who refuse to interact with the wider public
public culture on terms that are fair. Rights to
culture but demand political recognition (group
recognition, in other words, are recursively justified
autonomy, for example, or separate schooling) none-
by the need for public deliberation itself. They help
theless. Perhaps we should just say that entering into
to foster a more secure sense of identity and status for
some kind of dialogue with the wider world is the
minority groups, not just for their own sake, but to
price to be paid for political recognition (even if that
empower them to participate in the collective re-
transforms a group who wished to use recognition to
definition of the public culture. The right to wear
insulate their collective identity in the first place).
religious dress at work, for example, or the right to
The third issue is the complex relationship I have
bilingual schooling do not just boost the self-esteem
glossed over between material social justice and
of members of minority cultures. Rather, they help to
cultural recognition. As Nancy Fraser effectively
create citizens who feel secure and esteemed as
argues, these two forms of justice can conflict with
members of the public culture too and are therefore
each other.
better able to co-deliberate on what its identity
cies, for example, would appear to conflict with
should be.
recognition-based affirmative action policies that
33
Race-blind equal opportunities poli-
positively esteem a marginalised racial group. Here I will only say, banally, that a unified liberal theory of
VIII
social justice needs to reconcile both sorts of claims.
As I said at the beginning of this chapter my aim has
But my main point in this essay is not, I hope, banal:
merely been to argue for an agenda: that claims for
recognition should be incorporated into the liberal
recognition need not be illiberal but rather should
identity in the twenty-first century.
Notes
1. Cf. the lists of `recognition rights' in E. A. Galeotti,
Citizenship (1995) offers a very sophisticated defence of
`Neutrality and Recognition', in Bellamy and Hollis
minority rights grounded in the Rawls/Dworkin account
(eds) (1999) and Kymlicka (1995), pp. 30±1.
of justice. However, Kymlicka does not view these as
2. For the theory of justice explaining and underlying the
rights which recognise the value of particular cultural
choice/circumstances division, see Dworkin (1981a)
and collective identities. Unfortunately, there is not the
and Rawls (1972), esp. pp. 83±90, 100±8, and for a
space to discuss Kymlicka's theory in this chapter. But
discussion of Rawls and Dworkin, see Kymlicka (1990),
see the discussion in Seglow (1998), pp. 966±9 and the
chapter 3. Kymlicka's well-known book Multicultural
secondary literature on Kymlicka cited there.
99
JONATHAN SEGLOW
17. Taylor, in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), p. 31.
3. Taylor, `The Politics of Recognition', in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 25±73. Taylor's is perhaps the best
18. Cf. K. Anthony Appiah, `Identity, Authenticity, Sur-
known, but by no means the only, theory of cultural
vival: Multicultural Societies and Social Reproduc-
recognition on the intellectual market. See, for ex-
tion', in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 149±63, at p. 153.
ample, the important works by Tully (1995) and
19. Hence Taylor's focus is somewhat narrower than our interest in the recognition of gender and sexual and
Young (1990).
religious identities.
4. Taylor (1989), p. 34.
20. Taylor in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 32±5.
5. Hence the recognition view cross-cuts the (false)
21. Taylor states that it `is axiomatic for Quebec govern-
dichotomy between the liberal autonomous self and
ments that the survival and flourishing of French
the communitarian encumbered one.
culture in Quebec is a good': Taylor, in Gutmann
6. Honneth (1995).
(ed.) (1994), p. 58.
7. Ibid., p. 169. 8. Ibid., p. 173.
22. For the philosophy behind this, see Taylor (1995).
9. Rawls, of course, lists self-respect as `the most impor-
23. A phrase Taylor borrows from Gadamer. See Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 66±73.
tant' of his primary goods: see Rawls (1972), pp. 440± 6. For a brief critique of this see Seglow (1998), pp.
24. Ibid., p. 66.
965±6. For a distinction between self-respect and self-
25. Ibid., pp. 72±3.
esteem similar to Honneth's see Sachs (1981).
26. Ibid., pp. 66±7.
10. Although Honneth has been criticised for glossing
27. For examples of the first argument see Ferrara (1998),
over the more collective media of recognition such as
p. 17; Rorty (1994); and S. Wolf's `Comment', in
group identity ± see Alexander and Lara (1996), esp.
Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 75±85. The best examples
pp. 133±5.
of the second are Cooke (1997) and Habermas's
11. I. M. Young's very interesting book Justice and the Politics
`Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic Con-
of Difference (1990) comes close to a wholly subjective
stitutional State', in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), pp. 107± 48.
account. She writes, for example, that `groups cannot be socially equal unless their specific experience, culture
28. Appiah, in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), p. 161.
and social contribution are publicly affirmed and re-
29. Ibid., pp. 162±3.
cognised' (p. 174) and she calls for a `politics [of
30. This example comes from Miller (1995), pp. 133±4
difference which] asserts that oppressed groups have
who argues for a democratic public culture but is critical of Taylor's politics of recognition.
distinct cultures, experiences and perspectives on social
31. Another example is the way that labelling people as
life with humanly positive meaning' (p. 166). 12. See Kymlicka (1995), pp. 107±9.
criminals,
13. Taylor, in Gutmann (ed.) (1994), p. 30.
through the judicial process, helps make them into
by
putting
those
charged
with
crime
criminals.
14. Ibid., p. 30. 15. This theme of self-sincerity links Taylor's account of
32. A consequence of this interpretation of the public
authenticity to that developed by another contem-
culture as ever-evolving is that no rights to recogni-
porary proponent, Alessandro Ferrara: see Ferrara,
tion are justified forever; they are instead revisable as
(1998), chapter 1.
the self-understanding of the public culture changes through public deliberation.
16. For more on the idea of exemplary validity, see ibid.,
33. Fraser (1995).
chapters 1 and 4.
100
8
THE ESSENTIAL INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE Rex Martin
allows for differences in income and wealth Rawls
I
refers to it as the `difference principle'.
1
John Rawls is probably the leading theorist of justice
A society that met this particular set of standards ±
in the world today (certainly the English-speaking
that is, which satisfied the goals set by equal basic
world). For him justice is, or should be, a virtue of
liberties, equality of opportunity and the difference
society, specifically of the political and social and
principle understood as mutual benefit ± would be
economic arrangements in its `basic structure'. In
`thoroughly just', in Rawls's view. But to be `perfectly
Rawls's view, what justice requires of these basic
just' it would also, at some point, have to maximise
institutions, as a set, is not only that they exhibit (1)
the level of income and wealth of the least well-off
the principle of equal basic liberties and (2) that of
group in particular ± say, the bottom one-fifth.
2
equality of opportunity, but also (3) that they work
This point about the maximising of the minimum
together in such a way as to (a) encourage contribu-
is not intended to identify a benefit for everyone in
tions that (b) increase the production of goods and
the target group. Rather, the relevant effects here are
services, which in turn are so distributed as (c) to
the effects on a `representative' person; they are
improve continually the level of income and wealth
effects on an ideal-type average individual in the
of all the various income groups involved, when
bottom group.
considered from the perspective of a representative
3
In the present chapter I want to focus attention on
person's whole life, a normal life.
Rawls's difference principle. In order to avoid con-
We might, following Rawls, describe (1) equal
fusion and distraction, I will specify this focal project
basic liberties and (2) equality of opportunity as prior
rather narrowly. Rawls is concerned principally to
demands of justice and (3) the principle of mutual
describe normal or standard patterns of just distribu-
benefit as a secondary demand, one that is to be
tion (without regard to prior maldistributions). In
fulfilled in the context of fulfilling these prior de-
other words, we are being asked to consider (at least
mands and without sacrifice by them. On this view,
as a first stage, in order to see what picture would
then, in a just or well-ordered society, inequalities in
result) what it would be like for a society simply to
economic or social positions and attendant inequal-
satisfy the difference principle and the other de-
ities in economic or social positions can be allowed ±
mands of justice.
4
indeed, should be allowed ± subject to meeting these
Rawls typically states his difference principle as
three conditions. Since the third of the conditions
being itself closely attached to the principle of
101
REX MARTIN
this, such a society should be concerned to reduce
equality of opportunity: the two together make up, in 5
I want to
the inequalities in income and wealth that will arise
begin, then, by examining the reasoning Rawls offers
between individuals and between groups of people.
his view, a single principle of justice.
in support of this single but composite principle.
6
We can treat these three thoughts as steps in a
First, he establishes the importance of the idea of
single overall argument designed to justify the com-
equality of opportunity. We can assume here, for
posite principle of justice we are here concerned with
purposes of exposition, that a group of people are
and to specify both a precise notion of equality of
thinking seriously about the way societies are ar-
opportunity and the content of the difference prin-
ranged respecting such matters as social and econom-
ciple. The argument we are examining, as Rawls
ic position and attendant income and wealth. They
initially states it, is an `informal' or `intuitive' argu-
note that, typically, there is considerable inequality
ment.
between persons and between classes in these mat-
we'll look briefly at what it would take (in Rawls's
ters. We can imagine now the following interior line
view) for it to become a fully formal and conclusive
of thought going on in the minds of the people in our
argument.
7
After we've canvassed the argument further,
group: each realises that inequality in position and
The argument starts with the idea of `democratic'
attendant wealth may well be involved for the
equality of opportunity ± conceived as the taking of
society they are in, but no one wishes to accept
remedial steps, conscientiously, to reduce the initial
an inferior position for oneself, even though it might
inequality in advantages accruing to individuals from
prove to be for the common good in a particular
two main sources. The idea that dominates this
society. Each person sees, then, upon reflection, that
particular discussion is that no one is responsible
it would be irrational from anyone's point of view
for ± hence no one deserves ± their own starting
simply to take an inferior position as their lot in life.
points, their natural endowment or the social posi-
Nor could anyone regard it as desirable to be forced
tion into which they are born and reared. Since
to take such a position. So, granting that inequality
equality of opportunity can never be strict or abso-
in positions is both highly likely (perhaps inevitable)
lute, Rawls introduces a further idea, the difference
and conceivably useful, each would want income-
principle, to complement equality of opportunity
and wealth-generating positions to be open to all on
and complete the initial line of argument. The
some principle of equality of opportunity.
difference principle adds two more ideas, two further
This establishes the point Rawls wants to make,
remedial steps; it adds the principle of everyone's
that equality of opportunity is important and that we
continual benefit, which in turn is constrained by
should want a principle specifying it. Then, next, in
the idea that, where there are several mutually
a series of further reflections on this very point,
improving options available, we should choose that
Rawls elaborates a set of ideas that, taken together,
option which most reduces the resultant inequality
constitute an argument for the composite (or sec-
in outcomes between the top-most and bottom-most
ond) principle of justice.
groups. The object of this three-step process is to
There are, in my view, three main thoughts or
reduce, ideally to minimise, the gap between persons
ideas advanced here. Let me sketch them briefly and
by taking account of both starting points and end
loosely, just to set the big picture in view.
results.
8
The first thought is that no person is responsible
The idea of collective asset, the name Rawls gives
for that person's own starting point in life. The
the argument just described, provides the rationale
second is that, in view of this first point, it makes
and justification for the main features of Rawls's
sense for people (acting as members of a single
second principle of justice. It underwrites both equal-
political economy) to attempt to achieve a higher
ity of opportunity in its `democratic interpretation'
index of wealth and income for all representative
and the principle of distributive economic justice ±
persons at the various income levels there (higher,
that is, the difference principle.
that is, than existed at some initial point of presumed equality). And the third thought is that, in doing
102
9
INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE
between the top-most and the bottom-most group.
II
This iterated pattern continues until we reach an
We get to the usual specification of the difference
optimum point, at which no further mutually im-
principle by reiterating the set of ideas just sketched.
proving moves are possible. At this point we have
That is, we do so (assuming here a continuing
minimised absolutely the difference in question, and
conscientious effort at achieving `democratic' equal-
those least well-off here have their greatest benefit.
ity of opportunity) by repeatedly deploying the
The leading ideas of this argument were sum-
principle of everyone's continual benefit as con-
marised (at the end of the previous section) under
strained by egalitarianism (thereby reducing differ-
the name `the argument from collective asset'. Per-
ences in outcome between the top-most and bottom-
haps calling it an argument may not convey the
most group) up to the optimum point, where this
exact picture I have in mind. Let us call it instead,
difference is absolutely minimised and the least well-
taking a hint from Rawls's later writings, a `procedure
off are as well-off as they can be (without making any
of construction'.
other group worse-off in the process).
more like a constructive proof in mathematics ± say,
12
A procedure of construction is
This particular iterated argument has a singular
a geometrical proof ± in which we get a result by
virtue; it explains a puzzling fact about Rawls's
making certain moves (constructing certain figures,
exposition
holds
making certain assumptions) than it is like a classical
throughout his book A Theory of Justice (hereafter
syllogism in which certain propositions simply fol-
TJ). Repeatedly, Rawls seems to shift between talk-
low, by logical entailment, from ready-made pre-
ing about the difference principle as improving every-
mises.
of
the
second
principle
that
body's prospects and, alternatively, as maximising the
So the kind of argument I have in mind is itself
benefits of the least well-off group. But the puzzle
best understood as a procedure of construction. Here
dissolves once we see that both these versions belong
a procedure is identified and then employed, by
to one and the same story. Each formulation specifies
reference to certain leading ideas (which give the
a single feature of the overall argument; one for-
point of the procedure), to get a certain result; that
mulation emphasises the idea that drives the differ-
procedure is iterated, repeatedly deployed, until the
ence principle ± the notion of everyone's continual
identified end point is reached. This point is the
benefit ± while the other emphasises the optimal
intended or optimum result (given the iterated pro-
result, the goal or end point of the entire argument.
cedure and its governing assumptions).
13
That goal can be stated in either of two distinctive
What is curious about Rawls's informal (or `col-
ways: (1) as absolutely minimising the difference
lective asset') argument ± as we actually find it in TJ
(measured in terms of income or wealth) between
(the heart of the discussion being at Chapter 2,
the top-most and bottom-most group, consistent
section 13) ± is that, while Rawls presents its gov-
with the realisation of everyone's continued better-
erning concerns clearly enough (in what I have
ment; or (2) as achieving `the greatest benefit of the
called three main `thoughts') and while he presents
least advantaged',
10
its goal point equally clearly (as the `greatest benefit
that is, the greatest benefit for
14
the least well-off group. Here we have a distinction
of the least well-off group'
without a difference; the two goal-point formulations
intermediate step (the procedure of construction
(1) and (2) say the same thing.
11
), he never lays out the
itself) whereby, through repeated deployment, we can get from these concerns to the goal point.
And here I come to the heart of my analysis, the main point I want to make. The difference principle
But once we actually `see' the procedure of con-
can be represented as an argument that proceeds
struction in action, as I have tried to represent it in
through a series of stages, each one of which embo-
the previous section, the move from governing con-
dies a conscientious effort at achieving equality of
cerns (as given in the three main thoughts) to goal
opportunity and each one of which repeats the same
point seems natural enough and even plausible. One
theme: first satisfy the standard of mutual benefit (or
point of the procedure is to show how in fact Rawls's
efficiency) and then reduce differences in income
conclusion (for example, the maximin result) follows
103
REX MARTIN
from his premises, the governing considerations (the
that the curves of the other groups could be higher as
three main thoughts).
well; and that (2) so long as reciprocal benefit is
In the present account, then, I'm suggesting that
possible or feasible it is in fact sustained right on up
Rawls's argument from collective asset is best under-
to the optimum or goal point.
stood as constituted by three distinct things. It
Clearly, we are not talking here about actual social
involves: (1) certain governing considerations which
relations in a certain pattern but about a `logical'
together model or specify a procedure of construc-
situation that must be realised whenever such a
tion; (2) the repeated deployment of that procedure
pattern actually does hold. We might describe this
up to an identified end point; and (3) the actual
situation, then, as the `presupposition' behind chain
reaching of that point by using that procedure.
connection: the presupposition that, so long as the
Is this argument, so understood, conclusive? I
benefit of the least well-off group could possibly be
think not. But it becomes logically conclusive if
higher, that of the other groups could also be higher,
we make certain simplifying assumptions.
right on up to the optimum or goal point.
We must assume, as does Rawls, that we start from
With the presupposition (or, if you will, the
a hypothetical `zero point' of strict equality. And,
possibility)
second, we must assume that chain connection (or
the idea here (as a simplifying assumption belonging
something like it) holds. Chain connection means,
to mathematics, not to social policy or, at least, not
roughly, that `if an advantage has the effect of raising
to a description of social reality) in place, as one of
the expectations of the lowest position, it raises the
the background assumptions, we have completed our
expectations of all positions in between.'
15
account of Rawls's informal argument for the second
Or, as
principle.
Rawls redescribes the same idea, so long as the `curve'
How would the argument fare as a formal argu-
of the least well-off class shows improvement, all the other classes do so as well.
16
of chain connection, as we are using
ment? How would it do in the original position?
The point is that,
without assuming chain connection (or something like it), we cannot guarantee ending up at the
III
optimum or goal point while deploying the threestep collective asset argument and the procedure of
Rawls's contractarian method is very complex. I will
construction identified in it. But with it we can.
be able to mention only a few of its main features
Chain connection is an idea Rawls himself uses
here. One which is often emphasised ± and that
and, with qualification, endorses. The qualifications
Rawls has continued to include even in his more
have to do with whether chain connection holds in
recent writings ± is that the `parties' to the contract
actual societies or would hold invariably in a just
are placed, in the original position, behind a thick
society modelled on the two principles. So under-
`veil of ignorance'. Here they are instructed in their
stood, chain connection is a description of actual
subsequent reasoning to ignore their own particular
social relations. The difference principle is not lo-
traits (traits that distinguish them from all or most
gically contingent on whether this actual relation
other people), to be unaware of (or, at least, to
holds or not.
17
ignore) their actual place in society, to be unaware of their society's place in history or in institutional
However, we are not in the present account using
evolution, and so on.
our variant of chain connection as a description of actual social relations. Rather, it is like the assump-
Thus extreme uncertainty (as to starting points
tion of starting from a position of strict equality in
and outcomes for any given individual) would char-
social primary goods. It is a simplifying assumption, a
acterise the deliberations in the original position
regulatory constraint designed to keep the collective
setting, in which individuals are called upon to
asset argument (and the deployment of the proce-
construct and then choose the principles of justice
dure of construction) in focus. The constraint re-
that they would prefer to govern the society in which
quires (1) that so long as the `curve' of the least well-
they are to spend their entire lives. Given this high degree of uncertainty, we find that
off group could possibly be higher it is also possible
104
INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE
Rawls's collective asset argument fares rather well.
that inequality. The idea is that even after mutual
For example, the transition from the idea that no-
benefit is assured one should continue to use equal
body deserves their starting points to the idea that
shares (of primary goods) as a standing constraint on
people should use their natural endowments and
beneficial options, as a tiebreaker of sorts. Here,
their social origins (where these things are advanta-
among available options, that efficient and mutually
geous) in such a way that everybody benefits would
beneficial outcome which most reduces inequality is
surely go more smoothly behind the veil of ignorance
to be selected. To do otherwise would be to opt for a
than it would where people were already aware of
surplus of inequality, that is an inequality greater
their own and others' natural endowments and social
than is required to achieve compensating reciprocal
origins. This transition would certainly carry more
benefit. It would be unsuitable, given the commit-
conviction for the parties in the original position and
ment to equality (an initial benchmark and a con-
would, presumably, be emphatically endorsed by
tinuing
them there.
inequality unnecessarily.
concern),
to
perpetuate
or
increase
And, for a second example, the mutual benefit
It is precisely where fundamental equality in start-
part of the collective asset argument would gain
ing points is not fully and strictly achieved, or cannot
strong endorsement there, especially if we assumed
be, that concern for reducing the inequality of
a starting-point of strict equality. The argument
resultant outcomes is in order. Thus, efficiency con-
would go as follows: the parties would have no reason
strained by egalitarianism is a standard that each and
to give up this equality in their choice of principles
all could appeal to in the original position. None
unless there were benefits for each and all, or at least
would veto it. So the parties would endorse the
for some of them (and no losses).
18
principle that, where two or more feasible efficient
Let me make the same argument now in somewhat
schemes were available, that option should be se-
different words. In the original position a certain
lected which most reduced the difference (when
amount of role-playing is allowed, individuals are
measured in terms of income and wealth) between
allowed to assume certain standpoints and then to
the top-most and the bottom-most group.
20
consider how things would play out in the delibera-
In sum, I think the collective asset argument
tions of the parties. One could assume, for example,
would fare well in the original position construct.
that one was in a religious minority or in the least
And, since that construct is hypothetical and is
well-off economic class.
19
Under such an assumption
defined by a number of ideal features, it seems that
and behind the veil of ignorance, no one would
the simplifying assumptions mentioned earlier ± that
prefer disadvantageous deviations (from equal or even
we start from a position of strict equality and that a
from unequal shares) were they on the losing end,
certain regularity condition (the possibility of chain
and hence would veto such deviations. Thus, only
connection) holds good ± would be comfortably at
deviations advantageous to all would survive the
home there.
veto (that is, only such advantageous deviations could
It important to see that Rawls nowhere repudiates
achieve the unanimity required of conclusive delib-
the informal argument, the argument from collective
erations in the original position construct). But it
asset. Indeed Rawls refers to TJ, section 13 (the very
would be rational, in the eyes of each, to allow for
heart of the informal argument), as the one that
mutually beneficial changes, where there were more
defines
benefits for each and all (or at least for some) and no
prominent argument that we do find in TJ, chapter
losses.
3 (the chapter devoted to the original position), the
It follows, too, where persons have an equal status
the difference principle.
21
And the most
famous maximin argument, actually presupposes and
(as parties to the deliberation) and each has equal
builds on the argument from collective asset.
claim to shares of primary goods, that the parties
We can put the line of reasoning in this well-
would prefer a mutually beneficial outcome that
known argument quickly and intuitively as follows.
reduced the difference in income between the top-
Behind the veil of ignorance and given the high
most and bottom-most group over one that increased
degree of uncertainty there, each individual thinks
105
REX MARTIN
that, since they don't know how or where they might
the maximin argument then chooses between. It
end up, it behoves them all ± behoves each of them ±
follows that, in order for the maximin argument
to set things up (in the principles they select, each
to function at all, the principles which generate
one having a veto there) so that the worst control-
these characteristic outcomes must themselves be
lable outcome (for any one of them) is the best of a
independently formulated and established, for other-
bad lot (the best, that is, of the set of worst out-
wise they could not give these well-defined results.
comes).
Thus the maximin procedure must actually presup-
This line of reasoning, which has its home in
pose these outcome-giving principles, presuppose
rational choice theory (and can be found in eco-
them
nomic theory and political science) is, as I've already
well-established.
as
independent
and
presuppose
them
as
23
indicated, sometimes called maximin reasoning (that
The maximin argument provides no arguments for
is, reasoning literally on the principle of maximising
the two principles per se, either for the first principle
the minimum). The standard line of interpreting
(which we've merely taken for granted in this chap-
Rawls's difference principle (at what I have called
ter)
its goal or optimum outcome) has been that it was
have already canvassed). Accordingly, it adds noth-
supported justificatorily and was rationalised by max-
ing new to the already established argument for these
imin reasoning. This maximin line of reasoning was
principles. Rather, it is an argument for preferring the
attributed to Rawls by his initial expositors (and
two principles, already established on other grounds,
often, then, they severely criticised him for holding
over the most plausible of the utilitarian theories, the
to it) and more recent critics (such as Will Kymlicka,
principle of average utility (a principle already es-
Jonathan Wolff and Andrew Williams) have con-
tablished in Rawls's account, on its own grounds, at
tinued to view maximin as the standard pattern of
TJ, section 27).
justification intended by Rawls for the difference principle.
22
24
or for the second (the arguments for which we
It is Rawls's view that utilitarians and others,
This line has, in the view of most, been
especially in the setting afforded by the original
encouraged by Rawls himself (and can be found
position, would allow the sacrifice or attenuation
clearly enough, they think, in TJ and later works).
of some of the demands of justice, of the prior
But, contrary to what most of his interpreters and
demands especially, or would do so for some people
critics suppose, Rawls does not claim that his differ-
at least. Thus, the maximin argument doesn't even
ence principle is itself supported specifically by max-
focus on the second principle, let alone its difference
imin reasoning. At least, he makes no such claim in
principle part. Instead, it focuses on the loss of equal
his published writings. Rather, maximin reasoning
basic liberties of the sort enshrined in the first
seems to have a secondary role in his account, as
principle.
developed in TJ and thereafter. It is brought in only
ground, in Rawls's view, for preferring the two
after his principles of justice have been formulated
principles over the principle of average utility.
25
And it is this fact that marks the primary 26
and established on other grounds; it is then employed
So much, then, for the usual reading of the
by him to defend the whole set of these principles.
maximin argument. It is based on a sort of optical
Here, the main use of the maximin argument in
illusion: that maximin is the argument for the two
Rawls's hands is to rule out or to constrain utilitarian
principles, in particular for the difference principle.
alternatives to his preferred principles of justice.
On the contrary, the maximin argument is not an
We can see the force of the contention just made
argument for the two principles per se; it neither
by noting a simple fact, that the outcomes, which the
formulates nor establishes them. Rather, it presup-
maximin argument ranges over, must themselves be
poses the two principles and the results they char-
generated somehow. They are in fact generated by
acteristically give and argues that these results are
the competing principles under review ± by the two
preferable (under original position considerations,
principles, on the one hand, and by the principle of
where maximin reasoning is at home) to those
average utility, on the other. It is these particular
characteristically given by the principle of average
outcomes, two sets of characteristic outcomes, which
utility. Most especially, and for the same reasons, it is
106
INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE
not an argument for the difference principle in particular. That principle is hardly touched upon
Fig 8.1
at all in the maximin argument, as we find it in TJ, Chapter 3. Indeed, the difference principle as such doesn't have a face-off with the principle of average utility until TJ, Chapter 5, and there (in section 49) the argument has nothing to do with maximin. Thus, we must look elsewhere for Rawls's argument for the second principle, in particular the difference principle. In Rawls's theory, the argument specifically and peculiarly designed for the purpose of supporting the difference principle in particular is the one based on the idea of collective asset; it is an argument for reciprocal benefit of the sort that could be developed in the original position.
27
In the figure, x1 is the axis line that measures well-
It is this
being for the better-off group (in terms of units of
argument that Rawls later calls the `compelling' one
income, say) and x2 serves similarly as the axis for the
for the difference principle.
less well-off group. The dotted line (running at a 45 8
28
A natural reading of Rawls's difference principle,
angle) is the equality line; it represents the points of
along the lines set by collective asset, is that (assum-
strict equality between the two groups. The space on
ing throughout a continuing conscientious effort at
and below the curve 0P (correctly read as zero/P)
achieving `democratic' equality of opportunity) it
represents the available economic options in a par-
requires mutual improvement and that, where more
ticular society, given its resources, reasonable expec-
than one pattern of mutual improvement is possible,
tations of development and so on (and subject, of
society should select that one which minimises the
course, to the constraint of meeting the prior de-
difference in income and wealth between the top-
mands of justice). The darkened line on 0P is the
most and the bottom-most group. A consistent
Pareto-optimal `zone'; in it, no improvements for any
application of this principle would yield an optimum
group are possible without worsening the prospects of
or goal situation where the well-being of the least
at least one other group. The point a, on the 0P
well-off group (the bottom 20 per cent, say) was as
curve (and in the Pareto-optimal zone), is the point
great as it could possibly be.
of maximum well-being for x2 within the available
The `everybody benefits' principle (as qualified by
space.
the egalitarian constraint) is fully compatible ± in
Now let us suppose, first, that we were on or under
principle ± with the optimum or goal point of
the curve 0a. From any given point within this space,
maximising the well-being of the least well-off group.
the mutual-benefit egalitarian solution (if we assume
Indeed, that principle (through the specification and
certain regularity conditions) would intersect the 0P
use of a procedure of construction) constitutes the
curve at a (= the point of maximum benefit for the
principal argument for reaching that very goal point.
least well-off group, the Rawlsian goal or optimum
Accordingly, there is always a determinate directive
point).
that can be given to society by the Rawlsian differ-
However, suppose next that we were on or under
ence principle: structure things via policies and
the curve aP (but not at a or on the dotted line that
suchlike such that mutual improvement leading
runs perpendicular from a to the x1 axis). Suppose,
ultimately to the greatest well-being of the least
for example, that we were at point j on the ub line;
well-off group is achieved.
here, the mutual-benefit egalitarian solution could not intersect the 0P curve at a; rather, it would intersect that curve somewhere in the segment aP
IV
Now consider the problem, set forth in figure 8.1.
(but not at a). 29
The only way we could get to a, once we were to
107
REX MARTIN
the right of the perpendicular, is to move in such a
blem or as a practical one. Let us turn first to the
way as (at some point) to reduce the well-being of the
theoretical problem. I will address the practical one
members of the x1 class, thereby violating the re-
subsequently.
quirement of everyone's benefit. And this the mu-
Collective asset (which includes the idea of mu-
tual-benefit solution, as I have portrayed it, would
tual benefit) is the argument for the difference prin-
not allow. Thus, the whole area to the right of the
ciple, in either its improving or its maximising
perpendicular is a `forbidden zone' for that particular
version (as we find these versions in TJ at pp. 60
solution.
and 83 respectively). This means that it is the
Indeed, within that area no satisfactory result is
argument for the conclusion Rawls wants to draw
possible. There is no way the determinate directive
respecting the optimum or goal point, the ultimate
(described at the end of the previous section) could
end of the whole process, so to speak. In the situation
be satisfied. One would have to choose either to
we are here contemplating, the preferred conclusion
satisfy the mutual-benefit egalitarian solution or the
and the argument for it have come apart. They are
maximin one. The two are no longer compatible in
literally incompatible. This is a serious problem for a
principle and hence, to realise the one, we would
theoretical, or ideal, argument to be in.
have to give up on the other. Here we encounter the
There are, of course, ways to avoid this problem.
essential indeterminacy of Rawls's difference princi-
And we are familiar with them from earlier discus-
ple.
sion (in section II). Thus, we conduct the argument starting from a standpoint of strict equality and we
It is possible that a society could find itself in this zone (and to find itself there without prior injustice
assume that the possibility of chain connection (as
having occurred). Imagine, for example, that a so-
there defined) holds throughout. The so-called for-
ciety is following a mutual benefit path (for example,
bidden zone, then, merely specifies a case where this
the ub line in the figure). Such a society would be a
argument would not ± logically could not ± be
`thoroughly just' one, by Rawls's standards; its being
applicable. It identifies a case where the presupposi-
at j on that line would not be unjust, nor would it
tion behind chain connection fails to hold and thus
reflect past injustice.
identifies a zone in which the procedure of construc-
There are two rather obvious possible cases here.
tion could not operate to effect its assigned end,
First, a society could already be at j (on the ub line,
could not so operate because one of the essential
the line it had been following) when TJ is published
background assumptions for its proper use fails to
and the inhabitants (members of a thoroughly just
hold in that entire zone.
society up to then) start thinking things through in
There is, then, a `theoretical' solution of sorts to
the light of its arguments. Second, a society (again, a
the theoretical problem. We achieve it by carefully
thoroughly just one up to that point) wanders into
seeing to it that our argument conforms to certain
the `forbidden zone' through a typical and non-
background assumptions; by doing so we necessarily
culpable ignorance of its full set of economic options
avoid the problem posed.
(its own feasibility curve) at the time. It does so
The theoretical solution envisioned here is ulti-
while at the same time staying on the ub line (up to
mately a very pricey one. It requires us to make some
point j). And we assume that the configuration of
rather strong assumptions: (1) that we start from
the curve doesn't change significantly after that so as
strict equality; (2) that the background presupposi-
to redefine the `forbidden zone' in the case at hand.
tion (that chain connection is possible and thus
For any society in the situation just described, the
realisable) holds good; (3) that we can readily iden-
Rawlsian difference principle could not afford direc-
tify a society's feasibility curve and, on it, the point of
tion, could not specify a coherent goal for policy. In
the greatest benefit for the least well-off group and,
short, the difference principle, on Rawls's usual
thus, readily identify the zone where the presupposi-
understanding of it, is here inherently indeterminate.
tion (in (2)) holds and the zone where it doesn't ± so
We can put the problematic now before us in two
that we can stay out of the latter. These are, as I said,
distinct ways. We can view it as a theoretical pro-
strong assumptions. Even so, we might admit them.
108
INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE
any given society. Indeed, it could arise in fact for
But they may be more than mere assumptions. In
many societies in the real social world.
Rawls's account the `parties' in the `original position' are invited to reason with certain assumptions at
Following good policies (policies of mutual benefit
hand. And they are invited to reason in earnest. For
designed to ensure `thorough' justice), even follow-
people so to reason, I would suggest, they must
ing the best policies (policies of mutual benefit as
believe that these assumptions are applicable to their
constrained by egalitarianism, policies designed to
own case.
assure, under a procedure of construction, the max-
Now take the third of the assumptions. If people
imum benefit of the least well-off group), will not
reasoned in the original position, with such an
guarantee that a society will not wander off course.
assumption in place, then they could guarantee that
There is no guarantee that it will not, under real
by staying in the zone where the background assump-
conditions of uncertainty (and risk), enter a zone in
tion held good they could employ the procedure of
which the procedure of construction cannot operate
construction to reach the assigned end in view. But
to effect its assigned end. The problem, in short,
so to reason suggests that they know (or believe) the
could arise for a thoroughly just society.
30
society they are here constructing (or evaluating)
A society that found itself in such a situation ± for
itself occupies, or can occupy, precisely such a zone.
non-culpable reasons and without having committed
As a belief about social location this is, given the
injustice ± would discover that, so long as the
veil of ignorance, not the kind of belief that could be
situation could not be altered or could not realisti-
admitted into the original position. Clearly, if one
cally be expected to change in any significant way, it
were to call such a belief a matter of knowledge, it
could no longer follow a coherent set of policy
would be impermissible to entertain it in the original
directives (as based on Rawls's collective asset idea)
position.
for reaching Rawls's preferred goal point. It could
So we strike the offending belief out; we do not
only act arbitrarily here ± adhering either to the
allow it to operate at all. But then the parties are
premises of the argument or to its conclusion but
forced to reason about matters of justice (matters of
not both. For the conditions under which the proce-
justice for them) that may not even be applicable to
dure of construction could operate, so as to hold the
the society they inhabit, or may not be applicable to
governing considerations and the end irrevocably
its expected or allowable course of development
together, would not obtain here.
(allowable, that is, if a society is to be and remain
It is no longer possible, in such a situation, to
a thoroughly just one). Indeed, reasoning in this way
coordinate a mutual benefit-egalitarian solution with
(reasoning without a well-founded belief as to sui-
the maximin one. To realise the one, we would have
table social location) may prove to be wholly un-
to give up on the other.
realistic.
This incompatibility in available strategies would
By developing the principles of justice under ideal
be a serious practical problem for any justice-aspiring
assumptions we guarantee an impeccable theoretical
society to find itself in. There is no theoretical solu-
result. At the same time we guarantee, should the
tion for the problem available to it, given Rawls's
assumptions fail to hold in fact, that the so-called
argument or Rawls's text. And yet it is a problem that
theoretical solution is inapplicable there.
requires to be resolved in a principled way.
A certain set of working assumptions has become
This is the dilemma, the deep incoherence, that
locked into the original-position argument pattern.
Rawlsian theory necessarily leads to, or could lead to.
Where these assumptions cannot hold there must be,
It is a situation that Rawlsian theory has not con-
for a certain zone of the suboptimal space, no the-
templated, but one that we, as friends of justice and
oretical solution available, not even in principle. We
perhaps of Rawlsian theory, need to think hard
have, in fact, made it systematically impossible to
about.
solve the problem of what to do in that zone. There will always be such a zone. Thus, the situation envisioned could in principle arise for
109
REX MARTIN
critical of arguments I have given in my works cited
A Postscript on Sources
above, which I have found helpful in the develop-
and Acknowledgements
ment of the present chapter. These studies are
The present chapter draws on two main sources. First
Lamont (1994) and Williams (1995). I cannot claim
it is based upon my book Rawls and Rights (Martin
to have answered all the criticisms made, especially
(1985)), chapters 4, and 5 especially, and also chap-
by Willliams, but these two studies did lead me to
ter 8. Chapter 5 is, in turn, a longer version of certain
significant reformulations and to some new lines of
sections of Martin and Shenoy (1983). I owe to
thought, as sketched in the present chapter.
Prakash Shenoy both the idea for the efficiency-
Finally, for their assistance on the present chapter
cum-egalitarianism presentation of Rawls's differ-
(or on earlier versions of it), I want to thank Prakash
ence principle and much of the formalism developed
Shenoy (with whom I've been discussing, on and off
for it in the present chapter and in Martin (1985). In
since February 1994, the problem identified in sec-
particular, I owe to him the idea that chain con-
tion IV) and Ann Cudd (with whom I've discussed
nection (or, rather, something like it) must be
one of Williams's leading criticisms, that the effi-
assumed in society with n classes (where n > 2).
ciency-cum-egalitarianism presentation of Rawls's
And I owe to him the development of the egalitarian
difference principle fails to satisfy the standard of
matrix in which, in a situation of n classes, we
`contraction consistency' ± a criticism which I do not
minimise (reduce as much as possible) the difference
address in the present chapter and one which I do
between the top-most class x1 and the bottom-most
not credit, in the end). I have been helped too
class x2. (Rawls's own analysis on this very point, we
(especially in developing the argument of section
may recall, was wholly confined to a two-class situa-
IV) by students in my classes and by audiences, in
tion and did not take account of sub-optimal situa-
both the US and the UK, before whom I've pre-
tions). Finally, the important appendix in Martin
sented earlier versions of this chapter. The present
(1985) is entirely his work. Secondly, this chapter is
chapter is a shortened version of one I published in a
also based upon my paper `Economic Justice: Con-
volume of papers entitled Rights and Reason, edited by
tractarianism and Rawls's Difference Principle', in
Larry May and Marilyn Friedman for Kluwer (2000).
Boucher and Kelly (eds) (1994), pp. 245±66. Let me mention as well two recent studies, both
Notes
1. See Rawls (1972), pp. 60±1 for the Rawlsian `first
3. It is important to bear in mind throughout that the
statement' of the principles of justice, which I have
difference principle is an aggregative principle; it
tried to convey in the paragraph to which this note is
concerns groups (in the example given, the bottom
attached.
20 per cent of wage earners); it does not concern
2. See ibid., pp. 78±9, 319 for the distinction between
individuals per se, i.e. people readily known to us by
thoroughly/perfectly just. Rawls adds, in each of these
their proper names (ibid., p. 78). The same could be
discussions, the proviso that the income expectations
said of the other income groups (say, the top 20 per
of the various groups are to be understood as making a
cent and so on). Our focus is always on an ideal-type
positive functional contribution to one another, and
average individual within that particular group, not on
as doing so in some accredited setting ± in an open and
any given, single individual who happens to be there.
competitive market, say. Thus, in a `perfectly just'
4. Rawls makes clear that the account of distributive
situation the contribution is such that no further
shares that accords with the difference principle `be-
improving `changes in the expectations of those better
longs to strict compliance theory and so to the consideration of the ideal scheme' (ibid., p. 315).
off can improve the situation of those worse off' (ibid., p. 78). In a `thoroughly just' situation, on the other
5. See, for example, ibid., pp. 60, 83, 302±3.
hand, the key claim is that if the expectations of those
6. Rawls refers to this composite principle as his second
better off were somehow `decreased, the prospects of
principle of justice at, for example, ibid., section 12;
the least advantaged would likewise fall' from their
the first principle, of course, is his principle of equal
present point (ibid., p. 78).
basic liberties (ibid., pp. 60±1). And in his book there
110
INDETERMINACY OF RAWLS'S DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE
is a strict priority, of the first principle over the second:
Sandu called a `logic game' in his paper `Games in
ibid., pp. 61, 302±3.
Logic', presented at the conference on Logic and Ontology at the University of the West, Timisoara,
7. Ibid., p. 78.
Romania, in May 1998.
8. The argument for this final thought, that we should manifest a continuing concern for minimising inequal-
14. For example at Rawls (1972), p. 83.
ity, is a simple and appealing one. We apply the same
15. Ibid., p. 80.
standard to end points (or outcomes) that we had
16. Ibid., pp. 81±3; see also Martin (1985), p. 199.
earlier applied, in the `democratic interpretation' of
17. See Rawls (1972), p. 82.
the second principle, to starting-points. That is, we
18. Here I paraphrase Lamont (1994), p. 318. And La-
begin by conscientiously reducing ± as we much as we
mont, in turn, was describing one argument, which he
can (all things considered) ± the difference in starting
thought successful, from Martin (1985) and my `Eco-
points that accrue to individuals from the two main
nomic Justice' in Boucher and Kelly (eds) (1994).
sources, from one's natural endowment and from one's
Rawls represents the reasoning of the parties in the
initial social position, and then we repeat the same
original position as `part of the theory of rational
procedure with respect to outcomes. The rationale for
choice' (Rawls, 1972, p. 172). The parties there are
doing this is that, since we can never reduce the initial
taken to be rational (ibid., p. 25) and to lack envy
differences to zero, it is permissible to reduce differ-
(ibid., p. 143). Thus, under the assumption that `more
ences in outcomes as well. The idea of reducing
is preferred over less', the parties are simply concerned
differences in outcomes between two or more feasible
to ensure a suitable ensemble of primary goods (for
options, available at a given time, is a natural com-
themselves individually and their descendants), in the
plement to the theme of equal opportunity with
social world they will inhabit, under a rule that they all
respect to starting points with which we began. In-
agree to and each could have vetoed (ibid., pp. 263, 270).
deed, it is one and the same idea applied to both starting points and outcomes. This thought, then, is a
19. Ibid., pp. 96±9 and section 33.
fitting completion to the pattern already established in
20. Some of Rawls's clearest statements of this line of
Rawls's first two thoughts. The egalitarian motif of
argument, stressing (as a consideration in the original
`reducing' ± ideally of minimising ± differences in
position) the continuing importance of the bench-
income between the top-most and bottom-most group
mark of equality in a condition of fundamental in-
is expressed most clearly in ibid., section 17 (esp. p.
equality in starting points, is found in his `A Kantian
104). See also Rawls's `Reply to Alexander and Mus-
Conception of Equality', Rawls (1999) at pp. 262±4;
grave', in Rawls (1999) at pp. 246±7, including n. 7;
`Reply to Alexander and Musgrave' in ibid., at pp.
and `Social Unity and Primary Goods' in ibid., at p.
246±7; `Some Reasons for the Maximin Criterion' in
374, n. 12.
ibid., at pp. 230±1; and `Distributive Justice: Some
9. Let me be a bit more precise here. Rawls calls the first
Addenda' in ibid., at p. 165. Thus I think Pat Shaw is
two ideas ± `democratic' equality of opportunity and
wrong to suggest that the difference principle is unconcerned with equality: Shaw (1992), p. 76.
everyone's continual benefit, when taken together in the way I have just described ± the idea of `collective
21. Rawls (1999), p. 594 n. 55.
asset'. The folding of the third idea, of minimising
22. For Kymlicka, see Kymlicka (1990), pp. 61±6. For
inequalities, into collective asset is, in my view, part of
Wolff, see Wolff (1996), pp. 168±87. See also Williams (1995), section III.
Rawls's overall account, though less explicitly so than the other two ideas. The development of, and main
23. A further point. Rawls says that certain considerations
argumentation for, the collective asset idea is found in
make the maximin argument appropriate and render it
Rawls (1972), pp. 72±5, 101±4 (see also pp. 179, 523).
usable. The three most important of these are given in
To this main argumentation should be added his paper
Rawls (1972), p. 154; the latter two could not be
`The Basic Structure as Subject', in Goldman and Kim
convincingly stated and invoked without relying upon
(eds.) (1978), pp. 47±71, at sections 5, 7 and 8. (This
background arguments, of the sort already familiar
paper is reprinted as Lecture VII in Rawls (1996).) See
from the present chapter. For example, one of the
also Rawls (1999), pp. 246±8. For further discussion of
considerations Rawls cites is that `the rejected alter-
the relationship of the collective asset idea to indivi-
natives have outcomes that one can hardly accept.'
dual desert, see Martin (1985), chapter 2, section 2.
But we could have no clear idea of what might be
10. Rawls (1972), pp. 83, 302.
acceptable (or not) without relying upon the very
11. For a proof of this contention, see the appendix in
arguments that would be made in favour of the two principles in the first place. Maximin, in sum, does not
Martin (1985), pp. 197±201.
provide the background argumentation. That argu-
12. See Rawls (1996), Lecture III and, for the quoted
mentation must, then, be developed elsewhere; it is,
phrase, p. 93.
specifically, in the argumentation for the two princi-
13. The procedure has many similarities to what Gabriel
111
REX MARTIN
total wealth (of all classes) would be closely compar-
ples, and in inferences from these arguments. Maximin
able with the result given by classical utility theory.
presupposes these arguments and could not work
27. Rawls is quite explicit on this point; see Rawls (1999),
without them. Thus, a `straight' maximin argument
pp. 165, 246±7.
for the second principle, by-passing the existing argument from collective asset, simply could not be devel-
28. See ibid., p. 230; see also p. 226.
oped.
29. This figure is an adaptation of figures Rawls himself uses; see Rawls (1972), pp. 76±7, 81. Rawls's justi-
24. See Rawls (1972), pp. 60±1 and 302. Rawls significantly recasts the first principle in his later writings ±
fication
see Rawls (1996), p. 291 (in a formulation that dates
position) presupposes that representative members
of
inequality
(in
from 1982) and p. 5 (in a formulation that dates from
of the least well-off group are better off (or at least,
1993).
no worse off) than they would be under a `hypotheinitial arrangement
income,
in
which
wealth,
all
the
social
25. Rawls (1972), pp. 156, 158±9; see also section 49.
tical
26. John Harsanyi, among others, has criticised Rawls's
primary goods are equally distributed', which would
social
argument here. His point is that the principle of
include that `income and wealth are evenly shared':
maximising average utility would fare as well as Raw-
ibid., p. 62. This standard is met by all points in the
ls's two principles under any sort of maximin test; see
so-called available space in the figure. If more than
Harsanyi (1975). D. W. Haslett has argued something
two classes were involved, we would have to repre-
similar with respect to the principle of total utility;
sent their situation in a more complex way. I pre-
specifically, he has argued that the principle of max-
sume, though, that no significant difficulty is posed
imising total utility would fare better under any sort of
on this particular score for my account of the figure drawn here.
maximin test than Rawls's difference principle, at least as regards the distribution of income and wealth ± see
30. One thing we mean when we say that Rawls's theory is
Haslett (1985). I do not find Haslett's argument
ideal is that it is strictly complied with. Its theoretical
convincing. Haslett fails to see that Rawls's main
strictures are fully met. Thus, we would have strict
focus, in the maximin test, is on liberties, not on
compliance if a strategy of everybody's benefit, as
income and wealth. Even on the latter point, Haslett
constrained by egalitarianism, was consistently fol-
fails to see that the judgement at each stage, as to
lowed. The stipulation here is not that the strategy
which to select, is made from a standpoint that
has been optimally followed (`in the best way' or with
incorporates results from the previous stages; Haslett,
the best result); rather, it is merely required that the
on the contrary, treats each sequential choice simply
strategy be completely followed in all cases. My point,
on its own, without regard to where things stand as the
then, is that even if this were done, a society could still
result of prior choices. Finally, in Haslett's own sample
end up in the forbidden zone. A strict compliance
matrix, if the scheme of selection were the one
strategy would not preclude this. A society that so
advocated in the present chapter, where everybody's
acted would not be unjust. Thus, even if the principles
cumulative benefit is constrained at each stage by
of justice are strictly complied with, a problem of
egalitarian considerations, then the worst-off class
essential indeterminacy could still arise. The proble-
would end with a higher index of income and wealth
matic I am describing, then, is a real one for Rawls's
than that afforded by total utility and the resultant
theory.
112
9
RAWLSIAN THEORY, CONTEMPORARY MARXISM AND THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE Rodney G. Peffer
In this chapter, my overall goals are to put the case
politics, the full implications of that victory may
for a Marxist politics today and to proclaim the
still be very far from being recognised and worked
utility to that case of Rawlsian theory ± which is,
through. If an authentically Marxist politics can be
of course, contemporary liberalism's most influential
justified from a Rawlsian perspective, the idea of
contribution to the venerable debate about what
liberalism's `triumph' over Marxism is clearly pro-
`justice' requires. In the history of modern progressive
blematised.
at-
To illustrate this argument, I will first summarise
tacked liberalism for what they perceive to be serious
the key claims in my modified Rawlsian theory of
deficiencies in their theorising of justice. Contrary to
social justice. I shall then seek to rebut some of the
what many people appear to have concluded in the
major reasons why critics have thought that Raw-
wake of Soviet-block communism's collapse, I do not
lsian concepts and prescriptions are inadequate for
believe that the socialist challenge has been at all
`justice'. This section will necessarily be incomplete
discredited. Indeed, I continue to defend the overall
in its coverage; there is simply not the space for a full
Marxist position I first elaborated in my 1990 book
airing of the issues and we should not doubt that the
political
thought,
socialists
have
persistently
However, a
controversy over justice remains variegated and vig-
major theme of that work was that Rawls's theory
orous. But I hope at least to suggest how we might
of justice need only be modified to yield the position
construct a case for saying that Rawlsian theory still
I wished to defend. In other words, there need be no
stands up well in the debate about how `justice'
great moral gap between at least some versions of
should be characterised; it would be vastly premature
liberalism and the ostensibly much more radical
to proclaim the need for its supersession. Finally, I
politics inspired by Marxism. If valid, such a con-
shall offer defence of the claim that my theory really
clusion has at least two profound consequences. The
can count as Marxist. I shall attempt to situate it in
first is that, even when it is granted that arguments
the general school of thought made up of contem-
for socialist politics carry greater weight in the justice
porary liberal-egalitarians and what I shall call the
debate, it need not be necessary to abandon liberal
liberal-socialist egalitarians (among whom we find
theory (at least in its Rawlsian form) to make them.
certain contemporary variants of Marxism who reject
The second is that, in so far as Rawlsianism may be
the official hostility to morality of its `orthodox'
thought to give voice to the liberalism that is widely
version and with which my theory has sufficient
regarded as having won the `battle of ideas' in
affinity to adopt the label itself).
Marxism,
Morality
and
Social
Justice.
113
RODNEY G. PEFFER
of capitalism); and [3] attempts to defend the
Throughout this chapter, I shall leave aside questions of how to generate and justify principles of
Marxist's
justice; I am concerned only to apply intuitive and
The first of these positions is that socialism ±
basic
normative
political
positions.
analytical tests of the moral adequacy of those pro-
that is, democratic, self-managing socialism ± is
posed. Also, such is the enormousness of the various
morally preferable to any form of capitalism as
issues raised here that I can only outline positions
well as to any other form of (modern, mass,
and arguments, aiming to persuade readers to take
pluralistic) society possible under the conditions
them seriously enough to pursue further. The chap-
of moderate scarcity and moderate egoism. The
ter's success in this aim may be gauged by the extent
second is that social and/or political revolution, if
to which it shows how Rawlsianism, the staple diet of
necessary (and sufficient) to effect the appropriate
contemporary liberalism, can push us towards a
transformations, is prima facie morally justified.
1
radical politics that many assume to be completely anathema to the liberal project.
My strategy towards the end of creating such a theory has been to combine a slightly modified Rawlsian theory of social justice with a minimal set of Marxist
A Modified Rawlsian Theory
empirical assumptions to create a theory that ade-
of Social Justice
quately argues for the desirability of working toward a
Since my explicitly stated aim has been to create an
worldwide federation of democratic, self-managing
`adequate' Marxist moral and social theory, I should
market socialist societies. This outcome is not the
first explain what I mean by that phrase. As I noted
one envisaged by Marx, of course. But I ± along with
in the first paragraphs of my 1990 book:
many other thinkers who position themselves within the Marxist tradition today ± reject the feasibility of
By a `moral and social theory' I mean one that
Marx's `higher stage' of communism; the lower,
provides a set of moral principles or standards by
`socialist' stage of post-capitalist society can suffice
which to judge social arrangements and, by so
for Marxism's practical purposes. Furthermore, the
doing, provides criteria to decide between com-
`command economy' model for socialism in mass,
peting sets of historically possible social arrange-
industrial societies has been sufficiently discredited
ments. Such a theory must contain enough of an
for us to prefer a suitably regulated form of market
empirical, social-scientific theory to determine
economy as socialism's best vehicle.
2
which sets of social arrangements are real histor-
Although I wouldn't go so far as to call my theory
ical possibilities and ± of those that are possible ±
a marriage of Marx and Rawls (since this would
which best conform to the moral principles or
probably have to be a `shotgun wedding'), I am
standards
willing to call it an attempt to make Marx and Rawls
propounded
by
an
adequate
moral
theory . . .
seem `comfortable bedfellows'. As a first step in this
By an `adequate' moral and social theory I
direction, in the aforementioned work I surveyed
mean one that is based on a correct set of em-
numerous leftist or left-leaning objections made
pirical, social-scientific theories and on an ade-
against Rawls's theory, arguing that most of them
quate (i.e. correct) moral theory. By an `adequate'
were based on misunderstandings of his theory and/
or `correct moral theory I mean one that is most in
or on faulty reasoning. However, I agreed that there
wide reflective equilibrium with our considered
were four legitimate objections which, although not
moral judgements . . .
requiring a complete rejection of his theory, neces-
By a `Marxist' moral and social theory I mean
sitated some relatively minor modifications. These
one that [1] is informed by the spirit of Marx's
resulted in the following claims:
radical humanism and egalitarianism; [2] is based on the empirical theses centrally important to the
1. There must be a minimum floor of well-being
Marxist political perspective (particularly, Marx's
below which persons are not allowed to fall,
theory of classes and class struggle and his analysis
and observance of this principle must take
114
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
precedence over any other principle of social
Now let us consider my modified Rawlsian theory
justice.
of social justice in full (the principles being listed in
2. There must be at least approximate equality in
order of lexical priority), which I believe captures
the worth of liberty as well as strict equality of
more clearly the sense of `justice' than Rawls's own
liberty per se.
two principles:
3. The difference principle must take the social basis of self-respect ± as well as material wealth
1. Everyone's basic security and subsistence rights
± as a good to be maximised for the least
are to be met (that is, everyone's physical
advantaged.
integrity is to be respected), and everyone is
4. Democracy must not be limited to the political
to be guaranteed a minimum level of material
realm but be implemented in the social and
well-being including basic needs (that is, those
economic realms as well, most especially in the
needs that must be met in order to remain a
workplace.
3
normally functioning human being and citizen).
One significant outcome of these arguments is that
2. There is to be a fully adequate scheme of equal
in his most recent book, Political Liberalism, Rawls
basic liberties, including:
has explicitly acknowledged three of the four mod-
a. freedom of speech and assembly, freedom of
ifications as being persuasive and, in effect, accepted
conscience and thought, freedom of move-
them. As remaining points of dispute between us,
ment and free choice of occupation, the
this leaves only my suggested modification in favour
right to hold (personal) property, freedom
of a principle of social and economic democracy
from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined
(modification 4) and a disagreement over whether
by the concepts of due process and the rule
or not the difference principle governing fair dis-
of law;
tributions of material primary goods (income, wealth
b. the political liberties such as the right to
and leisure time) should be applied only within
vote and to run for (and hold) political
nations (Rawls's position) or internationally (my
office. These political liberties ± including
view as well as the view of many other writers
the rights to free political speech and as-
and theorists).
4
sembly ± are to be guaranteed their equal
However, part of our ongoing dis-
worth.
agreement over the former seems merely semantic in nature. Rawls's stated reason for rejecting it is that, as
3. There is to be fair equality of opportunity in
a first principle of social justice, it would automati-
the competition for social positions and offices.
cally require some form of socialism and thus illegitimately prejudge the practical project of selecting a
4. Social and economic inequalities are justified
suitable regime for justice given the contingencies of
if and only if they benefit the least advantaged,
the circumstances in question. I believe that this
consistent with the just savings principle, but
argument fails in so far as it is based on a non-
are not to exceed levels that will undermine
standard definition of socialism which obscures the
(a) (approximately) equal worth of the liber-
fact that a society which has some significant degree
ties required by due process, or (b) the good of self-respect.
of social and economic democracy need not be thought of as `socialist' by definition. It is also at
5. There is to be an equal right to participate in
least logically possible that a capitalist society could
decision-making processes within the social
be characterised as having a substantial amount of
and economic institutions of which one is a
social and economic democracy.
5
member.
Hence it is wrong
6
to think that the modification selects the best form of regime in advance of the evaluation of actual cir-
Let us call these principles (1) the Basic Rights
cumstances. (I shall return to the latter dispute
Principle; (2) the Equal Basic Liberties Principle;
shortly.)
(3) the Fair Equality of Opportunity Principle; (4)
115
RODNEY G. PEFFER
the Modified Difference Principle; and (5) the Social
(structured so as not to skew distribution according
and Economic Democracy Principle. As with any
to the unearned or otherwise undeserved possession
abstract theory, a number of caveats, clarifications
of certain attributes). Any theory that does not
and principles of application must be mentioned and
adequately take these points into account will not
I want to highlight a few that are important in the
be judged adequate within this tradition.
9
consolidation of my argument. One important gen-
Let us briefly highlight some features of my first,
eral point to remember is that Rawls's theory applies
second, third and fifth principles, saving the Mod-
specifically to a society's `basic structure' (the poli-
ified Difference Principle for a more extended ana-
tical constitution and the nature and structure of the
lysis in the next section. With respect to my first
economy, including the provision of public goods,
(Basic Rights) principle, it is evident that different
taxation and redistribution policies, and environ-
conditions in the physical and mental health of
mental regulation). Together with the fact that at
individuals will mean that the resources allocated
a micro-level, so to speak, many institutions, both
to meet people's basic needs will not be equal in
public and private, will have areas of activity ± such
amount; no crude `uniformitarian' equality is sought.
as competitions for positions, awards and prizes ±
Therefore, we must say that the equality in this
within which individual merit, effort or accomplish-
principle is cashed out in terms of everyone posses-
ment are legitimate criteria for awards, this point
sing an equal right to have their security and sub-
bears out the insistence by Michael Walzer (among
sistence rights met (or an equal right to be given the
others) that there are different spheres of justice
opportunity to meet their subsistence rights in the
which may have different criteria for just distribu-
case of able-bodied and able-minded people). More-
tions of benefits and burdens. Clearly, this thesis
over, when it proves not to be possible to meet
could be perfectly compatible with Rawls's theory,
everyone's basic needs (as when, say, there are not
deliberately restricted in its scope of application as it
enough hearts available to meet each need for a heart
7
is.
And even though we are to decide on more and
transplant), it could be consistent and perhaps ne-
more specific questions and issues at each subsequent
cessary to invoke notions from other traditional
stage of Rawls's four-stage decision-making sequence
canons of distributive justice to decide how distribu-
± in which, after the choice of basic principles of
tion ought to proceed in such suboptimal circum-
social justice in the initial original position, we have
stances. At a more general level, to operationalise
the constitutional, legislative and judicial stages ± all
this principle social and political theorists must turn
choices are to be made on the basis of these prin-
to social-scientific theory and research to determine
ciples of social justice and are applicable only to
how various types of societies (and governments)
public or publicly supported institutions.
8
under various historical conditions can be expected
It should also be mentioned that Rawlsian theories
to meet people's subsistence and security rights.
and indeed all other theories of social justice devel-
Moral and political theory shouldn't hubristically
oped within the contemporary liberal-egalitarian/
claim to settle all such questions in advance.
10
liberal-socialist tradition are motivated by a genuine
Discussion of my first principle is a good point at
concern for individual liberty/autonomy as well as for
which to stress the ambition of my theory to have
human well-being/flourishing. We should always
global applicability. I may be going against the
keep in view the point that we should not select a
normatively localising grain of much contemporary
conception of justice that overly compromises these
thinking about justice here, but one of the virtues of
considerations. One manifestation of this is that,
the Marxist account is that it forcefully illustrates the
when it comes to principles designed to govern
direct dependence of the achievement of justice in
and judge the distribution of material resources,
the developing world (surely, given the conditions
we are concerned to develop a theory that, to a
there, justice's most urgent priority) upon the beha-
relatively high degree, is both ambition-sensitive (cap-
viour of the developed world. Localised or relativised
able of rewarding autonomous initiative over indo-
accounts of justice (favoured by many communitar-
lent passivity, say) as well as endowment-insensitive
ians) are thus deeply irresponsible in failing both to
116
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
recognise how a society's own behaviour and internal
These duties obviously require us to do what we can
make-up can profoundly affect the prospects for
± including getting our governments to do what they
justice in other societies and for refusing to include
can ± to try to make sure that everyone in the world
them
result.
is raised up out of absolute poverty and that no one
Although it might be tempting to think that I
has their security rights violated. (Or rather, it
diverge sharply from Rawls in terms of the theory's
requires us to do at least our fair share to accomplish
relevance to the developing world, this would be a
these goals.) However, one of the reasons that I
mistake. It may be the case that Rawls doesn't go as
believe my version of his theory has a greater degree
far as he should in applying certain aspects of his
of clarity is that my Basic Rights Principle explicitly
theory to the relationships between the developed
states that both people's subsistence and security
and developing parts of the world (governing the
rights (the correlates of his duties not to harm and
distribution of goods between rich and poor nations).
to aid the severely deprived) must be respected and
in
their
theorising
of
justice
as
a
Yet even an unmodified version of his theory has
protected and that this is the most important or basic
some important things to say about this issue. First,
principle of social justice which must thus take
his distinction between the general and the special
precedence over all others in the design of social
conception of justice as fairness is of the utmost
institutions, policies and programmes.
14
importance because the general conception (which
Let us turn now to the first part of principle 2, the
applies within developing societies) actually requires
Maximum Equal Basic Liberties Principle. To allay
the difference principle to be applied to all the social
socialist suspicions that Rawlsian theory is some kind
primary goods (liberties and opportunities, income
of bourgeois apologia, the nature of the property
and wealth, and the social bases of self-respect) as a
right as referring specifically to personal property must
package. Therefore, it allows trade-offs between
be stressed. We must keep in view the point that the
them. In contrast, the special conception (the more
right to own large-scale productive property ± which is
familiar two principles of justice, applying only to
here opposed to `personal property' ± is not taken as
well-developed societies) lists the principles govern-
one of the basic liberties. Whether there should be
ing these goods in order of lexical priority such that
such a right can only be answered at the second
any amount of increase in `lower-order' goods (such
(constitutional) stage of the Rawlsian four-step de-
as income and wealth for the least well-off) cannot
cision
be traded off for the least decrease in higher order
known about the effects that such a right would
goods (such as liberties or fair access to opportu-
have in terms of the realisation of the basic principles
nities).
11
procedure, after
more
empirical
facts
are
The reason that Rawls makes this distinc-
of social justice. This allows for the possibility of
tion is precisely because he doesn't want his theory to
socialism on Rawls's view (although a democratic
be committed to the absurdly heartless doctrine that
form of market socialism), as he makes abundantly
liberties and fair access to opportunities can never be
clear in his first book.
15
limited to any degree in any society, even if this were
Moving to the second part of this principle: as
necessary, say, to save people from starvation. And
Rawls argues, guaranteeing people (approximately)
he is genuinely concerned with `how the poorer and
equal worth of their political liberties would seem at
less technologically advanced societies of the world
a minimum to require full public financing of elec-
can attain historical and social conditions that allow
toral campaigns (at least in a society such as ours in
them to establish just and workable institutions.'
12
which wealthy individuals, corporations and interest
Although often forgotten in discussions of Rawls's
groups can disproportionately influence electoral
work, his theory of natural duties which posits,
outcomes) and perhaps other innovative electoral
among others, the duties not to harm and of mutual
modifications.
aid (that is, the duty to aid those whose basic needs
it advocates will clearly not sanction those distor-
are not being met) has always been taken by Rawls
tions due to unequal wealth that capitalist democ-
himself to apply between individuals no matter
racies (particularly the US) typically experience.
whether or not they belong to the same societies.
13
16
In short, the kind of democracy that
The primary moral thesis behind principle 3 ± the
117
RODNEY G. PEFFER
Fair Equality of Opportunity Principle ± is that
every institution in which they participate. Nor does
persons of (approximately) equal talents and abilities
it claim that there cannot be administrative hierar-
ought to have (approximately) equal chances of
chies in such institutions.
20
succeeding in life (whatever their idea of success
The essential distinction between socialism and
may be, within the constraints of justice already
capitalism, I maintain, is that in a socialist society
specified). In particular, such persons ought to have
the preponderance of large-scale productive enter-
(approximately) equal chances in the competition
prises (and investment capital) are socially owned
for desirable offices, jobs and positions.
17
In order to
and utilised primarily for the purposes of fulfilling
accomplish this goal at least two conditions must be
human needs and for the public good. In capitalism
met. First, there must be no discrimination based on
these enterprises (and capital) are largely owned
race, ethnicity, gender, sexual preference and so on.
privately and are geared to maximise the profit of
Second, everyone must be given an equal start `out of
their owners. Whether it is empirically possible or
the gate', so to speak, in the race for life's favourable
likely that socialism or capitalism can or will better
offices, jobs and positions or, more broadly, success.
facilitate social and economic democracy cannot be
And to accomplish this it is reasonable to think that
read off from these institutional ideals alone. Many
the minimum which must be done is that all children
theorists, I think, assume that socialism is more likely
are given equal access to high-quality education from
to allow for social and economic democracy, even if
a very young age. Assuming that there are no natural
some of them doubt that this would be a good thing
differences in general intelligence and suchlike be-
or suspect that it may not concomitantly allow
tween racial and ethnic groups (which we have every
increased political democracy. But whether or not
18
), there probably would be no
any society has (or will) meet the definitional criteria
need for compensatory or remedial measures such as
I have lain down for socialism is still a matter for
affirmative action programmes if these conditions
debate, as is whether or not human needs can be
were fulfilled since, presumably, there would be no
adequately fulfilled and the public good accommo-
statistical discrimination against any of the groups.
dated in various capitalist societies by trickle-down
However, in a society like ours in which such dis-
mechanisms and/or enlightened government poli-
crimination clearly exists, there are ± I submit ±
cies. Here, at the level of practical application, would
strong
seem to be the place at which substantive disputes
reason to assume
moral
arguments
for
such
remedial
grammes in the construction of a just society.
pro-
19
between liberals and socialists remain. Certainly, it is at this point that I would make my case for socialism.
Principle 5 ± the Social and Economic Democracy Principle ± is, admittedly, particularly vague as to
This concludes the summary of my modifications
what it requires given that regime selection is not to
to Rawls's theory, with the exception of the Modified
be made at the level of principle. Specifically, I do
Difference Principle (principle 4).
not take it in itself to be pre-emptively, definitionally endorsing socialism over capitalism, as we earlier saw
A Defence of
Rawls mistakenly believing my theory to be doing. I
the Modified Difference Principle
completely agree with his claim that a theory of social justice should not prejudge the choice of social
The question we now need to take up is whether the
system until we take into account empirical, social-
Modified Difference Principle is sufficiently robust to
scientific information about how they actually per-
take its place in a Marxist account. As space is
form or can be expected to perform under specified
limited, I will concentrate on some reasons to think
historical conditions. But I would submit that justice
that it is more ambition-sensitive and endowment-
requires members of institutions to have some right
insensitive than many critics, who have accordingly
to participate in social decision-making processes
formulated alternative accounts of justice, realise. I
concerning matters that affect them and the institu-
claim that this could form the core of a fuller
tion. However, it doesn't necessarily give everyone
argument that the Rawlsian approach should still
full voting rights with respect to every decision in
command our attention as an adequate characterisa-
118
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
tion of justice. I bolster this idea with an argument
charge against Marxist accounts of egalitarian justice
which shows that supposedly more `orthodox' Marx-
and one which I agree would, if valid, discredit this
ist thinking on justice does not yield self-evidently
general approach). For one consequence of Rawls's
superior concepts for its own purposes.
demand that the difference principle be applied
We might suspect that one Marxist reservation
lexically is that it can deflect the charge that it does
about Rawlsian theory is that, because it is `liberal' in
not meet the Pareto optimality requirement and
origin, it is not sufficiently egalitarian in the relevant
must consequently be rejected. This requirement
way. So it is only fair to the difference principle to
holds that if someone or some group can be made
begin by reminding ourselves that Rawlsian theory
materially better off without anyone else (or any
demands (1) that the least well-off group be maxi-
other group) being made worse off, then this must be
mally benefited, not simply benefited (whatever that
done (or allowed). Without this requirement, it
would mean), and (2) that the difference principle
seems that the `only-if' clause of the difference
be applied lexically, that is after the life prospects of
principle's claim (holding that material inequalities
the least well-off group are maximised then the life
are to be allowed ± by the background institutions,
prospects of the next least well-off group are to be
policies and programmes ± if and only if they will
maximised and so on.
21
In the light of this, we can
maximally benefit the least well-off group) does not
already sense the oddity of the standard Marxist
allow inequalities that would benefit a group of
charge that Rawlsianism is merely a species of capi-
people which is materially more well-off than the
talist ideology; we must not underestimate its poten-
least well-off (poorest) social group even when, for
tial as a sanction for strongly egalitarian policies.
whatever reason, nothing further could be done to
My claim that The Modified Difference Principle
improve the life prospects of the latter. Now to deny
is (even) more egalitarian than Rawls's original
an improvement in material well-being for someone
version is generated from the point that, for mine,
if this won't prevent a benefit from accruing to
the allowable economic inequalities are not to ex-
anyone else ± specifically, in Rawls's view, to the
ceed levels that will (1) undermine (approximately)
least well-off ± does seem unjustifiable. And this is
equal worth of the liberties required by due process,
precisely what the lexical application of the differ-
or (2) undermine the good of self-respect. I have
ence principle is designed to prevent since it `goes all
previously noted that Rawls has recently accepted
the way to the top'. So, for example, if every income
these points and I think he is able to do so because
level group has had its life prospects maximised in
they are arguably already implicit in his own work.
lexical order (as described above) and it turns out
He thinks his difference principle compensates for
that something can still be done to improve the
any lesser worth of liberty among the `less advan-
material life prospects of the wealthiest group, then
taged' given that it would be worth even less if the
the background institutions must allow for it. Of
difference principle had not determined distribution.
course, it is not easy to envisage clear-cut, concrete
And self-respect, explicitly identified as a social
examples of this, certainly not any in which wide
primary good, depends in part upon mutual respect
gaps would remain between the least advantaged and
and social recognition, which may be less forthcom-
those above them. Although it is possible that the
ing where there are widespread and large-scale in-
lexical application of the principle would result in
equalities.
22
In this respect, my modifications do not
greater inequalities between upper and lower income
seem to be leading us in a direction that Rawls
groups, in most real-world scenarios it still seems
himself would never be prepared to take. (Under
likely that its effect will be significantly to reduce
what economic conditions people's self-respect may
inequalities. In any case, as a matter of principle this
be undermined is again an issue for the social and
part of Rawls's theory avoids the criticism that it
psychological sciences to decide.)
violates the Pareto optimality requirement.
Conversely, this direction should not be thought
Another charge against Rawlsian theory which
of as leading to the crudely ambition-insensitive
accuses it of ambition-insensitivity says that, by
policy
counting talents and capacities as socially useful
of
`levelling-down'
(the
standard
vulgar
119
RODNEY G. PEFFER
resources rather than as vehicles for individual gain,
dividuals on the grounds that they are producing
it leads to the `slavery of the talented'. This claim
benefits for a wider society (capitalists in particular
holds that it is unjust to reward gifted individuals for
typically cite this argument when justifying the large
the usage of their abilities only in so far as that would
pay rises they award themselves, implicitly conceding
maximise the position of the least advantaged; their
the inadequacy of any argument that says their
gifts are not being rewarded in their own right. It
talents demand such rewards regardless of the ben-
focuses upon the very heart of what might build the
efits they supposedly bring). And many complaints
bridge between Rawlsian and Marxist justice: Rawls's
about low rewards often proceed from the claim that
interpretation of that often-neglected liberal value of
the social benefit of the job in question is not being
`fraternity' as a conception of `democratic equality',
properly recognised. Even when people think they
in which people agree to `regard the distribution of
are judging the `intrinsic' rather than instrumental
natural talents as a common asset . . . [t]hose better
(social benefit) value of someone's talents, the cri-
circumstanced are willing to have their greater ad-
teria they use often still implicitly rely upon some
vantages only under a scheme in which this works
notion of those talents' social utility. How else, we
out for the benefit of the least advantaged.'
23
might wonder, could we ultimately judge what any
One interpretation of this position that may in-
talent is worth? Further, even what counts as a
advertently fuel the `slavery' critique holds that
`talent' rather than a mere `capacity' may be at least
Rawls rejects a crucial part of what G. A. Cohen
partly
calls the principle of self-ownership: `Because it is a
ideology, after all, the idea that the market rewards
matter of brute luck that people have the talents that
talented effort and achievement necessarily relies
they do, their talents do not, morally speaking,
upon the distinctly instrumentalist idea that what
belong to them, but are, properly regarded, resources
counts as `talented' ± rewardable ± contributions is
over which society as a whole may legitimately
determined by what other people in the marketplace
dispose.'
24
determined
by
social
utility;
in
capitalist
demand.
No great imagination is required to read
into this a sanctioning of some kind of forced-labour
Of course this is not to claim that people are
policy, which would be the grossest violation of the
therefore already thinking in terms of the difference
stipulation that justice should facilitate, not crush,
principle and I don't deny the fact that people also
autonomy. But Cohen's wording is unfortunately
ordinarily use rival notions of justice as well. But I am
misleading if this is the reading it prompts. Neither
saying that there is something in ordinary discourse
Rawls's theory nor my own deny people the right to
about justice upon which Rawlsianism can latch to
choose how they use their talents. Society is not said
develop its case. Such a case should stress that (in particular) anti-
to `own' them in the sense of having the right to tell people how and when they should be employed.
25
socialist criticisms of Rawlsianism usually assume (1)
Strictly speaking, what society is primarily laying
that individuals are garnering most of their material
claim to is the wealth used to compensate for and/
resources (income and wealth) by working (as either
or reward their employment. Rawlsian theory insists
an employee or their own boss); (2) that individuals
that people have no particular claim on this wealth
are usually materially rewarded due to their effort or
simply by virtue of the talents they have chosen to
socially useful contribution; and (3) that the level of
exercise; a socially determined concern for a com-
recompense is usually correlated with natural talents
mon good provides the distributive criterion instead.
and abilities, at least in a just or relatively just
This might still sound too radically egalitarian for
society. But in contemporary class societies these
some liberals, which once led Cohen to think that
assumptions are highly dubious. In capitalist socie-
26
But
ties, members of the highest income/wealth socio-
reflection on how people ordinarily think about
economic group ± that is the capitalist ruling class
justice can readily show that, on this score, Raw-
and its `hangers-on' ± often inherit the great pre-
lsianism may not be all that out of the ordinary to
ponderance of their wealth rather than garner it by
many. For people often justify high rewards to in-
their labour or effort. Moreover, the investment
perhaps Rawls was not a `proper' liberal at all.
120
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
is able to command.
income they receive through rent, interest and di-
28
vidends (which normally dwarfs their salaried in-
Although Rawlsianism clearly poses a large chal-
comes, even if they are top corporate executives) is
lenge to capitalist thinking about justice, G. A.
not earned in any socially useful, morally significant
Cohen has claimed that socialists should still not
sense. As David Schweickart has argued, to allow
be satisfied with the difference principle for another
capital to be used is hardly a genuinely productive act
reason.
± since, at most, it requires signing some papers on
`incentive principle', sanctioning unequally large
the part of those who own it ± even if the capital
rewards to the talented rich on the grounds that
owner's permission is legally required for its deploy-
they will consequently have the incentive to work
ment within the socio-economic system in ques-
hard and thereby generate wealth which will `trickle
tion.
27
29
He notes its familiar presentation as an
And to claim that corporate executives,
down' to the least advantaged and benefit them more
bank presidents and suchlike really deserve what
than would any other arrangement. (This, of course,
they earn (because they are the only ones who
has been the staple justification of regressive taxation
can do the job or are really the best qualified) surely
policies since the Reagan/Thatcher days.) Leaving
strains the limits of credibility. In an interesting ploy
aside the debate as to whether the `trickle-down'
to disprove such widely accepted nonsense, the
thesis actually holds (for if it does not, such a policy
politically
Ben
would clearly not be sanctioned by the difference
and Jerry ± of the highly successful Ben & Jerry's
principle), Cohen claims that the `incentive' con-
ice cream parlours ± some years ago advertised the
struction of the difference principle's operation relies
position of president of their corporation to the
upon certain assumptions that are incompatible with
general public, requiring only a one-page letter of
the attitude towards one's talents that Rawls himself
interest initially and then follow-up interviews. They
believes is required by justice. Simply put, a talented
ended up selecting an African-American man in his
capitalist entrepreneur who is paid a particularly high
fifties who had only a high school education and had
salary as an incentive to create jobs which would not
been employed as a janitor most of his life, with
otherwise be created for the least advantaged is
absolutely no ill effects for the corporation.
typically not unable to do the same job for a lot less.
radical
American
entrepreneurs
One might agree that rewards at the `top end' of
Rather, he is unwilling to do so and he is effectively
capitalist society (including entertainers and sports
using his socially valuable talents as his own `bar-
stars as well as capitalists) far outstrip any plausible
gaining chips' to enhance his own personal gains at
assessment of their talent's worth, however this is
no extra benefit to the community. In other words,
assessed. But the claim that even individuals in the
he is not treating his talents as `common assets', for if
middle and lower classes usually get paid what they
he did he would not need incentives to work (in-
deserve
(on
deed, he probably does not `need' them at all, but is
grounds, for example, that people normally receive
nevertheless able to claim so as he holds the rest of
an income commensurate with the productive value
the community to ransom by threatening to with-
and relative scarcity of their work abilities and skills
hold his talents if he is not paid more).
for
their
work
in
market
societies
under equilibrium market conditions) is highly sus-
It is hardly clear that Rawls would wish to depart
picious because of the general impact that non-
from Cohen's claim that the `incentive' scenario
market factors such as social custom, political reg-
described above involved an unjust rejection of
ulation and the strength of organised labour (each of
community and its claims on the talents of its
which may be connected with the others) have on
members. As we have seen, his own notion of
the determination of remuneration by the `free mar-
democratic equality rests upon a specific understand-
ket'. In general, there are just too many counter-
ing of `community' whose members would reject such
vailing forces in the operation of the capitalist
a selfish attitude to their own talents. Thus, it would
market to make us happy with the idea that the
be misleading to think that the difference principle
social value of people's talents is appropriately re-
sanctions such an incentive payment as being itself
warded by the wage or salary that their labour-power
just. (Cohen would agree that if incentives were the
121
RODNEY G. PEFFER
only way to get the talented to work and that their
opportunities actually exist); (2) whether this is a
labours would indeed maximise the position of the
justified social policy (or principle of social justice)
least advantaged, then it would be justified. But this
regardless of what Rawls's theory says about it.
would be the application only of a principle to
Now I claim that (1) Rawls's theory does not
ameliorate injustice in an unjust world and not what
require such a policy; and (2) assuming that there
full justice itself would mandate.) Admittedly, a
are genuine opportunities for people to earn a living
Rawlsian might sanction incentives on the grounds
under decent conditions and with decent recom-
that they would be necessary to attract people to
pense, a social policy (or principle of justice) that
careers that are socially necessary but exceptionally
would allow such free-riders is not justified or at least
difficult or dangerous and hence unlikely to be
not required.
chosen without them. To this I have two brief
Rawlsians have split over both of these issues such
replies. One is to point out that this observation
that, for example, I have been scolded by certain of
does not serve many of today's incentive-claiming
Rawls's former students for both (supposedly) mis-
talented rich particularly well; they would doubtless
interpreting Rawls and for being too much of a
still have picked their chosen careers even if the
`puritan' in rejecting such a policy. I have also
material rewards were somewhat less because they are
encountered
not `dangerous' or particularly difficult. Indeed, in a
who have agreed with me on both points. Happily,
just society such incentives may be necessary to
Rawls is now on record as not requiring such a policy,
attract people to the kind of work which is very
since in his typescript `Justice as Fairness: A Restate-
often exceptionally low-paid in capitalist society.
ment' he writes:
30
Admittedly, both Rawlsians and non-
both
Rawlsians
and
non-Rawlsians
Secondly, my rendering of Rawlsianism as a socialist doctrine consolidates within its terms the ideal of
Particular distributions cannot be judged at all
people freely choosing to dispose of their talents in a
apart from the claims (entitlements) of indivi-
socially beneficial way. To be sure, some difficult and
duals earned by their efforts within the fair system of
dangerous tasks may still require incentive payments,
co-operation from which those distributions re-
if other ways are not found for allocating them. But,
sult. In contrast to utilitarianism, the concept of
in general, I don't conceive of people needing huge
allocative justice has no application. There is no
incentives to work in a socially beneficial rather than
criterion for a just distribution apart from back-
selfish way in the just socialist society, certainly not
ground institutions and the entitlements that
to the kind of inegalitarian degree supposedly re-
arise from actually working through the procedure
quired in capitalist society.
[emphasis added].
31
The `slavery of the talented' critique has probably had most bite in the rather different criticism that
It should be noted, however, that to prevent able-
since his difference principle and minimum floor
bodied people from being free-riders when there are
requirement seem to assure the least well-off ± in
opportunities available for them to earn a decent
fact, everyone ± a minimal income or set of material
living by their own efforts is neither an endorsement
resources, Rawls's theory is not sufficiently ambition-
of the kind of movement to have `workfare' replace
sensitive because it seems not to require anyone to do
`welfare' underway in the US (since the opportu-
anything in order to be entitled to this income or set
nities may not be well-paying enough once one
of resources; it encourages free-riding and hence
includes childcare and transportation expenses into
discourages the formation of the kind of community
the equation), nor an affirmation of the view that
just described above. There are actually two ques-
people must work if they are able-bodied (which I
tions that must be distinguished here: (1) whether
would regard as a genuinely puritan attitude). My
Rawls's theory requires that this minimum income
only claim is that able-bodied people should not be
simply be given to anyone whether or not they are
supported by the state or society in general if they
willing to do anything to earn it (assuming that they
refuse to do anything to earn a living (assuming,
are able-bodied and able-minded and that such
again, that decent opportunities exist for them to
122
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
do so). If they can sponge off others while not doing
tical perspective that is inclined towards impatience
anything illegitimate to garner the material goods
with regards to some types of `armchair' reflection.
and services they need, the state or society has no
The nub of Rawls's argument is that social primary
business telling them that they can't live their lives
goods are all-purpose general resources in modern
this way, as far as I'm concerned . . . at least if
societies that can usually be utilised by individuals
requiring people to do socially useful work is not
who have them no matter what their life plans are.
absolutely necessary for society to meet the first
Because they constitute a specific, limited set of
(Basic Rights) principle of justice.
goods, they should be easier to track in the process
I now want briefly to reflect upon the objection
of distribution than the wider and more nebulous
that Rawls's notion of `social primary goods' mis-
categories of (opportunities for) resources, welfare or
identifies what theories of social justice should be
advantage. In other words, policies of social justice
concerned to distribute (such as welfare or utility, or
may be easier to operationalise with a concept of
material resources). Space does not allow a full
social primary goods as their currency. This claim is
discussion of all of Rawls's rivals, so I can only sketch
reinforced by Rawls's insistence that his theory is one
the case for retaining his approach. I will, though, say
of `pure procedural justice' in which an outcome is
a little more on `exploitation', a category which
judged to be just wholly in so far as it has arisen
many might think Marxism ought to prefer as the
through the operation of just procedures. He writes
key term in its account of justice.
that:
Richard Arneson helpfully distinguishes between four alternative principles of justice, based around
The great practical advantage of pure procedural
two different types of good to be distributed ± `wel-
justice is that it is no longer necessary in meeting
fare' and `resources' ± and two types of `end-state' ±
the demands of justice to keep track of the endless
based upon whether justice is concerned with the
variety of circumstances and the changing relative
amount possessed of each good or merely with the
positions of particular persons. One avoids the
opportunity to acquire them:
problem of defining principles to cope with the enormous complexities which would arise if such
1. the Equality of Welfare Principle;
details were relevant. It is a mistake to focus
2. the Equality of Resources Principle;
attention on the varying relative positions of
3. the Equal Opportunity for Welfare Principle;
individuals and to require that every change,
4. the Equal Opportunity for Resources
considered as a single transaction viewed in iso-
Principle.
32
lation, be in itself just. It is the arrangement of the basic structure which is to be judged, and judged
To this we might add a fifth, developed by Cohen
from a general point of view . . . Thus the ac-
and, because of his own political pedigree, one that
ceptance of the two principles constitutes an
may be of particular interest to socialists:
understanding to discard as irrelevant as a matter of social justice much of the information and
5. the Equality of Access to Advantage Principle.
33
many of the complications of everyday life.
34
All five have been much discussed in order to ascertain which one does the best job of capturing
This is not to say that institutions should never be
what justice intuitively requires. Typically, their
scrutinised for their justice-promoting abilities once
respective proponents all claim superiority over Raw-
they have been established. In his `Restatement',
ls's approach in this regard. Important issues are
Rawls talks of `pure adjusted procedural justice',
undoubtedly raised in this debate and I accept that
introducing the caveat that `certain rules for making
it would be premature to foreclose on it. But there
adjustments must be included in the basic structure
may be a case for thinking that it should not pre-
as a system of social co-operation so that this system
dominate in the discourse about justice in the way it
remains fair over time.'
has done recently, particularly from a radical poli-
35
These features are, I would argue, great strengths
123
RODNEY G. PEFFER
37
of his theory since they make it more readily applic-
in order to fulfil valuable human functionings.
able to the workings of actual societies and less
approach is not easily classifiable as either welfarist or
This
intrusive into people's individual lives. On Rawls's
resourcist as, strictly speaking, it seeks to equalise
approach, so long as people act within the confines
neither. But it has the advantage of carrying our
of justice and so long as what they are able to garner
moral view to a very deep level of what is really
for themselves is accumulated within the confines of
(intrinsically) valuable in human lives. It keeps us
the background institutions set up by the principles
focused on the fact that, due to differential natural
of social justice they ± and their legitimate material
talents and abilities, people differentially convert
holdings ± are not to be interfered with. This may
resources into valuable `functionings' (or capabilities
contrast with those theories of justice which do not
for such functionings) and that it is these with which
have such in-built delimitations, for they may inad-
theorists of justice should be primarily concerned.
vertently sanction a political `micro-management' of
However, Rawlsian theory is not blind to this point.
social and personal life that, apart from anything
It does not cease to be interested in how people stand
else, would conflict with the fundamental respect for
with reference to their primary goods once they have
individual autonomy and well-being identified ear-
been distributed. A crucial consideration in selecting
lier as central to justice's concerns.
the best form of social and political order for Raw-
To consolidate this part of the case for Rawlsian
lsian justice is precisely which of the alternatives best
theory, it is worth reflecting upon this claim of
allow people the chance to utilise these goods in
Arneson's, who, having surveyed numerous compet-
pursuit of their own life-plans. My own case for
ing theories of justice, concludes that their practical
socialism, indeed, would partly rest upon the claim
implications
that a socialist order is much more amenable to the process of converting `goods' into `functionings'.
may be hard to discern, and may not diverge
And once that is recognised, the advantages of Sen's
much in practice. Familiar information-gathering
approach diminish in so far as it is limited to covering
and information-using problems will make us
only basic capabilities. Once these are achieved, it
unwilling to authorise government agencies to
doesn't tell us how to govern any further distribu-
determine people's distributive shares on the basis
tions of resources above the levels necessary for these
of their preference satisfaction prospects, which
purposes. Indeed, `capacities' may simply cease to be
will often be unknowable for all practical pur-
useful beyond this basic level. As G. A. Cohen puts
poses. [So, for example], we may insist that gov-
it, `capacities beyond the basic (Can I run a mile?
ernments have regard to primary goods equality or
Can I impress Ukrainians with my impersonation of
resource equality as rough proxies for the welfarist
Russians? Can I sew more quickly than you?) seem
equality that we are unable to calculate.
36
quite irrelevant to measurement, deprivation, inequality or anything else of urgent concern from 38
If it is indeed fair to say that these rival theories will
the point of view of justice.'
tend to converge upon similar concerns and recom-
see that subsistence rights are cited as something that
mendations in practice, then the case for `social
must be fulfilled by my Basic Rights Principle, Sen's
primary goods' on the grounds of their theoretical
concerns with basic capabilities would already seem
parsimony is indeed strong. The substantive disputes
to be accommodated. No practical advantage over
about justice could then shift to the debate over
the `social primary goods' approach is gained.
which form of regime may best bear the concerns of
In any case, once we
Finally in this section we turn to `exploitation',
justice (more on this in the next section).
which many Marxists might wish to make central to
One noteworthy critic of Rawls who also opposes
any discussion of justice. Now there has been much
the `welfarist/resourcist' axis is Amartya Sen, who has
discussion as to how `exploitation' should be con-
defended a `basic capacities' approach, arguing that
ceptualised, led by John Roemer in particular, and
justice should seek to assure that people have the
there is no space here to enter this debate.
opportunity to exercise their basic human capacities
I simply want to offer one definition of the term ±
124
39
Instead,
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
which I take to be much more `orthodox Marxist'
possibility, capitalist exploitation is all-things-con-
than Roemer's ± and then sketch an argument which
sidered unjustified.)
holds that `exploitation' could not substitute for
Further, I would also argue that not only does
anything like my Rawlsian account of social justice
`exploitation' need a fuller morality to supplement it,
in a plausible political morality.
it can also be replaced or subsumed by one such as my
I contend that, for Marx, `exploited labour' is (1)
Rawlsian theory. For the elements of `force', `robbery'
forced (because workers have no realistic choice but
and `loss of control' in exploitation proper can all
to sell their labour-power to capitalists); (2) unpaid in
also stand condemned by specific components of that
its yielding of surplus value or product (that is, the
theory. `Exploitation' adds nothing new or necessary
profit the individual capitalist accrues from the
to it.
commodities
produced
by
workers'
labour); also
(3): the product of the labour is lost to the producer ± it comes under the control of someone else.
40
`But Is This A Marxist Theory?'
The
question for theorists of justice here is what, exactly,
Now I should make clear why I say that my overall
is wrong with exploitation? We can answer this using
moral and social theory is a Marxist theory and what
a three-way distinction between types of exploita-
is contained in its minimal set of Marxist empirical
tion.
41
assumptions. To the first question, my answer is (as it
First, we have simple exploitation, denoting the
has previously been) that it is not a specifically
appropriation of surplus value, or the fact of the
Marxist moral theory. This should not be surprising.
direct producers not getting back the full value of
Not even Marx's implicit moral theory per se is a
what they produce. Note that there is no reference to
specifically Marxist theory. There is, in fact, no such
`force' here, so the Marxist notion does not come
thing as a specifically Marxist moral theory. There is,
under this heading. It highlights merely the transfer
however, such a thing as a specifically Marxist moral
of value from producers and it cannot be considered
and social theory, i.e. a theory which combines a
even prima facie wrong because this could come
moral theory with a set of empirical, social-scientific
about as the result of a genuinely free and fair
theses in order to judge alternative sets of social
agreement. Exploitation proper is forced, unpaid, sur-
arrangements, programmes and policies. In fact, any
plus labour, the product of which is not under the
moral and social theory that utilises a recognisably
control of the direct producers. This brings in the
Marxist set of empirical, social-scientific theses and
crucial element missing from simple exploitation and
supports a recognisably Marxist set of normative
I would say it is prima facie wrong. But it may not
political positions qualifies as a Marxist moral and
always be wrong. Imagine that the apologists for
social theory.
42
capitalism were correct in arguing that capitalism
However, since my 1990 book was published right
was necessary to promote the undoubted moral goods
at the time of the so-called `fall of communism' in the
of meeting people's basic needs, preserving their
Eastern Bloc ± causing even some who thought it
liberties and allowing for democracy. In this in-
succeeded in its stated goal of creating an adequate
stance, the moral harm suffered by exploited labour
(or, at least, more sophisticated) Marxist moral and
is outweighed by the moral benefits that only capit-
social theory to call it an excellent exemplar of
alism brings. So at the very least there must be more
Hegel's famous quip about the Owl of Minerva flying
to the morality of justice than the category of ex-
only at the end of the day ± I find myself, upon
ploitation if such judgements are to be made. This
occasion, having to defend the relevance of a the-
fuller morality would therefore allow us to identify
oretical project that still:
instances of all-things-considered unjustified exploitation, which is `exploitation proper' that is not justi-
1. takes a minimal set of Marxist empirical as-
fied by its promotion of some other weighty moral
sumptions ± in particular about the nature of
concern. (Contra the capitalist apology, my Marxist
capitalist society ± as plausible and relevant
theory naturally claims that, with socialism a real
(even though it is based on a slimmed-down
125
RODNEY G. PEFFER
Marxism which jettisons some of its orthodox
linist and post-Stalinist claims about how far
baggage);
Soviet-style communist regimes had actually
2. argues for a kind of socialism, albeit a demo-
progressed towards socialism and communism
cratic, self-managing form of socialism based
were complete travesties and misrepresenta-
on a regulated market economy rather than a
tions of Marxist theory and should not be
command
economy,
43
which, within
allowed to distort our understanding of what
well-
the theory sanctions in practice.
developed societies, would be committed to
4. The struggle to establish and preserve social-
protecting civil liberties as much as any bour-
ism in various countries may be somewhat
geois capitalist democracy; 3. defends socialist regimes and socialist revolu-
more likely to succeed in light of the theore-
tions in the developing world as the only way
tical work and institutional changes advocat-
to overcome the absolute poverty and extreme
ing and implementing market socialism as
subservience characteristic of such societies,
opposed
and forcibly confronts us with the possibility
(which, whatever its role in industrialising
that `parliamentary' politics may not be en-
the former Soviet Union and helping to defeat
ough even in developed nations to overcome
fascism in The Second World War ± for which
capitalist resistance to the requirements of
the world owes the former Soviet Union an
justice.
eternal debt of gratitude ± simply does not
to
command
economy
socialism
seem to be capable of adequately functioning in consumer-oriented, modern, mass socie-
Thus, I want to comment very briefly on the con-
ties).
tinued relevance of at least some components of Marxist empirical theory as well as on the continued
5. Even the dissolution of the Soviet Union and
relevance of some kind of socialism as a worthy goal
the `fall of communism' in the Eastern Bloc
or ideal.
44
does not necessarily herald the end of attempts
My response to the charge that Marxist
to establish post-capitalist, or nascent socialist,
 is as follows. theory is now passe
societies or to preserve them where they still 1. So many of Marx's views have passed more
exist (such as in Cuba and China), especially
widely into the social sciences and our modern
in light of the fact that under the hegemonic
world-views that perhaps we tend no longer to
domination of international capitalism, the
appreciate the true significance and lasting
plight of the world's poor ± as well as the
legacy of his thought and work.
world's natural environment ± has continued to
2. As shown by continuing sophisticated developments of certain components of
worsen,
with
world
capitalism
showing
neither the ability nor the inclination to solve
Marx's
these problems.
economic, sociological and political theories by the Analytical Marxist tradition and others, it is only certain orthodox and dogmatic inter-
Of all these claims, it is most immediately important
pretations
to substantiate the first one and I shall do so by
of
Marxism
that
have
become
stating the minimal set of Marxist empirical assump-
otiose, not Marxist theory in general. 3. By Marx's own definition, no society on this
tions which, when combined with my modified
planet has ever become even a fully socialist
Rawlsian theory of justice, yield the appropriate
society ± that is, one which has fulfilled all of
Marxist political conclusion:
the requirements of Marx's so-called first stage of communism, which include full democratic
1. As a result of the logic of the maximisation of
rights ± let alone a full-fledged communist
profit, all capitalist societies ± developed or
society (in which, ex hypothesi, there would
developing ± exhibit and will continue to
be no political state as well as no social classes
exhibit certain economic and social problems
and no significant social conflict). Thus, Sta-
(inflation, depression, recession, unemploy-
126
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
arms race.
ment, poverty, failure to regulate environmental pollution sufficiently, and so on) that
8. The bureaucracies of such post-capitalist so-
can be solved only by the institution of a
cieties genuinely want to reduce or eliminate
regulated, partially planned (but not neces-
arms expenditures in order better to satisfy
sarily command) socialist economy.
the consumer appetites of their own populations.
2. Even the mixed, welfare-state capitalist societies of the advanced, industrialised nations
9. Without the economic, diplomatic, and mili-
in the West exhibit severe social inequalities
tary pressure of the western capitalist powers
and ± if sufficiently threatened by mass work-
such
ing-class movements for social equality ± will
achieve
almost undoubtedly exhibit severe repression.
either evolutionary or revolutionary means).
(The possibly irreversible decline of the Key-
10. Socialist transformations can occur in the
post-capitalist significant
societies
may
democratisation
industrialised
countries
of
well (by
nesian welfare state is evidence of how capi-
advanced
talist societies will inevitably `resolve' the
West, and such transformations can lead to
the
tensions between social justice and the logic
democratic forms of socialism; thus a world-
of capital in favour of the latter.)
wide federation of democratic, self-managing, socialist societies is a genuine historical pos-
3. The world capitalist system causes in the
sibility.
Third World both extreme inequality and
45
suffering, on the one hand, and (often) extremely repressive regimes, on the other.
Although these theses were put forward just before
4. So long as it is dominant on an international
the fall of the Soviet Union, I don't think that this
scale, the capitalist system will not allow the
development or any since then has decisively falsi-
massive transfers of capital, technology and
fied any of them. The only one put into question at
knowledge
Third
all would seem to be the ninth thesis since, although
World's major social and economic problems.
significant democratisation has occurred in most of
5. Such conditions in the Third World make for
the former so-called communist countries, this has
perpetual social instability since those who
been conjoined with a movement ± by no means
are severely oppressed and/or deprived will
complete as of yet and certainly not completely
organise and, if necessary, fight to better their
successful ± toward capitalism. On the other hand,
condition.
it will be observed that the theses concerning the
6. The
necessary
predictable
to
response
solve
from
the
the
most
lack of ability of capitalism to solve the world's socio-
powerful nations at the capitalist `centre'
economic problems have tended to be strengthened
(primarily the United States now and for
rather than falsified, not least in many of the former
the foreseeable future) is first to install and/
so-called communist countries of the defunct Eastern
or aid those Third World regimes or military
Bloc, where the movement towards capitalism has
cliques that can best suppress these mass
resulted in substantial increases in unemployment,
movements for radical social change and,
poverty, social inequality, homelessness and lack of
second, if that strategy fails, to intervene
adequate health care accompanied by skyrocketing
either directly with its own military forces
corruption, crime and gangsterism. Moreover, the
or indirectly through proxy armies and `low-
theses concerning the potential ability of Third
intensity warfare'.
World socialist (or at least post-capitalist) societies
7. However else we may characterise contem-
to solve their basic social problems have also, I think,
porary post-capitalist societies such as Cuba,
continued to be borne out, even though under
it seems clear that they are not the primary
contemporary world circumstances, post-capitalist
cause of the many indigenous revolutionary
societies such as Cuba and China have had to resort
movements in the Third World and do not
to market mechanisms and even foreign capital
bear the primary responsibility for the nuclear
investment, usually in jointly owned enterprises.
127
RODNEY G. PEFFER
(But this, of course, is no mark against these socie-
political philosophy within this general tendency
ties, so far as I'm concerned, since I support market
are part of the Analytical Marxist tradition that
socialism to begin with.) And it is also arguable that
has developed over the past twenty years or so. As
such societies would be able to do even better
such, they have no problem operating within the
economically if the powerful capitalist nations ±
general analytic-philosophical paradigm that empha-
especially the US ± were not constantly attempting
sises conceptual clarity and logical rigour or within
to undermine them.
the general framework of liberal egalitarian theory
Note that this set of empirical assumptions does
developed by Rawls. In fact, Analytical Marxists are
not include dialectical materialism, orthodox or even
an integral part of the current discussions specifically
reconstructed versions of historical materialism, or
involving Rawls's theory and similar theories of
such lower-level empirical theses as the labour theory
social justice. There is little (if anything) to distin-
of value and the `collapse' theory of capitalism. This
guish them from the non-socialist liberal-egalitarians
is not to say that some of these theories ± at least in
who participate in these debates, save their greater
their more sophisticated forms ± are not plausible or
commitments to certain parts of Marxist empirical,
arguably true. But it is to claim that the truth of these
social-scientific theory and thus to the idea that
components of Marxist theory is not necessary in
morally defensible forms of socialism are genuine
order for the basic normative political positions to be
historical possibilities which should be advocated
justified. Most emphatically, this set of empirical
or at least discussed as genuine options. It should
theses does not entail the view that socialism and/
be stressed, of course, that these theorists are all
or communism are historically inevitable, or that
proponents of political democracy and civil liberties
genuine,
be
(which they believe can thrive in socialist societies
achieved within one or a few countries (in isolation
under favourable circumstances) and, thus, critics of
from the rest of the world). Nor does it imply that
the kind of Stalinist political organisation that so ill-
Marx's higher state of communism is historically
served the socialist cause. In addition, most are
possible (as opposed to a utopian impossibility that
advocates (if not always without reservation) of
should not even be seriously considered when doing
market socialism and opponents of command-econ-
social and political theory).
omy socialism.
full-fledged
socialist
societies
can
I recognise, of course, the prima facie oddity of
So let me assert again that what divides contem-
conjoining these theses with Rawlsian moral and
porary egalitarian liberals such as Rawls from liberal-
political theory. Yet that I should develop a theory
socialist egalitarians such as myself is not moral
which attempts to synthesise Rawls's theory of justice
theory but differences in empirical beliefs and prac-
and the salvageable components of the Marxist
tical political convictions. It would be difficult to
tradition should not, in fact, seem all that strange
isolate any normative moral thesis that was univer-
to anyone familiar with moral, social and political
sally agreed upon by those in one category and
philosophy over the past thirty years or so. From the
universally denied by those in the other. The first
last third of the twentieth century this realm's domi-
category is thus composed of theorists who don't
nant tendency in English-speaking societies, Scan-
explicitly advocate socialism, but who could admit
dinavia and the Netherlands has been composed of
that a democratic-liberal form of socialism would be
liberal-egalitarian
egalitarian
justified if certain empirical, social-scientific theses
theorists who, for the most part, take Rawls's theory
that Marxists put forward about capitalism and so-
or similar theories of social justice to be basically
cialism were true. This category includes not only
correct. Most of these theorists also respect much of
Rawls but such figures as Ronald Dworkin, T. M.
what Marx said and much of what he was trying to
Scanlon, Norman Daniels, Thomas Nagel, Amartya
accomplish and they accept some, although certainly
Sen, Martha Nussbaum, Brian Barry, Amy Gut-
not all, of Marxist empirical theory as true.
mann, Bruce Ackerman, Jeremy Waldron, Henry
and
liberal-socialist
Moreover, most contemporary Marxist theorists
Shue, Philippe Van Parijs, Samuel Scheffler and
involved in current debates in moral, social and
Susan Moller Okin. The second category ± the
128
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
liberal-socialist egalitarians ± includes such figures as:
enterprises (from seed capital provided by large
G. A. Cohen, John Roemer, Jon Elster (at least until
socialist enterprises or the banks) and then sell them
recently), Kai Nielsen, Michael Walzer, David Mill-
off to the public sector after they reached a certain
er, William McBride, Roger Gottlieb, Jeffrey Reim-
level of productivity. But, as in Rawls's property-
an, David Schweickart, Nancy Holmstrom, Andrew
owning democracy, no one would be able to pass on
Levine, Alex Callinicos, Norman Geras, Mark Evans
significant levels of wealth to anyone else, although
and me.
46
There is also a category of philosophers
Roemer suggests they might be able to donate all or
within this tradition who speak more sympatheti-
much of their wealth to their choice of socially
cally than the liberal-egalitarians of certain aspects of
approved charitable or philanthropic causes.
Marxism and/or socialism, but don't explicitly or at
other important view worthy of further attention is
least very strongly advocate socialism, so it is difficult
represented by Phillipe Van Parijs, who, even though
to decide in which category they should be classified.
a close associate of the Analytical Marxists, actually
This would include, I think, Robert Paul Wolff,
advocates an extremely egalitarian version of social-
Joshua Cohen, Allen E. Buchanan, Thomas Pogge,
democratic, welfare-state capitalism.
48
An-
49
Richard Arneson, Will Kymlicka and Sharon Lloyd.
But despite these `second-stage' disagreements, I
(Hence my categories are useful terms of reference to
think it justified to propose that the most plausible
guide us in the debate, but not strict and exhaustive
moral, social and political philosophy/theory must lie
classifications.)
somewhere within the general confines that I think
Here, we should recognise the complication that
Rawlsian principles adequately map ± and it is, in
to rely simply on the categories of capitalism and
general form, liberal-egalitarian in moral theory and
socialism may not do justice ± so to speak ± to the
Marxist in political theory and action. What motivates
richness and complexity of the institutional arrange-
my Marxist convictions above all is this final claim: if
ments suggested by these two groups of theorists
we are genuinely concerned about justice, then we
when they propose how their recommended policies
should be firstly and profoundly concerned about the
might best be implemented. For example, Rawls
desperate plight of the vast majority of people in the
suggests that his theory of justice could be best
developing world in particular. And I think that
implemented in what he calls a `property-owning
contemporary liberal debate should increasingly focus
democracy', in which most large-scale productive
upon the liberal-egalitarians upon whom, if they ac-
enterprises would not be socially owned ± hence,
knowledge the huge gap between the reality of global
it is not a form of socialism ± but in which all citizens
injustice and their own standards of justice, it should be
would somehow own some productive property (pre-
incumbent to argue against what I take to be the fact
sumably in terms of stocks and/or bonds), and in
that such injustice can be fully rectified only by anti-
which significant wealth could be accumulated by
capitalist revolutions, and genuinely socialist property
one within one's own lifetime but which could not
relations and social policies, together with genuinely
be passed on to the next generation ± or anyone else,
fair relations between the developed and developing
for that matter ± due to strenuous inheritance and
worlds. Arguably, this may only occur with the trans-
gift taxes.
47
Somewhat similarly, in John Roemer's
formation of the major industrial societies of the North
model of market socialism room would be made in
into socialist societies ± a goal that the Marxist em-
the economy for entrepreneurs to make virtually
pirical theses would also indicate is necessary for the
unlimited amounts of money within their lifetimes
achievement of justice within them as well.
50
if they could organise a series of successful economic
Notes
1. Peffer (1990), p. 3.
3. Ibid, pp. 419±20.
2. See Peffer (1990), especially chapter 10, for substan-
4. Rawls (1996), pp. 7±8 n. 7, and Rawls (1999), pp.
tiation of these modifications.
558±9, Peffer (1994).
129
RODNEY G. PEFFER
Rawlsian theories in general ± including mine ± are
5. See Peffer (1994), pp. 261±2 for more on the defini-
relevant to the relations between the developed and
tion of `socialism'.
the developing world and thus provide at least a
6. Peffer (1990), pp. 418±20; Peffer (1994), pp. 264±5.
starting point to a case for international justice.
7. See Walzer (1983).
15. See Rawls (1972), pp. 270±4, 280±2.
8. See Rawls (1972), pp. 195±201 for discussion of the four-stage decision-making sequence. Of course, these
16. For philosophical perspectives on these issues see
restrictions upon the domain of Rawlsian justice do
Pateman (1970), Cohen and Rogers (1983), Green (1985), Cunningham (1987).
not deny that people's conduct even within private institutions and situations is still subject to criminal
17. Rawls (1972), pp. 72±108.
and civil law.
18. See Holmstrom (1994). 19. See, for example, Sher (1975).
9. These terms are coined by Dworkin (1981a), p. 311. See also G. A. Cohen (1989) and his `Equality of
20. See Peffer (1990), pp. 396±403.
What? On Welfare, Goods and Capabilities', in Nuss-
21. Rawls (1972), p. 83.
baum and Sen (eds) (1993), pp. 9±29, and Kymlicka
22. See Rawls (1972), pp. 204±5, 440±6; Peffer (1990), chapter 9; and Peffer (1994).
(1990), pp. 75±85.
23. Rawls (1972), pp. 101, 105.
10. Although this is far from being uncontroversial, I believe that a strong case can be made for the view
24. Cohen (1986), p. 79. His concern here is, in fact,
that, in the developing world, only certain socialist
primarily with the `right-wing liberal' or libertarian view espoused in Nozick (1974).
countries (such as Cuba and China) as well as the Indian province of Kerala (which has had a socialist
25. One might want to think or hope that genuinely
government since shortly after the Second World
`fraternal' (socialistic) individuals would choose to
War) have generally succeeded in fulfilling their
use their talents in whatever maximally socially ben-
populations' subsistence rights. It seems clear to me
eficial way they could. But it would surely be stretch-
that if one agrees that the empirical evidence shows
ing credibility to think that every individual in a
the only way for developing societies to ensure that
socialist society would always freely surrender all their
people's subsistence rights are met is to institute
talents to whatever task `society' allocated them.
socialism and if the empirical evidence shows ± as I
26. Cohen (1986), p. 79. He recognises the oddity of this
believe it does after having tracked Amnesty Inter-
thought, produced by the claim that liberals were
national reports for the past twenty years or so ± that
defined by acceptance of a full-blown principle of
under normal circumstances socialist regimes in the
self-ownership, and retracts his characterisation in Cohen (1995), p. 116 n. 1.
developing world generally do a better job of protecting their people's security rights than capitalist Third
27. Schweickart (1993), p. 17.
World countries, then one should seek to support
28. Even within a just society it would be dubious to
and promote such socialist regimes and movements
assume that there will be a watertight correlation
as a first duty of social justice, rather than attempting
between people's natural talents and abilities and their
to undermine and destroy them as the government of
ability to garner greater income and wealth under
the United States has so often been guilty of and
`unregulated' social and economic conditions. This
which, I'm ashamed to say, it is continuing to do with
is because, even if all children were to be guaranteed
respect to socialist Cuba.
equal access to high-quality education, quirks of their
11. See Rawls (1972), pp. 150±2.
personalities and/or accidents of family circumstances
12. Rawls (1999), p. 537.
(such as whether their parents or other family mem-
13. See Rawls (1972), pp. 114±18.
bers or close associates made them feel loved and
14. My continuing disappointment with Rawls's attitude
secure), and the operation of blind chance in general,
to global justice is due to the fact that in `The Law of
will affect whether or not particular individuals are
People', which he had actually intended to be an
successful. This is not to say that in presently existing
appendix to Political Liberalism, he has, for reasons I
societies there is no discernible correlation between
still do not understand, continued to refuse to apply
natural talents/abilities and success, nor to deny that
his difference principle internationally. Although he
the correlation should and could be made much higher
does call for `standards of fairness for trade and other
in a genuinely just society. It is only to say that the
co-operative arrangements' and for `certain provisions
assumption that `the talented' in even a perfectly just
for mutual assistance between peoples in times of
society will be able to parlay their talents into success
famine and drought' (Rawls, 1999, p. 541) there is
(however they come to define it) is, to some extent, unjustified.
the question as to why this should only apply to `reasonably developed liberal societies' and also why
29. See Cohen (1996).
the difference principle itself shouldn't be so applied.
30. For a defence of the opposite position, however, see Van Parijs (1991).
But, in any case, it seems clear that Rawls's theory and
130
RAWLSIAN THEORY AND CONTEMPORARY MARXISM
31. Rawls (1990), p. 42. I would like to thank John Rawls
operating on the ultimately self-refuting notion that
for giving me permission to quote from this typescript
there is no such thing as rationality, or with those who
in my work.
merely claim that Marxist theory is irrelevant and/or
32. See Arneson (1989). Dworkin (1981a) and (1981b)
illegitimate because it is (supposedly) based on grand
also discusses many of the ideas within these princi-
historical meta narratives, the claim that all aspects of
ples.
Marxism and all hope for socialism must be abandoned
33. See Cohen (1989).
just doesn't hold water. To say that Marxism and
34. Rawls (1972), pp. 87±8.
socialism are now irrelevant theoretical or practical
35. Rawls (1990), p. 42.
political traditions is absurd given the quantity and
36. Arneson (1988), p. 89.
quality of the theorising that they still inspire, which is
37. See Sen (1984), chapter 13, (1985),(1992), and
due to the insights they offer into humanity's most
`Capabilities and Well-Being' in Nussbaum and Sen
urgent political challenges. Given the popularity and
(eds) (1993), pp. 30±53; for commentary on Sen, see
influence of postmodernism within certain circles, it is vital to insist upon these points.
Crocker (1992).
45. Peffer (1990), pp. 458±9. In fact, this set of assumptions
38. Cohen (1994), p. 119.
is so minimal that, if they can indeed be adopted by non-
39. See Peffer (1990), pp. 137±65 for my analysis of this
Marxists/socialists, some would say that they are not
debate. 40. Ibid., pp. 142±6. The fact that Marx often called this
Marxist at all. But because they originate within the
an example of `theft' by capitalists is strong evidence
Marxist tradition and continue to animate it, I see no
that ± perhaps despite himself ± he did not think
good reason to withdraw the label from them ± parti-
morality could only ever be an ideological phenom-
cularly when, as in my case, they are used to energise a
enon relative to and supportive of a specific mode of
particular political position opposed to capitalism for which Marxism has long held the banner.
production, a `prop' which would become increasingly redundant in post-capitalist societies.
46. Notice that this list of socialist theorists (who are,
41. This section follows ibid., pp. 146±7.
broadly speaking, within the analytic-linguistic tradi-
42. Peffer (1990), pp. 433±4.
tion of philosophy) by no means exhausts the category
43. The notion of `regulated' market economy as an
of socialist or quasi-socialist theorists who participate
antonym for `capitalist economy' is pivotal here, but
in contemporary debates since it doesn't mention: the
would obviously need to be substantiated in a fuller
Yugoslav Praxis school of Marxian philosophers and
account, not least because no capitalist economy is
similar socialist humanists (such as Svetozar Stojono-
entirely unregulated and so cannot accurately be
Â, Mihaelo Markovic Â, Gajo Petrovic Â); critical thevic
defined as being in opposition to regulation. In gen-
orists (such as Ju È rgen Habermas, Karl-Otto Apel,
eral, what will distinguish the market socialist econ-
Albrecht Wellmer, Thomas McCarthy, Richard Bern-
omy in this regard is the degree of regulation and, most
stein, Nancy Fraser, Doug Kellner and Stephen Best);
signficantly, the ends to which it is put.
Hegelian Marxists (such as Shlomo Avineri and Ber-
44. Here, we should also confront the claim by various
tell Ollman); liberation philosophers (such as Enrique
postmodernists that it is no longer possible to take
Dussel and Horacio Cerruti); Cuban political philo-
Marxism to be a serious theoretical tradition or soci-
sophers (such as Thalia Fung, Olga Fernandez, and
alism to be a legitimate historical goal because they are
Pablo Guadarrama); other socialist philosophers from
based on so-called grand historical meta narratives.
the developing world (such as Francisco Miro Ques-
But the brief outline of the lower-level empirical
ada, Adolfo Sanchez Vazquez and Pablo Gonzalez
claims still taken seriously by the Analytical Marxists
Casanova); socialist feminists (such as Alison Jaggar,
and others given in this section should suffice to show
Ann Ferguson, Heidi Hartmann and Nancy Hart-
how utterly bogus this claim is. For the parts of Marx's
sock); socialist theorists who are primarily economists
theory still being utilised have nothing whatever to do
and only secondarily philosophers (such as Alec Nove,
with grand quasi-Hegelian claims about inevitable
Branko Horvat, Jaroslav Vanek, Thomas Weisskopf
movements in history. Indeed, they are quite the
and Robin Hahnel); world-systems theorists (such as
opposite: they are the more concrete empirical claims
 Gunder Frank and Immanuel Wallerstein, Andre
that can be (and are) seriously discussed by social
Samir Amin) or theorists of development ethics (such
scientists, political thinkers and ordinary people inter-
as David Crocker, Denis Goulet and Luis Camacho);
ested in politics everywhere. To think politically we
radical sociological theorists (such as Claus Offe,
cannot avoid making certain assumptions about what
Ernesto Laclau, Alain Touraine); social-democratic
social,
pro-
theorists (such as Michael Harrington, Robert Heilbr-
grammes and policies will best accomplish given goals
oner and Cornell West); or the so-called Marxist
or support and promote certain values. So whether we
amoralist theorists who argued that Marxism is in-
are dealing with those postmodernist thinkers who are
compatible with morality in general or at least with
economic
and
political
institutions,
131
RODNEY G. PEFFER
justice in particular (such as Allen W. Wood, Richard
50. I would like to thank G. A. Cohen and David Miller
Miller, Anthony Skillen and Andrew Collier). This
for comments on a previous version of this paper given
last view is one that I spend over 100 pages critiquing
at Oxford University as well as Neil Harding for
and, I believe, decisively refuting in Peffer (1990).
comments on a version of it given at the University
47. See Krouse and McPherson (1988); Peffer (1994).
of Wales Swansea. I would especially like to thank
48. See Roemer (1994).
Mark Evans for his incisive comments and his editorial
49. Van Parijs (1992).
help and suggestions.
132
Part Four PROBLEMS OF LIBERAL JUSTIFICATION
This page intentionally left blank
10
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR Peter Lassman
The wars of this century with their extreme violence
One consequence is that this leads to what we
and increasing destructiveness, culminating in the
might call the `Weimar problem';
manic evil of the Holocaust, raise in an acute way the
3. that John Rawls's Political Liberalism, the most
question whether political relations must be gov-
systematic attempt to construct a liberal re-
erned by power and coercion alone. If a reasonably
sponse, fails in its attempt to provide a solution
just society that subordinates power to its aims is not
to
possible and people are largely amoral, if not incur-
ought instead to present itself in terms of
ably cynical and self-centred, one might ask with
Judith Shklar's idea of `the liberalism of fear'.
Kant whether it is worthwhile for human beings to
This humble, cautious liberalism is probably
live on the earth?
1
the
problem.
Contemporary
liberalism
the best that liberals can hope for in such a pluralistic social world. Fortunately, it is enough to save us from conceding the bleakly
I
negative possibility described in the opening quote.
The argument of this chapter is: 1. that pluralism, in the sense of `the wide di-
This chapter's epigraph, taken from the introduc-
versity and deep conflict among different con-
tion to the second edition of his Political Liberalism,
ceptions of ends prevalent in modern societies
can be read as a statement of the `esoteric doctrine' or
and different patterns of life and the institu-
`inner citadel' at the heart of John Rawls's political
tions that go with them', is the distinctive
philosophy.
problem which modern politics has to face;
2
3
It is what motivates his project and the
centrality of the discussion of Rawls's work in con-
2. that before this topic became of central con-
temporary political philosophy is a reflection of the
cern for current political theory Max Weber
insightful way in which it engages with the problem
had proposed an interpretation of the modern
which all contemporary political philosophies face in
world in terms of value pluralism and `the
light of the conditions of modernity first sketched by
disenchantment of the world' which provides
Max Weber. This claim, of course, appears to pre-
the (usually unacknowledged) foundation for
suppose that we accept Weber's sketch as true. What
most contemporary liberal debate. This ac-
I do think is true is that the picture of the modern
count, however, raises serious problems for
world which Weber painted has been highly influ-
our understanding of modern liberalism, de-
ential even, or especially, among those who deny its
mocracy and the legitimation of political rule.
relevance or who fail to mention it in their work. In
135
PETER LASSMAN
other words, it haunts much contemporary political
always, however, remain and limit the extent of
thinking despite the negative assessment many thin-
possible agreement.'
kers make of it.
4
6
Here, then, I simply want to stand
This limitation may explain why, in his more
by a recent statement made by Habermas: `I feel that
recent work, there are several hints that he is
Max Weber's question regarding the paradoxes of
troubled by the thought that his whole project
rationalisation is still the best key to a philosophi-
cannot possibly succeed, that conflict will always
cally and scientifically informed diagnosis of our
undermine the possibility of agreement. He accepts
time.'
5
We shall shortly see how, despite itself, the
that many will `regard it as obvious' that `a just and
Rawlsian viewpoint is shadowed by the Weberian
well-ordered democratic society is not possible'. But
sketch. Let us begin, though, by seeing how Rawls
this is a conclusion he thinks we must resist. One of
conceptualises his project of political philosophy as
the interesting reasons why Rawls feels that we can
the positive response to Kant's question.
resist this conclusion is bound up with his conception of the nature of political philosophy itself. In some of his remarks on this Rawls is responding to
II
critics such as Michael Walzer who have charged
In the concluding paragraphs of his introduction to
that his theory is too abstract, that it does not deal
the second (paperback) edition of Political Liberalism
with the real problems of contemporary politics, and
Rawls refers to three kinds of conflict in modern
that its philosophical structure displaces `genuine
societies, the confrontation with which is the main
politics' and is therefore entirely at odds with the
preoccupation of his political philosophy. The first
nature of democratic pluralist society.
derives from `citizens' conflicting comprehensive doctrines'
and political conflict are unlikely to find their
and goals by which people structure their lives);
resolution in his kind of abstractive philosophical
the second derives from citizens' `different status,
methodology. But Rawls himself has always expli-
class position, and occupation, or from their ethni-
citly argued the reverse. He states very clearly that in
city, gender, and race'; while the third is a result of
`political philosophy the work of abstraction is set in
what Rawls calls the `burdens of judgement' (the
motion by deep political conflicts.'
inevitable indeterminacies and consequent diver-
political philosophy when our `shared political un-
gent results of rational and reasonable normative
derstandings' break down and `equally when we are
deliberation in free societies). Rawls states that his
torn within ourselves'. Abstraction from that which
theory of political liberalism `mitigates but cannot
divides us is a way of finding grounds for ideas which
eliminate the first kind of conflict, since compre-
might unite us and that is where we find the basis for a
hensive doctrines are, politically speaking, unrec-
principled resolution of conflict.
and
organised
remain
sets
of
beliefs,
The thought here is that the problems of social
values
oncilable
(the
7
inconsistent
with
8
We turn to
one
The emphasis on possible unity shows that Raw-
another'. Nevertheless, Rawls argues that the prin-
lsian political philosophy is not in the business of
ciples of political liberalism, `the principles of justice
uncovering actual conflict-resolving consensus upon
of a reasonably just constitutional regime', are cap-
principles. Operating in the realm of the possible
able of reconciling the second kind of conflict.
obviously includes acknowledging the possibility of
Once we accept the principles of justice, preferably
failure, hence Rawls's disquiet. Yet we ought not to
those of his own theory, this kind of conflict `need
accept the sceptical argument against the possibility
no longer arise, or arise so forcefully'. It appears,
of a conflict-resolving (or at least a conflict-mana-
then, to be this kind of conflict whose non-resolu-
ging) and well-ordered liberal-democratic society, in
tion would plunge us into the amoral world of `pure'
Rawls's view, without first being clear about what the
power described in the opening quote. And it is the
consequences would be `for our view of the political
confidence that it can be transcended which stokes
world, and even the world as a whole.'
Rawls's optimism. Unfortunately though, he thinks
conception of the nature of political philosophy
conflicts `arising from the burdens of judgement
and, by implication, of the responsibility of the
136
9
Rawls's
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
political philosopher means that we must be aware
crucially impacts upon how we might develop pos-
that the answer we give to general and abstract
sibilities for the avoidance of the Weimar problem.
questions does have a bearing upon our `background thoughts and attitudes about the world as a whole.'
III
Thus, if we are convinced on abstract philosophical grounds that a just and stable democratic society is
The variety of ways in which liberal theorists have
not possible then this will have a great impact upon
responded to this problem is striking, indicating the
`the underlying attitudes of the public culture and
variety within the liberal tradition. There are those,
the conduct of politics.' It is at this point that Rawls
such as Rawls, Larmore, Nozick and Hayek, who
revealingly points to the case of the Weimar Repub-
have asserted the reality of moral pluralism while
lic and to one of its most outspoken critics, Carl
arguing, at the same time, for the possibility of a
Schmitt.
ranking of values so that one value, liberty, can take
Rawls presents the Weimar Republic as offering us
precedence. Others, such as Williams, Berlin and
a particularly dramatic example of exactly what he
Hampshire, have stressed the ineliminable and often
fears. One of the reasons for the fall of the Weimar
tragic character of value conflicts. For example,
Republic and its replacement by Nazi dictatorship
Hampshire has argued the case for a strong thesis
was that both the traditional elites and a large
that, on the basis of an analogy between moralities
section of the intellectuals were unwilling to support
and natural languages, `nature has so designed us
it on the grounds that they could no longer believe
that, taking humanity as a whole and the evidences
that any form of democratic and liberal society was
of history, we tend to have conflicting and divergent
possible. Given what we now know of the terrible
moralities imbedded in divergent ways of life, each
consequences
the product of specific historical memories and local
of
this
particular
political
failure,
Rawls urges that we
conditions.'
11
For him
must start with the assumption that a reasonably
the diversity in conceptions of the good is an
just political society is possible, and for it to be
irreducible diversity, not only because no suffi-
possible, human beings must have a moral nature,
cient reasons have been given, and could ever be
not of course a perfect such nature, yet one that
given, for taking one end, such as the general
can understand, act on, and be sufficiently moved
happiness or the exercise of reason, as the single
by a reasonable political conception of right and
supreme end; but also because the capacity to
justice to support a society guided by its ideals and
develop idiosyncrasies of style and of imagination,
principles.
10
and to form specific conceptions of the good, is the salient and peculiar capacity of human beings among other animals.
The vital moral and political need to believe in
12
the possibility of justice, however, should not lead theorists to a wilful blindness over the true nature of
However, this second group's acceptance of the
the pluralism which divides societies and puts the
reality (as they see it) of such conflicts has created
question of justice on the political agenda. Thus the
problems for the coherence and tenability of their
idea of moral and value pluralism has increasingly
own defence of the value of liberalism. If the ex-
become a central concern for political theorists,
istence of plural and conflicting values is accepted as
especially liberal theorists, working in both what
an unavoidable reality then it follows that the claims
can loosely be called the Anglo-American and Con-
made for any particular political theory must be at
tinental traditions of political thought. Pluralism is
best both severely limited and local in their applica-
therefore widely seen as a defining characteristic of
tion. But the first group of theorists, in accepting that
modernity and as the most significant challenge to
we are in some way faced with a pluralism of funda-
political philosophy's search for conflict-resolving
mental and conflicting values, are confronted by the
agreements. How it is to be conceptualised, then,
problem of explaining how their own theory's sup-
137
PETER LASSMAN
port for liberal principles is able to escape from
free and equal citizens profoundly divided by rea-
insoluble conflicts of value.
sonable though incompatible religious, philosophi-
From Rawls's earliest work it is possible to observe
cal, and moral doctrines?'
15
a concern with how we might get out of this parti-
There is some disagreement among advocates of
cular bind. In his first published paper `Outline of a
pluralism concerning its historical status. Hampshire,
Decision Procedure for Ethics' he asked if there
as we might ascertain from his quotation above, sees
existed
pluralism as not being either a peculiarly modern or democratic phenomenon or an unexplained general
a reasonable decision procedure which is suffi-
fact of human existence. Moral pluralism and moral
ciently strong, at least in some cases, to determine
conflict are, for him, an essential product of the
the manner in which competing interests could
imaginative powers of human beings in general. But
be adjudicated, and, in instances of conflict, one
the idea that an irreducible plurality of values has
interest
and,
transformed the way people think about how a
further, can the existence of this procedure, as
specifically modern politics should be conducted is
well as its reasonableness, be established by ra-
increasingly influential. Rawls makes this kind of
given
preference
tional methods of inquiry?
over
another;
13
interpretation of our moral history absolutely central for his account of `political liberalism'. He argues that
In his most recent writings Rawls is concerned to
`modern democratic political culture' itself is to be
work out his version of `political liberalism' with the
sharply distinguished from all that preceded it so that
same set of problems in mind. The central problem
its `special nature' accounts for, to a large extent, `the
which he now recognises as forcing him to modify
different problems of political philosophy in the
the account of stability put forward in Part Three of
modern as compared with the ancient world.'
16
his A Theory of Justice is what he terms `the fact of
Rawls cites both Weber and Isaiah Berlin as
reasonable pluralism'. Pluralism is `reasonable', he
offering important and influential accounts of the
says, because it is the outcome that we should expect
idea of the pluralism of values. These thinkers,
of people freely using their powers of moral reasoning
however, provide ways of challenging his own ac-
under liberal-democratic institutions; it is, as we
count of pluralism's nature and hence his ideal
have noted, the product of the burdens of judgement.
solution to the Weimar problem. Let us, then, look
In other words, such is the nature of human value
first at Berlin's ideas.
and value judgements in free societies that we should
Initially, Berlin appears to be equivocal on the
expect such conflict.
question of the historical character of pluralism. In
Crucially, Rawlsian `reasonable pluralism' is not
tracing the roots of the doctrine of pluralism to the
itself supposed to be a claim about the truth of
Cynics and the Sceptics he seems to be saying that
values (for that is something that can be reasonably
there is a perennial quality in the conflict between
contested between monists and pluralists), only
monism and pluralism in western political thought.
about the reasonableness of the disputes that con-
But, in pointing to the importance of Machiavelli as
stitute the fact that there are plural values.
14
It is
the `first person to indicate a conflict of real values',
not officially, then, conceding the truth of the
he also indicates the significance of a peculiarly
Weberian sketch of modernity (for that is just
modern quality to the recognition of pluralism.
one of potentially numerous incompatible world-
According to Berlin it was Machiavelli who was
17
views it is reasonable to affirm). Support for the claim that Rawls inadvertently leans in Weber's
the first to make it clear that the very idea of a
direction has yet to be adduced, but there is already
Christian commonwealth is a contradiction in
an initial, fleeting point of convergence: both wish
terms: one cannot be a Christian and an heroic
to accommodate, not suppress, pluralism. Rawls
Roman citizen at the same time. Christians must
poses the challenge thus: `How is it possible that
remain humble, to be trampled on at times; Ro-
there may exist over time a stable and just society of
mans resist this successfully. This implies an
138
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
irreconcilable dualism. One can choose one life or
all-embracing solution to all human problems
the other, but not both; and there is no over-
which, if there is too much resistance to it, might
arching criterion to determine the right choice;
need force to secure it, only tends to lead to
one chooses as one chooses, neither life can
bloodshed and the increase in human misery.
objectively be called superior to the other.
18
Berlin takes the idea of the pluralism of values to This prompts a significant insight according to
be central for his understanding of both the history of
Rawls, which goes a long way in distinguishing
political thought and of his own liberalism, not in
modern liberal from premodern political thought.
the sense that he has provided a general explanation
This is the claim `there is no social world without loss
for the existence of pluralism, but simply in the
± that is, no social world that does not exclude some
consequent necessity that we be reconciled with
ways of life that realise in special ways certain
the basic fact of life that `values can clash ± that
fundamental values. By virtue of its culture and
is why civilisations are incompatible.'
institutions, any society will prove uncongenial to
ism of values implies the `clash of values'. If the
some ways of life'. These values may be fully objec-
reality of plural and conflicting values is ineliminable
tive,
19
22
The plural-
then it follows that there is no `perfect world in
but the harsh fact of life is that their full range
which all good things can be harmonised in princi23
is too extensive to fit into any one social world; not
ple.'
only are they incompatible with one another,
search for perfection or utopia is both incoherent and
imposing conflicting requirements on institutions,
dangerous.
The implication of this is, for Berlin, that the
but there exists no family of workable institutions
This understanding of the pluralism of values
with sufficient space for them all. That there is no
coheres with Berlin's depiction of the good society.
social world without loss is rooted in the nature of
The good society is to be understood as one in which
values and the world, and much human tragedy
maximum space is allowed for those forms of life
reflects that; a just liberal society may have far more
which can be guided by a principle that competing
space than other social worlds, but still, it can never
values can be allowed to flourish within the terms of
accommodate all possible ways of life.
20
a shared social space. Berlin thinks that the form of society in which this is most likely to occur typically
For Berlin, as for Rawls, the reality of the pluralism
happens to be governed by the principles of liberal-
of values is tied to the possibility of political philo-
ism. The virtue of a liberal society resides in the fact
sophy itself. He argues that if
that, while the impossibility of realising all relevant values remains an impossibility, it ± more than any
we ask the Kantian question, `In what kind of
other kind of society ± is one which recognises and is
world is political philosophy ± the kind of dis-
strengthened by the pluralism of values. It is one of
cussion and argument in which it consists ± in
the marks of a liberal society that it tolerates or even
principle possible? the answer must be `Only in a
encourages value pluralism. It does not attempt to
world where ends collide.'
21
reduce the pluralism of values in the interests of any one particular value or set of values supported by the authority of the state.
But the Berlinian thesis of pluralism (the now much-discussed `inner fortress' of his thought) warns
Clearly, for Berlin, the recognition of the reality of
political philosophy that `the pursuit of a single,
the pluralism of values (his `objective pluralism') is
final, universal solution to human problems' is a
itself to understand a truth about the nature of
fundamental and dangerous error. It is essential to
values. This is the main point of departure from
recognise that there are
Rawls, who wants his political philosophy to abstain from such truth-statements about what he regards as
many ideals worth pursuing, some of them are
reasonably contested metaphysical and meta-ethical
incompatible with one another, but the idea of an
claims. Plainly, too, Berlin takes our awareness of the
139
PETER LASSMAN
existence of plural and competing values as being
be committed to the primacy of at least the value of
itself a good. He seems to take this understanding as
liberty. In other words,
itself constituting an argument for liberalism because a liberal society will express this understanding more than any other.
24
the mere fact that values are `plural' . . . tells us
As pluralism implies that `since it is
nothing about which of the vast range of values
possible that no final answers can be given to moral
known to us from human experience are the
and political questions, or indeed any questions
values we ought to choose for ourselves and
about value' then
our social institutions. Pluralism tells us that we must choose but not what to choose.
29
room must be made for a life in which some values may turn out to be incompatible, so that if
Furthermore, it is notable that Berlin (despite his
destructive conflict is to be avoided compromises
concern with the significance of Romantic and
have to be effected and a minimum degree of
Counter-Enlightenment thinkers) does not discuss
toleration, however reluctant, becomes indispen-
those
sable.
25
twentieth-century
theorists,
such
as
Carl
Schmitt, who having taken the argument for pluralism seriously saw it as the first step in the destruction
This suggests that those societies which respect
of liberalism as a substantive normative standpoint.
this truth are preferable to those which do not.
This may be explained by the fact that Berlin's
Furthermore, there seems to be an assumption here
pluralism ultimately stops short of being absolutely
that not all values possess an equal survival value
`total' in the sense that, after all he says, he still
within a society which allows maximum space for
balances it with a belief in a universal human nature.
value pluralism (those forms of life which are less
His conception of it is thin enough to underdeter-
tolerant of pluralism are perhaps more likely to be
mine any one substantive moral doctrine but it is still
`squeezed out', yet this may be cause for less regret
capable of yielding the basic principles of a universal
than if other forms of life were to wither).
26
`minimum morality'.
In this
30
This theoretically prevents
sense value pluralism itself cannot pretend to be
the concession of a total incommensurability of
neutral with regard to outcomes even if its philoso-
values and the relativising impossibility of critique
phical outlook and political intent is neutral with
levelled at any moral schema. Such a morality could
regard to the initial support, or lack of it, given to
further justify a liberal social order, and values/forms
ways of life supported by different values.
of life sympathetic to its principles, as an explanation
Nevertheless, the connection between liberalism
of the liberal bias in Berlin's view. But because this
and pluralism is not as cast-iron as one might expect.
morality does not constitute liberalism in its entirety,
Berlin insists that pluralism and liberalism are `not
it is in principle compatible with other forms of
the same or even overlapping concepts. There are
social order. The connection between liberalism
liberal theories which are not pluralistic.' While
and pluralism remains historically contingent; plur-
defending the value of both he is clear that there
alists need not be liberals.
31
is no logical connection between them. The con-
It is, of course, a profoundly contentious point as to
nection between pluralism and liberalism is one of
exactly how such a `minimum morality' position can
`elective affinity',
27
be defended from the kind of objective-pluralist per-
grounded as much as anything in 28
But it could be argued that
spective with which Berlin confronts us. An indica-
not only is there no logical connection between
tion of the difficulty is clearly signalled when he
liberalism and pluralism but that they are actually
equates the universal minimum-moral outlook with
incompatible. If pluralism is taken to mean that there
that of the less-than-global `western world'; as Perry
is no one particular value or set of values which,
Anderson says, `the universal shrinks with every step
when in conflict with other values, can always claim
back to the local.'
our allegiance then it must be incompatible with
that upon which the possibility of `justice' ± under-
liberalism. As a distinctive doctrine, the latter must
stood loosely as the peaceful, principled resolution of
historical experience.
32
140
If this outlook is supposed to be
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
conflict ± is to rest, perhaps it is one that political
more than just the expression of our preferences,
philosophy has to construct rather than just assume is
but who refuse to believe that it has its home in a
ready to hand. Here, then, is Rawls's main difference
harmonious cosmos (as Aristotle thought) or in
from Berlin and his distinctive characterisation of the
God's plan.
fact of pluralism is the key to the hope that the Rawlsian project will not founder on the same kind
For Larmore, liberalism too is very much a product of
of justificatory paradox that underpins Berlin's at-
this intellectual milieu. It has `distinguished itself
tempt to stand for a universal minimum morality.
from earlier political philosophies by its refusal, ever
At this point we need to ensure that we keep clear
more pronounced, to base the principles of associa-
the distinction between (1) pluralism as a doctrine
tion upon a vision of God's plan or of an ordered
about the nature of value (Berlin's position) and (2)
cosmos.'
the phenomenon of deep disagreement about the
of liberalism and pluralism have seemed so closely
nature of the good (Rawls's position, based upon `the
entwined. And even though the Rawls/Larmore
burdens of judgement'). This is a move urged by
project wants to distinguish the former, in its epis-
Larmore, who originally coined the term `political
temically abstinent `political' guise, from the latter as
liberalism'. The reasoning behind the latter is that
a doctrine about the objective nature of value,
pluralism, understood as a doctrine about the nature
Larmore concedes that both are `distinctively mod-
of the good, is itself a controversial doctrine. If this is
ern in that they have something to do with the
so then pluralism cannot possibly stand as a support
metaphysical-religious
for `political liberalism' which itself attempts to stand
world.'
clear of all controversial philosophical and religious
standpoint on the nature of value.
35
36
It is unsurprising, then, that the doctrines
disenchantment
of
the
And this is itself a particular metaphysical
doctrines in search of the agreement upon principles
The suggestion, then, is that some version of
which it posits as necessary for political resolution of
`doctrinal pluralism' is an idea that shadows moder-
the conflicts of value.
33
The idea that reasonable
nity and hence contemporary liberalism, even when
people will tend to disagree about significant ques-
the latter attempts to distinguish it from the separate
tions is not to be confused with either pluralism or
thesis of pluralism as reasonable disagreement. As we
scepticism. It is, according to Larmore, the fact of
saw with Berlin, it is this idea which makes the
reasonable disagreement rather than the `doctrine of
justification of liberalism so problematic. It is in the light of this suggestion that we can
pluralism' which lies at the heart of modern liberal
illuminate the problem of liberalism and pluralism by
political philosophy.
placing it into the context of Weber's thought.
Nevertheless, Larmore's idea of reasonable disagreement shares with Berlin's concept of pluralism the belief that they are both reflections of a pecu-
IV
liarly modern reality. Despite his criticism of Berlin's failure to distinguish pluralism from the persistence
Weber was probably the first to take seriously as a
of reasonable disagreement he sounds much like
basic feature of modernity the idea of a pluralism of
Berlin in his argument that we are now reversing
conflicting values in a way which has a direct bearing
the belief embedded in our `intellectual tradition'
on politics. Most of the themes concerning the
which `has been to a large and important extent
question
rationalist', that `reason is what brings us together.'
34
of
incommensurability,
disenchantment
and tragic choices which are discussed by Berlin, Larmore,
On this account pluralism is a
Williams,
Hampshire
and
others
were
raised in his work. Although I do not want to claim characteristically modern outlook. It is likely to
that Weber carried out a systematic and satisfactory
appear attractive only against the background of
analysis it is instructive to take a brief look at his
metaphysical
It
discussion of these topics because it starkly reveals
recommends itself to those who continue to
some of the problems and dangers involved. Weber is
believe that value can be objective, something
therefore interesting because his problems remain, in
and religious
disappointment.
141
PETER LASSMAN
my view, to a large extent our problems. Although
There are doubtless numerous ways of rendering
there is some controversy concerning the question of
vivid the idea that Weber somehow haunts con-
whether Weber can be classified as a liberal at all it
temporary liberalism, including political liberalism,
seems to me that he was, at least, `a Liberal of a
and why it is his pluralism ± as opposed perhaps to
strange kind'.
37
Berlin's ± that informs the most disturbing challenges
Weber's problem was that he wanted to defend
to it. But here are a few considerations that can
liberal values and institutions while, at the same
contribute to it. First, Larmore is right that the
time, his general philosophical outlook with its
peculiarly modern phenomenon of disenchantment
acceptance
as
has historically fuelled the politics of liberalism in so
our fate led to a radical scepticism concerning our
far as people have increasingly appreciated that
ability to produce, under modern conditions, a con-
politics in modern, diverse societies cannot rest upon
vincing theoretical justification for them. In other
any one `enchanted' doctrine; to avoid outright
words, in Weber's account we have a defence of
conflict, it must accommodate a plurality of such.
liberal institutions and values without the support of
Second, this concession to the existence of plural
of
disenchantment
and
pluralism
an explicit liberal political philosophy.
38
At the
values has a tendency (albeit not logically) to further
extremes this could be interpreted, for example, as
the subjectivist account of value which the supre-
either an early recognition of postmodern reality, the
mely disenchanted (`scientific') practices of instru-
inevitable contingency of any `defence' available to
mental rationality promote as they burgeon in social
liberalism, as Rorty would argue, or as an example of
life. Third, this renders increasingly irresistible a
the failure of the whole tradition, as Leo Strauss and
frankly Nietzschean view of politics, where subjec-
his followers seem to urge.
tive wills battle it out for power over each other with
Weber's account of the fate of politics in a world of
no grand metaphysical-moral story to be told by
plural and conflicting values is embedded in a `nar-
which to cloak the brute reality of the struggle.
rative of modernity'. According to him we live in an
Fourth (and this is arguably where Weber himself
increasingly secular, rationalised and `disenchanted'
ultimately stumbled), the case for liberalism ± or any
world in which we are confronted with an opposition
other political order ± rests only upon individuals'
between the seemingly unstoppable development of
decisions to support it, with nothing independent to
the `housing for the new serfdom' (the instrumen-
ground or validate them, a form of political existen-
tally rationalising bureaucratisation of social institu-
tialism in other words. And if accelerating disen-
tions and practices) and the need for the individual
chantment is deepening pluralism, the prospects of
to make choices between ultimately irreconcilable
conflict-managing agreements in decisions accord-
ultimate values, `the unending struggle between the
ingly recedes.
gods.'
39
On Rawls's analysis, here is a key point of
The problem with Weber's position looked at
difference between Weber and Berlin. Eschewing
from some liberal points of view is that he was only
any notion of objective pluralism, `Weber's view
able to offer two unacceptable solutions for the
rests on a form of value scepticism and voluntarism;
predicament of the individual under these condi-
political tragedy arises from the conflict of subjective
tions. One is a re-enchantment of the world, which
40
Rather than the
would mean a return to rule by what Rawls would
apparent reification of values through the language
call a fully comprehensive moral and philosophical
of `objectivity' (which also facilitates the notion of a
doctrine. As Anderson stresses, First World War
thin objective morality that we have argued pluralists
nationalism disturbingly seems to function in this
struggle consistently to defend), Weber's outlook
role for Weber.
strips `reality' right back to the bare fact of people's
decisionism propels the individual into a radical
different, clashing subjective opinions and wills.
fatalism; the accident of birth within a particular
Furthermore, the deeper the process of disenchant-
national community is our chance to escape the
ment the more intense the struggle between their
gloom of disenchantment, to embrace the destiny
contending viewpoints becomes.
of the nation as our own. The remaining sphere for
commitments and resolute wills.'
142
41
Here, the arbitrariness of his
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
freedom would be one in which the individual is
with democracy's claim to value and embody the
thrown back on his or her own resources (the
collective will of the people, making `liberal democ-
meagreness of which may encourage individuals to
racy' ultimately oxymoronic and ± particularly when
give up still more of their own `being' to the `nation's
popular will runs against liberal democracy ± doomed
cause').
to implosion.
43
)
The other solution perhaps lacks some of the
It is in the light of this that we can see why, for
ominous portent of the first, but is ultimately no
Rawls, it might seem to be `a great puzzle to me why
more satisfactory. In his later writings on political
political liberalism was not worked out much earlier:
affairs Weber came to argue that in a modern
it seems such a natural way to present the idea of
democratic state the only acceptable response would
liberalism, given the fact of reasonable pluralism in
be a mixture of charismatic rule backed up by a legal
political life.'
order as a form of rule. The problem here is that the
become political in the way in which he proposes
legitimacy of this form of state is based entirely upon
because, under conditions of pluralism, it cannot
its success in being successful. There are `no other
assume that liberal ideas are the non-controversial
criteria for success beyond success itself.'
42
44
For him, liberalism has been forced to
foundation of social and political life.
And if
45
It is, then, a
regimes resting upon such bases are not `successful' ±
direct development from the specifically modern
if, for example, they struggle to cope with social and
form of post-Reformation religious pluralism. `For
political conflict ± they have nothing upon which to
the moderns the good was known in their religion;
fall back to argue that they are nevertheless legit-
with their profound divisions, the essential condi-
imate. (Compare this with a regime whose citizens
tions of a viable and just society were not.'
widely accept its authority as being derived from
distinguishes the modern from the ancient world.
`God'. It, too, may experience functional inefficien-
`What the ancient world did not know was the clash
cies but its lack of success doesn't exhaust its legit-
between salvationist, credal, and expansionist reli-
imating grounds and hence it is likely to be more
gions.' Crucially, this
46
This
stable.) The problems and tensions in Weber's account of the problem of the legitimation of political
introduces into people's conceptions of their good
rule within a plural moral universe lead directly to
a transcendent element not admitting of compro-
the `Weimar problem', the crisis of justification
mise. This element forces either mortal conflict
which liberalism faces as soon as the implications
moderated only by circumstance and exhaustion,
of
or equal liberty of conscience and freedom of
pluralism
become
apparent
and
are
thought
through in a particularly radical direction.
thought. Except on the basis of these last, firmly
The `Weimar problem' which follows from We-
founded and publicly recognised, no reasonable
ber's diagnosis of the political crisis of our time is one
political conception of justice is possible. Political
in which the central debate concerns liberalism's
liberalism starts by taking to heart the absolute
ability to cope with pluralism. A common conclu-
depth of that irreconcilable latent conflict.
47
sion reached is that it could not. According to Carl Schmitt, for example, all political theories contain
Political liberalism's task is to seek self-justifica-
an element of `surplus value' of meaning. It is in their
tion in terms of ideas which, aside from those which
nature to claim a truth for themselves which they
reasonably divide them, all people qua citizens of
cannot possibly justify by rational means. In the eyes
constitutional democracies can nevertheless share.
of many, and Schmitt is the most well-known ex-
In other words, as the basis of political agreement,
ponent of this view, liberalism is bound to oscillate
liberalism must try not to take sides in the wider,
between a self-interpretation of impartiality, or neu-
plural comprehensive doctrines of value. Hence the
trality mixed with proceduralism and a commitment
great significance he attaches to the role of political
to the more substantive values which it peculiarly
philosophy and its abstract constructivist methodol-
embodies. (Schmitt's particular complaint was that
ogy: it is, with hindsight, the obvious as well as
liberalism's claims to be objectively valid conflicted
morally and politically necessary strategy to ward
143
PETER LASSMAN
off the Weimar problem. It helps us, too, to see that
doctrine of the very kind which he is attempting to
modernity need not treat pluralism as some kind of
exclude.
secular equivalent of the fall from grace. For Rawls,
This profoundly suggests the possibility that there
the pluralism of comprehensive doctrines is `not seen
is no one way of characterising pluralism, as a
as a disaster but rather as the natural outcome of the
grounding notion in any case for a liberal politics,
activities of human reason under enduring free in-
which could command universal agreement. It has
stitutions. To see reasonable pluralism as a disaster is
been frequently observed how, in other respects,
to see the exercise of reason under conditions of
Rawls's doctrine falls back upon the kind of com-
freedom itself as a disaster.'
48
prehensive liberalism he seeks to avoid in justificatory arguments.
At once humble in its attempt to avoid grand
51
What this argument suggests is
`metanarratives' and ambitious in its quest for poli-
that we should not be very surprised at this, because
tical agreement amidst reasonable pluralism, it is
the account of pluralism with which the whole
here ± in the account of pluralism that grounds it
project starts already begins to show `comprehensive'
± that we can begin to spot political liberalism's
biases.
problem. For, although Rawls does not see it this
The worry that we are doomed never to be able to
way, the above assessment of pluralism is itself a
deliver a form of theory which is not just `another
deeply controversial interpretation. After all one
controversial and partisan vision of the good life' and
could equally see this version of modern history as
which `will cease to be a plausible solution to one of
a story of `error and illusion, or at least as the
our most pressing moral and political problems' is at
intensification of tragic conflicts of value.'
49
Rawls,
the heart of modern liberalism's anxieties. Larmore
against the strictures of political liberalism, is already
has argued that if we are so condemned then political
favouring one version of history and one attitude
liberalism will `become just another part of the
towards pluralism. Would those who do not accept
problem'. The conviction that `we can agree on a
this version of history be included among `the rea-
core morality while continuing to disagree about
sonable', those who in principle may endorse the
what makes life worth living' may `turn out to be
principles of political liberalism?
50
baseless. Liberalism may necessarily be just one more partisan ideal'
52
± a fear which is most perturbingly
captured in the context of the Weberian picture.
V
The strong resemblance the problem has to that
The paradoxical nature of modern liberalism resides
which contributed to the intellectual and political
in the fact that it, more than other political the-
collapse of Weimar democracy dramatises this pro-
ories, takes pluralism, understood both in terms of
blem into much more than just a philosophical
an interpretation of the sources of value and as
curiosity.
reasonable disagreement, to be both a fundamental
What chance, then, do liberals have of warding off
feature of the modern world and as a problem which
the Weimar problem without engaging in self-delud-
it must cope with in order to establish its own
ingly reassuring `reassessments' of pluralism's proble-
legitimacy. One of the interesting features of Rawls's
matic significance? I want to suggest that Judith
attempt to construct a `political liberalism' is that he
Shklar's idea of the `liberalism of fear' indicates
sees pluralism as built into the nature of modern
the way forward. It has some interesting similarities
constitutional liberal democracy, the natural out-
to Weber's interpretation of the fate of liberal ideas
come of the `burdens of judgement'. However, to
under modern conditions and offers us a way of
take this example, Rawls fails to notice that in
thinking about the predicament of modern liberalism
defining one of the criteria of `the reasonable' in
which, while suitably pessimistic, is not unduly so. So
his account of pluralism and the constitutional-
if it has been valid to talk of the Weberian under-
democratic citizen's appropriate response to it as
current in contemporary liberalism, the extent to
the `willingness to accept the burdens of judgement'
which the liberalism of fear can speak to it is a clear
he is introducing into his theory a controversial
indication of its relevance. Further, Rawls approv-
144
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
ingly notes that the idea has certain similarities with political liberalism too.
53
lity in retreat or tries to calm the warring factions
However, it falls well short
around her, she must prefer a government that
of the full political-liberal strategy ± but herein may
does nothing to increase the prevailing levels of
lie its strength.
fanaticism and dogmatism. To that extent there is
Shklar argues that `the liberalism of fear' does not
a natural affinity between the liberal and the
rest upon a theory of moral pluralism of the kind
sceptic.
58
advocated by Berlin. It does not deny pluralism, though; rather, the point is that the case for liberal-
Those who may be swayed by sceptical arguments
ism does not need to rest upon such metaphysical
of the sort that Weber prompts are nevertheless
claims about the nature of value and suchlike.
54
Here
availed of a definite argument for liberal politics,
is the big difference between Rawls and Berlin on the
precisely because it tries to derive the latter from a
one hand, whose liberalisms start with specific ac-
mutual concern or impulse ± the avoidance of fear
counts of pluralism, and the liberalism of fear on the
and cruelty ± rather than a substantive (contested)
other: all that the latter really needs to begin with is
metaphysical/moral doctrine. But those who have
an account of the `summum malum, which all of us
not succumbed to scepticism, who continue to hold
know and would avoid if only we could. That evil is
other `comprehensive doctrines', can be equally im-
cruelty and the fear it inspires, and the very fear of
pressed by the case for liberalism because, again, it
55
So for Shklar the `deepest grounding' of
rests upon a concern that is shareable not in people's
liberalism as a distinct doctrine is to be found in the
philosophies but in their psychological motivations.
conviction `that cruelty is an absolute evil, an of-
Hence Shklar argues that to embrace the liberalism
fence against God or humanity. It is out of that
of fear is not to embrace any form of normative or
tradition that the political liberalism of fear arose and
cultural relativism. It makes a universal and cosmo-
continues amid the terror of our time to have
politan claim for liberalism while, at the same time,
fear itself.'
relevance.'
56
recognising its local origins and the infrequency of its
The fear which is to be prevented is
full realisation.
the fear created by arbitrary and unnecessary force
59
and by acts of torture and cruelty performed by states
A crucial element in the liberalism of fear is what
and their agents. Historical experience has shown us
some take to be the excessive modesty of its ends.
how such fears are not groundless nightmares; that
`Liberalism has only one overriding aim: to secure
self-same experience teaches us how liberal political
the political conditions that are necessary for the
practices and institutions have so often been the best
exercise of personal freedom.'
hope people have had to remove cruelty and fear
ence with the freedom of others is how liberal
from political life. It is thus historical memory, as
politics removes what sources of fear it can from
opposed to speculative metaphysics, with which the
people's lives; beyond that, `liberalism does not have
liberalism of fear should launch its case.
57
60
Prohibiting interfer-
any particular positive doctrines about how people are to conduct their lives or what personal choices
The case for seeing how the liberalism of fear may
61
address the fears raised by the Weberian picture of
they are to make.'
modernity and the Weimar problem is twofold. First,
unduly cautious, Shklar has more than just historical
having explicitly eschewed reliance upon a Berlinian
memory to make us see the liberalism of fear as both
account of pluralism, Shklar notes that there is a `real
judiciously prudent and no mean achievement in its
psychological connection' between liberalism and
own right. Some of us may nowadays be able to take
the kind of value-scepticism to which Weber gives
the security of the liberal order for granted and hope
paradigmatic expression:
for more adventurous and `imaginative' politics. But
If some might think this is
our foreign news should surely remind us of the scepticism is inclined toward toleration, since in
global prevalence of the most brutal illiberalisms.
its doubts it cannot choose among the competing
There may indeed be more morally `exhilarating'
beliefs that swirl around it, so often in murderous
liberalisms, but they are surely less urgent.
rage. Whether the sceptic seeks personal tranquil-
62
There is another way of expressing reservations
145
PETER LASSMAN
about the apparently limited nature of Shklar's lib-
the price of utopian ventures, least of all those
eralism. Those who are troubled by the Weberian
invented by other people.'
64
sketch of modernity may wonder whether, in its
Space has allowed only a brief sketch of the liberal-
refusal to theorise substantive `positive' goals for
ism of fear. But perhaps enough has already been said
the social and political order, it tacitly grants free
to suggest the attractiveness of its politics, which
rein for instrumental rationality to dominate in
admittedly may not be evident at first sight. We
modern society. But Shklar believes the liberalism
may also be able to appreciate the potential fruitful-
of fear has two powerful responses here. First, if
ness of its approach to justifying liberalism when the
`instrumental rationality' refers purely to political
fact of pluralism, itself so variably interpretable, had
practices which pursue only `efficiency' or `means±
apparently left all such ventures toppling into self-
end calculation', without questioning the rationality
contradiction. It concedes that we have to work from
or desirability of whatever end to which they are put,
our own traditions and experiences in order to arrive at
then it does not apply to the liberalism of fear. For it
a form of self-understanding for our political ideas,
has very definite, substantive ends in its desire to
even when we deliberate for universal ideals. This may
avoid the institutionalisation of fear and cruelty, and
make our political thought paradoxical but it does not
political practices are to be explicitly scrutinised with
make it incoherent.
these in view.
65
As a response to Kant's question, with which this
The second response has `instrumental rationality'
chapter began, the liberalism of fear suggests some-
describing a politics that places all its confidence in
thing very different in content to Rawlsian political
procedures, without adequate attention to the ra-
philosophy even though it shares with Rawls the
tionality of the conduct and discourse of those who
project of explaining what `should be the public
participate in and follow them. It trusts the mechan-
philosophy in a reasonably just constitutional re-
isms for creating consent and ensuring fairness, with-
gime.'
out any attention to the character of the individual
of argument in Shklar's favour. The exemplars of
citizens or to that of the society as a whole.
63
66
But the difference is what can tip the scales
philosophy examined here proved unable to con-
But Shklar, of course, wants the liberalism of fear
vince us that they could answer the question, that
to justify a liberal regime that may be little more than
they could avoid the Weimar problem. All that the
a modus vivendi, a political accommodation shared by
liberalism of fear needs, though, is the fear that
people of diverse natures, tastes and goals mutually
motivates the question ± which perhaps receives
motivated by a fear of political cruelty. To invest
its most acute expression with the Weberian sketch
politics with a more substantively rational goal, to
of modernity as its backdrop ± to begin the political
take sides in the pluralism of possible forms of life, is
argument for liberalism. Under the conditions of
to risk precisely the kind of totalitarian oppression
modern pluralism, this is probably the best we can
which provides part of the historical memory psy-
do. But the Weimar problem, and the existence of
chologically motivating the liberalism of fear. To
widespread cruelty still in the world, should leave us
think that this charge of `instrumentality' has any bite
with no doubt that this argument is still very much
is to show `disdain for those who do not want to pay
worth pursuing.
Notes
1. Rawls (1996), p. plxii.
of which the war is being waged ± will, as a rule, turn
2. Richardson (1994), p. 238.
out to be relatively simple and unsophisticated': Berlin (1969), pp. 200±1.
3. The idea of the `inner citadel' here is drawn from Berlin: `the deepest convictions of philosophers are
4. Weber's picture is one way of substantiating the
seldom contained in their formal arguments: funda-
notion of the `default' position in political theory,
mental beliefs, comprehensive views of life, are like
an idea suggested by Mark Evans in Chapter 11 of this volume.
citadels which must be guarded against the enemy . . .
5. Habermas (1998a), p. 60.
the inner fortress itself ± the vision of life for the sake
146
DISENCHANTMENT AND THE LIBERALISM OF FEAR
37. Hennis (1988). For the idea of a `strange liberal', see
6. Rawls (1996), p. lx.
Boesche (1987).
7. See Walzer (1983); cf. Griffin (1994).
38. See, for example, Eden (1982). Indeed, the uncer-
8. Rawls (1996), p. 44.
tainty about the classification merely reinforces the
9. Ibid., p. lxi.
claim that Weber poses problems for liberals.
10. Ibid., p. lxii.
39. Weber
11. Hampshire (1983), p. 162.
(1994)
p.
68;
Gerth
and
Wright
Mills
(eds.)(1991), p. 153.
12. Hampshire (1989), p. 118. 13. Rawls (1999), p. 1.
40. Rawls (1999), pp. 463 n. 24.
14. Rawls (1996), p. 55.
41. Anderson (1992), pp. 193±7.
15. Rawls (1996), p. xx.
42. See, on this point, Dyzenhaus (1997), p. 12.
16. Ibid., p. xxiii.
43. See Schmitt (1985); cf. Larmore (1996), chapter 8 for critical discussion.
17. Jahanbegloo (1993), p. 56. 18. Ibid., p. 45.
44. Rawls (1996), p. 374.
19. For the interpretation of Berlin as an objective plur-
45. Dyzenhaus (1997), p. 16.
alist, which sharply distinguishes him from Weber, see
46. Rawls (1996), p. xxvii.
Gray (1995b).
47. Ibid., p. xxviii.
20. Rawls (1999), pp. 463 n. 24; cf. ibid., pp. 462±3.
48. Ibid., pp. xxvi±vii.
21. Berlin (1978), p. 148.
49. Wenar (1995), p. 48.
22. Berlin (1991), p. 12. John Gray refers to Berlin's
50. Ibid. 51. For an example of such that Rawls himself concedes
`phenomenological certainties' in Gray (1995b), p. 62.
but which may be far more likely than he would hope,
23. Ibid.
see Rawls (1996), pp. 152; cf. Evans (1999).
24. See B. Williams, `Introduction', in Berlin (1978). 25. Jahanbegloo (1993), p. 44.
52. Larmore (1996), p. 151.
26. For a version of this argument, see Raz (1986), chapter
53. Rawls (1996), p. 374. 54. Shklar (1989), p. 29.
14.
55. Ibid.
27. This is a term used by Max Weber, taken from Goethe, to describe such relationships; see Gerth and Wright
56. Shklar (1989), p. 23.
Mills (eds) (1991), pp. 62±3.
57. Ibid., p. 27.
28. Berlin and Williams (1994), p. 309.
58. Ibid., p. 25.
29. Crowder (1994), p. 303.
59. Ibid., pp. 29, 34.
30. Berlin (1991), pp. 80, 203, 205.
60. Ibid., p. 21.
31. Kekes (1993), p. 199.
61. Ibid.
32. Anderson (1992), p. 245.
62. Ibid., p. 38.
33. Larmore (1996), chapter 7.
63. Ibid., p. 33.
34. Ibid., p. 174.
64. Ibid., p. 33.
35. Ibid., pp. 166±7.
65. See Michelman (1995) for discussion of this claim.
36. Ibid., p. 167.
66. Rawls (1999), p. 622.
147
11
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS Mark Evans
clear that the prominence of the `Rorty debate'
I
reflects a widespread belief that he has thrown down
Despite the hostility that much of it bears to its
an important challenge. After all, if he is right then
object, the extent of the response to Richard Rorty's
the very need for liberal moral and political theory
intervention in liberal political theory is testament
(or, indeed, any other kind) is clearly called into
to the significance that so many commentators
question.
attach to it. Rorty believes that liberal convictions
Thus, in a book devoted to mapping out new
are utterly contingent upon the preferences of those
research agendas for liberalism, Rorty's challenge can
in liberal cultures, that philosophy adds nothing
hardly be avoided. But as this chapter will contend,
useful to the holding and promotion of such con-
he has arguably not posed it in anything like the
victions and is probably best abandoned, and that
terms in which it could and should be presented. The
these considerations need not disrupt the way in
full consequences for liberal politics in particular are
which we `handle' such convictions. He wants us to
not teased out and so he does not give us the
treat these claims as profoundly liberating, in that
opportunity to appraise the whole effect of `contin-
they say liberals can be freed from thinking they need
gency' upon our thinking and our practice. One
(perpetually elusive) theoretical justifications ± in
purpose of this chapter, then, is to develop a `Ror-
particular the `foundationalist' claims that purport-
tyean view', a characterisation of aspects of his
edly establish their `truth' ± in order to entertain
thought that is fuller than he himself provides but
their principles. But, despite his constant reassurance
which does not depart in essence from his pragma-
to the contrary, the idea of `contingency' and its
tism. This view will allow us to depict and apprise
rejection of `foundationalism' strikes many liberals as
more
being fraught with danger, leaving us teetering on
liberal moral and political commitments, which
the brink of nihilism, sidestepping all manner of
Rorty believes can survive the abandonment of
issues in complacently claiming that `our' liberalism
the philosophical search for their foundations.
thoroughly the Rortyean
interpretation
of
can survive the embrace of contingency and the
The particular aspect of liberal commitment to
disengagement from philosophy intact. Some critics
which Rorty is obviously passionately attached is
have felt that Rorty is so insouciant that his ideas are
what he calls the `human rights culture' (hereafter:
not, ultimately, worth taking seriously. Yet, unless
`HRC').
(implausibly) the continued critical interest in him is
be very wary of overly homogenising our conception
merely the result of a popular desire among theorists
of `the' HRC, the chapter proceeds from the plau-
to engage with what they regard as an easy target, it is
sible assumption that many who hold its commit-
148
1
Now if we grant the point that we should
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
ments do so in a foundationalist manner. That is to
him. If they did, he might well have obtained a
say that they believe human rights claims are `true',
deeper sense of what moral and political problems
for they think such rights are objectively valid
may open up, rather than disappear, with the aban-
despite whatever certain people may think or prac-
donment of foundationalism.
tise to the contrary. Paradigmatic of this approach to
What may strike one as paradoxical about this
rights is the American Declaration of Independen-
indifference is that the pragmatist approach to hu-
2
In
man rights is motivated by the idea that, because the
more recent documents, the notion of `objective
philosophical search for the `foundations' of rights
validity' is conveyed by the idea that codifications
has proved to be so inconclusive, it is actually of little
of rights (such as the Universal Declaration of Hu-
use in spreading acceptance of human rights around
man Rights) are designed to `recognise' and `observe'
the world and should no longer detain us. Rorty's
the rights, rather than to create them. In other words,
concern, then, is explicitly practical: he wants to do
such documents are posited as an acknowledgement
what will best promote the HRC globally. Yet there
of the independently grounded moral validity of
is no real engagement with those questions about the
ce's assertion that they are `self-evident' truths.
3
Such ideas, I suggest, are reflected in the
justifiability of the coercive rights-enforcing actions
way rights are popularly regarded by most of those
which often accompany the actual political pursuit
rights.
within the HRC.
4
of the human rights agenda. He seems to rest content
If, as I will hereafter assume, the HRC is pro-
with an idea that a liberal-pragmatist society `will get
foundly foundationalist in outlook, it is hardly clear
accustomed to the thought that social policy needs
that Rorty's pragmatist approach can allow it con-
no more authority than successful accommodation
sistently to stand in anything like its familiar form.
among individuals . . . It will be a society . . . that
The modified Rortyean view, then, will be designed
takes reflective equilibrium as the only method
to test just how conservative of the moral culture's
needed in discussing social policy.' This recommen-
self-understandings Rortyean pragmatism might al-
dation gives us no insight into how the genuinely
low us to be.
deep and persistent conflicts over human rights,
5
The centrepiece of this enquiry concerns not only
either within a state or internationally, are to be
what morality looks like from a Rortyean perspective
tackled when `accommodation' is impossible or un-
about those we call `rights-violators'. It also focuses
desirable. Two commentators, Guignon and Hiley,
upon what many who share the HRC believe is
have written that what is most admirable in Rorty's
politically sanctioned by the `truth of human rights',
work `is the courage, integrity and clear-sightedness
namely that violations of human rights constitute
with which he bites the bullet and draws out the
objective moral wrongs which, in at least some
inevitable consequences of anti-foundationalism for
circumstances, may be sufficiently bad to warrant,
moral and social thought.' Unfortunately, this cour-
for example, the `humanitarian intervention' by
age abruptly evaporates once the really tough ques-
certain states in the affairs of others. The founda-
tions of political justification are reached. In this
tionalist nature of human rights on the HRC view as
respect, we have a bullet which Rorty has barely
interpreted here gives rights a seemingly authorita-
nibbled.
6
tive basis which is sufficiently `weighty' to legitimise
The value of suggesting what account a suitably
the use of force in their support. Whether Rorty's
developed Rortyeanism may give of this problem is
anti-foundationalism can provide a suitable substi-
probably best grasped by thinking about the follow-
tute for the foundationalist rights-enforcing sanc-
ing suggestion as to why his work has attracted so
tion, or whether it should not be perturbed if it
much attention. I propose that the Rortyean view
cannot, are surely questions of considerable signifi-
articulates what might be thought of as a `default'
cance. But here is where a charge of complacency
position in moral and political theory. That is to say,
against Rorty has real bite, for such questions of
it represents the kind of philosophical outlook which
political justification ± seeking reasons to justify the
many contemporary thinkers fear would have to be
exercise of political power ± do not particularly vex
conceded if their alternative, opposed theories are
149
MARK EVANS
shown to be unsuccessful.
7
The worrying feature of
This might immediately suggest that nothing really
the `default position' lies in its apparent, complete
hangs upon the fact that the HRC tends to employ
reduction of fundamental moral values to a whimsi-
foundationalist moral concepts.
cal subjectivism that would destroy the point of
happy to leave these in place, simply because it
moral and political theory and, more importantly,
makes little difference one way or another to the
leave us just a `change-of-feeling' away from sanc-
HRC's promotion.
10
Rorty might be
tioning the embrace of completely abhorrent values.
This resolution of the possible conflict between
It is a horror at having to accept that this is all there
the commitments to pragmatist contingency and the
is to morality that so much philosophical labour is
HRC is too quick, however. For Rorty doesn't
devoted to contending that this is not the case.
abstain entirely from meta-ethical claims; he actually
The default position takes on a particularly sinister
adopts a provisionally non-cognitivist position, and
hue for many liberals in political thinking. As we
this crucially underpins his practical recommenda-
shall see, nowadays they often argue that the justi-
tions. This position is evident in the way he attacks
fication for imposing their principles with political
foundationalism, which he defines as a theory of
power rests upon some notion that the `receivers' of
moral knowledge holding that we draw values from
such power can, in some way, consent to those
non-moral premises: `to claim such knowledge is to
principles.
8
claim to know something which, though not itself a
I suggest that Rorty, given his remarks
11
on reflective equilibrium above, falls into this broad
moral intuition, can correct moral intuitions.'
camp. Now one might not be concerned about
rhetorically demands whether there is this kind of
imposing purely subjective and contingently held
knowledge and argues that the extent to which the
principles upon people if the latter could plausibly
philosophical search for it contributes little or noth-
agree to them in some way. Yet if, as implied by the
ing to the promotion of moral values is the extent to
role of coercion in spreading the HRC, we cannot
which we have reason to think there is no such
always rely upon such agreement in politics, where
knowledge.
does the default position leave the argument for such
the wide diversity of, and persistent disagreement
political imposition?
between, the myriad accounts of moral knowledge
12
He
This claim is defensible by pondering
Rorty's indifference to the questions raised thus far
and the related unpersuasiveness of any one of them
may make the `default' position in his hands rela-
to a significantly large number of rationally enquiring
tively easy to dismiss. I think it poses a more per-
minds. Obviously this is not enough in logic to
plexing challenge, not least because I argue that the
clinch Rorty's conclusion that there is no one `cor-
Rortyean view can be made to do a better job of
rect' morality at all (the phenomena of diversity and
defending some aspects of the HRC. This allows us
disagreement could be explicable in various ways).
to take fairer and fuller measure ± and hence to assess
But he is only really interested in offering enough
the limits ± of a theory whose conclusions may be
prima facie evidence in support of non-cognitivism to
profoundly unsettling for many liberal political the-
disarm those who think that continuing the search
orists.
for moral knowledge remains the best way of promoting moral values. Consequently, he urges the embrace of what is actually the classic non-cogniti-
II
vist approach to moral revision as the most effective
Rortyeanism asks us not to bother pursuing any
means to pursue this goal: the manipulation of
philosophical questions whose resolution has no
sentiments to change the way people feel about moral
significant bearing on the practical pursuit of our
matters.
13
goals (in this instance the spreading of the HRC's
It could be objected that a non-cognitivist ac-
acceptance). For Rorty, meta-ethics falls into this
count cannot be objectivist about moral value: how
category. `The difference between the moral realist
can a value be objective if it does not exist inde-
and the moral anti-realist', he writes, seems to be `a
pendently of people's attitudes? Given the objectivist
difference which makes no practical difference.'
9
quality typically assigned to `human rights' in the
150
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
HRC, we may already have reached the point at
2. the reduction of moral judgement to a basis
which tensions surface between Rorty's philosophi-
which is at least potentially inconstant, ren-
cal commitments and the standpoint of the HRC.
dering the content of morality unstable, adap-
Certainly, if we adopt what can be called a trans-
table merely as our whims desire.
cendentalist conception of objectivity, which natu-
rally attaches to moral realism in holding that there
Rorty veers towards both in his provisional rejec-
is a realm of facts `out there', independent of our
tion of the HRC's foundationalist underpinnings and
attitudes, we could agree that `objectivity' should be
in his belief that a properly ironist view will always be
purged from a Rortyean view. But it can be recast in
disposed to treat our current moral vocabularies as
is
revisable. But here is where we can develop a
achieved in the agreed outcome of a discourse over
Rortyean view sympathetically in a way which mini-
values which has conformed to certain ideal condi-
mises the discrepancy with the HRC.
conversationalist
terms,
in
which
`objectivity'
tions of validity (without any implication that the
Rorty asks us to think of moral values as `we17
agreed outcome of moral conversation thereby iden-
intentions',
tifies
`independently
ments as to what should and should not be done
Successful moral arguments
within that community. Hence `the core meaning of
any
of
the
grounded' moral facts).
cognitivists' 14
summaries of a community's agree-
create, rather than discover, what is objective. This is
``immoral action'' is ``the sort of thing we don't
precisely in accord with Rorty's claim that for prag-
do'' ',
matists
didn't do. Moral understandings evolve over time
18
or, better, what we would rather people
in a community's practices as people work out for the desire for objectivity . . . is simply the desire
themselves commodious ways of living and, as Mar-
for
as
garet Macdonald (another non-cognitivist defender
possible . . . Insofar as pragmatists make a dis-
of rights) describes, they become `expressed in the
tinction between knowledge and opinion, it is
life of the society and constitute its ``quality''. They
simply the distinction between topics on which
are conveyed by its ``tone'' and atmosphere as well as
such agreement is relatively easy to get and topics
its laws.'
as
much
intersubjective
agreement
on which agreement is relatively hard to get.
15
19
A non-cognitivist could describe this in
terms of socialisation imparting specific moral attitudes to its subjects, furnishing them with an attitu-
Yet if `objectivity' in some form need not be
dinal moral perspective that reflects how those who
denied to the Rortyean view altogether, it might
share it feel about desirable and admirable forms of
still be feared from the standpoint of the HRC that
conduct and their obverse. Once developed, a moral
the conversationalist variant is a very pale imitation
perspective can quickly acquire the status of a set of
of `real' objectivity. The non-cognitivist underpin-
social facts, impressed upon people by what are
ning of the Rortyean view, so the fear runs, will
experienced as the external forces of socialisation
always conflict with the way in which the HRC
and passed on as purportedly self-standing rules.
conceptualises its moral commitments.
Hence people are confronted by morality as an
20
apparently supra-individual, `weighty' and hence at least apparently objective phenomenon. But in this
III
perspectivist analysis this feature is testament not to
This concern arises from the common belief that
the actual, external existence of moral facts but to
non-cognitivism is driven towards these positions:
the content and depth of people's socialisation into the conventions of morality.
1. the explanation of the virtually ubiquitous
Applying this account to describe the HRC, it can
realist terminology in moral discourse by an
be said that, in our socialisation into its perspective,
`error' theory, which says we mis-describe the
we acquire an outlook in which rights are attributed
nature of our moral commitments when we
to all: when we conceptualise `human being' we
express them in such a way;
16
conceptualise `rights-bearer'. `Rights' are the summa-
151
MARK EVANS
23
ries of our culture's ideals of how all humans should
action;
be treated. Rorty calls moral judgements `ethno-
validating them from a transcendental perspective.
he just denies that there is any useful way of
centric' to indicate their cultural particularity, drawing one's attention to the cultural specificity of such judgements and the beliefs that form them.
21
IV
As a
Thus far, we have seen how the Rortyean view could
`final vocabulary' he thinks the discourse of rights has 22
Any arguments
furnish itself with non-relativised moral prescriptions
in favour of them are going to be, in some way and at
and has at its disposal a sociological explanation of
some level, question-begging, only working by as-
why morality appears to have an objectivist, foun-
suming the validity of the very values that a dis-
dationalist quality. But the question remains as to
putant is throwing into doubt. But, in response to
whether a non-cognitivist should still recommend
concerns that this might be a deeply unsatisfactory
the replacement of the realist, objectivist language of
feature of a final vocabulary's justification, we might
morals, for the sake of `philosophical hygiene'. If so,
wonder whether other, if any, of our deep commit-
then the view still threatens to destroy the form of
ments (to family, friends, personal projects, organisa-
discourse typically employed in the HRC.
no non-circular means of defence.
tions) can ultimately be justified in non-question-
Simon Blackburn has argued that it is perfectly
begging ways. Is there, for example, necessarily a
legitimate to employ realist-seeming terms when
non-question-begging justification to explain why I
accounting for what are in fact only products of
love my wife and have committed my life to her?
attitudes. We can be what he calls `quasi-realist'
Furthermore, is it necessarily appropriate to think
in our moral judgements, projecting values on to
that I need a non-question-begging justification for
the world from one's moral perspective.
such a commitment? (Isn't the sheer fact that I love
shares a broadly similar account of the purpose of
her enough to justify my loving commitment to her?)
thinking about morality to Rorty's:
24
Blackburn
A Rortyean, therefore, may be able to argue that there is no deficiency in any final vocabulary's
we should not theorise about morality and ethics
circular defence.
as if they are in the business of describing aspects
As Rorty has frequently stressed, admitting to the
of the world . . . To enter a moral claim is . . . to
epistemological relativism of the `ethnocentric' ap-
take up an attitude or stance, and centrally it
proach does not necessarily entail a normatively
involves making an emotional response to con-
relativistic configuration of the values held within
templated events and states of affairs . . . Moral
any perspective. To see this point, it should be
and ethical vocabulary . . . enables us to share our
remembered that perspectives are unrankable with-
stances with others, to shape our sensibilities in
out adopting standards which are only available
light of opinion of others.
within a particular perspective. Outside of any moral perspective, from the morally vacuous standpoint of
In short, `the essence of ethics lies in its practical
the world `as it is', no moral evaluation of any kind ±
function' ± a natural ally, then, for the Rortyean
relativist or otherwise ± can be sanctioned. No
view.
grounds therefore present themselves from the per-
vism' suggests a way of describing human rights from
spectivist outlook per se as to why we must relati-
within an attitudinal moral perspective in terms that
vistically concede equal validity to all perspectives.
realists often think are reserved for themselves.
Any insistence upon normative relativism has to be
Projectivism is a complex philosophical position
based upon an essentially coherentist claim that it
and only some of its basic features can be outlined
would be internally inconsistent for the human
here; moreover, it is reasonable to assume that Rorty
rights perspective to be constructed
without it.
himself might part company with it at several key
Clearly, Rorty finds no such grounds for this posi-
points. Enough, though, can be said to illuminate the
tion. He thinks it proper that people should make
proposal for its partial incorporation into the Ror-
judgements about fundamental rules of human inter-
tyean view.
152
25
More pertinently still, Blackburn's `projecti-
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
Although Blackburn does not believe that values
root of 144?' ± which would refer to how the con-
are intrinsically part of their objects, his key claim is
ventions within mathematics produce this result ±
that there is no bar to using the language of `percep-
with an external question `why do we say 12 is the
tion of the actual' in attributing moral properties to
square root of 144?', which would direct us towards
people because
the origins and nature of the conventions themselves. So P can legitimately answer `why is cruelty
we speak of the perception of every single cate-
wrong?' by referring to those features of cruel acts
gory of thing and fact that we ever communicate.
which make cruelty wrong from the moral perspec-
We speak of perception of numerical truths,
tive, rather than having to say that his attitudes to
truths about the future, truths about the past,
cruelty are what make it wrong. Within his moral
possibilities, other minds, theoretical entities of
perspective, it is actually the case that cruelty is
all kinds . . .
26
wrong and using realist language to express this is a coherent way of stating what is the case in his outlook.
± mind-dependent features, in short.
27
Further, he contends that realist language turns
Transferring this analysis to the projection of
out to be a proper way of expressing commitment to
human rights: if we ask the `outside' question `why
that which we deem to be valuable. One way of
do we say people have human rights?', the reply
grasping this claim is to see the realist-sounding
should focus upon the attitudes people have about
language of the projectivist as expressions of how
how they think humans should treat each other.
things indeed are from the standpoint of our perspective.
From within the perspective, though, rights are
Moral statements are properly statements from the
projected onto people first as an act of valuation,
`inside', internal to one's moral perspective. To
to follow a distinction made by David Wiggins,
believe that realist language ought to be abandoned
which identifies what is felt to be sufficiently im-
because our moralising has its origins in attitudes is to
portant about a human being to warrant a certain
step outside of the moral way of looking at things and
kind of morally obligatory respect, and then as a
confuses the language which is appropriate `intern-
directive judgement (which holds that `because X is
ally', within the moral outlook, with what is appro-
valued, Y ought to be done'), creating the rule
priate
from
embodied in the idea of people possessing a right
nowhere' that we conceptualise as lying beyond all
to expect a certain kind of treatment with respect to
perspectives. Blackburn's example of characterising
the valued attribute.
`externally'
from
the
moral
`view
28
29
cruelty illustrates this. If a projectivist, P, is asked
I suggest, then, that the Rortyean view's provi-
`why is cruelty wrong?', he is asked a moral question,
sional non-cognitivism need not force the abandon-
which is properly understood to enquire as to what
ment of the realist, objectivist discourse of the HRC.
judgements are made within a moral outlook. If he
Of course, like any other philosophical position,
were to answer `because it is not something I like' ±
projectivism has its critics and some would urge that
making cruelty wrong because of the responses he has
its usage of realist terms is too hollow to be accep-
to it ± a realist would swiftly point out the obvious
table (I expand upon some of these doubts in the
anti-realist character of the reply. But P's answer is
final section). This may be so ± but it requires
not the one he has to give to a moral question.
philosophical argument to prosecute such conten-
Answers in which attitudes figure are appropriate to
tions. And that is an activity which, it is now clear,
`external' questions about the nature of morality,
Rorty abandons too quickly. Here, we have had to
such as `why do we say cruelty is wrong?' But this
retrieve it on his behalf to tackle the problem of the
is a different kind of question from the one asked
HRC's foundationalist character. If the simple graft-
within the moral view and we should not give
ing of projectivism onto the Rortyean view is not
answers to questions which are raised from different
enough to satisfy the doubters, then this is all the
standpoints. A parallel would be to contrast an
more reason to keep philosophical enquiry alive.
internal mathematics question `why is 12 the square
153
MARK EVANS
type of action to propagate human rights among
V
others is to show coherentistically that the action
We now turn to the heart of Rorty's own practical
would conflict with other principles within the hu-
concerns: the business of promoting the HRC, most
man rights perspective to which a liberal ought to
of all among those who actively reject it. At this
accord primacy. And that perspective, of course, is
point, it is apposite to distinguish clearly between
held utterly contingently, the product of nothing
three types of justificatory argument:
other than our affirmation of the values of our culture.
1. Moral justification. With respect to beliefs, this
From a non-cognitivist position, the force of the
is generally concerned to offer arguments as to
idea that action in support of human rights can
why we should support certain moral princi-
trump other moral codes can only ultimately lie in
ples and not others. With respect to our ac-
the fact that the rights we embrace in the HRC
tions, moral justification asks whether morality
represent firm, settled and passionately held attitudes
gives us warrant for acting in a particular way.
as to how people should be treated. Some ± perhaps
It requires us to connect our actions to moral
many ± liberals may agree with the argument that
beliefs and assess their moral worth accord-
there
ingly.
merely
is
nothing possessing
philosophically universalistic
inconsistent moral
in
attitudes
2. Political justification. This question specifically
non-cognitivistically. Yet they could still be pro-
asks for a justification for the exercise of
foundly perturbed at the contention that it is per-
political power. When talking about the po-
missible politically to act upon these, to promote or
litical imposition of a moral principle, it may
even enforce any moral perspective among others
not be enough to justify that action via a moral
who do not share it when it can have no indepen-
justification of the principle alone. The prin-
dent warrant or authority beyond the contingent
ciple may indeed be morally valid, but that
commitment they happen to have formed to it. They
may not suffice to make its forcible imposition
may ask themselves whether it would be appropriate
justified. (It may be morally right, for example,
for them qua liberals to do this given the ethno-
to condemn adultery but many would not
centric provenance of their morality.
think that judgement sufficient to justify its
It is clearly important to think hard about coher-
criminalisation.) One consideration in the
ent plausible conclusions which could be drawn by
search for political justification may be the
liberals from the normatively anti-relativist insistence
third argument.
that all should respect human rights when made
3. The justification of political authority, the estab-
within such a contingent perspective. The liberal
lishment of the right of an institution (such as
schema of universal human rights can readily be
the state) to be the one to exercise power
grasped as definitive of liberalism's essence, expressing
(separable from (2) in so far as the question of
what it means to view humans as free and equal
who should exercise power is distinct from that
beings for whom cruelty is the worst thing that could
of which among our (moral and non-moral)
be suffered. `We liberals' can say that we feel so
ends can be promoted with political power).
strongly about them that we are convinced that all should respect rights, even if others do not see things
These are crucial distinctions yet Rorty's political
the same way. Thus, our primary commitment to
theory (if indeed it can be properly called that) has
rights rules out the possibility or need to admit the
little grasp of them. Once again, we must see how we
legitimacy and permissibility of any moral system
might construct his position to accommodate them.
which systematically denies them.
Instantly we should reiterate a point that helps to
Hence, liberals do not have to adopt a `live and let
frame the disquieting character of the Rortyean view
live' attitude of tolerance to rights-violating systems.
as a default position: the only way for non-cogniti-
Indeed, if they were to be this sensitive to the views
vism ultimately to preclude the acceptability of any
of other societies then they may well be abandoning
154
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
much of their own fundamental commitment to
be a project of sentimental education would be the
human rights: what is the point, after all, of taking
effort to break down such discriminating divisions of
`human' rights seriously if they are going to be
humanity to forge an increasingly shared way of
prepared to acknowledge that some societies could
viewing and treating human beings. We can hope
quite acceptably ignore or violate them?
to encourage non-rights-respecters to make an ima-
One might hope that much of the concern about
ginative, sympathetic or empathetic identification
the promotion of the human rights perspective could
with the plight of those who, from our perspective,
be mitigated by adopting the essentially non-coer-
are having their fundamental rights brutally vio-
cive, persuasive or `conversational' approach to mor-
lated.
al conversion that Rorty obviously prefers. Even if it
consequences of rights-violations and to care that
is employed by bodies (states, quangos or interna-
such should henceforth be avoided. That, as much as
tional organisations) which wield political power it is
anything, is a powerful reason for keeping alive
arguable that no question of physical enforcement on
through historical narrative the memory of those
their part necessarily arises if they adopt this ap-
terrible atrocities which have made us now so con-
proach alone in HRC-supporting policies ± and of
cerned with human rights.
32
We can try to get others to see the awful
course the persuasive strategy need not be under-
Despite its status as a final vocabulary, the human
taken only by political institutions (or at all ± it
rights perspective need not shut out all opportunity
could be left to private individuals and organisations
for critical reflection on the HRC's present content.
such as churches and charities). If this is what Rorty
This may further placate liberal concerns that some
has in mind, the lack of a specifically political edge to
kind of cultural imperialism is being sanctioned here,
his theory might be more understandable.
for this point encourages an appreciation of the
Certainly, there are potentially wide resources to
potential for refinement, improvement or transfor-
pursue the persuasive-conversational strategy. We
mation of our commitments even when we currently
could start by noting that many of the world's
hold fast to them. Rorty warns us to be sensitive to
governments pay lip-service to international under-
how `redescription' often humiliates in undermining
standings of rights and can be charged with promise-
the existing self-understandings of those whose views
breaking, hypocrisy and illegality in international
we seek to convert. But if it is acknowledged that
law to the extent that they actually violate rights
redescription need not all be `one-way' ± that A
(urging coherence, or consistency, between pro-
might enrich her own moral sensibility from the
claimed and actual standards of behaviour). The
dialogue she has with B even when she hopes that
tendency of human rights to gain support in the
B may come to share her view ± the potential for
international community as agreed standards of mor-
humiliation on either part may be lessened.
al behaviour is a further crucial point which could be
However, the bottom line of the human rights
cited in favour of this perspective (`since so many
perspective must surely be that, though the moral
millions of people sincerely and fervently support
beliefs which supplement basic rights may be revi-
human rights, isn't this at least a good pro tanto
sable, there is probably little left open for debate as
reason for others to do so as well?').
far as the latter are concerned. Anyone whose views
Another part of the persuasive strategy for the
have to be redescribed in order to begin fostering a
liberal could be, in Rorty's rather playful phrase, the
respect for human rights may well deserve to be
telling of `long, sad, sentimental stories' designed to
humiliated, if that is how they feel when confronted
shape the feelings and evaluative dispositions of
by the viewpoint of the HRC.
those who do not (yet) share the rights perspective.
30
As Rorty has observed, the perpetrators of such deeds
VI
typically assume not that human beings are not the
So far, liberals may be happy enough with the
sorts of creature who have human rights, but that 31
Ob-
Rortyean view's approach to the HRC. But in the
viously, then, a decisive part of what would in effect
realm of conversational persuasion, of course, we
their victims are not really humans at all.
155
MARK EVANS
35
have gone no further than the activity of moral
through dialogue.
justification. The critical political problem in spread-
those who won't peacefully concur with the dialo-
ing the HRC is, of course, that conversation is likely
gical outcome (the issue of political justification)
to get us only so far towards this end in many cases.
and, if we are to turn to coercion, how to establish a
And at the point at which persuasion ceases to be
body's right to use power (the justification of poli-
effective Rorty falls silent, even though he is per-
tical authority) are not directly confronted.
fectly well aware that there will be those utterly
Mouffe's diagnosis of this feature identifies the ap-
unconvinced by our redescriptions alone. If there is
plication to politics of the specifically philosophical
nothing more that can be said to Nietzsche, Loyola
techniques of Kantian ethics, with their emphasis
or the committed, consistent Nazi, he throws up his
upon the securing of agreement in public reason, as
hands and dismisses them as `mad'.
33
Questions about what to do with
36
Part of
But what do we
the reason why fundamental conflict is not squarely
do about such people thereafter? Do we leave the
addressed. Rorty's parallel problems with politics may
genocidal maniacs of the world alone as much as
likewise come from the application of his implicit
possible, to carry out their own `ethnocentrically
meta-ethical Humeanism, with its emphasis upon
determined moralities'?
sentiment manipulation through story-telling and suchlike, to what Mouffe insists is the agonistic,
Although questions of rights enforcement can
conflictual realm of politics.
arise even within the boundaries of a liberal state (with respect, say, to a non-liberal minority), let us
Yet such political quietism should be available
focus here upon the issue of humanitarian interven-
least of all to Rorty, given his explicitly practical
tion when one or more states uses force to punish
conception of theory. One would surely have ex-
and/or halt rights violations by another state against
pected a pragmatist to have been dismissive of
its own citizens. Since the end of the Cold War in
traditional non-cognitivism's attitude to political
particular there has been a growing recognition that
questions and have been similarly critical of the
the `international community' has rights to act thus
neo-Kantian `evasion of politics' decried by Mouffe.
(grounded in international law) when basic rights ±
So once again `the Rortyean view' has to be
usually, the specific right to life ± are being violated
developed out of Rorty's own position to ascertain
on a systematic, widespread scale. This recognition,
the character of a Rortyean politics that aims to cope
therefore, is undoubtedly part of the HRC's self-
with political conflicts beyond the illusion that
understandings ± but it is strikingly absent from
persuasion and consensus is all we need. To focus
Rorty's own account of it.
upon the most disturbing aspect of this as a default
In fact it would be unfair to single out Rorty for
position, I propose to pass fairly briefly over the
avoiding questions of the political justification of
question of how political authority is constituted.
coercion. Non-cognitivist moral and political theory
Let us assume that, qua liberal, Rortyeans would
has always tended to dodge such questions. Because it
argue that consent is the key: institutions that right-
treats questions of value as questions of attitude, it
fully exercise power must in some meaningful way
typically holds that `theory' has no specially privi-
have gained the consent of their subjects to do so.
leged insight into what attitudes should be held and
This idea may already do considerable work in
has consequently left the determination of what
justifying
should be done to the actual business of political
pointed out in many instances that rights-violating
life.
34
humanitarian
intervention.
It
can
be
states have freely joined the United Nations and
Moreover, many contemporary liberalisms from
officially support the documents of international law
other traditions are also vulnerable to the charge
that require observance of human rights. Hence, it
of evading the `challenge of the political'. Chantal
could be said that their free adherence to the inter-
Mouffe, for example, has argued that Kantian poli-
national community implies acceptance of its right
tical theory (typified by John Rawls) seems to reduce
to force them to act according to its standards, or at
the resolution of political conflicts to an ultimately
least to punish them when they fail to do so.
consensual
process
of
agreement
formulation
37
But let us concentrate upon the idea of a `rogue
156
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
state' which has consciously broken with the stan-
sense that there is no independent consideration to
dards of international law and has effectively `with-
mandate such a policy ± fails because, from the
drawn
political
Rortyean standpoint, all moral positions ± including
authorities. This state has embarked upon systematic
that of non-intervention ± are `arbitrary'. The case
violations of human rights (a policy of genocide, say,
for saying that, despite the lack of full political
against a certain group of the population). What are
authority, there is sufficient political justification
the pragmatically minded Rortyeans to do and what
for intervention rests upon the idea that, from the
account can be given of what they do?
Rortyean liberal perspective, rights matter so much
its
consent'
from
supra-national
The bald fact of the matter is that the only reason
and express such deep-seated convictions about how
available to them for not advocating the use of force
people should be treated, based upon our reactions to
even in the absence of what they judge to be full
the horrendous cruelty that has been inflicted upon
political authority to do so (that is, the consent of
millions throughout history, that objections and
the `rogue state' to suffer the consequences of breach-
reservations about intervention can be outweighed.
ing international law) would seem to be that it is
Even if this is `cultural imperialism', no alternative
prohibited according to the specifications of the
rights-violating culture necessarily has to be toler-
values within their attitudinal perspective. And
ated by liberals on their own terms.
there is no compelling `internal' reason why these
It needs to be stressed that a belief that it is
values cannot be configured within this perspective
politically justifiable to impose certain human rights
to sanction a coercive strategy.
upon societies failing to respect them will not necessarily lead those of a liberal sensibility straight to
This is the point, the crux of the default position, at which many liberals (and others) will throw their
the conclusion that they must do so. The claim that
hands up in horror. How, they will want to know,
force is permissible where persuasion fails (and, qua
can a liberal argue for the acceptability of such
liberal, we can assume that Rortyeans will exhaust
coercion when it is openly claimed that the princi-
the possibility of persuasion before turning to force)
ples in question are held purely contingently, of
need not be configured to yield a conviction that
`ethnocentric' origin and supported by nothing more
force is obligatory. It might be that the moral costs of a
than arbitrary attitudinal conviction? At least with
justifiable enforcement would outweigh the moral
the liberal account of political authority, even if we
gains. Nor does this claim entail that such interven-
accept the idea of `consent' as a contingently held
tion should necessarily be a regular feature of a liberal
moral commitment, the fact that it sanctions coer-
state's behaviour. We may admit to valid, non-moral
cion only with some notion of agreement from the
reasons for not enforcing rights; it may be too
coerced suggests a less troubling, less imperialistic
difficult or otherwise impractical to force a rogue
scenario. But how could the contingent liberal sin-
state into respecting them.
cerely, consistently make this claim about our atti-
tially liberal sensibility will prevent liberals from
tude to the rogue state? Surely, we are now in the
blithely neglecting the concerns of imperialism al-
realms of `might is right', with a liberal `will-to-
together. Their sensitivity to diversity can still lead
power' seeking to stamp its image upon others in
them to tolerate some forms of social life even when
a world that is, in itself, morally meaningless.
they find them unfitting for humans as they con-
Now the point of the default position is that this
38
Further, a quintessen-
ceptualise them, and they will not treat all aspects of
last proposition is indeed, in essence, the view with
their own culture as fit to be embraced by others.
which it seeks to reconcile us. `Outside' of the liberal
All this notwithstanding, we still have the crucial
moral perspective, this is how we must conclude
point
things are. Yet the claim to be urged here is that this
forced to rest content in principle with a persuasive
gives liberals no necessary reason within their moral
strategy. This is just as well because, whatever re-
perspectives to back away from such policies as
servations they may have about particular instances
humanitarian intervention against rogue states. For
of possible intervention, most who share the HRC
a start, a charge that this is purely `arbitrary' ± in the
are probably not prepared to rule it out in principle
157
that
Rortyean
liberals are
not necessarily
MARK EVANS
always and everywhere. The moral mathematics or
that they could be acceptable to the targets of their
pragmatic costs may not always come out against
policy, such reason-giving `justification' is in fact
coercion and ± to take up another familiar reserva-
`self-explication'. Liberals can think it admirable
tion about intervention ± it is hardly clear that a
and probably necessary on their own terms to render
state cannot act against another to prevent, for
their considerations clear and transparent to them-
example, `ethnic cleansing' or genocide just because
selves and others, sincerely and rigorously. This,
of its own dubious moral past. It may be more
though, is as far as `justification' can extend in this
vulnerable to charges of hypocrisy if it fails to live
case.
up to its own moral standards, but this vulnerability need not constitute a reason for arguing against the
VIII
appropriateness of an interventionist strategy. One does not have to deny that the United States (to take
Thus far, it has not been the concern of the chapter
one example of a potential `rights-enforcing' state) is
to uphold this view against its rivals, merely to
very deeply flawed on such counts and that it is
elaborate it as sympathetically as possible. But it is
desirable to be vigilant over, and suspicious of, its
appropriate to conclude by reflecting on whether
actions (for liberals should be aware of disingenuous
there is much point in taking this view seriously. If it
uses of the human rights banner) in order to agree
is indeed a `default' position, how urgent is the need
that these factors do not constitute decisive bars
to try to escape it?
against its ever rightfully using its power genuinely
One important reservation about it is this: because
to prevent genocidal violations of human rights.
it cannot ultimately help but explain human rights in
This is particularly so if it turns out to be the only
terms of being reified, ethnocentric attitudes that
power capable of doing so.
39
one (albeit very large) group of people wishes to
What, though, does `justification' really signify
impose on others, it is just too brazenly advocatory of
here? From the Rortyean viewpoint it is clear that
the imposition of the powerful's preferred standards
it can only ever be a question of the consistency of a
upon others for liberals ever to feel comfortable with
principle and/or its practical consequences with the
it. The projectivist account of the HRC's moral
overall attitudinal moral perspective. (The notion of
discourse, according to this reservation, is ultimately
`wide reflective equilibrium', in which the perspec-
too flimsy to reconcile liberals to this point; the
tive's convictions, their consequences and relevant
`conversationalist' idea of objectivity, for example,
background considerations are brought into a coher-
patently fails to accommodate those who haven't
ent balance, illuminates how `justification' might
agreed with the results of, or even participated in, the
40
) In the absence of any independent cri-
relevant `conversation'. It provides an all-too-fragile
teria (objective moral truths), the liberalism of the
drape, easily blown away to reveal the realities of
view may always turn to persuasion first, hoping that
unadorned, shameless power.
proceed.
its moral and political cases can be based upon
A deeper worry is that liberals may thus lose
reasons that the others in question can accept.
confidence in their own moral rectitude if they posit
But this commitment to giving reasons acceptable
their belief-system as just one among many of the
to others is now not, as it appears with Rorty himself,
`warring gods' in a disenchanted world. Incapable in
something with which we should rest content. Nor is
principle of giving reasons why their morality is
it, as it appears to be in Kantian `public-justificatory'
superior to others, liberals shrink from the battle
liberalisms, a necessary precondition of all successful
to impose their views ± and perhaps cede the ground
41
It is at best an
to, say, a fascist doctrine whose very point is to
aspiration, which may be consistently pushed aside
impose order and leadership in a fragmented social
when certain moral considerations pertain. In in-
milieu.
stances such as humanitarian intervention, even
foundationalists, who would urge that foundational-
liberals of the Rortyean hue will continue to give
ism is the only internally tenable form liberalism
reasons for their actions. But without the assumption
(and perhaps any other doctrine) could take.
or legitimate political justifications.
158
42
This picture may be gleefully painted by
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
I believe that liberalism is indeed in trouble if it
making a pragmatic or provisional prior commitment
makes `public acceptability' a precondition of its
to their values. Put bluntly, they are committed to
political legitimacy in such a divided and hostile
them in the first instance because they are desirable;
world (as with Rawlsians and more authentic neo-
that they correspond to some independent moral
Kantians), or if it does not push beyond Rorty's own
reality is accepted on faith and, as such, the Rortyean
apparent evasion of politics. But the Rortyean view
can say, is incidental to the commitment ± and
has
therefore dispensable.
deliberately
abandoned
these
approaches.
43
Hence, its ability to avoid the deliquescence of
So the Rortyean view beguilingly contends that
liberalism in the tides of contingency rests upon
the kinds of moral commitment we are all entitled to
its propensity to maintain its convictions that respect
make depend rather less upon the nature of one's
for principles such as rights would make the world a
meta-ethical beliefs than foundationalists in parti-
much better place, even if there is nothing outside of
cular often urge. It can say to the foundationalist
such convictions to `ground' them.
human-rights supporter `given that we share the
To conclude, I suggest that there may be a smaller
same goals, the same language of rights, what profit
gap in this regard between the foundationalist and
is to be gained by continuing the dispute about the
the Rortyean than the former might presume. For it
nature of values? We should be allies and not
can be argued that a foundationalist has great diffi-
enemies.' Thus, a case can be made to take the
culty in supporting principles in a way which avoids
Rortyean view as seriously as other intellectual ap-
the kind of non-foundationalist commitment held by
proaches to the spreading of the HRC around the
anti-foundationalists. A foundationalist who affirms
world. As a `default' position, its increased theore-
the existence of human rights and the rectitude of
tical strength may make it either a tougher target for
whatever action may be appropriate in their pursuit
critics or, perhaps, a less troubling prospect for those
must be convinced that he has indeed discovered the
who fear that those critics may not be able to argue
appropriate truths to justify the conviction. Some
convincingly against it. Of course it remains afflicted
foundationalists are this confident, of course. But
by serious doubts and we might eventually decide
there are pitifully few who agree with any one of the
that the Rortyean view would be insufficiently cap-
particular foundationalist philosophies on offer; de-
able of handling its problems for us to persevere with
bate rages on, apparently interminably. One could
it. But then, which of the rival views can credibly
use this observation to urge that the foundationalist's
claim to be free of similarly extensive problems?
moral commitments persist without the compelling
Moral and political theory could well have a
evidence that the facts indeed support them. (`Given
dangerous potential to frustrate or preclude moral
the criticisms of any one foundationalist position,' so
and political action if we believe we must disen-
this critique runs, `does one still not need a good deal
tangle all such problems before our morality's call to
of faith to hold fast to one's values?')
arms can be answered. If it does nothing else, the
In the absence of secure proof, then, a founda-
Rortyean view suggests that this fear is, mercifully,
tionalist might say that the search for `the truth' has
misplaced: we can be foundationalist or anti-foun-
simply yet to be completed. But this again embodies
dationalist and still affirm human rights in the way
a faith that there is such moral truth to be discov-
they are held in the HRC. Who needs philosophy
ered, which is hardly obvious given the wreckage of
to ground the conviction that a world where there is
previous unsuccessful philosophical searches. More-
no genocide is better than one where there is, and
over, few ± if any ± foundationalists who continue
that we ought to use whatever means we can to
the search believe that they must suspend all their
secure the former? What matter most of all, we
moral commitments prior to the moral discovery
might finally be able to agree, are the urgent moral
they seek to verify. Yet, given that they typically
and political demands of those who suffer so dread-
do not regard themselves as morally impotent in the
fully when the idea of human rights is contemp-
absence of secure knowledge, they must end up
tuously cast aside.
159
44
MARK EVANS
Notes
14. D'Agostino (1993). The `conditions of acceptability'
1. Rorty (1998), p. 170. 2. See Peterson (ed.) (1977), p. 235.
typically include requirements that the agreement be
3. See, for example, Brownlie (ed.) (1981), p. 143.
reached freely and fairly, and be based upon `consid-
4. Space does not permit a full substantiation of this
ered and critical reflection', not instantaneous opinio-
claim and I do not wish to deny that different accounts
natedness.
may be given of how at least some people regard the
regarded as purely contingent criteria from the Ror-
Of
course,
these
must
themselves
be
tyean perspective.
notion of human rights. But I am more interested here in the specific question of how well Rorty's thought
15. Rorty (1985), p. 5.
can support this particular general account, rather
16. A view famously adopted on behalf of non-cognitivism by Mackie (1977), chapter 1, especially pp. 48±9.
than the separate issue of how widely accepted the latter is. (I think it is sufficiently familiar not to deny
17. Rorty (1989), chapter 3, especially pp. 59±60.
its presence in the HRC.)
18. Ibid., p. 59. 19. M. Macdonald, `Natural Rights', in Waldron (ed.)
5. R. Rorty, `The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy',
(1984), pp. 21±40, at p. 36.
in Malachowski (ed.) (1990), pp. 279±302, at p. 286.
20. For the concept of `social fact', see Durkheim (1982),
6. C. Guignon and D. Hiley, `Biting the Bullet: Rorty on
especially chapter 1.
Public and Private Morality', in Malachowski (ed.)
21. Rorty (1985), p. 13.
(1990), pp. 339±64, at p. 343.
22. The notion of `final vocabulary' is discussed at Rorty
7. I am not claiming that all theorists regard this as the
(1989), p. 73.
only `default' position lurking in the wings and waiting for our philosophies to fail. I suspect, though, that this
23. See Rorty (1998), p. 170 for his conviction that a
specific position frequently haunts much philosophi-
`human rights' perspective constitutes a morally superior way of viewing and treating people.
cal debate.
24. Blackburn (1984), chapter 6, and (1993), especially
8. For example Rawls (1996), p. 136: `Our exercise of
chapters 8±9.
political power is fully proper only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution the essen-
25. Blackburn (1996), pp. 82±100.
tials of which all citizens as free and equal may
26. Blackburn (1993), p. 161.
reasonably be expected to endorse in the light of
27. Ibid., chapter 9, especially pp. 172±5.
principles and ideals acceptable to their common
28. Wiggins (1988), pp. 133±4.
human reason.'
29. One potential problem with this interpretation of projectivism is that Blackburn has recently contended
9. Rorty (1998), p. 172. 10. At ibid., p. 171, Rorty defines `foundationalism' as a
that `non-cognitivism' is actually an inappropriate
type of moral doctrine which tries to find indepen-
term to characterise it (Blackburn, 1996, p. 82). He
dently verifiable truths (usually about human nature)
claims it is compatible with a notion of `best moral
from which our moral intuitions may be directly
sensibility', derivable thus: conceptualise one's current
inferred. Although constructivism affirms the idea
moral perspective and all possible rival perspectives as
of `moral knowledge as well, it is clear that moral
akin to the structure of a tree in the following way.
realism is really what is signified here; cf. the reference
The `trunk' contains all of those features that we
at n. 11.
would think any acceptable moral perspective would
11. Ibid., p. 172.
have to hold. It is this that provides the content of
12. Ibid., pp. 171±3.
what he says we can legitimately claim to know as
13. Ibid., p. 176 and passim. It is possible to argue that
moral truth. Thereafter, the trunk branches out, in so
Rorty need not have gone as far as he does in
far as we conceptualise the perspectives diverging in
provisionally adopting non-cognitivism because his
their attitudes from this shared core. Blackburn thinks
sentimentalist approach to moral conversion is com-
it is possible to remove the possibility of branching: if
patible with the form of realism, defended by John
my perspective branches out because I believe that A
McDowell, which holds that, although moral proper-
is better than B while I acknowledge the possibility of
ties inhere in their objects independently of our
a perspective that says B is better than A, I have the
attitudes, they can only be perceived when one is
following choices: I can stick to my current belief, in
suitably disposed attitudinally. See, for example, his
which case the alternative disappears from my `tree' as
`Values and Secondary Qualities' and `Projection and
a candidate for a suitable sensibility; or I concede its
Truth in Ethics', in McDowell (1998), pp. 131±50 and
validity, in which case my branch should disappear.
pp. 151±66, respectively.
Alternatively, I concede the merits of both cases, in
160
PRAGMATIST LIBERALISM AND THE EVASION OF POLITICS
which case I should improve upon my current belief
sion of Kuwait and not China for its occupation of
that A is better than B: again, this branch should
Tibet? We need hardly be ignorant of the cynicism
disappear. Now it must be a matter of considerable
that doubtless enters into the politics of intervention
doubt as to whether this could plausibly yield a single
to query which moral direction this point is supposed
set of moral truths, or whether the label of `truth' is
to take us. If the argument is that we should never
simply being used rhetorically to affirm a suitably
sanction humanitarian intervention unless we consis-
refined set of attitudes. For this reason, we leave this
tently apply the same moral considerations in every
issue aside in the present analysis.
other like instance, one must wonder whether the
30. Rorty (1998), p. 185.
proper object of moral concern hasn't been entirely
31. Ibid., pp. 167±9.
misplaced here. Would the Kosovar Albanians or the
32. Martha Nussbaum is arguably the most prominent
East Timorese thank us for leaving them entirely alone
exponent of literature's value in shaping people's
to their fate, appreciating that we are primarily con-
moral sentiments; see Nussbaum (1995).
cerned that our own precious moral consistency might be impugned if we intervened on their behalf while
33. Rorty, `The Priority of Democracy to Philosophy' in
continuing to tolerate the rights violations of the
Malachowski (ed.) (1990), p. 288.
Chinese state?
34. In practice non-cognitivism has usually been aligned
40. See Daniels (1996), chapter 2 for the concept of wide
with some version of the liberal view that the consent
reflective equilibrium.
of those subject to power legitimises its exercise.
41. I criticise the concept of public-justificatory liberalism
35. Mouffe (1993), chapters 3, 9.
in Evans (1999).
36. In a much-debated passage, Rawls concedes that imposition of fundamental liberal values upon a steadfast
42. Carl Schmitt famously offers a version of this critique,
anti-liberal (a violent religious fundamentalist, for
claiming that liberalism's claims to embody objective
example) may be necessary if the latter is incapable
moral truths conflicts with democracy's claim that
of accepting the principles (Rawls, 1996, p. 152).
legitimacy is based upon the collective will of the
Although it is significant that Rawls's theory does
people, thus making `liberal democracy' philosophi-
not recoil from the advocacy of coercion, this case
cally oxymoronic and, in a fractured social world,
appears to be sufficiently marginal and exceptional in
practically
Rawls's mind not to need systematic analysis and
(1996), chapter 8. 43. Isaiah
justification (or so he thinks). My suggestion here is
unworkable.
Berlin
observes
For that
analysis, `the
see
very
Larmore
desire
for
that politics may be a lot more agonistic and antag-
guarantees that our values are eternal and secure
onistic than he presumes, and the coercive (as opposed
in some objective heaven is perhaps only a craving
to consensual) resolution of political conflict is far
for the certainties of childhood, or the absolute
more central to everyday politics than Rawls believes.
values
See, in this regard, Rawls (1999), pp. 529±64, where
172. If this is so, then the need for foundationalist
he sketches the possibility of an internationalist `law of
belief may not be dispensable, though some anti-
peoples', including a scheme of basic human rights.
foundationalists would put this down to an inability
Although applicable to all humans, Rawls recognises
to
that perhaps not all societies could agree to affirm such
manner. Certainly, a purely evaluative conviction
a law; in their case, he says, there is in principle no
may be vulnerable to dissolution through the waning
peaceful solution except a modus vivendi, `the domina-
of attitudes, but yet again there is not quite the
tion of one side or the peace of exhaustion' (ibid., p.
unfavourable contrast with realist convictions that
564). At this point, perhaps, we have nothing other
one might think. Crises of faith (sometimes term-
than Rorty-type contingent attitudes by which to
inal) in examples of the latter are, after all, familiar
orientate political responses to such societies.
enough to challenge the foundationalists' argument
live
of
our
primitive
without
holding
past':
values
Berlin
in
an
(1969),
p.
erroneous
that their form of moral conviction is that much
37. This, of course, simplifies and glosses over a lot of
more insulated from doubt.
issues. I merely sketch the outline of a possible argu-
44. I would like to thank John Torrance and Roger Crisp
ment, to allow swift passage to the particular problem I
for comments on a distant ancestor of this chapter
wish to address. 38. See Parekh (1997) and Mu È llerson (1997), pp. 164±5
which helped to shape its current form. Thanks are
for some possible conditions for justifiable interven-
owed as well to the participants at the 1999 University
tion.
of Wales Swansea political theory conference at Gregynog, and in particular Bruce Haddock, for valuable
39. A familiar criticism of interventionist actions by wes-
discussion.
tern powers is that realpolitik produces hypocritical selectivity: for example, why attack Iraq for its inva-
161
12
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY Bruce Haddock
Liberals, or at least theorists concerned to defend
(purely contingent) national tradition. Liberals may
liberal political positions, have in the last decade
express their loyalty in terms of doctrinal commit-
seemed peculiarly diffident about the foundational
ments. But once they recognise the fragility of the
arguments which were once the stock-in-trade of
assumptions they have made (regarding progress,
liberal theory. Rawls's defection from foundational-
rationality, personal autonomy and so on), they
ism in Political Liberalism is the most celebrated (and
are bound to accept that the sources of their attach-
arresting) case of a phenomenon which is wider and
ment are cultural rather than philosophical. There
deeper, going to the heart of what we might mean by
may well be decisive practical reasons for endorsing
normative political philosophy.
1
Rawls continues to
liberal institutions and practices as the best means of
espouse a comprehensive liberal doctrine, but he is
preserving and developing the advantages which
anxious to show that terms of political cooperation
accrue from flourishing civil societies. But such a
can be defended independently of the particular
defence could never be more than conditional and
comprehensive doctrine he happens to endorse.
certainly could not assume the guise of a deontological theory.
Other theorists (Rorty and Gray have been prominent here) defend the institutions and values of
Closer inspection, however, reveals that these
the liberal communities they happen to have grown
retreats from foundational argument are far from
2
Rorty's
clear-cut. Rawls is the most interesting case, since
liberal ironist can delight in the cultural diversity
he accepts that the resources of comprehensive
which confronts him, enriching the heritage through
doctrines can be used to defend a liberal political
complex description rather than analysis. Sentimen-
consensus. His concern is to ensure that a particular
tal stories may be said to enhance possibilities for
political consensus should not be identified with any
self-understanding. They do not furnish rules to live
particular comprehensive doctrine. Clearly he is
by. Rules which purport to be theoretically defen-
trying to walk a fine line here. As Leif Wenar has
sible are in fact simply arbitrary conventions which
recently pointed out, a (supposedly) non-conten-
facilitate mutual enjoyment. But they do not facil-
tious notion of reasonableness is being asked to do
itate everybody's enjoyment. The pretence that ar-
a great deal of work.
bitrary conventions are necessary conditions for a
distinguish theoretically between reasonable and
just society is one of the principal foundational
unreasonable pluralisms, though in practice crude
illusions that the liberal ironist is concerned to
political judgements about what should or should
dispel.
not be tolerated are made all the time. Similar
up in, but for purely contingent reasons.
3
It is extremely difficult to
Gray's position (at least in his more recent writ-
problems arise when we try to distinguish reasonable
ings) is more straightforward. He simply asserts that
from unreasonable comprehensive doctrines. Is it
attachment to liberalism is a function of loyalty to a
simply the case that any comprehensive doctrine
162
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY
9
which endorses a reasonable political consensus (for
tent of natural law' for support.
whatever reasons) is to be adjudged reasonable? Or is
allow, however, is that this `universal minimum
there something about the comprehensive doctrines
content of morality' (whatever it might comprise)
themselves which distinguishes them as reasonable?
should be specifiable in theoretical terms which
Wenar argues that the conception of political rea-
could serve as a normative foundation for a variety
sonableness Rawls invokes is comprehensive (Kan-
of political settlements.
tian)
that value incommensurability is an irreducible fea-
rather
than
limited,
excluding
not
only
10
What he cannot
Following Berlin, he insists
11
fundamentalists and fanatics from a reasonable prin-
ture of pluralist societies.
cipled consensus but also Catholics, Hobbesians and
what we confront in the last resort is existential
Humeans.
4
In this scheme of things,
Wenar's solution is to make the concep-
choice unaided by practical reason. The appeal to a
tion of political reasonableness even more limited,
`minimum content of natural law' or a `universal
thus making it non-contentious from the perspective
minimum content of morality' does no normative
of comprehensive doctrines. But in that situation it is
work here.
unlikely that comprehensive doctrines would gen-
Rorty makes fewer concessions to even a residual
erate the kind of principled support for a political
foundationalism. But it is worth noting in passing
consensus which would transform a modus vivendi
that when he claims that (for liberals) `cruelty is the
into a principled agreement. It would also make
worst thing we do', he is invoking an evaluative
Rawls even more vulnerable to critics who argue
criterion which is far from clear in its meaning and
that political liberalism requires more rather than less
scope.
foundational support.
5
12
Mill scholars have always recognised that
the relevant sense of `harm' for liberal theory needs
What is clear is that Rawls
13
himself insists that some sort of bridge between a
to be specified carefully.
political consensus and reasonable comprehensive
Kekes has argued that priority can only be accorded
doctrines is indispensable to his position, citing
to the claims of cruelty at the cost of undermining
Hart's notion of `the minimum content of natural
the specifically liberal character of a state.
law' as an example of the kind of argument he has in
point to insist on here is that assertion of the
mind.
6
And more recently John
14
The
significance of cruelty in liberal doctrine needs to be supported by argument. It is vacuous as a simple
Gray's position is ambivalent in precisely the same
description of liberal sensibilities.
way. He feels free to equate `a commitment to the
What we see emerging here is a series of more or
preservation of civil society' with `a commitment to 7
And though he
less reluctant adjustments to a minimal foundation-
accepts that association on these terms `may be only
alism, couched often in such broad terms that the
one of the diverse forms of flourishing our species has
idea of a foundation serves no normative function.
achieved', he nevertheless defends a form of civil
This in itself is philosophically interesting, even if it
society as not only `the best in our cultural inheri-
impinges hardly at all on the more immediate prac-
tance' but also `the best that the species can presently
tical concerns of political theorists. It is surely sig-
the maintenance of civilisation.'
8
Having withdrawn from lib-
nificant that allusions to Hart's `minimum content of
eral universalism, then, he continues to defend a
natural law' are often made in passing, as if discussion
position which is far broader than the discrete
at the most general level could have no implications
traditions which have sustained modern western
for the claim that liberal values are contingent. And
political culture. Certainly civil society can be en-
it must be said that the way Hart presents his case
dorsed from within these traditions but cannot be
rather encourages that view. The `minimum content
identified with them. And to specify even in the
of natural law' is not a contentious conclusion to an
broadest formal terms what human beings as a species
elaborate argument, but a series of `simple truisms'
might `reasonably hope for' surely takes us beyond
which afford reasons for adopting legal and moral
the contingent theoretical resources of particular
practices.
cultures.
viability of any legal system, rather than with the
reasonably hope for.'
Like Rawls, Gray turns to Hart's `minimum con-
15
Hart's concern in this section is with the
desirability of a liberal system or any other variant. In
163
BRUCE HADDOCK
The Concept of Law Hart treats (almost exclusively)
We may say, at the very least, that recognition of
liberal discussions of law within the broader context
mutual vulnerability commits us to the adoption of
of legal order as such. My concern in this chapter is
some rules of social cooperation. These rules may be
to reverse the direction of the argument in order to
many and varied and may in substance be wholly
develop the normative implications of a formal legal
arbitrary. But that there should be some rules may be
framework. My claim is that reflection on the idea of
said to be a defining characteristic of a society. Given
a formal legal framework furnishes grounds for pre-
that societies with (necessarily) limited understand-
ferring certain forms of political or legal order to
ing and scarce resources will have to make hard
others. I do not claim that only liberal political
choices, we must assume that they will have author-
orders are defensible, or that all forms of liberal order
itative procedures for allocating resources. Govern-
are
philosophical
ment of some kind will have to be carried on, even if
grounds for preferring to manage public affairs in a
a formal specification of institutional roles is not
context of liberal institutions and practices.
developed. But, of course, to recognise the necessity
desirable,
only
that
there
are
What Hart focuses on in the brief passage on natural
of government in certain circumstances is not to
law which has been cited so frequently is the con-
endorse any particular kind of government. Hart is
tingent predicament in which all societies find them-
concerned to do no more in his discussion of the
selves. Adapting arguments from Hobbes and Hume,
minimum content of natural law than to set before
he depicts a context which must inform the moral and
his readers the general predicament to which all legal
legal reflection of all communities, anywhere. Indi-
and moral schemes must respond; he is interested in
vidual vulnerability to personal attack, relative equal-
questions of viability rather than desirability. And
ity (such that even the weak can threaten the strong
even Hume, whose discussion of justice has the
through stealth), limited altruism, limited resources,
conveniences of commercial society in mind, offers
limited understanding and suchlike put clear con-
generic principles which all viable societies will have
straints on the kinds of institutions and practices
to endorse. On the face of it, little follows from the
which could (in principle) be devised to sustain social
`three fundamental laws of nature' which constitute
life. We can imagine situations in which these restric-
justice for Hume.
tions would not apply. We can fantasise about heaven
must sustain `stability of possession' without specify-
on earth, where both resources and goodwill are
ing precise terms on which property might be en-
superabundant. But whatever arrangements people
joyed.
in that happy situation might devise for their delight,
`transference by consent' is simply to insist that there
we can assume that distributive and coercive proce-
should be some procedural rules, not that any specific
dures would not be among them. Politics as we know it
rules should be deemed to be appropriate.
would simply not be necessary. At the other extreme,
third dimension of justice (`the performance of pro-
as Hume argued, absolute scarcity renders conven-
mises') is more fruitful.
tional institutions and practices redundant. Where
stress the utility of promise-keeping, but reflection
starvation is a likely prospect, we cannot assume that
on the constitutive role of truthfulness in any con-
the law of property would be greatly respected. As
ception of agency extends the discussion to the
Hume expressed the point, in a dire emergency `the
necessary requirements of intelligible agency.
19
18
Similarly,
We can grant that all societies
to
21
move
from
possession
20
to
The
Hume himself may want to
strict laws of justice are suspended . . . and give place
The key issue here is not how particular practices
to the stronger motives of necessity and self-preserva-
(like promising) might be justified but what makes
tion.'
16
practices
In the ordinary way of things, of course, we are
possible.
Following
Wittgenstein
and
not faced with such stark dilemmas, except in cases
Winch, we have come to accept a capacity for rule
where regimes actually break down. What Hart asks us
following as a constitutive feature of human con-
to consider is the normative impact of truths that are
duct.
`contingent on human beings and the world they live
course of their lives and that we can make reasonable
in retaining the salient characteristics which they
predictions about what people might do from a basis
have.'
22
17
We know that things happen to people in the
of crude generalisation. But doing things involves
164
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY
applying criteria, and these criteria consist of (more
speak. We also acquire a rudimentary understanding
or less formally acknowledged) social rules. It is
of how we should respond to other speakers. The use
important to stress that we do not need to be able
of a language is thus a social engagement which
to specify the rules we are following in order to be
commits us to much more than a basic set of
said to be following rules. Wittgenstein classically
grammatical rules.
focuses on the grammar of a language as a framework
Lyotard, among others, has stressed the insepar24
of rules which enable us to speak. Children can use a
ability of speaking and listening.
language before they can analyse sentences. And we
societies devise complex ways (ritually and profes-
can imagine languages which have never been ana-
sionally) of limiting rights to speak about certain
lysed by anyone. The users of such languages can
matters. If someone were systematically denied the
nevertheless be said to be following rules even if the
right to speak on any occasion, however, they would
rules have not been formally specified. If they juxta-
effectively have been reduced to the status of a non-
pose sounds in a wholly arbitrary way they will not be
person, irrespective of whatever else might happen to
understood. Children acquiring the language will be
them. In this sense, some basic rights accompany
corrected by adults, though the adults may not be
language use. Rights can, of course, be forfeited
able to specify the linguistic rule which had been
through wrongdoing. But recognition of a prima facie
wrongly applied. We may expect the range of prac-
case to be heard can be justified simply by focusing
tical usage to be wide in a language which is wholly
on the logic of conversation. It would be absurd to
informal. But informal rules remain rules, specifiable
claim that everyone had a right to take part in any
in principle even if they have not been specified in
conversation, even in principle. I simply do not
practice. We simply cannot conceive of a language
know enough about brain surgery or football to insist
which is not (in some sense) rule-bound. It is surely
that my voice should be heard. Yet to be denied the
significant that we assume that anyone could (in
right to participate in any conversation would be
principle) learn any language. They may not be
tantamount to being excluded from all human com-
taught rules but they know how to carry on making
munity. Such things may be thought desirable in
meaningful sounds.
exceptional circumstances, but they would always
The framework of rules implicit in any language
have to be justified in terms of some conception of
may appear to be entirely neutral. Yet, as Winch has
human flourishing.
argued, a presupposition of truthfulness is a basic requirement of any language.
23
We know that
Just how far this sort of reflection can take us is a
People tell lies and
much-disputed question. Few modern philosophers
deceive one another because it can be assumed that
would want to follow Hegel's attempt in the Philo-
(on the whole) they mean what they say. He stresses,
sophy of Right to defend the necessity of a specific
too, that using a language is a practical engagement
institutional framework from a series of reflections on
in which commitments are made to other people.
the character of human agency. Yet it may well be
When children are taught a language they are at the
that what we should be worried about in Hegel is not
same time inducted into the ways of a form of life.
so much the ambition of the project as the detailed
The rules which constitute the form of life could not
development of the argument. Modern readers tend
be specified in abstract fashion. What we have,
not to find the elaborate deductive structure of the
instead, is a series of overlapping practices, not all
Philosophy of Right helpful. It should be clear, how-
of them mutually supportive, which yield a sense of
ever, that when he asks us in the compressed in-
how to carry on, how to respond to other people,
troduction to reflect on what we might mean by
what to expect of oneself.
agency, what we presuppose about human conduct
Language is instructive to us here as an illustration
when we make choices, how we should regard
of a natural practice. We do not choose to learn our
ourselves in relation to the cultures that sustain
first language, we may have little or no understand-
us, he is raising questions which any political phi-
ing of the grammatical rules implicit in that lan-
losophy must respond to.
guage, and yet we learn to correct ourselves as we
course, that these issues are always treated self-con-
165
25
It does not follow, of
BRUCE HADDOCK
sciously. For the most part, many basic presupposi-
repudiate all rules and conventions without ceasing
tions will simply be taken for granted in order to
to make sense, even to ourselves.
26
proceed with more specific and practically compel-
The intelligibility of our own conduct thus de-
ling questions. But it remains the case that presup-
pends upon the social dimension of the practices we
positions are made which have different implications
are inducted into. We can envisage an esoteric
for practice.
practice, but it is clearly parasitic on the fact that
Our concern, then, before we consider the institu-
we have been inducted into other practices naturally,
tions and policies we might happen to desire, is to
much as our ability to construct private languages is
explore the necessary requirements which enable
parasitic on the fact that we already know what
practices to flourish. We must assume that these
languages are.
requirements will be very general indeed since we
to be authoritative in some sense that we can be said
know from ordinary experience that different cul-
to engage in intelligible activity. And this applies
tures pursue all manner of ends in a variety of ways.
even if our concern is to revise radically the way a
Our focus should be on what people need to ac-
practice is carried on. The focus again is on how
knowledge in order to attain any satisfaction at all
things are done, not on the specific goals that are
rather than on the things they happen to want. We
pursued.
27
It is only because practices are held
have accepted (following Hobbes, Hume and Hart)
The conception of rules defended here does not
that recognition of mutual vulnerability commits us
depend upon the self-conscious adoption of rules of
to establishing terms of social cooperation. If you do
conduct in particular communities. Our concern is
not accept this point, you can have no interest in
rather with the necessary conditions of intelligible
normative political philosophy.
action. If we are to conceive of societies at all we
The point may be put more strongly. If you regard
must think in terms of rules which constitute prac-
social cooperation as optional or irrelevant, you will
tices. Of course, societies cannot be conceived in
have fundamentally misconceived the idea of human
purely procedural terms. Cultures and subcultures
agency. When we do things we apply and adapt rules
will endorse different conceptions of a worthwhile
and procedures, and these rules and procedures have
life, often pursuing ends which are strictly incom-
a public (social) life even if they are not formally
mensurable. And if we focus on these different ends,
acknowledged. To say or do things deliberately is to
it may be that we will have to accept that certain
apply criteria such that we might wonder whether or
ways of life are incompatible. We may not be able to
not we had said or done the right thing. Following a
find any common ground between deeply held be-
practice necessarily involves the possibility of mak-
liefs. No matter what we might say, however, about
ing a mistake. But it would make no sense to say that
the constitutive values of particular communities, we
it was entirely arbitrary whether or not a mistake had
still have to regard the practices within these com-
been made.
munities as instances of rule-following, even if it has
Practices are thus to be understood in terms of
never occurred to agents to describe their conduct in
rules and conventions which are more or less ade-
this light. They may think of themselves as marion-
quately observed. In relation to any specific engage-
ettes in a display of divine virtuosity, and we must
ment, the rules and conventions are regarded as
refer to these beliefs when we reconstruct their
authoritative. Sometimes (as in a game) the engage-
conduct. But what they are actually doing is making
ment is constituted by specific endorsement of a
decisions, appraising one another's conduct in terms
formal set of rules. You cannot play chess and
of assumptions and standards, correcting each other
repudiate the rules at the same time. The overlap-
when they make mistakes, arguing, reproaching or
ping (and largely informal) rules of social life are
punishing one another for failure to observe appro-
much more difficult to discern. In this case it makes
priate rules and procedures. The things they do can
perfect sense to suspend judgement about certain
be done well or ill, with more or less good faith. But
conventions while continuing to engage in coopera-
simply to say that they are doing something commits
tive projects more or less normally. But we could not
us to certain ways of conceiving of conduct.
166
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY
Oakeshott focuses on the quality of active engage-
understood within liberal theory. The point to focus
ment in his characterisation of a practice as `a
on is that philosophical reflection on the necessity of
prudential or an authoritative adverbial qualification
a minimal foundation may furnish grounds for pre-
of choices and preferences, more or less complicated,
ferring certain political options to others.
in which conduct is understood in terms of a procedure.'
28
Hart himself offers us some help along these lines
The terms of reference here are so broad
in the opening arguments of The Concept of Law. His
that it may be thought that nothing is ruled out. The
modification of the received version of legal positi-
conceptual clarification of what it means to carry on
vism depended largely on his adoption of a rule-
may seem to have no implications whatever for what
following model of law as a practice. Following
we should actually do. But this formal distinction
Wittgenstein and Winch, he sought to highlight
only holds while a practice is conducted within the
the rules (formal or tacit) which enable agents to
recognisable terms of reference of rule following. To
set themselves standards in the conduct of their
behave impulsively or wholly erratically is not to
business. An agent can only ask herself what she
engage in a practice at all, even though observation
ought to do (whether as a judge, a lawyer or a
of such behaviour may generate reasonably accurate
litigant) within the context of a practice constituted
generalisations. And Oakeshott himself, notably in
by procedural rules.
Rationalism in Politics, highlights the ruinous conse-
view (endorsed variously by Hobbes, Bentham, Aus-
quences which follow from misconceptions of hu-
tin and others) of law as an authoritative command
man agency.
29
31
This is not to say that the older
To suppose that all right-thinking
backed by coercive power is wholly redundant. This
people will necessarily endorse the same collective
may well be how law is regarded by people who do
goals, or that we can somehow stand outside all
not acknowledge the authority of a legal system or
practices in order to assess the rationality or desir-
who see themselves as free-riders prepared to exploit
ability of a particular practice, or that liberation from
the passive obedience of others, but it certainly does
the constraints of all conventions or traditions will
not help us to explain what makes conduct within a
somehow set us free, is to conceive of human life as it
legal practice intelligible.
could not possibly be lived. Philosophy, in this
Hart clearly expects his distinction between inter-
scheme of things, can specify the conceptual limits
nal and external perspectives (or rule-following and
of practical life, without telling us how we should
habitual behaviour) to do a great deal of work for
actually live.
him, but he is very cautious about drawing out
The stress on procedural rules should not be
normative implications. This is perfectly intelligible
misunderstood. The claim is not that a minimal
given the overall thrust of his argument. He is
framework is sufficient to sustain a polity, rather
interested in law as such, and not any particular
that the framework provides a basis for different
variety of law which may have emerged in a given
modes of political flourishing. Following Oakeshott,
context. A theory of law that simply reflected the
the framework may be described as `the minimum
culture and values of a particular community would
condition of any settled association among indivi-
(in his terms) be no theory at all. His modification of
30
But no polity actually flourishes on the basis
legal positivism thus involved only a minimal retreat
of minimal conditions alone. What is built upon this
from the moral neutrality which was central to that
minimal (or `weak') foundation will depend upon
theory. His conception of a `minimum content of
the specific (and contingent) features of a given
natural law' is conceived principally as a response to
political culture. The point, however, is that the
the contingent circumstances in which human life is
contingent values of particular cultures may distort
lived. He avoids reference to substantive concep-
or constrain practices which can be shown to be
tions of the good life which had been the stock-in-
constitutive of a flourishing political life. The terms
trade of the traditional theory of natural law. He
of reference here are still very broad indeed. We are
accepts that a formally viable legal system may be
dealing with the possibility of human flourishing
morally reprehensible. The fact that legal rules are
rather than preferences as these have often been
always grafted on to a moral context has (for Hart)
duals.'
167
BRUCE HADDOCK
no implications for the specification of the formal
The crucial distinction at work here is between
requirements of a legal system.
`primary' and `secondary' rules of obligation.
36
It is
Hart makes the point emphatically in his insis-
perfectly possible to envisage a community in which
tence that `the question what the criteria of legal
dealings between people would be regulated exclu-
validity in any legal system are is a question of fact',
sively in terms of customary rules. Social ostracism
stemming from the `rule of recognition' which hap-
clearly constitutes a powerful coercive constraint in
pens to be endorsed in the particular system.
32
A rule
contexts where alternative lifestyles are not avail-
of recognition may be complex (as in an elaborate
able. In a purely customary society one is not faced
juridical culture such as the United States) or for-
with choices between options but with more or less
mally straightforward (whatever the Queen in Par-
reluctant compliance. But, as Hart makes clear, such
liament enacts will be recognised as law in the
arrangements of unofficial rules can only work in `a
United Kingdom) or simplistic (the tyrant's will,
small community closely knit by ties of kinship,
Rex I in Hart's example,
common sentiment, and belief, and placed in a stable
law).
33
will be taken
to be
environment.'
Hart's point is that we can make sense of
37
Customary rules are simply given.
each of these legal systems in terms of criteria
As soon as we start wondering about their desir-
furnished by a rule of recognition, though in each
ability, we introduce hypothetical considerations
case the rule of recognition may be arbitrary. `Its
which may be contentious. The need to accommo-
existence', Hart insists, `is a matter of fact.'
34
date change of any kind obliges us to make judge-
What I
want to suggest, however, is that it makes the world
ments.
of difference that what we are talking about here is a
rudimentary level of social organisation. The point
Our
concern
here
is
with
the
most
rule. To be sure, the whim of Rex I constitutes a rule
to stress is simply that a (hypothetical) customary
only in the most primitive sense. But recognising
society ceases to function effectively when alterna-
that it is the existence of a rule which makes public
tive possibilities are made available. Disputes about
cooperation possible gives us grounds, all other
ends have to be settled somehow (through fighting,
things being equal, to prefer a rule which is more
ritual manipulation, social pressure or whatever). But
predictable in its operation rather than less.
it soon becomes evident that ordinary business re-
Hart's description of his work in the preface of The
quires authoritative procedures. Practical judgements
Concept of Law as `an essay in descriptive sociology' is
cannot be made in chronically uncertain situations.
35
It is better seen as an
The introduction of these authoritative procedures
exercise in normative theory extending beyond the
(or `secondary rules') constitutes, for Hart, `a step
normal confines of ideological dispute. Indeed the
from the pre-legal into the legal world'.
thus seriously misleading.
38
tension which some commentators have seen in
Note that the transition to a `legal world' is not a
Hart's work between his conceptions of critical
choice in any ordinary sense. We may regard dif-
morality and analytical jurisprudence can be easily
ferent legal rules as more or less useful or desirable,
resolved if the normative dimension of analytical
but we cannot reject the idea of legal rules without
jurisprudence is acknowledged. The point to insist
undermining our capacity to function as agents in
on is simply that the minimal criteria which enable
complex contexts. The notion of returning to a
us to identify a legal system will be more or less
`pre-legal' situation is no more than a nostalgic
effectively embodied in actual legal systems. Quite
fantasy. In an unfashionable speculative sense, we
how far this could take us in the critical amendment
may be said to have crossed a divide between kinds
of legal or constitutional practices is an open (and
of civilisation. The assumptions which enable cul-
contentious) question. But if it is accepted that
tures to function at this level are not choices or
predictability and transparency are essential to the
preferences. They are, rather, the `presuppositions'
furtherance of cooperative pursuits among autono-
or `hinges' without which we simply could not carry
mous strangers, then it is clear that we do have
on.
grounds for preferring certain institutional proce-
39
The claim that philosophical reflection on the
dures to others.
necessity of a legal framework is at the same time a
168
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY
justification of legal order should not itself be con-
Nor is there any suggestion that `true fictions' are
tentious. We can easily appreciate that a pure theory
unchanging. What needs to be presupposed in order
of legal order would not loom large in a society that
to make sense of ordinary experience will change
happened to display an overwhelming consensus
with the variety of circumstances, but not as a matter
around a substantive conception of the good. But
of taste or fashion and some very basic assumptions
it clearly would not follow that legal order depended
may be more or less invariable. The point, however,
upon such a substantive consensus. In practical
is that we cannot specify what will be assumed to be
terms, we simply have to accept a plurality of de-
invariable before critical enquiry begins. It would be
fensible values as a starting point for our reflections.
very odd if someone (other than a mischievous
Recognition of the contingency of values at this
philosopher) were to deny that things happen at
level, however, does not rule out the possibility that
some time in some place. And while we can conceive
more binding philosophical reasons might be ad-
of a human world in which moral choices were
vanced in defence of a political order which made
somehow unreal, we would nevertheless be surprised
diversity manageable.
(as a matter of fact) to learn that languages existed
Examples of the kind of argument I have in mind
without an imperative mood. At some level we
will be familiar to everyone from the canon of
picture human association as a matter of agents
`classics' of political philosophy. To be sure, the
making choices which affect others, even if a capa-
usual suspects among the classics constitute a motley
city for making autonomous choices is not greatly
crew. We find arguments ranging from the most
prized within a particular culture.
abstract accounts of conditions of theoretical intel-
The significance of agency for an understanding of
ligibility to detailed moral and political prescriptions
morality can be easily granted. What this concession
for proper conduct in everyday life, informed by
may commit us to at the political or institutional
personal obsessions which are (in some cases) laugh-
level is much less clear. At the very least, we must
able or contemptible. But this is just to recognise that
accept that intelligible agency depends upon stability
classics of political philosophy operate at many
of expectations. Stability, of course, can be attained
different levels, and that matters of philosophical
in all sorts of ways. There are stable expectations in
interest are sometimes concealed in the most un-
prisons and monasteries, yet it would be odd to
likely places. Whatever else might be going on in
regard either as models of social and political life.
such texts, we nevertheless find attempts to specify
Leviathan also secures stability, but at a price modern
what would need to be true about human beings
liberals have been reluctant to pay. If we supposed,
living in communities if the ordinary things they
however, with Hobbes, that an anarchic and un-
take for granted are to make any sense at all. This, of
predictable state of nature was the only alternative to
course, is not necessarily what political philosophers
authoritarian government, then we may accept that
always suppose they are doing, especially in cultures
authorising a sovereign to lay down binding rules was
untroubled by the `burdens of judgement'.
40
a small price to pay for a measure of `commodious
But we
living'.
go back to them as philosophers precisely because certain sorts of problems necessarily arise when we
In the ordinary way of things, we are not con-
take the justification of terms of social cooperation
fronting Hobbes's dilemma. We are faced with more
seriously. Oakeshott put the point nicely in a cele-
or less desirable options in viable political circum-
brated discussion of Hobbes. He defined philosophy
stances. What may be lost from sight is that stress on
as `the establishment by reasoning of true fictions.'
41
what is chosen may obscure the significance of an
Given the things we accept, there are certain notions
institutional context which makes choice possible. It
which simply have to be held to be true. The point is
is a paradox, as Oakeshott has pointed out, that
not that we can give a list of these indubitable truths,
`Hobbes, without being himself a liberal, had in him
rather that critical thinking depends upon presup-
more of the philosophy of liberalism than most of its
positions which can and (at times) must be exam-
professed defenders.'
ined.
significance of stability in contexts in which agree-
169
42
Recognition of the overriding
BRUCE HADDOCK
ment about ends cannot be expected does not
inappropriate or meaningless would surely cripple
commit us to Hobbesian measures. Stability of ex-
our critical endeavours.
pectations may also be achieved in legal orders which guarantee basic rights.
43
The implications of this view are wide-ranging
Philosophical interest fo-
and cannot be developed in any detail here. Even
cuses on the fact that we should have rights, not
if the radical contingency of liberal values and
simply on the specific rights we happen to value.
institutions is granted, we are still left with the
It remains the case, of course, that urgent and
problem of explaining what it means to make hard
contentious theoretical issues are raised when we
choices in contexts where binding decisions have
consider the sorts of rights that should be enshrined
to be made. For the most part, we can accept that
in a modern legal system. And at the policy level,
reasons which are regarded as compelling within a
too, it is by no means clear how a foundational
tradition may have little purchase beyond it. But
commitment to agency should be translated into
traditions are no more self-contained than lan-
concrete proposals for educational and health provi-
guage-games or forms of life. It is precisely when
sion, taxation and so on. Even theorists who share a
terms of reference are challenged that more basic
broadly neo-Kantian approach to these questions
forms of justification are called for. In these cases,
will diverge widely in their views on the role of
we have to give reasons for our choices which
44
Philosophical agreement
extend beyond the values we happen to have. We
is thus much more likely on the priority of liberty
do not have to presuppose that stark moral or
than (say) the difference principle.
theoretical dilemmas can always be resolved satis-
the state in specific areas.
factorily, only that we have to appeal to (some-
What I am defending here is the idea of a philosophy
thing like) practical reason whenever we are asked
through ideology to policy questions, rather than
to give a public justification of our preferences.
a categorial distinction between philosophy and
What makes liberalism distinctive is not so much
other modes of theoretical concern. Relations of
the rationalism that critics have often focused on as
entailment
spectrum;
the institutional procedures which have been de-
rather, we are dealing with compatibility in relation
vised to facilitate agreement in pluralist contexts.
spectrum
which
do
runs
not
from
obtain
political
along
the 45
The signifi-
My claim, then, is that a logic of practical reason is
cance of political philosophy at the level of policy is
at work whenever hard choices are made. Where
unlikely
to what Rawls terms `lexical order'.
political
liberal theory goes astray is in treating the strong
cultures. But contentious issues (such as abortion
version of practical reason that has emerged in
in the United States or welfare in Britain) cannot
pluralist societies as the ideal form for the resolution
be adequately handled without confronting (what
of public disputes in any context. If my argument is
still might properly be called) foundational ques-
correct a weak foundationalism, drawn from reflec-
tions. If we ask ourselves how the citizen should
tion on the necessary formal requirements for viable
stand in relation to the state in a modern polity, we
agency, can be seen to be at work in the positions of
are inviting reflection at a number of different
sceptical liberals even when they are reluctant to
levels. We could be concerned with the obligation
acknowledge the fact. To be sure, the idea of a
of parents to ensure that their children are educated
philosophical foundation invoked here is very gen-
and law-abiding or the obligation of the state to
eral indeed. Most regularian polities could be de-
provide support for the destitute or wider questions
fended along these lines. And, of course, no polity is
of shared responsibility for the conduct of public
merely regularian. My contention, however, is that
life. It would be too much to expect a seamless web
awareness of the necessary conditions for any polity
of doctrine to run through these questions. But the
to flourish does provide grounds for tempering more
claim that philosophical discussion is irrelevant,
narrowly ideological preferences.
to
be
intrusive
in
consensual
170
LIBERALISM AND CONTINGENCY
Notes
1. Rawls (1996).
17. Hart (1961), p. 195.
2. See Rorty (1989); Gray (1995a) and (1997).
18. Hume (1969), p. 578.
3. See Wenar (1995).
19. Ibid.
4. See ibid., pp. 60±1.
20. Ibid.
5. See Bellamy and Hollis (1995).
21. Ibid.
6. See Rawls (1996), pp. 109, 161, and Hart (1961), pp.
22. See Wittgenstein (1968) and Winch (1958). 23. See Winch (1972), especially pp. 61±3.
189±195. 7. Gray (1993), p. 328.
24. See Lyotard (1993), pp. 135±47.
8. Ibid., p. 328.
25. See Hegel (1991). For further discussion see Haddock (1993) and my `Hegel's Critique of the Theory of
9. Gray (1995a), p. 81.
Social Contract', in Boucher and Kelly (eds) (1994),
10. Ibid., p. 81.
pp. 147±63.
11. See Gray (1995b). Whether Gray is right to portray Berlin precisely as he does is, of course, another ques-
26. See Wittgenstein (1969).
tion. He draws attention (ibid., p. 14) to Berlin's claim
27. See `Can There Be a Private Language?', in Rhees (1970), pp. 55±70.
that `our conscious idea of man . . . involves the use of some among the basic categories in terms of which we
28. Oakeshott (1975a), p. 55.
perceive and order and interpret data.' And he is clear
29. See Oakeshott (1962) and, for discussion, Haddock (1996).
that these `basic categories' are neither empirical nor formal in any straightforward sense. Gray is happy to
30. Oakeshott (1975b), p. 62.
describe this as `a sort of quasi-Kantian transcendental
31. See Hart (1961), pp. 54±60.
deduction' (ibid., p. 14), without dwelling on the
32. Ibid., pp. 107, 245.
implications this might have for radical value pluralism.
33. See ibid., pp. 97±8.
In `Does Political Theory Still Exist?', however, Berlin
34. Ibid., p. 107.
also describes these `basic categories' as `universal ± or
35. Ibid., p. vii.
almost universal ± values'. See Berlin (1978), p. 166.
36. See ibid., pp. 77±96.
And in all his later writings he was careful to distinguish
37. Ibid., p. 89.
pluralism from relativism. See his `Alleged Relativism
38. Ibid., p. 91.
in Eighteenth-Century European Thought', in Berlin
39. The terminology here is drawn from Collingwood (1940), pp. 3±77, and Wittgenstein (1969), p. 44.
(1991), pp. 70±90. Berlin's sympathy for the variety of modes of human flourishing was always coupled with
40. See Rawls (1996), pp. 54±8.
recognition of the appalling cost of political folly,
41. Oakeshott (1975b), p. 25.
especially in the twentieth century. And he never
42. Ibid., p. 63.
wavered from the view that it was the responsibility
43. See Martin (1993).
of the political philosopher to specify the normative
44. Consider, for example, the contrasting positions of Rawls (1996), O'Neill (1996), Nozick (1974) and
limits of a defensible pluralism.
Hayek (1960).
12. Rorty (1989), p. 146.
45. Rawls (1972), pp. 42±8. A useful distinction between
13. See Rees (1985). 14. See Kekes (1996).
the philosophy and ideology of liberalism is also
15. Hart (1961), p. 189.
mooted but not defended in detail in Croce (1973),
16. Hume (1966), p. 186.
pp. 235±43 and 263±7.
171
This page intentionally left blank
Part Five LIBERALISM VERSUS REPUBLICANISM?
This page intentionally left blank
13
BACK TO THE FUTURE: PLURALISM AND THE REPUBLICAN ALTERNATIVE TO LIBERALISM Richard Bellamy
Contemporary societies are irreducibly pluralist.
1
general laws which constrains and provides the basis
Their growing differentiation and complexity gen-
for the operations of democratic institutions and the
erate a variety of interests, ideals, cultures and values.
economic market. However, if different liberties em-
This pluralism manifests itself in the wide range of
body incommensurable views of human flourishing,
ethnic, religious, ideological, occupational and other
as pluralists believe, then a clash of liberties will place
allegiances of citizens. The resulting diversity creates
this doctrine in trouble. No metric will be available to
potential conflicts between groups of people holding
adjudicate between different sets of liberties and show
different views and within single individuals. For
which combination most maximises freedom. Earlier
differing ends, outlooks and evaluations may prove
liberals avoided this problem by holding to a histori-
logically or practically incompatible and involve
cist faith in the progress of society. A view still held
incommensurable types of moral claim.
2
4
These ten-
implicitly and occasionally explicitly by many liberals
sions are the lifeblood of current democratic politics
today, this thesis assumes pluralism fosters autonomy
and its greatest challenge. Clashes of opinion and
and that an invisible hand reconciles the various
interest provide the rationale for democracy, yet
heterogeneous ends pursued by individuals in mu-
taken to extremes can make it totally unworkable.
tually supportive ways. Today's complex and diverse
5
Liberalism presents itself as the appropriate poli-
societies render such solutions sociologically unten6
tical form for such conditions. After all, its origins lie
able as well as theoretically debatable.
in the religious conflicts of early modern Europe and
spheres of life and world-views generate competing
the class struggles of the centuries that followed.
and conflicting ethical codes, goals and commit-
Liberalism tries to accommodate difference by pro-
ments. Worse, the very principles of liberalism can
tecting each person's capacity to pursue his own good
collide and are themselves subject to a plurality of
in his own way to the extent that is compatible with
incommensurable evaluations and interpretations.
the similar pursuits of others. According to the
Witness the debates over issues such as abortion,
standard liberal formula, this proposal involves seek-
freedom of information and social rights between
ing the maximal set of equal liberty rights capable of
rival factions within the liberal camp. Consequently,
3
being held by all.
Different
liberalism cannot hold the ring for such disputes. It is
These rights are usually to be
within, not above, the fray.
secured by a constitutional framework of universal,
175
RICHARD BELLAMY
To accommodate plurality requires an alternative
contract designed to legitimate the state's monopoly
approach, one I dub democratic liberalism. Of re-
of violence. According to this argument, free and
publican inspiration, it eschews a pre-political con-
equal citizens would only consensually submit to a
sensus on basic liberties for political negotiation
polity that removed the uncertainties of the state of
aimed at a fair compromise. Instead of relegating
nature while preserving the most extensive set of
the differences that accompany pluralism to the
equal natural liberties. Interference by the state or
private and civil spheres, it gives them public re-
law is only justified to reduce the mutual interfer-
cognition. Republicans view liberty as a civic rather
ences attendant upon social life so as to produce a
than a natural condition. Freedom only exists within
greater liberty over all. The separation of powers
a republican polity where self-government removes
supposedly fosters this aim by preventing any one
the possibility of domination by others through
from being judge in his or her own cause, thereby
allowing citizens to ensure the laws respond to their
constraining the arbitrary and partial framing and
7
various concerns and values. Within pluralist socie-
interpretation of legislation. The rule of men is
ties, these deliberations entail negotiating fair com-
replaced by the rule of universal and equally applic-
promises between the different ideals and interests in
able general laws.
10
play. Such reciprocal decision-making produces laws
Two features of these arrangements are worth
that recognise and reconcile the members of a
highlighting. First, as James Tully has observed,
pluralist polity, enabling them to live on an equitable
the normative consensus assumed by the `modern'
basis with others. Though republicanism and liberal-
liberal conception of constitutionalism hypothesises
ism are historically entwined, with elements of both
a degree of uniformity among the constitutive peo-
present in the political systems of most western
ple.
democracies,
8
11
It assumes that behind different beliefs and
coexistence should not be taken for
customs lies a common human nature, a natural
complementarity or overlap. As I shall argue below,
equality of status, and shared forms of reasoning
republican justifications and conceptions of liberty,
sufficient to generate agreement on constitutional
rights and the rule of law differ from the liberal's in
essentials. What divergences remain are supposedly
important respects ± most especially in relation to
eroded as historical progress leads to more homo-
9
Republicanism
geneous and less stratified societies that conform to a
issues in a democratic liberalism, where liberty and
similar pattern of social and political organisation,
rights are intrinsic to and only achievable through
and stand in contrast to the ranked societies and
democracy, not preconditions for the political pro-
cultural particularisms of the past. Nation-building
cess as liberal democrats contend.
further strengthens this process. As co-nationals, the
the role and nature of democracy.
people share a corporate identity as equal citizens of
The argument proceeds as follows. The next sec-
the polity.
tion analyses the weaknesses of liberal democracy
12
within complex and plural societies, while the suc-
Second, the rights-based approach goes together
ceeding section presents the democratic liberal alter-
with a conception of freedom as non-interference
native. I then present a defence of this proposed
and of the state as a neutral ringmaster, unconcerned
return to the liberties of the ancients against the
with upholding any particular set of values.
charges that it is now both impractical and undesir-
understanding of the constitution encourages in its
able.
turn a purely preference-based picture of the econ-
13
This
omy and an interest-based account of democracy. In each case, what matters is the degree outcomes
Liberal Democracy
correspond to the uncoerced choices and express
Liberal democracy rests on a distinction between the
desires of those concerned. The conditions of pro-
state and civil society. Liberals standardly see con-
duction and the protection of public goods enter
stitutionalism as a normative framework that sets
with difficulty into this view of the economy. The
limits on and goals for the exercise of state power.
first are assumed to be the result of voluntary con-
Traditionally, its principles are grounded in a social
tracts, the latter left up to an invisible hand. Like-
176
BACK TO THE FUTURE
wise, politics becomes a competitive market within
technical, less amenable to general regulations, and
which rival interest groups bargain with each other,
hence harder to control through centralised demo-
and involves no or little attempt to evaluate the
cratic mechanisms. The range and scale of decisions
interests concerned. Its purpose is largely instrumen-
handled by unaccountable specialised bureaucracies,
tal: to protect against incompetent or tyrannous
and involving considerable technocratic discretion,
rulers by allowing their removal, and to aggregate
expands.
individual preferences through majoritarian or con-
As the various areas of social life operate with
sensus voting and encourage politicians to pursue
increasingly distinct and largely self-validating cri-
policies that conform to them.
14
teria, so they become more conflictual. They become
Liberals accept that economy and democracy need
ever more taken up with their own concerns and
regulating when they threaten the constitutional
tend to interpret the world from their own perspec-
structure. However, identifying when such threats
tive, generating incommensurable and incompatible
occur and who possesses the authority to remedy
claims.
them proves problematic. Because the economy
horse-trading proves highly problematic. Clashes
forms part of the private sphere, there are difficulties
of interests appear more zero-sum, and their aggrega-
about whether the requisite interference is either
tion harder to legitimate and enforce because their
legitimate or perpetrates an even greater intrusion
relation to any given collectivity is unclear. Making
into people's lives than those it prevents. Such
and sustaining collective decisions is further com-
decisions cannot necessarily be left up to democratic
plicated by the spread of multiculturalism as im-
governments, since interest groups may use the
proved
state's coercive power to further their personal goals.
pluriethnic as well. Differences of beliefs and iden-
This dilemma raises a further source of tension
tities prove even less amenable to democratic bar-
between the hypothetical consent underlying the
gaining
constitution and the express will of the people.
majorities than economic and social interests. As
Liberals try to avoid this crux by treating the con-
a result, the likelihood of conflict or the oppression
stitution as a `higher' law that provides the precondi-
of minorities rises.
tions
the `normal'
legislation
arising
out
social
and
such
mobility
the
clashes
by
renders
formation
of
democratic
states
stable
and
more
fair
of
Liberals have responded to these failings of de-
democratic politics. They see judicial review by a
mocracy as an instrument for interest aggregation
court buttressed by a bill of rights as the best bulwark
and accountability by advocating the enhanced jur-
against the democratic subversion of the constitu-
idification of politics.
tion.
for
Reconciling
15
18
Worried by the destabilising
effects of pluralism, they look to a legal constitution
Pluralism erodes this liberal settlement. The social
grounded in a consensus on rights and principles of
and economic complexity of advanced societies, and
justice to guarantee the polity stays just. Contem-
the consequent multiplicity of interests and values
porary liberals suggest citizens can trim their diver-
within them, render majoritarian decision-making
gent substantive beliefs on the good to arrive at
more problematic, increase the difficulty of regulat-
agreement on what is politically right.
ing the unaccountable power located in civil society
distinction proves elusive. How and when rights to
and subvert the rights consensus upon which liberal-
privacy and to freedom of speech clash, for example,
ism rests.
16
19
But this
Increased functional differentiation re-
involve invoking notions of the presence and ab-
sults in a proliferation of autonomous centres of
sence of constraints which may be normatively and
17
These centres are capable of making deci-
empirically evaluated from a range of reasonably
sions according to a variety of criteria specific to their
different perspectives, giving divergent answers in
respective domains, with unpredictable knock-on
each case. In pluralist societies, the basic liberties and
effects for other parts of the social and economic
their interpretation become contested matters. In
system. Citizens find themselves locked into a variety
practice, therefore, liberal trimming entails the im-
of these spheres, and get pulled in opposite directions
position of a particular reading of liberalism and the
by the inner logic of each. Problems become more
judicial exclusion of dissident voices. Moreover,
power.
177
RICHARD BELLAMY
without democratic support the constitution and the
agents or agencies with considerable power over
courts risk appearing self-validating and being either
others. For example, attempts to reduce the arbitrary
practically impotent or obliged to adopt coercive
hold men have traditionally exerted over women in
measures. It remains to be seen if a more inclusive
marriage have been challenged on the grounds that
and political strategy is available.
they are too intrusive and themselves involve a greater degree of interference. Similar arguments have been used against laws to protect employees
Democratic Liberalism
from unscrupulous employers. Even social liberals,
Democratic liberalism harks back to a pre-liberal
such as L. T. Hobhouse, accept that the onus of proof
conception of constitutionalism that identified the
rests on the proponents of state intervention to show
constitution with the social composition and form of
that less interference is thereby created overall.
government of the polity.
20
22
Much as we associate a
Republicans by contrast, see debate about the legiti-
person's physical health with his or her bodily con-
macy of interference per se as misconceived. They
stitution and regard a fit individual as someone with
concentrate on providing a non-dominating envir-
a balanced diet and regimen, so a healthy body
onment where citizens can lead secure lives, plan
politic was attributed to a political system capable
ahead and live on a basis of mutual respect ± con-
of bringing its various constituent social groups into
ditions which may require intervention.
23
equilibrium with each other. The aim was to disperse
This view of liberty shapes the republicans' dis-
power so as to encourage a process of controlled
tinctive linkage of the rule of law with the distribu-
political conflict and deliberation that ensured the
tion
various social classes both checked and ultimately
constitution being a precondition for politics, poli-
cooperated with each other, moving them thereby to
tical debate becomes the medium through which a
construct and pursue the public good rather than
polity constitutes itself. This occurs not just in
narrow sectional interests.
exceptional, founding constitutional moments, as
As
Quentin
shown,
21
Skinner
and
Philip
Pettit
have
of
power
and
some liberals grant,
democracy.
24
Instead
of
the
but continuously as part of
the heart of the republican approach lies
an evolving process of mutual recognition. Domina-
in a different conception of freedom to the liberal's.
tion and arbitrary power involve more than an
As I noted, liberty is a civic achievement rather than
infringement of the formal rule of law espoused by
a natural attribute. It results from preventing arbi-
liberals. It is entirely possible to promote general
trary domination rather than an absence of inter-
rules based on whim or self-interest and that entail a
ference tout court. Domination denotes a capacity to
gross curtailment of people's freedom of action. The
intentionally control and diminish an agent's realm
generality and universality requirements can also
of choice, either overtly through various explicit
seem themselves arbitrary if employed to disqualify
forms of restraint or obstruction, or covertly by more
special rules that refer to properties that apply to only
subtle forms of manipulation and influence. Arbi-
some groups ± as when maternity leave for women or
trariness rests in the power to exert domination at
affirmative action policies are accused of being dis-
whim, and without reference to the interests or ideas
criminatory, or when such considerations are used to
of those over whom it is exercised. Pettit notes that
block any form of regulation which might seek to
an absence of interference can be consistent with the
focus on particular contexts or outcomes.
presence of domination. Those with such power may
formal
simply choose not to wield it. Social relations will be
tackling structural forms of domination, where dis-
adversely affected nonetheless. A good king may
crimination and selective blindness have been built
leave his subjects alone but they remain his subjects
into the institutions, norms, social and economic
and will treat him with deference for that reason
relations, and procedures within which the rules are
alone, regardless of whatever merit or demerit he may
framed.
criteria
appear
particularly
25
Such
inadequate
at
possess. Likewise, seeking to reduce interference may
Contemporary liberal jurists try to get around
in given contexts be compatible with leaving certain
these difficulties by adopting a more substantive
178
BACK TO THE FUTURE
view of the rule of law, identifying it with the upholding of rights by an independent judiciary.
to take the form of constructing a distinctive position
26
through argument that seeks to accommodate at
As I noted, this approach proves problematic. A
some level or another the various claims, values
political constitutionalism takes a different tack.
and interests at stake.
Justice becomes identified with the process of poli-
How such compromises are to be achieved will
tics. Political mechanisms not only ensure all are
vary according to the nature of the case. Thus, a
subject to the laws and that no one can be judge in
compromise might take the form of a composite
their own case ± the traditional tasks of the separa-
agreement in which each party gets some but not
tion of powers ± but also that the laws connect with
all of what it wants. This strategy usually proves
the understandings and activities of those to whom
easier when more than one policy is involved.
they are to apply ± the side benefit of dispersing
Because groups often have rather different priorities
power so that more people have a say in its enact-
with regard to a range of policies, it frequently proves
ment. Audi alteram partem forms the watchword of
possible for them to concede on issues they do not
legal fairness, not the formal or substantive properties
feel strongly about but others do in order to obtain
liberals associate with the law.
27
similar concessions from them or other allies on the
`Hearing the other side' within a pluralist polity
matters they regard as most important. Such pro-
implies respecting that people can be reasonably led
cesses are crucial to the log-rolling and coalition-
to incommensurable and incompatible understand-
building practised by political parties. This practice
ings of values and interests, and seeing the need to
does not entail that all views are reducible to inter-
engage with them in terms they can accept. This
ests, as is sometimes assumed. In fact, these sorts of
criterion places constraints on both the procedures
deals are more like bartering than normal bargaining.
and the outcomes of the political process.
28
It obliges
Indeed, they generally occur precisely because people
people to drop purely self-referential or self-inter-
hold a plurality of moral positions that lead them to
ested reasoning and to look for considerations others
evaluate goods and even what constitutes a matter of
can find compelling, thereby ruling out arguments
morality differently ± much as beads can be ex-
that fail to treat all as of equal moral worth. Political
changed for gold when one group's worthless shiny
actors must strive for common ground through mu-
substance is another's valuable commodity. The
tually acceptable modifications. Because the clashes
exchange entails incommensurability, since it might
of principle and preferences associated with plural-
well not have taken place had it been conceived in
ism preclude substantive consensual agreement, po-
standard `more or less' terms, with all goods trans-
litical compromise takes the place of a pre-political
lated into a single common currency. It also proves
consensus.
29
more responsive to intensity of feeling than a simple
The type of compromise, and the style of politics
bargaining model. However, it will only work if those
needed to achieve it, depends on the issue and the
involved can avoid judging particular issues on their
character of the groups involved. Compromise is
merits.
most familiar to us in `more or less' contexts where
When a compromise has to be reached on a single
we can `split the difference' so as to converge on an
issue, such trade-offs cannot be achieved. Moreover,
agreed decision through incremental mutual conces-
a mutual adaptation of views may be highly unsa-
30
Haggling over the price of a commodity such
tisfactory, producing a result that nobody wants
as a house or wage bargaining are typical examples.
rather than something for everyone ± precisely the
Such conflicts, however, are usually along a single
situation critics who accuse compromise of incoher-
dimension and involve a common denominator. As
ence most abhor. One way out of this dilemma,
such, this procedure is unsuited to the conflicts
recently proposed by Robert Goodin, is an agree-
associated with pluralism since it assumes commen-
ment on a second best.
suration. Compromises in `either-or' situations in-
economics, the basic idea is that modifications to
volving plural and competing values and interests
one's preferred option may be less desirable than
prove more exacting but not impossible. They have
obtaining one's next best or an even lower ranked
sions.
179
31
A notion adapted from
RICHARD BELLAMY
choice. A cheap sports car that pretends to be an
presented and the degree of autonomy particular
expensive one may have less appeal than an unpre-
bodies or sections of the community may claim.
tentious family estate, for example. Indeed, indivi-
They are integral to a political constitutionalism,
duals or groups with conflicting first preferences may
with its intimate linking of justice, the rule of law
have shared second preferences. A compromise on
and the democratic dispersal and division of power.
an agreed second best may prove a more coherent
In the ancient ideal of mixed government, the
and acceptable decision, therefore, than an attempt
favoured mechanism was to assign particular govern-
to combine first preferences in ways that transform
mental functions to different social classes. In con-
them out of all recognition or involve inconsisten-
temporary societies, the answer lies in multiplying
cies of various kinds.
the forms of representation and the sites of decision-
When a group makes a claim that involves special
making power.
treatment or imposing burdens on others, they may
As I noted, the key lies in ensuring all sides get a
have to compromise more unilaterally by appealing
hearing so that decisions can be justified to and
either to some norm of equity that the others also
accepted by all citizens. A notion linked to an ideal
share, or to ideals or interests that their interlocutors
of equality of concern and respect, the aim is not
can identify with through appeals to precedent, use
only to render inputs more equitable, but also out-
of analogy or a fortiori arguments.
32
Thus, a religious
comes.
34
On the whole, this goal is more demanding
group seeking public recognition for its beliefs, say in
than simply guaranteeing that everyone has their say
state support for its schools, will be unlikely to get
or gets a piece of the action, important though these
very far if it desires to set up a theocratic state. But
may be in attaining it. When the desired end is
they may be able to invoke a norm of equal treat-
simply to `split the difference', then the proportion-
ment by pointing to the existence of other publicly
ate weighting of interests or preferences may be all
funded religious schools. Or, where state education
that is required. But the character of compromise is
has hitherto been secular, the claim might involve
different in matters of principle, and equalising
drawing a parallel with state support for some hu-
representation in this way may be either too much
manist analogue to religious belief, such as the arts,
or not enough. Here the object will be to ensure
in which the cultural aspect of religion is empha-
equal consideration of the content and intrinsic
sised.
importance of different values for particular groups
Nonetheless, sometimes no compromise on sub-
of people, so that they seek solutions that are ac-
stance proves possible. This dilemma often arises for
ceptable to a variety of different points of view.
purely practical reasons to do with the nature of the
Instead of bargaining, participants in this sort of
decision rather than because of any lack of good will
dispute must negotiate and argue. In the case of
among those making it ± such as a choice between
bargained compromises, preferences can be taken
two somewhat different but equally good candidates
as exogenous to the system and democracy seen in
for a post, for each of whom a sound case might be
largely instrumental terms. A negotiated compromise
made. Only one can be chosen, and a compromise
involves a more deliberative model of democracy
candidate does not always make sense. In such
that leads to preferences being shaped and ranked
circumstances the compromise might have to be
endogenously through the democratic process itself
on accepting the outcome of a fair procedure, such
as otherwise inaccessible information regarding the
as tossing a coin. Within purely procedural versions
range and intensity of the moral and material claims
of democracy, the majoritarian principle can be seen
involved comes to light. Achieving this result re-
as a compromise of this sort.
33
quires that groups reach a sufficient threshold to
Constitutional design has the task of shaping the
have a voice that people take seriously. With very
political system so as to foster the form of democratic
small groups, that may involve more than propor-
debate appropriate to the requisite kind of fair
tionate voting power; with others somewhat less will
compromise. These considerations guide where de-
suffice.
cisions are to be made, how groups should be re-
35
Within a more complex and differentiated social
180
BACK TO THE FUTURE
context centralised and hierarchical ways of distri-
power remains with the people or their representa-
buting power will be inadequate. Territorially based
tives.
representation has to be supplemented by functional
acknowledgement of the standard liberal set of in-
and cultural forms within particular sectors. Social
dividual rights to freedom of expression, association,
and cultural interests are often territorially dispersed
bodily integrity and the like. Indeed, it compels
or located below any specific territorial unit. Em-
recognition of them.
powering certain groups may require their represen-
cratic balancing of their relative weight in relation to
tation within a specific location, or across a given
both each other and to additional values and inter-
sector, or in the case of vertical cleavages according
ests according to the issue and the people involved.
to segment. Workplace democracy and parent gov-
Diversity in the ethical reasoning of agents and of the
ernors at schools are examples of the first, corporatist
moral relevance of given factors is naturally to be
representation of unions, employer organisations and
expected within pluralist and complex societies.
professional associations of the second, consocia-
Dispersing power helps both the appropriate mix
tional representation for given ethnic, linguistic,
of voices to be heard and the peculiar circumstances
religious and cultural groups of the third.
36
39
That position remains consistent with the
40
Yet it also allows the demo-
Such
of particular contexts to be taken into account. Not
mechanisms allow minority opinions to have both a
only can general rules be tailored to a wide variety of
degree of autonomy within their own sphere com-
objects and concerns, and their implementation and
bined with a say in collective decision-making. On
monitoring enacted to meet the special requirements
the one hand, all groups (those asking for special
of a given situation and constituency, but also ± and
consideration included) are obliged to consult the
often more importantly ± specific norms can be
broader interests and concerns of society as a whole.
established to meet special circumstances and rele-
On the other, these same mechanisms operate as
vant
checks and balances on the purely self-interested or
minishes
partial exercise of power.
constitution to frame democracy. Judicial review
differences. for
a
In
consequence,
judicially
the
monitored
need
di-
principled
Democracy plays a central role in this system,
can track whether reasoned debate occurs, but need
protecting against arbitrary rule and enabling edu-
not substitute for an absence of such deliberation. As
37
Decisions may be
in a trial, the judge may advise on points of existing
contested and the rationale behind them tried.
law and ensure debate is conducted in a procedurally
Interests are not simply advanced and aggregated,
correct matter, but like a jury the demos or its
as in liberal accounts of the democratic process. They
representatives will make the decision for themselves
get related and subjected to the criticism of reasons,
and may even overturn established precedent if the
cative engagement with others.
transforming politics into a forum of principle.
38
circumstances warrant it and make new law.
41
Positions can shift and common views emerge. De-
This politicised account of justice suits a concern
mocracy also operates within civil society as well as
with domination and the fact of pluralism. Domina-
the state, acknowledging the power exercised by
tion most commonly manifests itself through inhi-
private bodies and the need to publicise them ± a
biting or preventing groups or individuals from
point liberal democrats tend to overlook by making
having a voice in the decisions governing their lives.
too sharp a public/private distinction. Power is not
When this occurs they are far more likely to find
simply devolved down in a hierarchical manner to
themselves oppressed by social structures that stunt
lesser levels of the state, as in a standard federal
or prevent their capacity to employ and develop
system. It is dispersed among semi-autonomous yet
their capacities or lead lives expressive of their beliefs
publicised private bodies. In this way, politics shapes
and culture.
rather than being simply shaped by social demands.
certain groups' ability to influence both the issues
42
For if political institutions constrain
Paradoxically from a liberal perspective, a demo-
that get discussed and how those that do get decided,
cratic liberalism contends that the rule of law de-
they will lose status and standing, and become
pends upon the rule of men. The only guard against
marginalised and ultimately exploited. Typically,
arbitrary and dominating rule is if the law-making
oppression has manifested itself indirectly through
181
RICHARD BELLAMY
the mechanisms of hegemony. At the extreme,
their aim not so much a unified as a mixed polity. It
however, exclusion from politics may eventually lead
was the insistence on the need for politics to con-
oppressed groups to resort to extra-political means to
front the social reality of class and ideological strug-
put their case ± a move that often lends legitimacy,
gles that attracted the writers of the Federalist Papers,
albeit of a spurious nature, to the employment of
who adapted republicanism to the needs of a modern
outright force against them. Such has been the fate of
large-scale
indigenous peoples in colonial societies, of many
modern heir Max Weber appreciated, this feature
ghettoised immigrant communities, of workers de-
also makes it suited to tackling the problems of
nied the vote either in general elections or in the
pluralism.
workplace, to name but a few well-known examples
the two standard criticisms of it prove misdirected. I
of this phenomenon.
shall take each in turn.
45
commercial
society.
As
Machiavelli's
When republicanism is so conceived,
As these cases indicate, such domination involves
Critics of republicanism's practicality assume that
not just an oppression of human beings but of a
the complexity of large-scale societies can only be
diversity of ways of life, values, interests and alle-
handled by the market or a centralised bureaucratic
giances. In other words, it is linked to the denial of
state or ± more usually ± some combination of the
pluralism. Since these diverse attitudes and concerns
two, with both social democrats and moderate lib-
are often related in their turn to different concep-
ertarians falling into this last camp. However, de-
tions of the right and the good, the injustice their
volved and more deliberative decision-making, far
suppression entails is not fully captured by reference
from being obsolete, has many advantages over these
to a particular conception of justice that may ±
alternatives. Pluralism and complexity usually go
perhaps unwittingly ± itself embody aspects of the
together in the sense that what makes a problem
dominant position. Justice can only be done, there-
complex is not simply its scale and the sheer number
fore, by being seen to be done within a non-dom-
of factors involved, but the fact that it can be
inating political structure that allows the various
conceived and evaluated in numerous different ways.
conceptions to confront each other so that their
As such, complex problems resist decomposition into
conflicts can be resolved through free negotiation.
their component elements so that priorities can be hierarchically ordered. Different actors and observers may not agree on what these are let alone on what, or
Two Criticisms
whether, they can be ranked on any given scale.
Two criticisms are often ranged against schemes of
It is precisely this kind of complexity that markets
the sort proposed. Modern complex societies are said
and bureaucracies often handle badly. Take the
to render a more participatory and deliberative pol-
example of environmental issues, which typically
itics together with any notion of agreement on
display
common policies not only impractical but also un-
how best to handle acid rain, for instance, experts
desirable. A political constitutionalism is said to be
dispute both its causes and consequences. It has been
suited only to the small-scale and homogeneous
traced to a number of natural and humanly produced
communities that originally gave birth to the idea.
emissions and associated with various sorts of damage
Such criticisms are historically and substantively
to a wide range of objects and entities. Yet the extent
mistaken. They gain credibility from certain com-
to which particular damage can be attributed to any
munitarian views of republicanism. These latter tend
given cause is far from clear. Additionally, the hu-
to stress the supposed ethical and social unity of the
man actors involved as both potential contributors
ancient polity.
43
these
characteristics.
46
When
discussing
However, the key issue for repub-
to and victims of pollution are similarly varied ± from
lican theorists from Aristotle to Machiavelli was
private motorists and consumers, to a whole host of
class conflict and the difficulties of balancing the
industrial and agricultural producers of one sort or
44
Their
another. Their concerns will be similarly diverse, and
view of politics was consequently less idealised and
it is highly likely that each may be to some degree
more realist than many communitarians appreciate,
both polluter and polluted. Since they will almost
various interests of different social groups.
182
BACK TO THE FUTURE
certainly hold differing beliefs and values, how even
in such decision-making negotiate a collective policy
members of a given group appraise their interests is
rather than engage in pluralist interest-group bar-
going to vary greatly.
gaining if they are to arrive at a full perspective on
We have here two basic aspects of political disagreement:
namely
cognitive
indeterminacy
the dimensions of the problem and prevent stalemate
and
or distorted solutions, such as prisoners' dilemmas.
Bureaucratic
The way institutions operate will be crucial to
management will be highly inefficient and reductive
achieving this, as we have seen. However, this
in such instances. For there will be no clearly
feature gives rise to the second set of criticisms of
demarcated ends or interests to be served, and the
republicanism. Some critics worry that this sort of
relationships between the multifarious actors in-
institutional design amounts to social engineering
volved cannot be tracked. As Hayek noted, admin-
and is driven by a misguided pursuit of an unobtain-
istrators would have to be omniscient, omnipotent
able agreement on an elusive common good that can
and unwaveringly angelic to carry out such a task.
only be attained through manipulation and covert
Markets sometimes fare better in offering a system of
coercion. The deliberative ideal is charged with
dispersed knowledge, but not when public goods or
assuming unity to be a prior condition of reasonable
bads are concerned for the well known reason that
discussion, and with having consensus as its goal.
conceptual essential contestability.
47
49
the externalities involved are non-excludable. The
With regard to the first part of the charge, certain
price mechanism and the view that all values are
theorists have argued that a deliberative democracy
mere subjective preferences are also insensitive to
assumes a demos bound by a common fate and shared
conviction-based or cultural difference. Moreover,
understandings.
market exchanges are rarely solely among individual
tlements motivated by this ideal ± notably the Uni-
consumers and entrepreneurs, but between private
ted
institutions that are themselves bureaucratically or-
exercises in nation-building. Critics, however, point
ganised and suffer from the self-same managerial
out the often exclusionary consequences of these
defects libertarians level at the state.
projects, and in particular the marginalisation of
States
50
They note how constitutional set-
Constitution
±
were
simultaneously
By contrast, a political constitutionalism attempts
those deemed not capable of joining in the conver-
to confront this complexity head on by bringing
sation ± such as women workers, and members of
together the actors concerned in an effort at mutual
non-western cultures. If a people are to subject
understanding and accommodation. Devolved and
themselves to often onerous burdens to generate
deliberative
appropriate
collective benefits for others, then they will have
ends and means to be fixed on by fostering coopera-
to feel bound to them in some significant way. How
tion and coordination by multiple actors across a
far such bonds must rely on a common culture as
host of domains. Both the norms to be applied and
opposed to mere functional interdependence and
their enforcement arise out of discussion, and could
territorial contiguity is difficult to say. States display
not be fixed in advance without introducing biases
a bafflingly wide variety of mixes of these and other
and oversimplifications of the problem with poten-
elements. Historical contingency probably plays the
tially disastrous knock-on effects. Dryzek cites the
major factor. While starting from the status quo is
resolution of a dispute over the construction of a dam
inevitable, a political constitutionalism is not tied to
and water supply system near Denver, Colorado as a
any particular definition of the demos or the polity.
decision-making
enables
successful instance of this approach.
48
A plethora of
On the contrary, both are explicitly seen as political
federal and local agencies and groups were involved
artefacts fashioned by the people themselves. More-
and produced an appropriate fair compromise in
over, it operates with a dynamic of inclusiveness that
which the dam was built but substantial mitigating
places the burden of proof on those wanting to
measures were instituted. The success of this `Foot-
exclude others or, via secession, themselves. They
hills' decision led to the institution of a Metropolitan
must show such choices to be consistent with a norm
Water Roundtable to mediate future cases.
of equal worth and mutual acceptance, and that they do not cause even more damage to others than
It is of paramount importance that those involved
183
RICHARD BELLAMY
benefits to themselves. But that leaves ample scope
one's particular practices, however, is perfectly con-
for the renegotiation of the terms by which citizen-
sistent with a universal principle of equal moral
ship is defined and political structures operate. In-
worth, and particular rules may be applied in as
deed, once it is understood that the reconstitution of
consistent and unbiased a manner as general ones.
a polity is an ongoing process, then there can be
Universality and impartiality in these senses protect
considerable openness and flexibility in how the
particularity by insisting that any case for special
constituent groups might relate to each other.
consideration must avoid subjecting others to dom-
With regard to the second part of the charge, I
ination. Arguments, such as those of sexists or racists
argued above that consensus need not and often
that assert that certain people's views or interests
could not be the goal of discussion, as certain
count for less than those of others will be treated as
theorists of deliberative democracy claim. They look
prima facie unacceptable, for example. A claim by a
for a `republic of reasons' in which the most compel-
religious minority for public funding of its own
ling arguments prevail.
51
However, pluralism renders
schools will probably not be, since it asks for equal
such reasoning problematic, since more than one
recognition rather than denying it.
rationally compelling argument may be in play. That
A political constitutionalism also allows for dif-
makes compromise necessary. Achieving a fair com-
ferent styles of argumentation and suggests that as
promise also entails a change in the character of
much attention should be paid to the different
politics, but of a slightly different nature to one
cultures of negotiation as to differences in the sub-
oriented towards consensus. It requires a move from
stance of what is negotiated.
a purely individualistic and instrumental politics to a
been recognised by students of diplomacy looking at
more interactive and problem-solving model. Rather
international negotiations across cultures.
than viewing other people's interests and values as
tional pluralism means that domestic politics must
mere constraints on getting one's own way to which
also take such factors into account. Here too a
minimal concessions should be made, this approach
problem-solving approach seems the most appropri-
leads to the search for solutions that attempt to
ate, with symbolism and honour counting for as
integrate the various concerns of the parties in-
much as argument and strategic gains.
volved. This possibility need not rely on transcendent
criteria,
however,
merely
a
53
This need has long 54
Infrana-
Nevertheless, it is doubtful that any process of
reciprocal
negotiation would be possible unless people saw the
understanding of the frameworks of other actors,
political norms framing the discussion as generating
the ability to engage with them and to seek agree-
some form of common good. Civic freedom operates
ment on what is desirable even if this is based on
in this context as what Joseph Raz has called an
differing views of why it might be.
`inherent public good'.
55
That is a good the benefits
At its heart, this conception of politics has an
of which are under the sole control of each potential
attachment to civic liberty, the guiding principles of
beneficiary and which by their nature could not be
which are non-domination, mutual acceptance and
voluntarily controlled and distributed by any single
accommodation. What these conditions all point to
agency. For one cannot create such an environment
is a vision of society in which all enjoy equal status.
except through the active collaboration with others,
This implies universality and impartiality, in the
nor control the beneficial externalities that it gen-
sense that all persons must be treated as of equal
erates so as to channel them only to certain others,
moral worth and claims based on self-serving bias or
though one could cut oneself off from them through
prejudice should be ruled out. But that does not
one's own anti-social and intolerant actions. Put
mean that all citizens must be regarded as having
another way, the condition of living as equals has
identical needs or the same values ± quite the
to be desired in and for itself ± as an intrinsic aspect
reverse. This supposition appears to arise from the
of a certain kind of society ± rather than instrumen-
belief that only general rules can meet these criteria,
tally, since that would allow selective domination to
and that these will be blind to people's particular
acquire personal advantage. To the extent pluralist
concerns or convictions.
52
conflicts are rightly characterised as struggles for
A claim for respect for
184
BACK TO THE FUTURE
recognition, then this goal should appeal to the
not). Secession or conscientious objection may still
parties concerned.
have to be options for groups or individuals whose
Though this argument goes beyond the purely
values and convictions prove totally incompatible
formal proceduralism advocated by thinkers like
with those of the majority. Their reasons could not
Habermas, who offer an entirely circular case for
be, however, claims to superiority ± that their values
constitutional norms via the self-validating character
and interests are worth more than those of others ± as
of democratic discourse,
56
it does not imply agree-
was effectively argued by advocates of apartheid, for
ment on substantive ends. Indeed at times it may be
example. Rather, the case must be that such drastic
possible to do no more than agree to disagree and
measures are necessary to ensure equal worth and
accept the authority of the democratic procedure
that otherwise their cultures and concerns might be
itself. In these cases the majority principle acts as a
totally eroded, as indigenous peoples seeking protec-
means for resolving conflict in an authoritative
tion against a dominant post-colonial community
manner when a compromise on substance cannot
have contended. Even here alternative solutions,
be achieved. Authority here rests on neither claims
such as greater autonomy or special rights, might
to superior reason nor coercion but the simple
be available to keep them within the polity.
acceptance of the procedure as authoritative (in the sense of being `in' authority) for the disputing
Conclusion
parties. Here the authority of law rests on the legitimacy of the political system which generates
I have argued that to meet the challenges of the new
it. Parties acknowledge that in some cases there may
millennium, liberalism needs to take a step back to
not be any `correct' or `most just' way of resolving a
the future and draw on the resources of the repub-
clash between incommensurable plural values, but
lican tradition. The resulting democratic liberalism
that the ways of ending the dispute are acceptable.
employs the notion of a political constitution based
The procedural fairness of the process of justice can
around the dispersal of power and the mixing and
be more important than the favourability of, or
balancing of social classes. It incorporates the liberal
consensus about, the outcome.
57
concern with freedom and justice into the demo-
A more political constitutionalism does not turn
crat's desire to ensure that citizens have an equal say
on the existence of a homogeneous community,
in influencing and holding to account the rules and
therefore, as some communitarian theorists maintain
rulers governing them. As such, it offers a means of
and certain critics complain. The political system
both recognising and reconciling differences through
can operate as a public good for a plurality of social
negotiation of fair compromises that embody mutual
groups, without assuming they share other values
acceptance and accommodation.
(indeed, perhaps for the very reason that they do
Notes
1. Much of this chapter's argument emerged from an
VI, para. 57; the French Declaration of the Rights of
ESRC research project on `Sovereignty and Citizen-
Man and the Citizen of 1789, especially Articles 1, 2,
ship in a Mixed Polity' (R000222446) undertaken
4, 6, 14 and 16; I. Kant, `On the Common Saying:
with Dario Castiglione of Exeter University. I am
``This May be True in Theory, But It Does Not Apply
grateful for his comments, those of the editor and
in Practice'', in Kant (1991), p. 73; J.S. Mill, `On
the participants at the Swansea `Liberalism at the
Liberty', in Mill (1972), p. 75; and Rawls (1972), p. 60.
Millennium II' conference, to Richard Dagger and
4. On this problem, see O'Neill (1979) and Gray (1989),
others at a seminar at All Souls College, Oxford, and
especially chapter 9.
to Cecile Laborde. I have also drawn on my Liberalism and Pluralism (Bellamy, (1999), especially chapter 5.
5. The locus classicus of this view is of course Adam
2. See Bellamy (1999), `Introduction', and Kekes (1993)
Smith: Smith (1976), p. 456. But the thesis is far from being confined to economic liberals. See, for example,
for a discussion of this problem.
Mill (1972), pp. 73±4; Raz (1986), pp. 369±70, 394.
3. For example, Locke (1991), Second Treatise, chapter
185
RICHARD BELLAMY
23. See Sunstein (1993), pp. 3±4.
6. I explore the breakdown of this social thesis and the related philosophical thesis in late nineteenth- and
24. For example, Ackerman (1991).
early twentieth-century thought in Bellamy (1992).
25. See Hayek (1960), pp. 153±4. 26. For example, Dworkin (1985), p. 2.
7. In employing this formula, I am referring to the neo-
27. Pettit (1997), p. 189. See too Hampshire (1991), pp.
Roman version of republicanism identified by Skinner
20±1.
(1998) and Pettit (1997), rather than the more loosely defined republicanism espoused by communitarians
28. See Gutmann and Thompson (1996), p. 57 and J.
such as Michael Sandel, for example in Sandel (1996).
Cohen, `Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy', in Benhabib (ed.) (1996), pp. 95±119,
8. See Isaac (1988).
at pp. 100±1.
9. My main dissent from Dagger (1997) arises from his
29. What follows draws on R. Bellamy and M. Hollis,
underplaying these differences. 10. See the references cited in note 3.
`Consensus, Neutrality and Compromise', in Bellamy
11. Tully (1995), chapter 3.
and Hollis (eds) (1999), chapter 5, and Bellamy (1999), chapter 4.
12. For example, see Locke (1991), Second Treatise,
30. I owe the distinction between `either/or' and `more or
chapters II and VIII; Mill (1972), pp. 188±98; and
less' conflicts to Hirschman (1994), pp. 203±18.
R. Dworkin's `Liberalism', in Dworkin (1985), pp.
31. Goodin (1995).
181±204.
32. See Manin (1987), p. 353.
13. Once again the examples cited in note 3 provide
33. Singer (1974), p. 32 sees it as `a paradigm of a fair
exemplary instances of this mode of thinking.
compromise'.
14. For an analysis of historical and contemporary models of liberal democracy, see Held (1996), chapters 3, 5, 6
34. Beitz (1989), p. 155.
and 7.
35. See Kymlicka (1995), chapter 7.
15. For examples from the left and right of the liberal
36. For examples of each of these mechanisms see, respec-
spectrum, see Dworkin (1985), p. 197 and Hayek
tively, Hirst (1994), Dahl (1985) and Lijphart (1968).
(1976), pp. 62±3.
I review the merits and weaknesses of these forms of pluralist politics in Bellamy (2000).
16. These processes are naturally exacerbated by globalisation. Many liberal theorists believe this challenge
37. Pettit (1997), p. 30 and Skinner (1998), p. 74 n. 38
can be met by extending liberal democracy in a
stress the first benefit but regard the second as a civic
cosmopolitan direction, for example Held (1995).
humanist rather than a neo-Roman concern, which
However, the forces supposed to underpin this exten-
smacks dangerously of `positive' liberty. Putting history
sion of liberalism have in reality given rise to the very
to one side, substantively I do not believe a weak
kinds of diversity that make liberal democracy hard to
`positive' appreciation of the virtues of participation can be totally excised from republicanism.
sustain. For the same processes that drive globalisation have
augmented
functional
differentiation
38. See Sunstein (1991), pp. 3±34 for discussion of these
in the
points.
economy and society and fostered multiculturalism.
39. See Skinner (1998), pp. 74±6 for the history of this
I have criticised the cosmopolitan liberal thesis, and
insight.
provided an indication of how democratic liberalism can be extended to transnational political commu-
40. See J. Cohen, in Benhabib (ed.) (1996), pp. 102±5.
nities in Bellamy and Castiglione (1998). Despite
41. As Jeremy Waldron has recently insisted, we are sadly
global pressures, however, the state remains the pri-
lacking a model of jurisprudence which takes legislation
mary locus of political authority and this chapter
as seriously as judicial reasoning. Republicanism supports his plea for such an account. See Waldron (1999).
addresses that context.
42. I'm here following Young's distinction between dom-
17. The analysis that follows draws on Luhmann (1981)
ination and oppression, and the relation between the
and Zolo (1992).
two; see Young (1990), pp. 37±8 and chapter 2.
18. For example Dworkin (1995), pp. 2±11 and Rawls's identification of public reason with judicial reasoning
43. For example Taylor (1995), pp. 141, 191±2, 302 n. 15.
in Rawls (1996), Lecture VI.
44. See Bellamy, `The Political Form of the Constitution', in Bellamy and Castiglione (eds) (1996).
19. Rawls (1996) offers the most sophisticated example of this approach. See Bellamy (1999), chapter 2 for a
45. Bellamy (1992), chapter 4.
detailed critique.
46. I owe this example and much of the argument that follows to Dryzek (1990), chapter 3. I have also drawn
20. For a brief history, see my `The Political Form of the
on Cohen and Rogers (1995).
Constitution: The Separation of Powers, Rights and Representative Democracy', in Bellamy and Casti-
47. See Mason (1992), chapters 1 and 2.
glione (eds) (1996), pp. 436±56.
48. Dryzek (1990), pp. 73±4.
21. Skinner (1998), Pettit (1997).
49. See, for example Young (1990), chapter 4.
22. Hobhouse (1964), p. 71.
50. For example, Miller (1995), pp. 150±2.
186
BACK TO THE FUTURE
51. Sunstein (1993), chapter 1.
54. For example, Cohen (1991).
52. See, for example, Young (1990), chapter 4.
55. Raz (1986), pp. 198±9.
53. Young, `Communication and the Other: Beyond De-
56. Habermas (1979), p. 90. 57. See Lind and Tyler (1988) for empirical evidence to
liberative Democracy', in Benhabib (ed.) (1996), pp.
this effect.
120±35, at pp. 128±32.
187
14
ACCOMMODATING REPUBLICANISM David Rasmussen
Presently, there is a debate raging in political theory
In the following I want to turn to that portion of
over two approaches to theorising justice: the deonto-
the 1995 debate between Rawls and Habermas
logical, which holds that justice can be achieved by the
which focuses on the Ancients and the Moderns
establishment of specific principles and procedures as
in order to clarify what is at stake in what I have
opposed to the achievement of a substantive common
called `accommodating republicanism'. Such is the
good as a goal or `end-state', and the teleological, which
significance of these two thinkers in modern political
conceptualises the achievement of justice as end ± or
theory that it is useful to set out the `liberal ±
goal-oriented, justifying whatever principles and pro-
republican' debate at least partly in the terms sug-
cedures may be necessary as means to the realisation of
gested by their exchange. We will see how `law' turns
that specific end. No doubt, both Ju È rgen Habermas
out to be at the centre of this controversy, whether
and John Rawls would want to see themselves on the
one wants to see it in the form of Rawls's constitu-
deontological side of this debate. In their own ways,
tionalism or Habermas's co-originality thesis. It will
they present their theories as proceeding from the
become clear that the question of the distinctiveness
acceptance of certain assumptions about the need to
between the two may rest upon whether Rawlsian
respect wide value-pluralism. These assumptions are
constitutionalism provides a genuine alternative to
held to be incompatible with the teleological ap-
the co-originality thesis. This will be a crucial test of
proach, whose specified end ± however characterised
Rawlsian liberalism's conceptual strength, if we grant
± is in some way reasonable to contest and disavow in
that accommodating the republican insight is a
the light of them. However, each accuses the other of a
necessary move for it to make. We will then be in
kind of latent Aristotelianism, which is one way of
a position to identify an important issue that should
1
characterising `teleology'. The source of that accusa-
be placed on the liberal ± republican research agen-
tion is clearly to be found in both thinkers' attempts to
da.
accommodate the influential critique of liberalism by republicanism. They both want to acknowledge the
Rawls and Habermas:
connections between public political life and `private'
`Ancient versus Modern'?
liberty upon which the critique insists, but without sacrificing an essential respect for individual liberty
The battle between Rawls's `interpretative construc-
and diversity that liberalism aspires to typify. The
tivism' and Habermas's `argumentative constructi-
accusation by one implies that the other has somehow
vism' comes to the fore over Benjamin Constant's
failed in the attempted synthesis of liberalism and
distinction between the liberties of the moderns and
republicanism.
the liberties of the ancients, and the claim that these
188
ACCOMMODATING REPUBLICANISM
should be nourished by the same root. Constant
private rights? Given that, as we shall see, Haber-
claims that `modern' liberty ± the liberties of private
mas's response involves a radical conceptual and
individuals ± is best directed towards self-develop-
practical extension of democracy, we may go on
ment which, in his view, is most effectively achieved
to ask how one might realise the substantive mor-
through free, collective political participation. (This
al/political goal of justice as fairness while assuring
is the exercise of `ancient' liberty, the ideal which
the liberal goal of impartiality in a political process
particularly
that is comprehensively democratic.
attracts
contemporary
republicans.)
Hence Constant calls for an efficacious combination of the two types of liberty.
Habermas's solution is based on a notion of re-
2
ciprocity derived from the procedure of argumenta-
Habermas's point connects ancient and modern
tion. He stresses how language, with which people
liberty much more tightly than what, in Constant's
reason and communicate with each other, is essen-
approach, is still an instrumental linkage of the two.
tially intersubjective. He urges that we must there-
He argues simply that what he calls `public' and
fore think of `justified' norms as being those which
`private'
and
would emerge from free and equal discourse. The
`modern' respectively) are `co-original'; neither is
Habermasian thesis is that justice as fairness can only
prior to the other in any plausible conceptual sense.
be achieved through an adequate notion of recipro-
He thinks that Rawls finds himself defending the
city. In turn, such a notion can only be gained from
quintessentially liberal position of prejudicing the
the procedure of argumentation in which the actors
liberties of the moderns, the private rights of private
in the political process mutually recognise the claims
individuals, over those of the ancients, the political
and counter-claims of one another. Here, we en-
rights of public individuals, or `citizens'. This is
counter the centrality to Habermasian political the-
because the Rawlsian `political' sphere, from which
ory of public will-formation ± by which is meant
are drawn the shared ideas used to justify liberal
democratic procedure ± which can be reconstructed
politics (and which for Rawls, of course, prioritise
as a public and intersubjective process derived from
individual liberties in the lexically primary first
the procedure of argumentation. The emerging thesis
principle of justice), is already `given' in his theory.
postulates the assumption that the norms of private,
It just appears, so to speak: a ready-made domain
individual rights can only be derived from the pro-
demarcating the sphere in which constitutional de-
cess of public will-formation; they are not prior to it.
mocratic politics thereafter takes place and from
It follows from this that private and public autonomy
which reasons to provide public justifications for
are co-original, the consequence of which being that
autonomy
(analogues
such politics are drawn.
for
`ancient'
3
rights are democratically grounded from the outset.
Now the republican critique says about liberalism
The point of this argument is the claim that for
the very thing that Habermas is here saying about
Rawls rights are not democratically grounded. Ha-
Rawls, namely that liberalism functions to justify
bermas believes the upshot is as follows: if Rawls had
private rights above all else and, indeed, tends just to
accepted his critique, which epistemically associates
assume
`ready-to-hand.'
the reasonable and the true with the consequence
Among other complaints, republicanism believes
that consensus and validity are linked from the
that this
outset,
them,
as
leaves
being
simply
liberalism
fatally
inattentive
to
4
then he wouldn't have had to use the
how a society can establish and maintain the public
original position as a device of representation. This
conditions necessary for the kind of liberty-promot-
is because he would have found that `the moral point
ing politics it favours. Given that republicans do not
of view' is implicit in the socio-ontological constitu-
want to reject wholesale liberalism's general ideals of
tion
just governance, we can conceptualise the heart of
Further, Rawls would not have had to make the
the liberal ± republican debate as posing this ques-
second step in his theory, that is the step to over-
tion: how does one retain the basic framework of
lapping consensus, because the public practice of
liberalism while at the same time accommodating
argumentation requires the `complex relations of
the republican critique of liberalism's prioritisation of
mutual recognition that participants in rational dis-
189
of
the
public
practice
of
argumentation.'
5
DAVID RASMUSSEN
course ``must'' accept (in the weak sense of transcendental necessity).'
6
democratic life of a political community. In other
In other words, Rawls should
words, given such a scenario legal regulation would
have built consensus fully into the first stage of the
determine the distinction between the public and
theory (the original position in which rationally
private in a democratic way in the sense that those
choosing agents choose under reasonable procedural
under the law would be its own authors. The reigning
constraints) rather than adding it on in the second
question would then be: `which rights must free and
stage (the step to overlapping consensus as the
equal persons mutually accord one another if they
achievement by justice as fairness ± the outcome
wish to regulate their existence by the legitimate
of original-position deliberation ± of the right kind of
means of positive and coercive law?'
stable public support). This would have enabled his
put the question that way it would follow that
political liberalism to escape both the arbitrariness of
Rawls's characterisation of a private domain, which
the second stage (for here `the philosopher can at
contains the realm of the comprehensive as distin-
most attempt to anticipate in reflection the direction
guished from a public realm that characterises `the
of real discourses as they would probably unfold
political', would be a lot less necessary than his
7
11
If one were to
under conditions of a pluralistic society' ) as well
political liberalism would have us think. Habermas
as the implicit monological perspective of the first
would therefore shift the Rawlsian distinction be-
stage (for Rawls `imposes a common perspective on
tween the private and the public, or the compre-
the parties in the original position through informa-
hensive and the political, to the domain of the
tional constraints and thereby neutralises the multi-
procedure of legal regulation which would accord
plicity of particular interpretive perspectives from
the right to equal `actionable subjective liberties' as
8
well as the public autonomy of its citizens.
the outset' ). In the Habermasian alternative, with its `speech-act' view based on the nature of perfor-
In brief, Habermas holds that legal procedure
matives from which one derives a certain intersub-
presupposes the subjective autonomy of its citizens,
jective necessity, intersubjectivity ± and its notion of
what Rawls would call the domain of private right.
reciprocity to guarantee impartiality ± is written into
At the same time legal procedure in a democratic
the theory from the outset. In this sense, practical
society cannot be legitimate without the public
reason is actualised through mutual recognition: `we
exercise of democratic law-making. So private and
could say that precisely those principles are valid
public autonomy presuppose each other. Hence, one
which meet with uncoerced intersubjective recogni-
would infer from the argument that Rawls should
tion under conditions of rational discourse.'
9
have concentrated on the procedure of democratic
`Con-
12
sensus' need not be an afterthought, following in the
law-making.
wake of the construction of principles of justice.
without moving beyond the bounds of the procedur-
He could have done this, it seems,
From Habermas's point of view Rawls's distinction
al towards teleology because Habermas's democratic
between the private and the public, which underlies
law-making entrusts even more responsibility in
his distinction between the political and the com-
formulating norms than Rawls does to that political
prehensive, is not only unnecessary but leads to
procedure.
13
undesired consequences, particularly when one fo-
In his `Reply', Rawls sets out a rigorously con-
cuses on liberties and rights. It runs against the
structed rebuttal of Habermas's characterisation and
historical insight that the `boundary' demarcating
critique of his project. He contends that if one pays
the relative spheres is always shifting, due to the
careful attention to the actual practice of designing a
basic shifts in political will-formation (Habermas's
constitution in relationship to the process of govern-
example is that of the welfare state's development,
ment it can be seen that private autonomy cannot be
which turned formerly private matters of welfare into
regarded as pre-political at all. The public political
public political concerns).
10
From this perspective,
culture which grounds it is not just `given', for there is
Habermas thinks that Rawls would be better off
a real, founding constitutional convention that se-
subsuming this distinction under that of `legal reg-
lects a constitution with its Bill of Rights and this
ulation' which would in turn be determined by the
`restricts majority legislation in how it may burden
190
ACCOMMODATING REPUBLICANISM
such basic liberties as liberty of conscience and freedom of speech and thought.'
14
at stake, we may ask if the question of the co-relation
To be sure, then,
of the liberty of the ancients and the liberty of the
rights `trump' popular sovereignty, but only as pop-
moderns, of private right and popular sovereignty,
ular sovereignty is expressed in the legislature in-
can be resolved independently of a contingent con-
asmuch as those very rights are derived from a
stitutional history. In Rawls's view it could be that
democratic
foundation.
`Habermas may have no objection to justice as fair-
Hence, basic liberties are `incorporated into the
ness but may reject the constitution to which he
constitution and protected as constitutional rights
thinks it leads, and which I think may secure both
on the basis of citizens' deliberations and judgements over
the ancient and modern liberties.'
process
of
time' (emphasis added).
constitutional
15
20
Fair enough.
In other words, and this is
Rawls is willing to concede that `he and I are not,
a distinctly American view, popular sovereignty is to
however, debating the justice of the United States'
be distinguished from `parliamentary supremacy'.
constitution as it is; but whether justice as fairness
Following Locke's dualist idea of a constitutional
allows and is consistent with the popular sovereignty
democracy Rawls contrasts ordinary law-making by a
he cherishes.'
21
legislature and the `people's constituent power to
However, Rawls is clearly sensitive to the inter-
form, ratify and amend a constitution' in order to
pretation, and thus the critique, that Habermas gives
clarify the distinction. A parallel distinction is then
of the liberalism he articulates. Hence, in support of
drawn between `higher law of the people' and the
his argument that individual rights are not pre-
`ordinary law of legislative bodies'.
16
It is important
political, and to some extent in support of his
that the example which illuminates Rawls's argu-
own more interpretative view, he cites an argument
ment is historical, not abstractly conceptual. Follow-
which Habermas uses against Charles Larmore. Lar-
17
he cites the three most
more has argued that one right has to proceed and
significant, decisive innovations in American con-
constrain democratic will-formation: `no one should
stitutional history: the founding and initial develop-
be forcibly compelled to submit to norms whose
ment of the constitution during the period 1787±91,
validity cannot be made evident to reason.'
the post-Civil War Reconstruction, and the New
bermas interprets this as a denial of co-originality,
Deal under President Franklin D. Roosevelt in the
meaning the establishment of a pre-political right
mid±1930s. Rawls observes that in these periods it
against the state which is perceived under the cate-
was the electorate which `confirmed or motivated
gory of violence. Against this view Habermas pre-
the constitutional changes that were proposed and
sents a two-stage model which begins with the
ing Bruce Ackerman,
finally accepted.'
18
22
Ha-
`horizontal sociation of citizens who, recognising
Of course, Rawls's case, derived from historical
one another as equals, mutually accord rights to
interpretation and not purely from philosophical
one another. Only then does one advance to the
argumentation (hence the contrast between inter-
constitutional taming of power presupposed with the
pretative and argumentative constructivism), is pre-
medium of law.'
23
sented as reliant upon the development of the
Now Rawls believes that his own construction can
constitutional history of the United States. As such,
be viewed in a similar way. Hence, he arrives at two
he argues this reference proves that justice as fairness
conclusions, namely that Habermas's position is not
is a political notion rather than one derived from
that different from his own,
pre-political natural law. He insists that for him `the
mistakenly unleashes a critique in his interpretation
liberties of the moderns do not impose the prior
of
restrictions on the people's constituent will'
19
liberalism.
25
Habermas
24
and that Habermas
thinks
that
liberalism
± and
founders on the dilemma generated by the conflict
to that extent he, too, thinks he can accommodate
between these two propositions: `no moral law can
the republican critique.
be externally imposed on a sovereign democratic people' and `the sovereign people may not justly
But does Rawls's argument prove anything beyond
26
something which is peculiar to the constitutional
. . . enact any law violating these rights.'
history of the United States? Or, to rephrase the issue
Rawls there is no true dilemma here: both proposi-
191
But for
DAVID RASMUSSEN
tions are correct and `simply express the risk for
Rawls, not everybody need pursue the good embo-
political justice of all government, democratic or
died in the politics of old as an intrinsic element of
otherwise; for there is no human institution ± poli-
the good life today ± but Habermas's theory seems
tical or social, judicial or ecclesiastical ± that can
implicitly to curtail this possibility.
guarantee that legitimate (or just) laws are always enacted and just rights always respected.'
27
It is quite
The Persistence
conceivable that a single person could stand alone
of The `Teleological Question'
and be right to say that law and government are unjust. `No special doctrine of the co-originality and
So Rawls's reply to Habermas raises a very interesting
equal weight of the two forms of autonomy is needed
point to which, to my knowledge, Habermas has yet
to explain this fact,' Rawls writes. `It is hard to
to reply. I would contend that it can be used to
believe that all major liberal and civic republican
formulate an urgent issue for the liberal/republican
writers did not understand this. It bears on the age-
research agenda. His critique can be formulated as
old question of how best to unite power with law and
follows: if one asserts the co-originality thesis in the
justice.'
28
way that Habermas does, with its implicit assumption
At this point, we see Rawls making no attempt to
about the primacy of the political in the ancient as
do anything other than defend his position against
opposed to the modern sense, then one buys into a
the presumption of a liberal bias for private rights.
teleology which can only be justified through a
But clearly he doubts that Habermas's theoretical
comprehensive philosophical framework.
construction, such as the co-originality thesis, will
it suggests that Habermas may have gone too far in
guarantee the proper exercise of law and justice in
his attempt to accommodate the claims of repub-
practice. Equally, he questions the emphasis on the
licanism; a crucial modern insight about the plur-
political in Habermas's apparent claim that `the
alistic nature of the good has gone unrespected.
internal relation between the two forms of autonomy
Rawls claims to get by his interpretative constructi-
depends upon ``the normative content of the mode of
vism what he contends Habermas does not get by his
exercising political autonomy.'' '
29
30
If valid,
Rawls wants to
alternative argumentative constructivism. As I un-
know how we might justify the idea that it is
derstand it, Rawls claims to be able to assert a merely
incumbent specifically upon the political realm to
political and non-comprehensive notion of demo-
provide the basis for private autonomy, given that
cratic procedure through his use of the claims of a
activity in the institutions and practices of civil
certain form of constitutional legal theory. It would
society could also provide a sufficient basis for it.
be equally interesting to know if Habermas believes
He speculates that the origin of Habermas's prior-
that Rawls, by relying on American constitutional-
itisation of political activity is found in civic human-
ism, could successfully avoid a similar dilemma ±
ism (by which it is reasonable to assume that he
namely, the assertion of the teleological primacy of
means Aristotelianism). The crucially relevant fea-
the public on grounds which depend too specifically
ture here is that for civic humanism the greatest good
(`comprehensively') on the particularities of Amer-
is conceived of as active participation in political life,
ican historical experience.
31
a paradigm of the teleological approach. For Rawls,
Either way, the republican insight into the rela-
this notion is really derived from a comprehensive
tionship between the public and the private may
doctrine. I take his critique of Habermas to be based
seem to be one that must be coherently adopted by
upon the idea that it is reasonable that not everybody
any theory sharing the broad moral and political
pursues the good defined specifically in terms of
purposes of Rawls and Habermas. But, as their ex-
political life and activity. Non-political public pro-
change shows, it is as yet far from clear that it can be
jects and private interests and pursuits are equally
accommodated without reliance upon the kind of
reasonable. From the point of view of political
teleological assumptions from which many contem-
liberalism, then, it would be inappropriate to assert
porary political theorists ± Rawls and Habermas
one comprehensive view over others. Hence, for
included ± emphatically wish to distance themselves.
192
ACCOMMODATING REPUBLICANISM
Notes
1. The appropriateness of the term `Aristotelianism' may
concept of law has been clarified in this way, it
be questionable. I presume that its spirit is what
becomes clear that the normative substance of basic
Habermas invokes when he associates Rawls with a
liberal rights is already contained in the indispensable
classical theory which legitimates its theory of justice
medium for the legal institutionalisation of the public use of reason of sovereign citizens'; ibid., p. 130.
by assuming the actuality of just institutions in chapter 2 of Habermas (1996). He also thinks that the fact
13. Ibid., p. 131.
that `the issue of principles of justice can arise only in
14. Rawls (1996), pp. 404±5.
the guise of the question of the just distribution of the
15. Ibid., p. 405.
primary goods' is more consistent with `Aristotelian or
16. Ibid., pp. 405±6; cf. ibid., pp. 231±40.
utilitarian approaches than with a theory of rights,
17. Ackerman (1991), chapters 3±6.
such as [Rawls's] own, that proceeds from the concept
18. Rawls (1996), p. 406; cf. ibid., pp. 233±5.
of autonomy' (Habermas, 1995, p. 114). Further, I
19. Ibid., pp. 406±7.
assume that the term captures what Rawls means when
20. Ibid., p. 407.
he associates Habermas with civic humanism, which
21. Ibid.
he does at Rawls (1996), p. 420.
22. Cited in Habermas (1996), p. 456. 23. Ibid.
2. See B. Constant, `The Liberty of the Ancients Compared with that of the Moderns', in Constant (1988),
24. Rawls (1996), p. 407.
pp. 308±28, at p. 327; cf. Habermas (1995), p. 129.
25. Ibid., p. 412.
3. Habermas (1995), esp. pp. 126±9.
26. Ibid., pp. 411, 416.
4. Ibid., pp. 119±26, especially p. 122.
27. Ibid., p. 416.
5. Ibid., p. 127.
28. Ibid.
6. Ibid.
29. Ibid., p. 419.
7. Ibid., p. 121.
30. Ibid., p. 420; cf. pp. 376±80.
8. Ibid., p. 117.
31. Habermas has recently had more to say about the
9. Ibid., p. 127.
distinction between the reasonable and the true in
10. Ibid., p. 129; cf. Benhabib (1992), pp. 89±120.
Rawls's work. However, at the time of writing there
11. Habermas (1995), p. 130.
remains much more mileage in their exchange; see
12. Ibid., pp. 130±1. Habermas believes that `once the
Habermas (1998b), pp. 75±101.
193
This page intentionally left blank
Part Six THE `AUTONOMOUS INDIVIDUAL': FEMINIST CRITIQUES AND LIBERAL REPLIES
This page intentionally left blank
15
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT Kate Soper
women appeared a barbaric anachronism. For them,
I
parity of treatment for the sexes was viewed as
Like many other intimate relationships, that of
essential to bringing political practice into confor-
feminism and liberalism has from the outset been
mity with liberal philosophy ± and this view has been
troubled by contention, but it has also proved to be
shared by all those who have subsequently carried
very resistant to any final severance. By common
forward the `equal opportunities' campaign for an
consent, the modern feminist movement has its roots
end to female subordination.
in the philosophical liberalism of the Enlightenment,
What is essentially at issue for all such critics is the
but it has also since its origins constituted itself at
arbitrary and unjustifiable exclusion of women as
least in part through an immanent critique of the
proper
partialities and hypocrisies of its humanist and ega-
claimed to be due to humanity at large: a line of
litarian claims. Yet it has belonged within, even as it
objection which has in recent times been focused on
has conducted a continuous polemic against, the
the extent to which liberal humanist discourse has
framework of liberal-Enlightenment thinking. This
functioned historically as a cover under which both
is so in two senses: firstly, in the sense that although
gender and racial difference can be safely ignored and
they were highly critical of the patriarchal culture of
the particular interests of a white, male and bourgeois
the liberal Enlightenment, most of those arguing for
elite be the better secured.
candidates
for
the
freedoms
and
rights
female emancipation from the end of the eighteenth
But feminism has also been viewed as rooted in
century until relatively recently have viewed that
liberal-Enlightenment values in the further and re-
project as not only consistent with liberal principles
lated sense that in developing this immanent cri-
but as requisite to their full implementation. For
tique, it was doing no more than observing the self-
Wollstonecraft, it seemed only rational that a Lock-
critical, constantly revisionist spirit of those values
ean-liberal
citizenship
themselves. To point this out, however, is clearly to
should extend to women on the same grounds and
beg the question as to how self-critical this spirit can
in equal measure as it did to men, even though in
become before it turns heretical. At what point does
demanding that it should be, she was asking for an
feminist criticism of liberalism cease to be immanent
extension of rights and franchise that was totally
to it and become outright dissidence?
conception
of
rights
and
1
unacceptable to the political culture of her time.
One possible answer might be at the point when it
From the perspective of the form of liberalism de-
casts doubt on the capacity of liberal-democratic
fended by John Stuart Mill and Harriet Taylor in the
institutions and political process to deliver the `free-
nineteenth century, the continued subjection of
dom and equality' for all individuals that liberalism
197
KATE SOPER
abstractly professes to uphold and seek to advance. It
tedly not all of it) between liberal and socialist
is always debatable, however, at what point exactly
feminists would seem to be over means rather than
this may be said to occur in any feminist critique of
ends: what is at issue is the capacity of liberal forms of
liberalism. Virginia Sapiro, to take but one example,
polity to deliver on the emancipatory agenda rather
has presented Wollstonecraft as challenging not just
than the agenda itself.
the masculinity of the liberal conception of citizen-
inist critique remains ultimately consistent with the
ship but also ± and even more radically for her times
commitment to liberal goals and values even as it
± its rigid distinction between `public' and private'
rejects the liberal conception of the procedures
spheres. But Sapiro nonetheless seems to view such
through which they might be realised.
4
In this sense socialist-fem-
demands as capable of accommodation, at least in
If this is right, then one might claim that the point
principle, within the existing framework of a liberal
of final rupture with the immanent feminist critique
politics. Thus she writes that Wollstonecraft's argu-
of liberalism has come only more recently in the form
ment on democracy offered a `means of stretching
of the postmodernist rejection of the `foundational-
the liberal temperament to incorporate into political
ist' metaphysics and universal humanist commit-
thinking explicit concern for the quality of personal
ments of liberalism. For we are talking here of an
relations and day-to-day conditions of the lives of
attack on liberalism not for its political shortcomings
2
citizens.' On the other hand, one might be inclined
in realising its professed Enlightenment commit-
to argue in the converse sense, that if Wollstonecraft
ments, but of an attack directed against liberalism's
can indeed be interpreted as launching an early
Enlightenment pedigree itself. Nor is it any accident
`feminist' assault on the private-public division, then
that much of this critique has been formulated in
she is not so much `stretching' as directly contesting
terms of liberalism's unfortunate inheritance of, and
3
liberal sentiment. In other words, what seems raised
continued reliance upon, a so-called `Enlightenment
here is how far liberalism, not only in Wollstone-
subject'.
craft's time but also since then, is consistent with the
In effect, there are two aspects of this critique
dissolving or transcending of the public-private di-
corresponding to two related, but distinguishable,
vide that is called for in this form of feminist critique,
constructions to be placed upon the notion of the
or tolerant of its insistence on such a `politicising' of
`Enlightenment subject'. In a first and more histor-
the `personal'.
ical understanding, the idea refers us to the ideals of
But whether one reads Wollstonecraft as pushing
human subjectivity first promoted in the late seven-
the limits of liberal politics or as more radically
teenth century and more fully elaborated in the
breaking through these, there is little doubt that
historical period that we know of as `Enlighten-
in the later argument of the socialist feminists, it is
ment.'
liberal political institutions themselves that are un-
of `autonomy': the liberated or Enlightened indivi-
der attack. In arguing that without the overthrow of
dual is one who, in Kant's phrase, `dares to know',
capitalist exploitations and its class-based forms of
who is no longer in thrall to received ideas and
oppression, female emancipation will always be par-
externally imposed rules of comportment but thinks
tial, more formal than real and tend always to be
and acts in accordance with self-ordained principles
restricted to the more affluent and educationally
± who prescribes the law unto the self. Self-mastery,
privileged, socialist feminism would seem clearly at
independence, freedom from superstition and un-
odds with liberal reformism. Even so, given that it
thinking subservience to religious dictates, the ex-
clearly retains a commitment to some of the key
ercise of reason in pursuit of self-chosen ends: these
emancipatory goals of the liberal Enlightenment (to
are the recommended qualities of the subject as first
those of freedom, parity of treatment, self-realisation
promoted in the writings of the Enlighteners. The
and so on), one may still question whether socialist
subject in this conception is central to a normative
feminism really constitutes a decisive break with the
theory about what it is to be a fully realised, auton-
immanent critique of liberalism's essential mode of
omous human person, and in an important sense it is
reasoning. After all, much of the dispute (if admit-
a historical category, referring us to one who comes to
198
5
Most prominent among these is the idea
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT
as a consequence of the new rationality and
`autonomous' individual as a delusion of the bour-
scientific understanding illuminating the period of
geois epoch itself. The objection here is not so much
the Enlightenment. One might note, in this con-
that this conception of the self as `sovereign being'
nection, the contrasts which scholars have drawn
validated forms of independence whose enjoyment
between conceptions of reason in the seventeenth
was systematically denied to women, but that it
and eighteenth centuries. Cassirer, for example,
promoted a misguided ideology of personal autono-
argues that, for the later century, `it is no longer
my through which all individuals were encouraged to
the sum total of ``innate ideas'' given prior to all
overlook their actual ties of dependency on others,
experience which reveals the absolute essence of
and men, in particular, were enabled to justify their
things. Reason is now looked upon as rather an
detachment from the sphere of domesticity and
be
acquisition than a heritage.'
6
reproduction. Individuals are not only culturally
In a second and more abstract conception, on the
embedded and embodied to an extent and depth
other hand, the `Enlightenment subject' refers us to a
that liberal humanist ideals of selfhood utterly fail to
rather different theoretical entity, namely that ab-
appreciate; they are, in virtue of being so, fragmented
stracted individual who underpins the cosmopolitan
selves: the unified subject of the liberal-Enlighten-
and humanist aspirations of the liberal-Enlighten-
ment is a fiction as well as a masculine fetish.
ment project. This is the subject stripped of the
Postmodernist criticism of the Enlightenment sub-
accretion of culture, the bare-forked creature, the
ject in the `abstract' sense, on the other hand, is
human being conceived (in Wollstonecraft's phrase)
directed not at the discounting or downgrading of
as `naked human nature': the subject who is invoked,
specifically
either implicitly or explicitly, as the ground of the
against what is said to be a mistakenly universalist
project to unify the various tribes and nations of
and essentialist conception of humanity which lies at
man. It invokes that `common humanity' through
the heart of the Enlightenment and liberal-humanist
which, or on the basis of which, it alone makes sense
projects. The problem is not (as a feminist such as
to aspire to liberal forms of solidarity and the realisa-
Wollstonecraft supposed) that women have been
tion of universal values within the human commu-
irrationally and hypocritically excluded from the
nity.
claims that are made about the human subject,
feminine
values
and
attributes,
but
Even if these two conceptions of subjectivity are
but rather that this notion is itself a dangerous
linked in the sense that it was thought that everyone,
fiction: to invoke the idea of a universal humanity,
by virtue of possessing those attributes which are
so it is said, is to be guilty of a certain imperialism, to
definitive of human nature, could in principle realise
lend oneself to an anti-democratic impulse to over-
the ideal of autonomy, they are clearly distinguish-
look cultural and personal difference.
able inflections, and corresponding to them, as sug-
Going together with this feminist critique of the
gested, we find differing emphases in the feminist
Enlightenment conceptual legacy there has also been
polemic.
a tendency for feminist historians of the eighteenth
In their critical engagement with the `historical'
century to portray the ferments of the French Re-
sense of Enlightenment subjectivity, feminist the-
volution in a very negative light, and to deny they
ories have delivered a series of powerful arguments
had any positive role to play in the advance of female
against the idealisation of autonomy, objecting that
emancipation. In the argument of Joan Landes, the
it makes a fetish of masculine attributes (or at any
period is associated with the opening-up of the
rate of those associated with male performance in
exclusively `masculine' space of the `public' and
patriarchal culture). They have relatedly claimed
the dominion of a `reason' which is again viewed
that this devalues other ± `feminine' or culturally
as the exclusive attribute of the male.
coded `feminine' ± attributes which can contribute as
are led to believe, had little or nothing to gain from
much if not more to civilised culture and are there-
the process of liberalisation, and those of them who
fore just as worthy of advancement. Most damningly
were calling for women to be included within the
of all, they have dismissed the very idea of the
remit of the so-called `rights of man' tend to be
199
7
Women, we
KATE SOPER
dismissed as colluding in the maintenance of patriarchal culture.
8
relativism within feminism has been stated with
Modernist feminists from de Beau-
sufficient potency for it to be rather pointless for
voir onwards have been similarly charged by the
me to add much further to it here. Those who have
postmodernists
`Enlighten-
not been so convinced to date are unlikely to have
ment' ± and hence, so it is implied, inherently
their thinking on these issues altered by further
with
perpetuating
an
9
`masculine' ± cultural perspective. As Pauline John-
restatements of the realist argument.
son has pointed out, such feminists have presumed
But there is a somewhat different line of response,
that the critique of the claims of transcendent reason
which has received less attention, and which I
has `established modern feminism on the path of
propose to develop in more detail here. In essence,
counter-Enlightenment' and that feminism now re-
what I shall be arguing is that critics of liberalism
quires a `fundamental break from the Enlightenment
who see this as shamed or deeply flawed by virtue of
cause of reason and truth, which is exposed as
its Enlightenment origins and conceptual sources are
nothing more than a distorted and disguised will-
basing their argument on an extremely partial con-
to-power.'
10
In some cases, in fact, the Enlighten-
ception of this theoretical and cultural legacy. In
ment and liberal humanism by association have been
other words, the postmodernist feminist critique of
treated as if they were more or less synonymous with
liberalism is itself flawed to the extent that it is
everything white, male, middle class and heterosex-
reliant on a distorted and caricaturised version of
ual, and we have been invited to revile them accord-
liberal-Enlightenment thinking on gender issues.
14
ingly. Now, for the most part, where feminists have
II
countered the postmodernist positions on the Enlightenment subject, they have focused on the in-
In this context any attempt to offer a corrective to
consistencies
argument.
this version will necessarily have to be rather brief
They have sought to reveal the incoherence of
and synoptic. But a first point to be made is that the
denying any existential unity and autonomy at the
feminist dismissal of the liberal-Enlightenment is
level of subjectivity while seeking to expose cultural
often based on an overly homogeneous conception
norms and `constructions' as having negative con-
of its thought and culture. As recent scholars of the
sequences for female emancipation and self-fulfil-
period have been insisting, the scope and quality of
ment.
11
of
their
anti-essentialist
They have pointed out that it makes little
Enlightenment thinking even within a single nation
sense to advocate the politics of `identity' while
± let alone across Europe (and into America) ± is a
theoretically denying subjects any powers over their
good deal more varied, complex and uneven in its
self-formation. They have insisted on the incompat-
development than is allowed for by this feminist
ibility of a democratic politics of a kind purportedly
rhetoric. In recognition of this, Dorinda Outram
being defended in postmodernist argument with
proposes in her recent study what she terms a
respect for an indefinite plurality of cultural values
`capsule' conception of Enlightenment as containing
and aspirations. They have, relatedly, taken issue
sets of debates, stresses and concerns rather than
with the extremely reactionary forms of traditional-
representing a single, unified value system.
ism and fundamentalism that they see as licensed by
Enlightenment, according to Outram, presented it-
the postmodernist refusal to recognise any essential-
self as a series of processes and problems to those, like
ist or universalist position on human nature.
12
15
The
Even
Kant and Mendelssohn, who attempted to define it.
Derrida, Spivak and other figures associated with the
It was not so much a `modern paganism' as a quest for
deconstructionist position have, in the light of this
a `rational Christianity'.
ethical problem, made some gestural moves towards
with cultural difference, of continuous questioning
acknowledging the necessity of a minimalist essenti-
and relativisation of European `civilisation', and of
alism.
13
16
It was a period obsessed
Although I shall have a word more to say on
critique of colonialism. Most contemporary com-
these arguments in my concluding section, I believe
mentators also emphasise the disparate and uneven
the case against the incoherence of postmodernist
development of the `pockets' of Enlightenment con-
200
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT
cern in the different countries of Europe and their
ment's gains is open to the charge that it too readily
emergence in non-European locations during the
abstracts from gender-blind or patriarchalist dimen-
eighteenth
America.
sions of Habermas's social theory. Indeed, my own
Where once the Enlightenment was viewed as con-
position would be that you can endorse a broadly
fined to the argument of a few French philosophes
Habermasian
towards the close of the century, the contemporary
being a good deal more critical of Habermas's general
assessment favours a very long and geographically
neglect of gender issues along lines discussed by
extensive Enlightenment, by no means local to
Nancy Fraser and others. (Fraser has suggested that
Europe, and stretching temporally from the mid-
Habermas is guilty of a certain gender-blindness in
seventeenth right up to our own times ± and even
failing to see how close a critique of the commodi-
beyond. As Habermas has famously pronounced, the
fication of the cherished `symbolic' realm of child-
task of Enlightenment has still to be completed if we
rearing and nursing can come to rationalising female
are to be enabled to act as human beings.
domesticity.
century,
most
notably
in
22
position
on
Enlightenment
while
) All the same, I certainly think Jacob
It is also important that those relying on the anti-
is right to remind the postmodernist feminist histor-
Enlightenment rhetoric recognise that there is ex-
ians of the reactionary quality of the politics they risk
tensive debate today about the role that women
endorsing in their dismissive position on the Enlight-
played in Enlightenment and the gains they derived
enment legacy. I think they should acknowledge,
from it. Margaret Jacob and other recent historians of
too, how problematic their own position looks in
Enlightenment have challenged accounts of its un-
relation to the arguments of those seeking to advance
remittingly patriarchal character, insisting on its
female emancipation in the age of Enlightenment
overall positive impact for the feminist cause, and
itself.
arguing that it represented a very significant advance
One might briefly illustrate this point by reference
on the oppression of the Church-dominated and
to one of its better-known disputes ± that between
Absolutist political orders which it supplanted.
17
Wollstonecraft and Burke. From Burke's perspective,
To deny that, Jacob suggests, is implicitly to align
Wollstonecraft is indeed an abstractor from cultural
oneself with the position of the eighteenth-century
difference bent on denuding society of those distinc-
enemies of the revolution and with a long tradition
tions which are of its essence and which endow it
18
She acknowl-
with cultural richness. Thus, he professes, he cannot
edges that participation in the `public sphere' re-
relate to `human actions and concerns, in a simple
quired one to be both literate and in possession of
view of the object, as it stands stripped of every
adequate funds for club membership, theatre atten-
relation, in all the nakedness and solitude of meta-
dance and so forth, and that this restricted it to the
physical abstraction.'
of right-wing rejection of its legacy.
better-off among women.
19
23
For Burke, it is what distin-
But she denies that there
guished man from beast, culture from nature, that
was any increasing `masculinisation' of the `public
humanity is differentiated, its culture functioning as
sphere' in any of the main centres of Enlighten-
the sanctum of such difference:
ment,
20
and rejects the currently fashionable view of All the pleasing illusions, which made power
the French Revolution as a defeat for women. Rather than imagining the French movement
gentle, and obedience liberal, which harmonised
towards egalitarianism, leading to the contestations
the different shades of life, and which, by a bland
of the 1790s, as the signal of women's first defeat in
assimilation, incorporated into politics the senti-
modern democratic politics, the evidence, when seen
ments which beautify and soften private society,
comparatively,
The
are to be dissolved by this new conquering of light
emergence of the public sphere put women's rights
and reason. All the decent drapery of life is to be
on the western agenda just as it augured all the other
rudely torn off. All the super-added ideas, furn-
struggles about the meaning and truthfulness of
ished from the wardrobe of moral imagination,
suggests
quite
the
opposite.
democratic politics with which we still live.
21
which the heart owns, and the understanding ratifies, as necessary to cover the defects of our
Jacob's Habermasian defence of the Enlighten-
201
KATE SOPER
naked shivering nature, and to raise it to dignity
the Enlightenment, (to the distress of the more
in our own estimation, are to be exploded as
feminist-minded) was in reality a period obsessed
ridiculous, absurd, and antiquated fashion. On
with the topic of sexual difference: its origin, nature
this scheme of things, a king is but a man; a
and social implications. Indeed, it has been main-
queen is but a woman; a woman is but an animal;
tained that it is only in the period of Enlightenment
and an animal not of the highest order.
24
that the issue of feminine difference ± both corporeal and mental ± begins in any serious sense to be
For her part, Wollstonecraft was happy to plead
addressed, and hence only in the Enlightenment,
guilty to these charges in a polemic against the
when women are recognised as possessed of a quite
`gorgeous drapery' in which Burke had `enwrapped
separate and sui generis sexuality, that the sex-gender
his tyrannic principles': a polemic through which she
distinction, with its acknowledgement of the differ-
seeks both to expose the principles themselves and to
ence between what is given by nature and what is
denude them of their rhetorical garb. For Wollstone-
socially cultivated, is seen as having application. `No
craft, Burke's eloquence masks a profound irration-
longer would those who think about such matters',
alism, a defence of bigotry in the name of reverence
writes Thomas Laquer of the eighteenth century,
for
implication
`regard women as a lesser version of man along a
would be that slavery ought never to have been
vertical axis of infinite gradations, but rather as an
abolished. The Burkean doctrine would have us
altogether different creature along a horizontal axis
submit to this `inhuman custom' simpy because it
whose middle ground was largely empty.'
was the creation of `our ignorant forefathers', who,
tively he argues that it was only then that sex was
`not understanding the native dignity of man, sanc-
invented, that `science fleshed out, in terms presen-
tioned a traffic that outrages every suggestion of
table to the new epistemology, the categories ``male''
cultural
tradition,
reason and religion.'
whose
logical
25
26
Correla-
and ``female'' as opposite and incommensurable bio-
No doubt some will object to this association of
logical sexes', and hence only then that the speci-
the conservative Burke with contemporary defen-
ficity of the female body was fully recognised with all
dants of cultural relativism, given the difference in
its various discursive implications.
their motivations: Burke's to preserve aristocratic
tion he notes the influence on the eighteenth cen-
privilege, the latter's to check the normalising power
tury of Poulain de La Barre, who had challenged the
of western discourse. But the comparison certainly
notion of the inferiority of women on the ground
serves to dramatise the tensions, and potentially
that since sex difference was solely a matter of the
reactionary implications, of these positions which
body, there could be no social grounds to maintain
we have been invited to view as a wholly positive
it.
rupture with humanist thinking. Moreover, the fact
there were many voices ± most famously Diderot and
that certain parallels can be drawn here should give
Condorcet ± who argued for political and legal
pause for thought to all those who would sponta-
equality for both sexes, and deplored the neglect
neously acclaim Wollstonecraft's contribution to
of the education of women. Condorcet even went so
feminist and democratic theory while subscribing
far as to deny that natural differences between the
to theoretical positions very much at odds with hers.
sexes had any bearing on their rights of citizenship:
In this connection, one might note how paradox-
why deny to women on the grounds of their suscept-
ical it is, in view of the current emphasis on `differ-
ibility to pregnancy what no one dreamt of denying
ence', that it tended to be the more progressive, and,
to men cooped up for half the year with the gout?
28
27
In this connec-
Among the philosophes themselves, of course,
if one could call them so, `feminist' elements in the
Of course, as Joan Scott has pointed out, Con-
eighteenth century who were most resistant to re-
dorcet was in something of a minority in pursuing
cognising any major natural, as opposed to culturally
this line on the issue of equality and natural differ-
induced, divergences between the sexes. The con-
ence,
verse side of this paradox is that so far from obscuring
numerous
or abstracting from the specific conditions of women,
which were prejudicial and in many cases deeply
202
29
and I am not disputing the existence of the other
discourses
on
female
difference
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT
offensive in their suggestions about female limita-
effeminacy, and regarded women as a threat to a
tions and deficiencies. The point is, rather, that there
`natural'
was a much wider and more varied spectrum of
might note, Tomaselli has questioned the tendency
arguments about gender and subjectivity than is
of much feminist theory to represent women as
recognised by the contemporary dismissive refer-
having been thought closer to nature. At least in
ences to the Enlightenment subject. One might cite
the period of Enlightenment, she suggests, culture ±
as one example here the extremely crenellated de-
the move away from nature ± is represented as a
bate on the extent to which women had gained from
(variously benign or malignant) emasculation.
the process of civilisation.
30
masculinity.
33
In
this
connection,
one
The more conventional Enlightenment emphasis
There was some general agreement even among
on the difference of the sexes went together, of
those critical of the contemporary treatment of
course, with the genderisation of mental faculties.
women that the latter had only benefited in the
Reason, presented in Kantian philosophy as the
progress out of savagery. For Catherine Macaulay,
distinctive attribute of personhood, was viewed as
woman `in the barbarous stages of mankind' had
a pre-eminently masculine possession, and in the
been reduced to a state of abject slavery; for Diderot,
writings of a number of eighteenth-century thinkers
`the unhappy woman in the cities is far unhappier
± notably Rousseau and Kant ± women are depicted
31
and he, William
as by nature more capricious and emotional creatures
Alexander and John Millar all thought that the
incapable of attaining to a fully rational autonomy.
degree of civility gained could be judged by the
But even Kant implies this is a deficit brought about
manner in which women were treated. Alexander
by lack of education and inappropriate patronage.
additionally presented women as having ± through
Kant has often been rebuked by feminists for his
their cultivation of beauty ± also stimulated men to
condescension. But when he remarks ironically in his
experience a romantic affection for a particular in-
essay on Enlightenment that `those guardians who
dividual, a personalisation of attachments through
have so kindly assumed superintendence over them'
which they had spared themselves the misery and
will soon see to it `that the step to competence is held
barbarism of anonymous sexual relations. Such con-
to be very dangerous by the far greater portion of
ceptions, however, did not sit easily alongside the
mankind (and the entire fair sex)'
recognition by these thinkers of the continued en-
perfectly consistent with the sort of claims made
slavement of women in their society ± especially
by Wollstonecraft and others concerned in the per-
where this went together (as it did very notably in
iod with improving female autonomy.
still in the midst of the forests';
34
his point is
the case of Diderot) with a critique of the corruption
But more importantly, perhaps, one must note
and decadence of civilisation and a call `to return to
how much there is in the culture and argument of
nature'. Diderot tends to forget (or is necessarily
the period which runs counter to any simplistic
forced to abstract from) his negative assessment of
presentation of the liberal-Enlightenment as the site
the condition of women in primitive society, in his
or time of the privileging of the type of reason which
praise of primitivism. `Ask civilised man whether he
modern critics refer to as `masculine', meaning by
is happy. Ask the savage whether he is unhappy,' he
that a narrowly instrumental, overly logical and
writes. `If both reply ``No'' the dispute is settled.' But,
abstracted mode of cognition. We have only to
as Tomaselli points out, `to have asked a woman the
consider the attention paid by theorists from the
same set of questions would have yielded, judging by
late seventeenth century onwards to the role of
Diderot's own account, both a ``no'' and a ``yes''.'
32
sensory experience, to the imagination, to the pos-
Rousseau, on the other hand, viewed the turn to
session and development of what was termed `sen-
`Romantic' love not as a source of commendable
sibility'
civility and liberation from barbarism, but as the
judgement, to the aesthetic as mediator between
enslavement of men. Though agreeing to the role of
reason and the sense, to realise how much more
women in cultivating luxury and beauty, he saw the
there was to the Enlightenment discourses of the
advance of culture as a progression in a deplorable
self.
203
35
to
the
analysis
of
taste
and
aesthetic
The Age of Reason `distrusted Reason,' argues
KATE SOPER
E. L. Tuveson, `as it had been understood for many
Addison's or Carter's is better interpreted as belong-
centuries ± far more deeply than did any preceding
ing to a proto-Romantic reaction to the liberal-
period.'
36
Enlightenment rather than as contributing to its
Another commentator goes on to claim:
stock of ideas. Yet if we follow the contemporary It would be mistaken to think of reason as the
disposition to think in terms of a `long' Enlight-
rallying cry of the Enlightenment thinkers except
enment, then we must view it as encompassing much
in so far as it was opposed to faith, and the Age of
pre-Romantic and Romantic argument on the self,
Reason as opposed to the Age of Superstition. If
directly opposed though such argument was to scien-
one's gaze shifts away from the battles with l'In-
tific positivism, mechanistic conceptions of nature
à me, then the `Age of Sentiments', `Sentimenfa
and the dogmatic pursuit of reason. Or, to put the
tality', `Feelings', `Passions', `Pleasure', `Love' or
point otherwise, Romanticism, which retains the
`Imagination' are apter titles for the movement of
core Enlightenment idea of a unitary subject pos-
ideas in the eighteenth century.
37
sessed of autonomous agency ± and which, after all, owes a great deal to the influence of two figures,
This is surely to overstate the case against reason,
Rousseau and Kant, usually deemed to belong un-
which remained the sovereign court of appeal, and
controvertibly to the Enlightenment ± can be viewed
was viewed by Condorcet, Voltaire and Diderot and
itself as part of the unfolding process of Enlight-
most key thinkers of the age as of critical importance
enment self-criticism. One might argue, too, that
to controlling the flights of fancy and excesses of the
there
imagination. But we certainly need to recognise the
mediated Enlightenment rationality still at work
force of the point made earlier regarding the im-
in John Stuart Mill's liberalism and that this gives
portance of distinguishing between a typically se-
a particular inflection to his argument on a range of
venteenth-century view of reason as `sum total of
topics, including that of female subjection.
is
something
of
this
same
Romantically-
innate ideas' and the more characteristically eighteenth-century Kantian ± and liberal ± view of it as
III
committed to an unprejudicial `critique' of `pure' reason, and to sceptical investigation of the knowl-
I have tried to show here that Enlightenment culture
edge claimed on the authority of `innate ideas'. We
was a good deal more complex, and in a number of
should recognise, too, that the tendency of some
ways more sensitive to the limitations of its own
contemporary feminist criticism to equate Enlight-
universalising and rationalising claims, than glib
enment with the exercise of a narrowly conceived
postmodernist dismissals often allow. I have tried
`masculine reason' is to abstract from the many
to show, too, that one rejects the period of Enlight-
nuanced discourses that went into its intellectual
enment and its legacy as radically unfriendly to the
ferment. It is also to ignore the voices of those (such
advancement of feminist demands only at the risk of
as Hume, Addison, Hutcheson, Shaftesbury, Burke,
appearing to opt for a theoretical perspective that
Smith) who in the period itself did challenge the
shares more with Burke's patrician defence of culture
exclusive endorsement of reason. Among the women
and custom than with Wollstonecraft's attempts to
who did was Elizabeth Carter, acclaimed by Johnson
strip away the veils of patriarchal privilege. It would,
as the best Greek scholar in the kingdom, who
of course, be quite mistaken to present either Woll-
followed Addison in her scepticism about science
stonecraft in particular, or the voices of liberal-En-
and argued (as did Addison and Adam Smith) for
lightenment in general, as offering the last word on
the indispensability of the imagination as a source of
female emancipation. My plea here is only that they
empathy with others and the need to strengthen
should be acknowledged as an important first step in
what Hutcheson called the `sympathetick sense'. It is
the right direction, and that when feminists de-
not reason, she argued, but imagination which dis-
nounce liberalism simply in virtue of its Enlight-
tinguishes us from the beast.
enment `rationalism' or `humanism' or conceptions of subjectivity, they are making use of an easy
Admittedly, it may be argued that a voice such as
204
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT
rhetoric rather than engaging in serious and discri-
denial of this that has licensed some of the most
minating critique.
callous political neglect of the miseries and oppressions of others.
They are also, as suggested earlier in my brief remarks on the inconsistencies of the postmodernist
Postmodernist feminists should therefore accept
defence of `difference', frequently arguing in ways
that in the end their critiques of liberal humanism
which are covertly reliant on liberal-democratic
make better sense and retain more internal coher-
values themselves. What sense, for example, can
ence if presented as a continuation of the immanent
we ultimately make of postmodern feminist critiques
critique of Enlightenment first sounded in the dis-
of the conflationist and Eurocentric tendencies of
course of Wollstonecraft and other proto-feminist
liberal humanism if not in terms of its failure to
liberal critics. Or if they do not agree to this, they
advance a more genuinely universal conception of
should at least be ready to accept the full implica-
the human community? How do we understand the
tions of their value-relativism and anti-realism, and
charge that liberal approaches to emancipation are
thus accept that there are ultimately no objective
`ethnocentric' or less than `democratic' in the respect
criteria of female emancipation, and no grounds
extended to `otherness' or `difference', if we do not
therefore on which to defend any projected vision
presuppose a commitment to some minimally essen-
of this as more or less `progressive'. To deny that
tialist and universalist conception of human nature:
there is any link between the discourses of `power'
unless, that is, we hypothesise a common suscept-
and `oppression' and specific extra-discursive condi-
ibility to pain and humiliation in the absence of
tions of existence and forms of human experience, is
certain forms of respect and recognition? Liberalism
to disown the political teleology associated with the
in general, and liberal feminism in particular, are
feminist movement, whether this be given a more
indeed open to the charge of having taken class-
liberal or more socialist interpretation. A postmo-
biased and culturally partial views of what is suppo-
dernist position can, in other words, escape the
sedly common to everyone. But it is one thing to
charges of being inconsistent in its treatment of
expose this bias and partiality; it is quite another to
liberal-democratic values, but only at the cost of
condemn liberal thinking for its invocation of a
licensing an indefinite and uncontrollable play of
shared structure of cognition, need and affectivity,
meaning such that any and every treatment of
since little sense can be made of the request for
women might count, under some discursive regime
greater tolerance of other viewpoints and more
or within a particular political context, as a further-
recognition of specific identities and constituencies,
ance of feminist goals. The question then is: can this
unless some commonality of cognitive and emotional
still count as a distinctively `feminist' theoretical
response to the world is presupposed. Indeed, it is the
offering at all?
Notes
1. As Peter Hulme and Ludmilla Jordanova claim of the
other. But I think there is enough shared commitment
Enlightenment period, since this was `in many of its
to these formal principles for the point to have some validity.
aspects, highly critical, it was inevitable that, even as
5. I put the point in these terms in order to leave open
its identity emerged, it was subverted.' Hulme and
the question of the periodisation of Enlightenment,
Jordanova (eds) (1990), p. 2. 2. Sapiro (1992), p. xiv.
which it is not my intention to address in this chapter.
3. Cf. my own discussion of Sapiro's position in Soper
Suffice it to note that there is still considerable dispute on both the temporality and the definition of Enlight-
(1997). 4. Obviously, this is a rather bald claim as it stands and
enment. As Hulme and Jordanova point out, there are
much could be said in qualification of it. I would not
basically two approaches to the issue, the first con-
want to deny that liberal and socialist feminists will
fining it more narrowly to the ideas of a group of
differ on the `order' of the agenda and the relative
(mainly French) intellectuals during the period dating
priority to be given to the items on it ± especially those
from the death of Louis XIV (1715) to the events of
of freedoms, on the one hand, and equality, on the
the French Revolution (1789±94); the second ap-
205
KATE SOPER
proach, which is altogether broader, would emphasise
17. Ibid., pp. 95±113; see also the studies by Jacob, Phyllis
the origins of Enlightenment in the work of Bacon,
Mack, Ruth Perry and Margaret Hunt in Women in the
Newton and Locke in the seventeenth century and
Enlightenment, in Women and History, 9 (1984) (rep-
argue for a much longer Enlightenment ± at least into
rinted in book form by the Institute for Historical Research and the Haworth Press, 1984).
the early decades of the nineteenth century, and even beyond: Hulme and Jordanova (eds) (1990), pp. 1±15.
18. Jacob (1994), p. 98 f.
Although the recent Blackwell Companion to the En-
19. Ibid., p. 100f.
lightenment focuses on the years 1720±80 (Yolton, et
20. As Jacob points out, most historians now accept the
al. (eds), 1991), historians of the period today increas-
importance for understanding of the eighteenth cen-
ingly favour the idea of a `long' Enlightenment. For a
tury of the category of the `public sphere' (by which is
brief guide to the recent history of Enlightenment
intended the universe of `public opinion formation,
interpretation, see Outram (1995), chapter 1.
informal sociability, intellectual interaction and net-
6. Cassirer (1951), p. 13; cf. Pauline Johnson's discussion
working beyond the family and outside the formal
(and illustration of this difference in respect of the
institutions of the state), as they do the role of
concepts of reason employed respectively by Mary
Habermas's work in drawing attention to it, notably
Anstell
and
Mary
Wollstonecraft)
in
Habermas (1992).
Johnson
21. Jacob (1994), pp. 106±7.
(1993), pp. 3±12.
22. The Habermasian framework tends both to obscure
7. Landes (1988). 8. See Jardine (1985); cf. also the dispute between
the very material character of much child-rearing
Timothy Reiss and Frances Ferguson in Kauffman
activity and the extensive permeation of family life
(ed.) (1989) (where Ferguson defends Wollstonecraft
by the systemic forces of power and money. Feminists
against Reiss's claim that her assertion of the rights of
have also accused him of failing to appreciate the
women was bound to prove ineffective because it was
dualised
so immersed in the dominant discourse of Enlight-
(which may reduce female dependency on the male
enment). See also Johnson (1993).
breadwinner, but only at the cost of exposing women
and
gendered
nature
of
welfare
systems
9. See, for example, Evans (1985); Lloyd (1984), chapter
to a patriarchal and androcentric state bureaucracy).
6. Toril Moi discusses and defends de Beauvoir against
See Fraser's `What's Critical About Critical Theory?',
similar charges in Moi (1992). For a brief survey, see
in Benhabib and Cornell (eds) (1987); cf. also the
again Johnson (1993), pp. 3±4.
article by Linda Nicholson in the same volume. (Of course this type of feminist criticism is itself caught in a
10. Johnson (1993), p. 3.
certain tension since it is reliant on a privileging of the
11. See Fuss (1989); Kate Soper, `Feminism, Humanism, Subjectivity
`symbolic', feminine-associated values and forms of
and the Question of Value', in Soper (1990), pp.
human interaction in its overall critique of patriarchy,
228±45; and Squires (ed.) (1993), pp. 17±30 respec-
even as it is critical of Habermas's failure to draw out
tively; also Lovibond (1989) and (1994).
the implications of his normative schema for feminist
Postmodernism'
and
`Postmodernism,
12. Soper (1990), and `Postmodernism. Subjectivity and
theory and practice.)
the Question of Value', in Squires (ed.) (1993); see
23. Burke (1961), p. 19.
also Nussbaum (1992).
24. Ibid., p. 90. 25. `A Vindication of the Rights of Men, in a Letter to the
13. See, for example, Derrida (1989), esp. p. 56f.; Spivak
Right Honourable Edmund Burke', in Wollstonecraft
(1991) and the essays in Spivak (1993).
(1989), p. 14.
14. In this respect I am pursuing the general line of response already opened up by Johnson (1993). I
26. Laquer (1990), p. 148. Cf. Outram (1995), chapter 5,
see my own survey here as offering further support
which also stresses the concern with female difference
for her claim that contemporary feminism is working
± and its contradictory implications in view of the
within a distorted and partial version of Enlighten-
Enlightenment emphasis on a universal human nature
ment and its commitment to reason.
and human history, both validated by the possession of
15. Outram (1995), p. 12.
a single human form of rationality. See also the
16. See ibid., chapter 3; cf. Margaret Jacob's argument that
discussion of the concept of the `individual' in Scott (1996), pp. 5±14.
the `two extremes of Spinozism, pantheism and materialism, lurked in the underground on both Protes-
27. Laquer (1990), pp. 149±50.
tant sides of the Channel, but from Samuel Clarke to
28. Ibid., p. 155±6.
Johannes Stinstra, Betje Wolff, and Aagje Deken,
29. Scott (1996), pp. 7±8.
godly Enlightenment ± born out of their reading of
30. As discussed in Tomaselli (1985).
the new science ± seemed a sufficient antidote to
31. Both cited in ibid., p. 109.
dogmatism,
32. Ibid., p. 117.
enthusiasm,
or
absolutism'.
Jacob
33. Ibid., pp. 118±20. Cf. Outram (1995), pp. 88±9.
(1994), p. 98.
206
LIBERALISM, FEMINISM, ENLIGHTENMENT
which threatens them if they try to go alone'. Kant
34. Kant (1963a), p. 3 (a more cutting translation of Kant
(1963a), p. 3.
(1991), p. 54). Kant continues: `After the guardians
35. See, for example, Tuveson (1960); Engell (1982); Taylor
have first made their domestic animals dumb and have
(1989), parts III and IV; Eagleton (1990), chapters 2±4.
made sure that these placid creatures will not dare take a single step without the harness of the cart to which
36. Tuveson (1960), p. 24.
they are tethered, the guardians show them the danger
37. Yolton, et al. (eds) (1991), p. 446.
207
16
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY: THE CHALLENGE OF FEMALE GENITAL CUTTING Diana Tietjens Meyers
Terminology for the multiform phenomenon I shall
euphemistic because the analogy with male circum-
discuss is itself a matter of vexed controversy. Some
cision suggests a relatively risk-free, minor procedure
scholars prefer the expression `female circumcision'
that
on the grounds that this is the expression preferred
Although one form of the female procedure is aptly
by women who are now subject to the practice. To
analogised to male circumcision, most are not.
does
not
interfere
with
sexual
pleasure.
adopt any other language, they maintain, would be
On the other hand, the morally condemnatory
to show disrespect for these women and their cultures
language, `female genital mutilation', prejudices the
and perhaps to engage in cultural imperialism. Other
Á -vis this practice. question of women's autonomy vis-a
scholars opt for medicalised terminology ± either
Since there is a presumption that a person who
`female genital surgery' or `female genital operations'.
chooses to be mutilated does not choose autono-
Still other scholars prefer the expression `female
mously, this language is question-begging in the
genital mutilation' on the grounds that no other
context of my present topic. Moreover, I suspect
language expresses the suffering inflicted by this
that Euro-Americans are attracted to this language
practice and that other labels implicitly condone a
largely because they do not imagine that women like
cruel practice that sustains male dominance by tor-
themselves have in the past consented to such
menting women.
`mutilation' and that mothers in their own society
I have adopted the expression `female genital
today continue to authorise comparable procedures
cutting' in order to address several concerns. On
on their daughters. Consequently they fail to em-
the one hand, I see the medicalised terminology and
pathise with contemporary women in other societies
the culturally relative terminology as euphemistic.
who make similar choices. Thus, I have sought
Although
expressions accurately
terminology designed to avoid denying the pain
represent the hygienic conditions of the hospitals
and impairment often associated with female genital
in which some Euro-American and African female
cutting but also to avoid presuming that women
genital cutting is performed, they give the false
involved in the practice have no autonomy.
the medicalised
impression that female genital cutting is usually a
Many Euro-Americans might doubt that there is
sanitary procedure performed with anaesthesia. Un-
any basis for ascribing autonomy to women whose
fortunately, the procedure is seldom performed under
cultures mandate female genital cutting. Yet, the
safe conditions, and it never improves women's
feminist literature on female genital cutting provides
health. The culturally relative terminology is also
ample evidence that many women exercise effective
208
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
agency with respect to this practice. One striking
programmes may not be the most effective way to
finding is that autonomy is to be found among its
eradicate female genital cutting, they have proved
accommodators as well as resisters, and that neither
to be the most effective way to promote women's
group can be presumed to enjoy greater autonomy
autonomous control over their sexuality and health.
than the other. If this is so, one cannot identify
Finally, I consider how the cultural imperative of
autonomy or lack of it simply by looking at what
self-perpetuation entails both support for and lim-
people choose or refuse. Autonomy must dwell in the
itation of autonomy. If cultures are to meet the need
process of deciding, not in the nature of the action
for change in response to historical contingencies,
decided upon. Moreover, students of female genital
they must ensure that cultural initiates have auton-
cutting regard it as essential to avoid the trap of
omy skills that enable them to adjust their tradi-
conceding that resisters are western dupes and, as
tions. Yet, if cultures are to survive, they must
cultural outsiders, have no right to press for change,
channel exercise of these autonomy skills into
whereas accommodators are more authentically re-
constructive critique framed by cultural allegiance,
presentative of their culture of origin and, as female
and
insiders, confirm the legitimacy of the practice. To
autonomy skills which heighten discontent and
overcome this dilemma, one must resist the tempta-
precipitate defection. I argue that autonomy-aug-
tion to explain greater autonomy as a function of the
menting educational programmes succeed by devel-
reduced influence of cultures that mandate female
oping
genital cutting. Culture cannot be cast as the villain
systematically,
that paralyses some women's autonomy, nor can it be
ceived as the exercise of self-discovery, self-defini-
cast as the hero that frees women into autonomous
tion
lives. Still, in acknowledging that some social con-
culture is not only intelligible, it is a morally
texts are more conducive to autonomy than others,
defensible
students of female genital cutting spotlight the am-
autonomy for an era of global feminism.
they
must
discourage
autonomy
and
but
skills
skills,
politically
development
that
needlessly,
self-direction and
the
cultures suppressed.
of
have Con-
autonomy-within-
viable
conception
of
biguous role of culture with respect to the question of women's autonomy.
Cultural Contexts
My project is to explore the implications of these
and Female Genital Cutting
understandings of the relation between culture, female genital cutting and women's agency for
Among Euro-Americans, misapprehensions about
autonomy theory. I begin by surveying the reasons
culture and female genital cutting abound. For ex-
different cultures give for female genital cutting and
ample, many people associate female genital cutting
the different types of female genital cutting. My
with a single region, usually sub-Saharan Africa. But
purpose in exhibiting the enormous variation in
the practice is also found indigenously in North
this practice and in women's responses to it is to
America, Asia and the Middle East, and immigrants
undercut simplistic dismissals of women's autonomy
have spread their practices far and wide.
with respect to female genital cutting that rely on
misconception is that female genital cutting is rooted
attention-grabbing horror stories and generalised
in a single culture, but this is far from the case. A
theories of patriarchal domination. I then examine
highly diverse array of cultures furnish a variety of
two kinds of autonomy theory ± latitudinarian,
rationales for female genital cutting.
1
A related
value-neutral accounts and restrictive, value-satu-
Many people are astonished to learn that, among
rated accounts ± and I argue that neither approach
middle-class white Americans in the late nineteenth
adequately addresses the phenomena of women's
century and continuing into the early twentieth
autonomy
To
century, clitoridectomy was a popular and medically
bring these phenomena into focus, it is useful to
certified `cure' for hysteria, nymphomania, lesbian-
review a number of strategies for augmenting wo-
ism
men's autonomy regarding female genital cutting. I
though, there are cultural groups that practice female
urge that, although culturally anchored educational
genital cutting today for the opposite reason: they
regarding
female
genital
cutting.
209
and
`excessive'
masturbation.
2
Curiously,
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
believe that female genital cutting enhances women's sexual desire.
3
fies the individual and enhances her fertility, for they
More typical, though, are ra-
believe that the clitoris can kill a man if it touches
tionales similar to those formerly current in the US:
his penis or that it will kill the baby during child-
many cultural groups maintain that female genital
birth.
cutting reduces women's sexual appetite, enforces
cessary to morally appropriate fertility, and morally
norms of chastity and thereby protects family hon-
sanctioned fertility may be thought necessary to
our.
4
10
Female genital cutting may be thought ne-
producing socially and morally viable children.
11
Repressing women's sexuality is by no means the
In one Sudanese community, `son of an uncircum-
only, nor even the most frequent, reason given for
cised mother' is among the most derogatory epithets
female genital cutting. Gender regimentation is a
one can utter.
prevalent rationale, as well. From this perspective,
aesthetic standards as well as moral standards, and
the purpose of female genital cutting is to ensure that
aesthetic considerations sometimes dictate female
the individuals assigned to dichotomous gender ca-
genital cutting. A woman who belongs to a culture
tegories have anatomically suitable genitals.
that considers gaping orifices, including the mouth,
In the USA today, female genital cutting is a
12
Gender norms are associated with
distasteful asks, `which is better, an ugly opening or a 13
routine, though increasingly contested, medical in-
dignified closure?'
tervention when a condition called `ambiguous gen-
is pivotal. Some cultural groups believe that Islam
5
In some cases, religious doctrine
italia' is diagnosed. Physicians and parents generally
mandates female genital cutting and that Allah will
presume that left `untreated' an elongated clitoris
not hear a woman's prayers if she has not been cut.
will have deleterious effects on a girl's psychological development and will prove socially disabling.
6
14
Another cluster of reasons concerns intercultural
To
political relations. Within a local framework, cultur-
the extent that this negative prognosis is warranted,
al identification is sometimes cited: whether wo-
it is because contemporary US culture insists that
men's genitals are cut or not and, if they are cut,
there are only two kinds of people ± males and
how they are cut may be an important way in which
females ± and because this particular culture pre-
cultural groups inhabiting the same geographical
scribes genitalia conforming to restrictive norms for
region are differentiated.
7
15
From a global perspective,
each category. Without `corrective' demasculinising
loyalty to one's cultural roots and repudiation of
surgery, it is thought that a genetic female endowed
western influence are sometimes cited: female genital
with `ambiguous' genitalia will be unable to attain a
cutting was often seen as testifying to opposition to
feminine identity. The theme of demasculinisation is
colonialism and more recently as affirming indigen-
also found in some non-western cultures. Anticipat-
ous tradition in the face of western contempt for
ing Freud, those cultures view the clitoris as a mascu-
non-western cultures and western economic and
line organ and therefore regard excision as necessary
cultural penetration.
to achieving a feminine gender identity.
8
16
World-
Although cultural rationales for female genital
wide, it seems, people believe that babies can be born
cutting can be classified according to the broad
with `unnatural', though not sexually or reproduc-
themes of sexual repression, gender identity, and
tively dysfunctional, genitalia.
group cohesion, there is no uniformity whatsoever
Whereas American culture currently mandates
in the specifics. This heterogeneity is echoed in the
female genital cutting as a corrective for what it
variety of forms that female genital cutting takes.
deems `abnormal' genitalia, members of many other
Many Euro-Americans believe that female genital
cultural groups regard female genital cutting as an
cutting is a single procedure, but this is not true. In
indispensable rite of passage through which all girls
addition to western cosmetic procedures designed to
must pass in order to attain the identity and the
`feminise' ostensibly male genitalia, practices range
status of women. Some see female genital cutting as a
from sunna ± that is removal of the clitoral prepuce ±
test of courage and endurance that prepares the
to infibulation ± that is excision of the clitoris, the
individual for labour pains and birthing.
9
Others
labia minora and the labia majora and suturing the
contend that female genital cutting physically puri-
remaining tissue together to create a minuscule
210
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
orifice.
17
Correlated with this spectrum of outcomes
Á -vis female genital cutting cannot rest on my vis-a
is a spectrum of health risks in the immediate after-
generalisations about the severity of the outcome, for
math of the procedure and a spectrum of long-term
the medical and psychosexual consequences vary
consequences for women's sexuality, physical health,
substantially. Women's autonomy with respect to
and psychological well-being. Moreover, different
female genital cutting cannot be ruled out on the
groups perform the cutting procedure at different
grounds that no one could freely choose the endan-
ages ± some on infants or very young girls, some on
germent and impairment resulting from these pro-
adolescents. Adult women participate in this prac-
cedures, for the consequences are not always grave.
tice not only by authorising and/or carrying out the
Nor can one assume that the reasons women have for
procedure but also, in groups where infibulation is
either accommodating or resisting female genital
the rule, by agreeing to reinfibulation after child-
cutting are consistent across cultural groups. So a
birth. It is a mistake, then, to suppose that female
theory of women's autonomy that is applicable to
genital cutting has the same impact on all affected
societies in which female genital cutting is practiced
women's lives.
cannot rely on ascriptions of particular reasons to the
Finally, it is necessary to dispel some prevalent
women who are subject to this practise. The content
misconceptions about culture. The misconception
of women's deliberations cannot settle the question
that most incenses non-western women is the `other-
of their autonomy, for the reasons they invoke are
ing' of the very idea of culture ± that is the supposi-
not uniform.
tion that culture itself is a non-western phenomenon
It is clear that some cultural groups pre-empt girls'
and that westerners are not themselves enculturated.
autonomy by cutting their genitals when they are
Alternatively,
that
young and helpless. However, female genital cutting
everyone is enculturated yet assume that, unlike
westerners
is part of an adolescent initiation rite in many
western cultures in which dissent is tolerated and
cultural groups. Although it is troubling that these
cultural change is ongoing, non-western cultures are
girls may have little experience of their own genital
homogeneous and static.
18
may
acknowledge
Nothing could be farther
eroticism and presumably have no experience of the
from the case. Members of a cultural group do not
interpersonal intimacies that this sexual responsive-
think and live in lockstep. Within cultural groups,
ness makes possible, it is doubtful that girls of this age
interpretations of cultural beliefs vary, and so do
altogether lack autonomy.
interpretations of cultural practices. Drawing on the
participate in this practice as midwife practitioners,
countless beliefs and practices that constitute a
as mothers who arrange female genital cutting for
culture ± beliefs and practices that are in some
their daughters and as postpartum mothers who
respects in tension with one another ± and accenting
request reinfibulation. It is important to bear in
and linking some of these beliefs and practices while
mind, as well, that during the nineteenth century
de-emphasising or isolating others, people individua-
many adult Euro-American women anxiously sought
lise their cultural heritage. As a result, traditionalists
relief from psychopathology or sexual deviance and
often coexist, albeit uneasily, with nonconformists.
willingly underwent clitoridectomy. Whatever one
Moreover, the survival of cultures depends on their
may think of juvenile agency, these women's agency
capacity to modify their beliefs and practices to meet
must be analysed on its own merits.
20
Likewise, adult women
new contingencies, and their capacity to adjust
It is wrong, moreover, to assume that all female
depends in part on the internal variegation I have
members of cultural groups that practice female
described.
19
genital cutting collaborate with this practice. Wo-
A seamless, timeless culture is a dead
men are not in the grip of totalising, internalised
culture. This brief survey of the anthropological back-
cultures which drive them to comply with a female
ground of female genital cutting is sufficient to
genital cutting imperative. There are many instances
demonstrate the daunting complexity of analysing
of individual women persuading their families not to
women's agentic position with respect to this prac-
uphold the practice, and instances of women orga-
tice. Evidently, judgements about women's autono-
nising against female genital cutting are on the rise.
211
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
Although data about the prevalence of female geni-
what their capacities and limitations actually are,
tal cutting is disputable, it is quite possible that
and so forth ± and they enact this introspective
adherence to the practice is waning. Accordingly,
understanding of their `true' selves in their lives.
to declare women who belong to cultural groups that
There is a good fit between their identity, their
practice female genital cutting devoid of autonomy
attitudes toward themselves and their conduct. Col-
would be to deny existing opportunities for choice
loquial expressions, such as `I feel at one with myself'
and to erase the real, sometimes courageous, choices
and `I feel right in my skin' voice this sense of
women have actually made.
integration. As these idioms suggest, living autono-
Women exercise agency, then, both by complying
mously is satisfying, sometimes exhilarating. Subjec-
with and by resisting female genital cutting. A theory
tively, then, the value of autonomy stems from the
of women's autonomy must take these realities into
fascination of self-discovery and the gratification of
account, but it must also ask whether women have as
self-determination. Objectively, it rests on the dig-
much autonomy as they should have with respect to
nity of the distinctive individual and the wondrous
female genital cutting.
diversity of the lives individuals may fashion for themselves. A second aim an account of autonomy should
Female Genital Cutting's
fulfil is to explicate the nature of the personal and
Challenge to Autonomy Theory
social costs of suppressing autonomy. Individuals
The phenomenon of female genital cutting presents
experience lack of autonomy as a sense of being
two opposed temptations for autonomy theory. On
out of control or being under the control of others ±
the one hand, latitudinarian, value-neutral accounts
whether other identifiable individuals or anonymous
of autonomy ± whether rational choice models or
societal powers. At odds with themselves, at odds
hierarchical identification models ± are attractive
with their behaviour, or both, non-autonomous in-
because they do not withhold respect from women
dividuals often feel anxious about their choices,
who accommodate female genital cutting by impugn-
contemptuous of themselves and disappointed with
ing these women's ability to make their own judge-
their lives. Alternatively, they may simply feel hol-
ments and choices. On the other hand, restrictive,
low, for they may feel they have been made into
value-saturated accounts of autonomy that deny that
vehicles for projects that they do not disavow but
people can be both oppressed and autonomous are
that are not their own. In one way or another, non-
attractive because, in claiming that false conscious-
autonomous individuals suffer from alienation from
ness blocks the self-determination of women in
self. I would add, moreover, that societies that are
cultures that mandate female genital cutting, they
not conducive to autonomy incur a moral loss since
highlight the harsh personal cost of living under such
they thwart (or try to thwart) insightful social cri-
oppressive
tique. When a society discourages self-exploration
social
regimes.
Neither
of
these
ap-
and self-expression, it discourages attention to symp-
proaches is ultimately convincing, however. Preliminary to characterising the weaknesses of
toms of discontent and shields social ideologies and
these approaches, it is useful to review what an
institutions from probing examination and opposi-
account of autonomy should accomplish. An ac-
tional activism. Autonomy exposes the need for
count of autonomy aims principally to explicate
social change and equips people to pursue it.
an especially valuable mode of living. That mode
I shall not linger long over latitudinarian, value-
of living is captured in a number of familiar expres-
neutral views for their weaknesses have been diag-
sions: `she lives by her own lights'; `he is his own
nosed and elaborated elsewhere. Briefly, rational
man'; `she's always been true to herself'; and the like.
choice views take people's desires, values and goals
Autonomous individuals are not mere conformists.
for granted and identify autonomy with devising
They need not be eccentric, but they do rely on their
plans
own judgement. They know who they are ± what
identification
really matters to them, who they deeply care about,
scrutiny in light of second-order volitions and link
212
that
maximise
satisfaction.
21
Hierarchical
views subject first-order
desires
to
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
autonomy to reconciling the two levels to achieve a harmonious whole.
22
Babbitt is correct to say that the categories of Mister's
Both types of theory neglect
ideology provide no direct, authoritative way for
the possibility that an oppressive social context
Celie to assert her moral status, but it is evident
could subvert people's autonomy by imparting detri-
that Celie is able to give her knowledge a proposi-
mental desires, values and goals or warping people's
tional form and to encode her knowledge in intel-
second-order volitions. Such theories make no ade-
ligible speech.
quate provision for `authenticating' the concepts and
Oppression deprives Celie of conventions ± read-
commitments that structure one's interpretations
ily available, generally accepted discursive formulae
and propel one's deliberations and choices. In con-
± through which she can articulate her convictions,
trast, restrictive, value-saturated accounts of auton-
protests and aspirations.
omy, such as Susan Babbitt's and Paul Benson's,
knowledge, oppressed people must resort to circum-
insist on the need to distinguish real from apparent
locution, devise figures of speech and work to re-
desires and authentic values from spurious ones, and
define
they draw these distinctions by placing constraints
understanding, interpersonal relations and moral
on what people can autonomously choose.
reflection. Thus, they must summon extraordinary
the
terms
28
To articulate their self-
that
frame
intrapersonal
According to Susan Babbitt, ideological oppres-
imaginative and linguistic powers if they are to gain a
sion instils preferences and desires that do not ade-
rich understanding of who they are and why their
quately reflect an interest in one's own flourishing
needs and desires deserve respect. Nevertheless, in
and that prevent one from pursuing one's `objective
light of her defiant self-recognition and her poignant
interests' even when one is aware that one has an
self-assertion, it seems doubtful that Celie lacks an
option to pursue them.
23
The problem, claims Bab-
`adequate' sense of self. I see no reason, then, not to
bitt, is the individual's `not possessing a sense of self
trust her to sort out her own values and goals and
that would support a full sense of flourishing' ± that is
conduct her own life. Still, it is undeniable that Celie's social context is
one has been deprived of a precondition for wanting 24
Although the
doing everything possible to stifle her autonomy and
oppressed have non-propositional knowledge ± that
to defeat her. Likewise, women who demand reinfi-
is, knowledge in the form of intuitions, attitudes,
bulation because it is beautiful, because it is a pre-
ways of behaving and so on ± that adumbrates their
condition for womanly virtue, because it is `our way'
objective interests, this knowledge is inexpressible
or because the World Health Organisation is trying
within the existing ideological regime and is not
to force us to stop doing it hardly enjoy cultural
to pursue one's objective interests.
25
Mute and
environments that encourage them to do what they
subjugated, the agency of these individuals can only
think is best for themselves. For this reason, I expect,
be
Paul Benson would argue that attributing autonomy
translatable into autonomous action. salvaged
through
`transformative
experiences'
that, as it were, upgrade their selfhood.
26
to these women betokens a `Pollyanaish' confidence in their agentic capabilities.
I doubt that oppression renders people's non-
According to Benson, `certain forms of socialisa-
propositional knowledge inexpressible. In fact, I
29
think one of Babbitt's examples amply demonstrates
tion are oppressive and clearly lessen autonomy.'
my point. Commenting on Alice Walker's novel
There are two forms that oppressive socialisation
about domestic violence, The Color Purple, Babbitt
takes: (1) coercive socialisation that inflicts penalties
claims that Celie's knowledge that she is a morally
for noncompliance with unjustifiable norms; and (2)
worthy person is non-propositional and inexpressi-
socialisation that instils false beliefs which prevent
ble. I would argue that Celie's knowledge indeed
people from discerning genuine reasons for acting.
stems from non-propositional sources, her feelings,
Autonomous people are `competent criticisers' who
attitudes and perhaps her intuitions. But, as Babbitt
can `detect and appreciate the reasons there are to
reports, when taunted by Mister ± `You nothing at
act in various ways.'
all' ± Celie trenchantly replies, `I'm pore, I'm black, I
systematically obviates and obfuscates victims' rea-
may be ugly and can't cook . . . but I'm here.'
27
31
30
But oppressive socialisation
sons for acting. As Benson puts it, oppressive socia-
213
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
each of these groups who have experienced compar-
lisation limits in `well-organised ways what sorts of 32
More-
ably oppressive socialisation. Undeniably, they have
over, bi-directional integration ± that is, mutual
more to overcome in order to attain autonomy than
adjustment and reconciliation of first-order desires
some other women, for they must mobilise extra-
and second-order volitions about first-order desires ±
ordinary introspective and volitional powers to figure
is no guarantee of autonomy, for oppressive sociali-
out what they really want and to act on their own
sation could implant such deficient values that a
desires. But it is hard to believe that none of them
person could have degraded first-order desires that
chooses autonomously.
reasons to act people are able to recognise.'
would
by second-order
The fact is that we are all immersed in a culture at
Internalised oppressive socialisation, it
a historical moment. How do we know that some of
nonetheless be endorsed
volitions.
33
us have attained adequate selfhood and thus have
seems, can `shanghai' a person's entire life. Presumably, Benson would conclude that, because
the epistemic perspective needed to grasp what full
of their socialisation, the many women who do not
flourishing is like? How do we know that some of us
repudiate female genital cutting have defective rea-
have highly developed, acutely sensitive reason-de-
son-detection faculties ± defective at least in so far as
tection faculties and thus have the epistemic skills
they are oblivious to the `decisive' force of the
needed to determine what cannot be a good reason
reasons against this practice ± and thus that they
to act or what is a dispositive reason to act? It seems
have been deprived of autonomy at least with respect
to me that we would need far more consensus than
34
But I would urge that Benson's grim
we presently have (or are likely to get) about human
assessment of the sinister potency of oppressive
nature and social justice before we could conclude
socialisation exaggerates the impact of socialisation
that women who opt for compliance with female
generally. It just isn't true that oppressive socialisa-
genital cutting norms never do so autonomously. We
tion always decreases autonomy. Some people be-
would have to be persuaded, in other words, that all
come
them
women's interests are such that this decision could
flourish in that role. In cases of firebrand, adven-
not accord with any woman's authentic values and
ture-loving resisters, one suspects they would have
desires under any circumstances. If we are prepared to
had a hard time fitting in and living autonomously if
acknowledge that a woman who has undergone
they had been born into a just society during peace-
oppressive socialisation but who rebels against its
time. Other people carve out lives that enact `in-
dictates may be accessing her authentic values and
appropriate'
the
desires and acting autonomously, it seems to me that
constraints that society imposes. They find pockets
we cannot rule out a priori the possibility that a
of lapsed surveillance or permissiveness within op-
similarly socialised woman who chooses otherwise
pressive regimes and devise ways to express their
may be autonomous, too.
to this choice.
oppositional
values
activists,
in
the
and
some
interstices
of
of
those
In sum, restrictive, value-saturated accounts of
spaces. Still others endorse at least some of the values
autonomy are troubling because they homogenise
upon which oppressive constraints are based and on
authentic selves and autonomous lives. The para-
balance accept the constraints and conform their
doxical effect of ahistorically, acontextually foreor-
lives to them. We find all of these possibilities
daining
represented in connection with female genital cut-
autonomously choose is to deindividualise autonomy.
ting ± women fleeing their homeland and seeking
Yet, latitudinarian, value-neutral accounts of auton-
asylum to avoid having their genitals cut or to
omy are troubling, too. On this view, failures of
protect their daughters from cutting, women orga-
autonomy are failures to obtain and take into ac-
nising locally and nationally to modify or eradicate
count relevant information, or they are failures to
female genital cutting, women concluding that cul-
integrate one's values, desires and the like into a
tural tradition and cohesion or getting married and
coherent outlook and a feasible course of action. The
bearing children are more important than bodily
paradoxical effect of neglecting the possibility that a
integrity. I would venture that there are women in
well integrated, smoothly functioning self could be in
unorthodox
values
and
commitments
in
214
what
individuals
can
and
cannot
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
need of rigorous scrutiny and drastic overhaul is to
and their awareness of their own sexual impairment.
abandon the individual to the influence of a culture's
Likewise, health education can kindle cognitive
prevailing beliefs and practices. Such a view over-
dissonance by highlighting potential conflicts be-
simplifies self-alienation and blunts autonomy's po-
tween women's desire to bear children and their
tential to spur social critique. Neither of these
commitment to female genital cutting, which can
approaches offers a compelling theory of individua-
reduce fertility.
lised autonomous living.
quiry into the symbolic meanings that one's culture
38
Programmes designed to elicit en-
attaches to female genital cutting have proved effective, too.
Autonomy-Augmenting Programmes
39
An international organisation called
Women Living Under Muslim Laws has developed
and Female Genital Cutting
educational
strategies
that
encourage
women
to
Feminist students of female genital cutting have
analyse and reconstruct their own identities within
analysed a number of programmes that have en-
their cultures. Through education, this organisation
hanced women's autonomy in regard to this practice.
seeks to debunk the myth of one universal Muslim
Moreover, they have proposed legal reforms, and
identity and to offer women the opportunity to read
they have documented the effects of social trends
and interpret Islam's sacred texts for themselves.
on female genital cutting. I shall briefly survey this
discovering how differently women live under dif-
literature with the aim of using it as a springboard for
ferent Islamic regimes and how weak the tie between
developing an account of women's autonomy-with-
Islamic scripture and current religious doctrines re-
in-culture.
quiring female genital cutting actually is, many
40
In
My reading of this literature suggests that educa-
women realise that they could modify their beliefs
tion is the least controversial and most effective
regarding female genital cutting without sacrificing
approach to augmenting women's autonomy regard-
their religious beliefs. Intellectual and emotional
ing female genital cutting, but the success of this
space hospitable to envisaging a different conception
approach depends on the nature of the educational
of the ethics and aesthetics of womanhood is thus
programme. Again and again, scholars stress the need
opened.
for grassroots participation in conceiving the aims of
Sometimes women become convinced that they
educational initiatives, in formulating educational
can flourish as women with their genitals intact.
agendas and in devising educational presentations
Kenyan women and their families have created
and materials. Phrases like `education for critical
`circumcision through words' rituals in which cultur-
consciousness' and `emancipatory education' imply
al teachings about womanhood are transmitted and
the need for institutionalising self-determination at
girls' entrance into womanhood is celebrated, but the
the founding and throughout the implementation of
traditional cutting is eliminated.
education programmes.
35
41
Sometimes wo-
This imperative has been
men remain convinced that female genital cutting is
put in practice through dialogic programme planning
necessary, but they alter the practice either by re-
and dialogic `classrooms' and also by adopting cul-
ducing it to a symbolic pricking or by medicalising
turally familiar media for `instruction'.
36
it.
Songs, plays
42
Sometimes they insist on upholding tradition.
and puppet shows followed by exploratory discussion
Hofriyati women whose husbands have returned
sessions often replace lectures and rote learning.
from working in Saudi Arabia convinced that in-
Experience shows that many women are receptive
fibulation is contrary to Islam and that sunna is the
to information about the health risks associated with
religiously sanctioned form of female genital cutting
female genital cutting.
37
have resisted the ensuing pressure to adopt the less
Successful educational pro-
43
grammes often capitalise on women's dissonant ex-
extreme practice.
perience
For
ritual surrounding female genital cutting not only
example, health education can juxtapose women's
confers the status of womanhood on the initiate but
commitment to female genital cutting with their
also creates lifelong social bonds among the girls who
awareness of traumatic outcomes (sometimes deaths)
undergo the ritual together. Thus another important
Á -vis vis-a
female
genital
cutting.
215
In some cultural groups, the
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
task of educational programmes has been to create
point out that these two strategies are not necessarily
substitutes for the `age groups' established by female
compatible with cultural perpetuation, and they do
genital cutting. In central Kenya, the social benefits
not necessarily ensure increased autonomy for wo-
formerly delivered by age groups ± solidarity among
men. Endowing women with the right to penalise
women and consolidation of women's social author-
female genital cutting practitioners pits women from
ity ± are now secured by women's self-help economic
the same cultural group against one another and pre-
organisations.
44
empts the possibility of their working together to
In addition to such culturally attuned, participa-
transform cultural norms and obtain economically
tory education, we also find more coercive legal and
viable employment. Some women may gain auton-
social forces at work. Female genital cutting is pro-
omy. But their gains may be made at the expense of
hibited in a number of countries where the practice
other women's autonomy, and relying on the na-
has been common. However, the history of crim-
tional judiciary to make these gains may short-circuit
inalising female genital cutting and disseminating
cultural processes through which womanhood might
information about women's legal rights does not
be redefined without shattering all continuity with
inspire confidence in this approach. Either these
traditional conceptions of womanhood. While some
measures have had little impact or they have in-
women's autonomy may be enhanced, their auton-
tensified reactionary traditionalism.
45
But legal sanc-
omy may be dissociated from their culture of origin.
tions could take a different form. One scholar, Asma
More obviously, social and economic mobility
Mohammed A'Haleem, proposes that laws be passed
gained through geographic mobility often dissolves
giving adult women the right to sue the practitioners
networks of mutual recognition and shared beliefs
who cut their genitals when they were children.
46
As
and practices that are necessary to sustain cultures.
a precedent for her proposal, she points to the
Migration
passage of parallel laws protecting women from
norms in one's new place of residence and work.
compulsory marriage. Women who were adequately
Assimilation weakens, if it does not sever, one's ties
informed of these laws frequently went to court and
to one's culture of origin. Some women who move to
sued to enforce their rights.
47
often
leads
to
assimilating
prevalent
Perhaps women would
urban areas and marry into families with different
also avail themselves of rights to seek compensation
cultural backgrounds gain greater autonomy by aban-
from female genital cutting practitioners, which
doning their own culture and becoming integrated
would discourage women from entering this trade
into a more congenial cultural milieu. Others suffer a
and encourage practitioners to find other sources of
loss of autonomy. They find their cherished beliefs
income. It seems clear, however, that whereas legal
denigrated or derided; they experience a sense of
measures produce mixed results, urbanisation and
dislocation and disorientation, and they are blocked
industrialisation predictably curtail female genital
from enacting values they consider authentically
cutting. In Nigeria, for example, one report shows
their own.
how the rise of western-style education has led to a
What these observations show, I would urge, is
marked decline in female genital cutting. Busy with
how important it is to bear in mind the difference
book-learning and preoccupied by extracurricular
between eradicating the practice of female genital
activities, girls have no time at puberty for lengthy
cutting and augmenting women's autonomy with
seclusion periods and ceremonies.
48
respect to female genital cutting.
As education,
50
Ceasing to be
employment, and marriage increasingly take place
subject to a cultural imperative mandating female
away from girls' communities of origin, the power of
genital cutting does not in itself constitute increased
cultural tradition wanes and the incidence of female
autonomy. The educational programmes I described
genital cutting plummets.
49
may well try the patience of feminists who are (in my
I do not object to social and economic mobility
opinion, justifiably) appalled at the harm inflicted by
provided that individuals welcome it and benefit
female genital cutting. Yet, these programmes have a
from it, nor do I object to using law to bring about
distinct advantage from the standpoint of autonomy,
ameliorative social change. Still, it is important to
for they are designed to engage women's autonomy
216
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
skills without exposing them to autonomy-disabling
practices. Thus, serviceable cultures nurture those
cultural alienation. In short, these programmes pro-
autonomy skills that people need to get along within
mote autonomy-within-culture.
their existing cultural framework and those that they need to improvise adjustments when circumstances render long-standing cultural beliefs and practices
Autonomy-within-Culture
untenable. However, in so far as cultures perpetuate
Michelle Moody-Adams points out that successful
injustice by selectively suppressing autonomy skills, I
cultures must preserve people's capacities for the ex-
would insist that they are not merely regulating
ercise of judgement and discretion.
51
people's capacity for judgement and discretion, but
`Any culture that
rather that they are impairing it.
worked to impair these capacities', she adds, `would be 52
I agree
It seems to me that cultures do this in two main
that a viable culture cannot turn its adherents into
ways. First, cultures furnish repertories of concepts
indoctrinated automatons who cannot question cul-
and interpretive schemas that focus perception and
tural beliefs and practices and who cannot instigate
shape reflection. Thus, cultures lead people to notice
creating the conditions for its own demise.'
53
cultural change.
some phenomena and overlook others, and they lead
Still, I find Moody-Adams' view of
people to ascribe certain meanings to their experi-
autonomy-within-culture overly sanguine. A thriving culture must evolve, but it must persist
ence and to disregard other possible meanings. Sec-
as well. If cultures are self-perpetuating systems, they
ond, cultures valorise some autonomy skills over
must have in-built mechanisms that shield their
others. Hence they commend child-rearing practices
beliefs and practices from criticism so zealous and
that nurture these skills and establish social struc-
damning that it triggers cultural decline or foments
tures that reward individuals who have them, and
mass defection. The slightest acquaintance with hu-
they let other autonomy skills languish. The fa-
man history confirms that cultures need not depend
voured autonomy skills are skills that enable people
on the justice of their beliefs and practices to secure
to function well in their cultural context, and the
the loyalty of their adherents. Indeed, cultures, in-
repertories of concepts and interpretive schemas
cluding the most unjust ones, may have a willing co-
provide input for these deliberation skills that is
conspirator in human psychology. People commonly
pre-selected and pre-processed in culturally conge-
exhibit a conservative bent ± preferring the known
nial ways. The disfavoured autonomy skills are skills
over the unknown, even preferring the security of
that might lead people to question the adequacy of
having more or less mastered coping with a known
the culturally approved repertory of concepts and
evil over the risk of being thrown off balance by
interpretive schemas and, perhaps, to condemn their
whatever might succeed it. Still, this conservative
cultural heritage.
culturally
For example, middle-class Euro-American culture
abetted. Cultures ward off the perils of internal
prizes means/ends rationality and vigorously culti-
dissension and disruption by circumscribing adher-
vates the skills needed to pick goals with high
ents' exercise of autonomy skills. Adroitly channel-
satisfaction yields and to plot successful goal-directed
ling exercise of these skills where they are needed
campaigns. In this culture, however, valorised auton-
while limiting the scope of their application enables
omy skills are gendered. Although child-rearing
cultures to evolve and endure.
practices and reward structures do not extinguish
disposition
is
to
a
significant
degree
Moody-Adams might reply that what I have de-
means/ends rationality in middle-class Euro-Amer-
scribed is not impairment of capacities for judgement
ican girls, their interpersonal skills are accentuated. I
and discretion. On the contrary, she might say,
confess I do not know which autonomy skills are
cultures guide and modulate the exercise of auton-
valorised in the innumerable cultures that practise
omy skills, and rightly so. To some extent, I would
female genital cutting. But I believe it is possible to
not take exception to this rejoinder. No doubt,
infer which autonomy skills they devalue in women
cultures exist because people cannot lead fulfilling
by examining the education programmes that aug-
lives without stable systems of shared beliefs and
ment women's autonomy.
217
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
Successful educational programmes mobilise wo-
and vividly apprehend the American mother's dis-
men's introspection, empathy and imagination skills.
tress about her daughter's purportedly unnatural
One programme invited women to explore their
condition and her worries about the problems she
feelings about their sexuality ± their sufferings, their
expects her daughter will encounter if her `patholo-
frustrations, and their disappointments, as well as
gical' genitals are left untreated. It is easy, then, to
their pleasures ± and to sift through the possible
understand her decision to authorise surgery. Indeed,
54
In effect, this pro-
many middle-class Euro-Americans might find with-
gramme encourages women to acknowledge the
holding permission to operate incomprehensible or
complexity of their emotional lives and to take their
irresponsible.
meanings of these stirrings.
own subjectivity seriously. Another programme ca-
Sometimes when I start a conversation with a
pitalised on situations in which local girls and wo-
middle-class Euro-American acquaintance by elicit-
men
and invited
ing empathy along the lines I have just sketched and
women to empathise with the suffering of the in-
by eliciting reflection on the reasons for the ease of
fected individuals and the grief of the families of girls
this empathy, it proves possible for my acquaintance
and women who died. Instead of rationalising the
to transfer this understanding to the larger issue of
pain and dismissing the sorrow as passing, women
female genital cutting. Sensitised to the role that
were freed to regard such suffering as significant and
western gender norms are playing in one's empathy
had become
55
infected
or
died
Some programmes invite women to
for the American mother, one now appreciates how
imagine the lives of women whose cultures are
potent culturally specific feminine bodily norms are,
different but whose religion is the same as their
and one can sympathetically reconstruct how a
avoidable.
56
Sharing a religion builds a bridge to empathy
vastly different set of norms could figure in an
with these cultural strangers and provides a link that
African mother's feelings and decision about infibu-
legitimates using empathic understanding of these
lation. Thus empathy with a fellow cultural initiate
other women's lives to reflect critically on one's own
and introspective reflection on how culture facil-
experience and culture.
itates one's empathy for this individual make it
own.
I suspect that these educational programmes owe
possible to empathise with a woman from a different
their success to synergy among introspection, em-
culture and to interpret her subjectivity and choices
pathy and imagination. Empathy with others can
charitably.
embolden one to confront and enrich one's inter-
Narrow categories and prejudicial values often
pretation of one's own experience, and insightful
distort or block introspection and empathy. Yet,
introspection can facilitate empathy with other peo-
opportunities to examine one's subjective experience
ple's experience and equip one to interpret their
with supportive associates, to discover hidden simi-
experience sympathetically and respectfully. As evi-
larities between others' experience and one's own,
dence, let me offer a sequence I have observed.
and to talk about unorthodox ideas in a safe envir-
Most middle-class Euro-Americans initially find it
onment can correct and deepen both self-knowledge
virtually impossible to empathise with an African
and insight into others. Introspection and empathy
mother who consents to and actively participates in
can expand one's repertoire of concepts and inter-
the infibulation of her daughter. Yet these indivi-
pretive schemas beyond the culturally furnished
duals typically find it easy to empathise with an
stock. The educational programmes I have described
American mother who consents to reconstructive
suggest that this struggle for introspective and em-
surgery on a daughter whose genitals are considered
pathic access and for language that adequately ex-
ambiguous. Not only does one assume that surgery in
presses
the US will be performed under sterile conditions
undertaken as an open-ended, collective endea-
and that anaesthesia will be used, but also one is
vour.
oneself imbued with the same image of an appro-
individuals to novel viewpoints that may never have
priately gendered female body that is guiding the
occurred to each of them separately, but also the
American mother's decision. Thus one can readily
sharing of conclusions and the process of reaching
57
218
one's
new-found
knowledge
is
best
Not only does interaction with others expose
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
them infuses these dissident views with an authority
omy that alienation from one's culture and isolation
they might otherwise lack. It seems, in sum, that
from other members of one's cultural group can
women who participate in these educational pro-
inflict. Still, I would be remiss if I did not acknowl-
grammes gain intellectual tools and self-confidence,
edge that Babbitt and Benson bring out important
and that they license themselves to recirculate their
dimensions of women's autonomy with respect to
discoveries and use them to refurbish or jettison
female genital cutting, and these insights into wo-
traditional beliefs and practices. Introspection and
men's autonomy lend support to a skills-based, pro-
empathy thus emancipate their imaginations. Beliefs
cessual account of autonomy.
and practices that once seemed degraded and abhor-
Benson's chief contribution to a theory of wo-
rent can now be pictured as constituting an honour-
men's autonomy over female genital cutting rests on
able and fulfilling way of life.
his observation that oppressive socialisation compartmentalises critical skills and receptivity to rea-
The capacity for imagination is complex, for it
58
recruits subsidiary skills and orchestrates them. In-
sons.
trospection and empathy can spark imagination, as
competence with respect to her education but not
can dialogic and consensus-building skills. More-
with respect to her appearance.
over, imagination depends on the concepts one
seen that cultures place female genital cutting be-
has at one's disposal and the meanings one associates
yond the purview of women's introspection, empathy
with phenomena. Prescriptive norms shape imagina-
and imagination skills, yet they rely on women to
tion. Thus, cultures can limit imagination by furnish-
exercise these very skills in other areas of life such as
ing an impoverished repertoire of concepts and
child-rearing. Although the importance of introspec-
interpretive schemas, by stunting the development
tion, empathy and imagination for gaining autonomy
of skills that contribute to imagination, or by deva-
over female genital cutting suggests that it would be a
luing imagination itself. My hypothesis, then, is that
mistake to confine autonomy skills to critical reason-
cultures that mandate female genital cutting either
ing and the need for cultures to deflect exercise of
altogether devalue imagination in women or else
autonomy skills away from culturally destructive uses
value imagination in women only when it is serving
suggests that it would also be a mistake to suppose
specific approved purposes. In the latter case, cul-
that only oppressive enculturation compartmenta-
tures may foster the subsidiary skills that imagination
lises autonomy skills, it is true that cultures' self-
enlists only in so far as these skills promote the
protective
condoned forms of imaginative activity.
and that these devices can have deleterious effects
His example is a woman who exercises critical
devices
include
59
Similarly, we have
compartmentalisation
A culture's ultimate defensive weapon is to make
on autonomy. Indeed, it seems to me that the success
alternative ways of life unimaginable or imaginable
of the educational programmes I discussed is due in
only as bizarre or loathsome specimens. There is no
part to their effectiveness in decompartmentalising
more effective way to galvanise cultural allegiance
and redirecting autonomy skills that women already
than to suppress people's ability to imagine a pro-
have.
foundly different life as a life they might gladly lead.
Babbitt claims that altered settings can prompt
There is no better evidence, I would add, that
transformative experiences that enhance autonomy,
cultures typically perpetuate themselves by impairing
and this view is borne out to some extent by the line
empathy with cultural outsiders and thwarting ima-
of thought I have presented. I would take issue with
gination of cultural alternatives than the fact that
her, though, when she allows that foisting a new set
ethnocentricity and xenophobia are as rampant and
of opportunities on people is an ethical and effica-
virulent as they are.
cious way to increase their autonomy.
60
That legal
Whereas I am convinced that Moody-Adams
reforms and social or economic upheaval produce
overestimates the autonomy proficiency that viable
mixed results for women's autonomy over female
cultures must secure, I am convinced that the two
genital cutting raises doubts about the defensibility
restrictive, value-saturated theories of autonomy I
of manipulating the context of women's choices.
discussed earlier underestimate the damage to auton-
Since
219
autonomy-augmenting
educational
pro-
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
grammes are typically developed by cultural initiates
their values and commitments before they partici-
who rely on traditional modes of expression and
pate in such programmes. Understanding autonomy
appeal to traditional values, it is reasonable to sur-
as I have proposed, then, makes sense of the claim
mise that autonomy is best extended by avoiding
that women
cultural alienation and by building on women's
cutting are not without autonomy. But this under-
61
who
are
subject to
female
genital
Still, I agree with Babbitt
standing of autonomy entails neither endorsement
that women's participation in these educational
of female genital cutting nor resignation to its
programmes can be transformative, for breaking
persistence. Since cultures that practise female gen-
through the barriers erected by a culturally trans-
ital cutting may have selectively nurtured and stifled
mitted cognitive system can radically reconfigure
women's autonomy skills, and since these cultures
perception and open previously unthinkable vistas
may shield the issue of female genital cutting from
of reflection and choice.
exercise of autonomy skills, developing and coordi-
existing autonomy skills.
nating women's autonomy skills and extending the
Successful educational programmes embody four
range
assumptions about autonomy:
of
application
of
these
skills
are
key
to
augmenting their autonomy. Individuals may identify
1. Autonomy is best understood as socially situ-
points
of
self-estrangement
±
doubts
about
ated ± that is, as autonomy-within-culture.
values or tensions between private feelings and
2. Autonomy couples self-discovery and avowal
conduct ± and decide to revise their convictions and openly oppose tradition. They may find them-
with choice and self-redefinition.
selves unconflicted about their cultural heritage and
3. Gaining autonomy consists of exercising a
renew their traditionalist convictions from a broader
complex set of skills. 4. One's authentic values and real desires are
perspective. Or they may pursue some nuanced,
those that emerge as one exercises autonomy
intermediate path, embarking upon a process of
skills.
renegotiating
and
revitalising
cultural
traditions.
Although no uniform outcome is guaranteed, the From their inception, autonomy-augmenting pro-
trend when the scope of women's autonomy is
grammes regard women in cultures that practise
expanded has been towards erosion of the practice
female genital cutting as self-determining indivi-
of female genital cutting. This skills-based, proces-
duals. Since it is obvious that these women have
sual view of autonomy insists on respecting people
some degree of proficiency with respect to auton-
as self-determining agents and refuses to prejudge
omy
empathy,
what values and practices autonomous people can
before these programmes ever become available, it
endorse. Nevertheless, this view does not collapse
is clear that they have some understanding of what
into indifference to values or cynicism about social
matters to them and how best to proceed in light of
reform.
skills,
such
as
introspection
and
62
Notes
1. Toubia (1995), p. 21; Obiora (1997), p. 298.
nises are considered too small or who lack testicles. It is
2. Gifford (1994), pp. 334, 361; James (1998), p. 1037.
worth noting, though, that gender symmetry is not
3. Ogbu (1997), p. 414.
necessarily the rule. Just as some cultures practise female
4. Obiora (1997), p. 298; Kouba and Muasher (1985), p.
genital cutting but not male genital cutting, others cut boys' genitals to bring about a masculine identity (some-
104; Ogbu (1997), p. 414.
times the cutting is as radical as infibulation) but do not
5. Diamond and Kipnis (1998); Fausto-Sterling (2000),
cut girls' genitals; see James (1998), pp. 1041±3.
chapters 3 and 4.
8. Kouba and Muasher (1985), p. 103; Obiora (1997), p.
6. For documentation and critique of these attitudes, see
297.
Diamond and Kipnis (1998).
9. Obiora (1997), p. 296.
7. In the US today, we find gender parity where ambiguous
10. Ogbu (1997), p. 415; Kouba and Muasher (1985), p.
genitalia are concerned. Cosmetic surgery is also routi-
103.
nely performed on genetically male infants whose pe-
220
FEMINISM AND WOMEN'S AUTONOMY
11. Boddy (1989), pp. 57, 60.
custom' and as keeping girls' sexuality under control
12. Sussman (1998), p. 21.
until marriage, but they also asserted that it was `bad'
13. Boddy (1989), p. 52.
because it was illegal and unchristian (Walley, 1997,
14. Kouba and Muasher (1985), p. 104.
p. 411). One student who had `enthusiastically in-
15. Obiora (1997), p. 297; Ogbu (1997), p. 415; James
vited' Walley to her sister's genital cutting nevertheless declared that it was another way of `destroying'
(1998), pp. 1041±3.
women's bodies (ibid.). As Walley observes, the stu-
16. Toubia (1995), p. 37. 17. Obiora
(1997),
pp.
288±9;
Kouba
and
dents' arguments in favour of female genital cutting
Muasher
parrot local authorities' pronouncements on cultural
(1985), p. 96.
propriety, while their critiques parrot doctrines taught
18. Walley (1997), pp. 408, 420; Narayan (1997), pp. 14±
in the official Social Education curriculum (ibid.). I
17.
suspect that they saw the writing assignment as an
19. Meyers (1993), pp. 16±19; Moody-Adams (1994), pp.
academic exercise which called upon them to recite
305±7. 20. An interesting complication concerns the potential
what they had learned, rather than as an opportunity
for dramatic development of the individual's erotic
to reflect and reveal what they personally thought. If
responsiveness over the course of time. In this con-
such exercises contribute to their autonomy, it is only
nection, it is worth noting that throughout our lives
in virtue of maintaining their consciousness of dis-
we are obliged to make choices that, for better or
parate views of female genital cutting. Perhaps they
worse, cut off other possibilities. Alas, we cannot
appropriate and individualise some of the ideas they
always foresee what options we are eliminating, nor
have been exposed to in their private conversations
can we always appreciate just how desirable foresee-
and kvetching sessions.
able, forgone options really are. Rational choice the-
37. Obiora (1997), p. 361.
ory's requirement that choosers have full knowledge of
38. Ibid., p. 362.
the consequences of their choices is an ideal that
39. Ibid., p. 361.
usually cannot be approximated very well. Thus, a
40. Shaheed (1994), pp. 1009, 1011; Shaheed (1995), pp. 80, 86.
realistic theory of autonomy must work within the
41. James (1998), p. 1046. This cultural change highlights
limits of human prescience.
the importance of bringing men into the educational
21. For development of this critique, see Babbit (1993)
and cultural reconstruction processes. When and how
and Meyers (1989), pp. 77±8.
women choose to do this varies greatly from cultural
22. For critique, see Meyers (1989), pp. 33±41 and (2000),
group to cultural group.
pp. 169±72; Benson (1991), pp. 391±4.
42. Obiora (1997), pp. 368, 371±3; Gunning (1997), pp.
23. Babbit (1993), pp. 246±7.
455±6.
24. Ibid., p. 248. 25. Ibid., pp. 252±4.
43. Boddy (1989), pp. 52, 319.
26. Ibid., pp. 252±3.
44. Robertson (1996), pp. 616, 631.
27. Ibid., p. 253; emphasis added.
45. Obiora (1997), p. 357; Kouba and Muasher (1985), pp. 104±5.
28. Walker (1998), pp. 125±8. 29. Benson (1991), p. 385.
46. A'Haleem (1992), p. 155.
30. Ibid., pp. 388±9.
47. Ibid.
31. Ibid., pp. 396±7.
48. Ogbu (1997), p. 420.
32. Ibid., p. 396.
49. Ibid., pp. 420±1.
33. Ibid., p. 395.
50. It might be argued that eradicating female genital
34. I want to acknowledge that Benson realises that
cutting is objectively in the best interests of the
oppressive socialisation does not necessarily rule out
cultural groups that practise it, for repudiating the
autonomy in all aspects of the victim's life. He dis-
practice would decrease disease and increase fertility.
cusses the possibility that a person's critical compe-
Although this may be so, I believe that social change
tence can be compartmentalised ± that is, one can
that is disconnected from individual autonomy is, as
exercise critical capabilities in one arena but be unable
often as not, counterproductive. It often proves cul-
to exercise these capabilities in another; ibid., p. 397.
turally destructive, for it alienates members of the
35. Kouba and Muasher (1985), p. 108; Obiora (1997), p.
group. But when it is culturally advantageous, it often sacrifices some members of the group and their inter-
361; Mugo (1997), p. 467. educational
ests to the interests of the larger social collectivity.
methods do not seem particularly fruitful. In her role
Individual autonomy may not always be the most
as English teacher, for example, Kathleen Walley gave
efficient way to promote cultural interests, but I am
her pupils the option of writing an essay about female
convinced that it is the most humane way to advance
genital cutting. Many students defended it as `our
this goal.
36. Mugo
(1997),
p.
467.
Conventional
221
DIANA TIETJENS MEYERS
3; `Outliving Oneself: Trauma, Memory and Personal
51. Moody-Adams (1994), p. 307.
Identity', in Meyers (ed.) (1997).
52. Ibid. 53. See Meyers (1993), p. 17.
58. Benson (1991), p. 397.
54. For discussion of the need to pay attention to sub-
59. Ibid.
jectivity, see Gifford (1994), p. 338, and Meyers
60. Babbit (1993), p. 256±7.
(1989), pp. 79±89. For related discussion of `outlaw'
61. More generally, I would urge that transformative experiences that do not engage autonomy skills are
emotions, see Jaggar (1997). 55. For related discussion of empowerment, see Okin
extremely hazardous. Cults specialise in transformative
(1998), p. 47; for related discussion of empathy, see
experiences, and some people who undergo transfor-
S. Bartky, `Sympathy and Solidarity: On a Tightrope
mative experiences get converted into neo-Nazis in-
with Scheler', in Meyers (ed.) (1997) and Meyers
stead of feminists. Although there is no way to
(1994). In an intriguing aside, Walley wonders whether
immunise people against such ill-fated transforma-
incidents in which girls reveal `cowardice' ± in one
tions, autonomy skills are the best protection there is.
cultural parlance, they `cry the knife' ± could be enlisted
62. I would like to thank Ken Kipnis for a pre-publication
to reconstruct values (Walley, 1997, pp. 418±19).
copy of the Diamond and Kipnis paper I have cited
Might this ostensible cowardice be reinterpreted as
and for his helpful comments on an earlier draft of this
resistance?
chapter. I am also grateful to Berel Lang and Sara Ruddick for their suggestions.
56. Shaheed (1994), pp. 1009±10. 57. For relevant discussion, see Scheman (1993), chapter
222
Part Seven LIBERALISM BEYOND THE NATION-STATE
This page intentionally left blank
17
CIVIL ASSOCIATION: THE EUROPEAN UNION AS A SUPRANATIONAL LIBERAL LEGAL ORDER Robert Bideleux
It is widely recognised that the integration theories
democracy was preceded and made possible by sev-
which have hitherto dominated studies of the Eur-
eral decades of limited government, liberal consti-
opean Union have failed to shed much light on the
tutionalism, the rule of law, and the separation of
nature of the nascent supranational polity, as distinct
public and private as well as political and economic
from the processes that brought it about. Such
spheres. The liberal institutions, procedures, prac-
theorising has latterly been going round in circles
tices and patterns of conduct which paved the way
and repeating itself, without getting us much closer
for liberal democracy have subsequently helped to
to a satisfactory conceptualisation of the order that is
safeguard most western democracies against the perils
emerging in Europe. In order to gain a surer under-
of
standing of the new political order, it is necessary to
point is that liberty is safeguarded not so much by
draw upon and creatively adapt elements of main-
democracy as such as by liberalism, limited govern-
stream political theory. This chapter attempts to
ment and the rule of law, which long antedated and
develop a different way of discussing and thinking
did not depend upon the existence of democracy. It
about the emerging European order, using a language
might be objected that, when democrats and theor-
which owes rather more to the writings of two
ists of democracy and democratisation talk about
eminent liberal thinkers, Friedrich Hayek and Mi-
`democracy', they are merely using that word as a
chael Oakeshott, than to integration theory.
1
unconstrained
majoritarianism.
The
essential
They
form of shorthand and take it for granted that
would perhaps have been surprised, but I hope not
democracy must be buttressed by liberalism, limited
too displeased, at the ways in which their ideas and
government and the rule of law, without which a
concepts have been deployed.
system based upon freely contested multi-party elections and a broad suffrage is unlikely to function well or survive for long. However, this shorthand is
Democracy and the Liberal Legal Order
misleading, in that it appears to suggest that the
It has always been imprudent to treat the `liberal' and
crucial safeguards of liberty are the specifically de-
the `democratic' components of liberal democracy as
mocratic components ± procedural democracy (pri-
if they were two halves of the same walnut. In most
marily the holding of regular elections), the political
western states, as is well known, the advent of liberal
mobilisation of the demos and some form of repre-
225
ROBERT BIDELEUX
sentative and/or participatory government ± rather
The European Union as a Liberal
than the liberal elements. In fact, inasmuch as
Rather Than a Democratic Project
democracy has an in-built tendency towards unlimited government, because majorities (however tem-
The European Union, crucially, is a liberal project
porary) generally hope and expect to get their own
rather than a democratic one. It rests upon a
way and often resent any obstruction of their will by
supranational system of rules, regulations and laws
law courts, second chambers, heads of state and other
engendered by judicial and quasi-judicial processes
checks and balances, democracy as such not infre-
as well as by highly consensual negotiation-cum-
quently poses major threats to the liberties which are
horse-trading between liberal democratic states.
in practice upheld by liberalism, limited government
Liberalism, rather than democratic theory, is the
2
and the rule of law. `Liberalism' here refers not only
key to understanding what the European Union is
to the classic liberal political and economic doc-
and how it works. Admittedly, European federalists
trines, but also to the belief that societies ± in the
in the mould of Altiero Spinelli and Mario Alber-
broad sense ± should primarily be based upon and
tini wanted European unification to assume the form
held together by impersonal law, interests, calcula-
of a supranational European democracy structured
tion and contractual relations of a Lockean kind,
as a federal European state,
rather than by `primordial' ties of religion, race,
always been rejected by both public opinion and the
ethnicity and kinship. It will be contended that
powers that be. The constitutive treaties of the
religious and ethnic collectivism are fundamentally
European Communities and the European Union
at odds with the cosmopolitan, supranational liberal
have been ratified by the parliaments (and in some
legal order which is being constructed by the Eur-
cases the electorates) of each of the member states,
opean Union.
while successive treaties have acquired the status of
3
but such a path has
These distinctions are of crucial importance. They
a constitution or fundamental legal charter. Never-
enable us to see more clearly that the political
theless, the Union does not rest upon direct demo-
performance and EU membership prospects of states
cratic legitimation at a supranational all-Union
such as Serbia, Croatia, Albania, Romania and
level. The Union has a telos, but there is no nascent
Bulgaria are being impaired not so much by a lack
European demos standing above the separate demoi
of democracy (they actually have executives and
of the constituent member states, nor is there a
legislatures which have been more or less freely
transnational EU `public opinion'. There is very
and fairly elected by universal suffrage in multi-party
little articulation and aggregation of interests at a
contests) as by insufficient respect for minorities and
supranational level ± only business interests are well
for the rule of law, by inadequate constraints on the
organised in this respect.
exercise of power by the state and its officers, and by
ion-wide' political parties fighting EU elections on
the weakness or shallow roots of liberal doctrine and
transnational `European' platforms and issues. Elec-
sentiment. Conversely, what has placed countries
tions to the European Parliament are characterised
such as Hungary, the Czech Republic and Poland at
by low and steadily declining turnouts and minimal
the front of the queue for membership of the EU is
public
not a greater commitment to democracy as such, but
from `national' programmes, policies, personalities
rather their stronger commitment to the rule of law,
and issues. Moreover, the Union's institutional
their greater respect for the liberties of individuals,
design
engagement
4
with
There are no truly `Un-
`European'
as
distinct
their stronger constraints on the power of the state, and their fuller understanding of the requirements of
does not conform to the traditional separation of
liberal governance. These same qualities also explain
powers between legislative, executive and judicial
the greater success of their transitions to market
branches of government. Rather, decisions evolve
economies.
from intense bargaining within and across the policy-making institutions . . . The Union is not a traditional hierarchy with a clearly defined
226
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
centre of political authority . . . As a result,
not they are democracies.' Thus it is not whether a
Europe's citizens have difficulty in identifying
polity `is a liberal democracy that most fundamen-
`who governs' in the Union and cannot . . .
tally determines its legitimacy; it is how well it
5
dismiss them at elections.
secures its citizens against the worst evils.' Post
facto
7
popular approval of what has been
Increased `openness' and `transparency' may be de-
achieved has been a bonus rather than a precondi-
sirable in their own rights but they do not of
tion for the success and the legitimacy of an elite-
themselves reduce the so-called `democratic deficit'
driven integration project which has contributed so
of the European Union. They skirt round rather than
strongly to the peace and prosperity of Western
tackle the problem head on.
6
Europe since the 1950s. The latter stands in marked
As a polity, the European Union and its policy-
contrast to the devastating and debilitating conflicts
making processes have been based upon mutual
which resulted at least in part from the democratic
accommodation of elites, rather than on specifically
mobilisation of ideological mass movements during
democratic procedures. It has been constructed, not
the first half of the twentieth century. West Eur-
by democratic mobilisation of peoples in support of
opean elites have in effect succeeded in putting the
`ever closer union' and the `idea of Europe', but
destructive genies of mass politics back into their
rather by consensual negotiation and horse-trading
bottles, thereby making Western Europe a much
between European governments and officials. There
freer, safer and more prosperous place than it had
have been no great waves of popular support for a
been earlier in the twentieth century, and than
united Europe ± certainly none that are even remo-
south-eastern Europe and the former Soviet Repub-
tely comparable to the periodic populist backlashes
lics still were at the end of it.
against the idea. From the outset, the construction of
The frameworks of EU law and regulation which
the European Communities and the EU has been the
increasingly govern the Single Market, environmen-
work of cosmopolitan elites pursuing their own elite
tal policies, health and safety provisions, the terms
agendas, rather than a response to popular demands
and conditions of employment, monetary policy,
for European integration. However, this elitism has
industrial policies, regional policies and agricultural
been not a weakness, as many critics complain, but
policies have transformed the EU into a multi-tiered
one of the Union's strengths. If it had been necessary
`regulatory federation' which increasingly defines
to wait for its peoples to voice demands for `ever
and upholds the rights and obligations of its citizens.
closer union', Western European integration would
The state-like institutional skeleton of the EU has
not have advanced nearly so far as it has done in so
fostered growing expectations that it should behave
short a time. The crucial point is that European
and grow `like a state'. Relative to other multi-tiered
states would have had to devise ways and means of
federal systems of governance, however, `the Eur-
coexisting more peacefully and harmoniously, no
opean framework has strikingly modest resources of
matter what the subjective preferences, prejudices,
its own. Consequently, there are major constraints
bugbears or grievances of their citizens, in order to
upon the nature of the activity that can be pursued.'
avert any potential return to the destructive inter-
In particular, there is very limited scope for redis-
and intra-state conflicts and beggar-my-neighbour
tributive measures, which in turn virtually imposes
protectionism
the emphasis on regulatory governance.
of
Europe's
`Second
Thirty
Years
9
8
The EU is
War' (1914±45). These matters were too important
emerging as a legal federation, as an economic
to be submitted to the vagaries of public opinion. In
federation, and as a regulatory federation, but it lacks
any case, as argued by John Gray, the current shrill
either the design or the wherewithal to discharge the
and single-minded insistence on democratic legiti-
classic Hobbesian and Weberian functions of a state
macy is somewhat over the top. In practice, forms of
± especially the monopoly of organised violence ±
governance `are legitimate in so far as they meet the
and it can and should be prevented from acquiring
needs of their citizens. Those that fail in this will be
them.
judged by their citizens to be illegitimate whether or
Within the European Union, political and civil
227
ROBERT BIDELEUX
rights and liberties are being ever more deeply em-
and Pacific countries, the Europe Agreements with
bedded in a strong supranational legal and constitu-
former Communist states, the Euro-Med Partnership,
tional framework, albeit one which in the last resort
international cooperation on environmental regula-
can only be upheld by national law courts and national
tion and the inchoate Common Foreign and Secur-
police forces ± as the EU has no national-level courts
ity
or police of its own. This supranational legal order
mechanisms and procedures through which the ex-
helps to safeguard rights and liberties against poten-
ternal economic and (increasingly) non-economic
tial violation by various powerful actors, including
relations of EU member states can be continuously
the governments of member states which still control
and intensively coordinated. Indeed, on most mat-
national armed forces, police forces, law-courts, na-
ters pertaining to external economic relations (espe-
tionwide bureaucracies and other legitimate instru-
cially foreign access to the Single Market), the EU
ments of enforcement and surveillance at that level.
Commission is empowered to act and to negotiate
Contrary to the fears and alarmism of the Euro-
agreements on behalf of the member states. More-
phobes, the EU does not itself control or possess
over, as Michael Smith has emphasised, `the see-
any such forces with which it could conceivably
mingly ``domestic'' concerns of market regulation,
coerce those citizens, enterprises and member states
standards setting and competition policy' have in-
who occasionally violate its rules and laws, although
creasingly become `the stuff of international poli-
it has generated ever-growing political and economic
tics'.
incentives for compliance as well as penalties for
regulatory matters in international relations and in
non-compliance.
The
only
conceivable
Policy:
11
all
have
involved
the
creation
of
The mounting importance of economic and
direct
regional security, together with the launching of the
threats to liberty within the European Union come
Single Market programme, has steadily increased the
from states, large companies, organised crime, terror-
number and importance of the areas within which
ists and private security forces rather than from the
EU institutions have supranational competence to
European Union as such. The European nation-state
act on behalf of the member states. Even before the
has lost some functions while gaining others `in what
end of the Cold War, the security of the EU and its
had previously been more private and local spheres',
member states was becoming less and less concerned
but overall `the bars of the cage have not changed
with traditional questions of war and peace and
very much. Citizens still need to deploy most of their
military capabilities, and increasingly to do with
vigilance at the national level.'
10
economic security, market access, fishing rights, en-
So long as the
British and the Scandinavians continue to hold out
vironmental
against the aspirations of some member states to
rights, immigration issues, drug trafficking and inter-
regulation,
human
rights,
minority
create a strong supranational European army or a
national crime. As argued by Michael Mann, during
supranational European police force with a strong
the 1990s Western Europe gained `the geopolitical
capacity for electronic surveillance of (and data
security it has always wanted, as well as client states
banks on) EU citizens, the possibility of the EU
and even supplicant states between itself and any
becoming an Orwellian `big brother' superstate will
threat coming out of the East.' So long as such
remain nothing more than a figment of the `black
conditions continued to pertain (and here both
propaganda' put about by prominent British `Euro-
Mann and the EU were in danger of complacency),
phobes' such as Margaret Thatcher, Norman La-
the EU would have `little need for efficient geopo-
mont, William Hague and John Redwood.
litical decision-making'. The EU represents a `Lock-
Even the external relations of the European Un-
eian heartland' of civil association and contractual
ion have become increasingly enmeshed in a supra-
relations, although not far beyond its southern and
national framework of rules and regulation. The
eastern borders (for example, in the Maghreb, Egypt,
Common Commercial Policy, the Common Exter-
Bosnia,
nal Tariff, the Common Agricultural Policy, the
comes into more `Hobbesian' terrain.
Common
Fisheries
Agreements
with
Policy,
the
successive
and
south-eastern
Turkey)
one
12
 Lome
The mere existence of the EU has helped to
Caribbean
transform the very nature of European external
successive
African,
Kosovo
228
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
relations. Much of what used to be regarded as foreign
transnational capitalism and information/communi-
policy or international relations (especially the often
cations technologies can in many ways help to
bellicose relations between European states in the
promote the geographical diffusion of the rule of
past) has been `domesticated' and `civilianised' ±
law, liberal values and liberal democratic forms of
becoming part of the civil order and internal relations
governance. But it should be pointed out that they
of the EU, dealt with by institutions and mechanisms
also give rise to market forces and concentrations of
formerly associated with `domestic' matters. The EU
power which are increasingly beyond the control of
comprises a complex mesh of institutions, rules and
the individual states or groups of states which remain
laws which structure both the internal and external
the principal sites of democratic accountability. This
dealings of the EU as a whole and its individual
growing democratic deficit afflicts states which are
member states, as a result of which there is `a
not members of the EU every bit as much as (and
constant rule-governed process of negotiation be-
often more than) those within it, and therefore should
tween actors which produces policy positions and
not be simplistically or demagogically `blamed' upon
13
The scathing pub-
the EU. Indeed, during the 1990s the economies of
licity given to the Union's inability to project im-
many non-EU states were even more severely buf-
perialistic military might in the manner of the
feted than those of EU states by global market forces
United States has diverted public attention from
over which their political and monetary authorities
the large areas of consensus and joint activity in
have little control. Public allegiance to the European
the Union's external relations, and from the fact that
nation-state persists, but this is increasingly out of
the EU as a vast and economically powerful `civil
kilter with the actual locus of economic and military
association' exerts enormous influence and `magnetic
power and decision-making, which has to a large
pull' on the states and peoples lying to the south and
extent shifted to higher levels (not just to the EU,
east of its current borders.
but to NATO, the WTO, the IMF, other interna-
international policy outcomes.'
tional agencies and giant transnational corporations).
From `Democratic Deficits'
Moreover,
inasmuch
as
the
`national'
governments of the member states of the EU con-
to `Cosmopolitan Democracy'?
trolled 52 per cent of GDP (on average) in 1993,
Many critics of the European Union regard the fact
whereas the institutions of the EU controlled a mere
that it is a supranational liberal legal order, rather
1.3 per cent of their combined GDP, `democratic
than a form of democracy, as a woeful deficiency. Yet
deficits' actually pose much more of a problem at the
in reality that is its greatest virtue. Critics decry the
national than at the EU level.
EU's so-called `democratic deficit', as if either its
Even though there has been a lot of influential
present constitution or even the very existence of the
wishful thinking about supranational forms of `cos-
European Union were the intrinsic source of the said
mopolitan democracy', much of it by eminent poli-
deficit. In fact, it is the development of mighty global
tical
market forces and global information and commu-
demonstrated any way in which it might be possible
nications networks, rather than the increasingly
to establish direct democratic accountability and
federal character of the European Union, that pose
control over governance at the supranational level.
the greatest threats to `sovereignty' and democratic
An important body of supranational `cosmopolitan
control and accountability. This is so, not only at the
law' has already emerged (most notably in the form
national level, but also indirectly at the EU level.
of European Union law), but `cosmopolitan democ-
Globalisation and the diminishing capacity of either
racy' remains a mirage. It is likely that any thorough-
national or EU parliamentary and executive institu-
going
tions effectively to control and hold to account the
decisions, policies and regulations directly to detailed
forces of global capitalism and global information
scrutiny and control by `sovereign' national parlia-
and communications networks have created demo-
ments would induce political paralysis or deadlock,
cratic deficits at all levels. This is not to deny that
while attempts to subordinate them to `sovereign'
229
theorists,
attempt
14
to
no
one
subordinate
has
all
convincingly
supranational
ROBERT BIDELEUX
supranational elected bodies could lead to excessive
that increasingly govern their lives. The citizens of
centralisation of power and to a real possibility of the
small and medium-sized states in other parts of the
Orwellian `superstate' so feared and berated by Brit-
world have no such means at their disposal.
15
Thus:
ish `Europhobes'. Although the overriding aim of European federalists in the tradition of Altiero Spi-
except for the European Union, the prospects for
nelli and Mario Albertini was to transcend the perils
even
and defects of the European states system, the crea-
transnational political associations are poor. Even
tion of a European superstate would merely repro-
if
duce many of those self-same defects (and others
strengthened, for a long time to come decisions
moderately
transnational
`democratic' political
governments
systems
are
of
greatly
besides) on an even larger scale than before. That
are likely to be made by the delegates appointed
would be to jump out of the frying-pan into the fire.
by national governments. Thus the link between
In a European `superstate', whether unitary or fed-
the delegates and the citizens will remain weak;
eral, the police forces, the bureaucracies and the
and the democratic process will be even more
military forces holding sway over Europe would be
attenuated.
even larger and even harder to subordinate at all times to democratic control and accountability than
Dahl suggests that disgusted democrats should seek
are their present-day `national' counterparts. Thus,
solace in enhanced participation and deliberation in
although the European Union and its member states
the national and subnational democratic processes
do indeed suffer from democratic deficit, these would
and institutions which could indeed exercise `what-
not be significantly reduced either by creating a
ever democratic control may be possible over the
European `superstate' or by reasserting full national
authority delegated to transnational decision makers'
sovereignty and autonomy ± even if either of these
and thus help to sustain a `healthy democratic
options were to be politically feasible.
political life within the large sphere of relative
The European Union as presently constituted, far
autonomy that democratic countries will still pos-
from being the intrinsic source of Western Europe's
sess', including increased local control over such
democratic deficit, is the most promising means of
matters as education, town and city planning, public
limiting and mitigating the potential negative conse-
amenities, and social and health services.
quences of the democratic deficits caused by the
loaf is better than none. It is mainly at these lower
expansion of transnational capitalism, communica-
levels that more `radical' conceptions of democratic
tions networks, bureaucratic `big government' and
participation and control, including `electronic de-
transnational military bureaucracies beyond demo-
mocracy' or `cyberdemocracy', are most relevant and
cratic control. As the doyen of American democratic
realisable.
theorists has emphasised:
opment of electronic democracy offers a means of
17
16
Half a
It is sometimes claimed that the devel-
overcoming the EU's so-called democratic deficit by The boundaries of a country, even one as large as
creating a `wired-up Europe' (or, through the next
the United States, have become much smaller
generation of information technology, a `wireless
than the boundaries of the decisions that signifi-
Europe'), by connecting the European Union's citi-
cantly affect the fundamental interests of its
zens directly to the EU institutions and one another,
citizens . . . Thus the citizens of a country cannot
by-passing national governments. However, it is
employ their national government, and much less
more likely that the new technologies will merely
their local governments, to exercise direct control
reinforce elite dominance and magnify the inequal-
over external actors whose decisions bear criti-
ities of power and influence even further, because it
cally upon their lives.
is Europe's elites that have the greatest resources for doing this and that are most adept and assiduous at
The European Union, in Robert Dahl's view, affords
deploying them to their own advantage.
its citizens some mechanisms of indirect political and legal monitoring, regulation and control over the forces
230
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
described as `the most crucial problem of political
The EU Legal Order
organisation, namely how to limit the ``popular will''
and Limited Government
without placing another ``will'' above it'.
21
The
The French legal scholar L. Cohen-Tanugi has
exigencies of accommodating the ever-increasing
argued that two conceptions of democracy currently
political, economic and cultural diversity of the
coexist in Western Europe: the Jacobin tradition of
membership of a steadily expanding EU further
`elective democracy founded solely on universal
ensure that it will have to remain a polity based
suffrage', and that of the constitutional state
on limited government, consensual negotiation and the rule of law ± indeed, unless it is held together by
founded on higher principles of law, equity and
an iron frame of law, it could burst apart at the seams.
procedure . . . Like other organisations of a fed-
Of course, even this might not be enough. Never-
eral type, the Community is building itself by
theless, the national and/or religious ties on which
law . . . European integration has promoted the
nation-states (whether liberal democratic or other-
`return of law' and the promotion of a democratic
wise) have hitherto implicitly relied to foster the
ideal which does not draw its legitimacy solely
active commitment and loyalty of citizens to their
from the law of the majority, but also from
polities are being steadily loosened and eroded by
fundamental principles ± those of the European
globalisation, regional integration, multiculturalism,
Convention of Human Rights, for example ± and
acceptance of difference and the growing fragmenta-
from a system of judicial recourse largely open to
tion of political and cultural identities.
citizens against national states.
18
Squeezed
between a globalised economy and
aggressively
In the words of J. Temple-Lang, each member of the EU
introverted
cultures,
the
political
space is fragmenting and democracy is being now has two constitutions: its national constitu-
debased ± reduced, at best, to a relatively open
tion and the Community constitution, which it
political marketplace, which no one troubles to
shares with other member states. Member states'
defend because it is not the object of any intel-
legislative, executive and judicial powers under
lectual or affective investment . . . The danger
their national constitutions can be exercised only
here is that [multi]culturalism, in the name of
within the framework and limits imposed by
respect for differences, will encourage the forma-
Community law.
19
tion of localised power that will impose an antidemocratic
authority
within
particular
communities. Should that happen, political so-
Ian Loveland, another legal scholar, contends that
ciety will become no more than a marketplace EC Treaties stand in marked contrast to our own
where communities locked into an obsession with
domestic law-making process. They are not the
their identities and internal homogeneity enter
product of majoritarian or even super-majoritar-
into loosely regulated transactions.
22
ian law-making. Their every provision has been arrived
negotiatory
So far, however, global capitalism and regional in-
process . . . The prospect of EC law being nar-
at
through
a
consensual
tegration have seemed incapable of fostering feelings
rowly majoritarian, and hence oppressive or irra-
of belonging and allegiance to replace those which
tional, has been reduced almost to vanishing
they are helping to dilute and disempower at the
point. In that sense, it is a `higher' form of law
level of the nation-state. In such circumstances,
than can be produced by any of the EC's member
political order can only be maintained within the
states within their own legal systems.
20
broader framework of a large and consensual polity whose laws are impartial in the specific sense of being
The European Union thus represents an original
incapable of being merely the expression of the
and constructive solution to what Friedrich Hayek
interests and/or wishes of a dominant majority group
231
ROBERT BIDELEUX
and whose function is not to promote agreement on
extension of uniform rules, regulations and laws
substantive goals and projects but rather to allow a
which all the participants can live with and the
great diversity of persons and states the maximum
placing of the EU's policies, functions and activities
scope for defining and pursuing their diverse goals
on an increasingly law-governed footing.
and projects while minimising the scope for friction and mutual interference.
The European Union
Significantly, in an article published in 1939,
as an Oakeshottian `Civil Association'
Hayek argued that `the abrogation of national sovereignties and the creation of an effective international
According to the British philosopher Michael Oa-
order of law is a necessary complement and the
keshott, the proper business of government is `to try
logical consummation of the liberal programme', if
to keep its subjects at peace with one another in the
only because `an essentially liberal economic regime
activities in which they have chosen to seek their
is a necessary condition for the success of any inter-
happiness.' Therefore:
state federation.'
23
Indeed, since the citizens of such
a federation `will be reluctant to submit to any
the only appropriate manner of ruling is by mak-
interference in their daily affairs when the govern-
ing and enforcing rules of conduct . . . which, in
ment is composed of people of different nationalities
the circumstances, are least likely to result in a
and different traditions', it follows that `the govern-
collision of interests . . . Thus governing is re-
ment in a federation composed of many different
cognised as a specific and limited activity; not the
peoples will have to be restricted in scope.' Since the
management of an enterprise, but the rule of
full realisation of the potential economic benefits of
those engaged in a great diversity of self-chosen
such an entity would in Hayek's view entail eco-
enterprises.'
25
nomic and monetary union, there would have to be `less government all round' if such a federation was to
The rule of law is, in Oakeshott's view, `a method of
be practicable. Economic policy would then `have to
government remarkably economical in its use of
take the form of providing a rational permanent
power' and, `while losing nothing in strength, is
framework within which individual initiative will
itself the emblem of that diffusion of power which
have the largest possible scope.'
24
it exists to promote'. It is `the greatest single condi-
Hayek's linking of
tion of our freedom'.
inter-state federation to limited government and
26
projects for economic and monetary union pres-
Oakeshott's conception of civil association was
ciently anticipated what were to become the most
put forward in contradistinction to `enterprise asso-
distinctive features of European Union governance.
ciation', in which the state is perceived as an orga-
Of course, the European Union is far from being a
nisation for the attainment of prescribed ends which
perfect embodiment of liberal governance. Its ten-
are incumbent upon its citizens (as in the Thatch-
dencies towards corporatism, clientelism, corruption
erite project to transform the UK into UK plc, of
and a `fortress Europe' increasingly concerned with
which we were all to have become compliant em-
keeping out unwanted `aliens' compromise its liberal-
ployees, as well as in the more overtly teleological
ism. Nevertheless, its central emphases on the rule of
`planned
law, the uniform adoption and enforcement of stable
summed up Oakeshott's conception of a civil asso-
and predictable rules and the creation of an extended
ciation as `an association of persons who, having no
spontaneous legal order are bedrocks of liberalism on
ends or purposes held necessarily in common, never-
which a more completely liberal and cosmopolitan
theless coexist in peace under the rule of law. On this
order is gradually being built. The horse-trading,
account, the office of law is not typically to impose
deals and manoeuvres which take place at or prior
any particular duty or goal on men, but instead seeks
to meetings of the European Council and the Coun-
principally to facilitate their dealings with one an-
cil of Ministers often appear unseemly and cynical.
other'.
Yet they are intrinsic to the consensual adoption or
concept of civil association is that `the rules which
232
27
economies').
John
Gray
has
incisively
The distinctive feature of the Oakeshottian
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
constitute it are non-instrumental: they do not em-
Hence values such as legality, morality and justice
body any specific project, but instead act as condi-
are `best regarded not as ends but as values embodied
tions whereby individuals and groups pursue their
in the constraints governing all action . . . Even
own several and diverse projects. In its moral aspect,
peace is better regarded as a constraint than as a
civil association is
purpose', since it requires not the avoidance of all uses of force but rather an acceptance that `force is to 30
that mode of association which exemplifies in-
be used only in authorised ways'.
dividuality ± the condition in which human
associations are constituted by the ends they serve or
beings accept and celebrate their autonomy . . .
pursue, whereas practical associations are based upon
In its political dimension, civil association is
the forms of conduct which they either authorise or
characterised by the diffusion of power through-
prohibit. In these terms, international society and by
out society ± by a complex structure of counter-
implication most forms of international association
vailing institutions of precisely the sort that is
cannot be `purposive' (even though they are often
threatened by contemporary collectivist projects
seen as such), on account of the great diversity of
(of the Right and Left) of transforming govern-
goals and aspirations that exists among states.
ment into an enterprise association.
28
Thus purposive
31
`International society' is best conceived as an inclusive `practical association' geared to the main-
Terry Nardin has drawn upon Oakeshott's distinc-
tenance and observance of certain practices and rules
tion between civil and enterprise associations to
of conduct designed to minimise the risks of armed
fashion a similarly useful distinction between `prac-
conflict and to maximise the scope for peaceful
tical' and `purposive' conceptions of international
coexistence between states engaged in the pursuit
society and of international associations:
of widely differing goals, values, beliefs and projects.
Practical association is a relationship among those
Some international associations are purposive;
who are engaged in the pursuit of different and
they exist for the sake of pursuing various shared
possibly incompatible purposes, and who are as-
purposes; the rules they adopt and the ethic they
sociated with one another . . . only in respecting
foster are instrumental to the achievement of the
certain restrictions on how each may pursue his
purposes for which they were created. But inter-
own purposes . . . Purposive association is a
national society as such ± that inclusive society of
relationship among those who co-operate for
states, or community of communities, within
the purpose of securing certain shared beliefs,
which all international association takes place
values and interests, who adopt certain practices
± is not a purposive association constituted by
as a means to that end, and who regard such
a joint wish on the part of all states to pursue
practices as worthy of respect only to the extent
certain ends in concert. It is, rather, an associa-
that they are useful instruments of the common
tion of independent and diverse political com-
purpose'.
29
munities, each devoted to its own conception of the good . . . The common good of this inclusive
Admittedly, any association is created to serve a
community resides not in the ends that some, or
purpose and is in that sense purposive but:
at times even most, of its members may wish collectively to pursue but in the values of justice,
The purposes of practical association, however,
peace, security and coexistence, which may be
are of an altogether different order from those
enjoyed through participation in a common body
served by purposive association . . . The values of
of authoritative practices.
32
practical association . . . are those appropriate to the relations among persons who are not neces-
In Nardin's view, international society has to take a
sarily engaged in any common pursuit but who
form that is capable of accommodating culturally and
nevertheless have to get along with one another.
ideologically heterogeneous states. This kind of in-
233
ROBERT BIDELEUX
ternational society first emerged in Europe following
international associations such as the EU, most of his
the sixteenth- and seventeenth-century wars of re-
insights can be applied to Europe as well. In practice,
ligion, when it became necessary
the participants in the EU are united not so much by engagement in common endeavours (however much
to work out principles of coexistence among
they say they are!) as by their acceptance that they
individuals and groups committed to different
are members of an association defined by a common
conceptions of truth and the good . . . Thus
set of rules and laws designed to allow each of them
the kind of legal order that developed in Europe
to pursue their own goals and ambitions with the
was shaped by the gradual discovery that, in the
minimum of friction and mutual impairment.
absence of agreement on ends, agreement on procedures is required if destructive conflict is to be avoided.'
Given the existence . . . of significant differences
33
of belief, value and interest, the expectation of . . . unity on the basis of shared purposes is
Therefore, it is also necessary to
sure to be disappointed. The basis of international association lies in deference to practices that
reject all extreme claims that shared purposes [or
embody recognition of the fact that we must
values or beliefs] are a necessary condition of
coexist . . . with others with whom we some-
international order . . . International law, and
times share little beyond a common predica-
especially customary international law, embodies
ment.
36
the minimum principles of mutual accommodation required for the coexistence not only of
The fact that the European Union lacks a single
separate states but of different kinds of states . . .
centre of power, decision-making and authority but
It is through the experience of international
instead has a multiplicity of such centres has been
association defined and directed by this common
conducive to the dispersal of power, authority and
law that an appropriate international culture
functions which Oakeshott regarded as the chief
bridging other cultural differences is created.
34
safeguards of liberty. Further, the fact that the European Union's budget has not been allowed to
Part of the attraction of the terms of reference
exceed 1.27 per cent of the combined GDP of its
employed by Oakeshott, Hayek and Nardin is that
member states has in effect forced it to remain an
they eschew the impersonal pseudo-scientific abstrac-
Oakeshottian `civil association', even though some
tions involved in analyses of behaviour, forces, pro-
observers consider that it harbours (in my view
cesses, variables and correlations, and speak instead of
unrealisable) ambitions to become an `enterprise
conduct, society, law and individuals as moral agents
association' in certain sectors. The Single Market
who deliberate and make reasoned judgements and
programme, the EU's growing social and environ-
choices. As Nardin puts it, his concern is
mental regulation responsibilities and the project for Economic and Monetary Union (EMU) are major extensions of the law-governed regulatory federation
not with international relations understood as a system of causally or functionally related variables
and civil association characteristics of the EU, rather
but with the arrangements of an international
than great leaps towards the creation of `big govern-
society constituted by the actions of thinking
ment' at the supranational level. Indeed, the Eur-
agents who must take each other into account
opean Union is governed by impersonal rules and
in making decisions . . . and whose acts are
laws to a far greater extent than any `really existing'
understood as being shaped and guided by rules
democracy. Contrary to the claims of British Euro-
of conduct rather than laws of behaviour.
35
phobes, EMU is governed by stringent rules and a regulatory committee of bankers rather than by an
Although Nardin focuses on relations between
emergent European superstate with major redistribu-
states in the world at large rather than on regional
tive capabilities. The EU corruption scandals of 1998
234
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
and 1999 highlighted how little (rather than how
common purpose. The observance of rules by all
much) power is wielded by individual commissioners
will be important for each because the achieve-
and other officials. It is not only power that corrupts,
ment of his purposes depends on it, but the
so does powerlessness.
respective purposes of different persons may be
The main virtue of the creation of a supranational
wholly different.
38
liberal legal order which functions in the manner of an Oakeshottian `civil association' rather than a
This is the way in which the European Union has
more purposive, redistributive and potentially coer-
accommodated a diversity of states and peoples,
cive `enterprise association' is that it erects a strong
assisting them to pursue their own very diverse
supranational framework of rules and laws (a form of
purposes within a common framework of rules and
`governance without government') which can reg-
laws which has maximised peace and prosperity and
ulate political and economic activities and power
minimised the scope for friction and conflict be-
without fostering a European `superstate' with more
tween them. This has much more to do with the rule
obviously Hobbesian, Weberian or Orwellian fea-
of law, consensual negotiation of mutually accepta-
tures and potential. Another of the virtues of such a
ble rules and laws, negotiated accommodation of
civil association is its ability to maximise the cer-
differences and `judicious' interpretation of rules
tainty, equity and transparency of the rules govern-
and laws by the (European) Court of Justice than
ing economic, social and environmental matters,
with democracy as such. As Hayek remarked, `the
above all through the equal application of its rules
ideal of individual liberty seems to have flourished
and laws to all. Rule certainty and stability of ex-
chiefly among people where, at least for long periods,
pectations lie at the heart of the Single Market
judge-made law predominated'.
programme and Economic and Monetary Union,
judicial or quasi-judicial rulings, the task of the
from which Europe's hitherto inflation-prone and
judges and of the EU Commission is not to ascertain,
relatively unstable less developed peripheries poten-
reflect or uphold the wishes of a demos or even of the
39
In making their
tially have much more to gain than do the already
fifteen separate demoi, but to endeavour to maximise
stable and disciplined `core' states, which have been
the internal consistency and viability of the EU legal
enjoying low levels of inflation and correspondingly
order and to minimise the scope for friction, conflict,
low `risk premia' on their interest rates for decades.
37
malfunction and acrimony. The major political safe-
In this situation, the case for redistribution of income
guard is not a democratic one involving the submis-
from the `rich core' to `poor peripheries' and for an
sion of the decisions reached and policies adopted
expansion of the European Union's redistributive
after protracted and tortuous negotiation to various
capabilities is correspondingly diminished.
forms of popular and/or parliamentary approval or ratification. Rather, it is the fact those decisions and
As emphasised by Hayek, the aim of the rules
policies can rarely go forward without gaining acmust be to facilitate that matching or tallying of
ceptance (often reluctantly and only after a great
the expectations on which the plans of the in-
deal of horse-trading) from fifteen separate states.
dividuals depend for their success . . . But all rules
One of the major implications of all this is that the
can achieve in this respect is to make it easier for
current `eastern' applicants for EU membership need
people to find together and to form that match;
neither expect nor be required to undergo major
abstract rules cannot actually secure that this will
extensions of democracy as such. Indeed, procedu-
always happen . . . Indeed, the superiority of
rally, in most cases their parliaments and govern-
certain rules will become evident largely in the
ments are as freely and fairly elected as their Western
fact that they will create an effective order not
European counterparts. Rather, what they have to
only within a closed group but also between
accept and adjust to is working within a political and
people who meet accidentally and do not know
economic environment which is much more exten-
each other personally. They will thus . . . create
sively and exactingly regulated by consensually ne-
an order even among people who do not pursue a
gotiated
235
and/or
judge-made
supranational
rules,
ROBERT BIDELEUX
regulations and laws ± most obviously those govern-
over, government itself is `increasingly contracted
ing the Single Market, but also those now pervading
out through various forms of privatisation and semi-
almost every aspect of the EU's operations.
40
Eur-
privatisation'.
44
These momentous changes are in
opean states which do not uphold liberal democracy,
turn blurring the distinctions between what is public
basic individual rights and liberties, market princi-
and what is private, between state and non-state,
ples and the rule of law exclude themselves from
between internal and external, between what is
potential membership of the European Union be-
military and what is civil, and even between war
cause of their consequent incapacity to discharge in
and peace.
full the essential requirements of EU membership.
rise of limited constitutional government, civil so-
This is no longer merely a matter of choice or
ciety and liberal democracy in the West, and the
preference on the part of the current member states,
blurring of such distinctions is potentially a very
but rather a sine qua non for the long-term survival
ominous
and effective functioning of the European Union.
now arise mainly within and across rather than
Ian Ward has rightly pointed to `the role that law
between states, as the emergence of new privatised
plays in determining who is ``European'' in the new
and transnationalised forms of organised violence
Europe, and who is not.'
41
45
Such distinctions were crucial to the
development.
Indeed,
armed
conflicts
erodes and in some cases completely disintegrates states. Thus the growing `privatisation of organised violence' in the Balkans, Transcausasia, Africa and
Power and Governance
parts of Asia and the Middle East is a reversal of the
in a Metamorphosing World
process by which states emerged and, if allowed to
The erosion of state power and autonomy, to which
continue unchecked, could bring about similar re-
the emerging western neoliberal policy consensus of
sults in the West.
46
the 1980s and 1990s most powerfully contributed,
However, it would be more appropriate to see this
has by no means been confined to the economic
`privatisation of organised violence' as just part of the
domain and the growth of transnational information
more pervasive `privatisation of power'
and communications networks. Mary Kaldor has
been in full flood since the neoliberal counter-re-
highlighted the degree to which the state has lost
volution in economic policy and governance during
its former near-monopoly of the means of coercion,
the 1980s. Privatisation, economic liberalisation and
which has been `eroded from above by the transna-
the unfettered development of transnational capit-
tionalisation of military forces' through membership
alism and global communications has engendered
of security organisations such as NATO and the
autonomous market forces and concentrations of
former Warsaw Pact,) and `eroded from below by
private economic power and influence whose com-
the privatisation of organised violence' as a result of
bined strength far exceeds that of any elected gov-
the often interlinked emergence of private security
ernment. The vast daily financial flows on the
services, paramilitary forces, mercenary armies, large-
world's currency and stock markets periodically set
scale gangsterism and arms/drug-dealing mafias, and
in motion tidal waves which could even overwhelm
the widespread disintegration and/or demobbing of
the US authorities and their Federal Reserve Board
regular armed forces engendered by proliferating
or the EU authorities and their European Central
instances of `state failure' as well as by the end the
Bank. `Over $1 trillion flows across the world's
Cold War (for example, in parts of Africa and the
foreign exchange markets every day; over 50 times
former Soviet and Yugoslav federations).
42
47
which has
The pri-
the size of world trade and dwarfing the collective
vatisation of organised violence is assuming less
foreign exchange reserves of the world's richest
blatant forms in Western Europe and in the USA,
states.'
where private security guards now outnumber the
been released from their old `national power-con-
police by two to one, but Kaldor warns that it is
tainers', which were much more amenable to na-
nevertheless taking place and that the West should
tional-democratic control than are the new global
beware of complacency in these matters.
43
48
The genies of transnational capitalism have
forces and regional power blocs. Yet any attempt by
More-
236
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
democrats to put them back into `national power-
anarchic) brave new world which has already ar-
containers' would precipitate a collapse of global
rived. The study of these great bodies of thought and
capitalist trade, production and economic confi-
policy prescription might remain a valuable intellec-
dence even worse than the one that occurred be-
tual exercise and of interest to historians, but it will
tween 1929 and 1931. Quite simply, liberalised
offer precious little guidance either as to what is
transnational capitalism has attained levels of eco-
happening or to what policies might be effective in
nomic activity, specialisation, innovation and dyna-
the future.
mism which would be unsustainable in a world
In these changed circumstances, the quest for
which attempted to reassert `democratic' control
increased democratic control ± whether national,
over supranational economic forces, especially if that
supranational or `cosmopolitan' ± is the pursuit of
control
nation-states.
a mirage. Demands that supranational regulatory
Whereas it was still possible to reassert national
bodies and rule-making organisations should be sub-
control of economies and thereby promote various
jected to democratic control and accountability, as
nationalist and etatist forms of autarkic or semi-
well as the anxieties arising from the fact that they
autarkic
early
are not, often stem from mistaken assumptions con-
1930s to the 1970s, these have ceased to viable
cerning the origin of most laws at the national level.
options since the late 1970s. Thatcherites rant in
As a result the so-called democratic deficit at the EU
vain against the erosion of `national sovereignty' and
supranational level is misleadingly contrasted with
state autonomy which they have misleadingly attrib-
supposedly `democratic' processes at the national
uted to the development of the European Union but
level. In fact, the executive branches of western
which was mainly a consequence of the neoliberal
governments have come to exercise inordinate con-
counter-revolution in economic policy and the ram-
trol over the legislatures, with the result that parlia-
pant globalisation which they themselves helped to
ments have become less and less effective as checks
unleash. The most that Europe can hope to do for
on the power of the executive.
now is to regulate, constrain and channel the liberated
small fraction of the huge volume of government
global market forces and the privatisation of power,
business comes under the direct control and scrutiny
both through the elaboration of supranational rules
of the elected parliaments in most western liberal
regimes of the sort maintained by the UN and the
democracies, especially under the secretive and oli-
World Trade Organisation and through the suprana-
garchic British system of `elective dictatorship' (as
tional legal order created by the EU. The Single
Lord Hailsham so aptly described it). Every four or
Market programme and the project of Economic and
five years electorates have a fleeting opportunity to
Monetary Union are therefore designed to promote
vote in a new `dictator' for the next few years ± that is
`more Europe' as well as `more market' ± more
the realistic extent of democracy in most western
effective regulation at the EU level to compensate
countries most of the time. What has made such
for the diminishing efficacy of regulation at the level
systems of government more bearable and effective
of the nation-state.
than any alternative system yet devised is not their
were
to
be
economic
exercised
development
by
from
the
49
Moreover, only a
(actually rather limited) elements of democracy. It is the very considerable heritage of liberal constitu-
Ways of Coping with
tionalism, limited government, accommodation of
Uncertainty and Friction
cultural diversity and rule of law which has safe-
Europe has now entered wholly uncharted waters.
guarded western liberties whose origins long predated
Several centuries of Western political and economic
democracy as such and have usually helped to pro-
thought and prescription premised upon the exis-
tect western democracies against the worst dangers of
tence of polities which are capable of exercising
majoritarian tyranny.
more-or-less effective jurisdiction over `their own'
Fundamentally,
as
argued
by
Hayek
(among
bounded territories, economies, citizenries, societies
others), few of the legal frameworks and other rules
and cultures have very little relevance to the (more
that regulate human conduct have ever been con-
237
ROBERT BIDELEUX
sciously and deliberately devised, laid down or or-
advance what will be successful and what will not,
dained by particular (far-seeing) parliaments, judici-
what will meet the paramount needs of the future
aries, governments or individual rulers. Rather, they
and what will not, or even to specify in advance what
have emerged `through a gradual process of trial and
those needs will be, as those who suffered several
error', to which the experiences and learning pro-
decades of Communist economic planning learned
cesses of successive generations have contributed.
to their great cost. It will be safer to base the EU on
Many rules have come into being because, in certain
the experimental, empirical liberalism of Hayek and
types of situation, friction is likely to arise among
Oakeshott than on the more controlling and pre-
individual actors about what each is entitled to do,
scriptive rationalist versions of liberalism. Explicitly
which can be prevented only if there are rules to tell
encouraging the EU to develop along more Oake-
each clearly what their respective rights and obliga-
shottian lines, as a civil rather than an enterprise
tions are. The gradual, piecemeal, iterative elabora-
association, ought to be Britain's distinctive contri-
tion of such rules is one of the means by which
bution.
51
mankind has learned to cope with the inherently incomplete, fragmented and dispersed nature of all
The Blessings of `Cosmopolitan Law'
human knowledge. Rules do not just restrict; they also empower and facilitate by fostering increased
Supranational European Union law has a particular
certainty, stability and security. For the most part
advantage over the `democratic' laws of liberal de-
our `actually existing' rules, regulations and laws
mocratic states with multi-ethnic, multi-racial or
have emerged, not as the results of conscious gov-
multi-denominational populations (that is, all of
ernmental or parliamentary decisions, but as the
Europe's liberal democracies, with the possible ex-
outcome of endless mutual adjustment of human be-
ception of Iceland). No matter how liberal and
haviour, without the deliberate intervention of an
democratic a liberal democracy might become, its
ultimate arbiter ± not unlike the continuous mutual
laws are still likely to embody (or at least to be seen as
adjustment of the spontaneous activities of indivi-
embodying) the interests and preferences of the
dual actors in market economies.
50
dominant national, ethnic or religious group(s),
In an increasingly `globalised' and `regionalised'
and to place (or at least to be seen as placing) various
world, laws, rules and regulatory regimes will increas-
minority groups in disadvantageous positions. Spe-
ingly have to deputise or substitute for the ever-
cial protection of the group rights of ethnic and
diminishing scope for democratic control and ac-
religious minorities rarely solves such problems, and
countability as the (supposedly) standard means of
more often than not entrenches divisions, conflict
safeguarding civil and political liberties and/or eco-
and perceptions of difference in ways that are coun-
nomic prosperity. Hayek's emphasis on the limits of
ter-productive.
our knowledge about the present (let alone the
EU laws and regulations is that they do not reflect,
future) is even more appropriate to the new circum-
nor are they based upon, the interests and aspirations
stances in which we now find ourselves. The best we
of any ethnic, religious or national majority. It is
can hope for is trial-and-error improvisation and
arithmetically impossible for any single ethnic, na-
adaptation of rules that can continue to allow us
tional or religious group to dominate the law-making
to live, work and trade together with the minimum
and governance of the European Union. The largest
of friction and the maximum of mutual benefit in a
single nation/ethnic group makes up no more than
shrinking and increasingly dangerous world. These
one-quarter of the population and it is greatly under-
`discovery processes' are iterative and pragmatic rather
represented in the EU Commission, the Council of
than democratic. Indeed, one must be on one's guard
Ministers and the European Parliament due to the
against nationalists, socialists, populists, neo-fascists
significant weighting in favour of small nations.
and even some well-meaning democrats who pedal
Roman Catholicism, the European Union's largest
preconceived blueprints and panaceas for the future,
single religious denomination, does not enjoy special
because it is simply not possible to identify in
favour. Indeed, EU law-making and governance are
238
52
By contrast, a major advantage of
CIVIL ASSOCIATION AND EUROPE
in no way directed against the national, ethnic and
monic ethnic and/or religious majorities. Such pro-
religious minorities `native' to Western Europe, even
blems can only be resolved within a larger framework
though few (if any) of the member states can wholly
in which no one group can establish a privileged or
escape accusations of racism and/or religious intol-
hegemonic position, because every group has become
erance towards various categories of immigrants of
a small minority. Thus Timothy Garton Ash is right
non-EU origin. There are indeed mounting tensions
to characterise the EU as a non-hegemonic liberal
between the European Union's liberal-cosmopolitan
order, although (like so many Anglo-Saxon com-
aspirations and founding ideals and its increasingly
mentators) he seriously misunderstands the political
exclusionary and intolerant stance towards immi-
implications of EMU and misconstrues it as a threat
grants from outside the EU, laying it open to charges
to ± rather than as an extension and reinforcement of
of malfeasance and hypocrisy. Its main line of de-
± this supranational liberal legal order.
55
fence must be the morally lame one that `political
The resultant shift of emphasis from unfettered
communities endure because they are exclusive, and
sovereignty and democracy to a supranational liberal
most establish their peculiar identities by accentuat-
legal order that drastically circumscribes national
ing the differences between outsiders and aliens.'
53
sovereignty and `unlimited' democracy, far from sig-
The EU has often been likened to the Austro-
nifying some huge `sacrifice' or `retrograde step' (as
Hungarian Empire, which was similarly held together
many `Europhobes' and the more blinkered demo-
by a supranational rule of law, and within which no
crats would have us believe), is actually the major
single ethnic group held an absolute majority. Never-
benefit that the EU can confer on its member states.
theless, the cosmopolitan universalism of the EU is a
The alternatives foregone are only illusions of na-
vast improvement on the ethnic particularism, paro-
tional sovereignty and democracy, mere fig leaves
chial narrow-mindedness and widespread religious
which barely conceal the reality of inescapable de-
bigotry and segregation which many Central Eur-
mocratic deficits at all levels, since national democ-
opeans have acknowledged as central characteristics
racies
of the Habsburg domains, which did have dominant
branch control of the legislature and the media while
(albeit non-majoritarian) ethnic groups with ethnic-
Europe as a whole is falling increasingly under the
collectivist mindsets and a strongly collectivist domi-
sway of global capitalism, global information and
nant religion. EU law, which has acquired `supre-
communications networks, and an expanding trans-
macy' and `direct effect' in the member states, is
national security alliance (NATO). The emerging
probably the only `actually existing' legal framework
supranational EU legal order cannot make good
in the world within which `cosmopolitan law-en-
Europe's growing democratic deficits, but it can
forcement' could be rendered fully operational.
54
have
succumbed
to
increasing
executive
mitigate the consequences and confer major com-
This supranational system of `cosmopolitan law',
pensating benefits which would be unattainable
rather than utopian conceptions of `cosmopolitan
within a more fragmented and fractious Europe of
democracy', offers the basis on which the EU can
nation-states. My pessimism concerning the pro-
best help to defuse Europe's potentially explosive
spects for liberal democracy is combined with a
`minority problems'. The essential point is that
considerable optimism that this particular cloud
`minority problems' can never be fully resolved with
has a very substantial silver lining.
a framework of nation-states which contain hege-
Notes
to Terry Nardin's use of Oakeshott's distinction be-
1. I was first drawn to Hayek through my earlier work on
tween civil and enterprise associations.
centrally planned economies and to Oakeshott by Samuel Brittan's columns in The Financial Times,
2. Hayek (1993), volume 1, pp. 1±3.
but my understanding of both has been enhanced
3. See Spinelli (1957) and Albertini (1999), passim.
by several years of fruitful discussion with Bruce
4. Merkel (1994), p. 38.
Haddock. He and Noel O'Sullivan drew my attention
5. Laffan (1999), p. 336.
239
ROBERT BIDELEUX
6. Lodge (1994), pp. 364±5.
32. Ibid., pp. 18±19.
7. Gray (1998), pp. 149±50.
33. Ibid., p. 318.
8. Majone (1992), pp. 77±101.
34. Ibid., pp. 222±3.
9. Bulmer (1993), pp. 375±6.
35. Ibid., p. 32.
10. Mann (1993), p. 130.
36. Ibid., p. 324.
11. Smith (1996), p. 253.
37. Gros and Steinherr (1994), p. 76.
12. Mann (1993), pp. 131, 135.
38. Hayek (1993), volume 1, pp. 98±9.
13. Smith (1996), p. 259.
39. Ibid., p. 94.
14. For example, Held (1995) and (1996).
40. This argument is presented at greater length in Bideleux (1999b).
15. This is a major reason why other regional blocs, most notably in Latin America, are seeking to emulate the
41. Ward (1997), p. 79.
European Union's success.
42. Kaldor (1999), pp. 4, 5, 28, 91±6, 140.
16. Dahl (1994), pp. 26, 32±3.
43. Ibid., p. 11.
17. This is the main theme of Tsagarousianou, Tambini
44. Ibid., p. 74. 45. Ibid., pp. 2, 29.
and Bryan (eds) (1998). 18. Quoted by Ladrech (1994), pp. 78±9.
46. Ibid., pp. 4, 5, 11.
19. Temple-Lang (1996), p. 126.
47. This apt phrase may have been coined by Bruce Haddock, from whom I first heard it.
20. Loveland (1996), pp. 534±5. 21. Hayek (1993), volume 1, p. 6.
48. McGrew (1997), p. 6.
22. Touraine (1997), pp. 2, 4.
49. Hayek (1993), volume 3, chapter 13.
23. Hayek (1939), p. 146.
50. Hayek (1960), pp. 157±9.
24. Hayek (1939), pp. 141±3.
51. Bideleux (1999a), pp. 116±18.
25. Oakeshott (1962), p. 189.
52. This is argued in more detail in Bideleux (1996), pp. 288±90, and in Bideleux and Jeffries (1998), pp. 407±
26. Ibid., pp. 40±1.
34 and 460±6.
27. Gray (1989), p. 207. 28. Ibid., p. 210.
53. Linklater (1998), p. 1.
29. Nardin (1983), pp. 9, 14.
54. Kaldor (1999), pp. 124±31, uses this in a more military and intergovernmental sense.
30. Ibid., pp. 12±13.
55. Garton Ash (1998), pp. 59±64.
31. Ibid., pp. 14, 24.
240
18
THE IDEA OF A LIBERALDEMOCRATIC PEACE Howard Williams
An impressive literature has developed in recent
deciding what the argument looks like from Kant's,
years dealing with the topic of a `liberal-democratic
or a Kantian, perspective. In the literature on demo-
peace'. Indeed, a debate has raged in American
cratic peace, Kant has been much referred to: it is
political science journals such as International Secur-
true to say that he has become an emblem of the
ity and Comparative Political Studies about the validity
thesis. This is so to such an extent that authors need
of the hypothesis that the growth in the number of
only cite Kant in their title to show that they are
states with liberal-democratic polities will lead to a
engaging with the debate. Others make play with
more stable and harmonious international order.
Kant's name to demonstrate their topicality, such as
The debate is conducted in a most civil and fair
Christopher Layne's title to his article on `Kant or
way, with a great deal of emphasis being given to the
Cant: The Myth of the Democratic Peace'.
1
empirical evidence for the truth or otherwise of the
The treatment of Kant in such articles tends to be
hypothesis. Nonetheless, lines have been drawn:
quite cursory and the emphasis generally turns very
some stand on the side of optimism and a whole-
quickly to the evidence. Here I want to alter this
hearted endorsement of the thesis, while others are
emphasis by attempting to measure the democratic
more lukewarm and await more evidence. Yet others
peace thesis by Kant's standards. We will find that
are entirely sceptical, doubting whether liberal in-
there are intriguing differences of emphasis between
stitutions bring peace and whether or not interna-
current international peace theorists and Kant's
tional peace is possible at all. It looks as though the
original argument, which tells us a lot about the
debate is set to run and run as more evidence is
priorities of liberal internationalism now, and Kant's
gathered and greater subtlety is shown in the inter-
contrasting objectives for practical philosophy and
pretation of regimes and liberal theory itself.
humanity in general.
My object is neither to add to nor query the relevance of this interesting literature. I think the
Michael Doyle
debate is most welcome, particularly as it demonstrates the relevance of political theory to issues of
The debate on the democratic peace has its origins in
international politics and security. My object is
a resurgence of interest in Kant's political philosophy
rather to examine the philosophical basis of this
and international relations which occurred in the
discussion. I want to travel down the path of demo-
early 1980s. One of the writers who most effectively
cratic peace, not with the present preoccupation in
caught on to this trend was Michael Doyle, who in
mind of deciding whether or not such a democratic
two 1983 articles in Philosophy and Public Affairs
peace is on its way, but rather with the intention of
highlighted Kant's legacy to liberalism and interna-
241
HOWARD WILLIAMS
tionalism; these were distilled into the one key 1986
states may have been prone to be `trigger-happy',
article `Liberalism and World Politics' in the Amer-
contrary to Kant's pacific recommendations. Where
ican Political Science Review.
2
Although in the latter
liberal-democratic states have become involved in
Kant is cited along with Machiavelli and Schump-
wars to defend liberal causes this has often turned out
eter it is clear that Kant forms the centrepiece of
badly. In so far as western democratic states have
Doyle's argument. For Doyle Kant's views on politics
found liberal grounds for aggression Doyle thinks
not only have a valuable policy component in that
they have strayed from Kant's conceptions.
they show how American foreign relations ought best to be framed but they also have a significant
Francis Fukuyama
empirical relevance in that Kant is `a liberal republican whose theory of internationalism best accounts
Further credence has been given to the democratic
for what we are.' In contrast Machiavelli is `a classi-
peace thesis by Francis Fukuyama's writing on the
cal republican whose glory is an imperialism we often
End of History. Fukuyama is perhaps better known for
practice.'
3
Doyle's object, then, is to put forward
the Hegelian connections of his thinking, especially
Kant's political theory as a model of good practice for
the striking claim that there are no major progressive
liberal-democratic states to follow.
political developments yet to come in human his-
Doyle's thesis has a moral and an empirical side to
tory, but nonetheless he does draw very heavily upon
it. The moral side is naturally that policy-makers
Kant and the idea of a pacific union. However,
should be informed by Kant's liberal international-
Fukuyama gets to democratic peace via a very dif-
ism and the empirical side shows that where policy-
ferent route from Doyle. He is particularly struck by
makers have been informed by Kant's principles they
the notion of a struggle for recognition that occurs in
have, in terms of promoting peace, turned out to be
human history, borrowing this from Hegel's philo-
quite successful. In this liberal-democratic thesis,
sophy (the idea of such a struggle figures quite
then, the behaviour of states that conform as near
prominently in the Phenomenology of Spirit and the
as possible to Kant's model of a republic comes under
earlier
close scrutiny. The number of wars they have been
(1804±6)).
engaged in, their nature and their length are docu-
gle for recognition ± a struggle which affects all
mented accurately and the results weighed very
human individuals ± as a means of dismissing all
carefully. This meticulous research is a feature of
but the democratic republic as a legitimate form of
Doyle's work. The 1986 article has a three-page
government. According to him, the difficulty with
appendix where all the liberal regimes which have
all non-democratic forms of government is that they
existed from 1700 to 1982 are listed and all the
prevent the struggle for recognition, which always
international wars since 1817 are given chronologi-
occurs between free human individuals, from work-
cally. Doyle rests some of his conclusions upon this
ing itself out in a non-destructive form. The beauty
evidence. As he states in the article's abstract, `liberal
about the democratic mode of government is that it
states are different. They are indeed peaceful.' But
allows everyone to follow their own paths in a
the evidence is that they are not always inclined to
competitive way without preventing others from
peace: `they are also prone to make war. Liberal states
doing the same. Earlier, more authoritarian forms
have created a separate peace, as Kant argued they
of government stand in the way of such an equal
would.'
4
unpublished 5
work
from
his
Jena
period
Fukuyama uses the notion of the strug-
The evidence is therefore mixed but in no
form of recognition. They are based upon forms of
sense refutes the position Doyle believes Kant and
recognition which elevate one individual or a group
other liberals to hold. Living by the rules outlined by
of individuals above the rest. Fukuyama believes that
Kant in his Definitive Articles to Perpetual Peace can
societies which are properly democratic are non-
pay in terms of the avoidance of war. Indeed Doyle
antagonistic within themselves and therefore are
seems to believe that even closer attention to Kant's
also likely to be non-antagonistic towards each
arguments might have paid off because he fears that
other. Like Doyle, Fukuyama provides his own list of
in some respects the rulers of liberal-democratic
242
THE IDEA OF A LIBERAL-DEMOCRATIC PEACE
6
democratic states in his writings. He sees the spread
way of their seeking mutual recognition in the world.
of democracies as part of the universal history of
But Fukuyama believes that the growth of modern
mankind which is leading to the worldwide recogni-
science and the technological improvement which
tion of all individuals as equals. Fukuyama is highly
follows from it means that human desire and human
optimistic about this course of events. In his view,
reason point in the same direction. Economic effi-
`the growth of liberal democracy, together with its
ciency flows from the adoption of liberal-democratic
companion, economic liberalism, has been the most
practices and rules. No state can afford to go it alone
remarkable macropolitical phenomenon of the last
in the modern world economy. To flourish, states
four hundred years.'
7
In liberal democratic states no
have to open their markets and encourage both trade
adults are in general excluded from the political
and investment. In this respect, Fukuyama envisages
process. They all equally are given the right to vote
a kind of economic determinacy which forces people
and can themselves usually stand for office if they
towards greater democracy and the opportunity of
wish to do so. This widening of participation in the
peace. This argument seems very similar to the
political process takes the edge off the natural com-
`guarantee' of eternal peace which nature provides
petition for preference among individuals. The com-
that Kant puts forward in the first supplement to
petition does not disappear but is channelled in a
Perpetual Peace.
civil direction. States that allow full democratic civil
mism about the applicability of his own peace thesis
competition fall outside history and those who fail to
we can take the following: `In fact, such a Kantian
allow it are regarded as still within history. They
liberal international order had come into being
have yet to make the step to the condition wholly
willy-nilly during the Cold War under the protective
appropriate to human life. `The post-historical world
umbrella of organisations like NATO, the European
is one in which the desire for comfortable self-pre-
Community,
servation has been elevated over the desire to risk
GATT.'
one's life in battle for pure prestige, and in which
theory ceases to be a hypothesis and becomes instead
universal and rational recognition has replaced the
a reality.
struggle for domination.'
11
10
the
As evidence of Fukuyama's opti-
OECD,
the
Group
of
Seven,
With Fukuyama the democratic peace
8
Fukuyama believes that Kant foresaw such a con-
`Liberalism and World Politics'
dition of universal peace in his political philosophy and therefore provided the basis for the development
Clearly, the empirical tone of the debate is most
of a convincing liberal interpretation of this phe-
marked in both Fukuyama and Doyle, focusing upon
nomenon. So although it is Hegel who inspires his
the factual reality or otherwise of Kant's outline for
vision of the universal homogeneous state Fukuyama
perpetual peace. This is very flattering for Kant's
gains the idea of a democratic world peace from
argument but I am not sure at all that it is the kind of
Kant. He is well aware that many of the liberal
reception he had in mind. At the general philoso-
internationalist movements inspired by Kant, such
phical level it should be borne in mind that Kant is
as the League of Nations, have ended in failure. But
more often regarded as a transcendental idealist
he argues that `what many people have not under-
rather than a straightforward defender of empiricism.
stood, however, is that the actual incarnations of the
Kant was very impressed by the empiricist philoso-
Kantian idea have been seriously flawed from the
phies of Locke and Hume but ultimately wished to
start by not following Kant's own precepts.'
9
differ with them about the importance of observation
Broadly speaking, Fukuyama believes the move-
in the construction of human knowledge. Kant
ment towards peace and democracy represents an
wanted to emphasise in his critical philosophy the
irreversible process. This does not mean that he
active human part played in the production of
thinks it is an inevitable outcome at any point in
knowledge as well as the passive part played by
time. The leaders of states may make poor choices or
the absorption of data. This brings us to the most
fail properly to see the road ahead. Their desire for
striking overall difference between the Doyle/Fu-
power and prestige may momentarily stand in the
kuyama approach to the growth of a peaceful world
243
HOWARD WILLIAMS
order and Kant's. In many respects Doyle and Fu-
essay by themselves, and more than half when taken
kuyama play the role of passive spectators in obser-
with the preliminary articles, this is a striking omission.
ving the role of liberal republican regimes in bringing
Doyle does have a strong justification in that the three
about peace whereas Kant's main emphasis is on the
definitive articles represent the main positive points
role that the leaders of states and an enlightened
that Kant wished to highlight in his essay. These
public can play in realising the goal. Kant's Perpetual
stipulate the requirements for (1) a republican form
Peace represents the most explicit kind of moral
of government; (2) a federation of free states; (3)
advocacy in which facts are cited to demonstrate
cosmopolitan law to be limited to the right of universal
that the author's goals are not wholly unrealistic,
hospitality. These three definitive laws provide the
whereas Doyle and Fukuyama's work is directed more
backbone for Doyle's argument and the first two are
to showing the empirical feasibility of the goal of a
also highlighted by Fukuyama.
democratic peace and thereafter its possible moral
analyses in sufficient detail the `guarantee' for perpe-
desirability. For Doyle and Fukuyama the lure of the
tual peace which Kant presents in the first supplement
democratic peace thesis lies mainly in its apparent
to his essay which would seem, dealing as it does with
present empirical validity whereas for Kant the allure
the course of history upon the development of peace, to
of his thesis stands independently of particular pre-
have an important bearing on their arguments. Over-
sent facts. For him, we ought to aim for a world made
looked also are Kant's views on the role of the philo-
up of free, republican states because this is the right
sopher, his discussions of morality and politics, and his
thing to do even if present circumstances do not
reflections on the role of publicity in politics.
13
Arguably, neither
indicate with total clarity that this will bring lasting
Doyle's account of Kant is therefore a highly
peace. Kant thinks that we have to work on the
selective one. But in those matters he chooses to
assumption that the thesis can be shown both mo-
discuss he is persuasive. Indeed, in very many re-
rally as well as empirically to be correct.
spects both he and Fukuyama get Kant right. Doyle
Doyle's position is therefore not at odds with
in particular provides a highly accurate report of the
Kant's argument for peace. The criticism that might
kind of internal social and political structure it is
legitimately be levelled at Doyle and Fukuyama is
important to have in order to ensure the most rapid
that they tell only part of the story. The part they tell
progress towards peace, and his discussion of Kant's
is the one which is empirically reassuring. As Doyle
cosmopolitanism
eloquently puts it:
Although Doyle's Kantian argument has been called
is
illuminating
and
valuable.
the `democratic' peace theory, he himself sensibly Beginning in the eighteenth century and slowly
stresses that Kant's main emphasis is upon the re-
growing since then, a zone of peace, which Kant
publican nature of the ideal form of government. In
called the `pacific federation' or `pacific union',
fact we can add that in his original account of the
has begun to be established among liberal socie-
kind of rule most suitable for bringing international
ties. More than 40 liberal states currently make up
harmony in Perpetual Peace Kant is quite hostile to
the union. Most are in Europe and North Amer-
the democratic form. As he puts it:
ica, but they can be found on every continent.
12
Democracy, in the truest sense of the word, is It is interesting to note that Doyle draws his argu-
necessarily a despotism, because it establishes an
ment primarily from one section only of Perpetual
executive power through which all the citizens
Peace: this is the section in which Kant outlines the
may make decisions about (and indeed against)
three definitive articles for a lasting peace. Doyle
the single individual without his consent, so that
makes little use of the earlier section containing the
decisions are made by all the people and yet not
three preliminary articles and hardly touches at all
by all the people.
14
upon the various supplements and appendices which follow upon the definitive articles. As the supplements
Kant's republican ideal is intended to prevent all
and appendices constitute more than a third of the
kinds of despotism, not only the despotism of one
244
THE IDEA OF A LIBERAL-DEMOCRATIC PEACE
individual who rules arbitrarily from the top but also
sion that Kant rules out democracy as a possible form
the despotism of a group of people who might seek to
of viable government. Kant thinks there are essen-
rule arbitrarily from the bottom. In a republic, as
tially only two forms of government: the despotic or
Kant understands it, there has to be a proper separa-
the republican.
tion of powers between the executive, legislature and
critique, Kant has in mind a more radical kind of
judiciary. Not only are the rulers not allowed to
direct democracy than is now usual in western states.
make the law, they are also not allowed to interfere
Yet still, I would argue, there are elements of Kant's
in the adjudication of infringements to the law. Law-
objections to democracy which have a bearing on
makers should not also be in a position to affect the
the current practices of western democracies and on
actions of rulers in the execution of the laws, nor can
the application of Kant's peace theory. Although
they seek to influence members of the judiciary in
Kant's advocacy of the republican form of govern-
the decisions they make. Equally, members of the
ment can be read as favouring the kind of represen-
judiciary are not under any circumstances to interfere
tative democracy to be found in countries such as the
in the work of the legislature and executive.
United States, Germany and France it can also be
17
It might be argued here that, in his
read as a warning against tendencies towards a majoritarian style of democracy which, from time,
The First Definitive Article
to time, influence the government of these countries.
This very strict separation of powers rules out direct
Like Mill and Tocqueville, Kant fears the tyranny of
democracy as an ideal of government for Kant.
the majority and believes a genuinely rational form
Certainly, he is very much in favour of citizens
of government has to be properly structured to
developing
their
prevent it occurring. For example, it is difficult to
views be known. He thinks that every citizen is as
see how his republicanism might wholly embrace the
valuable as the next. He does not take an elitist view
kind of party politics now prevalent in western states.
of politics, believing that political decision-making
It is conceivable that Kant's guidelines are compa-
should be confined to those `in the know'. But he has
tible with parties competing for representation with-
a logical or technical objection to the idea of every-
in legislatures and so with their success putting
one trying to have a hand in running a state. As he
forward a certain legislative programme. However,
sees it, the people as a whole cannot rule themselves.
it is difficult to see how Kant's principles might be
No one should be allowed to be a judge in their own
used to endorse parties competing for sole executive
cases. And where each branch of the polity is under
authority,
the control of the people as a whole this can easily
matched by an equal dominance in the legislature.
occur. Just as it would not be right if one individual
Where a party uses executive authority to press
sought to control each branch of government so also
through its own programme, and this programme
it has to be wrong if the people as a body seeks to
is willed by a certain section of the population and
control the executive, legislature and judiciary. We
not all, then the government must, according to
have to be ruled by our representatives. As Kant puts
Kant, tend towards despotism. It is true that most
it, `any form of government which is not represen-
parties in western states are not monolithic structures
political
awareness
tative is essentially an anomaly.'
and
15
letting
particularly
if
that
dominance
were
If we expect rules
and have their own internal representative features
to be fairly administered then those who are subject
which mitigate the problem. But where such parties
to them should not also at the same time be respon-
tend towards unity or uniformity the danger of
sible for making them.
straying towards despotism (as Kant understands
Although Doyle stresses this claim of Kant's,
16
it) must exist. Thus, peculiarly, from Kant's stand-
there is a large gap in his presentation of Kant's thesis
point the more diverse, open, representative and
in relation to democracy. While making no attempt
pluralist a party, the more it will conform to his
to suggest that Kant is an enthusiast for democracy,
ideal
he does not bring out the objections Kant has to it.
power.
of
government
should
it
gain
executive
The fact that Kant's prescription for the ideal
We cannot, for instance, glean from Doyle's discus-
245
HOWARD WILLIAMS
polity requires majoritarian tendencies to be kept in
possibility of a democratic peace. He thinks that
check has important implications for his peace the-
such independent individuals who form a republic
sis. Kant would regard states whose representative
will be unlikely to seek war with other states, first
systems were liable to factional control as possibly
because through their representatives they would be
more inclined to belligerence than other states where
making decisions on their own behalf and, second,
the republican model he outlines is more rigidly
if there were costs to be borne, they themselves
adhered to. Democratic states which allowed one
would have to bear them.
party to control both the legislature and executive
In this respect Doyle believes that `the apparent
might be more prone to war than others, just as
absence of war between liberal states, whether ad-
democratic states which allowed one set of opinions
jacent or not, for almost 200 years thus may have
to predominate at the expense of others through
significance.' In states where the Kantian features of
inadequate public debate might be seen as less peace-
a separation of powers, representative government
able. Doyle and Fukuyama's optimistic approach to
and some form of adult suffrage have been absent
Kant's thinking seems to overlook these possibilities
there seems not to have been the same restraint
which surely would have exercised Kant. It is very
shown in relation with other states. `Feudal, fascist,
important for Kant that all citizens should regard the
communist, authoritarian forms of rule' do not,
rulers as acting on their behalf, and with their
according to Doyle, have such a good record.
authority, even if in many respects they disagree
he finds particularly striking is the behaviour of
with the policies being pursued. Should political
liberal states (which best approximate to the Kantian
structures within a state systematically exclude one
model) when major wars actually occur. Not only do
section of the population (which might be seen as
such states not fight wars with each other, they also
occurring where some discriminatory political prin-
tend, when forced, to concur in their view as to
ciples are taken to their extreme) then they cannot
which constitutes the `bad' side. As Doyle puts it,
be fully regarded as co-citizens. Subjects who are
`when states are forced to decide on which side of an
alienated in this way from their states are more liable
impending world war they will fight, liberal states all
to be indifferent to possible aggressive foreign poli-
wind up on the same side despite the complexity of
cies and are possibly more likely to be used as
the paths that take them there.'
19
What
20
`cannon-fodder' in any war. Thus Kant's liberal
Doyle is correct to emphasise how the behaviour
republicanism needs emphasising if the `democratic
of non-despotic states tends to point in the same
peace' thesis is to be true to its origins.
direction. But it is doubtful that Kant would see this as proof of his contention. This is because even if the leaders of a republican state were to take the `wrong
The Second Definitive Article
side' in a world war (which Finland is alleged to have
What Doyle also perhaps glosses over in his writ-
done at the time of the Second World War in some
ings, and the liberal treatment of Kant in general
of the literature calling the democratic peace theory
has to deal with carefully, is Kant's attitude to the
into doubt
role of women as citizens. Essentially, Kant excludes
states from the duty of trying to hold to the project of
all women from active citizenship, as he does all
perpetual peace in all their future actions. It is
dependants including wage-workers, servants and the jobless.
18
21
) this would not absolve the leaders of all
interesting that in Perpetual Peace Kant does not
Far from being unfortunate prejudice
cite the behaviour of republican states to demon-
which is readily dispensable in his overall account,
strate the truth of his plan; rather, he refers to such
he makes this stipulation on the grounds that to be
states from the standpoint of the example they might
in a proper position to have an enlightened and
set to other states. He makes this clear in his com-
disinterested view of the rules that bind together a
ments upon the Second Definitive Article where he
society you have to owe your existence to no one
states: `If by good fortune one powerful and enligh-
other than yourself. Such people, he thought, could
tened nation can form a republic (which by its nature
not. This is absolutely pivotal in his account of the
is inclined to seek perpetual peace) this will provide
246
THE IDEA OF A LIBERAL-DEMOCRATIC PEACE
a focal point for federal association among other states.'
the unrestricted sovereignty of states. The recom-
22
mendation that a pacific federation of free states be
A great deal of the discussion in the democratic
formed is one that flows from this initial objection.
peace debate has focused on the extent to which
Kant holds that very little progress can be attained in
states with Kantian-style constitutions form a pacific
international politics if the leaders of states behave as
union. Enthusiasts for the proposition have discov-
rulers of entirely self-contained and wilfully inde-
ered that states with liberal constitutions tend to
pendent territories who can declare war wherever
keep the peace in relation to each other and those
they see fit upon any other sovereign entities. The
who question the peace theory suggest that there is a
very conception of an international politics based
great deal of evidence that states with such consti-
upon such wholly unrestricted sovereignty carries the
tutions are still liable to war. Doyle's thesis is that
seeds of its own destruction. As Kant sees it.
`liberal republics will progressively establish peace among themselves by means of the pacific federation
the concept of a law of nations becomes mean-
(foedus pacificium) described in Kant's Second Defi-
ingless if interpreted as the right to go to war. For
nitive Article.'
23
In his view, `most liberal theorists
this would make it a right to determine what is
have offered inadequate guidance in understanding
lawful not by means of generally valid external
the exceptional nature of liberal pacification.' Where
law, but by means of one-sided maxims backed up
many fall down, he thinks, is in their inability to
by physical force.
27
explain the way in which some liberal states tend also to get embroiled in war. In this respect, he claims that `Immanuel Kant offers the best guidance.'
Doyle is highly conscious of the federative aspect
24
of Kant's peace plan but does not bring out this
Kant is able to understand the tendency of liberal
indictment of the traditional notions of state sover-
states to form with each other islands of peace and
eignty which underlie Kant's critique of interna-
their tendency to be less at home with non-liberal
tional law. He notes that Kant's
states. Doyle understands Kant to be recommending in
pacific union is not a single peace treaty ending
his Second Definitive Article neither a formal fed-
one war, a world state, nor a state of nations. Kant
eration nor any institutionalised form of cooperation.
finds the first insufficient. The second and third
Mainly, he is emphasising a disposition of states with
are impossible or potentially tyrannical. National
republican constitutions not to attack each other
sovereignty precludes reliable subservience to a
militarily. But Doyle does go a bit further to suggest
state of nations; a world state destroys the civic
that Kant `appears to have in mind a mutual non-
freedom on which the development of human
aggression pact, perhaps a collective security agree-
capacities rests.
ment.'
25
28
This seems very close to what Kant suggests
when he proposes that the `law of nations should be based on a federalism of free states.'
26
Now although it is indeed true that Kant rules out for
But care is
the foreseeable future a world state resting upon a
necessary here before we endorse Doyle's interpreta-
worldwide civil society, this is not because the pur-
tion in its entirety. Particularly important in the way
suit of such a condition is morally wrong. In his view
in which Kant formulates the Second Definitive
we ought to give up the total and arbitrary indepen-
Article is its markedly counterfactual nature. He is
dence of our national state and seek to approximate to
not speaking directly of any empirical state of affairs,
a world state. Our present condition is not one of
present or future, in the Article itself. He has in mind
which we can be proud. What prevents us from
much more the intellectual presuppositions which
attaining the condition of world statehood which
form the basis for an effective international law.
reason prescribes is the sheer physical difficulty of
Indeed, I think the main thrust of the Article for
coordinating government against the entrenched
perpetual peace is a criticism of prevailing concep-
habits of the leaders of sovereign states, and over
tions of international law which ground that law in
huge tracts of territory, some of which are not
247
HOWARD WILLIAMS
developed (in Kant's day this was of course a much
direct recognition of the kind of mutation of state
greater problem than it is now). In Kant's view the
sovereignty this might involve. In the kind of world
former point poses the greatest difficulty. There is an
Kant envisages no one state can prevail over an-
irrational immaturity in the attitude of states' leaders.
other; each has always to accommodate itself to the
They are prepared to drive humanity to destruction
next as though they were neighbouring citizens
to retain their own standing as unrestricted sover-
within a civil society and state. But Fukuyama and
eigns. The attainment of state sovereignty is indeed a
Doyle both realise that in a peaceful condition of the
great step forward in the development of the human
Kantian variety state sovereignty cannot play the
race, but it is not an absolutely valid arrangement. As
role it once did. Without clearly stating it both imply
Kant sees it, state sovereignty attains its proper
that the kind of unrestricted state sovereignty that
validity when it merges over into a wider interna-
once prevailed in international society has had its
tional sovereignty of free states. The splendid ma-
day.
31
jesty of the absolutely unrestricted sovereign state is an obstacle to world peace:
The Third Definitive Article
We look with profound contempt upon the way
One of the great virtues of democratic peace theory is
in which savages cling to their lawless freedom.
its moral egalitarianism. Each human individual for
They would rather engage in incessant strife than
the proponent of a democratic peace counts for as
submit to a legal constraint which they might
much as every other. Each individual, wherever they
impose upon themselves, for they prefer the free-
might live, is deserving of representation and of the
dom of folly to the freedom of reason. We regard
right to elect that representative. With Fukuyama
this as barbarism, coarseness, and brutish debase-
this moral egalitarianism is evident in his emphasis
ment of humanity. We might thus expect that
upon what he calls isothymia. Fukuyama defines the
civilised peoples, each united with itself as a state,
term in relation to its opposite megalothymia. This is
would hasten to abandon so degrading a condi-
the `desire to be recognised as superior to other
tion as soon as possible. But instead of doing so,
people', whereas `its opposite is isothymia, the desire
each state sees its own majesty (for it would be
to be recognised as the equal of other people.'
absurd to speak of the majesty of a people) pre-
thesis is that the world must change, and is changing,
cisely in not having to submit to any external
to a situation where each person lives under a system
32
His
legal constraint, and the glory of its ruler consists
of rule which fosters isothymia or equal recognition.
in his power to order thousands of people to
He sees this happening, however, mainly within
immolate themselves for a cause which does
states. As what he calls `the universal homogeneous
not truly concern them, while he need himself
state' becomes more widespread where such equal
not incur any danger whatsoever.
29
recognition is found this will have a beneficial effect upon peace and security amongst states. In drawing
Fukuyama also does not realise the extent to
this picture of extending worldwide equality Fukuya-
which Kant's Second Definitive Article implies a
ma's inspiration is Hegel who, in his conception of
critique of the traditional notions of state sovereignty
the state, properly develops the idea of mutual
and international law. Kant wants to rewrite the
democratic recognition.
rules of international society in a rational form
This is not incompatible with the Kantian per-
whereas Fukuyama is more concerned to point out
spective. However, it is important to bear in mind
how international society has already taken on a
that for Kant there is a moral equality which both
rational form. He tends as a consequence to cham-
historically and geographically extends beyond the
pion the changes Kant wants without fully realising
state. By definition human individuals, who are the
how difficult they might be to achieve. In keeping
only rational animals, are equal. It is an offence
with Kant, Fukuyama argues that `international law
against our dignity to treat another human indivi-
is merely domestic law writ large,'
30
dual or group as inherently unequal to us. In this
yet there is no
248
THE IDEA OF A LIBERAL-DEMOCRATIC PEACE
respect Doyle captures the spirit of Kant's philosophy
their own powers. They cannot extend their sover-
well. He sees that Kant's cosmopolitanism leads to a
eignty in such a way. Rather, they should look to the
different style of international politics from that to
host country to guarantee the property of their
which we are now accustomed. Kant's doctrine of
nationals while they are resident in those territories.
right would provide no grounds for the western
The civil order of a foreign state is primarily its own
imperial project of the modern world, or for any
responsibility. All other states can ask is that the
missionary intention forcefully to `civilise' non-wes-
liberty of their subjects should not be arbitrarily
tern countries. Kant rules out a patriarchal approach
limited.
to government both internally and externally.
33
The
development of societies outside Europe must possess
The Guarantee of Perpetual Peace
a voluntary dimension. Natives have to play a part themselves in drawing towards civilisation. The most
In one of the most interesting supplements to Per-
that European visitors can ask of the inhabitants of
petual Peace Kant outlines what he describes as a
territories they arrive in is that they not be treated
guarantee provided by `the great artist nature her-
with hostility. This point comes out in Doyle's
self'.
interpretation of the Third Definitive Article to
course of historical development tends in the direc-
Perpetual Peace. `Hospitality', says Doyle, `does not
tion of human improvement, often against our will.
require extending to foreigners either the right to
He cites a number of mechanisms that help to bring
citizenship or the right to settlement, unless the
this about such as our competitiveness, self-inter-
foreign visitors would perish if they were expelled.
ested pursuit of trade, the rivalry among nations and
Foreign conquest and plunder also find no justifica-
even war itself. Even when against our will, these
tion under this right.' Imperialism of any kind is ruled
forces can oblige us to enter into more peaceful
out. `Hospitality does appear to include the right of
relations with one another.
36
Here, he argues that the apparently unguided
access and the obligation of maintaining the oppor-
Both Doyle and Fukuyama cite this mechanism of
tunity for citizens to exchange goods and ideas with-
nature with approval. They commend Kant's guar-
out imposing the obligation to trade (a voluntary act
antee because it highlights an empirical process
in all cases under liberal constitutions).'
34
which can help underpin the liberal-democratic
Doyle argues that liberal states, despite their inter-
peace. For Doyle the guarantee works not because
nal liberal structures, have been prone to war with
we are politically moral beings but through our less
non-liberal societies. As he puts it, `the historical
agreeable side. Our desire for advantage over others
liberal legacy is laden with popular wars fought to
makes us into `asocial-sociable beings' who are just as
promote freedom, to protect private property, or to
much inclined to rivalry as cooperation with them.
support liberal allies against non-liberal enemies.'
35
Our paradoxical aim is to succeed in the eyes of
He suggests that Kant's position would be at odds
others but also at their expense. However, we learn
with this outcome. Partly, these wars have occurred
through sad experience that this is not the proper
because the leaders of liberal states have demanded
way to conduct human affairs. Under the pressure of
more than hospitality for their citizens and subjects
insecurity and actual war we learn the advantages of
in their relations with other states. In seeking to
republican government.
promote the freedom and advantage of visitors to
tory both through our good and our bad side. Doyle is
foreign territories they often have asked not simply
not quite sure how to handle this dialectical process.
for safe passage but that a certain form of life be
Whereas it might be argued that Kant is quite happy
respected which is contrary to native traditions. Kant
to see human short-sightedness and downright evil
believes we ought not to venture beyond peaceful
inadvertently playing a progressive role and this
persuasion in trying to advance the condition of
conflicting with the moral spirit within us, Doyle
other nationals in their own states. Similarly, liberal
wants us to unify the two moral forces. Those who
states are in no position to guarantee the property of
are entirely focused on their selfish interests are also
their nationals abroad simply through the exertion of
playing a moral role. With Doyle the `hidden plan' of
249
37
Progress can occur in his-
HOWARD WILLIAMS
38
However,
justify us from a moral standpoint pursuing progres-
with Kant the hidden plan steps in only where we
sive policies. Nature may help us some of the way but
fail in our moral duty. For him, the plan is not right
ultimately we have to choose to improve. Doyle and
in itself; rather it provides us with an incentive to do
Fukuyama tend to overlook the voluntary side of
what is right.
human progress which forms the essential part of
nature complements our moral duty.
This is a significant point. Kant argues that we
Kant's guarantee. Both Doyle and Fukuyama are
cannot depend on the guarantee from a theoretical
enthusiastic about the natural mechanism, especially
standpoint. In other words, if we view the guarantee
Fukuyama who devotes several passages in his writ-
as a scientific prediction we cannot expect it to come
ings to the economic, social and political forces that
true. As Kant puts it, `we cannot actually observe
drive us willy-nilly towards cooperation.
such an agency in the artifices of nature, nor can we
material acquisition under a free-market system re-
even infer its existence from them.'
39
40
Successful
However, the
quires long-term peace and security. According to
thesis possesses sufficient reality for us to entertain it
Fukuyama, a preoccupation with acquiring more
from a practical standpoint: from the moral point of
consumer goods diverts people away from aggressive
view we can assume it to make sense, at least
foreign policies and war. In keeping with Doyle and
sufficient sense for us to persist with a foreign policy
Fukuyama's interest in the determinist side of Kant's
based upon morality.
`hidden plan' the literature on democratic peace concentrates heavily on the empirical verifiability
We can rightly suppose that there are natural
41
mechanisms at work which promote the aim of
of the perpetual peace thesis.
lasting peace. Despite the expressed aims of less
entirely off the Kantian track, since the more em-
scrupulous political leaders and their subjects, we
pirical evidence for the thesis which exists the fewer
can discern over the longer term underlying trends
excuses there can be for refusing to seek progress in
which appear to be taking the human race forward.
external policy. However, in the light of Kant's
Perversely, war itself might further these trends by
priorities the emphasis is still a little one-sided.
bringing home to people the doleful effects of war-
His main purpose is to bring morality and politics
fare. Societies who engage in this aggressive beha-
into accord; only then will perpetual peace be
viour are forced to modernise quickly in order to
achieved. The actual past course of events naturally
employ the most modern means for engaging in war.
plays a key role in conditioning the present, but so
But this modernisation takes place with a concomi-
also must the intentions of policy-makers and those
tant growth in the potential and demand for freedom
they represent.
This may not take us
within the state. Self-interest is, above all, what brings the progressive mechanisms of war into play.
Conclusion
The hard-nosed pursuit of economic gain may have peaceful consequences. Although primarily moti-
What does our examination of the liberal-demo-
vated by the pursuit of profit those professionally
cratic peace thesis advanced by Doyle and Fukuyama
engaged in trade and commerce come to dislike the
from the standpoint of Kant's original peace theory
disruption caused by wars. Over the long term Kant
tell us? Our first conclusion might justifiably be that
thinks that business prefers peace to war.
there is more to Kant's original view than the
Kant realises that such projections about the
democratic peace theorists convey. There are ele-
progressive mechanism of history are not subject
ments in Kant's argument, such as his powerful
to clear empirical proof. There are countless events
objections to forcible intervention in the affairs of
which may tell in the opposite direction, but again
other states, his views on property rights and the use
no one can offer conclusive proof that the human
of national debt to finance war, which are not fully
race is bound not to improve. Kant's object is not to
considered. Just as Doyle and Fukuyama's new inter-
create sufficient certainty from a scientific stand-
pretations of Kant's thinking have uncovered many
point but rather sufficient certainty from a moral
valuable ideas we might legitimately claim that there
standpoint. He thinks there is enough evidence to
is even more to be discovered which might not only
250
THE IDEA OF A LIBERAL-DEMOCRATIC PEACE
add to the democratic peace thesis but also provide
Although Doyle stresses once again the peaceful
insights in other connected areas of politics. Classical
impetus brought about by overlapping economic
political theory, such as Kant's essay on Perpetual
interests,
Peace, provides a permanent source of new insight
be weighed against the ambiguous, if not entirely
into current national and international issues.
contrary, empirical evidence. It is true to say that
43
the optimistic Kantian picture has to
But such sources have always to be treated criti-
Kant was not depending on the world economic
cally. Kant would have himself emphasised that we
system automatically to bring about peace. His whole
have to judge what constitutes knowledge and un-
philosophy implies that there has to be an effort of
derstanding ourselves. There are no wholly reliable
will to overcome our previous bad habits. His point is
external authorities. Kant's political writings should
that the long-term contract ± upon which trade and
of course be treated with respect, but not slavishly
commerce rest ± cannot function without trust and a
followed. Doyle and Fukuyama are, each in their
sense of community. From an intelligible or logical
own way, critically receptive. I am not sure they go
standpoint war and trade are plainly at odds. But
far enough. For a second conclusion that we might
maybe Kant was not sufficiently alert to the way in
draw from our engagement with present and Kantian
which, in the short term, trade can in fact reinforce
peace theory is that just as where Kant seems correct
our bad habits. Empirically, the case for the moral
and affords insight so also where he seems mistaken
worth of unrestricted commerce is not a strong one.
he may equally lead us to think carefully and judge
There is an irony here in that contemporary
problems afresh. Two particular issues stand out as
democratic peace theory has strongly emphasised
obviously problematic in his account: (1) the exclu-
the empirical dimension of Kant's thinking. Above
sion of women from politically relevant roles; (2) his
all, the literature has concentrated on analysing the
apparently optimistic view of the role finance and
behaviour of states with constitutions approximating
trade (operating through self-interest) can play in
to the one recommended by Kant. Their conclusion
the forging of international peace.
is that in relation to each other such states behave
In terms of the first, it is clearly fair to say that,
well, but they do not tell us it is because of the
empirically, the facts run against Kant's position. We
convergence of economic interests of these states or
can say this not only in the sense that since the end
the peaceful intentions of their rulers. From a Kan-
of the eighteenth century most democratic republics
tian perspective, the main gap in the contemporary
of the Kantian variety have extended the franchise
literature is its tendency to under-emphasise the
to include women, but also in the more interesting
moral side of Kant's argument. Kant's allusion to
sense that the involvement of women in politics has
empirical developments is intended primarily to
tended to add to the peaceful tendencies of poli-
strengthen his moral argument rather than to pro-
ties.
42
Evidence seems to suggest that women are less
vide a knock-down proof. Those who require knock-
likely than men are to condone the use of violence to
down proof of the viability of the peace project
resolve international disputes. In terms of the sec-
before signing up to it are precisely those Kant
ond, it might be argued that the extension of trade
was not aiming to attract to his argument. His `pitch'
and financial interests in the international sphere
for perpetual peace is made to those who already
has seemingly had as many drawbacks as advantages.
have moral intentions in politics. The primary pre-
Nineteenth-century imperialism, which was some-
mise for the success of his argument is goodwill. The
times violent and rapacious, seems to have ridden on
liberal-democratic peace will work only for those
the back of financial and trade interests just as much
who aim to live in a morally regulated peace with
as it was restrained by them. The seeds of wars seem
others.
often to lie in conflicts of economic interests. There
Not surprisingly our comparison of peace theory
seems to be no shortage of interpretations of twen-
then and now leads us to the conclusion that there is
tieth-century armed conflicts which provide grounds
more to be said ± and much more in international
for hostilities in disputes over economic spheres of
politics itself that can be done ± to engender this
influence, markets and sources of raw materials.
goodwill, the basis of peace as theory and practice.
251
HOWARD WILLIAMS
Notes
1. Layne (1994).
27. Kant (1991), p. 105.
2. Doyle (1983a), (1983b), (1986).
28. Doyle (1986), p. 1158.
3. Doyle (1986), p. 1151.
29. Kant (1991), pp. 102±3.
4. Ibid.
30. Fukuyama (1992), p. 281.
5. See Hegel (1969), pp. 213±17 and also Avineri
31. This is a fairly striking example from Fukuyama
(1972), chapters 3, 4. Jonathan Seglow's chapter in
(1992), p. 283: `The United States and other liberal
the present volume also explores the notion of `re-
democracies will have to come to grips with the fact
cognition' as a concern for liberal political theory.
that, with the collapse of the communist world, the
6. Fukuyama (1992), pp. 49±50.
world in which we live is less and less the old one of
7. Ibid., p. 48.
geopolitics, and that the rules and methods of the
8. Ibid., p. 283.
historical world are not appropriate to life in the post-
9. Ibid., p. 281.
historical one. For the latter, the major issues will be
10. Kant (1991), pp. 108±14.
economic ones like promoting competitiveness and
11. Fukuyama (1992), p. 283.
innovation, managing internal and external deficits,
12. Doyle (1986), p. 1156.
maintaining full employment, dealing co-operatively
13. Fukuyama (1992), p. 281.
with grave environmental politics, and the like.'
14. Kant (1991), p. 101.
What might be said from a Kantian perspective is
15. Ibid., p. 101.
that rulers should have attempted to overcome geo-
16. `By republican Kant means a political society that has
politics just as much before the collapse of communism as after it.
solved the problem of combining moral autonomy, individualism and social order. A private property and
32. Fukuyama (1992), p. 182.
market-oriented economy partially addressed that di-
33. Cf. Williams (1983), pp. 129±37.
lemma in the private sphere. The public, or political
34. Doyle (1986), p. 1158.
sphere was more troubling. His answer was a republic
35. Ibid., p. 1160.
that preserved juridical freedom ± the legal equality of
36. Kant (1991), p. 108.
citizens as subjects ± on the basis of a representative
37. Doyle (1983a), p. 225.
government with a separation of powers. Juridical
38. Doyle (1986), p. 1159.
freedom is preserved because the morally autonomous
39. Kant (1991), p. 109. Contrary to Doyle's view the
individual is by means of representation a self-legis-
supposition of progress in history is primarily a kind of
lator making laws that apply to all citizens equally,
heuristic device (Doyle, 1986, p. 1159) ± but a
including himself or herself. Tyranny is avoided be-
heuristic device with a practical rather than theoretical importance.
cause the individual is subject to laws he or she does
40. Fukuyama (1992), especially chapters 1, 5 and 6.
not also administer.' Doyle (1986), p. 1158.
41. Cf. Oneal and Ray (1997) and Mansfield and Snyder
17. Kant (1991), p. 101. 18. Cf. Saage (1973), pp. 83±93; Kersting (1993), p. 382.
(1995). Note the conclusion of the second article: `In
19. Doyle (1986), p. 1156.
the long run, the enlargement of the zone of stable
20. Ibid., p. 1156.
democracy will probably enhance the prospects for
21. See Russett (1995), p. 168.
peace. But in the short run, there is a lot to be done to
22. Kant (1991), p. 104.
minimise the dangers of the turbulent transition' (p. 38).
23. Doyle (1986), p. 1158. Cf. Doyle (1983a), p. 226.
42. Lisa Brandes, Public Opinion, International Security and
24. Doyle (1983a), p. 225. 25. Ibid., p. 227.
Gender: The United States and Britain Since 1945, Yale
26. This is my own translation; cf. Kant (1991), p. 102:
University PhD dissertation, 1994. Cited in Russett (1995), p. 167f.
`The Right of Nations shall be based upon a Federa-
43. Doyle (1986), p. 1161.
tion of Free States.'
252
19
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY: LIBERAL THEORY, DEVELOPMENTAL COMMUNITARIANISM AND INTERNATIONAL ETHICS Peter Sutch
That these currents are present in liberal interna-
Introduction
tional theory is highlighted in the recent critical 1
This chapter offers a reading of liberalism's normative
work on John Rawls's contribution to the debate.
theory of international politics. As the ideology of the
Rawls's international relations theory is often viewed
dominant powers in the recent history of interna-
as falling between a rock and a hard place. He is
tional politics and as the theoretical substructure that
either a failed liberal universalist who dilutes human
underpins the claim that human rights should be the
rights in order to accommodate statism or a failed
guiding force in the future development of interna-
communitarian who relies upon covert liberal as-
tional relations, liberalism undeniably forms a vital
sumptions in order to make international politics
part of the world order. In trying to determine whether
and justice compatible. One of the principal sources
the expansion and (to use a very popular liberal
of this interpretation is mainstream liberal interna-
characterisation of the process) ultimate universalisa-
tional relations theory;
tion of a liberal human rights culture really is a move
part, the hostile reaction to (or, more often, the
towards international justice as liberals claim, an
sheer unwillingness to engage with) Rawls's ideas or
exploration of the way in which this process is justified
with the ideas of those thinkers who take a similar
in contemporary theory offers some very interesting
approach to questions of international justice.
2
perhaps this explains, in
insights. In particular, in this chapter it becomes clear
In exploring contemporary liberal international
that there are two distinct traditions in contemporary
relations theory, this chapter falls into two parts.
liberal international theory: the cosmopolitan strand
First, I want to suggest that the dominant liberal
which has been traditionally attributed to liberalism
response to developments in world politics and
and a more particularistic norm-governed approach
international relations theory does not adequately
which is derived from liberalism's often hidden, non-
show why international justice must be cosmopolitan
Kantian (occasionally ex-Kantian) ancestry.
in character.
253
3
My principal concern is that the
PETER SUTCH
constructivist move from the requirement that prin-
account of the way it constructs or portrays inter-
ciples of ethics be universalisable to the requirement
national community. In doing so it must relinquish
that principles of ethics be cosmopolitan is incom-
or radically reconstruct some of liberalism's most
plete. What is missing is an appropriate conception
prized goals. My reasons for making this argument
of international community. I will then propose that
stem from several sources: firstly, a belief that the
the more cautious reaction of what I will term (in
justifications that liberals are obliged to construct for
order to make a clear distinction between the types
their theory are not strong enough to ignore the facts
of liberal theory on offer) the constructivist and
of pluralism in international politics; secondly, an
developmental communitarianism of thinkers such
uneasiness with the cosmopolitan-liberal assumption
as Frost,
4
5
offers the invaluable
that sovereignty ± one of the political cornerstones of
link between international politics and constructi-
international relations ± is antithetical or irrelevant
vist liberal theory that the liberal tradition needs if it
to justice; and thirdly, my belief that the assumption
is to take account of the problems and possibilities
that sovereignty is hostile to concepts such as human
Rawls and Walzer
posed to it by the extension of its concerns into the
rights which are thought by definition both universal
international
of
and cosmopolitan in character is obscuring a very
Frost, the communitarian liberalism of Walzer and
fruitful seam in liberal international relations theory.
arena.
The
Hegelian
liberalism
the political liberalism of Rawls promise a genuine
One of the most theoretically complete examples
alternative to cosmopolitanism by (as Brown writing
of constructivist cosmopolitanism is to be found in
about the position of Frost notes) `starting from the
the work of Onora O'Neill.
position that the value that people and states quite
latest and arguably the most sustainable form of
clearly do assign to sovereignty cannot simply be
theoretical
dismissed as the product of defective powers of
Her insistence that approaches such as those of
reasoning or some kind of persisting mass hallucina-
Walzer and Rawls are neither liberal nor just gives
tion.'
6
justification
7
for
It comprises both the international
justice.
my choice of her work as the example of liberal international relations theory particular pertinence. Here I intend to outline the three main claims
Constructivist Cosmopolitanism:
motivating O'Neill's argument to highlight construc-
Contemporary Liberal Internationalism
tivist cosmopolitanism's basic position. While this
Contemporary liberal international relations theory
cannot do justice to its sophistication, this exercise is
can best be described as `constructivist cosmopoli-
useful because it shows how the cosmopolitan out-
tanism'. Theoretically it is constructivist, showing
look can be maintained within a constructivist jus-
the influence of liberalism's engagement with con-
tificatory strategy. The claims are as follows:
temporary debates in political philosophy. Politically it is cosmopolitan in that it maintains that the projects it has inherited from its Kantian origins still
1. The basis of any theory of international pol-
represent the only practical liberal solution to the
itics must be relevant to all parties concerned;
moral problems of international politics. There is
that is, the premises of international relations
nothing particularly surprising about this opening
theory must be universalisable across the re-
statement. The extension of liberal values and prac-
levant domain.
8
tices to international relations is rarely regarded as
2. The actual circumstances of justice and injus-
anything other than an absolute good, yet there is
tice in the modern world (understood by
nothing in constructivist liberal political theory that
looking at the assumptions that agents make
requires or necessarily underwrites cosmopolitan in-
when acting) are more-or-less cosmopolitan in
ternational relations theory. In this chapter I suggest
scope.
9
that a successful constructivist liberalism (hereafter
3. Those theories that acknowledge the theore-
simply `liberalism'), if it is to produce a political
tical relevance of borders (sovereign, commu-
theory suited to world politics, must take proper
nal or moral) are inadequate.
254
10
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
From these, O'Neill concludes that constructivist
responsibilities to non-citizens cannot automatically 13
cosmopolitanism is the only valid option. Now in
outweigh an appeal to justice.'
the cause of brevity `cosmopolitanism' as a political
O'Neill call the legitimacy of such boundaries into
theory can be usefully explained via Thomas Pogge's
question? Essentially, she does so by suggesting that
description of its core elements. He thinks that three
the requirement that practical reason be universali-
elements are shared by all cosmopolitan positions:
sable plus the fact that we are connected to all other
But how does
agents on a more-or-less cosmopolitan scale requires First, individualism: the ultimate units of concern
a cosmopolitan approach to international politics.
are human beings, or persons ± rather than, say,
The `either-justice-or-sovereignty'
argument has
family lines, tribes, ethnic, cultural or religious
been one of the principal reasons why liberal ideal-
communities, nations or states. The latter may be
ism (as it is often termed) now has little support in
units of concern only indirectly, in virtue of their
the study and practice of international politics. The
individual members or citizens. Second, univers-
alternative form of liberal international relations
ality: the status of ultimate unit of concern at-
theory that I wish to outline is, I shall argue, appro-
taches
to
every
living
human
being
priately universalist but not cosmopolitan ± and, as
universally . . . Third, generality: this special
such, seems to make more sense of both our actual
status has global force. Persons are ultimate units
commitments in world politics and the liberal drive
of concern for everyone ± not only for their fellow
for justice.
compatriots, fellow religionists, or such like.
11
Universalisability and Cosmopolitanism
This quotation is particularly interesting because of the description of universality that Pogge offers. It is
The flip-side of my position is that, of O'Neill's three
not simply a depiction of formal universality. The
claims, only the first is truly stable. Its stability comes
individualism
from its constructivist methodological basis and, to
and generality are incorporated into the description
advance the overall argument, we should now grasp
of moral universalism. This (sleight of hand?) is char-
the meaning of `constructivism', a vital part of con-
acteristic of much liberal international relations the-
temporary liberalism's armour, in this context. To
ory. My concern here is to ensure that this fact does not
construct a political theory is to avoid reliance upon
go unnoticed and to examine the pattern of argument
discredited metaphysics, or contested truth-claims,
that allows (or purports to allow) cosmopolitan the-
or the revealed word of one culture's prophets, and
orists to link the formal criterion of moral universali-
thus to avoid the criticisms of foundationalist reason-
sability with the liberal-cosmopolitan political project.
ing that many fear threatened the paralysis of justi-
What is instructive about O'Neill's theory is that its
ficatory
goal is to lay out fully the predicates of her thesis and to
simple case for theoretical constructivism in ethics
show the validity of her reasoning in so doing.
is that the reasons we give for selecting principles of
substantive
liberal
commitments
to
political
philosophy.
O'Neill's
elegantly
international ethics must be relevant to all con-
So let me state my reading of O'Neill's work
cerned parties. For her:
boldly. My principal contention is that claims two and three in her argument, which are not (in my 12
illicitly `construct' the con-
Constructivism in ethics . . . is not a novel
ception of international community which allows
philosophical method or procedure. To construct
O'Neill to suggest that principles of practical reason
is only to reason with all possible solidity from
must be universalisable and cosmopolitan. The po-
available beginnings, using available and followable
litical core of O'Neill's cosmopolitanism (and that of
methods to reach attainable and sustainable con-
liberal international relations theory more generally)
clusions for relevant audiences.
opinion) defensible,
14
is the claim that `once the legitimacy of treating actual state boundaries has been called into question,
The key to understanding O'Neill's work is the idea
an appeal to sovereignty or to assumed lack of
that principles of ethics must be accessible to the
255
PETER SUTCH
`relevant audiences'. O'Neill's case, put simply, is
allowed to pretend that all the world is a liberal
that any stretch of reason that cannot appeal to all
utopia but neither are we allowed to pretend that
relevant agents and is therefore not universal in its
there are no ethical and political issues that we
domain cannot be called `reasoned'. She goes on to
genuinely share and that constitute the context of
show that, of the various conceptions of practical
our actions. So to generate genuinely shared reason-
reasoning offered by many universalist and particu-
ing, one must operate with premises that are based
larist thinkers, most do not meet even this basic
upon considerations abstracted from agents' actual
standard. Arguments that employ `end-oriented' rea-
situations, accessible to all because they really do
soning, such as that used by `platonist' thinkers who
apply to all.
provide a conception of a specific, independently
The question now is whether constructivism sup-
specified good `end' as being ultimately the purpose
ports cosmopolitan universalism. There are, O'Neill
of agents' actions, will appear arbitrary unless the
claims, two senses in which principles may be for-
appropriate metaphysics is universally validated (ex-
mally universal. The most elementary is if a principle
tremely implausible in the light of the apparent
`applies to or holds for all rather than merely for some
diversity of human ends). Instrumental reasoning
cases in its domain.' The second sense is where `the
(again end-oriented) will appear `barefacedly' arbi-
range of beings is seen as extensive: the scope of
trary to those who do not share its contestably
principles is inclusive, perhaps (more-or-less) cosmo-
subjective
politan.'
conception
of
practical
reason's goal.
16
Even `act-oriented' reasoning (theorising the re-
Of these senses of universalism, the first definition
quirements of action without reference to any spe-
is relevant to O'Neill's case that all those agents
cific end towards which it may be directed) of the
concerned must (potentially) be able to agree that
particularist variety (communitarian norm-oriented)
the principles of practical reason adopted are rele-
would appear incomprehensible to `outsiders' (those
vant to them in their shared condition. This, it must
alien to the particular context) even when those
be noted, does not tell us which agents are concerned
`outsiders' fall within the relevant sphere of action.
15
by what problem in any particular domain. The
Remember that all O'Neill is claiming here is that
second feature is yet to be proven relevant, relying
principles have to meet the requirement that they
upon a heavily contested empirical and theoretical
could be universalised to cover all relevant others.
notion of how agents are meaningfully connected to
Her blanket rejection of all end-oriented and source-
one another across the globe. Indeed, it appears to
derived conceptions of practical reason does not (on
rely upon a liberal individualist conception of agency
the strength of arguments made thus far) have to be
that does not actually derive (and cannot be derived)
accepted, but the requirement that they have to be
from O'Neill's constructivism. This can be shown, I
accessible to all concerned does. O'Neill argues that it
believe, by applying J. L. Mackie's questions con-
is vital that we develop intelligible and abstract
cerning the status of ethics and universality to
principles of action that can avoid the problems of
O'Neill's argument.
17
relativism and idealisation. Here, `relativism' and
Taking issue with the philosophical requirement
`idealisation' are key notions in understanding the
that practical reason be universalisable, it is clear
failure of much international and political theory.
that O'Neill is suggesting we must focus upon what is
The main conclusions from her brief survey of con-
morally relevant and discount those aspects of our
temporary thought are that particularistic relativism
lives that are `arbitrary' in some way. For her, local
cannot adequately provide for the modern circum-
and bounded traditions and practices are examples of
stances of justice and that much universalist writing
such arbitrariness and fall far short of the require-
appears arbitrary in that it relies upon idealised
ment of practical reason because they do not and
starting points. The simple case being made here
cannot take adequate account of all relevant and
is that, in accepting that foundational universalism
connected others (the links between agents across
idealises (makes up) its ethical starting point, we are
such particularised contexts). This follows, she main-
not required to endorse relativism. We are not
tains, from the logical structure of moral reasoning
256
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
itself and not from some substantive, idealising lib-
structure of ethics. Rather, she is insisting that
eral-cosmopolitan standpoint. I do not believe that
accounts of ethics that do not give ethical priority
this is the case. Following Mackie's seminal line of
to individuals are subordinate to her cosmopolitan
reasoning here is particularly enlightening. He be-
conception of ethics which clearly does. This is not a
gins by posing the same question as O'Neill (albeit in
justifiable
a different form), but when he explores the logical
O'Neill's claim is that particularist practices, value
structure of moral reasoning he comes to a very
systems and politics are morally irrelevant, that the
different conclusion.
treatment of (for example) non-Muslims in a funda-
position
for
a
constructivist
to
hold.
mentalist Muslim state and in a liberal state are Do the desires and especially the sufferings of
relevantly similar. This argument employs all three
other people, if known to me, constitute a reason
stages of universalisation and, while it may be in-
for me to do something, if I can, or try to do
tuitively powerful it is, as Mackie points out, a
something to satisfy those desires or to relieve
peculiarly liberal stance.
21
those sufferings? It would be natural to say that
The crucial point to note here is that what is
they constitute some reason; how strong a reason,
hidden by the phrase `relevantly similar' is the con-
how easily over-ruled by other considerations,
struction or portrayal of the international political
may be a matter of dispute.
18
arena. O'Neill does not make enough of her recognition that `connection will peter out at differing boundaries for different agents and in activities of
For Mackie, moral judgements are universalisable:
22
any truly moral statement concerning an action is
differing sorts in different circumstances.'
nonsensical if it cannot hold for any relevantly similar
in order to underpin her cosmopolitanism O'Neill
action. As he notes, the key to understanding the logic
claims that neither particularism nor Rawlsian lib-
of morality is the idea of `relevantly similar';
19
Rather,
he goes
eralism can provide principles relevant to the mod-
on to argue convincingly that there are three stages of
ern circumstances of justice. Her principal claim is
universalisation that attempt to account for it. It is
that the modes of existence they privilege are not
worth quoting him at some length here:
accessible, and cannot adapt to become accessible, to all relevant agents in world politics. For O'Neill,
There are . . . different kinds or stages of uni-
anything less than an individual-centred, cosmopo-
versalisation. In each of them a moral judgement
litan conception of agency would be so restrictive
is taken to carry with it a similar view about any
that it simply could not generate principles of ethics
relevantly similar case. But the first stage rules out
that relate to the world as we know it. This critique
as irrelevant only the numerical difference be-
of non-cosmopolitan reasoning relies upon her argu-
tween one individual and another; the second
ment that we can abstract from all the contingencies
stage rules out generic differences which one is
and detail of political pluralism to a core of shared
tempted to regard as morally relevant only be-
reasoning.
cause of one's particular mental or physical qua-
are in fact connected to all other human individuals
lities or condition, one's social status or resources;
as individuals (and not as, say, citizens of a state) are,
the third stage rules out differences which answer
though, highly contestable.
23
Both this claim and the claim that we
to particular tastes, preferences, values and ideals.
For O'Neill, the constructivist projects (that she
It is at most the first stage . . . that is built into
convincingly shows to be necessary) share a common
the meaning of moral language: the correspond-
aim. It is `in the end no more, but also no less, than
ing logical thesis about the second stage is more
an attempt to work towards a result that is neither
controversial, while that about the third stage
unattainable for those whose lives are both led using
would be plainly false.
20
the categories and norms of restricted milieu and connected to those of others with differing categories and norms, nor unsustainable for what they could
If this argument holds, and I believe it does, then
become.'
O'Neill is not merely outlining the necessary logical
257
24
However, I believe that the more limited
PETER SUTCH
projects of developmental communitarianism take
having chosen the term. The `communitarian/norm-
more than satisfactory account of this aim. In doing
oriented method' of these thinkers is not an argu-
so, they can avoid O'Neill's criticism of particularism
ment about the essential primacy of community over
and build a bridge between the Westphalian, state-
the individual but of the justice or injustice of the
centric system of international politics and liberal
dominance of certain principles of international
international relations theory, thus making the latter
politics. Their disagreement with liberal-cosmopoli-
consistent with the realities of international politics
tanism does not focus upon the notion of universa-
and its development.
lisability but on the idea of the `relevantly similar'. In this regard, denying the reality of claims to sovereignty, self-determination or human rights does not
Introducing Developmental
make sense of international politics. To argue, for
Communitarianism: Constructing
example, that sovereign borders and the rights of
an International Community
citizenship hinder the cause of international justice
I now wish to present three examples of the devel-
assumes that we are justified in including a strong
opmental communitarian method in international
notion of transnational community in our theory.
relations theory. One of the principal advantages of
The strong abstraction necessary to make this argu-
developmental communitarianisms is that they begin
ment is not thought to be warranted. Rather, argue
their constructivist projects by attempting to con-
the developmental communitarians, we may abstract
struct a viable image of international community ± of
to the existent plurality of political communities and
the `relevantly similar'. Although I cannot provide a
to the consensus upon principles of international
full account of the conclusions of Frost, Walzer and
justice implicit in the actions and norms they share.
Rawls, I do want to demonstrate some of the reason-
We can go on to show how important the norms of
ing behind their positions. Not only do they offer a
human rights and other liberal principles are to the
construction of ethical principles, they also provide
existence of international politics only if this fact is
an account of how these principles become valued by
clearly an uncontested assumption of world politics.
the actors in world politics. This second task is a vital
This distinction makes a significant difference to
aspect of their constructivist project because it re-
claims to have legitimately reached broadly liberal
fuses to assume that the first principles of practical
principles of international justice. Indeed, as earlier
reason have moral and political validity regardless of
demonstrated, it is hard to see how O'Neill's theory
all other considerations yet it still maintains (con-
can reach the cosmopolitan conclusions she does
trary to O'Neill's opinion) the theoretical where-
without the aid of some strong liberal assumptions.
withal to condemn injustice in world politics.
The limited conclusions of the developmental com-
I have chosen to label Frost, Walzer and Rawls as
munitarians seem more suited to the realities of the
`developmental communitarians' for two primary
pluralistic-yet-connected world. The liberalism of
reasons. Firstly, I wish to stress how far removed
Walzer, Rawls and, to a more limited extent, Frost
are the justifications of their liberal ideas from those
is a conclusion rather than an assumption and it is
of liberal cosmopolitanism. Cosmopolitan liberals
this fact, one that results from their general method,
believe, as noted in the previous section, that the
that marks them off from traditional liberal and
first principles of liberalism should apply to all in-
cosmopolitan theory.
dividuals irrespective of their historical and political situation. For the developmental communitarians,
Frost: Social Norms and Human Rights
however, the justifications of the first principles of liberalism are themselves contingent upon history,
The basic tension in contemporary liberal interna-
upon consensus or the shared development of a
tional relations theory is portrayed with appealing
background justification for the principles of inter-
clarity in Frost's Ethics in International Relations,
national politics. This I believe to be a vital point,
which charts the development of the norms of
and one which feeds into the second reason for my
sovereignty,
258
human
rights
and
democratisation.
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
For Frost, the starting point for an analysis of inter-
eral theorists are right to suggest that `it may be
national politics is the `modern state domain of
argued that the primary question for a normative
discourse', an image of contemporary practices that
theory of international relations is whether the system
makes a realistic attempt to construct international
of sovereign states is a justifiable way of organising
community by recognising the tensions between the
the government of the world.' Yet he recognises that:
remnants of the Westphalian order and a postWestphalian system.
25
He explains these tensions
On reflection, what is striking about the foregoing
by referring to the settled norms that are shared within
list is the primacy of the first two items on the list.
this practice. He lists those norms that he considers
Most of the other settled goods are in some way
within the modern state domain of discourse under
derivatives of them . . . Thus any satisfactory
the subheadings `sovereignty' norms (S), `interna-
background theory will have to justify the settled
tional law' norms (L), `modernisation' norms (M)
belief that the preservation of a system of sover-
and `domestic' norms (D). Summarising them, Frost
eign states is a good.
28
claims that that the following goods have the status of `settled':
Frost's general approach to the philosophy of international ethics, one that coheres with the cen-
S1. The preservation of the society of states.
tral tensions of contemporary international relations
S2. State sovereignty.
theory outlined above, really gets to the heart of the
S3. Anti-imperialism.
matter. He recognises that in order to follow the
S4. The balance of power.
cosmopolitan line of reasoning one must question
S5. Patriotism.
the settled status of S1 ± and for Frost so much in
S6. Protecting the interests of a state's citizens.
international politics only makes sense in relation to
S7. Non-intervention.
S1 that to reject its importance would be to radically
S8. Self-determination.
misunderstand
L1. International law.
tions.
L2. Ius ad bellum.
the
nature
of
international
rela-
29
The central point of Frost's position could easily
L3. Ius in bello.
be misread as pleading a conservative case with the
L4. Collective security.
correlative argument that it is never going to be
L5. Economic sanctions (under specified circum-
possible to challenge the settled status of S1. How-
stances).
ever, a more generous reading ± and one that Frost's
L6. The diplomatic system.
more recent articulations of his theory appears to
M1. Modernisation.
endorse
M2. Economic cooperation.
making any theoretical transition of norms justified
D1. Democratic institutions within states.
in reference to S1 to a system of norms justified (for
D2. Human rights.
26
30
± would argue that it is more a case of
example) in reference to D2 compatible with a practical (and just) transition from a world organised
The first step in Frost's procedure for looking into the
around S1 to a world organised around D2. Captur-
background for the modern state domain of discourse
ing this transition, rather than defining and defend-
is to start with what everybody knows. Essentially,
ing the old international order or the potential
this process leads to the creation of the above list of
transnational order, would seem to be a vital task,
settled norms. It is important to remember that this
vital because it would be inappropriate to build an
seemingly comprehensive list is (or could be) made
ethical theory suited only to an imagined or inde-
up of some strikingly different conceptions of what
fensible theory of international politics.
each of the norms calls for. It is also quite clear that
The resources within the developmental commu-
there is a certain `tension' between those goods that
nitarian tradition of liberal theory are well suited to
concern sovereignty and those that concern the
this task. The work of thinkers such as Walzer and
rights of individual persons.
27
Rawls has advantages over much cosmopolitan and
Frost argues that lib-
259
PETER SUTCH
communitarian writing. Their work is constructivist
cerned to explore precisely those problems faced by
in that it attempts to avoid the difficulties of philo-
international relations theory today. The liberalism
sophical foundationalism while actively combating
that Rawls transplants from his Political Liberalism is a
the ethical scepticism that is often seen as a con-
political mechanism for dealing with the question of
sequence of foundationalism's crisis in theoretical
pluralism in international politics and examines the
justification. It therefore attempts to theorise inter-
guiding concepts of international relations theory,
national politics on premises that are both philoso-
testing their legitimacy in the face of prevailing
phically secure and able to be the object of some kind
conditions of world politics. Similarly, the perceived
of consensus among the plurality of international
difficulties in Walzer's work have led to an insuffi-
actors. Such an approach, combined with a focus on
cient examination of some very interesting ideas.
the competing claims of sovereignty and universal
Walzer's work is either viewed as statist, commu-
rights, would suggest that their ideas really should
nitarian and therefore relativist, or as failing even
demand the close attention of international relations
these standards and relying on covert and illegiti-
theory.
mate liberal principles. His use of `universal rights to life and liberty' has attracted more than their fair
Rather than pursue Frost's reading of contemporary international relations theory here,
31
share of criticism.
I wish to
32
However, his reworking of his
turn to a brief examination of the work of Rawls and
`minimalist morality' and its subsequent portrayal as
Walzer which, I maintain, follows a similar theore-
`reiterative universalism' as opposed to `covering law
tical pattern to Frost's. For Rawls, this theoretical
universalism' gets right to the heart of contemporary
and political process would, over time, lead the
international relations theory.
actors in the international sphere to realise indepen-
son why Rawls and Walzer are treated variously as
dently that toleration of reasonable pluralism is the
failed universalists or failed particularists is because
chief virtue in international ethics. This realisation
the aim of reconciling political life within an inter-
(in the most optimistic interpretation of Rawls's `Law
national system with an emerging global politics is
of Peoples') would lead to the move from the modus
inadequately conceptualised.
33
The principal rea-
vivendi of international law to a fully overlapping
Interestingly, O'Neill herself criticises non-cosmo-
consensus on the value of toleration and thus to a
politan liberal theory ± and particularly that of Rawls
new understanding of human rights suited to liberal-
and Walzer ± on many points. The most important
ism at the turn of the millennium. In Walzer's less
here are her claim that Rawls can only make his law
confident brand of developmental communitarian-
of peoples attack crucial problems in world politics
ism this process would lead (at the very best) to a
by relying (covertly) upon idealised liberal assump-
shared understanding (and, more optimistically, a
tions about human agency and the suggestion (aimed
shared articulation) of a `moral minimum' which
at Walzer and MacIntyre) that any contemporary
could again equip liberalism with a normative stand-
international political theory that takes account of
point capable of tackling contemporary global chal-
pluralism when constructing an account of ethical
lenges.
universality is doomed to inaccessibility and thus political irrelevance. The idea, common to liberal literature, is that only a cosmopolitan account of
Rawls and Walzer:
universality provides principles of international jus-
Consensus and Reiteration
tice. However, the developmental communitarian
Rawls's Amnesty lecture `The Law of Peoples' (here-
account of universality offered by Walzer and Rawls
after: LOP) is often taken as an incomplete expres-
is not rendered ineffectual by its reliance upon norm-
sion of ideas that have their roots firmly in liberal
governed rather than a priori Kantian principles of
political culture. It is therefore viewed as tangential
practical reason and it does not rely upon concealed
to the needs of international relations. Nothing
liberal assumptions to construct a useful theory of
could be further from the truth. Originally entitled
international justice. In particular Rawls, in moving
`Constructivism and Universality' the essay is con-
towards the communitarian camp in an attempt to
260
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
construct a conception of the relevantly similar and
shift towards a communitarian position. For Rawls,
in modifying his Kantian predicates to make the
even though
liberal criterion of universality a realistic require-
politics is characterised by a plurality of reasonable
ment in political theory, avoids both these criticisms
yet incompatible social systems (what he terms the
and develops a redefined liberal international rela-
`fact' of reasonable pluralism), human rights, or a
tions theory.
version of that doctrine, can ± and should ± be
(or perhaps because) international
O'Neill's case against Rawls is that his famous use
supported by any legitimate state. We must remem-
of the modifier `reasonable' in relation to the fact of
ber that Rawls believes that the background condi-
pluralism illegitimately assists the work of his theory
tions are central to the construction of any principles
of justice. This, however, is not the case. At the most
of justice. The spur, if any, to greater cooperation or
basic level in Rawlsian constructivism there is a
to justice in world politics must be seen to stem from
division between the Kantian and communitarian
world politics itself and not from Rawls's liberal
elements of his thought. For example, the regulative
position. For this reason, he reconstructs the idea
role of what Rawls calls Kant's theory of `constitutive
of human rights and its role in liberal international
autonomy' is abandoned in favour of the political
relations theory.
value of a shared public life.
34
In separating his
For Rawls,
constructivism from Kant's `deeper', comprehensive approach, Rawls notes that `the full significance of a
The fact of reasonable pluralism is not an un-
constructivist political conception lies in its connec-
fortunate condition of human life, as we might say
tion with the fact of reasonable pluralism.'
35
A
of pluralism as such, allowing for doctrines that
recognition of the importance of this `fact' means
are not only irrational but mad and aggressive. In
that the in-built cosmopolitan universalism of con-
framing a political conception of justice so it can
stitutive autonomy is replaced by the notion of what
gain an overlapping consensus, we are not bend-
Rawls calls `doctrinal autonomy, a conception that
ing it to existing unreason, but to the fact of
gives full weight to the autonomy of all `appropriate
reasonable pluralism, itself the outcome of the
conceptions of society and the person.'
36
free exercise of human reason under conditions of
Here,
liberty.
Rawls rejects the notion that constructivism should
39
provide universality (for which read cosmopolitanism) from the start.
37
The analytic idea of the
The idea implicit in the emerging political culture of
reasonable links a very thin conception of practical
international society is that societies capable of
reason with the idea of the relevantly similar, and
international cooperation are already contributing,
tells us how and why peoples may enter into the
and will continue to develop a workable system of
political process in international politics. For Rawls
human rights. The recognition that a plurality of
an appropriate account of practical reason allied to a
states, some comprehensively liberal, some politi-
norm-governed framework (the construction of the
cally so, and some non-liberal or hierarchical can
relevantly similar) provides `both the form that
(and do) share political principles informs the inter-
practical reason requires for its application . . .
national ethics of Rawls and Walzer.
[and] the context in which practical questions and
them believes that there exists an international
problems arise.'
38
40
Neither of
The idea of the reasonable ensures
consensus sufficiently robust to ground a cosmopo-
that the conception of agency we use in our con-
litan or egalitarian human rights project. Neverthe-
struction is accessible to all in the relevant domain.
less both thinkers agree that a `minimal' conception
It is precisely because Rawls must take account of all
of universal rights plays an important role in world
appropriate accounts of agency that he believes the
politics. In trying to reconcile human rights and
cosmopolitan project to be insecure and he thus
pluralism, Rawls argues in favour of the develop-
focuses upon peoples as politically organised rather
mental potential of a constitutional (political) con-
than as individual agents. This move towards a
sensus and Walzer for a minimalist morality formed
particularist stance is indicative of Rawls's general
out of repeated encounters with international pro-
261
PETER SUTCH
blems. For Walzer `the value of minimalism lies in
the institutions of justice. Beyond modus vivendi exist
the encounters it facilitates, of which it is also a
conditions of society which, if the forms of consensus
product. But these encounters are not ± not now at
(constitutional or ideally overlapping) occur, offer
least ± sufficiently sustained to produce a thick
the possibility of a greater transnational interaction.
morality.'
41
Similarly for Rawls the value of inter-
It is interesting to see how Rawls cashes out the
national justice stems from a consensus on a need to
relationship between the idea of stability and the
fix the political situation and put issues of justice
differing forms of consensus in his international
beyond particularist interest, not upon any consensus
relations theory. Human rights, in Rawls's ideal
strong enough to underwrite cosmopolitanism.
portrayal of a liberal international society, represent
For Rawls the basic principles of the law of peoples
a `thick' conception of rights founded upon speci-
that have evolved historically as a modus vivendi are
fically liberal ideas. They signify that each person is
unsurprisingly traditional. But the key to Rawls's
`assigned a certain status, the status of members of
project in LOP lies in his reworking of his seventh
some society who possess rights as human persons.'
principle,
human
Yet human rights in the fully extended law of
The empirical claim that since The Second
peoples represent a `minimum standard of well-
World War human rights have been on the agenda
ordered political institutions for all peoples who
of international relations theory is supplemented by a
belong, as members in good standing, to a just
justification of their prominence, as for Rawls the
political society of peoples.'
existence of liberal/cosmopolitan human rights is
that much of international society does not hold a
unstable in the sense that it lacks the normative
western individualist conception of the person and
justification
therefore assigns rights differently, and this fact
rights.'
42
sphere.
43
that
`peoples
are
appropriate
to
to
honour
46
the
international
alters
The idea of justification that Rawls applies
his
discussion
of
47
Rawls is acutely aware
stability
and
consensus.
to international relations is modelled on that found
The form of consensus reached between liberal
in Lecture IV of his Political Liberalism and he
and non-liberal states is likely to be analogous to
completes his sketch of a law of peoples by arguing
the
for two further conditions that lend normative and
Liberalism where
idea
of
constitutional
consensus
in
Political
practical stability to his project. The first of these two conditions is that the international order should be
a constitution satisfying certain basic principles
stable `in the right way'; that is, they pursue stability
establishes . . . procedures for moderating poli-
for reasons of justice rather than of mere accommo-
tical rivalry within society . . . Where there is
44
The second condition is
agreement on certain basic political rights and
that the law of peoples should ideally be the object of
liberties . . . there is disagreement . . . as to the
an
more exact content and boundaries of these
dation (modus vivendi). overlapping
consensus:
people
would
ideally
rights.
come to affirm the moral value of the law of peoples.
45
48
The conditions of stability and consensus
represent the philosophical justification of the se-
Constitutional consensus arises, argues Rawls, as
ven-point law of peoples that Rawls argues is con-
the only workable solution to endless destruction
sistent with both liberal and non-liberal perspectives.
and strife, and can be thought of as the product of
Elements of international law that are controversial
what Rawls calls the `dramatic shift' in international
(peculiarly liberal) in character (human rights for
law since the Second World War.
example) are likely to receive whatever justification
of this stage in Rawls's theory is both its historicity
they get from a variety of incompatible philosophical
and its dynamism, its potential. For him:
49
The importance
or doctrinal sources. It is here that the relationship between stability and consensus shows us the source
At the first stage of constitutional consensus the
and potential of Rawls's theory. Stability is the goal
liberal principles of justice, initially accepted
of society, a condition in which we know that those
reluctantly as modus vivendi . . . tend to shift
with whom we share political space will comply with
citizens' comprehensive doctrines so that they
262
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
at least accept the principles of a liberal constitu-
perhaps even helps to explain the appeal of moral
tion. To this extent the [state's principles] are
particularism.
52
reasonable if they were not before: simple pluralism moves towards reasonable pluralism and constitutional consensus is reached.
In making his case Walzer contrasts `covering-law
50
universalism' with `reiterative universalism'. The central difference between
them is neatly sum-
marised by Miller, who writes that
Let us just look at the three requirements Rawls places upon international society, his construction of international community, and see whether it seems
`covering-law universalism' affirms the rightness
reasonable to use these ideas to support a construc-
of a particular way of life, and sees one nation as
tivist theory of international justice. The image of
the bearer of that way of life . . . `Reiterative
international politics that Rawls presents is one
universalism' . . . recognises that, subject to cer-
where:
tain minimal constraints imposed on all, there are a number of radically different and valuable forms of life which flourish in different places.
1. the fact of reasonable pluralism must lead to
53
consensus upon the need to fix the political situation and put such issues beyond particu-
Our main focus here is on the content of those
larist interest;
`minimal constraints' and upon their construction.
2. the application of principles of justice pays
For Walzer we cannot use an inaccessible account of
heed to the guidelines of public reason. These
agency to ground a `thick' covering-law universal-
guidelines and rules must be specified in re-
ism.
ference to forms of reasoning available to all;
something much weaker, on `overlapping expecta-
3. (dependent on 1 and 2) those involved believe
Rather,
reiterative
universalism
tions' about the behaviour of others.
the principles are just and thus the consensus works effectively.
54
55
relies
on
Walzer's
`rights to life and liberty' stem from reiterated claims
51
made by significantly different agents over time and in response to specific problems in international politics.
Rawls's use of the `reasonable', it would seem, is itself a move to ensure the accessibility of principles of
One reason why Rawls and Walzer are often
international justice to those whose autonomy does
sidelined in liberal international relations theory is
not rely upon a politically western and ethically
that what they believe they are obliged to allow to
Kantian heritage.
stand as legitimate domestic arrangements can take
The aims of Walzer's moral theory also explicitly
many forms, some of which may not appeal to our
engage with the problems of how we may link
liberal conception of legitimacy. As Walzer observes,
theories of international ethics with an appropriate
`by democratic standards, most states throughout
conception of international society. His approach
human history have been oppressive and illegiti-
sums up much of what Frost and Rawls can be seen to
mate, but those are not necessarily or even usually
be engaged in:
the standards by which they are judged by their own people.'
56
Given this, plus the contestability of the
Advocates of liberal enlightenment confront ad-
foundational assumptions of liberal human rights
vocates of communal tradition; those who aspire
theory, Walzer (and Rawls) want to promote inter-
to global reach confront those who yearn for local
national interaction while guarding against the uni-
intensity. We all know one another's lines . . . I
versal imposition of what Walzer calls an `alien
want to argue from within what I, and many
maximalist morality'.
others, have taken to be the opposing camp; I
principle that expresses moral minimalism in inter-
want to take my stand among the universalists
national affairs is self-determination, a concept ab-
and suggest that there is another universalism, a
stracted from its many reiterations or occurrences to
non-standard variety, which encompasses and
signify the protection of the political liberty of
263
57
To this end, his primary
PETER SUTCH
members of a plurality of communities.
58
From here
we would wish a theory of human rights to do. This
the rights to life and liberty develop to be repeated
charge is drawn from the long history of human
and reiterated at times of international and domestic
rights theory that insists that it is possible to develop
tyranny. They do not (yet?) form a transnational
a conception of international justice from outside
moral Esperanto,
59
but the political consequences of
the practice of international politics. But to do so is
recognising such values are genuinely progressive.
to ignore the constitution of the international com-
For Rawls, as for Walzer, the central idea is that the
munity and thus of the philosophical notion of the
benefits of true stability only derive from a fair
`relevantly similar', thereby risking the alienation of
construction of principles of justice among consent-
liberalism from the real world of international rela-
ing and dependable parties. The rights this process
tions. The power of human rights discourse is sig-
makes explicit, argues Rawls, are politically neutral
nificantly weakened if its justification belongs to one
in the sense that they are not specific to western
particular culture, even more so when it appears to
liberal culture.
60
foster the desires of the established hegemonic block. The liberalism of the developmental communitarians offers a way beyond this problem. If the outline
Conclusion
of this developing liberal discourse does fulfil the
There is a lot that liberals do not like about the
requirements of constructivism in ethics, then it is
international relations theory of Frost, Walzer and
certainly time to admit the non-Kantian liberalism of
Rawls. Prime among these dislikes are the limitations
Frost, Walzer and Rawls into mainstream interna-
that these thinkers have to place upon the role of
tional relations theory. As for the practice: limited
international justice. For example, it may appear that
and progressive liberalisation of international poli-
the human rights that non-cosmopolitan liberals
tics may not be all we can hope for, but it may be all
develop have no teeth: they cannot do the work
that we are justified in demanding.
Notes
13. O. O'Neill (1994), `Justice and Boundaries', in Brown
1. See, in particular, Rawls (1996) and (1999), chapters
(ed.) (1994), pp. 69±88, at p. 85.
24 and 25.
14. O'Neill (1996), p. 63.
2. See, for example, Beitz (1979); P. Jones, `International Human Rights: Philosophical or Political?', in Caney,
15. Ibid., p. 51.
George and Jones (eds) (1996); Moellendorf (1996);
16. Ibid., p. 74.
Paden (1997); and Pogge (1994).
17. As discussed in Mackie (1977).
3. Cosmopolitanism is a well-defined and well-under-
18. Ibid., p. 78.
stood tradition. For the purposes of this chapter,
19. Ibid., p. 83.
Brown's analysis stands as a perfect example of what
20. Ibid., pp. 97±8.
I have in mind: Brown (1992), pp. 23±51.
21. Ibid., p. 98.
4. Frost (1996).
22. O'Neill (1996), p. 117.
5. See, particularly, Walzer (1977) and (1994).
23. See, for example, O'Neill (1988).
6. Brown (1992), p. 120.
24. O'Neill (1996), p. 64.
7. O'Neill (1996).
25. Frost (1996), p. 79.
8. Ibid., especially chapters 2 and 3.
26. Ibid., pp. 111±12.
9. Ibid., especially chapter 4.
27. Ibid., p. 137. 28. Ibid., p. 112.
10. Ibid., chapters 1 and 2. 11. T. Pogge, `Cosmopolitanism
and Sovereignty',
29. Ibid., p. 112 n. 7, pp. 229±30.
in
30. Frost (1997a), (1997b).
Brown (ed.) (1994), pp. 89±122, at p. 48.
31. This task is completed in Sutch (2000), forthcoming.
12. These points must be considered subject to all the controversy surrounding the empirical and theoretical
32. See, for example, Doppelt (1980), Luban (1980).
debates over such issues as interdependence and glo-
33. Walzer (1994); see also Walzer (1990), p. 509.
balisation, and to the philosophical and political
34. Rawls (1996), pp. 98±100.
debates concerning the constitution of a moral com-
35. Ibid., p. 90.
munity.
36. Ibid., p. 98.
264
CONSTRUCTING INTERNATIONAL COMMUNITY
37. Cf. Rawls (1999), p. 532.
level of consensus would play a role in international
38. Rawls (1996), p. 110.
relations, but as a vital element of Rawls's conceptual
39. Ibid., p. 144; see also p. xxiv.
mechanism (and if appropriately modified) I think it is fascinating at least to attempt the transition.
40. The language is, of course, Rawls's but the ideas are implicit in Walzer's communitarianism and in early
49. Ibid.; see also Rawls (1999), p. 535.
stages of Frost's work.
50. Rawls (1996), pp. 163±4.
41. Walzer (1994), pp. 18±19.
51. Ibid., pp. 161±2.
42. Rawls (1999), p. 540.
52. Walzer (1990), p. 509.
43. Ibid., p. 542.
53. Miller (1995), p. 10.
44. Ibid.
54. Walzer (1990), pp. 522±3.
45. Ibid., p. 543. For a fuller account of stability and
55. Ibid. 56. Walzer (1980), p. 128.
consensus, see Rawls (1996), Lecture IV, section 2. 46. Ibid., p. 566.
57. Ibid., pp. 519±20.
47. Ibid., p. 552.
58. Walzer (1994), pp. 67±8.
48. Rawls (1996), pp. 158±9. I am aware that there is no
59. Ibid., p. 7. 60. Rawls (1999), p. 552.
textual evidence to support the claim that this middle
265
This page intentionally left blank
Part Eight NEW DIRECTIONS FOR LIBERAL THINKING
This page intentionally left blank
20
LIBERALISM AND POSTCOMMUNISM Richard Sakwa
priate for each specific country? And how can
Introduction
liberalism be established from scratch?
The last hundred years have been a troubled time
The post-communist transitions have raised the
for liberalism. An idea whose prospects seemed so
most profound questions, not only about the current
Á cle was drowned in the bright in the last fin de sie
status of liberalism, democracy and economic mod-
blood of the First World War and the left and right
ernisation, but also by forcing old issues once again to
authoritarianisms that emerged out of that conflict.
the fore. In a way post-communist transformation is a
This has now all changed. `Suddenly', Ernest Gell-
replay of the struggle for liberalism in Europe from
ner notes, `the century of troubles and tribulations
the late seventeenth to the nineteenth centuries.
of
often
Similar fears about the dangers of excessive state
looked as if it were to witness liberalism's demise,
power have been voiced, while the establishment of
in fact documents its almost embarassed triumph. It
secure property rights was at the centre of the
liberalism
is
all
over.
A
century
that
does not quite know what to do with it.'
1
This
European and post-communist social revolutions.
Francis
Indeed, post-communism forces us to rethink the
Fukuyama in his thesis on `the end of history',
relationship between the two faces of liberalism:
arguing that with the fall of communism there was
political democracy and the market economy. Emer-
no longer any sustained programmatic universal
ging out of the command economy it is understand-
victory
was
given
intellectual
2
form
by
There has always been
able that the predominant belief at the fall of
a type of liberal historicism that favoured the view
communism was that without economic freedom
of an evolution through stages in human affairs,
all other freedoms, civil and political, are threatened.
rejecting cyclical theories (Spengler, Toynbee), or
It was soon realised, however, that freedom (espe-
those that
cially if confined to the economic sphere) is not the
alternative to liberalism.
thought in terms of stasis
and self-
sum of liberalism.
perpetuating order of a Chinese sort. Yet many impeccable liberals (like Dahrendorf) found Fu-
 Merquior, we can consider liberalFollowing Jose
kuyama's radical restatement of a liberal historicism
ism as ideally comprising the following four elements:
profoundly offensive and ± unliberal. Some sort of
`(1) the (negative) freedom of not being subjected to
victory for liberalism was, however, recorded with
arbitrary interferences; (2) the (positive) freedom of
the fall of communism. The question was not only
participating in public affairs; (3) the (interior) free-
what to do with this victory, but for the post-
dom of conscience and beliefs; and (4) the (personal)
communist countries the problem remained: how to
freedom of self-development for each individual.'
do it? Which liberal tradition is the most appro-
This is a full-bodied liberalism drawing on all five
269
3
RICHARD SAKWA
of the liberal traditions identified by Jaguaribe (classical, conservative, social, sociological and neo),
leading liberals, the mistake had been to ally with the
4
democrats from the old Communist Party of the 10
whereas the liberalism prevalent under post-commun-
Soviet Union (CPSU) in the late 1980s.
ism is predominantly of the neo-liberal type. The
1995 he had become convinced that there was no
ideologists of neo-liberalism are Von Mises, Hayek,
basis for a liberal democratic society in Russia. The
Nozick and Milton Friedman, all condemning state
problem was no longer the power of selfish ruling
regulation in favour of the unrestrained operation of
elites, but the conservative people, above all the
market forces and a radical individualism: prioritising
patriarchal-minded mass of peasants.
(1) and underplaying (2)±(4).
of contemptuous attitude towards their own people
11
By
It is this sort
While it is easy to condemn the excesses of neo-
that has characterised Russian liberalism. Sogrin
liberalism, especially in a post-Thatcher/Reagan era,
takes a more balanced view, arguing that while there
it is more difficult to sustain a defence of the
were the preconditions for liberal democracy in
rationality of the market and the enterprise as the
Russia, the objective reasons for the failures and
most efficient allocater of resources while simulta-
shortcomings of liberalism can be found in the
neously condemning the neo-liberal demonisation of
specific liberal democratic model that was adopted
the state and the attempt to impose `the law of the
and imposed by Russian liberals.
jungle on societies whose stability was obtained
was drawn between liberalism and democracy, and
thanks to the healthy effects of the welfare state.'
5
12
No distinction
only from around 1990 did liberalism begin to 13
These predicaments will be examined on the basis of
emerge as an autonomous political tendency.
developments in the post-communist world, primar-
then, the liberal trend failed to develop into a
ily in Russia and Poland.
genuinely popular movement and source of mass political action.
Even
14
Jerzy Szacki, a professor of sociology at Warsaw
From the Wreckage of Communism
University, argues that while the philosophy of
The emergence of political liberalism in Russia under
economic liberalism as such appealed only to a
Gorbachev in 1987±88 during `perestroika' (`restruc-
minority of dissidents, the political value of what
turing') was as a distinctive addition to socialism; only
he calls `protoliberalism' as an alternative `neglected
later did it emerge as an autonomous force in its own
path of anti-communism' actually increased.
right to triumph between 1991 and 1992.
6
15
He
This
argues that liberalism was a phenomenon of the
triumph, however, was ambivalent. Nodari Simonia
western world with few roots in Eastern Europe,
notes that `the defeat of the attempted coup in
and that communism, far from suppressing indigen-
August 1991 was no victory for democracy. Political
ous liberal development, artificially fostered it as its
democracy was the dominant tendency, but there
alternative political vision. As David Ost puts it,
was neither the social nor the economic base neces-
`when the enemy became the state, the opposition
sary for the establishment of democracy. A civil
became liberals.'
society had not yet been created.'
7
16
The fall of communism would
He goes on to
allow the anti-liberalism of Catholicism, in Szacki's
argue that `while the remnants of the ideological
view, to reassert itself (or, perhaps, any one of the
nomenklatura waged rearguard battles against Russian
numerous anti-liberal traditions of the area). He fails
democracy, an economic nomenklatura moved into
to realise that in modern pluralist societies even
8
It is for this
intrinsically authoritarian faiths can, if freely adopted
reason, according to Jerry Hough, that the end of
by its members and when part of a broader patch-
communism in the USSR, although no less of a
work of equally autonomous interests, strengthen the
revolution than the events of 1917 that had brought
liberal heterogeneity of society.
position to attain political power.'
the Bolsheviks to power, was relatively bloodless.
9
The argument, nevertheless, is an important one.
Within a year organised liberalism appeared to
Liberalism appeared less a systemic necessity and
have exhausted itself, and since then has been at a
outgrowth of the society than an instrument with
low ebb. According to Lev Timofeev, one of Russia's
which to assault the party-state. Many have argued
270
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
itself into a political danger zone, where the risks
that the social basis for liberal democracy was, quite simply, lacking in Poland,
17
were far greater than ever before.'
and if that was the case,
20
The liberal
then in Russia it stood no chance whatsoever. In
`party' in the anti-communist revolutions of 1989±
Russia it was Andrei Sakharov who became the
91 took the form of an inchoate social movement
symbol of the liberal opposition to the regime, yet
whose leadership was amorphous and its policies
paradoxically it was Solzhenitsyn, usually charac-
limited to the negative programme of opposition
terised as an authoritarian patriot, who advocated
to the decaying communist regime. Its positive pro-
a gradualist strategy of self-liberation from commun-
gramme was a transformative one that assaulted the
ism
18
while the `liberal' Sakharov espoused a more
society from which it sought to draw its democratic
revolutionary break with the past. It is out of para-
legitimacy: transformative legitimacy ran counter to
doxes such as these that post-communist liberalism
democratic legitimacy.
was born. In Hungary by 1998 the Prime Minister,
This was particularly the case in Russia. The main
Victor Orban, even went so far as to argue that
liberal `party' in the December 1993 State Duma
certain elements of West European liberalism could
elections,
not be `simply transferred' to Central Europe, and the
Russia (DVR), won 15.51 per cent of the party list
attempt to do so might often do `more harm than
vote, coming second to the 22.92 per cent for
19
Yegor Gaidar's
Democratic
Choice
of
Faced by rising crime rates the response is
Vladimir Zhirinovskii's Liberal Democratic Party
understandable, but his argument that the ruling
of Russia (LDPR) (which of course is not a liberal
Federation of Young Democrats-Hungarian Civic
party). Rather than organising as an autonomous
Party was now `much more than a liberal party'
force, liberals relied on the benevolence of President
suggested a deeper unease with liberalism itself.
Boris Yeltsin and sought to use the state to promote
We should thus examine liberalism as a transforma-
their policies. They thus became the first `party of
tive challenge, a set of ideas and a complex of
power', until losing out in political intrigues and
institutions.
defeat at the polls. Indeed, it appeared that there
good'.
were more liberals in the entourage of the relatively authoritarian Yeltsin presidency than in the parlia-
Liberalism and Capitalist Transformation
ment itself.
The central contradiction of post-communist liberal-
For liberals like Gaidar, it was fear of losing power
ism is that as an economic philosophy it was pre-
in 1994 rather than attempts to institutionalise their
dominant, and its political ideals of civil rights,
dominance that led them to activise their attempts
political pluralism, the separation of powers, toler-
to create a party to support their programme. The so-
ance and advocacy of non-militaristic solutions to
called democratic movement and the liberals asso-
domestic and foreign problems became the main
ciated with the Yabloko party fared dismally in the
currency of debate, but as an organised force it
regional elections between September 1996 and into
has tended to be weak.
early 1997, not winning a single governorship.
21
Federal party politics counted for very little in these elections in the regions, and even less in the repub-
Politically Organised Liberalism
lics, especially where titular ethnic elites dominated
The relationship between liberalism and mass de-
political life. Regime-type systems have proliferated
mocracy is at the best of times problematic, but in
in the regions and republics where more often than
post-communist countries it has fallen prey to the
not both liberalism and democracy have been com-
technocratic temptation. In 1991 the liberal concept
promised.
of a parliamentary constitutional state prevailed over
In the December 1995 elections the combined
residual notions of a socialist alternative. But, as in
liberal vote was only 16.2 per cent. Yet, as Steven
Germany in 1919, `politically organised Liberalism,
Fish has argued, the reason for the liberals' crushing
the Liberal parties, played no part at all in this
defeat lies not in any profound anti-liberalism of the
victory; and the victory drew Liberal democracy
Russian people as such, nor in the institutional
271
RICHARD SAKWA
framework, the electoral system, lack of resources or
right thinking, it is unclear what remains of a dis-
disunity among the liberal parties. Rather, he argues,
tinctively liberal agenda.
the answer lies in the deficiencies of the liberals
Economic liberalism became the guiding principle
themselves, and in particular their poor organisation
of post-communist transformations. The reasoning
(consistently
of
behind `shock therapy' was outlined by Leszek Bal-
miscon-
cerowicz, arguing against any evolutionary exit out of
ceived campaigns, and the legacy of the behaviour
the old state-planned system in favour of a complete
party
underestimating
organisation),
of liberals in power.
the
unprofessional 22
importance and
Organised liberalism in the
and radical institutional break with the past.
25
The
December 1999 parliamentary elections was even
issue of sequencing was crucial for him, insisting that
more fragmented and disorganised, grouped around a
systemic market-oriented reforms had to be achieved
number of leading personalities whose alliances were
during the period of `extraordinary politics' of high
as fragile as the differences between them were
political mobilisation early on in the process. An
minimal. The Right Cause (Pravoe Delo) grouping
even more robust defence of economic liberalism
brought together some of Russia's leading liberals,
came from Vaclav Klaus, Prime Minister of the
including Boris Nemtsov, Anatolii Chubais and
Czech Republic from 1991 to 1997, where he praised
Boris Fedorov, together with `the right-wing liberal'
the virtues of the untrammelled market and con-
Yegor Gaidar, `the odious architect of the attempts to
servative liberal principles,
implement ``shock therapy''.'
23
26
although in practice he
According to Buzga-
presided over a semi-reformed system that allowed its
lin, the author of the just-quoted sentiments, Right
own type of crony capitalism to emerge. Szacki's
Cause was dangerous for Russia because of the
warnings in this context about the shallowness of
`communist fanaticism' with which they sought to
true political liberalism in the region need to be
implement their plans. Few in Russia would forget
taken seriously. The balance drawn between eco-
the role that some of the members of Right Cause
nomic liberalism, liberal political ideas, the collec-
played in creating the system of oligarchical capit-
tive rights of the nation and the persistent support for
alism, accompanied by the immiseration of large
many features of the old state socialist welfare system
sectors of society. All of this is true, yet the trajectory
differed between states, but throughout the region
of post-communist liberalism has a more profound
none could avoid the dilemmas posed by these issues.
meaning. Transformative Liberalism Marketisation and Liberalism
These problems were particularly acute in Russia
Like the communist regimes that they replaced, the
where, according to Sogrin, a `radical liberal' ten-
liberalism that emerged in the post-communist states
dency predominated, characterised by a utopianism
was forced to create the grounds for its social ex-
that ignored the character of Russian society and
istence by a massive act of economic transformation.
civilisation.
Broader humanistic concerns were thus subverted by
Gaidar, Chubais and Fedorov dominated the Russian
the economism implicit in this transformative mis-
government. From 2 January 1992 they launched a
sion. Bellamy has noted the shift from ethical to
`shock therapy' economic reform with the liberal-
economic theories of liberal democracy,
24
27
From November 1991 liberals like
but under
isation of some prices. The economic legacy of this
post-communism this has taken extreme forms. Pol-
period is still debated, but the immediate result was
itics has been subordinated to the alleged economic
near-hyper inflation, a slump in production and a
imperative of social transformation. Old tensions
record deterioration in standards of living. More
within the liberal tradition, above all between social
positively, queues disappeared and market principles
liberalism, with its more positive view of liberty and
began to be introduced in the economy. By the end
state activism, and neo-classical liberalism, stressing
of the year Yeltsin had sacrificed the liberal refor-
the redemptive powers of the market, have burst out
mers, and from December 1992 Victor Chernomyr-
once again. Torn between social democracy and new
din took over as Prime Minister. Andrei Kozyrev, the
272
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
liberal foreign minister, stayed on until the Decem-
While there is no doubt that Nemtsov is an
ber 1995 parliamentary elections saw the commu-
economic liberal, in politics he is more of a national
nists become the largest grouping in the Duma, but
liberal with a statist bent. An admirer of Peter the
in the economic sphere only Chubais survived to
Great, he noted in an interview in February 1997:
mastermind the privatisation of the economy. This is one of the most spectacular shifts in ownership
I'm a liberal economist and support the idea of a
relations in history; today, less than a quarter of
strong state in politics. Yegor Gaidar, for instance,
the national economy is in state hands. Mass redis-
is a liberal in economics and a liberal in politics,
tribution of ownership was accompanied by equally
in the bad sense of this word. In Russia, such
spectacular corruption.
liberalism is ruinous.
31
Chubais was appointed head of the presidential administration
in
He advocated using Russia's financial resources to
June±July 1996, and was made a First Deputy Prime
following
buy up the city and naval base of Sevastopol. `His-
Minister in March 1997. This time, together with
torical justice should be restored by capitalist meth-
the other First Deputy Prime Minister, Nemtsov, he
ods,' he suggested. As Peter Rutland notes, `Nemtsov
sought to end the domination of the `old economic
may be a liberal, but he is a liberal with a Russian
nomenklatura', to break up the huge natural mono-
face.'
polies and the utilities, and to pursue housing and
Prime Minister from April to August 1998, when he
pensions reform.
28
Yeltsin's
re-election
32
The same could be said of Sergei Kirienko,
Although yoked together, Chu-
struggled to transform oligarchical capitalism into a
bais and Nemtsov represent two very different trends
more open version. His failure to deal with the legacy
in Russian liberalism. Chubais is a radical liberal,
of nearly a decade of mismanagement led to the
whereas Nemtsov represents a tendency dubbed by
partial default of 17 August 1998, and his own
Sogrin as `national liberalism' ± although it is un-
dismissal six days later.
likely that a direct reference is intended to Germany's National Liberal party established in 1867, and
The `Sin of Constructivism'
whose left wing seceded in 1880. While respecting traditional liberal values of private property, the
To achieve the desired socio-economic results and to
market, pluralism and political democracy, Russian
generate market-oriented behaviour by economic
national liberals sought to replace abstract or Wes-
actors, the post-communist state intervened on a
tern liberal models with one more suited to Russian
massive scale in the early years of the transition, thus
conditions. Disenchanted with Western democracy,
compromising, both politically and economically,
national liberals began to favour authoritarian gov-
many of the principles of the new `liberal' order.
ernment to democracy. They regarded the social
This `sin of constructivism', in the words of Szacki,
liberal idea of a universal welfare state as inappropri-
is reminiscent in an inverted form, not surprisingly,
ate for Russia, favouring instead a carefully targeted
of earlier `grand designs' of the communist sort. The
social policy. A national liberal economic model
Polish sociologist Radzislawa Gortat also referred to
equally rejects the monetarism of the radical liberals
`liberalism as constructivism',
and favours a more active role for the state in
eralism in Poland was born in a way that contra-
national economic development and a degree of
dicted its nature. Thus in its struggle to create
protection for national production.
29
34
33
describing how lib-
A representa-
capitalist institutions the Tadeusz Mazowiecki gov-
tive of this tendency was Alexander Lebed, who
ernment relied on the authority of the state to
sought to free the state from bureaucratic, nomenk-
achieve the desired results. The liberal reforms,
and criminal dominance, forces that had
lacking a social interest to act on its behalf, relied
usurped the fruits of reform by distorting the mar-
on an external agency to articulate an inevitably
latura
30
National liberalism represented the adaptation
synthetic and derivative version of the social ideal.
of liberalism with a social conscience to Russian
In the absence of social interests to articulate and
conditions.
promote the programme, the Balcerowicz plan of late
ket.
273
RICHARD SAKWA
1989, and the Gaidar model of social transformation
Kolodko's `Strategy for Poland' document of 1994.
in Russia from late 1991, could only be the creation
The Balcerowicz group, it argued, had an ideological
of the state.
35
commitment to liberal doctrine, pursuing its pro-
It is well-known that Hayek condemned Keynes's
gramme in a centralised, technocratic manner that
advocacy of government intervention in the econ-
treated the public as passive objects of transition.
omy to correct the market as presumptious `con-
This was, according to Jerzy Hausner, an `imperative'
structivism'. As Bellamy puts it (following John
method of post-communist change, that gave way
Gray), Hayek distinguishes `between the notion of
later to the `interactive' approach favoured by Ko-
society as a spontaneous order embodying evolution-
lodko. The `interactive' approach sought to ground
ary reason, on the one hand, and constructivist
ongoing processes of social change in a continuing
rationalist theories of society, on the other.'
36
In
discursive relationship between the authorities and
his Road to Serfdom of 1944, Hayek had condemned
the public. Rejecting the view that there was `no
western governments for subverting the law and
alternative' to the transition to an Anglo-Saxon style
replacing it with legislation. But what spontaneous
economy, the `interactive' approach recognised a
order could there be in post-communist conditions?
variety of capitalisms and that the role of the state
Liberals were forced to adopt the guise of revolu-
would be subject to negotiation rather than a priori
tionaries and act not as the defenders of a sponta-
rejected.
38
neously generated social order, but as a small sect of
It was this more interactive approach that was
priests who claimed a privileged understanding of the
favoured by the liberal opposition in Russia, and in
laws of history and social development. Solutions
particular Grigorii Yavlinskii's `social liberal' Yablo-
were imposed upon society and not derived from
ko party. However, there appeared to be no devel-
society.
oped alternative to radical liberal economic policies.
This should be placed in context, and the notion
Attempts to devise alternatives, even by the `demo39
of post-communist neo-liberal reformers as `Bolshe-
cratic opposition' in Yabloko, in practice failed.
viks of the market' should not be taken too far. In
These social liberals emphasised the social basis of
form, content and methods the differences are so
any viable political or economic order, while at the
large as to render analogies almost meaningless. As
same time insisting that it had to be rooted in the
Andrzej Walicki notes:
national interest. They took the universals of liberalism and sought to present them in a patriotic idiom.
One of the most conspicuous characteristics of
The behaviour of the radical liberals in power in
post-communist Poland is the omnipresent con-
Russia was characterised not only by constructivism
tradiction between the radical, uncompromisingly
but also by corruption, the denigration of patriotism,
anti-communist ideology and the principle of
the rupture of relations with the former Soviet states,
compromise that has enabled a smooth, peaceful
and by a narrow dogmatism that appeared to regard
transfer of power.
37
the dismantling of state capacity as the pinnacle of the liberal project. The social liberals promised to
The new authorities were revolutionary in their
continue the reforms but in a more socially oriented
actions but liberal in their methods. Yet the charge
way. They would remain tempted, however, by the
of constructivism is accurate, and one that tainted
sin of constructivism.
post-communist liberalism (above all in Russia) with the stamp of illiberality, if not authoritarianism and
Constrained Liberalism
hypocrisy. After the radical phase a reaction set in marked by
Kryzstof Bielecki, the liberal Polish Prime Minister in
a return to the politics of gradualism and a reconsi-
1991, has talked in terms of `constrained liberal-
deration of the social values of reform. In Poland this
ism'.
took the form of the Finance and Deputy Prime
`blockages' in legitimation `which stem from the
Minister (from May 1994 to February 1997) Grzegorz
elite's usage of outdated symbols and discourses in
40
274
Andrzej Rychard refers to what he calls
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
the construction of liberal democracy', failing above
to `fasten' identities to fixed, naturalised subject
all to negotiate with, and often even to explain to,
positions inevitably disciplines those subjects and
the populace over the strategies for reform. It instead
limits possibilities for political action. Further-
struck hard during the breathing space offered by the
more, discourses that seek to attain totality, even
period of `extraordinary politics' to impose ready-
a democratic totality, do so by covering over
made solutions, often imported from abroad.
41
He
discursive instabilities, by mistaking a unified
notes that `the communist order existed but was
subject for a fluid ensemble of subject positions.
47
[indiscriminately] rejected while the post-communist order has not been shaped but is [naively] accepted'.
42
Thus the liberal citizen was to be grounded in
The Mazowiecki government's liberal-
economic liberty, specifically private property as
minded Industry Minister's statement during his
the basis for civil society and the emancipatory
confirmation hearings before the Sejm in September
potential of economic empowerment. Post-commu-
1989 is instructive: `I represent subjects that do not
nist liberals thus appeared to be more Lockean than
43
The absence of any organised social force
Locke himself, `in implying not only that liberty will
to carry out the liberal reforms translated into what
be achieved by acting on the right to property, but
Jadwiga Staniszkis called a `revolution from above' in
through property itself'.
which the state promoted the (temporary) demobi-
achieved in what had previously united Solidarity,
lisation of society in order to achieve the economic
the combination of social power and individual
conditions that would allow greater public inclu-
rights. In Poland and elsewhere social power was
yet exist.'
sion.
44
48
A radical disjuncture was
consigned to some non-liberal limbo, together with
Constrained liberalism has yet another and per-
state activism in its entirety, while the liberal subject
haps more profound meaning. Janine Holc has ar-
was constrained by an eviscerated model of what the
gued that
citizen of this liberal utopia was to look like.
liberal
discourse
is
itself
part
of
the
construction of a very specific type of democratic subject in post-communism.
45
As she notes, `all
Liberalism and Post-communist Democracy
states ± indeed, all communities ± are based on
Philippe Schmitter has noted that:
assumptions about who properly belongs in them', and in Poland between 1990 and 1993 a very specific `liberal' narrative became dominant that explicitly
Liberalism, either as a conception of political
linked `private property, individual rights, and the
liberty, or as a doctrine about economic policy,
``shock therapy'' of the free market, and it implicitly
may have coincided with the rise of democracy.
constructed an ideal and quite fixed ``citizen'' of the
But it has never been immutably or unambigu-
new Polish democracy.'
46
ously linked to its practice.
Bielecki himself, as Prime
49
Minister in 1991, was the most radical of these liberal `identity-builders'. Not only was the state being
This question is particularly acute in post-communist
rebuilt, but the notion of what made up the citizen
countries, where the very `givenness' of a structured
was being reconstructed. Holc seeks to break away
society is in question. Implicit in many discussions is
from traditional institution-centred discussions of
the `Kirkpatrick principle', the view that in the
transition to examine the change in subjectivities
transition from authoritarianism to democracy, so-
involved. She sums up her argument as follows:
ciety can spring back into shape, whereas in the transition from totalitarianism, society is destroyed to
The rise and fall of the Liberal movement in
such a degree that it has to become an object of the
Poland illustrates the manner in which a vision
transition process itself.
or philosophy of government that assigns indivi-
The fate of liberalism in the post-communist
dual civil and economic rights to its citizens is not
world is dependent on the ability of democracy itself
inherently liberating or democratic for those sub-
to survive. This is nowhere more evident than in the
jects. Rather, any discourse of authority that seeks
sphere of party formation. Throughout the post-
275
RICHARD SAKWA
communist world the emergence of this quintessen-
financial crash of August 1998 effectively wiped out
tial aspect of a modern liberal democracy was a more
the nascent middle class. As Kagarlitskii puts it:
protracted, fragmented and tenuous process than in the other `third wave' democratising states in Latin
the retreat from communist ideology was accom-
America and Southern Europe. It might be noted
panied by the centralisation of power in the hands
that in America and elsewhere parties by no means
of the local bosses. The organs of local self-
developed at the same time as parliamentarianism
government, already very weak, were quite simply
and democracy. According to Kagarlitskii, the `plur-
abolished until revived as part of the centre's
alism of elites' allowed capitalism in its `primary
attempts to outflank the powerful regional bosses.
accumulation of capital' phase to preserve liberal
In conditions of economic crisis enterprise admin-
political institutions while keeping the people away
istrations strengthened their control over work-
from decision-making:
ers.
52
The interaction of a harsh and authoritarian
How can we explain this and in what terms can we
structure of executive power with a parliamentary
describe it? There are three substantive approaches
elite was an ideal recipe for oligarchical rule,
to the issue.
characteristic for the liberal-market capitalism of the nineteenth century.
50
1. Illiberal democracy
It was this sort of system, marked by a large number of
In a recent article Fareed Zakaria has implicitly taken
`independent' politicians elected largely due to their
up Raymond Aron's view that the concept of `con-
financial resources, that was created by what Kagar-
stitutional pluralism' is in many ways more accurate
litskii calls the `liberal-authoritarian' regime in Rus-
than the formula of `liberal democracy'. Zakaria
sia, a system that was ideal for the needs of the
distinguishes between liberal democracy, defined as
corrupted Russian bureaucracy, striving to gain for-
`a political system marked not only by free and fair
mer state property, and for western elites who sought
elections, but also by the rule of law, a separation of
a power strong enough to suppress any popular
powers and the protection of basic liberties of speech,
resistance to the `reforms' while avoiding the open
assembly, religion and property', which he calls
authoritarianism typical of Latin America. The sys-
constitutional liberalism, and illiberal democracy.
tem also corresponded to national traditions, where
In the latter `democratically elected regimes, often
nascent liberal institutions were always grafted on to
ones that have been re-elected or reaffirmed through
the authoritarian Russian state, whether this was in
referenda, are routinely ignoring constitutional limits
the late Tsarist period or in the late Soviet epoch,
on their power and depriving their citizens of basic
and acted as no more than a supplement to funda-
rights and freedoms'.
mentally non-democratic systems.
51
53
For Zakaria, the regular sta-
ging of relatively fair, competitive, multi-party elec-
In Russia this tension has taken extreme forms.
tions might make a country democratic, but it does
`Perestroika' was a battleground between the liberal
not ensure good governance. For him, constitutional
part of the nomenklatura and the nascent civil so-
liberalism
ciety. If `perestroika' was accompanied by the emergence of `civil society' movements dealing with local,
is not about the procedures for selecting govern-
environmental and civil rights issues, the triumph of
ment, but rather government's goals. It refers to
the liberal nomenklatura and intelligentsia in August
the tradition, deep in Western history, that seeks
1991 was followed very quickly by the stifling of this
to protect an individual's autonomy and dignity
social insurgency. In addition, throughout the 1990s
against coercion, whatever ± state, church, or
the status and material position of the liberal profes-
society . . . It is liberal because it draws on the
sions and intellectual life in general declined sharply,
philosophical strain, beginning with the Greeks,
damaging the core supporters of liberalism, while the
that emphasises individual liberty. It is constitu-
276
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
tional because it rests on the tradition, beginning
with the Romans, of the rule of law.
formalised but strongly operative practices ± clien-
54
telism,
patrimonialism,
and
corruption.'
58
The
notion of delegative democracy has clear applications to Russia, and has been used fruitfully in
In practice, even relatively free elections in coun-
59
tries like Kazakhstan `have resulted in strong execu-
analysing regional politics.
tives, weak legislatures and judiciaries, and few civil
has clear limitations when applied to Russia, ignor-
and economic liberties.'
55
However, the concept
Zakaria argues that while
ing precisely the political consequences of imposing
constitutional liberalism can lead to democracy,
a capitalist economic system. It is the combination of
democracy does not necessarily lead to constitutional
political reform and economic transformation that
liberalism. Thus the government of Hong Kong
allowed the whole process to be hijacked by sectoral
under British rule was epitomised by constitutional
and other special interests, not the flaws in the
liberalism, protecting the rights of citizens and the
democratic method as such.
rule of law, but it was far from democratic. The Central European post-communist states are nego-
3. Regime democracy
tiating the passage to democracy more successfully than the former Soviet states, it is argued, because
As Merquior noted of Brazil, the concentration of
they went through a long phase of liberalisation
economic power `is a freedom-killing exercise',
without democracy in the nineteenth century that
observation that is equally true of Russia and other
grounded the rule of law and property rights into
post-communist countries. These countries do not
social practices. The problem with this approach is
lack freedom; they lack liberalism. The new freedom
that it assumes that history is destiny and provides no
has allowed an oligarchical, corporate and corrupt
mechanism for a society to break out of `path de-
capitalism to emerge.
60
an
pendency'. It appears that if a country misses the bus
Regime-type politics are characteristic of all the
of constitutional liberalism it has little chance of
post-communist states of the former USSR (but not
getting on the bus called democracy.
Central Europe). This covers not only features like enhanced powers for the executive, the prevalence of personalised leadership where the personality
2. Delegative democracy
defines the contours of the political system, the
In a similar vein, Giullermo O'Donnell has argued
manipulation of parliaments, weak judicial over-
that in weakly established democracies a leader can
sight, seamless links between the political and new-
become so strong that he or she can ignore those who
ly-enriched
they are meant to represent. O'Donnell characterises
distinction between public and private posts, and
these countries as having `delegative' rather than
above all the lack of accountability of elected lea-
representative democracy, with the electorate alleg-
ders. The very nature of post-communism in this
edly having delegated to the executive the right to
region has taken on the colouring of what postmo-
do what it sees fit, `constrained only by the hard facts
dernists call a `decentred' politics. Although the
of existing power relations and by a constitutionally
powers of the executive everywhere have been en-
limited term of office'.
56
socio-economic
elites,
the
lack
of
Thus a government emerges
hanced, these are not classical presidentialist regimes
that is `inherently hostile to the patterns of repre-
of the Latin American type. Politics is too unstruc-
sentation normal in established democracies' by
tured, institutions too fluid and the personages too
`depoliticising the population except for brief mo-
constrained by the emerging class system and ethnic
ments in which it demands its plebiscitary support.'
57
contradictions to allow the emergence of a defined
This sort of democracy is, according to O'Donnell,
balance of powers. Instead regime politics is defined
underinstitutionalised,
re-
by flux within the parameters of the exigencies of the
stricted scope, the weakness, and the low density
transitional process itself: they are not arbitrary but
of whatever political institutions exist. The place of
neither are they ordered as part of a structured
well-functioning institutions is taken by other non-
political order (Ordnungspolitik). Its codes are not
`characterised
by
the
277
RICHARD SAKWA
formalised but they are recognised. The legitimacy
problematic, for Russia (and some other post-Soviet
inherent in the electoral process comes into contra-
states) post-communism has once again raised the
diction with the functionality of the transformative
question that has racked the country for at least the
impulse. In short, the political process in Russia and
last three hundred years: is Russia part of Europe or a
elsewhere lacks a subject, focused neither on person-
separate and distinct civilisation sufficient unto itself?
alities nor institutions but on fluid but ritualised
All of these countries, moreover, have been faced by
relations between universally objectified processes
the `Nuremberg question', the degree to which the
of transition.
perpetrators of the crimes of the old regime can be brought to book.
63
Whether there is a distinctively
`liberal' approach to this aspect of universalism is
Universalism and Post-communism
unclear, other than a commitment to the rule of law.
Although the domestic sources of liberalism may be
Too often decommunisation became an aspect of the
relatively weak in most post-communist countries,
partisan persecution of political opponents.
the international context is increasingly dominated
More broadly, the question is often posed whether
by the political counterpart of globalisation, what we
any universal agenda of human and liberal rights is
might call `universalisation'. It is under this nominal
no more than a covert form of imposing Western
rubric that the most important questions of our day
values on other societies. Some post-communist
are discussed. This is the question of the extent to
leaders have explicitly argued that liberalism is not
which the universal norms, as formulated above all
suitable for their societies at this stage of develop-
in the 1948 United Nations Universal Declaration of
ment. Familiar arguments about distinctive paths
Human Rights, are applicable to all countries, irre-
and `third ways' are being mobilised by post-com-
spective of their specific traditions. From this per-
munist leaders (for example, President Islam Kari-
spective globalisation can be challenged not so much
mov in Uzbekistan and the Mayor of Moscow, Yurii
from a `left' perspective as from a universal one, in
Luzhkov) and leaders of the developing countries
which a rich array of international and national
(for example, Prime Minister Mahathir Mohammed
organisations established in the postwar years can
of Malaysia). Both the `East' and the `South' are now
be mobilised to establish a set of international norms.
joined by a series of common dilemmas that trans-
In the European context the main instruments of this
cend issues of globalisation and focus on the cultural
universalism are the Council of Europe (CE) and the
and political identity of the nations themselves. The
Organisation for Security and Cooperation in Europe
former Second and Third Worlds are still far from
(OSCE). Russia joined the CE in February 1996, and
one, but when it comes to civilisational issues and
on 20 February 1998 the Duma voted to ratify the
developmental trajectories they do face some com-
European Convention on Human Rights, allowing
mon problems.
Russian citizens to file appeals to the European Court. By that time there were already 800 com-
Post-communist Liberalism
plaints from Russian citizens pending with the European Commission on Human Rights, the body that refers cases to the European Court.
Liberalism is an extended meditation on the legit-
61
imate sphere of state activism and the proper scope
Universalism has reforged a link between moder-
for public authority. As with any living idea, answers
nisation and development. While some Asian coun-
are always in the process of being rethought. Liberal-
tries, as Huntington has noted, have been able to
ism under post-communism becomes post-commu-
separate
nist liberalism.
modernisation
from
westernisation,
by
adopting western techniques but not capitulating to western culture in its entirety,
62
for post-commu-
Liberalism and the Post-communist State
nist countries this question is particularly acute. Although for most Eastern European countries the
The opening of John Stuart Mill's On Liberty has in
`return to Europe' is not perceived as particularly
effect become the slogan of the post-communist
278
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
revolutions: as countries become democratic, he
minimalism, reducing the legitimate scope of state
noted, people believed that `too much importance
activity. In the post-communist world the anti-statist
has been attached to the limitation of power itself.
strain in liberalism became an over-determined as-
That (it might seem) was a resource against rulers
sault on the very existence of purposive state action,
whose interests were habitually opposed to those of
something that China managed to avoid because of
the people.' With the people in charge, there was
its distinctive traditions and refusal to accept the
allegedly no need for such caution: `The nation did
agenda of `transition' and liberal democracy.
not need to be protected against its own will. There was no fear of tyrannising over itself.'
64
Gottfried Dietze has distinguished between `liber-
Mill of course
alism proper', defined as `liberty without restriction',
goes on to argue that
and `proper liberalism', a balance between personal liberties and social restrictions that allows the en-
the limitation . . . of the power of government
joyment of the one with the public order of the
over individuals loses none of its importance
other.
when the holders of power are regularly accoun-
has exerted a profound influence in post-communist
table to the community, that is, to the strongest
Russia accompanied by the weakening of law en-
party therein.
65
69
Clearly, it is a vulgar `liberalism proper' that
forcement, the privatisation of security (for those who can afford it) and lawlessness. There is a pre66
The
valent sense of lack of order and bespredel (absence of
peoples emerging from communism had learnt the
limits) that gives rise, as Fish notes, to the absence of
bitter lesson that it is precisely the attempt to fulfil
rights (bespravie) ± `albeit a very different form of
the entire potential of democracy that leads to
bespravie than existed under the Soviet regime,'
absolute servitude. Since the French revolution de-
an absence that in many ways is more substantive
mocracy has been associated with undivided popular
than earlier since it is experienced at the level of
sovereignty, forgetting Tocqueville's warning of the
daily life in a personal way. The denigration of the
`tyranny of the majority'. These lessons are now
state that had accompanied the assault against the
taken to heart, but there are other processes that
communist order was perpetuated in a simplified
undermine the emergence of clear conclusions.
`liberalism proper' that disregarded problems of pub-
Zakaria quotes this argument approvingly.
70
but
As we know, the advance of democracy led to the
lic order and personal security. Post-communist lib-
emergence of a state that is far from minimal and a
erals discovered that the threat to individual liberty
liberalism that embraced interventionism. While
could come as much from an anarchic society as from
Hayek's The Road to Serfdom, with its anti-construc-
an overweaning state or a sovereign people. The
tivist thesis that any state activism in the social
emergence of national liberalism was a response to
sphere provides scope for the development of tota-
this, but more common was support for neo-com-
litarianism, became popular reading in post-commu-
munist, nationalist and other quasi-authoritaran so-
nist countries, the experience of postwar democracy
lutions.
in Japan and the West demonstrated that `planned capitalism and the welfare state helped to avoid
Liberalism and Post-communist Social Democracy
totalitarianism because they contributed decisively to the neutralisation of political movements that carry a model of totalitarian socialism.'
67
Under post-communism the focus has been on re-
Under
storing the elements of classical constitutional lib-
takes
eralism, the critique of political power and the
on an extreme, virulent form at times, in which
attempt to impose restraints on despotism. With
antistatism ± one of the most lucid positions ± turns
equal force post-communist liberalism has had to
into a generalised statephobia, often accompanied by
face the question of the social sources of despotism,
post-communism
`economic
liberalism
68
still
The post-communist
the `tyranny of the majority' and of the masses on the
transitions coincided with the predominance of the
individual. In this context the social liberalism
globalisation
espoused by T. H. Green and his successors ± an
antidemocratic sentiments.' paradigm,
itself
a
recipe
for
state
279
RICHARD SAKWA
evolution that in the United States has redefined the
for this reason that he insisted that the ideology of
very meaning of liberalism to denote interventionist
Russia's modernisation could not be liberalism but
welfare state policies ± has been largely absent.
social democracy.
Sogrin notes that at the basis of the reformist policies
cogent exponent of the view that social democracy
of Russian radicals `lay a simplified Western liberal-
was the only way forward for Russia, remaining loyal
ism, stripped off practically all the humanistic for-
to a modified version of convergence theory, a
mulae of the twentieth century.'
71
76
Dzarasov emerged as the most
The insouciance
compromise (synthesis) of capitalism and socialism,
of the majority of post-communist liberals in the face
Marxism and liberalism. Russian liberalism, in his
of the social traumas of an almost unprecedented
view, was sustained by its ability to convince people
scale in peacetime did much to discredit the liberal
that all evil had arisen from communism, and that all
idea in its entirety.
things good came from the example and the recommendation of the West.
Irving Kristol may well be right to argue that `a conservative is but a liberal attacked by reality'
72
77
A turn away from the
West, however, thus ran the risk of a rejection of
but
liberalism in its entirety.
we can with equal force argue that a liberal is but a conservative attacked by conscience. The problem
It was only after successive electoral defeats and
under post-communism, however, is that this con-
political marginalisation, according to Sogrin, that
science is not well-developed. What liberalism there
social liberalism from 1994 became prominent.
is tends to emerge out of an abstract intellectualism
The social liberals, in sharp contrast to the radical
rather than the commitment to the broad range of
liberals, began to stress issues of social order, became
liberal values. The reconciliation between the so-
supporters of `civilised nationalism' and sought to
cialist striving for social justice and the liberal con-
bridge the gulf that had opened between liberalism
cern
and democracy.
with
individual
liberty
has
not
yet
been
79
78
The problem, however, is deeper
achieved, weakening both in the process. The very
than this. While classical liberalism may well have
notion of equality, which in a sense could be re-
advanced an individualistic view of society, today
garded as the ground for both socialism and sub-
the main actors in advanced democracies are col-
stantive (social) liberalism, has been delegitimated
lective: parties, trade unions, churches, lobby groups
by the experience of Soviet socialism. A `radical
and the government itself. In Russia these collectives
liberal'
considered
have not yet become `interest groups' on the western
any attempt to achieve substantive equality of out-
model; their identity is still Soviet, focused on the
comes, rather than simply `equal starting possibili-
internal management of their affairs rather than on
ties',
the external advancement of their interests. The
approach
as
an
predominated
outbreak
of
that
neo-Soviet
`equality-
73
mongering' (uravnilovka).
constituency for social liberalism remains passive and ideologised, rather than advocatory and struc-
As far as Dzarasov was concerned, a group of `anarcho-liberals' had come to power in Russia.
74
tured.
While extreme liberals in economic affairs, they were
Benedetto Croce is the arch-exponent of a liberal
at the same time destructive of the integrity of the
historicism, reabsorbing the thinking of Giambattista
state.
artificially
Vico into mainstream liberalism, but he is also
foisted on Russia, and that the population does
notable for his attempt to `re-moralise' liberalism,
not recognise the legitimacy of property acquired
endowing it with an ethical charge that was lacking
He
argued
that
capitalism
was
in the course of `mafia-nomenklatura privatisation'.
75
in economic utilitarian approaches. Croce is `Fu-
He insisted that Russia lacked the preconditions for a
kuyama with a conscience'. This trend is important
purely capitalist type of development. The Russian
in Russia, although lacking sustained formal expres-
bourgeoisie in his view was never concerned with the
sion. The conscience of liberalism remains abstract,
good of the country, and that the backbone of the
while the transformative challenge is immediate and
country was represented by hired labour (workers
urgent; the liberal historicist tendency has triumphed
and employees in the trade unions), `honest' entre-
at the expense of its ethical content. Neo-liberalism
preneurs and scientific-technical intelligentsia. It is
has predominated over ethical liberalism.
280
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
with a viable state. This is a harder task than might
Liberalism, the Nation-State and Nationalism
appear at first sight; how is it possible to reconcile
For Roland Axtmann, the only serious basis for
liberal individualism with the collectivism that is an
liberal democracy is the nation-state, but at the same
intrinsic part of nationalist discourse? In Russia the
time, it was enlightenment and liberal values that
issue takes on particular force since the collectivist
sustained the nation-state.
80
Liberalism is the most
ethos is the core of tradition, of history and of
universal of ideologies yet, paradoxically, it is the
politics.
most national in form ± a feature recognised by John
For Will Kymlicka there is not such a stark con-
Stuart Mill, Jules Michelet and Giuseppe Mazzini as
trast between the two principles as some of liberal-
they became the intellectual proponents of liberal
ism's critics have suggested,
nationalism.
81
84
but finding a balance
An appropriate combination of lib-
between collective traditions and individual rights
eralism and nationalism, however, is far from easy, as
remains a problem in many communities. In Dage-
the Frankfurt Assembly in March 1849 discovered to
stan, for example, the enormous burden (both fi-
its cost. After the collapse of the Assembly the link
nancial and emotional) of traditional rituals marking
between liberalism and nationalism in Germany was
the passage of each stage of life has led many to
severed, opening the way to the horrors that fol-
escape into the relative simplicity of the Wahhabi
82
Liberalism's relationship with authority in
form of Islam. Throughout Russia the struggle be-
pre-revolutionary Russia was equally ambivalent,
tween the abstract liberal principles embodied in the
espousing a progressivistic view of history while
constitution of December 1993 and myriad forms of
suspicious of the radical populism and socialism that
inherited collectivist communities (both Soviet and
sought to make historical progress their own. No-
pre-Soviet) represents a profound reorientation of
where were these tensions more apparent than in the
the culture. The tension between the two principles
person of Paul Milyukov, the effective leader of
cannot be wished away, but at the same time it
organised Russian liberalism in the form of the
should not be exaggerated. As the burgeoning lit-
Constitutional Democratic Party (Kadets). Liberal-
erature on identity formation suggests, cultures (like
ism in Russia, it appeared, was subverted even before
identities) are not stable unchanging entities but are
it had begun, unable to sustain itself as an indepen-
in a constant process of adaptation and renegotiation
dent political force or to reconcile the democratic
with the challenges of modernity.
and liberal impulses. Ironically, it was Milyukov's
has made the same point with regard to the mut-
pragmatic application of liberalism to Russian cir-
ability of political culture.
cumstances that brought him down when in 1917 he
communitarian
embraced `state consciousness (gosudarstvennost) and
cannot be reduced
sent off his ill-fated Note reasserting imperial war
and that communities can make enhanced claims
lowed.
aims.
83
thinking
86
85
Stephen Welch
The very resurgence of
suggests
that
to the sovereign
liberalism individual,
More broadly, the democratic revolution in
on an individual without infringing the principles of
Russia was shorn entirely of liberal coloration and
liberal individualism. The problem, of course, is: at
took an extreme Jacobin form. The tension between
what point does communitarianism become collec-
liberalism and democracy was to persist into the post-
tivism (in the negative sense of the term, that is
communist era.
when the community makes demands that undermine individual autonomy in threatening ways)? At
Liberalism requires home grown liberals to proto
what point do the rights of the collective and the
thrive, national cultures to be sustained, and char-
principle of collective rights lead to an anti-liberal
acteristic institutions and individuals to practise it.
collectivism?
mote
it,
specific
socio-economic
conditions
There is clearly a need for a new synthesis of liberal-
The rich vein of post-communist paradoxes does
ism and nationalism under post-communism; if lib-
not end here. While few would now defend the
eralism remains too internationalist, it will fail to
concept of empire (and for early post-communist
find a domestic constituency whose bonds of alle-
liberals it was clear that democracy and empire in the
giance would forge a new synthesis of a free society
old USSR were incompatible), the disintegration of
281
RICHARD SAKWA
the empire was not a sufficient, through probably a
The market, moreover, even in the best of times is
necessary, condition for the emergence of democ-
not a source of loyalty and allegiance (except perhaps
racy. Only the republics appeared to be an appro-
for the most rabid neo-liberals) but the source of
priate vessel in which democratic institutions could
enrichment (for some); people do not die for the
be constructed. As Dankwart Rustow argued, stable
market but they do for the state.
borders are a prerequisite for democracy.
87
Thus out
The attempt to combine patriotism and liberal
of the detritus of empire nation-states were to be
values gave rise to the national liberal tendency, yet
born ± this was one side of the liberal project ± but no
no adequate synthesis occurred, leaving the field
concessions were to be made to nation-state nation-
open to radical rejectionists of the whole new order.
alism ± the other side of liberalism. Even though
Alexander Prokhanov is one of the most eloquent of
Carlton Hayes had long ago argued that liberalism
those who condemn Russia's renewed westernisa-
and nationalism were far from antithetical, oeuvring between these two positions
88
man-
tion. He insists that `today's Westernisers in Russia
provoked
are the liberals and radicals. They are criminals; they 92
many painful contortions. The commitment to de-
are destroying Russia.'
mocracy was an intrinsic part of the formal move-
vanced by Alexander Tarasov when he details the
ment for national rebirth in Russia, and this perhaps
deaths resulting from the events of 3±4 October
made the democratic project rather more resistant to
1993. `This', he argues, `is what liberalism looks like
both nation-state nationalism and ethnic national-
in action.'
ism than in some other post-communist countries.
nationalist intellectuals who `viewed liberalism as
Yet the susceptibility was there, as evidenced for
too individualistic and horribly bourgeois, while
example by the nationalist turn taken by the Russian
democracy encouraged mediocrity and corruption'
Christian Democratic Movement despite its commit-
is shared by many citizens of the post-communist
ment to `enlightened patriotism'. Another example
world. Many, while not rejecting liberalism as such,
is that of the Jews in Russia, traditionally associated
have adopted anti-western, and in particular anti-
with the country's liberal and (especially in the pre-
American, views; modernisation based on Western
revolutionary era) radical movements, who gradually
models has lost its attractiveness.
associated more with Russian patriotic ideas. Ac-
communist years the neo-liberal economic reformers
cording to Dmitry Shlapentokh, `the emergence of
systematically dismantled Russia's ties with its former
this strange and unknown political species, red-to-
partner republics, and the language of national in-
brown Jews, was indicative not so much of a trend
terests was alien to them as they pursued a globalising
among Jews as of a deep crisis in Russian pro-Wes-
agenda. Nevertheless, liberals gradually came to
tern liberalism.'
89
93
A similar viewpoint is ad-
The sentiment of pre-fascist Italian
95
94
In the early post-
appreciate the importance of national identity in
Some key questions remain unanswered. Above
the state-building endeavour. A de-ethnicised de-
all, can an effective Russian state of whatever type be
mocracy did not necessarily mean a denationalised
constructed in the absence of agreement on Russia's
one. It remains to be seen what liberalism with a
historical border, and can a liberal Russia be estab-
Russian face will really look like.
lished if the country retains imperial pretensions outside Russia itself? These are the questions faced
Individualism and Civil Society
by the national liberals in the most acute form possible, perhaps trying to reconcile the irreconcil-
The shift in post-communism is from the aspiration
able. The powers given up by the communist state, to
to achieve an organic collectivist society to an
paraphrase Hoffmann's argument about the Eur-
individualist `civil society'. Civil society was the
opean Union, `have gone not to the new central
slogan of the anti-communist revolution, of course,
90
The liberalism that
and its central features at that time were the ad-
was successful in reducing the state's power, `has
vancement of negative liberty for the individual and
institutions, but to the market.'
91
char-
a public sphere where these individuals organised in
acterised by the eruption of crime and corruption.
civil associations could gather to influence policy.
created a formidable anonymous new power',
282
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
Neither has yet been entirely achieved, and indeed
consumerist version of citizenship has analogously
the
has
withdrawn the subject from the full-blooded political
tended to take on some of the features of Hobbes's
community, but this time it is post-political. The
`war of all against all', a state of nature of pre-liberal
social sphere vacated by the communist state has
and pre-contract societies. There is no guarantee
been filled not by political emancipation but by the
that the free market on its own leads to a free politics.
tyranny of a corrupted neoliberal market.
terrain
of
post-communist
civil
society
From the liberal perspective more broadly the relationship between the individual and the collec-
Conclusion:
tive, the personality (lichnost) and the community,
Systemic or Asystemic Liberalism
is not resolved in general, let alone in Russia. As David Ost puts it in the Polish context, `liberalism is
Does liberalism lack profound roots in the societies
no friend of community', and he goes on to argue
themselves? Is liberalism a systemic prerequisite of
that liberals `are in crisis everywhere in Eastern
post-communist societies, or was it imposed simply as
Europe. It is not so much economic as political
a byproduct of the anti-communist struggle and as a
96
`Negative liberty
function of aspirations to join the international
demands the creation of a social space in which
system? If the former, then despite many tribulations
the choices, preferences and will of each individual
it is here to stay, but if the latter, it is fragile and
liberalism that is in danger.'
97
The `political right to do wrong' is
liable to be swept away by more militant rejectionist
not yet entirely conceded, either from the national
nationalist agendas. Was Szacki indeed right to argue
or the ideological perspective. The agreement to
that liberalism was a specific western phenomenon
disagree was the basis of the modern liberalism
sustained only by the role it played in the anti-
emerging out of the Reformation and Counter-
communist struggle? He probably exaggerates the
Reformation, and the necessity of the principle
argument, especially since he fails to define what
has been amply confirmed by the ideological wars
he means by liberalism, preferring instead to stress its
of the twentieth century. The balance between
situational character. Even in Russia liberalism has a
individual
power
long history, going back at least to Herzen and
and social responsibility is far from having been
sustaining a vigorous literature over legal and local
achieved in post-communist societies.
government reform, and under communism it was far
are sovereign.'
civil
and
human
rights,
state
There is another aspect to post-communist indi-
more than an instrumental ideology to be discarded
viduation, discussed above in the context of con-
at the first opportunity. He is right to argue that
strained liberalism. The process has sometimes been
political liberalism can accommodate various types
described as the transformation of the individual
of property rights, but underestimated the problems
from `comrade' to `citizen'. This is indeed part of
facing
the truth, but an equally profound parallel transfor-
although this is not to say that neoliberal economic
mation is taking place: from `comrade' to `customer',
reforms were the only way forwards. Attempts to
in certain cases missing out the citizenship stage
devise `third path' strategies, however, like those of
altogether, and certainly everywhere undermining
Gay and Alekseeva have not been convincing.
the full political entitlements denoted by the con-
not at all clear whether more gradualist and organic ±
cept of citizenship. The will of the customer takes
indeed, more liberal ± methods would in the long run
priority over the will of the planner, production takes
have secured the future for liberalism as well as the
the place of distribution, and interdependence is
`illiberal' methods actually implemented.
placed above independence ± but where is the
economic
reformers
Post-communist
liberalism
in
marketisation
has,
98
±
It is
paradoxically,
emancipation of which Merquior spoke? While re-
used the power of the state to implement its eco-
ligions hold that there is a natural subject situated
nomic programme ± indeed, as Szacki would argue,
within the religious community itself and indepen-
hardly a demonstration of the triumph of liberalism.
dent of the particularities of the state-society rela-
Political
tionship (i.e. that this subject is pre-political), the
glected: the `universalist' principles of the post-com-
283
liberalism,
however,
has
not
been
ne-
RICHARD SAKWA
munist international community have been rein-
power communism of Gennadii Zyuganov and the
forced by the attempts by all Eastern European states
Communist Party of the Russian Federation (CPRF).
(including Russia) to return to Europe and the world.
As Sogrin puts it:
However, their implementation has often fallen far short of declarations, giving rise to an illiberal and
Radical liberalism was able to destroy the supports
constrained democracy of the regime system. The
of
democratisation of liberalism has yet to be secured.
breakthrough into market relations. But it became
At the same time, the basic principles of liberalism ±
increasingly clear that the radical liberal approach
individualism, tolerance, private property, pluralism,
to reconstructing Russia on the classical Western
restraints on state power ± have gained broader
model is nothing less than a utopia, and that in
support than people like Szacki and others who insist
Russian conditions radical liberalism leads to the
on a primordial collectivism and authoritarianism in
socio-economic polarisation of society and the
Poland or Russia would concede. The communist
poverty of the majority and enshrines the power
regimes did not simply perpetuate traditional pat-
of bureaucratic nomenklatura capitalism.
communism and helped
Russia
achieve
a
99
terns of authoritarianism; communist authoritativeness was based on thoroughly modern principles.
In its place a social liberalism emerged, but what was
Indeed, in yet another of those paradoxes that mark
really required according to him was a national
the post-communist world, in the social sphere the
liberalism. The challenge perhaps is even greater
communist period helped clear the way for liberalism
than this: to combine the political constitution of
by destroying the old aristocratic ethos of the old
liberty, the social basis for equal citizenship, the
Russian and Polish ruling classes.
patriotic consensus for national integration, and
However weak post-communist liberalism might
the developmental basis to allow the conversion
be, in Poland it was able to force the adaptation of
of constrained transformative liberalism into a gen-
the post-communist communists to its programme,
uine emancipatory liberalism.
while in Russia it has defeated (so far) the great
Notes
13. Ibid., p. 15.
1. Gellner, `Introduction', in Gellner and Cansino (eds)
14. This is examined by Pantin (1997).
(1996), pp. 1±4, at p. 3. 2. Fukuyama (1989), (1992).
15. Szacki (1995), chapter 5.
3. Helio Jaguaribe, `Merquior and Liberalism', in Gellner
16. Ost (1991), p. 91.
and Cansino (eds) (1996), pp. 21±36, at p. 24; in the
17. See ibid.
same volume see also Roberto Campos, `Merquior the
18. Solzhenitsyn (1974).
Liberalist', pp. 65±76, at p. 72.
19. Radio Free Europe/Radio Liberty, `Newsline', 10 August 1998.
4. Ibid., pp. 21±36. 5. Ibid., p. 32.
20. Schieder (1962), p. 39.
6. V. V. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii: peripetii i perspek-
21. See Russia Briefing, 12 February 1997, pp. 6±7.
tivy', Obshchestvennyie nauki i sovremmenosti, 1, 1997,
22. Fish (1997).
p. 13.
23. Aleksandr Buzgalin, `Right Cause: You Are Not Right, Gentlemen', Jamestown Foundation Prism, vol. V
7. Nodari A. Simonia, `Priorities of Russian Foreign
(14), part 6, 16 July 1999.
Policy and the Way It Works', in Dawisha and
24. Bellamy (1992).
Dawisha (eds) (1995), p. 17. 8. Ibid., p. 18.
25. Balcerowicz (1995).
9. Hough (1997), pp. 1±2 and passim.
26. Klaus (1997). 27. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii' p. 17 (see note 6 above).
10. Lev Timofeev, `Bol'shaya rastrata, in Izvestiya, 26
28. Rustam Narzikulov, Nezavisimaya gazeta, 11 March
February 1993.
1997.
11. Lev Timofeev, `Vse russko pechal'no', in Izvestiya, 31
29. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii' p. 21 (see note 6 above).
October 1995.
30. Lebed's ideas are outlined in Izvestiya, 24, 31 May
12. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii', p. 14 (see note 6 above).
284
LIBERALISM AND POST-COMMUNISM
1996 and Za derzhavu obidnu (Moscow: Moskovskaya
58. O'Donnell (1994), p. 59.
pravda, 1985). An analysis of his views is Vladimir
59. For example, Vladimir Gel'man, `Regional'nye rezhi-
Polushin, General Lebed ± zagadka Rossii (Moscow,
my: zavershenie transformatsii?', Svobodnaya mysl', 9,
1996).
1996, pp. 13±22; `Stanovlenie regional'nykh rezhimov v Rossii', NG-stsenarii, 19 September 1996, p.
31. Cited in Institute for East±West Studies, Russian
5.
Regional Report, vol. 2 (11), 20 March 1997.
60. As put by Roberto Campos in Gellner and Cansino
32. Ibid.
(eds) (1996), p. 73.
33. Szacki (1995), p. 150.
61. Radio Free Europe/Radio Liberty, `Newsline', 20 Feb-
34. Radzislawa Gortat, `Liberalizm jako Konstruktywizm',
ruary 1998.
in Przegland Spoleczny 6, 1992, cited in Szacki (1995),
62. Huntington (1993) and his later book (1996).
p. 154.
63. See, above all, Borneman (1997); Kritz (ed.) (1995);
35. This is above all the argument of David Ost, `Shaping a New Politics in Poland: Interests and Politics
Pogany (1998).
in Post-Communist Europe', Programme on Central
64. Mill (1972), p. 71.
and
65. Ibid., pp. 72±3.
East
Europe
Working
Paper
8
(Centre
for
European Studies, Harvard University, 1991), pp.
66. Cited in Zakaria (1997), p. 30.
4±5.
 Merquior, `A Panoramic View on the Renais67. Jose sance of Liberalisms', in Gellner and Cansino (eds)
36. Bellamy (1994), p. 420. For John Gray's view, see
(1996), pp. 7±20, at pp. 11±12.
Gray (1986), chapter 1. And for Hayek's own sum-
68. Ibid., p. 9.
mary of his position, see Hayek (1993), volume 1, p. 5.
69. Dietze (1985), p. 1; Fish, (1997), pp. 208±9, draws on
37. Walicki (1991), p. 106.
Dietze to make the same point.
38. Jerzy Hausner and Jacek Kuron, Strategia Negocjacyjina w Procesie Transformacji Gospodarki (Warsaw:
70. Fish (1997), p. 208.
Stefan Batory Foundation, 1994), p. 26. I am grate-
71. Vladimir Sogrin, `Zapadnyi liberalizm i Rossiiskie reformy', Svobodnaya mysl', 1, 1996, p. 43.
ful to Nick Spiro for drawing my attention to this
72. Quoted by Merquior, `A Panoramic View on the
debate.
Renaissance of Liberalisms', in Gellner and Cansino
39. Andrei Kolesnikov, `Liberalizm umer, da zdravstvuet
(eds) (1996), p. 7.
liberaliz!', Novoe vremya, 12 (1997), p. 15, cites the case of St Petersburg when Vladimir Yakovlev re-
73. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii', p. 16 (see note 6 above).
placed the `liberal' Anatolii Sobchak as mayor but
74. Soltan Dzarasov, `Liberalizm ili sotsial-demokratizm?', in Svobodnaya mysl', 4, 1996, p. 28.
was soon forced to pursue similar policies.
75. Ibid., p. 26.
40. Jan Krzysztof Bielecki interviewed by Nick Spiro,
76. Ibid., p. 31.
London, 2 August 1996.
77. Ibid., p. 31.
41. This theme is explored in the doctoral dissertation by Nick Spiro, The Politics of Economic Transition: Shock
78. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii', p. 18 (see note 6 above).
Therapy in Poland, 1990±1991, University of Kent at
79. Ibid., p. 19.
Canterbury, June 1998.
80. Axtmann (1996).
42. Rychard (1992), p. 144.
81. See Hoffmann (1995), p. 162.
43. Cited by Jadwiga Staniszkis in Staniskis (1991), p.
82. The point is made by Robert Taylor, `Springtime for Hitler?', in Prospect, March 1998, p. 13.
184. 44. Ibid.
83. Stockdale (1996).
45. Holc (1997).
84. Kymlicka (1989).
46. Ibid., p. 402.
85. For a particularly rich debate of the issue, see Rajchman (1995).
47. Ibid., p. 427. 48. Ibid., p. 416.
86. Welch (1993).
49. Zakaria (1997), p. 23.
87. Rustow (1970).
50. Boris Kagarlitskii, `Levye v Rossii: nadezhdy, neuda-
88. Hayes (1949). 89. Dmitry Shlapentokh, ` ``Red-to-Brown'' Jews and Rus-
chi, bor'ba', in Svobodnaya mys', 11, 1994, p. 33.
sian Liberal Reform', in The Washington Quarterly,
51. Ibid.
21(4), Autumn 1998, p. 112.
52. Boris Kagarlitskii, `Vremya neopravdavshikhsy na-
90. See Hoffmann (1995), p. 165.
dezhd', Svobodnaya mysl', 3, 1997, p. 10. 53. Zakaria (1997), p. 22.
91. Ibid., p. 175.
54. Ibid., pp. 25±26.
92. Alexander Prokhanov interviewed, `Western Values Âs', in Transitions, August 1997, p. 77. are Cliche
55. Ibid., p. 28.
93. Aleksandr Tarasov, `Striptiz liberalov', in Svobodnaya
56. O'Donnell (1994), p. 59.
mysl', 10, 1997, pp. 106±114, at p. 110.
57. O'Donnell (1993), p. 1367.
285
RICHARD SAKWA
97. Gregory R. Johnson, `Modernity and Postmodernity in
94. Richard Bellamy, `How Not to Make Italians', in
 Merquior', in Gellner and Canthe Thought of Jose
Times Literary Supplement, 22 December 1995, p. 12.
sino (eds) (1996), pp. 37±63, at p. 55.
95. Sogrin, `Zapadnyi liberalizm i Rossiiskie reformy, pp.
98. Gay and Alekseeva (1996).
32±3 (see note 71 above).
99. Sogrin, `Liberalizm v Rossii', p. 20 (see note 6 above).
96. Ost (1991), p. 85.
286
21
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS Brian Baxter
the call of liberals for the neutrality of the state with
I
respect to substantive views of the good life. Indi-
Throughout its long history liberalism has been
vidual persons are to be allowed, as far as is compa-
concerned almost exclusively with matters of human
tible with their all being allowed to do so, to pursue
well-being in so far as these are affected by social,
their own distinctive view of the good life. Each
economic and political arrangements. Until very
individual counts equally with all others, and no
recently virtually nothing has been said by liberals
one's view of the good life is to be accorded greater
about the issue to which Green political theorising so
weight than those of other individuals. For the
vehemently directs our attention, namely that of
liberal, the heart of morality is this impartiality
human relations with the natural context within
between persons.
1
The reason
Different individuals will have different value
for this neglect does not seem hard to find. It appears
commitments. Certainly, some may seek to attribute
to stem from the fact that the fundamental value of
non-instrumental value to the non-human, natural
liberalism is that of the pursuit by individuals of
world, and to seek to live lives in which the im-
personal projects which they have freely chosen for
plications of such valuing are worked out. But some
themselves.
may deny any such value, and seek to treat the non-
which all human action takes place.
Although on this planet these individuals com-
human world purely on the basis of what conduces to
prise solely members of the human species, in fact for
human well-being. For liberalism, such arguments
liberalism it is specifically personhood, in whichever
about which values should command our allegiance
species that is to be found, which is the crucial
are, of course, to be allowed and encouraged, and the
element. Persons are, by definition, entities able to
possibility of persuading others to our view of things
exercise certain kinds of choice over the pursuit of
must always be left open (with some tricky issues
their life-plans, and it is persons with which liberal-
about toleration's limits remaining an ongoing mat-
ism has exclusively concerned itself. Non-human
ter of debate). De facto universal agreement on
creatures and entities are noticed by liberalism pri-
substantive values is, thus, compatible with liberal-
marily as resources for human persons. At most the
ism provided the possibility of disagreement breaking
capacity for suffering which some of them possess has
out is always left open by, for example, the main-
been regarded as a source of certain kinds of limita-
tenance of free speech, freedom of conscience and
tions upon how precisely persons may put them to
the rest.
use ± limitations we call, revealingly, `humaneness'.
The view of values which is operating here is one
From this person-centred standpoint has emerged
which sees them as anthropogenic, originating in
287
BRIAN BAXTER
human (person) acts of valuing, and as anthropo-
clearly needed in order to establish for individual
centric, with human well-being as the fundamental
human beings some compelling sense that acting in
touchstone of what is good. Thus, even individuals
accordance with E will achieve for them, and the
who attribute intrinsic value to nature are inter-
individuals about whom they care most, a form of
preted as really finding a kind of `higher' (aesthetic,
human life which will be satisfying and fulfilling.
spiritual, non-practical) instrumental value for hu-
Without some such claim ecocentrists will lack a
man beings in the natural world.
connection between their fundamental value-postulate E and what Thomas Nagel has identified as the
On this view, then, liberalism treats environmen-
2
tal concerns in the way it treats any other substan-
`personal' standpoint,
tive value positions: they are located within the
the consciousness of self-aware beings such as our-
structures of individual preference and left to the
selves.
processes of liberal democratic politics for resolution.
Whether
they
should
lead
to
which always characterises
Liberalism, by contrast, makes this connection
wholesale
quite straightforwardly, for its basic value postulate
changes in human practices is a matter upon which
amounts to an endorsement of the importance of
liberalism, as such, has no view, save in one regard:
precisely that standpoint. It is true that, as liberalism
it is committed to opposing any changes which
also contends, we can, and must, also adopt the
threaten its fundamental value of individual choice
`impersonal' or universal standpoint, which is what
of life-project. Only when such changes are neces-
we do when we enunciate for general acceptance
sary to avert clear danger to the very survival of
liberalism's own fundamental value postulate. But for
human beings (persons) would liberalism permit
much of the time such impersonal conceptions are
them, temporarily and reluctantly, until the danger
weak sources of human motivation and always run
is past.
the risk of being trumped by the requirements of the
At least some Green political theorists will be
`personal' standpoint.
3
unhappy with this standpoint, for it appears to
The difficulty for the ecocentrist, of course, is that
accord no fundamental value to the non-human
on the face of it principle E sets out precisely to
world of nature. In particular, the position known
eschew the `personal' standpoint entirely and to bid
as ecocentrism, to which many Green thinkers have
people to adopt a point of view with respect to non-
given their allegiance, directly contradicts the liberal
human nature which completely leaves behind hu-
fundamental value postulate, for it enunciates the
man interests and concerns, including their personal
following rival basic proposition:
ones. Ecocentrism, then, needs a way of fusing the
[E] The non-human natural world has intrinsic
personal and impersonal standpoints. The view to
value, independent of its instrumental impor-
be defended below is that the key to this lies in
tance for human well-being.
developing the concept, whose importance to liberalism has already been noted, of personhood and
In other words, ecocentrism rejects the liberal inter-
relating it to non-human nature. In the course of
pretation of the attribution of intrinsic value to
doing this, however, we discover that the apparently
nature as really being the attribution to it of various
clear-cut distinction between anthropocentric (or
`higher'
personcentric) and ecocentric positions disappears,
forms
of
instrumental
value
for
human
beings.
and that reasons can be found within the liberal
However, ecocentrism is not the only possible
perspective for endorsing at a fundamental level the
basis for the development of a Green political theory.
kinds of value which Green theorists have so ar-
This is just as well, for ecocentrism faces rather severe
dently brought to political theorists' attentions. The
difficulties which I will try to explore. These centre
aims of liberalism and Green political theory turn out
on the problem of establishing an intrinsic connec-
not to be so completely at odds as appeared to be the
tion between principle E above and a conception of
case at first sight, provided that Greens accept the
human well-being or flourishing. This connection is
abandonment of pure ecocentrism, and liberals ac-
288
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS
cept Green arguments for a revised formulation of
dividually or as a species (domestic animals in factory
personhood.
farms, for example). Also, the kind of interconnectedness between ourselves and non-human life-forms is important
II
when we are considering our attitudes to non-human
Before developing this position, however, we need
nature. The science of ecology suggests the connec-
first to consider some arguments explored by Robyn
tions are physical and biological, via `energy path-
Eckersley,
4
which seek to elucidate and defend the
ways' for example. However, it is arguable that
ecocentric position in a rather different way, one
ecocentrists really need to establish interconnected-
which might be seen as reinterpreting such key
ness between human beings and non-human nature
liberal values as autonomy by finding ecocentric
at the level of value or meaning. The focus should
versions of them. It is a feature of the suggestions
thus be on the kinds of meaning ± moral, aesthetic,
she explores that they operate in such a way that the
religious, and so on ± which non-human nature can
intrinsic value of non-human nature is directly con-
have for people. Only thus is it going to be possible to
nected to human flourishing. Hence, if such argu-
establish the right kind of connection between prin-
ments work, then the above-noted difficulties faced
ciple E and the concept of human flourishing, which is
by ecocentrism ought to disappear. As will now be
value-laden and permeated with a concern with
contended, these arguments do not succeed and thus
meaning. One suggestion along these lines which Eckersley
a different mode of reconciling the personal and
explores is the ecofeminist claim that at least be-
impersonal standpoints will be required. Eckersley's discussion begins with the observation
tween one group of human beings ± women ± and
that ecocentrism takes its cue from the ecologically
non-human nature there is a connection of mean-
informed philosophy of the internal relatedness of
ing.
life forms within ecosystems, according to which
giving natures, are more `in tune' than men are with
`there are no absolutely discrete entities and no
natural processes. Thus they will find the caring and
absolute dividing lines between the living and the
nurturing attitude to non-human nature required by
non-living.'
5
6
Women, with their nurturing, caring and life-
the full recognition of E to be congenial and con-
Acceptance of this viewpoint in turn
ducive to their own fulfilment as women.
leads to an ethic of general emancipation, according
There may be truth in the claim that human
to which all beings should be permitted to fulfil themselves in accordance with their natures ± a
beings
principle which will apply both to human beings
and nurturing will find the forms of life enjoined
whose
self-understanding
involves
caring
and to non-human nature. We should note that such
by ecocentrists to be congenial in this way. But it is
a principle clearly chimes with the liberal concern
clear that this is a contingent fact about them, if it is
for human self-development embodied in its funda-
a fact at all. There seems to be no incoherence in the
mental postulate even though, as we have seen,
idea of a being whose caring and nurturing instincts
liberalism restricts its concerns in this regard solely
are directed only to its own kind, as is true of nearly
to human beings.
all non-human forms of life, for example. And in the
However, the ecological principle of intercon-
human case it is at least arguable that caring and
nectedness appealed to by Eckersley does not seem
nurturing comes most naturally, for both males and
to be straightforwardly related to the principle of
females, though on occasion for neither, with respect
general emancipation which is supposed to unite
to their own offspring and relations.
7
human and non-human flourishing. For all that
A more general kind of approach to the problem is
`interconnectedness' shows, it seems possible for
explored by Eckersley via direct consideration of the
the flourishing of some beings to require that others
concept, hotly debated between liberals and socia-
do not flourish (parasites, for example); or for the
lists, of autonomy. According to her, the key move is
flourishing of some beings to require only that others
to expand the concept of the `self' whose autonomy
exist, but not that they should flourish, either in-
is characterised in the classic Kantian terms as `living
289
BRIAN BAXTER
in accordance with self-imposed principle.'
8
What
autonomy as an exercise of rationality.
12
This may
this expansion seems to mean is, in effect, accepting
not be the only possible concept of rationality, but it
that non-human nature has its own capacity for
is one which excludes the attribution of autonomy to
autonomy. Non-human life-forms have their own
creatures believed to be devoid of the requisite kinds
ways of living and modes of being. Respect for
of rationality. Kant's argument is that since we must
autonomy in general thus requires respect for the
value our own rationality, as a condition of the
modes of living of such beings and underpins the
meaningfulness of our own existence, and since
project of `general emancipation' already alluded to
rationality is a matter of consistency ± not making
above.
a distinction without a difference ± we cannot value
The focus on autonomy, and the expansion of its
our own rationality without thereby committing
application mooted by Eckersley, allow her to estab-
ourselves to valuing the rationality of others, for
lish a link between principle E and human flourish-
to fail to do that would be making a distinction
ing. She argues that since ecocentrism is committed,
without a difference, and thus failing to value ra-
by its acceptance of E and the expanded concept of
tionality.
13
autonomy, to the project of general emancipation for
There is a problem about trying to rework this
all creatures, it necessarily also supports the condi-
argument if we do not understand autonomy as an
tions conducive to the exercise by humans of their
exercise of rationality, but instead regard it as synon-
autonomy. Giving this concept in turn what is in
ymous with the concept of self-renewal/production.
effect a socialist gloss, she then suggests that this
Certainly one can intelligibly claim that we must
commits ecocentrists to the pursuit of social justice in
each value our own self-renewing capacities, for we
human societies.
9
cannot have meaningful lives if we go out of ex-
Now these ideas are not pursued very far by
istence. However, this in no way commits us to the
Eckersley and it is, of course, a serious problem with
valuation of the self-renewing capacities of other
the suggestion she makes that it is not entirely clear
entities. We may, of course, value their self-renewing
what is meant by extending the Kantian sense of
capacities for instrumental reasons of our own, but that
autonomy (the `following of self-imposed principle')
does not amount to viewing them as possessing
to creatures which do not seem able to impose
intrinsic values, and in any case is a value-attribution
principles upon themselves in any sense.
exercise which requires us to consider each case on its
Another attempt at elucidating how one might
own (instrumental) merits. We are not committed to
reasonably arrive at an extension of the concept of
a blanket valuing of all self-renewing entities by our
autonomy to non-humans, thus motivating accep-
instrumental valuation of the self-renewing capacities
tance of the general emancipation principle, is via
of some of them. Thus Kant's argument works, if it
what Eckersley refers to as `Autopoietic Intrinsic
does, because of the peculiar logic of the concept of
10
In her account of it, the
rationality. It is plain that this concept is not in-
key claim of AIV is that non-human nature is
volved in the idea of self-renewing/producing beings
capable of being self-renewing and that self-renewing
and so it is hard to see how we can be argued into
entities are `ends-in-themselves'. This is another of
accepting the intrinsic value of entities just in so far as
Kant's
they instantiate this concept.
Value' (AIV) theory.
classical
characterisations
of
autonomous
beings ± beings which possess intrinsic, or noninstrumental,
value.
11
Hence
we
should
14
A further view, labelled `transpersonal ecology' by Eckersley,
extend
15
does not aim at argument to convince us
the concept of autonomy to non-human nature,
to accept E, she tells us, but rather attempts to
even to entities such as ecosystems, for they too
produce psychological conversion to the ecocentrist
possess self-producing or renewing capacities.
viewpoint. It does this by developing an extended
However, Kant's argument to persuade autono-
`sense of self'. That is, in the manner adumbrated by
mous agents to value the autonomy of others begins
Arne Naess, transpersonal ecologists seek to encou-
with the demonstration of the importance of one's
rage us to identify with non-human nature so that its
own autonomy, and then turns on the view of
flourishing and ours become one and the same.
290
16
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS
There are some obvious problems with this idea,
the key ideas is not the only one available. This may
especially given that it is supposed to lead us to
not seem possible at first because we appear to be
identify not just with aspects of non-human nature
faced with two contradictory requirements:
which possess a mentality and resemble us in various 1. that we `make over' the world so that it
respects, such as primates and higher mammals, but also with entities which we can only grasp via the
expresses ourselves to ourselves and to others;
possession of quite sophisticated theory and which
2. that we respect non-human nature by maintaining its processes intact as far as possible.
(on most views of the matter) are devoid of mentality, such as species and ecosystems. One can certainly care about such things: seek to preserve
Here, (a) seems to imply that we countenance
them, respecting and marvelling at them. But how
wholesale
feasible is it to identify with them, to regard them as
whereas (b) seems to imply that this be kept to a
in some sense part of ourselves?
minimum. However, it is arguable that in the con-
interference
with
non-human
nature,
There is one way in which this might be con-
text of our present world, (b) is to be regarded as
ceived to happen which I will now outline, although
being as much a manifestation of human making and
it is a way with which ecocentrists may not be
self-expression as would be the effort to convert the
entirely happy. It is possible to undergo an extension
whole of non-human nature into a global garden
of the sense of self with respect to at least some
city.
entities devoid of mentality. People, for example,
This is because, on any account, wilderness will
often seem to experience this with respect to their
not continue to exist, species will not survive, the
automobiles. However, it appears to be a condition
atmosphere and oceans will not remain unpolluted
of this happening that (1) there should be physical
unless human beings make strenuous and protracted
control of the entity concerned via the human body
efforts to secure these aims. If we do successfully
(the automobile is experienced as an extension of
achieve
the human body); (2) the external appearance of the
count as manifestations of praxis. And, as is inherent
entity needs to be regarded as a direct expression of
in the very idea of praxis, we will have remade
the human self in question (it `makes a statement'
ourselves in the course of this `making over' of our
about the owner).
world. It is perhaps not too strained to suggest that it
them,
then
they
can
unproblematically
If one were to generalise this idea to the relations
will be precisely a sense of our identity with non-
between the human self and non-human nature then
human nature, whose (continued) existence will
it implies (1) that we identify with non-human
then be in a clear sense our achievement and an
nature in so far as it is viewed as an extension of
expression of our values, which will then be attained.
our physical selves via our manipulation of it, which
In a nutshell, a world which shows as few obvious
suggests in turn the necessity for artefactuality; (2)
effects of human artefactuality as possible will, in
that we need to convert it into a symbolic expression
modern conditions, be the largest artefact we can
of our personal psychology, again requiring that it be
achieve. Such an artefact will be conceivable by us as
`made over' by us. These ideas are, of course, central
an extension of our (collective) personality and as
to the Hegelian/Marxist theme of the overcoming of
something which reflects that personality back to us.
alienation by praxis.
Non-human nature and the human world will then have been totally fused.
On the face of it, these suggestions are unwelcome to the ecocentrist position because they look to be a
There are, however, various problems with this
version of the Enlightenment theme of rendering
hypothesis. From the ecocentric point of view it
non-human nature entirely subservient to human
perhaps still looks too anthropocentric, as if it in-
purposes and needs when what is needed, according
volved the claim that the only way in which we can
to ecocentrists, is respect for non-human nature
be brought to recognise the value of non-human
because of its intrinsic value. But it may be feasible
nature is by making it an instrument of our human
to argue that the Enlightenment interpretation of
personality. Also, the hypothesis posits an enlarged
291
BRIAN BAXTER
sense of self as the result of the implementation of the
tionary thought that the `ecological' concept of the
Green project. But it does nothing to show people
person ought to be developed out of existing con-
why they should now embark upon such a protracted
cepts of the person with which people are reasonably
and difficult project in a situation where large num-
familiar.
bers of them do not have such a wider sense of self.
existing concepts is unlikely to have the appeal
18
A concept which makes no contact with
One point must be made at this juncture, now that
necessary to motivate action. The second is the
we have surveyed various suggestions for establishing
question of how persons, as opposed to the animal
the connection between principle E and human
species Homo sapiens, are to be shown to be part of
flourishing. We have looked at ecofeminist argu-
nature. As members of that animal species we are
ments, autopoietic intrinsic value theory and trans-
interconnected with non-human nature. But what is
personal ecology. I have indicated why they should
the significance of that fact for the persons which we
be regarded as not adequate to do the job required.
also are?
However, it should be noted that they all seek to
To answer this question we need to say rather
establish a connection between principle E and hu-
more about what a person is. The following char-
man flourishing by seeking to effect an identity,
acterisation, drawn from the European tradition of
partial or whole, between human beings and non-
philosophical and social-scientific thought to be
human nature. This suggests that the ecocentric/
found in thinkers such as Hobbes, Kant, Rousseau,
anthropocentric distinction has ceased to have any
Hegel and Marx, picks out the features essential to
real meaning. The defence of principle E turns out
personhood. Some of them are of direct relevance to
always to involve appeal to something of prime
our problem:
importance for human beings too, so that the idea of non-human nature's having intrinsic value, irre-
A person is a self-conscious being, with the
spective of human concerns, has become very un-
following abilities all being implicit in the posses-
clear. When we put non-human nature at the centre
sion of self-consciousness:
we find that we put ourselves there too. The real issue, therefore, is which of the ideological rivals has
1. to formulate intentions and determine how to
the most adequate conception of humanity, not
carry them out efficiently;
whether ecocentrism is superior to anthropocentrism
2. to develop a concept of self-interest and to
or personcentrism. As will shortly emerge, this also
pursue self-interest so conceived;
suggests a way in which the fundamental liberal
3. to commit itself to values and to criticise itself
value postulate may be interpreted so as to recognise
in the light of failure to realise those values to
and absorb the point of the ecocentric endeavour.
which it has committed itself;
However, before we reach that point we still need
4. to differentiate between itself and others of its
an argument to establish the connection between E
kind;
and the concept of human flourishing which can
5. to participate with others of its kind in creating
give people the motivation to undertake the Green
a culture of shared values and the associated
form of praxis. In the next section I will try to find
customs, traditions and institutions which em-
such an argument.
body those values.
19
It is a corollary of these features of personhood that
III
the prime focus of interest for persons is other persons
The point made at the end of the last section is
of the same kind. For it is from them that the values,
recognised in effect by Eckersley when she suggests
principles and conceptions come in the light of
that what is required is a new, ecological concept of
which the individual person formulates its projects,
the self, in which persons are related to, not set apart
criticises and assesses itself.
from, non-human nature.
17
20
Thus it is natural for persons to regard the nonperson context within which they are embedded as
Two points immediately arise. One is the cau-
292
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS
primarily, or essentially, vehicles for interpersonal
On the face of it this looks to be a highly im-
interaction. Hence one might well argue that it is not
plausible claim. Imagine that our world was made
anthropocentrism, conceived of as a viewpoint with
completely over into an entirely urbanised form,
its roots in Judeo-Christian and Enlightenment-phi-
with monocultural agriculture to sustain it, with
losophical modes of thought, which is the main cause
wilderness and wildlife existing only in zoos, genetic
of human persons' attitude of domination towards
banks, on film and in virtual-reality theatres. This
nature. Rather, if the above characterisation of
surely would be a description of a world in which
persons is correct, then persons of whatever species,
human culture had become all-pervasive, rather than
wherever they live in space and time, will tend to
one in which it had become impossible.
have that attitude towards the non-person world.
At this point, however, the possibility arises of
Thus, if any attitude is the problem here it is the
formulating what one might call the transcendental
attitude referred to at the start of this discussion as
deduction of the category of culture.
`personcentrism'.
here is that the resources for human culture (the
21
The key claim
If this charge is correct, then the question ob-
culture of a particular group of persons) must be non-
viously arises as to whether persons can ever avoid
human (non-personal). This is because it is impos-
personcentrism. It might be the case, for example,
sible for there to be a source of culture which was
that members of the human species could only avoid
entirely person-based. A world consisting only of
personcentrism by seeking to avoid being persons
persons would have no wherewithal to formulate
entirely, perhaps by trying to become purely `natural'
values, principles or purposes. This in turn is because,
beings, like non-human animals, locked into some
as the analysis at the start of this section indicates,
suitable ecological niche, living only for the moment
`personhood' can only be formulated in purely formal
and at the level of instinct. The cost of doing so
terms. If, per impossibile, a group of persons were to
would appear to be the destruction of the kind of
exist who were only persons, and not embodied in
mental life essential to personhood. However, as
some animal species located in some ecosystem on
long as the above-noted abilities remain intact the
some planet, they could not generate culture because
suppression of their exercise will be a very tall order.
they could not generate anything. Persons require to
The question which needs to be addressed, then, is
be embodied to become determinate enough to
whether it is possible for persons intelligibly to
develop the self-consciousness, intentionality, value
conceive of the non-person world as something more
and cultures which give them substantial existence.
22
than a mere vehicle for interpersonal interaction. It
The content and meaning of their purposes and
would clearly be very helpful for the ecocentric case
values then comes from their embodiment in a
if it were possible to establish a link between non-
context of extra-personal nature. The categories
human nature and personhood which was intrinsic
which human beings have used to establish their
to and ± at least in part ± determining of the very
particular aims and values are thus necessarily drawn
nature of personhood. Further, this should ideally be
from the animalian predicament of embodied per-
an intrinsic connection whose recognition by per-
sons inhabiting a non-human natural context ±
sons would lead naturally to humility before non-
`mighty hunter, feeder of my people'; `great builder';
human nature and a compassionate concern for its
scientist (`tamer of nature'); artist and priest (inter-
existence and well-being.
preters of nature's meanings). Non-human nature,
The beginnings of an answer may well be found in
then, has to be viewed as a concrete matrix of
ability (5) in the characterisation of persons noted
opportunity and opposition to give specific content
above. Persons are essentially culture-creators. Is it
to human values and purposes, and to furnish the
possible to argue that non-human nature is essen-
essential context within which human persons can
tially that out of which culture is created? If it were
`crystallise out' a sense of what they are, derived from
so, then if non-human nature were to be removed
their joint construction of a culture of artefacts and
there would be no person-created culture, and with
symbols, necessarily using their
no culture there would be no persons at all.
interpretations of non-human nature to do so.
293
experiences and
BRIAN BAXTER
This is the theme of `praxis overcoming aliena-
have an interest in as wide a range of species and
tion' again, but with the additional claim now
habitats continuing to exist as possible to provide
emerging that it is essential to culture and to person-
objects of study, sources of data and arenas for the
hood that what is alien should never be `made over'
testing of theories. Arguably it is from many of the
in its entirety, for then the material out of which
disciplines
culture, and hence personhood, is made disappears
which directly study non-human nature that we
and when that happens culture and personhood
are obtaining insights into our own nature as embo-
disappear too.
died persons. Many forms of art, too, need non-
and
subdisciplines
in
those
sciences
However, isn't this claim overblown? Even if the
human nature as a source of subject-matter and of
above argument is successful, does it not show only
design ideas, even in the practical design of artefacts.
that persons need non-human nature to get culture
Obviously, this applies to landscape painting, but it is
under way? Surely, however, once cultural creation is
essential to the development of any art with a strong
initiated then there is no essential need for non-
visual component, including architecture and dance.
human nature to remain as a sustainer of culture?
The endless variety of nature is essential here, as a
Why should not the cultural life of persons achieved
continuing source of forms, designs and motifs.
in the maximally person-transformed world outlined
The example of the art of painting may help to
above simply continue for as long as there are human
elucidate and support this claim. Can paintings be
beings in existence?
made entirely out of the experience of other paint-
We need to try to show, then, that human cultures
ings? It is certainly arguable that painters initially
cannot be sustained purely from cultural materials by
acquire the idea of what painting is from their
means of one, or both, of the following two processes:
encounters
with
existing
paintings,
encounters
which they can then use as launching-pads for their own works.
1. reflection, exploration and experimentation internal to a culture;
23
But it is clear that the painter needs to
return unfailingly to non-human nature in order to
2. encounters with other cultures: dialectical in-
replenish the wellsprings of painting. Even the de-
terplay; absorption; collage.
velopment of new schemata and new artistic vocabularies requires the painter to have encounters with
A culture is a more-or-less dynamic complex of
non-human nature in order to provide the elements
interrelated elements encompassing the following
experienced under the schemata, and this is no less
categories: language, art, religion and philosophy,
true of non-representational painting.
science and technology, economic and political
In reply to these considerations the point might be
systems, customs and traditions. (More rudimentary
made that such aspects of our own culture as appear
cultures will not have developed under science, but
to need direct confrontation with non-human nature
all cultures develop the other categories to a degree.)
conceived as such are by no means universal: not
The first point to make is that many cultural
everyone is interested in them. Also, there are plenty
activities under these headings do require a context
of ingredients in our culture ± many games, for
of non-human nature directly in order to exist at all
example ± which do not appear to need the con-
or to be fully intelligible. Within our own culture, for
tinued flourishing of non-human nature to provide
example, such widely popular activities as rambling,
them with meaning and purpose. So are not these
hill-walking,
and
points too weak to establish the necessity for human
hunting need non-human nature (albeit a nature
culture of the existence of non-human nature? Surely
which is often extensively made over by human
activities such as those mentioned may fade away
hands) to be feasible. Some scientific disciplines ±
without there being any significant diminution in
biology, ecology, ornithology, zoology and botany,
the cultural possibilities left to us?
mountaineering,
bird-watching
for example ± take non-human nature as their direct
However, the existence of such cultural activities
object of study. It is clear from the very idea of `sites
alerts us to the possibility of a Rawlsian-style defence
of special scientific interest' that such disciplines
of non-human nature,
294
24
and thus takes us in the
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS
direction of the absorption by liberalism of the main
exploring all the ways in which one may lead a truly
thrust of the ecocentrist argument. It is possible to
human life. Even if some such experiments in living
argue that activities such as those mentioned are
have their pernicious aspects, they add to the sum
clearly part of the self-understanding and flourishing
total of our self-knowledge and may contain redeem-
of those who take part in them. None of us can know
ing aspects for human culture which would be
for certain that they might not become part of our
otherwise unobtainable (for example, consider the
own conditions for flourishing, even if they are not
way in which blues and jazz emerged out of the slave
so at the moment. Also, such people as find them
experience in the USA).
essential to their sense of self are not members of a
The obverse of this point is that no single cultural
separate group of human beings. They are inter-
formation can be entirely adequate to all the sides of
spersed among the general population and are the
our human personality. This is, of course, a central
objects of caring feeling as children, spouses, parents
liberal theme but one which can be turned to good
and so on. Thus, even if these activities in our
account by Green theorists concerned to defend the
culture carry no meaning for a given individual, that
integrity and variety of non-human nature.
individual may find himself caring for others for
The second reason is that any single culture
whom they are extremely important.
which does not periodically, or continuously, re-
So we all have an interest in maintaining the non-
plenish itself by the second process noted above ±
human natural context within which such cultural
namely, encounter with other cultures ± runs the
activities are to be carried on. Rawlsian persons in
serious risk of becoming `played out'. The possibi-
the `original position' would undoubtedly want to
lities of purely internal development are probably
preserve as varied a natural context as possible to
limited. A culture which does not receive jolts from
permit the possibility of engaging in such meaning-
either direct contact with non-human nature or
conferring activities, for themselves or for those for
from contact with other cultures faces the strong
whom they might care. More generally, many com-
possibility of decay. A single, homogeneous world
plete forms of life, such as those centred on hunting
culture which we may be in the process of creating
and fishing, need the specific contexts and oppor-
would, on this view, be a disaster for human cultural
tunities provided by non-human nature in order to
development as a whole. Hence, we need to sustain
exist. The customs, traditions, art-forms, social ar-
as many diverse experiments in living as this tiny
rangements and religious beliefs associated with such
planet will allow, including those which require
lifestyles depend, therefore, derivatively on such a
healthy non-human natural environments within
context. Across the world, the spread of western
which alone they can develop.
cultural forms, the degradation of the natural envir-
In a nutshell, then, the personcentric argument for
onment and the sheer increase in human numbers
the maximum diversity of non-human nature is that
are attacking the underpinning in non-human nat-
it is needed for the maximum diversity of human
ure of such diverse `experiments in living'.
culture. The latter in turn is essential to the con-
However, it might be claimed that no human
tinued health of human cultural development. Re-
cultural form has to exist to secure human well-being
cognition of these points by liberalism requires no
and that diminution in the range of cultural forms is
more than an interpretation of traditional liberal
not necessarily a problem. For, after all, people are
defences of the diversity of human cultures and
adaptable and within a generation or so the grand-
subcultures via grasp of the implications of the
children of fisherfolk can happily exist as urban
necessarily embodied nature of persons. It is the
sophisticates.
25
latter which the defenders of Green political theory,
Why, then, should there be as wide a variety of
such as ecocentrists, have securely grasped. Accep-
human cultures as possible, including those directly
tance of it by liberalism enables the importance of
dependent on specific contexts of non-human nat-
the non-human world to be grasped from within the
ure? Two reasons may be given. The first is that the
liberal tradition in a way which enables an argument
variety is needed in order to allow the possibility of
to be mounted for the defence of the multiplicity of
295
BRIAN BAXTER
that world. Pure ecocentrism is rejected in this
the first round of arguments in the previous section
version of liberalism, but a fusion of the personal
be turned against such theories so as to argue for the
and impersonal standpoints is achieved in a way
possibility of, for example, patterns of urban organi-
which maintains the strong motivational impetus
sation within which very unecological modes of life
which is liberalism's strong point. Further, non-hu-
may be sustained (for at least some of our loved ones
man nature ± on this interpretation of liberalism ± is
may find these to be terribly important for their self-
at least as central a concern as the human (person)
understanding)? Clearly, what is needed at this stage by the
well-being with which it is inextricably entwined.
proponent of the personcentric argument for respecting the variety of non-human nature's world is a
IV
principle to deal with this objection. This principle
It has, of course, long been a liberal theme that only
will require that the maximum variety of human
within an economically dynamic capitalist system is
cultures is to be allowed compatible with the pre-
human diversity properly catered for. The trouble
servation of that diversity of non-human nature
with this view of that diversity is that it is concep-
which is needed to underpin cultures. That is, any
tualised too individualistically. Individual flourishing
culture which requires the eradication of the variety
only occurs within cultural formations. Diversity of
of nature is to be ruled out.
modes of flourishing, therefore, requires diversity of
Obviously, some cultures permitted under this
cultures and, as we have seen, that in turn needs
principle will have features which are morally objec-
diversity of non-human nature within which experi-
tionable on other grounds. However, the above
ments in living can take place. On this view a single,
principle at least allows the possibility of experiments
homogeneous
which
in living which require a specific context of non-
Green theorists fear that liberal-supported capitalism
human nature within which to operate, even if not
is setting in train, is an impoverished environment
all such experiments may be ones with which it
for persons, however materially well-off they may be.
would be in the moral interest of human beings to
This line of argument suggests that the personcentric
persist. To put the point in another way, the person-
version of liberalism developed above may be used to
centric argument for the variety of human cultures
formulate liberal reasons for moving away from un-
does not preclude moral criticism, and attempted
trammelled capitalism. In this respect, however, this
termination, of some of the experiments in living
version of liberalism has honourable antecedents
which natural variety makes possible.
technosphere,
of
the
kind
within the liberal tradition for many liberal theorists,
Thus from ecocentrism liberalism is able to ex-
from Mill to Rawls, have cast doubt upon the
tract an argument for claiming that human persons
necessary connection between the basic value pos-
would do well to maintain non-human nature in as
tulate of liberalism and the capitalist system.
rich and varied a form as possible, so as to provide
There is, however, a point critical of Green po-
the largest set of possibilities for contexts within
litical theory in general, and the `greened' person-
which human culture can find its significance and
centric version of liberalism in particular, which
resources. Since human culture as it has recently
emerges from these arguments for the diversity of
been developing has been extensively destroying
environments within non-human nature and the
non-person nature, human persons need to learn
diversity of cultures which they underpin. Such
to restrain their cultural acts so as not to cut off the
political theories, it may be claimed, seem them-
branch on which they are sitting. Human culture
selves to be aiming for a single, stable, ecologically
must limit itself so as to preserve itself, for only then
defensible cultural formation. Do not such theories,
can human persons guarantee their continued flour-
like all totalising ideologies, foreclose on certain
ishing as persons, which is the fundamental liberal
possibilities of human cultural development? Cannot
aim.
296
26
LIBERALISM, ECOCENTRISM AND PERSONS
Notes
1. Brian Barry (1995) and Marcel Wissenburg (1998) are
13. This, at least, is my understanding of what Kant is
the two contemporary liberal theorists who have most
saying in a notoriously difficult, though penetrating, discussion.
clearly shown an awareness of, and willingness to
14. It has been argued by, for example, Regan (1988) that
engage with, the arguments of Green political theor-
at least some non-human animals may be devoid of
ists. 2. See, for example, Nagel (1991), pp. 4±5: `The im-
rationality and thus autonomy, in the Kantian sense,
personal standpoint in each of us produces . . . a
and yet still be worthy of moral consideration. He
powerful demand for universal impartiality and equal-
argues that those animals which are `subjects of a life'
ity, while the personal standpoint gives rise to indi-
possess rights of the same sort and to the same degree
vidualistic motives and requirements which present
as do human beings. The concept of `preference
obstacles to the pursuit and realisation of ideals . . .
autonomy' applies to such creatures. Whatever the
My claim is that the problem of designing institutions
merits of this case it is clear, as Regan himself recog-
that do justice to the equal importance of all persons,
nises, that it extends the scope of human moral
without making unacceptable demands on indivi-
concern to only a relatively few members of the
duals, has not been solved ± and that this is so is
non-human realm. It also rests upon a concept of a
partly because for our world the problem of the right
`subject of a life' whose meaning and moral weight are
relation between the personal and impersonal stand-
likely to be highly controversial. Many may find it
points has not been solved.' The problem identified by
persuasive but it would be preferable if a concept of
Nagel is here supposed by him to arise with respect to
autonomy could be found which is applicable to non-
traditional political theories, but it plainly arises also
humans and which did not lend itself to being morally
for ecocentrism.
trumped by the Kantian concept of autonomy, involving rationality, which applies only to human beings
3. John O'Neill (1993, p. 159) offers an Aristotelian/
(as far as we know).
Marxist argument to connect individual human wellbeing and our capacity to appreciate disinterestedly
15. Eckersley (1992), pp. 61±3.
the intrinsic value of the natural world (as in scientific
16. See Naess (1989).
study of it, for example). The latter is claimed, cor-
17. Ibid., p. 54.
rectly I think, to be our characteristically human
18. I am here endorsing the general immanentist position
capacity and thus in exercising it we are at our most
in moral and political debate espoused, for example, by Walzer (1983), p. xiv.
fully and satisfyingly human. The argument, however, is open to the objection that, as Nagel has claimed, our
19. Different philosophers have stressed some of these
ability to ascend to the level at which we can view the
elements more than others. Self-interest and means-
world from the impersonal standpoint of morality and
end rationality (points (1) and (2)) were of particular
science is, for most of us, a fitful and fragile business.
importance to Hobbes and he gave a very specific
The arguments developed later in this chapter might
account of how (5) is possible and why it is necessary.
be seen as an attempt to connect the appreciation of
Self-consciousness and the differentiation of oneself
the intrinsic value of non-human nature with indivi-
from others were of great concern to Kant. Point (5)
dual human well-being in a more robust way, via the
was given a non-individualistic basis in Rousseau, a
conception of oneself as embedded in a culture. They
theme developed by Hegel and Marx and taken
are, therefore, intended as complementary to the
further in more recent socialist and conservative thinking.
Aristotelian/Marxist positions.
20. This is a theme at least as old as Rousseau's Discourse
4. Eckersley (1992), chapter 3. 5. Ibid., p. 49.
on the Origins of Inequality and has been the focus of
6. Ibid., pp. 63±71.
much of the discussion among recent communitarian theorists.
7. As one of the commentators on an earlier version of this chapter noted, Eckersley is herself critical of the
21. The allusion here is, of course, to Kant's attempt to
proposition that women are more `in tune' with
establish what is necessary for there to be the possi-
natural processes than men.
bility of experience. Here I try to establish what is necessary for there to be the possibility of culture.
8. Eckersley (1992), p. 54.
22. These claims may gain plausibility from the arguments
9. Ibid., p. 56. 10. Ibid., pp. 60±1.
put forward by P. F. Strawson to establish the logically
11. This point is attributed to Fox (1990), p. 172.
primitive nature of the concept of a person, in which a
12. Kant (1948), p. 91.
person is essentially conceived of as an entity to which
297
BRIAN BAXTER
both mental and physical attributes are to be ascribed.
tions, even though we cannot say in advance of an
See Strawson (1959).
analysis of a human community's mode of life (especially
23. This is the theme of Sir Ernst Gombrich's account of
the material culture) what those conditions will be (p.
the history of western visual art in terms of `schema-
174). Further, he makes a claim for the idea of an
and-correction', presented in Gombrich (1977).
environmental right to preserve the `ecological integrity
24. Rawls (1972), chapter 3.
of a sufficient geographical terrain for the living of that
25. Ted Benton has considered the claim that habitat
social life' (p. 175). These arguments are complementary
protection, while it may be necessary to preserve the
to my own, which might be regarded as furnishing
well-being of non-human animals, is not important in
reasons why even people who are not themselves mem-
the human case because the direct relations of causal
bers of a community whose culture is under threat may
dependency which link habitat conditions, patterns of
view such a threat as being directed towards them too.
social life and individual well-being in the case of non-
26. I would like to acknowledge the very helpful sugges-
human animals simply do not apply to humans (Benton,
tions made by Mark Evans concerning the revision of
1993, p. 174). He replies that human adaptability is
this chapter for the present volume. Any faults which
neither limitless nor devoid of definite causal condi-
remain are, of course, my own.
298
22
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE Mark Evans
in the basic principles to which anti-perfectionists
I
would restrict their concerns. He argues that being
The possibility and desirability of a perfectionist
autonomous is not sufficient to make a life good, for
liberalism, which encourages a liberal state to favour
autonomy must be exercised in pursuit of valuable
one or more conceptions of the `good' or `good life'
1
projects for it to have value. Believing that the
over others, has been much debated in contemporary
options from which people autonomously choose
political thought ever since John Rawls popularised
their projects are, in general, socially defined and
the opposing idea of liberalism as an essentially anti-
determined, Raz urges that to promote autonomy as a
perfectionist doctrine. Sometimes, the perfectionist
good, the liberal state may support those which are
case rests upon the claim that liberalism's funda-
indeed valuable.
mental political principles cannot be plausibly con-
responsibility, his theory has significantly challenged
ceptualised in abstraction from specific conceptions
anti-perfectionist liberalism's efforts to equate itself
about how it is good for people to live.
2
4
By offering liberal politics this
with liberalism in toto.
Alone, the
`conceptual inevitability' argument may not be en-
What is striking, though, about much of the
ough to win the day. Anti-perfectionists can admit
interest Raz has renewed in the idea of perfectionist
that liberal political principles unavoidably lean
liberalism is that the acceptance of engagement in
towards certain ideas of the good and away from
practice with certain conceptions of the good has not
others. But they view this bias with regret, as some-
been matched with a parallel examination of them in
thing to be avoided as far as possible when promoting
theory. He himself says little about which ideals a
3
Hence anti-perfec-
perfectionist liberal state might be inclined to fa-
tionism can be recast as a politics governed not by an
vour. Another liberal critique of anti-perfectionism,
liberalism's fundamental values.
5
implausible commitment to `total neutrality' but a
William Galston's Liberal Purposes, also strives to
tendency towards neutrality, going no further in fa-
restrict itself to a `minimal perfectionism', hardly
vouring particular good-life conceptions than is ne-
venturing
cessary to secure the basic liberal political values.
the good that anti-perfectionists might concede they
Perfectionist liberalism need not be so readily
beyond
need to make.
6
the
modal
assumptions
about
George Sher's Beyond Neutrality
rolled over, though. Joseph Raz, one of its most
develops an account of the good centred upon the
prominent followers, rejects `abstinence-where-pos-
pursuit and achievement of `near-universal and near-
sible' from good-life bias. He contends that a liberal
unavoidable goals' but it is noticeably reluctant to
state can and sometimes should actively promote
discuss in detail the possible content of these goals
certain good-life conceptions beyond those implicit
and their political ramifications. Peter Digeser's Our
7
299
MARK EVANS
Politics, Our Selves? puts forward a Raz-type case for
from it. It is hardly obvious, after all, that the mere
the liberal state actively supporting certain concep-
fact that liberals used to indulge thus is a compelling
tions of the ideal self to aid individuals' `self-crafting'
reason for their descendants to do so today.
but once more provides little clue as to which of such
Contemporary perfectionist liberals are likely to
conceptions might be worthy of the liberal state's
share with anti-perfectionists a much deeper sensi-
support.
8
tivity to human diversity than we find among their
It is almost as if an extreme caution in deliberating
predecessors, who typically operated with detailed
upon the nature of the good life as a political
metaphysical beliefs about human nature which
concern, which is turned into a regulatory political
enabled such confident talk about the good life's
principle by anti-perfectionists, also overcomes per-
composition. Given this sensitivity, such determi-
fectionist liberal theorising. The oddity of this char-
nate and prescriptive beliefs are now much more
acteristic can be more fully appreciated when one
difficult to entertain. Perfectionists don't go as far as
looks back at earlier liberals such as John Stuart Mill,
anti-perfectionists in using `diversity' as a reason for
T. H. Green, Leonard Hobhouse or John Dewey.
avoiding `good-life favouritism' in politics. But they
These thinkers offered substantive views on how it
might nevertheless be reluctant to theorise concep-
was good to lead one's life which they freely inter-
tions of the good because of a doubt that any theory
wove with their political reflections. The sharp
could meaningfully identify specific ideals in abstrac-
disjunction between political thinking and reflec-
tion from the myriad options that are actually avail-
tions upon ideals of personal conduct, which char-
able in society. Perhaps the good life is something
acterises so much contemporary liberal theory, is
that is pluralistic in content, or heavily determined
noticeably absent in many of its forebears.
by particular social context and hence capable of
Although it will be suggested that they should
formulation only by those to whom it applies as they
decline to follow such precedents to the letter, this
reflect upon their own circumstances. On this view,
chapter urges that today's perfectionist liberals can
there would be little for philosophers to say about the
and should seek to retrieve something of this tradi-
good life which would carry any weight over and
tion's spirit (thus it grants the perfectionist case as its
above the citizenry's deliberations. This might lead
starting point). It hopes to encourage a conversation
perfectionists towards what can be called a formal or
about the good as something that liberals shouldn't
`open-textured' perfectionism, which is deliberately
be afraid to join for fear of being thought `illiberal',
not given much content a priori. Instead, it specifies
`arbitrary', `authoritarian' or worse. It proposes some
the form of the good in highly abstract, generalised
elements of a perfectionist ideal that they could
terms alone, rendering it compatible with highly
support, defending their liberal credentials and in-
diverse substantive embodiments which individuals
dicating the role that liberal politics might play in
or groups must formulate for themselves. Those who
promoting them. As a prolegomenon, the chapter
adopt this approach may therefore insist that their
can do no more than indicate some of the possibi-
distinction from anti-perfectionism largely comes in
lities here (hence no irony should be read into the
their practice, not the content of their theories. For
skimpiness of what is proposed!). But if its sugges-
the diversity-sensitive open-textured perfectionist,
tions seem fruitful, it can perhaps energise a more
the most naturally liberal option could then be a
complete and rigorous discussion of the type that has
`democratic perfectionism' which would leave the
unfortunately and unnecessarily become alien to
deliberation over, and choice of, the perfectionist
contemporary liberalism.
ideal's content to the political arena itself. As Raz notes,
9
it is not difficult to appreciate how
liberals might be swayed by these intuitions. But they
II
are not strong enough to render it inappropriate for
Before explaining how to rehabilitate good-life the-
liberal political theory to formulate and examine
orising in liberalism, we should reflect upon the
candidates for perfectionist promotion. Even if we
possible reasons why perfectionist liberals shy away
accept (as this chapter does) that the choice of
300
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
whether to pursue perfectionist policies, and which
ceptions that all in the relevant domain could
ones, if so, should be left to a democratic process, it is
accept. Now, as indicated above, PL often contends
only when political theory is thought to be solely in
that principles of liberal justice are not obtainable
the business of identifying what principles must be
from anything other than a substantively, distinc-
adopted by the state that the case for abstinence from
tively liberal conception of the good. However, it is
perfectionist enquiries seems compelling. Yet not
still possible and certainly desirable for it to preserve
even theorists of justice, the staple diet of all liberal
some morally and politically relevant distinction
political thought, necessarily view the fruits of their
between `justice' and `the good' in the following
deliberations as claiming to be compulsory. Some of
sense. Principles of liberal justice have the specific
them, at least, also restrict themselves to theorising
function of organising basic social and political
what principles of justice might be adopted by a
institutions and if they unavoidably express certain
liberal-democratic
that
assumptions about how it is good to live, these
there could be reasonable alternatives which might
nevertheless pertain to what are deemed to be
citizenry.
They 10
recognise
They do not
people's `essential' interests (and it is the business
think that their function is to prejudge, and circum-
of a theory of justice to propose what these may be).
vent the need for, citizens' own choices.
Because they are `essential' the principles that these
be embraced with equal validity.
So in the way that theorists of justice use political
interests prompt have first claim on the state's
theory to articulate and analyse the candidate con-
attentions. Familiarly, liberals generally assume that
ceptions of justice to be offered up for approval or
people's primary interest lies at least partly in being
rejection by citizens themselves, I contend that
equally free and hence they prioritise a scheme of
perfectionist liberal political theory can also propose
basic liberties. But they regard these principles as
and scrutinise the possible candidate conceptions of
providing only a framework of rules rather than what
the good which might be presented as political
Rawls calls a `comprehensive doctrine' which orien-
options. To sketch one such candidate we need to
tates activity in many more, if not all, aspects of
clarify the main concepts it will employ. We must
individual and social life.
then attempt to characterise its possible content in a fashion
which
has
substantive
implications
11
The `gaps' in the framework can be filled by
(i.e.
conceptions of the good, which may be thought of
leading to both a theory and a practice which is
as those ideals of how an individual might conduct
bolder on good-life questions than anti-perfection-
her life, which projects to adopt and/or character-
ism and the cautious perfectionisms described ear-
istics/virtues to acquire within the boundaries of
lier) but yet performs the delicate balancing act of
justice. Qua liberal, PL will not prioritise its favour-
remaining faithful to the liberal ethos.
itism in good-life ideals over the need to secure justice. But it rejects the idea that the politics of liberal justice automatically rules out all perfectionist
III
concerns.
One way of thinking about the structure of a perfec-
We now need to consider what kind of perfection-
tionist liberalism (hereafter: `PL') is to reflect upon
ism a liberal might consistently adopt. Here, it helps
how it might diverge from anti-perfectionist liberal-
to think about how a liberal might understand
ism (`APL'). APL is typically constructed by sharply
`perfectionism'. The term has been used in confus-
distinguishing `conceptions of the good' and what we
ingly vague and varied ways. It can be `tightly'
can call the `principles of liberal justice', those
defined as a doctrine which holds the pursuit of
fundamental values that a liberal state is centrally
human perfection or excellence (however that may
concerned to enforce. This distinction relies upon
be understood) to be the object of morality. A
some version of the belief that the moral basis of the
slightly slacker definition drops the exacting notion
latter can be intelligibly described as being drawn not
of perfection and describes the goal to be the devel-
from any particular conception of the good alone but
opment of human beings' potentials and capacities to
from something impartial with respect to such con-
a full and flourishing degree (again variously under-
301
MARK EVANS
12
Contemporary liberal debate has tended to
other social influences already and inevitably exer-
use the term more loosely still to denote a doctrine
cised upon it. Consequently, a view of power which
which simply advocates the promotion of a specific
admits that its effects can be `constitutive' and not
ideal, or set of ideals, of how it is good to live (with
just `repressive' would seem to be an invaluable
no necessary reference to either `perfection' or `flour-
conceptual tool for this type of theory.
ishing').
to remove the automatic link between the exercise of
stood).
14
It helps
Although we are proceeding with the assumption
power in the application of perfectionist policy and
that PL will have more to say about the good than
the idea that it is necessarily an act of repression, a
the potentially vacuous notion of an `open-textured'
link which might otherwise make liberals altogether
perfectionism, to retain its liberal identity it still has
more suspicious of the perfectionist case.
to be in some way organised around a respect for human diversity. We shouldn't expect it to be overly
IV
detailed in its prescriptions and thus the loose definition is probably the most appropriate (although, as
My candidate PL initially divides its concerns into
I will later suggest, ideas of `flourishing' are not
two. I call them `self-pertaining' and `other-pertain-
necessarily absent). PL's ideals are also likely only
ing' issues, distinguishing them from the terminology
to be `partially comprehensive' (again following
of `self-regarding' and `other-regarding' acts which is
Rawls
13
popularly used to explicate Mill's famous harm prin-
), declining to provide a complete, rigorously
15
specific blueprint for all areas of life but focusing
ciple.
instead only upon certain aspects raised in the
potential concern to the state, whereas the politics of
question of how to live well.
PL has an interest in both self-pertaining and other-
The latter isolates what is and what is not of
Two final points before sketching a candidate PL.
pertaining acts. By `pertaining', then, I do not mean
A potential misapprehension concerning the perfec-
to identify aspects of life which in some way are
tionist project is that it necessarily posits a universal
either `of (political) concern' only to `self' or of
ideal of the good, which is said to hold true invar-
`others' too. Rather, a question about a `self-pertain-
iantly and without regard to time or place. It will be
ing' aspect of life relates to how one is living one's life
clear, though, that many of my examples of PL's
regardless of its effect on others. That's not to say a
concerns look very culturally specific. I suggest, then,
self-pertaining aspect of life doesn't affect others and
that even if we wish to retain universalist application
nor does it mean that others may not raise legitimate
for principles of liberal justice (which not all liberals
concerns about its effect upon them. If I ask the
wish to do anyway) it would seem appropriate to
question `is X a good thing to do?' part of the answer
make any perfectionist elements of a liberal doctrine
may well rest upon the effect that X has on others.
much more context-sensitive and localised.
But part of it can also refer simply to what good it
Secondly, recognition of cultural variability plus
does to the self alone ± and this is the self-pertaining
an acknowledgement of the role that socialisation
dimension.
plays in the adoption of lifestyles strongly indicates
This aspect can be illustrated by thinking about
that PL rests upon a theory of the self that stresses its
the following: whether to work hard to gain quali-
malleability, or plasticity, over any intrinsic or es-
fications and get a good job or reject hard work for a
sential features. Instead, the self can be seen as much
life of indolent pleasure; whether to produce and/or
less determinately constituted in its intrinsic nature,
consume great poetry or pornography in the privacy
awaiting instead the imprint of a culture for identity-
of your own home; whether physically to live health-
formation. PL therefore assumes that politics has
ily rather than unhealthily; whether to be a well-
some legitimate interest in influencing the forces
informed citizen willing and able to exercise one's
of socialisation that shape the self. Political inter-
political rights competently, or know nothing about
vention to encourage alternative influences upon the
politics and care even less; whether to live in squalor
construction of one's character need not be seen as
or cleanliness; whether to lead a life that is harmo-
qualitatively distinct in any significant way from the
niously and happily balanced between work and play
302
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
or in which work is so onerous that life is constantly
activities which do not fundamentally harm those
stressful; whether to regard sex as an activity to be
who `witness' them in a way that would make them
engaged in freely and lovingly or as a commodity to
matters for justice. In these instances people suffer no
be bought and sold; whether to live a life of drug-
physical injury and their own ability to choose their
induced stupor or alert and lively mental sobriety.
own conception of the good need not be fundamen-
Although all of these pairings may display other-
tally impugned, for example. Instead, they suffer
pertaining aspects, particularly when questions of
`offence', `embarrassment', `revulsion' or otherwise
justice are involved (for example if the pornography
experience such activities as unwelcome nuisances.
in question is paedophiliac), PL can also reflect upon
PL proposes that what effect they do have may
them as questions about the intrinsic quality of how
nevertheless warrant state intervention.
16
one's life is conducted, regardless of the effect upon
Perhaps under the influence of the general ten-
others, when justice is no longer at issue (unlike
dency to neutrality, the `other-pertaining' category
APL, whose political concern ceases at this point).
has been drastically under-theorised in much recent
PL is concerned first to specify those respects in
liberalism and it might therefore immediately strike
which politics may legitimately influence the life-
some liberals as too counter-intuitive to be some-
styles that people live from the self-pertaining per-
thing with which they should engage. But quite apart
spective, and then to propose some principles by
from the fact that this category is present in some
which the value of various ways of life might be
extremely influential members of the wider liberal
determined.
tradition,
17
I think that its neglect is extraordinarily
`Other-pertaining' aspects of life are identified
blinkered in another way. For it is a category that is
solely with the effect that they have on others. PL
familiarly operationalised as law in actual liberal-
identifies which ones may rightfully become matters
democratic states. Whatever is or is not tolerated in
of political concern, again proposing standards by
purely private conduct, all such states will regulate
which to evaluate the effects to determine whether
non-harmful conduct in public spheres and spaces to
they should be permitted, regulated or prevented
a greater degree. To take one simple example: what-
where possible. As we shall see, the kinds of beha-
ever sexual conduct is permissible in private, nearly
viour which might pertain to others are not simply
all of it is prohibited as a public performance. And I
what might `harm' them, which is the criterion for
think most liberals (including, if they are honest,
Mill's `other-regarding' acts. Let us assume that these
anti-perfectionists) would regard the existence of
are largely covered by the principles of justice. PL
some such restrictions as a good thing.
proposes that there are other respects in which
I am not invoking the crass argument that what-
people might justifiably expect or require certain
ever is actually done by liberal-democratic states
forms of behaviour from each other and in which
must therefore be permitted by liberals' political
PL may grant politics a stake.
theory (plenty of such states' activities are unsanc-
To illustrate this second aspect, think of the
tioned and indeed condemned by the theory). But I
following: drunken and foul-mouthed behaviour in
am arguing that the fact that we have this category in
the streets; public billboards displaying hard-core
political practice is a very strong prima facie reason for
pornography; playing music very loudly at the ex-
thinking that liberals can and should embrace it
pense of neighbourhood peace and quiet; advertising
theoretically. I suggest most liberals believe that
work in the sex industry as a career opportunity in
there are certain things which can be said and done
job centres and school career offices; running a
in private which, even though they do not `harm'
workshop in your own garage which generates un-
anyone, are rightfully prohibited in public. They
pleasant though not noxious or toxic smells that
don't want the state to forbid your viewing of ob-
nevertheless disgust your neighbours; engaging in
scene material in your front room, your nudist pro-
sexual intercourse on the upper deck of a crowded
clivities in the kitchen and your boorish, foul-
bus.
mouthed drunkenness when you're at a friend's
Let us grant that there are instances of such
house. But they do want it to forbid you from putting
303
MARK EVANS
your obscene photos on a public billboard, from
informed yet have not been willing to change their
walking naked up and down the high street or from
unhealthy ways.
being
drunkenly
foul-mouthed
at
the
bus
stop.
Transferring these activities into the public realm
2. A conception of psychological well-being
is what makes these acts of rightful concern to others. PL can therefore articulate a theory of `acceptable
Whereas it may be relatively easy to identify how it is
public conduct' (very generally understood) to help
good to live in terms of physical health given the
identify what should fall into this category.
availability of objective information on the subject,
Overall, then, PL seeks to support ways of life
it may be more difficult to do so with regard to some
that are `dignified' or `decent', `worthwhile' or `ful-
questions
filling'. The ideal to inform this commitment could
might agree that there are certain psychological
take one or both of the following forms: (a) a
disorders which can be diagnosed, the broader no-
conception of what is good for people, specifically
tion of the `ideal state of mind' is likely to be
to encourage its adoption; (b) a conception of what
altogether more nebulous and variable than `ideal
is bad in people's conduct of their lives (`undigni-
physical condition' is for any one individual. I do not
fied', `shameful', `worthless', `unfulfilling') to discou-
therefore envisage PL being too prescriptive in this
pursuit.
This
obviously
implies
psychological
health.
Although
we
by
regard (avoiding such banalities as `everyone should
counterposition some notion of what is good for
be happy and carefree!' It would be absurd to have a
people, but it could be compatible with various
state that campaigned against sullenness in the same
conceptions of the good life and is thus perhaps
way it campaigned against poor diet). However,
not as tightly prescriptive as (a).
there is some opportunity for it to posit certain
rage
its
of
psychological conditions which it is not good for people to experience and which its policies may
V
sensibly address.
It is now time to begin delivering on the promise to
Here is just one example to illustrate this possi-
sketch some definite content for PL. Here are three
bility. A wearily familiar refrain of many free-market
possible components.
libertarians in particular over recent years has been that the culture of competition in contemporary capitalist society, which has left people increasingly
1. The conception of physical well-being
insecure in their jobs and often having to work ever
Liberal justice may invoke an obligation to provide
harder to try to keep them, is nevertheless a good
adequate health care for all regardless of circum-
thing. They argue that such pressure increases pro-
stances, but it does not demand that the state make
ductive efficiency and hence brings material benefits
everyone healthy. Nevertheless, the liberal state can
to the economy. On this view it is good for employ-
(and often does) campaign to promote physical well-
ees in the sense that they are compelled to become
being, even though many people's conceptions of the
more `effective' in their work.
good life (smoking, drinking, prolonged sunbathing,
Leaving aside the arguments that such employ-
unprotected promiscuous sex, sloth) may be (some-
ment trends do not unambiguously increase produc-
times knowingly) to their physical detriment. PL can
tive
affirm that people ought to be free to determine how
questions about the quality of life are raised in these
to manage their own health, but it proposes that the
practices regardless of their material effectiveness. It
state has a legitimate interest in informing people of
could conceptualise some elements of ideal psycho-
the desirability of physically healthy lifestyles.
18
efficiency,
PL
could
maintain
that
serious
The
logical well-being to identify as undesirable certain
state may judge that ignorance over health matters
levels of stress which, for example, exacerbate feel-
leads too many people to misjudge what is good for
ings of alienation and distress, and destroy the
them. PL allows it to propagandise for healthy life-
capacity for a well-balanced personality to flourish
styles even with respect to people who are adequately
(not least if longer working hours in such a stressful
304
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
environment disable a person from properly experi-
Pupils are not only educated in certain academic
encing life's other facets). Thus, (2) could be in-
disciplines; they are also schooled (if often only
voked as at least part of the justification for policies
indirectly) in specific norms of conduct. Well-man-
which attempt to regulate working practices against
nered,
the interests of `economic efficiency.'
authority . . . a whole set of virtues and vices are
cooperative,
trustworthy,
respectful
of
assumed in the ways they are expected to behave. When we focus on the increasingly popular notion of
3. The ethical character-ideal
civic education in particular,
This is the third and most broad category, which
19
we can see this
project coalescing around a character-ideal of `good
specifies ethical standards by which it is thought
citizen' as being the intended end-product.
good for people to live. This can be subdivided into
Now APL can reconcile itself to the idea of en-
at least five (interlinkable) categories:
couraging such characteristics in so far as they are valuable for strictly political ends alone. It might also
1. the virtues and skills which facilitate the re-
reluctantly admit that fitting people for liberal politics
quirements of good citizenship;
could have knock-on or overspill effects upon other
2. the virtues and skills which facilitate autono-
spheres of life.
20
Thus teaching tolerance and equality
of respect for the political arena might introduce the
my;
3. the qualities which comprise an appropriately
exercise of such virtues in people's private relation-
fulfilling life for humans to lead;
ships. On my conception, PL might not do much more
4. the virtues which constitute admirable character
than APL to promote good citizenship but it may not
and the qualities which constitute a dignified
have the same degree of reluctance about its overspill.
life (`a life fit for a person to lead');
It could regard it as good and justifiable for a politically
5. The requirements that constitute socially ac-
mandated programme of civic education to encourage
ceptable conduct.
the development not just of good (tolerant, fairminded and reasonable) citizens but good people in
I treat (2) ± (4) as largely self-pertaining matters; (1)
general, who display the virtues of good citizenship in
and (5) identify other-pertaining issues, though both
all their dealings with others.
draw upon, and have consequences for, the self-
Of course, it would be desperately naive to expect
pertaining too.
education to yield exactly the same type of good
The first two categories might be thought of as
citizen/person in all children. Nor, in all probability,
those which primarily constitute the kind of char-
should PL even want it to or regret that it does not.
acter-ideal which is most directly favoured by liberal
We might be pleased at the fact that no such method
principles of justice (the conception of the good from
of socialisation is going to avoid the production of
which perfectionists might argue such principles are
highly diverse characters, some of whom will be rude,
necessarily drawn). Category (1) specifies the virtues
dishonest, ruthless, uncooperative and so on. It is a
± the ideal dispositions and characteristics ± that are
good thing that we don't have a society in which all
required by citizens to discharge the social role of
such vices have been knocked out in one's youth
citizenship well: civility, toleration, fair-mindedness,
(quite apart from the value of variety, maybe many
cooperativeness, among others. PL may hold that, in
necessary and great things can only be done by
its ideal of politics, public affairs should always be
people who display what we would ordinarily think
conducted with such virtues to the fore (and its ethic
of as unwelcome characteristics: ruthlessness, say).
can be the basis for attacking political conduct which
But still, this does not mean there is no moral worth
fails to exhibit them). But the liberal state would
or practical point in schools seeking to set such
have the largest scope for directly promoting virtue-
examples. There is no paradox in attempting to
based forms of conduct in the kind of education it
impart some character-ideals generally even when
provides for its children and it is on this matter that I
it is not necessarily to be regretted that some will not
shall restrict my comments regarding this category.
live by them.
305
MARK EVANS
Promoting autonomy (Category (2)) requires the
PL to take up such options. If people want to live
encouragement of both the taste and the aptitude for
lazy, slovenly lives passively consuming vast quan-
autonomous choosing, and the provision of a social
tities of lager whilst watching pornographic videos,
environment which facilitates it. PL could accept
the state cannot forbid them to do so (it need not
that the perfectionist liberal state should tolerate
subsidise them, though; if people have no source of
some ways of life which are not grounded in auton-
income but welfare payments, the liberal state may
omy and, in the name of providing a variety of
require them actively to look for work, or undertake
options, even allow it actively to sponsor some of
training programmes, to qualify for such benefits).
them (for we mustn't assume that the state cannot
One
equally support mutually incompatible forms of life for individuals
21
consideration
in
identifying
what
might
count as a valuable option is provided by Category
). But its preference for autonomy
(3). This retrieves from many prominent currents in
implies the possibility that it views these as less good
the liberal tradition the idea that the good life for
ways of living (note this is crucially distinct from
humans is one spent developing their potentials and
viewing them as bad, even though it does not adopt a
capacities. PL could favour activities that are devel-
relativist or sceptical approach to how lifestyles
opmental (creative, intellectual, physically demand-
might
ing)
be
evaluated).
Non-autonomous
lifestyles
rather
than
enervating.
Once
again,
it
is
may have a harder battle to survive than their
primarily in education that the perfectionist liberal
autonomous counterparts in a perfectionist liberal
state is most likely to be able to act in support of this
society where people are encouraged to choose for
ideal. It could, for example, attempt to gear a curri-
themselves. But this is not something that PL ne-
culum towards the development of a wide range of
cessarily regrets.
22
intellectual, creative, aesthetic, emotional and phy-
Realistically, PL must recognise that autonomy is
sical capacities well beyond the functional require-
always `bounded' in numerous ways: choices are
ments
inescapably limited by one's context. For example,
transferable skills'), the kind of economic imperative
in societies where one generally has to get a job to
that may come to inform education if the state does
live a minimally decent life, employment opportu-
not take care otherwise. Category (3) may also
nities are often severely restricted in particular loca-
facilitate a critique of the wider social and cultural
tions and contexts (if they are available at all).
environment to ascertain whether it is encouraging
Practical limitations may mean that an autonomous
or frustrating the development of individuals in
good life is always going to be a matter of degree and/
desirable directions. It may thus provide the grounds
or
mean,
for a radical condemnation of a culture that, say,
though, that one must always accept whatever lim-
fosters banality and stifles creativity and fulfilment.
episodic
in
character.
That
does
not
of
a
`flexible
labour
market'
(`personal
itations happen to pertain. Some of the restrictions upon people's choices may be intolerable and PL's
VI
theory could therefore provide a guide to identify situations in which autonomy has become unaccep-
Category (4) has close links to Category (1), in
tably restricted. I discuss an example of this in
which it was argued that PL would welcome the
section VII.
overspill of the good-citizenship virtues into people's
An important corollary of this function is that PL
characters
more
generally.
The
notion
of
what
can strive to widen and secure a range of valuable
counts as an `admirable character' could, then, sim-
options from which people may choose their auton-
ply build upon what is implicit in the citizenship
omous projects. This is the policy made familiar to us
character-ideal. It is potentially very wide, ranging
by Raz, whose perfectionism largely concentrates on
across large sets of ideal dispositions and character-
the possibility that the state can subsidise various
istics. To specify its content PL could, for example,
kinds of activity and lifestyle deemed to be worthy of
follow Joel Feinberg in drawing upon Hume's four-
people's support (particularly when they may struggle
fold categorisation of features which are (a) pleasing
to survive without such help).
23
to us; (b) pleasing to others; (c) useful to us; (d)
No one is forced by
306
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
useful to others (inverting each to obtain the set of
he conducted himself in these self-pertaining matters
vices which could be discouraged). PL would then
was widely thought to have been a poor example to
think it, on balance, good for people to be, say, clean
set to the nation and that the public had a right to
rather than dirty ((a)); tactful and tolerant rather
expect his behaviour, qua the leading public official,
than rude and insensitive ((b)); prudent and moti-
to be better. His adultery, lying to his family and the
vated to better oneself rather than reckless or in-
American people, the inappropriateness of the re-
dolent ((c)); trustworthy and cooperative rather
lationship with a very junior employee barely older
than deceitful and unreliable ((d)) ± the list could
than his own daughter: these are not illegal activ-
go on.
24
ities, but a certain widely shared conception of the
Now as ideals for conduct in spheres of life
good nevertheless condemned them, and deemed
stretching well beyond the political, these features
them particularly improper for the leading figure
may appear to be of no possible concern to any
in public life.
liberal politics ± beyond, again, the kinds of char-
We might have been similarly condemnatory of
acteristics that state-sponsored education may try to
such behaviour if Clinton had been the chief ex-
inculcate in children. Certainly, liberals would find
ecutive of a burger bar company. But it is not clear
ridiculous the idea of a state enforcing rules requiring
that citizens have the same legitimate expectation of
any such behaviour. But it is far from clear that an
ethical conduct from someone who does not hold
ethic governing such matters is and/or ought to be
public office. Of course it is true that people are
wholly absent from liberalism's political morality. To
nowadays very cynical about politicians' motiva-
explain just one possible reason why, we can add a
tions, suspecting (sometimes rightly) some hypocri-
sub-category to (4): (4a) The ethical standards of public
tical Machiavellianism behind their protestations of
officials.
virtue. Also, too much genuine moral sincerity from
This issue has received practically no attention in
their mouths can eventually sound just tiresomely
contemporary liberalism, but it points to what I take
sanctimonious and PL can recognise that the realities
to be a familiar way in which liberal politics may
of political life may well make it no place for moral
serve to promote substantive ethical character-ideals.
saints. But the very fact that there is a widespread
It entails the identification of standards of conduct
cynicism about the moral quality of political life
which, though their opposites are not to be legally
seems to imply some wish that it should really be
proscribed, it is right for citizens to expect their
more virtuous, and PL could give voice to that wish.
public officials in particular to exhibit. These func-
If it is therefore thought right that political repre-
tionaries have a responsibility, if not a duty, to
sentatives should display certain forms of conduct
support these ideals. If they fail to live up to them,
and avoid others to set suitable ethical examples in a
they set inappropriate examples of self-pertaining
way that would not be so publicly expected of the
behaviour to those whom they serve. The facts that
boss of McClinton's, then political theory may have
they can be condemned for doing so and that citizens
a legitimately vested interest in scrutinising this
have some legitimate expectation that they should
specifically political concern. PL can posit possible
not behave thus give credence to the idea of a self-
ideals to inform these expectations of conduct.
pertaining morality being a proper object of political concern.
To conclude this section, I offer just a few remarks
25
on the concept of a `dignified' life which was in-
Popular reactions to the revelations concerning
cluded in Category (4). I treat this as distinguishable
President Clinton's relationship with Monica Le-
from the notion of having an admirable character
winsky illustrate this claim well. It is doubtless true
and, again, it would be surprising if liberals of any
that the charge of perjury, which led to Clinton's
hue ± if they reflected hard on their ethical commit-
impeachment and which is primarily a matter of
ments ± would want to resist adopting some such
criminal justice, is what concerned people upper-
notion to put to political work. PL merely embraces
most.
26
this commitment openly and seeks to articulate it
Many people thought that his personal life
fully.
did not affect his ability to govern. But still, the way
307
MARK EVANS
It is best illustrated by an example of Sher's: that of
typically sexual ± that are other-pertaining even
drug addicts, living from fix to fix in excrement-
when no one else directly witnesses it (they think
stained squalor, hopelessly dependent upon their
it permissible legally to prohibit certain kinds of
dealers who ruthlessly take sexual advantage of
consensual sexual activity even when done in the
them.
27
privacy of one's own home because society's moral
Of course there may be questions of severe
fabric is supposedly damaged by them
injustice in this situation which take priority in its
28
).
condemnation. PL could also attack it for the loss of
In its self-pertaining deliberations, we have seen
autonomy and opportunities for leading a genuinely
that PL offers some recommendations as to how
fulfilled life. But on top of all this (if we are talking
politics might encourage or discourage people to live
about rich addicts who continually affirm an auton-
privately in certain ways. But questions of legal
omous desire both to take drugs and experience all
prohibition have not here been broached. Only
that their effects entail), it could also judge such a life
when certain activities move into the public realm
to be simply too degrading, undignified and unfit for
are they raised ± and this is a crucial part of what
humans to live. And, in self-pertaining judgements,
makes this a liberal conception. In so far as other-
it could employ this distinctive ethic of dignity in
pertaining judgements inform permissible restric-
campaigns against its adoption.
tions and prohibitions, it is largely informed by a conception of how it is bad to live and act in the public realm. Sometimes this draws upon self-per-
VII
taining judgements about how it is good and bad to
Finally, Category (5). Here we should recall that
live for oneself. At other times, it is only the location
other-pertaining judgements refer to phenomena
of the activity in the public realm that generates any
which become political concerns because of how
negative evaluation of it. Given that sexual conduct
they affect other people in terms other than the harm
is a significant topic in PL's morality, we can use
they may cause them. Often, their effect is sufficient
some examples of such to illustrate this point.
to justify legal restraint of the activity in question.
With one important potential exception to be
We have already rehearsed the argument that it is
explained shortly I take it that PL would, in general,
consistent and desirable for PL to address other-
have nothing to say about any form of private
pertaining questions, but is there a distinctively
consensual adult sexual activity that did not pose
liberal way of isolating which issues they may ad-
physical dangers to anyone else. But questions of
dress? In other words, can PL identify them in a way
public offence are clearly raised as far as sex in public
that would distinguish the liberal from non-liberal
is concerned. Thus, part of PL's concern in Category
approaches?
(5) is to identify those types of activity which,
Here is an inadequately brief reply which hope-
although all well and good in private, are wholly
fully is enough to suggest a distinctively liberal slant
inappropriate in public such that their public per-
to this issue. Although it has been the subject of
formance may rightfully be punished.
much conceptual attack, the classical distinction
The important exception provides an example
between public and private realms of life can remain
where a self-pertaining judgement is made about
operational for liberals in a very obvious way. Activ-
an act which directly contributes towards the for-
ities done without the presence of non-participating
mulation of an other-pertaining judgement about
others (in one's own home, paradigmatically) are
that act when publicly performed. This is when
private in the way that the same activities done in
sex is treated as a commodity, engaged in not for
the high street ± publicly ± are not. On this con-
love or pleasure but for money: prostitution and
ception, PL holds that other-pertaining activities
pornographic modelling. Let us leave aside the very
have to be public: they really can or do physically
real problems of injustice in the plight of the (often
confront other people who otherwise have no part in
very poor) women in the sex industry, which PL
them. This is distinguished from those conservative
could happily admit removes any grounds for con-
views which argue that there are private activities ±
demning the women. But this is not to say it cannot
308
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
condemn the kind of work they do and this is where
against whom some might take offence. I may be as
a self-pertaining judgement drawn from an ethic of
disgusted at the sight of people wearing orange flared
dignity, as suggested in (4), might be made.
trousers and open-toed sandals as others are at the
Consider a woman who is forced by economic
sight of explicit sexual imagery, but PL's ethic is what
circumstance into prostitution. Aside from the jus-
identifies my sartorial tastes as inappropriate for the
tice questions, the `dignity' issue can feature in the
legally controllable category of public offence.
following way. Most of us basically have to sell our labour-power to live and many may have little
VIII
meaningful choice as to what kind of job can be taken. This is an important way in which autonomy
Of course, all of this ± and particularly, I suspect,
is always constrained, as observed in section V. Yet if
some of the suggestions in the previous section ± is
the only option for an unemployed woman in a job
eminently contestable. And it is right that it should
market is to become a secretary or a clerk, we might
be so. It should be recalled, after all, that this theory
regret the lack of choice but not consider that any
was not designed to settle questions that are in fact
truly damaging harm has been done to her dignity as
only properly decidable in the political realm itself.
a human being. However, if the only option left was
But this chapter has been designed to show that it is
to fall into prostitution, then a liberal is much more
appropriate for perfectionist liberals not only to raise
likely to judge that her life choices had become
these questions but to venture some answers, elabor-
unacceptably limited and that there was something
ating the assumptions upon which they are offered
wrong with the socio-economic system that had left
and attempting to structure them into a coherent
her with such dismal prospects. This is where the
ethical outlook. In so doing, it has hopefully forced
ethic of dignity informs an ethically and politically
liberals to think harder about some of the ways in
crucial evaluation.
which ethical judgements of this kind are made in practice and to evaluate for themselves whether ±
Now for the way in which this self-pertaining judgement feeds into other-concerned legal restric-
despite
tions on the sex industry. Imagine that PL follows
prompt them to think ± it is in fact desirable for
what
the
tendency
to
neutrality
might
many liberals in thinking it desirable more fully to
liberals to preserve them in their theorising.
decriminalise prostitution and pornography for prag-
Still, it would be naive not to admit that serious
matic reasons. In such instances, it would still hardly
reservations may remain about the whole project.
require liberals to think it now acceptable to have
There is no space to address them all, but I conclude
explicitly pornographic advertising billboards, broth-
with a few remarks in PL's defence. I have not
els in any part of a town (next to an infant school or
claimed that my version of PL is the only way of
old people's home?) and advertisements for the sex
characterising a liberal theory of the good life, so the
industry in school careers centre advice packs and
conversation I advocate might well lead away from
Job Centre vacancy boards. For PL, there may re-
some of the elements I have proposed. For example, I
main something in the ethical quality of prostitution
can well envisage an argument holding that the gist
and pornography, marking them out as less than fully
of the comments concerning the sex industry reflect
dignified, which justifies their exclusion from the
an unnecessarily ± illiberal? ± `prudish' attitude,
immediate, unavoidable public realm in which we all
unfairly denigrating its work. I am happy to concede
necessarily move. That lack of ethical quality gen-
the conversation on this matter is far from over.
erates sufficient offence for many to desire not to
But one might also object that part of liberalism's
have to encounter it against their wishes in public. It
very point has been to try to reduce the state's
is this perfectionist liberal ethic that says it is right for
interest in such apparently paternalist matters and
the law to try to spare us all (not just children and old
that PL threatens a dangerously reactionary reversal
ladies) the sight of streetwalkers, kerb crawlers and
of this trend. Of course it is true that liberalism has
images of explicit sex on billboards or prime-time
mounted frontal assaults on many of the taboos and
television, but not other types of person and activity
conformist norms that permeated western cultures
309
MARK EVANS
until fairly recently. Yet it is wrong to conclude from
justify APL. Of course PL could be abused but then
this that liberalism, as many of its enemies often
so can, for example, the democratic ideal itself. Many
charge, is necessarily committed to abolishing all
dictatorships have co-opted `democracy' to `justify'
such standards and expectations of behaviour. Lib-
the most terrible tyranny, but we don't regard this as
eralism is certainly a politics of toleration ± but one is
sufficient reason to abandon the ideal, only to be
usually said to tolerate when one puts up with some-
more vigilant about its operation. And the dangers of
thing that one doesn't much like. This therefore
PL's abuse can be lessened precisely through the
assumes a standard of evaluation in itself, which PL
careful theorisation of conceptions of the good,
can articulate. And I have argued that liberalism
rather than abandoning the matter in its entirety
need not be (and in practice is not) open-endedly
to whatever instant, perhaps vulgarly prejudicial,
tolerant; there are limits. Such perfectionist judge-
opinions might be thrown into democratic debate.
ments are familiarly operationalised in political prac-
A properly thought-through PL, examined thor-
tice and, again, I insist that there is simply no
oughly and its moral positions exactingly contested
compelling reason to think that, by reflecting upon
both by professional political theorists and by a
this fact, liberals would wish to abandon such prac-
democratic citizenry in the political arena, would
tice altogether (they may want to alter some of its
seem to be the best guarantee we could hope for to
content, but that is a different matter).
avoid such tyranny.
It is also incorrect to think that, by permitting in
It may ultimately be the case that a liberal polity
principle the possibility of perfectionist politics, one
would decide against an active perfectionist agenda,
would inadvertently open the door again to the kind
in which case the articulation of such an ethic would
of bigotry that liberalism has worked so hard to
appear not to be necessary. But because liberal-
undermine. This claim usually proceeds with a `slip-
democratic states in practice do wander into perfec-
pery-slope' argument: `legislating against public of-
tionist territory, it is surely more incumbent upon
fence
encourage
APL to say why it is not good for states to do so
legislation against Y and it would be wrong to
(without caricaturising PL by raising the spectre of
legislate against Y.' This argument implies that an
some patently hideous Orwellian totalitarianism as
anti-X policy in itself has no serious drawback (if it
their reason). To add a final, brief remark to hint at
did have such, then we wouldn't need to condemn it
PL's possibilities (and to suggest as-yet uncharted
for the consequences it may have; its intrinsic flaws
future paths for research into it): it may be that the
would suffice). In principle, though, this argument
better-off denizens of the rich, capitalist west may be
fails if one can show that we need not necessarily
ultimately unable to sustain their kind of materia-
slide down the slope at all. And if anti-X has much to
listic lifestyles for two reasons. One is that the
commend it, then the argument in its favour could
demands of redistributive global justice will become
easily outweigh the slippery-slope argument.
so overwhelming that cosseted indifference will no
X
is
wrong
because
it
would
Given that we are to leave the final decisions
longer be possible. The second is that the need to
about perfectionist ideals to democratic deliberation,
avoid environmental catastrophe will require noth-
there is always a danger that PL's politics would
ing short of a profound change in the resource-
simply legitimise the enforcement of existing illiberal
ravaging lifestyles of the rich nations. Both points
majoritarian prejudices. There is a lurking worry
suggest the need to rethink fundamentally the ma-
about the tyranny of the majority here and perhaps
terially extravagant conceptions of human flourish-
a prudent (or, in Judith Shklar's sense, a `fearful'
29
)
ing encouraged in such societies. And to the extent
liberalism, designed to reduce the opportunities for
that political means may be required to facilitate
such unwelcome uses of power, would argue that,
these ethical changes, the attempted indifference of
attractive though PL sounds in theory, we cannot
APL will clearly have to be abandoned. So it is obvious that PL has been pushed by the
trust those who exercise power to do so wisely
tendency to neutrality onto the defensive far too
enough to encourage it in practice.
much. It would infinitely profit liberalism for it to
It is unclear, though, that this fear is enough to
310
PROLEGOMENON TO A LIBERAL THEORY OF THE GOOD LIFE
become more emboldened, and to think harder and
contribute to what is already that most challenging
more openly about the way in which politics might
of projects: leading a good life in the modern world.
Notes
1. I use the terms `good' and `good life' loosely and
include `offence' does not remove any problems over
somewhat interchangeably here. Sher (1997), pp.
arguing about the proscribability of offence; it just shifts them.
37±44 discusses some of the vagaries of `conception
17. Mill (1972), p. 167; Hart (1963), p. 47; Feinberg
of the good.'
(1985).
2. For example Galston (1991), part II.
18. In one sense, this might be an other-concerned activ-
3. See, for example, Rawls (1996), pp. 152, 199±200.
ity where the state (that is the taxpayer) shoulders the
4. Raz (1986), chapter 14 develops most of the points
cost of treating illness. But it is primarily self-con-
summarised here.
cerned in that it is left up to individuals to decide
5. Raz talks of values being grounded in `concrete social
whether they wish to lead healthy lifestyles.
forms', suggesting a rather conventionalist account of perfectionism's content. Even if this conservative bent
19. A familiar feature of American school life, civic
satisfies liberals ± and I will suggest it may not ± this is
education is now being incorporated into Britain's
still too insubstantial a formulation for us to have
national curriculum as well.
much idea of where Raz's perfectionism could lead us.
20. Rawls (1996), pp. 199±200.
6. Galston (1991), p. 177.
21. Raz (1986), pp. 161±2, 425.
7. Sher (1997).
22. For an argument urging liberals to reconcile them-
8. Digeser (1995).
selves to the fact that their doctrine will unavoidably
9. Raz (1986), p. 162.
discriminate heavily against certain kinds of cultures in modern society, see Fitzmaurice (1993).
10. See, for example, Rawls (1999), pp. 581±3. Rawls defends `justice as fairness' as a morality for political
23. Raz (1986), pp. 417±18.
fundamentals, but here recognises that it is only one of
24. Feinberg (1988), pp. 277±81.
many `reasonable' conceptions that might be adopted.
25. If it is posited that immoral conduct by its public
11. Rawls (1996), pp. 13, 175.
officials diminishes the polity as a whole, rather than
12. See Hurka (1993), pp. 3±4.
just simply sets bad examples to individuals, then such
13. Rawls (1996), pp. 13, 175.
behaviour arguably becomes other-pertaining too. On
14. This quasi-Foucauldian approach to power as consti-
this account, we would all be directly tarnished ethi-
tutively disciplinary of the self is discussed in Digeser
cally by the antics of our elected representatives, as a citizenry.
(1995), chapters 1 and 4. Space permits no more than a mention of this conceptual possibility; its articula-
26. Note, though, that certain forms of lie ± such as
tion and analysis is, though, a highly promising can-
perjury ± are criminalised even though it is not clear
didate for perfectionist liberalism's research agenda.
that people are always and necessarily `harmed' (in a
15. Although this specific terminology is F. H. Bradley's
classic liberal sense) by them. The wrongfulness of
rather than his own, Mill's distinction is implicit in his
lying might therefore be derived at least in part from a
On Liberty, Mill (1972), p. 78.
substantive ethical character-ideal which is separate
16. It might be argued that, for consistency's sake, liberal-
from the `harm' considerations that are primary in
ism needs to reconceptualise `harm' in order to justify
grounding principles of justice. If it is right that types
to itself the idea that these are proscribable offences.
of lying remain criminalised (as with perjury), then
The problem with this is that it threatens to stretch
perhaps we should admit that this is another example of perfectionist considerations in politics.
the concept of `harm' to breaking point. Quite apart from the fact that it is hardly clear that the coercive
27. Sher (1997), p.179.
repression of something becomes permissible simply by
28. Famously argued by Devlin (1965), chapter 1.
dint of redefining a concept, expanding `harm' to
29. Shklar (1989).
311
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Beitz, C. (1979), Political Theory and International Relations,
Ackerman, B. (1991), We The People: Foundations, Cam-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
bridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Beitz, C. (1989), Political Equality: An Essay in Democratic
Ackerman, B. (1994), `Rooted Cosmopolitanism', Ethics,
Theory, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
104, pp. 516±35.
Bellamy, R. (1992), Liberalism and Modern Society, Cam-
Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M. (1986), Dialectic of En-
bridge: Polity.
lightenment, 2nd edn, trans. J. Cumming, London: Verso.
A'Haleem, A. M. (1992), `Claiming Our Bodies and Our
Bellamy, R. (1994), ` ``Dethroning Politics'': Liberalism,
Rights: Exploring Female Circumcision as an Act of
Constitutionalism and Democracy in the Thought of F.
Violence in Africa', in M. Schuler (ed.), Freedom from
A. Hayek', British Journal of Political Science, 24(4), pp. 419±41.
Violence: Women's Strategies from Around the World , New
Bellamy, R. (1999), Liberalism and Pluralism: Towards a
York: Women, Law and Development, OEF Interna-
Politics of Compromise, London: Routledge.
tional. Albertini, M. (1999), Nazionalismo e federalismo, Bologna:
Bellamy, R. (2000), `Dealing with Difference: Four Models
Biblioteca Federalista/Fondazione Europea Luciano Bo-
of Pluralist Politics', in Parliamentary Affairs, 53(1), pp. 198±217.
lis. Alexander, J. C. and Lara, M. P. (1996), `Honneth's New
Bellamy, R. and Castiglione, D. (eds) (1996), Constitu-
Critical Theory of Recognition', New Left Review 220,
tionalism in Transformation, special edition of Political Studies (44(3)).
pp. 126±36.
Bellamy, R. and Castiglione, D. (1998), `Between Cosmo-
Anderson, P. (1992), A Zone of Engagement, London:
polis and Community: Three Models of Rights and
Verso.
Democracy within the European Union', in D. Archi-
Arneson, R. (1989), `Equality and Equal Opportunity for
bugi, D. Held and M. Koehler (eds), Re-Imagining
Welfare', in Philosophical Studies, 56, pp. 77±93.
Political Community, Cambridge: Polity.
Avineri, S. (1972), Hegel's Theory of the Modern State,
Bellamy, R. and Hollis, M. (1995), `Liberal Justice: Poli-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
tical and Metaphysical', Philosophical Quarterly, 45, pp.
Axtmann, R. (1996), Liberal Democracy into the Twenty-
1±19.
First Century: Globalization, Integration and the Nation-
Bellamy, R. and Hollis, M. (eds) (1999), Pluralism and
State, Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Liberal Neutrality, London: Frank Cass.
Babbit, S. (1993), `Feminism and Objective Interests: The Role of Transformation Experiences in Rational Delib-
Benhabib, S. (1992), Situating the Self, Cambridge: Polity.
eration, in L. Alcoff, and E. Potter (eds), Feminist
Benhabib, S. (ed.) (1996), Democracy and Difference, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Epistemologies, New York: Routledge.
Benhabib, S., Cornell, D. (eds.) (1987), Feminism as
Bader, V. (1997), `Transnational Citizenship', in Political
Critique, Cambridge: Polity.
Theory, 25(6), pp. 771±813.
Benson, P. (1991), `Autonomy and Oppressive Socialisa-
Balcerowicz, L. (1995), Socialism, Capitalism, Transforma-
tion', in Social Theory and Practice, 17, pp. 385±408.
tion, Budapest: Central European University Press.
Benton, T. (1993), Natural Relations: Ecology, Animal
Barry, B. (1995), Justice as Impartiality, Oxford: Oxford
Rights and Social Justice, London: Verso.
University Press.
Berlin, I. (1969), Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford: Oxford
Beetham, D. (1991), The Legitimation of Power, London:
University Press.
Macmillan.
312
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Bulmer, S. (1993), `The Governance of the European
Berlin, I. (1978), Concepts and Categories: Philosophical
Union: A New Institutionalist Approach', in Journal
Essays, ed. H. Hardy, London: Hogarth Press.
of Public Policy, 13(4), pp. 351±80.
Berlin, I. (1991), The Crooked Timber of Humanity, ed. H.
Burke, E. (1961), Reflections on the Revolution in France,
Hardy, London: Fontana.
New York: Doubleday.
Berlin, I. and Williams, B. (1994), `Pluralism and Liberal-
Cairns, A. and Williams, C. (eds) (1985), Constitutional-
ism: A Reply', in Political Studies, 42(2), pp. 306±9.
ism, Citizenship and Society in Canada, Toronto: Uni-
Bertram, C. (1997), `Political Justification, Theoretical Complexity,
and
Democratic
Community',
versity of Toronto Press.
Ethics,
Caney, S., George, D., Jones, P. (eds) (1996), National
107, pp. 563±83. Bideleux, R. (1996), `In Lieu of a Conclusion: East Meets
Rights, International Obligations, Oxford: Westview Press.
West', in R. Bideleux and R. Taylor (eds), European
Canovan, M. (1996), Nationhood and Political Theory, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Integration and Disintegration: East and West, London:
Canovan, M. (1999), `Trust the People! Populism and the
Routledge, pp. 281±95. Â anglaise devant l'inteBideleux, R. (1999a), `L'ambiguite
Two Faces of Democracy', in Political Studies, 47(1), pp. 2±16.
 de  ration ou gration', in A. Landuyt (ed.), Europe: Fe
Cassirer, E. (1951), The Philosophy of the Enlightenment,
nations, Paris: Sedes, pp. 97±120.
Boston, MA: Beacon.
Bideleux, R. (1999b), `Europeanization Versus Democra-
Claude, I. (1955), National Minorities: An International
tization in East-Central Europe, Ten Years On', in Society
and
Economy
in
Central
and
Eastern
Problem, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Europe
Cohen, G. A. (1989), `On The Currency of Egalitarian
(Budapest), 21(3), pp. 10±62.
Justice', Ethics, 99, pp. 906±44.
Bideleux, R. and Jeffries, I. (1998), A History of Eastern
Cohen, G. A. (1994), `Amartya Sen's Unequal World',
Europe, London: Routledge.
New Left Review, 203, pp. 117±29.
Blackburn, S. (1984), Spreading the Word, Oxford: Oxford
Cohen, G. A. (1986), `Self-Ownership, World Ownership,
University Press.
and Equality: Part II', in E. F. Paul, F. D. Miller Jr., J.
Blackburn, S. (1993), Essays in Quasi-Realism, Oxford:
Paul, J. Ahrens (eds), Marxism and Liberalism, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Blackwell, pp. 77±96.
Blackburn, S. (1996), `Securing the Nots: Moral Episte-
Cohen, G. A. (1995), Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equal-
mology for the Quasi-Realist', in W. Sinnott-Armstrong
ity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
and M. Timmons (eds), Moral Knowledge?, New York:
Cohen, G. A. (1996), `Incentives, Inequality and Com-
Oxford University Press, pp. 82±100.
munity', in P. King (ed.), Socialism and the Common
Blease, W. L. (1913), A Short History of English Liberalism,
Good, London: Frank Cass.
London: T. Fisher Unwin.
Cohen, J. (ed.) (1996), For Love of Country, Boston, MA:
Bobbio, N. (1996), The Age of Rights, Cambridge: Polity.
Beacon.
Boddy, J. (1989), Wombs and Alien Spirits: Women, Men Madison, WI:
Cohen, J. and Rogers, J. (1983), On Democracy, New York:
Boesche, R. (1987), The Strange Liberalism of Alexis de
Cohen, J. and Rogers, J. (1995), Associations and Democ-
and
the
Zar
Cult
in
Northern
Sudan,
Penguin.
University of Wisconsin Press.
racy, London: Verso.
Tocqueville, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Cohen. R. (1991), Negotiating Across Cultures, Washing-
Borneman, J. (1997), Settling Accounts: Violence, Justice and Accountability
in
Postsocialist
Europe,
Princeton,
ton, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.
NJ:
Collingwood, R. G. (1940), An Essay on Metaphysics,
Princeton University Press.
London: Oxford University Press.
Boucher, D. and Kelly, P. (eds) (1994), The Social Contract
Connor, W. (1984), The National Question in Marxist-
from Hobbes to Rawls, London: Routledge.
Leninist Theory and Strategy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton,
Bradley, I. (1980), The Optimists: Themes and Personalities
University Press.
in Victorian Liberalism, London: Faber & Faber.
Constant, B. (1988), Political Writings, ed. B. Fontana,
Brown, C. (1992), International Relations Theory: New
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Normative Approaches, London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Cooke, M. (1997), `Authenticity and Autonomy: Taylor,
Brown, C. (ed.) (1994), Political Restructuring in Europe:
Habermas and the Politics of Recognition', Political
Ethical Perspectives, London: Routledge.
Theory, 25(2), pp. 258±88.
Brownlie, I. (ed.) (1981), Basic Documents on Human
Croce, B. (1946), Politics and Morals, London: Allen &
Rights, 2nd edn. Oxford: Clarendon.
Unwin.
Brubaker, R. (1994), Citizenship and Nationhood in France and
Germany,
Croce, B. (1973), Etica e politica, Bari: Laterza.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Crocker, D. (1992), `Functioning and Capability: The
Press.
Foundations of Sen's and Nussbaum's Development
Bullock, A. and Shock, M. (eds) (1956), The Liberal
Ethic', Political Theory, 20(4), pp. 584±612.
Tradition from Fox to Keynes, London: A. & C. Black.
313
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Durkheim, E. (1982), The Rules of Sociological Method,
Crowder, G. (1994), `Pluralism and Liberalism', Political
trans. W. D. Hall, ed. by S. Lukes, London: Macmillan.
Studies, 42(2), pp. 293±305.
Dworkin, R. (1981a), `What is Equality? Part 1: Equality of
Cunningham, F. (1987), Democratic Theory and Socialism,
Welfare', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10(3), pp. 185±246.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dworkin, R. (1981b), `What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of
Dagger, R. (1997), Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship and Republican
Liberalism,
Oxford:
Oxford
Resources', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10(4), pp. 283±
University
345.
Press.
Dworkin, R. (1985), A Matter of Principle, Cambridge,
D'Agostino, F. (1993), `Transcendence and Conversation:
MA: Harvard University Press.
Two Conceptions of Objectivity', American Philosophical
Dworkin, R. (1995), `Constitutionalism and Democracy',
Quarterly, 30(2), pp. 87±108.
European Journal of Philosophy, 3, pp. 2±11.
Dahl, R. (1985), A Preface to Economic Democracy, Cam-
Dyzenhaus, D. (1997), Legality and Legitimacy, Oxford:
bridge: Polity.
Oxford University Press.
Dahl, R. (1994), `A Democratic Dilemma: System Effec-
Eagleton, T. (1990), The Ideology of the Aesthetic, Oxford:
tiveness Versus Citizen Participation', Political Science
Blackwell.
Quarterly, 109(1), pp. 23±34.
Eckersley, R. (1992), Environmentalism and Political Theory:
Dahrendorf, R. (1974), `Citizenship and Beyond: The
Towards an Ecocentric Approach, London: UCL Press.
Social Dynamics of an Idea', Social Research, 41, pp.
Eden, R. (1982), `Doing Without Liberalism: Weber's
673±701.
Regime Politics', in Political Theory, 10(3), pp. 379±407.
Daniels, N. (1996), Justice and Justification, Cambridge:
Elshtain, J. B. (1981), Public Man, Private Woman, Prin-
Cambridge University Press.
ceton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Dawisha, A. and Dawisha, K. (eds), (1995), The Making of
Engell, J. (1982), The Creative Imagination: Enlightenment to
Foreign Policy in Russia and the New States of Eurasia, New
Romanticism,
York: M. E. Sharpe.
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Derrida, J. (1989), Spectres of Marx, trans. by P. Kamuf,
Evans, M. (1985), Simone de Beauvoir: A Feminist Mandar-
London: Routledge.
in, London: Tavistock.
Devigne, R. (1994), Recasting Conservatism: Oakeshott,
Evans, M. (1999), `Is Public Justification Central to Lib-
Strauss, and the Response to Postmodernism, New Haven,
eralism?', Journal of Political Ideologies, 4(1), pp. 117±36.
CT: Yale University Press.
Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000), Sexing the Body, New York:
Devlin, P. (1965), The Enforcement of Morals, London:
Basic Books.
Oxford University Press.
Feinberg, J. (1985), Offense to Others, New York: Oxford
Diamond, M. and Kipnis, K. (1998), `Pediatric Ethics and
University Press.
the Surgical Assignment of Sex', Journal of Clinical
Feinberg, J. (1988), Harmless Wrongdoing, New York:
Ethics, 9(4), pp. 398±410.
Oxford University Press.
Dietze, G. (1985), Liberalism Proper and Proper Liberalism ,
Ferguson, M. (1985), First Feminists: British Women Writers
Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
1578±1799, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Digeser, P. (1995), Our Politics, Our Selves?, Princeton, NJ:
Ferrara, A. (1998), Reflective Authenticity: Rethinking the
Princeton University Press.
Project of Modernity, London: Routledge.
Dinnerstein, D. (1976), The Mermaid and the Minotaur:
Fish, M. S. (1997), `The Predicament of Russian Liberal-
Sexual Arrangements and Human Malaise, New York:
ism: Evidence from the December 1995 Parliamentary
Harper Colophon.
Elections', Europe-Asia Studies, 49(2), pp. 191±220.
Donnelly, J. (1989), Universal Human Rights in Theory and
Fitzmaurice, D. (1993), `Autonomy as a Good: Liberalism,
Practice, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Autonomy and Toleration', Journal of Political Philoso-
Doppelt, G. (1980), `Statism Without Foundations', Phi-
phy, 1(1), pp. 1±16.
losophy and Public Affairs, 9 (4), pp. 398±403.
Flax, J. (1995), `Race, Gender and the Ethics of Differ-
Doyle, M. (1983a), `Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign
ence', Political Theory, 23(3), pp. 500±10.
Affairs: Part 1', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12(3), pp.
Forsyth, M. (1987), Reason and Revolution: The Political
205±35.
 Sieye Á s, Leicester: Leicester University Thought of Abbe
Doyle, M. (1983b), `Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign
Press.
Affairs: Part 2', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12(4), pp.
Fox, W. (1990), Towards a Transpersonal Ecology, Boston,
323±53.
MA: Shambhala.
Doyle, M. (1986), `Liberalism and World Politics', Amer-
Franco, P. (1990), `Michael Oakeshott as a Liberal The-
ican Political Science Review, 80, pp. 1151±63.
orist', Political Theory, 18(3), pp. 411±36.
Dreze, J. and Sen, A. (1989), Hunger and Public Action,
Fraser, N, (1995), `From Redistribution to Recognition?
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dilemmas of Justice in a Post-Socialist Age', New Left
Dryzek, J. (1990), Discursive Democracy, Cambridge: Cam-
Review, 212, pp. 68±93.
bridge University Press.
314
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Goodin, R. (1988), `What Is So Special About Our Fellow
Fraser, N. and Nicholson, L. (1988), `Social Criticism
Countrymen?', Ethics, 98, pp. 663±86.
Without Philosophy: An Encounter Between Feminism
Goodin, R. (1995), `Political Ideals and Political Practice',
and Postmodernism', Theory, Culture and Society, 5(2/3),
British Journal of Political Science, 25(1), pp. 37±56.
pp. 373±94.
Gray, J. (1986), Hayek on Liberty, 2nd edn, Oxford: Black-
Frazer, E. (1996), `Feminism and Liberalism', in J. Mea-
well.
dowcroft (ed.), The Liberal Political Tradition, Chelten-
Gray, J. (1989), Liberalisms, London: Routledge.
ham: Edward Elgar.
Gray, J. (1993), Post-Liberalism: Studies in Political Thought,
Freeden, M. (1978), The New Liberalism: An Ideology of
London: Routledge.
Social Reform, Oxford: Clarendon.
Gray, J. (1995a), Enlightenment's Wake, London: Routle-
Freeden, M. (1986), Liberalism Divided: A Study in British
dge.
Political Thought 1914±1939, Oxford: Clarendon.
Gray, J. (1995b), Berlin, London: Fontana.
Freeden, M. (1996), Ideologies and Political Theory: A
Gray, J. (1997), Endgames: Questions in Late Modern
Conceptual Approach, Oxford: Clarendon.
Political Thought, Cambridge: Polity.
Freeden, M. (1998), `Is Nationalism A Distinct Ideology?',
Gray, J. (1998), `Global Utopias and Clashing Civilisa-
Political Studies, 46 (4), pp. 748±65.
tions: Misunderstanding the Present', International Af-
Frost, M. (1996), Ethics in International Relations: A Con-
fairs, 74(1), pp. 149±63.
stitutive Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Green,
Frost, M. (1997a), Layers of Justice: The Emerging Structure
P.
(1985),
Retrieving
Democracy,
London:
Methuen.
of Global Ethics, paper presented to the University of
Greenfeld, L. (1992), Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity,
Wales conference on Political and International The-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
ory, Gregynog. Frost, M. (1997b), The Role of Human Rights in Under-
Griffin, S. (1994), `Political Philosophy versus Political
standing World Politics, paper presented to the University
Theory: The Case of John Rawls', Chicago-Kent Law Review, 69, pp. 691±707.
of Manchester MANCEPT conference on Political
Gros, D. and Steinherr, A. (1994), `In Favour of EMU:
Thought and International Affairs.
A Manifesto of European Economists', in A. Steinherr
Fukuyama, F. (1989), `The End of History?', The National
(ed.), 30 Years of European Monetary Integration: From
Interest, 16 (summer), pp. 3±18.
the Werner Plan to EMU, London: Longman, pp. 74±
Fukuyama, F. (1992), The End of History and the Last Man,
79.
London: Penguin
Gunning, I. (1997), `Uneasy Alliances and Solid Sister-
Fuss, D. (1989), Essentially Speaking: Feminism, Nature and
hood: A Response to Obiora's ``Bridges and Barri-
Difference, New York: Routledge.
cades'' ', Case Western Reserve Law Review, 47 (2), pp.
Galston, W. (1991), Liberal Purposes, Cambridge: Cam-
445±60.
bridge University Press.
Gurr, T. (1993), Minorities at Risk: A Global View of
Garton Ash, T. (1998), `Europe's Endangered Liberal Order', in Foreign Affairs, 77(2), pp. 51±65.
Ethnopolitical
Washington, DC: Institute of
Gutmann, A. (ed.) (1994), Multiculturalism and the Politics
endon.
of Recognition, 2nd edn, Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-
Gay, W. and Alekseeva, T. A. (1996), Capitalism With a
versity Press.
Human Face: The Quest For a Middle Road in Russian
Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D. (1996), Democracy and
Politics, London: Rowman & Littlefield.
Gellner,
Conflict,
Peace Press.
Gauthier, D. (1986), Morals By Agreement, Oxford: Clar-
E.
(1983),
Nations
and
Nationalism,
Disagreement,
Oxford:
Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press.
Blackwell.
Habermas, J. (1979), Communication and the Evolution of
Gellner, E. and Cansino, C. (eds) (1996), Liberalism in
Society, trans. T. McCarthy, London: Heinemann.
 G. Merquior, Modern Times: Essays in Honour of Jose
Habermas, J. (1992), The Structural Transformation of the
Budapest: Central European University Press.
Public Sphere, trans. T. Burger and F. Lawrence, Cam-
Gerth, H. H., Wright Mills, C. (eds) (1991), From Max
bridge: Polity.
Weber, new edn, London: Routledge.
Habermas, J. (1993), `Struggles for Recognition in Con-
Gifford, E. A. (1994), ` ``The Courage to Blaspheme'': Confronting Barriers to Resisting Female Genital Mu-
stitutional States', European Journal of Philosophy, 1(2),
tilation', UCLA Women's Law Journal, 4, pp. 329±64.
pp. 128±55. Habermas, J. (1995), `Rawls's Political Liberalism', Journal
Gilligan, C. (1982), In a Different Voice, Cambridge, MA:
of Philosophy, 92(3), pp. 109±31.
Harvard University Press.
Habermas, J. (1996), Between Facts and Norms, trans. W.
Goldman, A. and Kim, J. (eds) (1978), Values and Morals,
Rehg, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
Habermas, J. (1998a), A Berlin Republic: Writings on Ger-
Gombrich, E. (1977), Art and Illusion, 5th edn, London:
many, Cambridge: Polity.
Phaidon.
315
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance , Cambridge:
Habermas, J. (1998b), The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in
Polity.
Political Theory, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Held, D. (1996), Models of Democracy, 2nd edn, Cam-
Haddock, B. (1993), `Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel:
bridge: Polity.
Philosophy of Right', in M. Forsyth, M. Keens-Soper,
Helgerson, R. (1992), Forms of Nationhood: The Elizabethan
J. Hoffman (eds.), The Political Classics: Hamilton to Mill,
Writings of England, Chicago: University of Chicago
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 104±36.
Press.
Haddock, B. (1996), `Michael Oakeshott: Rationalism in
Hennis, W. (1988), Max Weber: Essays in Reconstruction,
Politics', in M. Forsyth and M. Keens-Soper (eds), The Political
Classics:
Green
to
Dworkin,
London: Allen & Unwin.
Oxford: Oxford
Herman, B. (1985), `The Practice of Moral Judgment',
University Press, pp. 100±20.
Journal of Philosophy, 82 (8), pp. 414±36.
Hallowell, J. (1946), The Decline of Liberalism as an Ideol-
Hindess, B. (1996), Discourses of Power, Oxford: Blackwell.
ogy, London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co. Ltd.
Hampshire, S.
(1983),
Morality
and
Conflict,
Hirschman, A. (1994), `Social Conflicts as Pillars of
Oxford:
Democratic Market Society', Political Theory, 22, pp.
Blackwell.
203±18.
Hampshire, S. (1989), Innocence and Experience, London:
Hirst, P. (1994), Associative Democracy: New Forms of
Penguin.
Economic and Social Governance, Cambridge: Polity.
Hampshire, S. (1991), `Justice is Strife', Proceedings and
Hobhouse, L. T. (1924), Social Development: Its Nature and
Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 65(3)
Conditions, London: Allen & Unwin.
(Presidential Address).
Hobhouse, L. T. (1964), Liberalism, Oxford: Oxford
Harris, A. (1990), `Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal
University Press.
Theory,' in Stanford Law Review, 42, pp. 581±616.
Hobson, J. A. (1909), The Crisis of Liberalism, London: P.
Harriss, J. (ed.) (1995), The Politics of Humanitarian Inter-
S. King & Son.
vention, London: Pinter.
Hobson, J. A. (1928), `Review of G. de Ruggiero, The
Harsanyi, J. (1975), `Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality? A Critique of John Rawls's
History of European Liberalism', Journal of Philosophical
Theory',
Studies, 3, pp. 378±80.
American
Political
Science
Review,
69,
pp.
Hoffman, S. (1995), `The Crisis of Liberal International-
594±606.
ism', Foreign Policy, 98, pp. 159±77.
Hart, H. L. A. (1961), The Concept of Law, Oxford:
Holc, J. (1997), `Liberalism and the Construction of the
Clarendon.
Democratic Subject in Postcommunism: The Case of
Hart, H. L. A. (1963), Law, Liberty and Morality, London:
Poland', Slavic Review, 56(3), pp. 401±27.
Oxford University Press.
Holmstrom, N. (1994), `Humankind(s)', in M. Matthen and
Hartz, L. (1955), The Liberal Tradition in America, New
R. X. Ware (eds), Biology and Society: Reflections on Meth-
York: Harcourt, Brace & World Inc.
odology, Calgary: University of Calgary Press, pp. 69±105.
Haslett, D. W. (1985), `Does the Difference Principle
Honneth, A. (1995) The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral
Really Favour the Worst Off?', Mind, 94, pp. 111±15.
Grammar of Social Conflicts, Cambridge: Polity.
Hayek, F.A. (1939), `Economic Conditions of Inter-State
Hont, I. (1994), `The Permanent Crisis of a Divided
Federation', New Commonwealth Quarterly (September),
Mankind: ``Contemporary Crisis of the Nation State''
pp. 131±49.
in Historical Perspective', in Political Studies, 42, Special
Hayek, F. A. (1960), The Constitution of Liberty, London:
Issue on `Contemporary Crisis of the Nation State?', pp.
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
166±231.
Hayek, F. A. (1967), Studies in Philosophy, Politics and
hooks, b. (1981), Ain't I A Woman?, London: Pluto.
Economics, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Hough, J. (1997), Democratization and Revolution in the
Hayek, F. A. (1993), Law, Legislation and Liberty, 3 vols in
USSR, 1985±91, Washington, DC: Brookings Institu-
1, London: Routledge.
tion Press.
Hayek, F. A. (1976), The Road to Serfdom, London:
Hulme, P. and Jordanova, L. (eds) (1990), The Enlight-
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
enment and its Shadows, London: Routledge.
Hayes, C. J. (1949), The Historical Evolution of Modern
Hume, D. (1966), Enquiries Concerning the Human Under-
Nationalism, London: Macmillan.
standing and Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. L.A.
Heater, D. (1990), Citizenship: The Civic Ideal in World
Selby-Bigge, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
History, Politics and Education, London: Longman.
Hume, D. (1969), A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. E. C.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1969), Jenaer Realphilosophie, Hamburg:
Mossner, Harmondsworth: Pelican.
Meiner.
Huntington, S. (1993), `The Clash of Civilizations?',
Hegel, G. W. F. (1991), Elements of the Philosophy of Right,
Foreign Affairs, 72(3), pp. 23±49.
ed. A. W. Wood, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Huntingdon, S. (1994), The Clash of Civilizations and the
Press.
Remaking of World Order, New York: Simon & Schuster.
Held, D. (1995), Democracy and the Global Order: From the
316
BIBLIOGRAPHY
tions', Harvard Civil Rights ± Civil Liberties Law Review ,
Hurka, T. (1993), Perfectionism, Oxford: Oxford Univer-
22(2), pp. 507±87.
sity Press.
Krouse, R. and McPherson, M. (1988), `Capitalism, ``Prop-
Hutchinson, J. and Smith, A. D. (eds) (1994), Nationalism,
erty-Owning Democracy'' and the Welfare State', in A.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gutmann (ed.), Democracy and the Welfare State, Prin-
Ignatieff, M. (1994), Blood and Belonging, London: Vin-
ceton NJ: Princeton, University Press, pp. 79±105.
tage.
Kymlicka, W. (1989), Liberalism, Community and Culture,
Isaac, J. (1988), `Republicanism vs. Liberalism?: A Recon-
Oxford: Clarendon.
sideration', in History of Political Thought, 9, pp. 349±77.
Kymlicka, W. (1990), Contemporary Political Philosophy,
Jacob, M. (1994), `The Mental Landscape of the Public
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sphere: A European Perspective', Eighteenth-Century
Kymlicka, W. (1995), Multicultural Citizenship, Oxford:
Studies, 28 (4), pp. 95±113.
Oxford University Press.
Jahanbegloo, R. (1993), Conversations with Isaiah Berlin,
Kymlicka, W. (1996), `Concepts of Community and Social
London: Peter Halban. James, S. M. (1998), `Shades of Othering: Reflections on
Justice', in F. Olser Hampson and J. Reppy (eds), Earthly
Female Circumcision/Genital Mutilation', Signs, 23(4),
Goods: Environmental Change and Social Justice, Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 30±51.
pp. 1031±48.
Kymlicka, W. (1998), `Is Federalism an Alternative to
Jardine, A. (1985), Gynesis: Configurations of Women and
Secession?', in P. Lehning (ed.), Theories of Secession,
Modernity, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
London: Routledge, pp. 111±50.
Johnson, P. (1993), `Feminism and the Enlightenment',
Kymlicka, W. and Shapiro, I. (eds) (1997), Ethnicity and
Radical Philosophy, 63, pp. 3±12.
Group Rights, New York: New York University Press.
Kaldor, M. (1999), New and Old Wars, Cambridge: Polity.
Ladrech, R. (1994), `Europeanisation of Domestic Politics
Kamenka, E. (ed.) (1983), The Portable Karl Marx, Har-
and Institutions: The Case of France', Journal of Com-
mondsworth: Pelican.
mon Market Studies, 32(1), pp. 69±88.
Kant, I. (1948), Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals,
Laffan, B. (1999), `Democracy and the European Union',
translated by H.J. Paton as `The Moral Law', London:
in L. Cram, D. Dinan and N. Nugent (eds), Develop-
Hutchinson.
ments in the European Union, London: Macmillan, pp.
Kant, I. (1963a), Kant on History, ed. L. White Beck, New
329±49.
York: Bobbs-Merrill.
Lamont, J. (1994), `Pareto Efficiency, Egalitarianism and
Kant, I. (1963b), Lectures on Ethics, ed. L. Infield, New
Difference Principles', Social Theory and Practice, 20, pp.
York: Harper & Row.
311±25.
Kant, I. (1991), Political Writings, ed. H. Reiss, Cambridge:
Landes, J. (1988), Women and the Public Sphere in the Age of
Cambridge University Press.
the French Revolution, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Kauffman, L. (ed.) (1989), Gender and Theory: Dialogues on
Press.
Feminist Criticism, Oxford: Blackwell.
Laponce, J. (1987), Languages and Their Territories, Tor-
Kedourie, E. (1993), Nationalism, 4th edn, Oxford: Black-
onto: University of Toronto Press.
well.
Laponce, J. (1993), `The Case for Ethnic Federalism in
Kekes, J. (1993), The Morality of Pluralism, Princeton, NJ:
Multilingual Societies: Canada's Regional Imperative',
Princeton University Press.
Regional Politics and Policy, 3(1), pp. 23±43.
Kekes, J. (1996), `Cruelty and Liberalism', Ethics, 106, pp.
Laquer, T. (1990), Making Sex: Body and Gender from the
834±44.
Greeks to Freud, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Kelley, G. A. (1995), `Who Needs a Theory of Citizen-
Press.
ship?', in R. Beiner (ed.), Theorising Citizenship, New
Larmore, C. (1996), The Morals of Modernity, Cambridge:
York: State University of New York Press.
Cambridge University Press.
Kersting, W. (1993), Wohlgeordnete Freiheit: Immanuel
Laski, H. J. (1936), The Rise of European Liberalism, Lon-
Kant Rechts- und Staatsphilosophie, Frankfurt am Main:
don: Allen & Unwin.
Suhrkamp Verlag.
Laslett, P. (ed.) (1956), Philosophy, Politics and Society,
Klaus, V. (1997), Renaissance: The Rebirth of Liberty in the
Oxford: Blackwell.
Heart of Europe, Washington, DC: Cato Institute.
Layne, C. (1994), `Kant or Cant: The Myth of Democratic
Kouba, L. and Muasher, J. (1985), `Female Circumcision in
Peace', International Security, 19(2), pp. 5±49.
Africa: An Overview', African Studies Review, 28(1), pp.
Lijphard, A. (1968), The Politics of Accommodation: Plur-
95±110.
alism and Democracy in the Netherlands, Berkeley, CA:
Kritz, N. J. (ed.) (1995), Transitional Justice: How Emerging
University of California Press.
Democracies Reckon with Former Regimes , 3 vols, Wash-
Lind, E. A. and Tyler, T. (1988), The Social Psychology of
ington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.
Procedural Justice, New York: Plenum.
Kronowitz, R. (1987), `Towards Consent and Co-opera-
Linklater, A. (1992), `What is a Good International
tion: Reconsidering the Political Status of Indian Na-
317
BIBLIOGRAPHY
McGarry,
Citizen?', in P. Keal (ed.), Ethics and Foreign Policy, St
J.
(1998),
`Demographic
Engineering:
The
State-Directed Movements of Ethnic Groups as a Tech-
Leonards, NSW: Allen & Unwin, chapter 2.
nique of Conflict Resolution', Ethnic and Racial Studies,
Linklater, A. (1998), The Transformation of Political Com-
21(4), pp. 613±38.
munity, Cambridge: Polity.
McGrew, A. (1997), The Transformation of Democracy?,
Lloyd, G. (1984), Man of Reason, London: Methuen.
Cambridge: Polity.
Locke, J. (1991), Two Treatises of Government, ed. P.
Mendus, S. (1990), `Time and Chance: Kantian Ethics and
Laslett, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feminist Philosophy', Morrell Discussion Paper, Depart-
Lodge, J. (1994), `Transparency and Democratic Legiti-
ment of Politics, University of York.'
macy', Journal of Common Market Studies, 32(3), pp.
Mendus, S. (1992), `Losing the Faith: Feminism and
343±68. Loveland, I. (1996), `Parliamentary Sovereignty and the
Democracy', in J. Dunn (ed.), Democracy: The Unfin-
European Community: The Unfinished Revolution?',
ished Journey, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 207±
19.
Parliamentary Affairs, 49(4), pp. 517±35.
Merkel, W. (1994), `Deepening and Widening: The Limits
Lovibond, S. (1989), `Feminism and Postmodernism', New
of European Integration', in M. Szabo (ed.), The Chal-
Left Review, 178, pp. 5±28.
Lovibond, S. (1994), `Feminism and the `Crisis of Ration-
lenge of Europeanisation in the Region: East-Central Europe, Budapest: Kirali & Co., pp. 32±60.
ality', New Left Review, 207, pp. 72±86.
Meyers, D. T. (1989), Self, Society and Personal Choice,
Luban, D. (1980), `Just War and Human Rights', in
New York: Columbia University Press.
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 9(2), pp. 160±81.
Meyers, D. T. (1993), `Cultural Diversity: Rights, Goals
Luhmann, N. (1981), The Differentiation of Society, New
and Competing Values', in D. T. Goldberg and M.
York: Columbia University Press.
Krausz (eds), Jewish Identity, Philadelphia: Temple Uni-
Lyotard, J. (1993), `The Other's Rights', in S. Shute and S.
versity Press.
Hurley (eds), On Human Rights, New York: Basic Books,
Meyers, D. T. (1994), Subjection and Subjectivity: Psycho-
pp. 135±47.
analytic Feminism and Moral Philosophy, New York: Rout-
Macedo, S. (1989), `Capitalism, Citizenship and Commu-
ledge.
nity', in E. F. Paul, F. D. Miller Jr, J. Paul and J. Ahrens
Meyers, D. T. (ed.) (1997), Feminists Rethink the Self,
(eds), Capitalism, Oxford: Blackwell.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
MacIntyre, A. (1985), After Virtue, 2nd edn, London:
Meyers, D. T. (2000), `Intersectional Identity and the
Duckworth.
Authentic Self? Opposites Attract!', in C. Mackenzie
Mackie, J. L. (1977), Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong,
and N. Stoljar (eds), Relational Autonomy: Feminist
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency and the Social Self,
Majone, G. (1992), `Regulatory Federalism in the Eur-
New York: Oxford University Press.
opean Community', Government and Policy, 10, pp. 77±
Michelman, F. (1995), `On Regulating Practices with
101.
Theories Drawn from Them: A Case of Justice as Fair-
Malachowski, A. (ed.) (1990), Reading Rorty, Oxford:
ness', in I. Shapiro and J. W. DeCrew (eds), Nomos, vol.
Blackwell.
37: Theory and Practice, pp. 309±41.
Manin, B. (1987), `On Legitimacy and Deliberation',
Mill, J. S. (1972), `Utilitarianism', `On Liberty' and `Con-
Political Theory, 15(3), pp. 338±68.
siderations on Representative Government', ed. H. B. Ac-
Mann, M. (1993), `The Nation-State in Europe and Other
ton, London: J. M. Dent.
Continents: Diversifying, Developing, Not Dying', Dae-
Miller, D. (1976), Social Justice, Oxford: Clarendon.
dalus, 122(3), pp. 115±40.
Miller, D. (1995), On Nationality, Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Mansfield, E. D. and Snyder, J. (1995), `Democratization
versity Press.
and the Danger of War', International Security, 20(1), pp.
Minow, M. (1990), Making All The Difference: Inclusion,
5±38.
Exclusion and American Law, Ithaca, NY: Cornell Uni-
Marcuse, H. (1964), One-Dimensional Man, Boston, MA:
versity Press.
Beacon.
Moellendorf, D. (1996), `Constructing the Law of Peoples',
Martin, R. (1985), Rawls and Rights, Lawrence, KS: Uni-
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 77, pp. 132±54.
versity Press of Kansas.
Moi, T. (1992), Simone de Beauvoir: The Making of an
Martin, R. (1993), A System of Rights, Oxford: Clarendon.
Intellectual, Oxford: Blackwell.
Martin, R. and Shenoy, P. (1983), `Two Interpretations of
Moody-Adams, M. (1994), `Culture, Responsibility, and
the Difference Principle in Rawls's Theory of Justice',
Affected Ignorance', Ethics, 104, pp. 291±309.
Theoria, 49, pp. 113±41.
Mouffe, C. (1992), `Citizenship and Political Identity',
Mason, A. (1993), Explaining Political Disagreement, Cam-
October, 61, pp. 28±32.
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mouffe, C. (1993), The Return of the Political, London:
McDowell, J. (1998), Mind, Value and Reality, Cambridge,
Verso.
MA: Harvard University Press.
318
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Mugo, M. G. (1997), `Elitist Anti-Circumcision Discourse
Oneal, J. and Ray, J. L. (1997), `New Tests of the
as Mutilating and Anti-Feminist', Case Western Reserve
Democratic Peace: Controlling for Economic Interde-
Law Review, 47(2), pp. 461±80.
pendence', Political Research Quarterly, 50, pp. 1950± 85.
Mulhall, S. and Swift, A. (1996), Liberals and Commu-
O'Neill, J. (1993), Ecology, Policy and Politics: Human Well-
nitarians, 2nd edn, Oxford: Blackwell.
Being and the Natural World, London: Routledge.
Mu È llerson, R. (1997), Human Rights Diplomacy, London:
O'Neill, O. (1979), `The Most Extensive Liberty', Proceed-
Routledge.
ings of the Aristotelian Society, 80, pp. 45±59.
Naess, A. (1989), Ecology, Community and Lifestyle, trans. D.
O'Neill, O. (1986), Faces of Hunger, London: Allen &
Rothenberg, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Unwin.
Nagel, T. (1991), Equality and Partiality, Oxford: Oxford
O'Neill, O. (1988), `Abstraction, Idealization and Ideology
University Press. Narayan, U. (1997), Dislocating Cultures, New York: Routledge.
in Ethics', in J. D. G. Evans (ed.), Moral Philosophy and
Nardin, T. (1983), Law, Morality and the Relation of States,
Contemporary Problems, Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, pp. 55±69.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
O'Neill, O. (1996), Towards Justice and Virtue, Cambridge:
Neill, T. P. (1953), The Rise and Decline of Liberalism,
Cambridge University Press.
Milwaukee, WI: Bruce Publishing.
Orton, W. J. (1945), The Liberal Tradition, New Haven,
Newman, G. (1987), The Rise of English Nationalism: A Cultural History
CT: Yale University Press.
1740±1830, London: Weidenfeld &
Ost, D. (1991), `The Crisis of Liberalism in Poland', Telos,
Nicholson.
89, pp. 85±94.
Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York:
O'Sullivan, N. (1989), `The New Right: The Quest for a
Oxford University Press.
Civil Philosophy in Europe and America', in R. Eatwell,
Nussbaum, M. (1992), `Human Functioning and Social
N. O'Sullivan (eds), The Nature of the Right, London:
Justice', Political Theory, 20(2), pp. 202±46.
Pinter, pp. 167±91.
Nussbaum M. (1995), Poetic Justice, New York: Beacon.
O'Sullivan, N. (1997), `Difference and the Concept of the
Nussbaum, M. and Glover, J. (eds) (1995), Women,
Political in Contemporary Political Philosophy', Political
Culture and Development, Oxford: Clarendon.
Studies, 45(4), pp. 739±54.
Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A. (eds) (1993), The Quality of
Outram, D. (1995), The Enlightenment, Cambridge: Cam-
Life, Oxford: Clarendon.
bridge University Press.
Oakeshott, M. (1962), Rationalism in Politics, London:
Paden, R. (1997), `Reconstructing Rawls's Law of Peoples',
Methuen.
Ethics and International Affairs, 11, pp. 217±32.
Oakeshott, M. (1975a), On Human Conduct, Oxford:
Pantin, I. (1997), `Dramatic Confrontation of Democracy
Clarendon.
and Liberalism in Old and New Russia', Current Politics
Oakeshott, M. (1975b), Hobbes on Civil Association, Ox-
and Economics of Russia, 7(1), pp. 23±38.
ford: Blackwell. Oakeshott, M. (1996), The Politics of Faith and the Politics of
Parekh, B. (1995), `Politics of Nationhood', in K. von
Scepticism, ed. T. Fuller, New Haven, CT and London:
Benda-Beckmann and M. Verkuyten (eds), Nationalism,
Yale University Press.
Ethnicity and Cultural Identity in Europe, Utrecht: Eur-
opean Research Centre on Migration and Ethnic Rela-
Obiora, L. A. (1997), `Bridges and Barricades: Rethinking
tions.
Polemics and Intransigence in the Campaign Against
Parekh, B. (1997), `Rethinking Humanitarian Interven-
Female Circumcision', Case Western Reserve Law Review,
tion', International Political Science Review, 18, pp. 49±69.
47(2), pp. 275±378.
Parker, P. L. (ed.) (1912), Character and Society, London:
O'Brien, C. C. (1988), Godland: Reflections on Religion and
Williams & Norgate.
Nationalism, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Pateman, C. (1970), Participation and Democratic Theory,
O'Donnell, G. (1993), `On the State, Democratization and
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Some Conceptual Problems (A Latin American View with
Glances
at
Some
Postcommunist
Pateman, C. (1988), `The Theoretical Subversiveness of
Countries)',
Feminism', in C. Pateman and E. Grosz (eds), Feminist
World Development, 21(8), pp. 1355±69.
Challenges, Sydney: Allen & Unwin, pp. 1±10.
O'Donnell, G. (1994), `Delegative Democracy', Journal of
Peffer, R. G. (1990), Marxism, Morality and Social Justice,
Democracy, 5(1), pp. 55±69.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Ogbu, M. A. (1997), `Comment on Obiora's ``Bridges and
Peffer, R. G. (1994), `Towards a More Adequate Rawlsian
Barricades'' ', Case Western Reserve Law Review, 47(2),
Theory of Social Justice', Pacific Philosophical Quarterly,
pp. 411±22.
75(3/4), pp. 251±71.
Okin, S. M. (1994), `Gender Inequality and Cultural
Penz, P. (1992), `Development Refugees and Distributive
Difference', Political Theory, 22(1), pp. 5±24.
Justice: Indigeneous Peoples, Land and the Developmen-
Okin, S. M. (1998), `Feminism, Women's Human Rights
talist State', Public Affairs Quarterly, 6 (1), pp. 105±31.
and Cultural Difference', Hypatia, 13(2), pp. 32±52.
319
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Roemer, J. (1986), `Equality of Resources Implies Equality
Penz, P. (1993), `Colonization of Tribal Lands in Bangladesh and Indonesia: State Rationales, Rights to Land,
of Welfare', Quarterly Journal of Economics, 101, pp.
and Environmental Justice', in M. Howard (ed.), Asia's
751±84. Roemer, J. (1994), A Future for Socialism, Cambridge, MA:
Environmental Crisis, Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Harvard University Press.
Peterson, M. (ed.) (1977), The Portable Thomas Jefferson,
Rorty, A. O. (1994), `The Hidden Politics of Cultural
Harmondsworth: Pelican.
Identification', Political Theory, 22(1), pp. 152±66.
Pettit, P. (1997), Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and
Rorty, R. (1985), `Solidarity or Objectivity?', in J. Rajch-
Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
man and C. West (eds), Post-Analytic Philosophy, New
Phillips, A. (1993), Democracy and Difference, Cambridge:
York: Columbia University Press.
Polity.
Rorty, R. (1989), Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cam-
Pocock, J. G. A. (1957), The Ancient Constitution and the
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feudal Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rorty, R. (1998), Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers
Pogany, I. (1998), Righting Wrongs in Eastern Europe,
Volume 3, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Ruddick, S. (1989), Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of
Pogge, T. (1994), `An Egalitarian Law of Peoples', Philo-
Peace, London: Women's Press.
sophy and Public Affairs, 23(2), pp. 195±224.
Ruggiero, G. de (1927), The History of European Liberalism,
Pogge, T. (1995), `How Should Human Rights Be Con-
London: Oxford University Press.
È r Recht und Ethik, vol. 3, pp. 103±20. ceived?', Jahrbuch fu
Russett, B. (1995), `Correspondence: ``And Yet It Moves'',
Primus, R. A. (1999), The American Language of Rights,
International Security, 19(4), pp. 164±75.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rustow, D. A. (1970), `Transitions to Democracy: Toward
Rajchman, J. (ed.) (1995), The Identity in Question, Lon-
a Dynamic Model', Comparative Politics, 2(3), pp. 337±
don: Routledge.
63.
Ramsbotham, O. and Woodhouse, T. (eds) (1996), Hu-
Ryan, A. (ed.) (1979), The Idea of Freedom, Oxford:
manitarian Intervention in Contemporary Conflict , Cam-
Oxford University Press.
bridge: Polity.
Rychard, A. (1992), `Politics and Society After the Break-
Rawls, J. (1972), A Theory of Justice, Oxford: Oxford
through: The Sources and Threats to Political Legiti-
University Press.
macy in Post-Communist Poland', in G. Sanford (ed.),
Rawls, J. (1990), `Justice as Fairness: A Restatement'
Democratisation in Poland 1988±90, London: Macmillan,
(unpublished mimeo).
pp. 133±54.
Rawls, J. (1996), Political Liberalism, 2nd edn, New York:
Saage, R. (1973), Eigentum, Staat und Gesellschaft bei
Columbia University Press.
Immanuel Kant, Stuttgart/Berlin: Kohlhammer.
Rawls, J. (1999), Collected Papers, ed. S. Freeman, Cam-
Sachs, D. (1981), `How to Distinguish Self-Respect from
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Self-Esteem', in Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10(4), pp.
Raz, J. (1986), The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Claren-
346±60.
don. Â aume, D. (1995), `Justice Between Cultures: Autonomy Re
Sandel, M. (1982), Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Oxford: Blackwell.
and the Protection of Cultural Affiliation', University of
Sandel, M. (1984), `The Procedural Republic and the
British Columbia Law Review, 29(1), p. 121.
Unencumbered Self', Political Theory, 12(1), pp. 81±96.
Rees, J. C. (1971), Equality, London: Macmillan.
Sandel, M. (1996), Democracy's Discontent: America in
Rees, J. C. (1985), John Stuart Mill's `On Liberty', Oxford:
Search of a Public Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Clarendon.
University Press.
Regan, T. (1988), The Case for Animal Rights, London:
Sapiro, V. (1992), A Vindication of Political Virtue: The
Routledge.
Political Theory of Mary Wollstonecraft, Chicago: Uni-
Renteln, A. D. (1990), International Human Rights: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
versalism versus Relativism, London: Sage.
Saward, M. (ed.) (forthcoming), Innovations in Democratic
Rhees, R. (1970), Discussions of Wittgenstein, London:
Theory, London: Routledge.
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Scanlon, T. (1982), `Contractualism and Utilitarianism',
Richardson, H. (1994), Practical Reasoning About Final
in A. K. Sen and B. Williams (eds), Utilitarianism and
Ends, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.
Ritchie, D. G. (ed.) (1954), Natural Rights, London: Allen
103±28.
& Unwin.
Schaar, J. H. (1981), Legitimacy in the Modern State, New
Robertson, C. (1996), `Grassroots in Kenya: Women, Genital
Mutilation,
and
Collective
Action
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books.
1920±
Scheman, N. (1993), Engenderings: Constructions of Knowl-
1990', Signs, 21(3), pp. 615±42.
edge, Authority and Privilege, New York: Routledge.
Roemer, J. (1985), `Equality of Talent', Economics and
Schieder, T. (1962), The State and Society in our Times:
Philosophy, 1, pp. 151±87.
320
BIBLIOGRAPHY
th
th
Centuries,
J. Richardson (ed.), European Union: Power and Policy-
Schmitt, C. (1985), The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy,
Solzhenitsyn, A. (1974), Letter to the Soviet Leaders, Lon-
Studies
in
the
History
of
the
19
and
20
Making, London: Routledge, pp. 247±62.
London: Thomas Nelson & Sons.
don: Index on Censorship.
trans. E. Kennedy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Soper, K. (1990), Troubled Pleasures, London: Verso.
 des citoyens: sur Schnapper, D. (1994), La communaute
Soper, K. (1997), `Naked Human Nature and the Drap-
 e moderne de la nation, Paris: Gallimard. l'ide
eries of Custom', in E. Yeo (ed.), Mary Wollstonecraft and
Schweickart, D. (1993), Against Capitalism, Cambridge:
200 Years of Feminism, London: Rivers Oram Press, pp.
Cambridge University Press.
207±21.
Scott, J. (1996), Only Paradoxes to Offer, Cambridge, MA:
de Sousa Santos, B. (1996), Towards a New Common Sense,
Harvard University Press.
London: Routledge.
Scruton, R. (1990), The Philosopher on Dover Beach: Essays,
Spelman, E. V. (1988), Inessential Woman, Boston, MA:
Manchester: Carcanet.
Beacon Books.
Seglow, J. (1998), `Universals and Particulars: The Case of
Spinelli, A. (1957), `The Growth of the European Move-
Liberal Cultural Nationalism', Political Studies, 46(5),
ment Since World War II', in C. G. Haines (ed.),
pp. 963±77. Seligman, A. B. (1992), The Idea of Civil Society, New
European
Johns Hopkins
Spivak, G. (1991), `Remembering the Limits', in P. Os-
Sen, A. K. (1981), Poverty and Famines, New York: Oxford
borne (ed.), Socialism and the Limits of Liberalism, Lon-
University Press.
don: Verso, pp. 227±39.
Sen, A. K. (1982), Choice, Welfare and Measurement,
Spivak, G. (1993), Outside in the Teaching Machine, Lon-
Oxford: Blackwell. Sen, A. K.
Integration, Baltimore, MD:
University Press, pp. 40±63.
York: Free Press.
don: Routledge.
(1984), Resources, Values and Development,
Squires, J. (ed.) (1993), Principled Positions, London: Law-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
rence & Wishart.
Sen, A. K. (1985), `Well-Being, Agency and Freedom',
Staniskis, J. (1991), The Dynamics of the Breakthrough in
Journal of Philosophy, 82(4), pp. 169±221.
Eastern Europe, Berkeley, CA: University of California
Sen, A. K. (1992), Inequality Reexamined, Cambridge, MA:
Press.
Harvard University Press. Shaheed, F. (1994), `Controlled or Autonomous: Identity
Stanley, F.G. (1961), The Birth of Western Canada: A
and the Experience of Network, Women Living Under
History of the Riel Rebellions, Toronto: University of
Toronto Press.
Muslim Laws', Signs, 19(4), pp. 997±1019. Shaheed, F. (1995), `Networking for Change: The Role of
Stockdale, M. K. (1996), Paul Miliukov and the Quest for a
Women's Groups in Initiating Dialogue on Women's
Liberal Russia 1880±1918, Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univer-
sity Press.
Issues', in M. Afkhami (ed.), Faith and Freedom: Wo-
Strauss, L. (1968), Liberalism Ancient and Modern, New
men's Human Rights in the Muslim World, Syracuse, NY:
York: Basic Books.
Syracuse University Press, pp. 78±103.
Strawson, P. (1959), Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive
Shaw, P. (1992), `Rawls, the Lexical Difference Principle
Metaphysics, London: Methuen.
and Equality', in Philosophical Quarterly, 42, pp. 71±7.
Sunstein, C. (1991), `Preferences and Politics', Philosophy
Sher, G. (1975), `Justifying Reverse Discrimination in
and Public Affairs, 20, pp. 3±34.
Employment', in Philosophy and Public Affairs, 4(2),
Sunstein, C. (1993), The Partial Constitution, Cambridge,
pp. 159±70.
MA: Harvard University Press.
Sher, G. (1997), Beyond Neutrality, Cambridge: Cambridge
Sussman, E. (1998), `Contending with Culture: An Ana-
University Press.
lysis of the Female Genital Mutilation Act of 1996', in
Shklar, J. (1989), `The Liberalism of Fear', in N. Rosen-
Cornell International Law Journal, 31(1), p. 193.
blum (ed.), Liberalism and the Moral Life, Cambridge,
Sutch, P. (2000), `Human Rights as Settled Norms: Mer-
MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 21±38.
vyn Frost and the Limits of Hegelian Human Rights',
Shue, H. (1980), Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and US
Review of International Studies, forthcoming.
Foreign Policy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Szacki, J. (1995), Liberalism after Communism, Budapest:
Singer, P. (1974), Democracy and Disobedience, Oxford:
Central European University Press.
Oxford University Press.
Tamir, Y. (1993), Liberal Nationalism, Princeton, NJ:
Singer, P. (1993), How Are We To Live? Ethics in an Age of
Princeton University Press.
Self-Interest, London: Mandarin.
Taylor, C. (1989), Sources of the Self, Cambridge: Cam-
Skinner, Q. (1998), Liberty Before Liberalism, Cambridge:
bridge University Press.
Cambridge University Press.
Taylor, C. (1995), Philosophical Arguments, Cambridge,
Smith, A. (1976), An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of
MA: Harvard University Press.
the Wealth of Nations, vol. 1, Oxford: Clarendon.
Temple-Lang, J. (1996), `Community Constitutional Law',
Smith, M. (1996), `The EU as an International Actor', in
321
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Home and Abroad, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
in B. Laffan (ed.), Constitution-Building in the European
Dame Press.
Union, Dublin: Institute of European Affairs, pp. 124±
Ward, I. (1997), `Law and the Other Europeans', Journal of
40.
Common Market Studies, 35(1), pp. 79±96.
Tickell, T. (1822), Poems of Thomas Tickell, The British
Warnke, G. (1995), `Discourse and Feminist Dilemmas of
Poets, vol. XXVII, College House: C. Whittingham.
Tomaselli, S. (1985), `The Enlightenment Debate on
Difference', in J. Meehan (ed.), Feminists Read Haber-
Women', History Workshop Journal, 20, pp. 101±44.
mas: Gendering the Subject of Discourse , London: Rout-
ledge, pp. 247±61.
Toubia, N. (1995), Female Genital Mutilation: A Call for
Weber, M. (1994), Political Writings, eds P. Lassman and R.
Global Action, New York: Rainbo.
Speirs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Touraine, A. (1997), What is Democracy?, Boulder, CO:
Welch, S. (1993), The Concept of Political Culture, London:
Westview Press.
Macmillan.
Tsagarousianou, R., Tambini, D. and Bryan, C. (eds)
Wenar, L. (1995), `Political Liberalism: An Internal Cri-
(1998), Cyberdemocracy: Technology, Cities and Civic
tique', Ethics 106, pp. 32±62.
Networks, London: Routledge.
Wiggins, D. (1988), `Truth, Invention and the Meaning of
Tully, J. (1995), Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an University
Life', in G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Rea-
Turpel, M. E. (1990), `Aboriginal Peoples and the Cana-
Williams, A. (1995), `The Revisionist Difference Princi-
Age
of
Diversity,
Cambridge:
Cambridge
lism, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, pp. 127±65.
Press. dian Charter: Interpretive Monopolies, Cultural Differ-
ple', Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 25, pp. 257±82.
ences', Canadian Human Rights Yearbook, 6, pp. 3±45.
Williams, H. (1983), Kant's Political Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell.
Tuveson, E. L. (1960), The Imagination as a Means of Grace,
Winch, P. (1958), The Idea of a Social Science, London:
Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Van Parijs, P. (1991), `Why Surfers Should Be Fed: The
Winch, P. (1972), `Nature and Convention', in his Ethics
Liberal Case for an Unconditional Basic Income', in
and Action, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, pp. 50±
Philosophy and Public Affairs, 20(2), pp. 101±31.
72.
Van Parijs, P. (1992), `Basic Income Capitalism', Ethics,
Wissenberg, M. (1998), Green Liberalism: The Free and
102, pp. 465±84.
Green Society, London: UCL Press.
de Varennes, F. (1996), Language, Minorities and Human
Wittgenstein, L. (1968), Philosophical Investigations, trans.
Rights, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
G. E. M. Anscombe, Oxford: Blackwell.
Vincent, A. (1990), `The New Liberalism in Britain 1880±
Wittgenstein, L. (1969), On Certainty, eds G. E. M.
1914', Australian Journal of Politics and History, 36(3), pp.
Anscombe and G. H. von Wright, Oxford: Blackwell.
388±405.
Wolff, J. (1996), An Introduction to Political Philosophy,
Waldron, J. (ed.) (1984), Theories of Rights, Oxford: Ox-
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
ford University Press.
Wollstonecraft, M. (1989), The Works of Mary Wollstone-
Waldron, J. (1993), Liberal Rights, Cambridge: Cambridge
craft, vol. 5, 2nd edn, eds J. Todd and M. Butler, New
University Press.
York: New York University Press.
Waldron, J. (1999), The Dignity of Legislation, Cambridge:
Yolton, J., Rogers, P., Porter, R. and Stafford, B. (eds)
Cambridge University Press.
(1991), The Blackwell Companion to the Enlightenment,
Walicki, A. (1991), `From Stalinism to Post-Communist
Oxford: Blackwell.
Pluralism: The Case of Poland', New Left Review, 185,
Young, I. M. (1989), `Polity and Group Difference: A
pp. 92±121.
Critique of the Ideal of Universal Citizenship', Ethics,
Walker, M. U. (1998), Moral Understandings: A Feminist
99, pp. 251±74.
Study in Ethics, New York: Routledge.
Young, I. M. (1990), Justice and the Politics of Difference,
Walley, C. (1997), `Searching for ``Voices'': Feminism,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Anthropology, and the Global Debate over Female
Young, I. M. (1995), `Gender as Sociality: Thinking About
Genital Operations', Cultural Anthropology, 12(3), pp.
Women as a Serial Collective', in L. Nicholson and S.
405±38.
Seidman (eds), Social Postmodernism: Beyond Identity
Walzer, M. (1977), Just and Unjust Wars, New York: Basic
Politics,
Books.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.
187±215.
Walzer, M. (1983), Spheres of Justice, Oxford: Blackwell.
Zakaria, F. (1997), `The Rise of Illiberal Democracy',
Walzer, M. (1990), `Nation and Universe', in G. Peterson
Foreign Affairs, 76 (6), pp. 22±43.
(ed.), The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. XI, ed.
Zolo, D. (1992), Democracy and Complexity, Cambridge:
G. B. Petersen, Salt Lake City, UT: University of Utah
Polity.
Press, pp. 509±56. Walzer, M. (1994), Thick and Thin: Moral Arguments at
322
INDEX
abstraction, 76±7, 80, 199, 201, 256
Baumeister, A., 11±12
Ackerman, B., 54, 61, 128
Baxter, B., 13, 16
Addison, J., 204
Beitz, C., 53
A' Haleem, A. M., 216
Bellamy, R., 12, 272, 274
Albertini, M., 226, 230
Benson, P., 213, 219, 221n34
Alekseeva, T. A., 283
Bentham, J., 167
Alexander, W., 203
Benton, T., 298n25
alienation, 212, 291
Berlin, I., 57, 69, 137±42, 145, 146n3, 147n19, 161n43, 163, 170n11
Anderson, P., 140, 142 anti-essentialism, 75, 78±82, 200
Bideleux, R., 13
anti-foundationalism, 147±59, 162±3
Bielecki, K., 274±5
anti-perfectionism, 6, 8, 299±301, 303, 305, 310
Blackburn, S., 152±3 Brown, C., 254
see also impartiality; neutrality
Appiah, K. A., 97
Brubaker, R., 59±60
Aristotelianism, 56, 188, 192, 193n1, 297n3
Buchanan, A., 129
Aristotle, 56, 141, 182
bureaucracy, 177, 182±3, 284
Arneson, R., 124, 129
Burke, E., 201±2, 204
Aron, R., 276
Buzgalin, A., 272
Augustine, Saint, 52 Austin, J., 167
Callinicos, A., 129
authenticity, 95±8, 213±14, 220
Canovan, M., 11
authority, 154±6, 160n8, 167±8, 185
capitalism, 8, 17±18, 114±15, 117±18, 120±1, 125±9, 131n40, 134n43, 229±31, 236, 272±5,
autonomy, 13, 24, 28±9, 31, 32n42, 32n51, 54, 84,
280, 283±4, 296
90±1, 116, 162, 180, 185, 189±90, 192, 198± 9, 200, 204, 208±20, 221n50, 222n61, 233,
Carens, J., 44
261, 276±7, 289±90, 297n14, 299, 305±6, 308
Carter, E., 204 Cassirer, E., 199
Axtmann, R., 281
categorical imperative, 83 Babbit, S., 213, 219±20
Chernomyrdin, V., 272±3
Bader, V., 61
Chubais, A., 272±3
Balcerowicz, L., 272±4
Cicero, 67
Barber, B., 71
citizenship, 10±11, 37±8, 41, 51±61, 61n3, 75±84, 197±8, 202, 227, 231, 283±4, 305, 306
Barry, B., 128, 297n1
323
INDEX
civil association, 13, 63±4, 167, 225±39
186n16, 189±90, 197±8, 200±1, 205, 225±39,
civil society, 8, 25, 37, 162±3, 177, 192, 236, 247,
243±5, 263, 269±70, 272±3, 275±7, 280±1, 300, 303
282±3 Clinton, B., 307
deontology, 188
Cohen, G. A., 8, 120±2, 124, 129
Derrida, J., 200
Cohen, J., 129
Dewey, J., 54, 300
Cohen-Tanugi, L., 231
dialogue, 98±9, 155±6
communism, 49n21, 66±7, 113, 125±8, 238,
Diderot, D., 202±3 Dietze, G., 279
252n31, 269±84
difference, ethics/politics of, 11, 46, 75, 77, 79,
communitarianism, 9±10, 16, 22, 30, 94, 100n5,
80±1, 115±16, 205, 206n26
116±17, 182, 253±64, 281, 297n20
difference principle, 12, 101±10, 110n3, 115±16,
Condorcet, M. J. A. N., 202
118±23, 130n14
consensus, 10, 28, 67±8, 71±2, 95, 98, 156, 162± 3, 169, 176±7, 179, 184, 189±90, 214, 231,
Digeser, P., 299±300
258, 261±2, 265n45, 265n48
Dinnerstein, D., 78 Doyle, M., 241±51
conservatism, 32n38, 66, 68, 73n22, 94, 297n19,
Dryzek, J., 183
308 Constant, B., 56±7, 65, 188±9
Dworkin, R., 5, 25, 31, 54, 90, 128
constitutionalism, 49n31, 57, 179, 182±5, 188±92,
Dzarasov, S., 280
225, 237, 262, 276±7 Eckersley, R., 289±90, 292, 297n7
see also constitution(s)
ecocentrism, 13, 288±93, 295±6
constitution(s), 44±5, 168, 175, 177, 180±1, 185,
ecologism (`Green' theory), 13, 16, 182±3, 287±96
247, 262
education, 38, 40±1, 53, 76, 89, 96, 180, 215,
see also constitutionalism
217±19, 221n36, 305±7, 311n19
constructivism
egalitarianism, 101±9, 112n30, 113±16, 119±20,
as meta-ethical theory, 103±4, 107, 141, 188±
128±9
92, 253±7, 260±1, 264
see also equality
as form of political doctrine, 273±4 contractarianism, 9, 29, 104
Eisenberg, A., 40
cosmopolitanism, 11, 51±3, 55, 60±1, 61±2n3, 71,
Elshtain, J. B., 78
226, 229, 232, 239, 244, 248, 253±7, 260±2,
Elster, J., 129
264n3
Engels, F., 15 Enlightenment, 6, 10±12, 76, 197±205, 205n1,
counter-Enlightenment, 12±13, 140, 200
205±6n1, 206n14, 263, 291, 293
Croce, B., 25±6, 29, 280
equality, 6, 30, 35, 68, 71, 75±7, 80±1, 83±4, 94,
Cudd, A., 110
101±10, 111n9, 115, 117±18, 121, 123, 183±
culture, 8, 18±19, 35±47, 47n5, 49n24, 93±9, 138,
4, 198, 248±9, 280
162, 165±6, 183, 185, 199, 203, 208±20,
see also egalitarianism
293±6, 306
essentialism, 78±9, 200, 205 Dahl, R., 230
ethnocentrism, 78, 152, 157±8, 205
Dahrendorf, R., 57, 269
eurocentrism, 35, 47, 49n33
Daniels, N., 128
European Union, 13, 225±39, 240n15
de Beauvoir, S., 200
Evans, M., 12, 129, 146n4
deconstruction, 200
exploitation, 123±5
de la Barre, P., 202 democracy, 7, 15, 16±17, 39±40, 42, 67, 82, 99,
Fedorov, B., 272
115±18, 126±7, 136±7, 143±4, 175±85,
Feinberg, J., 306
324
INDEX
feminism, 11±12, 75±84, 197±205, 289
Hallowell, J., 27±9
Ferrara, A., 100n15
Hampshire, S., 137±8, 141
Fish, S., 271±2, 279
Harris, A., 75, 78±9, 111n8
Flax, J., 75, 78
Hart, H. L. A., 162±3, 166±8
foundationalism, 27, 29, 148±51, 153, 158±9,
Hartz, L., 26, 28 Haslett, D. W., 112
160n10, 162±3, 167, 170, 198, 255, 260 Fraser, N., 99, 201
Hausner, J., 274
fraternity, 120, 130n25
Hayek, F., 9, 65, 72n4, 73n22, 73n27, 137, 183, 225, 231±2, 234±5, 237±8, 239n1, 270, 274,
Freeden, M., 6, 11
279, 285n36
freedom, 6, 7, 23, 27, 35, 72, 76, 89, 93, 97, 145,
Hayes, C., 282
184, 198, 247±9, 269±70, 287
Hegel, G. W. F., 26, 125, 165, 242±3, 248, 292,
see also liberty/liberties
293n19
French Revolution, 70, 201, 279 Freud, S., 210
Held, D., 17
Friedman, M., 270
Herder, A., 95
Frost, M., 254, 258±9, 263±4
Herman, B., 83
Fukuyama, F., 6, 14, 18, 242±4, 246, 248±51, 269,
Herzen, A., 283 Hiley, C., 149
280 fundamentalism (religious), 15, 161n36, 200, 257
history, theory(ies) of, 14±15, 22±3, 25±7, 242±3,
Gaidar, Y., 271±3
Hobbes, T., 164, 166±7, 169, 283, 292, 297n19
Galston, W., 299
Hobhouse, L. T., 22±7, 29±30, 178, 300
Garton Ash, T., 239
Hobson, J. A., 23, 28, 30
Gay, W., 283
Hoffmann, S., 282
Gellner, E., 269
Holc, J., 275
genital cutting, 208±20, 221n50
Holmstrom, N., 129
Geras, N., 129
Honneth, A., 91±3, 97
Gilligan, C., 85n15
Hont, I., 70
globalisation, 16±17, 186n16, 229, 231, 238, 279
hooks, b., 75, 78
Goodin, R., 73n46, 179
Hough, J., 270
Gorbachev, M., 270
human rights, 7, 35±47, 49n24, 49n33, 51±3, 57±
249±50, 269
9, 63, 65, 69±70, 148±59, 160n23, 231, 253,
Gortat, R., 273
258±62, 264
Gottlieb, R., 129
see also group rights; minority rights; rights
Gray, J., 3, 4, 8, 13, 61, 66±7, 69, 73n39, 162±3,
humanitarian intervention, 70±1, 149, 156±7,
170n11, 227, 232, 274, 285n36
161n39
Green, T. H., 57, 280, 300 group representation, 10, 75, 81±2, 181, 185
Hume, D., 164, 166, 204, 243, 306
group rights, 11, 34±47, 49n24, 49n33, 55, 238
Humeanism, 156 Huntington, S., 278
see also human rights; minority rights; rights
Hutcheson, F., 204
Guignon, D., 149 Gutmann, A., 128
identity, 8, 66, 75, 81±4, 89±99, 200, 205, 231, 291, 302
Habermas, J., 53, 76, 82±4, 85n50, 135±6, 185,
Ignatieff, M., 69
188±92, 201, 206n22
impartiality, 10, 24, 26, 68, 76±7, 80, 82±3, 90,
Haddock, B., 12, 73n35, 240n47
184, 288, 297n2
Hague, W., 228
see also anti-perfectionism; neutrality
Hailsham, Lord, 237
325
INDEX
law/legal system(s), 43, 156, 164, 167±8, 176±81,
imperfect duty/obligation, 76, 82±3
185, 186n41, 190±2, 193n12, 225±6, 231±9,
individualism, 7, 10, 35, 38, 52, 184, 255, 281,
245, 248, 260±2, 303
282±3 individuality, 8, 16, 18±19
Layne, C., 241
Islam, 210, 215, 281
Lebed, A., 273 legitimation crisis, 17, 274±5
Jacob, M., 201
Lenin, V. I., 69
Joad, C. E. M., 27
Levine, A., 129
Johnson, P., 200
libertarianism, 7, 9
judicial review, 177, 181
liberty/liberties, 23, 26, 57, 67, 71, 101, 115±17, 119, 175±8, 186n37, 188±91, 225±6, 228,
see also Supreme Court
236±7, 263±4, 280, 282±3
justice, 7±9, 16, 22, 24, 29, 30±1, 35±47, 47n5,
see also freedom
76, 80, 82, 90±9, 101±9, 110n1, 110n2, 110± 11n6, 113±31, 135±8, 141, 143, 179±82, 185,
Linklater, A., 53
188±9, 233, 253±4, 257, 262, 264, 280, 301,
Lloyd, S., 129
311n10
Locke, J., 29±30, 32n54, 191, 243 Loveland, I., 231
justification, 11±12, 29, 94±5, 143, 154, 156, 158,
Luzhkov, Y., 278
164, 189, 262
Lyotard, J.-F., 165 Kagarlitskii, B., 276 Kaldor, M., 236, 240n54
McBride, W., 129
Kant, I., 51, 54, 61n2, 75, 83±4, 135, 146, 198,
Macaulay, C., 76, 203
200, 203±4, 207n34, 241±51, 252n16, 261,
MacDonald, J. A., 38
290, 292, 297n13
MacDonald, M., 151 McDowell, J., 160n13
see also Kantianism
Machiavelli, N., 138, 182, 242
Kantianism, 4, 6, 28, 53, 75, 82, 83±4, 139, 156, 158, 163, 170, 203, 252n31, 253±4, 260±1,
MacIntyre, A., 260
263, 289±90, 297n14, 297n19, 297n21
Mackie, J. L., 160n16, 256±7 Mann, M., 228
see also Kant, I.
market(s), 57, 120, 128±9, 175±7, 182±3, 229,
Karimov, I., 278
236±7, 243, 250, 269, 272±5, 282±2
Kekes, J., 163 Keynes, J. M., 274
Marshall, T. H., 58
Kirienko, S., 273
Martin, R., 12, 110
Klaus, V., 272
Marx, K., 15, 292, 297n19
Kolodko, G., 274
Marxism, 12, 26, 69, 113±32, 280, 297n3
Kozyrev, A., 273
maximin reasoning, 103, 106±9, 111n23, 119
Kristol, I., 280
Mazowiecki, T., 273, 275
Kymlicka, W., 10±11, 55, 95, 99n2, 106, 129, 281
Mazzini, G., 281 Mendelssohn, M., 200
Lamont, J., 110, 111n11
Mendus, S., 77
Lamont, N., 228
Merquior, J., 269, 277, 283
Landes, J., 199
Meyers, D. T., 13
language, 38, 40±1, 48n20, 93, 96, 165
Michelet, J., 281
Laquer, T., 202
Mill, J. S., 30, 35, 55, 69, 93, 163, 197, 204, 245, 278±9, 281, 296, 300, 302, 311n15
Larmore, C., 137, 141±2, 144, 191 Laski, H., 24, 32n60
Millar, J., 203
Lassman, P., 12
Miller, D., 100n30, 129, 263
326
INDEX
Milyukov, P., 281
Pettit, P., 178
minimum morality, 140±1, 163, 167, 260, 262±3
Phillips, A., 80
minority rights, 35±47, 48n6, 48n20, 99n2
Plato, 18 pluralism, 8, 12, 26, 82, 93, 99, 135, 136±44, 162,
see also group rights; human rights; rights
170n11, 175±85, 189±90, 200, 257
Mises, L. von, 270
`reasonable', 138±9, 141, 144, 162, 261, 263
Mohammad, M., 278 Montesquieu, C., 65
Pogge, T., 52±3, 61n3, 129, 255
Moody-Adams, M., 217, 219
political liberalism, 10, 29, 30, 31, 32n51, 135±8, 141, 143±4, 162±3, 188±92
Mouffe, C., 156
political philosophy/theory, 3±6, 13, 19, 19n1, 22,
multiculturalism, 10±11, 26, 35±47, 53, 177,
116, 135±6, 139, 149±50, 159, 162, 169, 241,
186n16, 231
255±6, 259 politics, conception(s) of, 30, 57, 63±4, 69, 75,
Naess, A., 290
139, 142, 156, 164
Nagel, T., 5, 128, 288, 297n2, 297n3 Nardin, T., 233±4, 239n1
Popper, K., 29
nationalism, 11, 15, 24, 28, 51±61, 63±72, 142,
post-communism, 13, 269±84 postmodernism, 130n44, 198±201, 205
280±4
practical reason, 12, 170, 255±6, 260±1
nationality, 11, 35±47, 51±61, 62n20, 63±72, 176
see also public reason; rationality; reason
Nemtsov, B., 272±3
pragmatism, 12, 27, 148±59
neutrality, 6, 31, 287, 299
praxis, 291±2, 294
see also anti-perfectionism; impartiality
progress, 13±14, 23±7, 29±30, 76, 162, 175, 249±
Nielsen, K., 129
50
Nietzsche, F., 156
progressivism, 6, 18, 32n38
non-cognitivism, 150±3, 156, 159, 160n16, 160±
projectivism, 152±3, 158
1n29, 161n34 Nozick, R., 9, 130n24, 137, 270
Prokhanov, A., 282
Nussbaum, M., 53, 75, 80, 85n14, 128, 161n32
public/private distinction, 28, 75, 78, 97, 181,
Oakeshott, M., 63±7, 72, 73n22, 167, 169, 225,
public reason, 6, 28, 30, 263
188±92, 198, 225, 302±3 see also practical reason; rationality; reason
232±4, 238, 239n1 objectivity, moral, 150±1, 158 O'Donnell, G., 277
Rasmussen, D., 12
Okin, S. M., 75, 80, 129
rational choice theory, 111n18, 212±13, 221n20
O'Neill, O., 83, 254±8, 260±1
rationality, 11, 28, 146, 162, 204, 290 see also practical reason; public reason; reason
Orban, V., 271
Rawls, J., 3, 5±6, 8±10, 12±13, 20n18, 23, 25, 28±
original position, 104±5, 109, 189, 295 Ost, D., 270, 283, 285n35
31, 36, 54, 90, 101±10, 110n1, 110n2,
Outram, D., 200, 206n26
110n4, 110±11n6, 111n8, 111n9, 111n18, 111n20, 111n23, 112n24, 112n26, 110n29,
Parekh, B., 68, 73n49
112n30, 113±29, 130n14, 135±9, 141±6,
Pareto optimality, 107, 119
147n51, 156, 160n8, 161n36, 162±3, 170, 188±92, 253±4, 258±64, 296, 299, 311n10
Pateman, C., 75±7 Peffer, R. G., 12
Raz, J., 6, 184, 299±300, 306, 311n4, 311n5
perfect duty/obligation, 76, 82±3
realism, moral, 150, 152±3, 160n13
perfectionism, 13, 16, 64, 299±311, 311n5
reason, 12, 24, 26±7, 76, 199±200, 203±4, 206n14 see also practical reason; public reason;
personcentrism, 13, 287±8, 292±3, 295±6
rationality
personhood, 287±8, 292±4, 297n19, 297±9n22
327
INDEX
 aume, D., 47 Re
Shklar, J., 12, 65, 72n16, 135, 144±6, 310
recognition, 12, 89±99, 100n2, 100n3, 180, 205,
Shlapentokh, D., 282 Shue, H., 128
242, 248 Redwood, J., 228
Ás, Abbe Â, 56 Sieye
Rees, J. C., 35
Simonia, N., 270
Regan, T., 297n14
Simpson, O. J., 68
Reiman, J., 129
Skinner, Q., 178
relativism, 9, 116±17, 152, 171, 202, 205
Smith, A., 185n5, 204
republicanism, 12, 18, 175±85, 186n7, 188±92,
Smith, M., 228 socialisation, 91, 151, 213±14, 221n34, 302, 305
244±6, 249
socialism, 7, 16, 18, 113±15, 117±18, 122, 124±9,
rights, 7, 92, 94, 115±17, 123, 126, 165, 175±7,
131n46, 198, 279±80, 297n19
181, 185, 189±91, 197, 216, 236, 275, 278,
Sogrin, V., 272±3, 280, 284
283, 297n25
Solzhenitsyn, A., 271
see also group rights; human rights; minority
Soper, K., 11±12
rights Rights of Man, 1789 Declaration, 59, 64±5, 70
Spelman, E. V., 75, 78±9
Roemer, J., 124±5, 129
Spinelli, A., 226, 230
romanticism, 18±19, 24, 140, 204
Spivak, G., 200
Roosevelt, F. D., 191
Staniskis, J., 275
Rorty, R., 7, 12, 142, 148±59, 160n4, 160n10,
state, 68±70, 227, 231, 247±8 Stoicism, 52±3
160n13, 160n23, 162±3 Rousseau, J.-J., 67, 203±4, 292, 297n19, 297n20
Strauss, L., 30, 142
Ruddick, S., 78
Strawson, P., 297±8n22
Ruggiero, G. de, 23±9, 54
Supreme Court, 28, 43±4, 45 see also judicial review
Rustow, D., 282 Rutland, P., 273
Sutch, P., 13
Rychard, A., 274±5
Szacki, J., 270, 272±3, 283±4
Sakharov, A., 271
Tarasov, A., 282
Sakwa, R., 13
Taylor, C., 20n27, 23, 54±5, 91, 95±8, 100n3, 100n15, 100n19, 100n21, 100n23, 100n30
Sandel, M., 9 Sapiro, V., 198
Taylor, H., 197
Scanlon, T., 5, 128
teleology, 188±90, 205
Schaar, J., 70±1
Temple-Lang, J., 231
Scheffler, S., 128
Thatcher, M., 228
Schmitt, C., 137, 140, 143, 161n42
Tickell, T., 70
Schmitter, P., 275
Timofeev, L., 270
Schumpeter, J., 57, 242
Tocqueville, A. de, 18, 65, 245, 279
Schweickart, D., 121, 129
toleration, 145, 154±5
Scott, J., 202
Tomaselli, S., 203
Seglow, J., 11±12
Tully, J., 176
self-esteem, 91±4, 100n9
Tuveson, E. L., 204
self-respect, 92, 100n2, 100n9, 115, 119 Sen, A. K., 9, 124, 128
United Nations, 36±8, 53±4, 65, 68, 80, 156
Shaftesbury, Third Earl of, 204
Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 35, 37, 65, 149, 278
Shenoy, P., 110
universalisability, 254±7
Sher, G., 299, 308
328
INDEX
Wenar, L., 162±3
universalism, 52, 59, 61, 71, 75±84, 140, 199±200,
Wiggins, D., 153
239, 253±7, 260±1, 263, 278
Williams, A., 106, 110
utilitarianism, 55, 106, 112n26, 163, 193n1
Williams, B., 137, 141 Van Parijs, P., 128±9
Williams, H., 13
Vico, G., 280
Winch, P., 164±5, 167
Vincent, A., 11
Wissenberg, M., 297n1
Voltaire, 204
Wittgenstein, L., 164±5, 167 Wolff, J., 106
Waldron, J., 128
Wolff, R. P., 129
Walicki, A., 274
Wollstonecraft, M., 76, 197±9, 201±2, 204±5, 206n6, 206n8
Walker, A., 213 Walker, G., 49n31 Walley, K., 221n36
Yavlinskii, G., 274
Walzer, M., 9, 54, 116, 129, 136, 254, 258±64,
Yeltsin, B., 271±3 Young, I. M., 10, 55, 75±7, 80±3, 85n23, 85n42,
297n18
100n11
Ward, I., 236 Warnke, G., 85n50
Zakaria, F., 276±7, 279
Weber, M., 17, 135±6, 138, 141±5, 146n4,
Zhirinovskii, V., 271
147n19, 147n27, 147n38, 182
Zyuganov, G., 284
Weimar `Problem', 135, 137±8, 143±4, 146 Welch, S., 281
329