Lecture Notes in Mathematics Edited by A. Dold and B. Eckmann
405 Keith J. Devlin H,~vard Johnsbraten
The Souslin Prob...
92 downloads
1106 Views
4MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Lecture Notes in Mathematics Edited by A. Dold and B. Eckmann
405 Keith J. Devlin H,~vard Johnsbraten
The Souslin Problem
Springer-Verlag Berlin-Heidelberg • New York 1974
Dr. Keith Devlin Seminar fer Logik und Grundlagenforschung der Philosophischen Fakult~t 53 Bonn BeringstraBe 6 BRD Dr. Havard Johnsbr&ten Matematisk Institutt Universitetet I Oslo, Blindern Oslo 3/Norge
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Devlin, Keith J The Souslin problem. (Lecture notes in mathematics, 405) Bibliography: p. 1. Set theory. I. Johnsbraten, Havard, 1945joint author. II. Title. III. Series: Lecture notes in mathematics (Berlin) 405. QA3.L28 no. 405 [QA248] 510'.8s [5!i'.3] 74-17386
AMS Subject Classifications (1970): 02-02, 02 K05, 02 K25, 04-02, 04A30 ISBN 3-540-06860-0 Springer-Verlag Berlin • Heidelberg • New York ISBN 0-38?-06860-0 Springer-Verlag New York • Heidelberg • Berlin This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically those of translation, reprinting, re-use of illustrations, broadcasting, reproduction by photocopying machine or similar means, and storage in data banks. Under § 54 of the German Copyright Law where copies are made for other than private use, a fee is payable to the publisher, the amount of the fee to be determined by agreement with the publisher. © by Springer-Verlag Berlin • Heidelberg 1974. Printed in Germany. Offsetdruck. Julius Beltz, Hemsbach/Bergstr.
Acknowledgements
The last five chapters of this book are based almost exclusively on a set of notes written by Devlin during the S11mmer of 1972.
During this time, he was living with,
and almost en-
tirely supported by his wife's parents, Mr and Mrs H. Carey of Sidcup, Kent, to whom thanks
should now be put on record.
The manuscript was typed by Mrs. R. Msller of the University of Oslo, for whose care and patience we owe a considerable debt.
CONTENTS
Chapter I. II.
Preliminaries
I
Souslin's Hypothesis
8
The Combinatorial Property
23
Homogeneous Souslin Trees and Lines
32
Rigid Souslin Trees and Lines
46
Martin's Axiom and the Consistency of SH
5~
VII.
Towards
68
V~I.
Iterated Forcing Jensen Style
74
How J e n s e n K i l l e d
97
III. IV. V. VI.
IX. X.
ConZFC
Con(ZFC + C H + SH) : A False Start
~
a Souslin Tree
Con(ZFC+CH+SH)
113
APPENDIX. Iterated Souslin Forcing and ~ ( ~ )
122
REFERENCES
426
GLOSSARY OF NOTATION
128
INDEX
CORRECTION
A n Israel£ mathematician
called Uri Avraham has pointed
t~at~ in Chapter
IX, the claim straddling
false as stated.
To be precise,
define,
for C a certain
order-embedding
~a+2
(although
on page
should have
In fact,
given an Aronszajn
closed unbounded
subset
tree ~, we
of ~ ,
a ('generic)
to all of ~° As we have set things up this
a slight modification
to the definition
105 would in fact make our claim said is not that our particular
all of @, but
105 and 106 is
of TIC into Q, and claim that this order-embed-
ding can be extended is false
pages
out
that it easily
this is perhaps
in terms of our original
true).
of
What we
embedding
extends
to
gives rise to such an embedding.
more easily definition
seen
(via Theorem II.5)
of special
Aronszajn
(Page
15)= By means of our embedding Um< Am, where
of TIC into Q, we may write TIC =
each A m is an (uncountable)
~:aml~ be a or~e-one enumeration ~ be the monotone e a c h ~ x e T c , let s x = able,
let
lysTlc
1- , , ( W z ~c~< & )~'-u { U - -, m - , m
Keith J. Devlin 1 4.9 • 74
of A m , each m, and let <m~l
+ I I x ~ ( z , x
The c_onstructible hierarchy,
If
2
so is
the a s s u m p t i o n
ZFC + V
= L .
(Hence,
any result w h i c h
V = L
will be c o n s i s t e n t
relative
to
.)
Theorem Let
2
(Condensation
lim(m) .
Theorem Let
If
X~
Lemma)
Lm
then
X ~ L~
for a unique
6 ~ m .
3
a I = w~
If
X~La2
If
A
, a2 = w~ .
, then
is a g i v e n
sets a n a l o g o u s l y allowing
A
XNLal
If
X~Lal
= LB
for some
set we can define to the d e f i n i t i o n
to figure
of the d e f i n i t i o n s .
, then
La+I[A]
for some
(LaEA] I a E 0 n )
of the c o n s t r u c t i b l e
will
6 ~ at°
B ~ ~I
a hierarchy
in the c o n s t r u c t i o n
(Thus
X = L~
as a u n a r y consist
of
hierarchy,
predicate
of all subsets
by
in all of
-3-
L [A]
which
structure
are f i r s t - o r d e r
(LaCA], E , A N L a [ A ] )
are g i v e n in [DeI], rems 2 and 3
where
.
from m e m b e r s
Full d e t a i l s
proofs
of
L [A]
of this
of the f o l l o w i n g
in the
construction
analogues
of theo-
may be found.
Theorem
4
Suppose
A ~ w L [ A ] . If
nals
definable
X-~L
[A]
, then
X T L ~ [ A 0 y]
ordi-
for unique
¥ < 8 _< ~ •
Theorem Let
5
ml = "I
for some
' ~2 = w
8 ~ ml
If
, A ~ ~I X
(2)
disjoint
S
x E S
from
D
has cardinality
versely,
x 6 S
2w .
there
x
from
S
defined by
fn(X)
= xn .
(Since
S
is complete,
subsets of
For
in
sequence
ISI ~ 2 w . ConS
into
n E w , let
Then the functions
by a theorem of J. Ball
~w
(D) ~
fn
2w.)
sequence fn : S ~ S be
are not all con-
[Ba I] .
question w h i c h h i s t o r i c a l l y
Mary Ellen Rudin
[Rul]
has shown that
exists a Souslin line, then there exists a normal Hausdorff
space w h i c h is not countably paracompact. C.H. Dowker
[Do I]
pact and normal
iff
we obtain that in (4)
sequence
D , a set of cardinality
In conclusion we m e n t i o n one topological
if there
of cardi-
as the least u p p e r bound.
with lub x .
SH .
In
Consequently:
exists a strictly i n c r e a s i n g
<x i l i e w>
has been connected with
D
there exists a strictly increasing with
S ,
is an uncontable
by (I), there exists an injection from
For each
tinuous,
[<x~,xv+1> I v < w l ]
of
conjecture.
has a dense subset
open intervals).
the set of all countable
(3)
S
a natural
is a strictly increasing
(for otherwise
family of pairwise
(7)
(x v Iv < ~>
If now
exists a Souslin line if and
There
that a topological X x I ZFC + xSH
is normal
space (I
space
X
is countably p a r a c o m -
is the real unit interval),
the f o l l o w i n g
exists a normal Hausdorff
not normal.
Together with the result of
is provable: X
such that
X x I
is
-11
Recently, ~SH
M.E. R u d i n [Ru 3 ]
, i.e. as a t h e o r e m in
-
has f o u n d a proof of (4) without a s s u m i n g ZFC
alone.
2. Souslin trees A tree is a poset [yET
Iy~x]
~ = (T,~)
is well o r d e r e d b y
the height of
x
we m a y define
ht(x)
For
a E On
We write For
such that for every
, ht(x)
, the
Tla
x E T
~
.
.
be a tree. ~
b y i n d u c t i o n as follows: ~
Tx = [yET1 ht(T)
x ~y]
T .
under
ht(x)
is the set
for the r e s t r i c t i o n of
sup[ht(x) I x E X ]
T
, is the o r d e r type of
~'th level of
we set
Let
x E T , the set
T
x E T ,
~
(Hence
= [xET
lht(x) =~].
Tla = U ~ a T ~ -
X ~ T
is called the length of
For
= s u p e r ( y ) lynx].)
to the set When
x =
we let ~ .
ht(X)
=
(From now on,
w h e n there is no danger of confusion, we denote a tree simply b y
T =
~T,~) • )
Two elements
x,y
of a tree
t h e y are incomparable, subset of x E b
T .
and
T
written
A branch
b
y ~ x , then
are c o m p a r a b l e if x ~ y xly
.
.
If
y~x
; if not,
A chain is a l i n e a r l y o r d e r e d
is a chain w h i c h is
y E b
or
ht(b)
~-closed,
= a , then
b
i.e. if is an
a-
branch.
An a n t i c h a i n is a set of p a i r w i s e i n c o m p a r a b l e elements of
A branch
(resp. an antichain)
in a l a r g e r b r a n c h
A tree T
T
ITI = w I
Ta
(resp. antichain).
Ta
ITI = ~I
is countable . T
T
is A r o n s z a j n or Souslin,
is an antichain~
and every chain in
is called a S o u s l i n tree if
and every chain and a n t i c h a i n in
N o t e that if each
is called maximal if it is not i n c l u d e d
is called an A r o n s z a ~ n tree if
and every level
T .
T
then
is countable.
ht(T)
= wI .
every S o u s l i n tree is Aronszajn.
Since Aronszajn
trees can (in the p r e s e n c e of the axiom of choice) be p r o v e d to exist (c.f.
[ J e l ], [ J e ~
, or [Ru2]). It is often convenient that the trees
satisfy c e r t a i n "normality" properties.
So let us call a tree
T
a
-12-
normal tree of length (i)
(ii) (iii)
ht(T)
T
= ~
has a unique least point,
each non-maximal
and
(v)
If
T
point
if:
(i.e. points
called the root of
T .
has at least two immediate
y
such that
ht(y)
= ht(x) + I
x ~ y ) ,
each
at each greater level
8 -branch has at most one immediate
< m ,
successor w h e n
is a limit ordinal,
each level
is normal,
Tv
is countable.
then
will be uncountable).
ht(T) ~ ml
chains.
without u n c o u n t a b l e
antichains.
Souslin tree.
(otherwise,
by (iii) and (iv), T I
A normal A r o n s z a ~ n tree is a normal mq-tree
without u n c o u n t a b l e
antichain,
m-tree)
x
each point has successors
8 (vi)
(or a normal
,
successors
(iv)
~
A normal Souslin tree is a normal
w I -tree
Then a normal Souslin tree is indeed a
(For an u n c o u n t a b l e
chain gives rise to an u n c o u n t a b l e
again by (iii).)
Theorem 3 Every S o u s l i n tree
T
Souslin tree
Similarly for A r o n s z a j n trees.
Proof:
T*
.
Remove f r o m
can be normalized,
T
the points
x
i.e.
for which
T
contains a normal
Tx
is countable,
then remove those points with only one immediate The resulting tree, T' , is still of length By induction,
pick out one point
in
To
sulting subtree,
struction applies also for A r o n s z a j n trees.
due to E.W. M i l l e r
ml ' hence Souslin.
in
T" 9 is a normal Souslin tree.
The long list of definitions [Ni I] :
successor.
and one point
every b r a n c h of limit length with extensions
and
T'
extending The r e -
The same con-
|
above is justified by the f o l l o w i n g fact,
-13-
Theorem 4 Souslin's h y p o t h e s i s tree,
to the n o n - e x i s t e n c e
of a Souslin
i.e. there exists a Souslin line if and only if there exists a
Souslin tree. cardinality
Proof:
is equivalent
Furthermore,
of
wI
Suppose S
every Souslin line has a dense subset
S
is a Souslin line.
is countable,
it is not dense in
union of a n o n - e m p t y open intervals.
collection
D
in
By induction, I(U~< a D ~ ) in
IS
assume
and let
Indeed,
T
I(D)
D
o
is the
of pairwise
disjoint
is countable,
since
is defined for consist
We claim that
S
~ < ~ .
Set
S.
I~ =
of one point from each interval and p a r t i a l l y order wI
T
b x re-
is a Souslin tree. with
"normality proper-
hence it is enough to show that every anti-
is countable.
f a m i l y of pairwise
S - D
of
consist of one point from
is a tree of cardinality
T
whence
D
above denotes the topological
T = U <Wl Im
(iii) satisfied,
chain in
Let
D~ Da
Now let
verse inclusion.
ty"
S. )
(~
S,
I(D)
And of course,
has the Souslin property. closure of
Observe that if a subset
But an antichain in
disjoint
open intervals
in
T
is just a
S , hence
count-
able. N o w we look at that
D
D = U~<wl D~ .
is dense in
< w1
S .
If not, let
there is an interval
Ja o J~+1 chain in
for each
a , so
T , impossible:
Clearly,
Jm E I m
tree.
.
containing
For each p .
But
is an u n c o u n t a b l e
Hence we have shown that a Souslin
suppose that
In fact, we may also assume that
lowing strengthening
p E S-D
[J~a
Then let
Let
such that
Tm
such that An'
b = it [~n ( t ~
that
ht(sn) > ~ n ' Sn)]. )
consist of the sequences
Ub s
for
s £TI~.
is defined.
antichain
of
T .
be a countable, A E M .
cally satisfied meters.
Define
So -->T s ~ and
T
Now
wq , so it remains
is countable. T,A c L
, so
Let
elementary
We also want
since b o t h are definable
Now we use Theorem 1.2.
be a w2
submodel of
T,w I E M ,
A
to
T,A E L
wI M
be a
such b r a n c h in the canonical w e l l - o r d e r -
show that every antichain of
Let
A n , n E w,
SUPnEw ~n = a "
is obviously a normal tree of length
maximal
antichains
Let
lies above a point in
be the least
s
6~ < w~ , so
U T8. Hence, for every s E Tim there exists an 8<m b going through s and m e e t i n g every A n (Such
a b r a n c h m a y be obtained as follows.
for each
Then
(L 2 , E )
such
but this is automatiin
L
w2 It follows that
w i t h o u t parawI O M
is
-q8 -
transitive,
so let
e = wI A M < w I
, the collapsing isomorphism,
(by
x E M .
So
Hence if
induction).
Lwq
ON, wI w(wq) = m .
Thus
= Ty
y
for
~(A)
c
Now,
y < wI .
,
But
e
= ~"(AON)
= AAN
of
Tie
and in
= ANT}a
.
But since
is maximal also in
Note:
By modifying
the
some
A ~ w I , then
~SH
If
A final remark.
e = ~(Wl)
ZF
L6e.
antichain of
T e , every point in
Corollary:
M,
is countable in
is a maximal
~(x) = x
is definable Ty E N
in
for y < ~.
,
N o w we are ready to conclude the proof. Lw2
so
Ty'S
.
Since
AcT,
so
~(A)
able in
T¥ Thus
is defined as the u n i o n of the
TI~
x c M,
= w " ( x N M)
= ~(Uy~.4~l Ty)
= Uy
~
TIC ~ t h e n there is a u n i q u e i s o m o r p h i s m
<S,~>
such that
~ " I s = Io(s)
for all
s E TIC
.
Lemma 8 Let
~ :<S,~)
~
<S,~>
such that if
s E Ta
Is , .
~
set
Hence
~(s)
s'
assume
: T~C ~ on
and
s' E Tm
a u t o m o r p h i s m on
and let
a : <S,~)
there exists a closed u n b o u n d e d TIC , and
TIC
.
~"I s =
TIC
if we
~
~
<S,~)
C ~ wI
.
such that
reverses the l e x i c o g r a p h i c a l o r d e r i n g
On the o t h e r hand, b y the p r o o f of T h e o r e m 3,
a < ml
Thus let
s,s'
such that if
E TIA
a ~ v < ht(s) , then
such that
~(s) ht(s'),
is h o m o g e n e o u s .
Indeed,
For
let
~x
be the l a r g -
= s~8
or
x~8
x 6 T
s u c h t h at
x~
let
= s'~B
.
by
{ i s'
if ~ v < x~x if v
~
we h a v e
= a
and
lim~
,
such that Or
s
= I -
S t
for
% > ~ .
H e n c e we o b t a i n (3)
If
a ~ wq
is c l o s e d u n b o u n d e d
automorphism s u c h that or Thus
T
If we let
mq
is c l o s e d u n d e r
ble.
|
T~A , then there i) h t (s)
> v ~ a ~ s
o
is an
is an
a < mq
> v ~ m - s v = o(s v) = 1-o(s
)
automorphisms.
S = S T , it f o l l o w s
Souslin line with S
either
ii) h t ( s )
has
on
and
exactly
wj
the m a p p i n g
that
S
is a h o m o g e n e o u s
automorphisms. s'-~s
.
Hence
But in this case, S
is r e v e r s i -
Chapter V
RIGID SOUSLIN TREES AND LINES
1. A rigid Souslin tree A poset ism on
X = <X, ~ > X .
is called rigid if
We now prove that in
idIX
is the only automorph-
L , rigid Souslin trees exist.
Theorem 1 Assume ~
Proof:
.
Then there exists a rigid Souslin tree.
Let
A ~ wI
IV.I.
and
Ma
(m < w I)
We define a standard tree
T~+ 1 = [ s ~ ( i ) with
Is E T
lim(~)
To define
T
^ i E 2]
as follows.
for
a < wq
As an induction hypothesis,
T~
we force over
=
E M a,
M
A p:a-
G c]P
be the least
rify.)
(in L[A])
is countable in
thesis that
TI8 E N B
Define for
Now let
assume
N -generic
Ma+ I , G E Na+ 1 .
for all
lim(B)
set for
ii) iiD iv)
bn
b n ~ bm each
bn
for is
a-branch
of
Tla,
n ~ m, N -generic for
if
nq,...,n m
are distinct,
bn I
x bn 2 × ... Xbnm
is
~
.
will be trivial to ve-
n E
is an
.
(Hence the hypo-
Claim: Each
TIa E M a .
(pn~qn)
bn = [Pn I p E G ]
i)
a < w
TI~)],
~-~ dom(p) ~ dom(q) ^ Vn E dom(q)
Na
= {d} and
O
with the set of conditions
p ~q
Since
.
T
defined as follows:
: [plSa c ®(lal a ,
since
and
d E Is,
Hence we have p r o v e d that
is rigid.
If now
S
was reversible,
then, b y Lemma IV.8 , there w o u l d
have b e e n an antilexicographical
automorphism
some closed u n b o u n d e d
But then
is impossible,
since
C ~ wI id
~
on
TIC
for
~ = ida(TIC) , which
is not at all antilexicographical
I
One might be t e m p t e d to conjecture not be reversible.
that a rigid ordered continuum can-
This is not so, however.
We now construct f r o m ~
a rigid Souslin line w h i c h is reversible. Theorem 3 Assume
~
.
tomorphisms,
Proof:
Then there exists a Souslin tree n a m e l y the identity on
T
T
= dom(s)
and
with exactly two au-
and the m a p p i n g
s E 2 <wl , ~
We recall at once that for dom(s)
T
s~ = q - s v
for
s~'~s
.
is defined by:
v < dom(s)
The tree
is d e f i n e d as the rigid tree, but with the f o l l o w i n g modifi-
cation:
If
we now define every branch
lim(~) , then T
to be
{s I s E bn}
Souslin b y Lemma IV.2. that
T
~ , G , b n (n E ~) [Ub n I n E w ] is
are as before.
U [~n
Ma-generic
for
InEw] T
But
" Of course,
, so
T
is
It is also clear from the c o n s t r u c t i o n
is closed under the a u t o m o r p h i s m
sr~s
.
As in the final part of the proof of Theorem I, the assumption that
~
is different b o t h from the identity and the m a p p i n g
-
s~s
-
readily leads to a contradiction.
as before. ther
~(x)
Then for every = x
x o I o(x o) ~ Xo that
o(x) ~ x ,
or "
By m o d i f y i n g the proof, r e p l a c e d by
TIC
o(x)
For let
x E T m , a(x)
= ~ .
Then,
hence
contradiction :
T
50
Let
taking o(x)
be
E Mm[x] , hence ei-
x ° E Tim
x E T m,
= x .
m = mm
be such that
x • x o , we have
But then
°(Xo)
= Xo ' a
|
one finds that this theorem is also true with
whenever
C ~ wI
is closed unbounded.
Theorem 4 Assume ~ .
Proof:
Then there exists a Souslin line (i)
S
is rigid,
(ii)
S
is reversible.
Let
T
be the tree of Theorem 5.
note above and Lemma IV.6
Set
we get that
as in the proof of Theorem 2.
to
such that
S = ST . S
<S, ~ > .
From the
is rigid,
Furthermore,
obviously gives an i s o m o r p h i s m from which is isomorphic
S
(S, ~ ) ( S
exactly
the m a p p i n g
br~b
onto a continuum
is obtained by remo!
ving the right-hand
sides of all gaps from
Chapter IV, section 2.)
ST
as defined in
|
3. S o m e final remarks We know from deed,
if
T
~
that there are two n o n - i s o m o r p h i c
Souslin trees.
is the rigid Souslin tree from section 1, then
In fact, by an easy argument, that there are
2 wl
Jech
non-isomorphic
LJe 3]
has p r o v e d that
Souslin trees.
to the '~classical" result of Gaifman and Specker
~
In-
T (0) ~ T ~1 implies
This is analogous
LGa Sp]
that
(in ZFC)
-
there are
2 wq
different
51
-
i s o m o r p h i s m types of A r o n s z a j n trees.
this context we also m e n t i o n that Devlin [De 2] of B a u m g a r t n e r
and proved that,
assuming
morphic A r o n s z a j n
trees w h i c h are
For normal trees
T
automorphisms
T .
on
of length Hence,
~(T)
= ~1
IV.
In fact, Jech [Je 3]
length
o(T) w = o(T)
.
2w
, there are
2 wl
if
T
e(T)
denote the number of
is rigid,
Souslin tree
is either finite,
then
T
has proved that if
c(T)
= 1 , and
constructed T
or
T
with
and
2 ml
~(T)
in Chapter
is a normal
tree of
2 ~ ~ o(T) ~ 2 wl
of arbitrary p r e s c r i b e d
provided
non-iso-
Q-embeddable.
He has also proved that it is consistent
a Souslin tree between
o(T)
has extended a theorem
]R-embeddable but not
wq , let
for the homogeneous
w I , then
In
and
that there is
cardinality
~w = ~ .
Jensen has proved that if we assume
, then there is a homogeneous
Souslin tree
(It is doubtful w h e t h e r this
is p r o v a b l e >+
T
such that
from
Define
.)
We scetch the proof.
6o , M o
chy of models
N'
~(T) ~ w 2 .
Let
(So l a < ~ 1 )
as in the proof of Theorem IV.1.
is defined as follows:
N'
O
A new hierar-
= L 6, [AJ
O
satisfy
where
6'
is
' O
the least
8
countable in case
such that N'
O
A tree
"
lim(a) : An
generic for
L6[AJ T
o-branch
TIo
and
~
ZF- + "8 a is countable".
is defined as before, b
of
b E N' . o
Tlo
on
Tla,
ded to an a u t o m o r p h i s m lim(S),
if
~ E Ms
on
then
a
is extended iff
TI(a+I)
Furthermore,
for
is an extendable
automorphism
on
(This is so b e c a u s e
M s ~ Hwl . )
of automorphisms
T .
Now,
)
and
A .
Let
is
T
on
let
TIS
a
c E Na
N* = L
Let
LIB] [B], ~2
B ~ wI
o < S < w I with
extending
then
M s I=
~"
be a sequence
code up
N v ~ N*,
is
can be exten-
T~m,
(av I ~ < Wl)
M o-
is a normal
We claim that there is an a u t o m o r p h i s m
(~ < ~1 ) , thereby p r o v i n g the theorem. (av I V < ~ l
i.e.
.
"there are u n c o u n t a b l y m a n y automorphisms
on
b
It also follows that if is extendable,
M o is
except for the
It easily follows that
Souslin tree which is homogeneous. an a u t o m o r p h i s m
Thus
o~,
p #o v
T , Nv
be as
-
in the proof of Theorem EC ~ B~ ~,CN~ the closed
~S~. Let
set
induction
on
phism on
TI¥ o
M¥o
be the monotone
a sequence
.
~P~ I v < w1>
such that
enumeration
NyvC My~
: Po
.
is an automor-
a ~(TI¥o)
for
TIyv+ 1
such that
~v+1 o pv
"
PK = ~ < ~
Now let
P~
for
p = U 4) that to
element
in
Souslin
algebra iff
der the reverse
algebra
with
are concerned with Boolean
~
G
such that
is homogeneous
algebras.
if to any o(b)
= b'
iff for all
~Ib
(the algebra obtained by intersecting
b ).
A complete
~
has a dense
ordering.
Boolean
algebra
~
b,b'
E
It b E~, every
is called a
subset which is a Souslin tree un-
(More on this concept
in Chapter VIII.)
-
5}
-
Now it is easy to prove that the canonical complete Boolean algebra constructed from the totally homogeneous Souslin tree of the last paragraph is a homogeneous Souslin algebra with at most Using the trees of Theorem I
and Theorem 3
wI
automorphisms.
we obtain in the same way
a rigid Souslin algebra and a Souslin algebra with exactly 2 phisms. w2
Finally, the definition of the homogeneous Souslin tree with
automorphisms
homogeneous. least
automor-
w2
can be modified so that the tree will be totally
Hence we obtain a homogeneous Souslin algebra with at
automorphisms.
C h a p t e r VI
MARTIN'S
We have
seen e a r l i e r
A X I O M A N D THE C O N S I S T E N C Y OF
that,
given a
are c a r d i n a l a b s o l u t e g e n e r i c
c.t.m.
extensions
M
SH
of
NI
ZFC + GCH
and
N2
of
, there
M
such
that (i)
NI ~
2$ = w 2
&
(ii) ~N2(w) =~M(~)
~ SH
and
N2 F
In this c h a p t e r and s u b s e q u e n t f
e ~Si
GOH
ones we shall show h o w it is p o s s i b l e
I
to o b t a i n m o d e l s
NI
and
N2
w h i c h give
ency r e s u l t s
SH
in place
the c o r r e s p o n d i n g
consistI
for
of
~ SH
.
The c o n s t r u c t i o n
w e l l known,
and there are at l e a s t
two good e x p o s i t i o n s
literature,
so we shall only s k e t c h the proof,
and use
of
N I is
already
in the
this s k e t c h
to
I
motivate
the c o n s t r u c t i o n
in the r e m a i n i n g
of
chapters.
N2 Most
w h i c h we shall give
of the r e s u l t s we shall m e n t i o n here
are due to S o l o v a y and T e n n e n b a u m . first established Suppose
the r e l a t i v e
then we are g i v e n a
a cardinal absolute in
~
.
ticular,
Thus,
in
generic N
any S o u s l i n
w h e n we pass
to
same cardinals, N
N
consistency
c.t.m.
M
linity"
by g a i n i n g an u n c o u n t a b l e
branch)
in
turns
N
tree
SH
ZFC of
M
it was
they who
.
, and we w i s h to find such that
SH
holds
to be no S o u s l i n trees.
~
in
M
antiehain
M
and in
M
N
to have
will
the
still be an
can only lose its "Sous(or, a f o r t i o r i ,
an
~1-
to c o m m e n c e by seeing h o w
the S o u s l i n i t y of single S o u s l i n However,
In par-
to lose its " S o u s l i n i t y "
~1-tree
So it is not u n r e a s o n a b l e
out to be r a t h e r easy.
l a t e r chapters,
of
w i l l have
it is clear that an
, so a S o u s l i n
we can d e s t r o y
of
Since we w i l l r e q u i r e
in
.
M
extension
~1-tree
N
In p a r t i c u l a r ,
there w i l l h a v e tree in
in full d e t a i l
tree in
to s i m p l i f y
M .
This
the n o t a t i o n
this s i m p l i f i c a t i o n w i l l be e x t r e m e l y h e l p f u l . ) ,
(In let
-
us first of all amend Aronszajn
we simply r e p l a c e (chapter II).
~T
than "depth",
and
terms of
rather
that n o w a S o u s l i n Thus,
if
T
force w i t h
tree)
by
To o b t a i n
re-
the a m e n d e d d e f J n i t ~ o n ,
in the o r i g i n a l d e f i n i t i o n s
still
talk about
"height" h o w e v e r ,
this w i l l m e a n than
~T
just what it did before,
")
The a d v a n t a g e
tree is a s p l i t t i n g poset
is a S o u s l i n tree in a
N
of
T , we do not d e s t r o y any cardinals. question,
but in
of this a m e n d m e n t
satisfying
c.t.m.
rather
is
c.c.c.
ZFC
, then if we
It turns out that
for we h a v e
already proved
in
( T h e o r e m II.7)
I N
be a
(Thus, limit b
of an
everywhere
C h a p t e r II the f o l l o w i n g l e m m a
Let
(and h e n c e
~T
we also a n s w e r our o r i g i n a l
Lemma
~1-tree
so that they "grow d o w n w a r d s "
as p r e v i o u s l y .
(We shall
~T
-
our d e f i n i t i o n of an
tree and a S o u s l i n
ther than " u p w a r d s "
55
c.t.m,
of
ZFC
in the real world, ordinal,
and so
T
~
, and let is an
has
if we take a S o u s l i n
be a S o u s l i n
a-tree
for
a-branches.)
Let
T
just in case
b
tree
T
in a
tree in
~ = w~
2~
w i l l be a c o f i n a l b r a n c h of
Hence,
T
e.t.m.
a countable
b c T . is
M
N.
Then
M-generic
of
ZFC
for
and
N
form a g e n e r i c e x t e n s i o n for in
T , then
T
N
N
M[G]
killin~ ly,
~ .
T .
by t a k i n g a set
tree in
We r e f e r
N
extension either:
it is dead and e v e r a f t e r r e m a i n s
that a h o p e f u l m e t h o d
iterate,
in some manner,
one at a time.
tial that the e n t i r e
G
w i l l be,
to this p r o c e s s
N
of
N[G]
once a S o u s l i n dead~
as clear-
, then tree is
This last o b s e r v a t i o n of
SH
w o u l d be
to
1, k i l l i n g all the S o u s l i n trees in
in o r d e r for this to work,
iteration
N-generic
, since
for o b t a i n i n g a m o d e l
lemma
Now,
M[G]
G
This term is j u s t i f i e d because,
any f u r t h e r g e n e r i c
will not be a S o u s l i n
sight,
M
w i l l not be S o u s l i n in
the S o u s l i n tree
killed,
of
, a c o f i n a l b r a n c h of
if we m a k e
means
M[G]
can be "handled",
it is e s s e n -
to some extent,
with-
-
in the original set theory,
Well,
any finite
number
We describe
be much easier their
M :
-
we want
our final model
and the only way we k n o w how
of forcing.
ged.
model
56
in the case of such)
associated
(complete)
is just a disguised this is clearly
not
below.
boolean
with
(and hence
is easily it turns
~ , concerned,
algebras.
form of forcing
irrelevant
this
However,
the posets,
(Since
BA(~)
as far as killing
arran-
out to
but rather
forcing
with
- see chapter
T
of
is by the method
extensions
successively,
this a r r a n g e m e n t
to consider
to do this
of two generic
formed
to be a model
I -
is concerned.)
This
N
will not be apparent next lemma, vantage
nificant
Let
but already
will be quite
to denote
Lemma
in the case
"complete
of two extensions
for doing
~
significant.
boolean
strengthening
"successive
in the
extensions"
the ad-
From now on, we shall use
algebra".
of lemma
described
The f o l l o w i n g
lemma
"BA"
is a sig-
1.8.
2 (Solovay) M
M~Bo )
be a
c.t.m,
be such that
M , a ~ique such that
of (in
m2
~A
M (~°)(]B1)
ZFC M)
.
Let
IB°
be a
I~ I is a BAI~O
BA
= ~
in
.
~ M (]B2) , and a canonical
Let
Then there
domOB 2) -- ~:x~M(]Bo)l
(with
M .
IIx~:~l]Po
complete
]BIE
is, in
= "n:})
embedding
e :]B ° - ]B2 . Furthermore, (i)
if
Go
]BI/G ° is
whenever is
M-generic
~i ) , then there
if that ~o that
G2
for
(the BA in M[Go]
such that (ii)
]Bo, ]BI, ]B2
is
]Bo whose
for
~2
e = idI~ ° in the above) and there MEGo][GI]
is an
GI
name
in the
°
which
is
we have:
M[Go]-generic ]Bo-forcing
is
M-generic
for
language for
~2
. then
(assuming
G o = G 2 0~ o
MEGo]-generic
= MEG2]
as above,
and
G2
is a set
M[Go]KG I] = M[G 2] M-generic
are related
set
GI
for simplicity
is for
M-generic ~i/Go
for
such
-
Proof:
This
of
fix E ~ II~ ° = ~] sense
of
~2
a unique and
such that The rest
2
trees
in one go.
, and,
the m a x i m u m
to define
principle
z E M (~°)
for
llb2 = ~I~ ° = b °
enables
~i)I~ ° = ~
is routine,
us to handle
any finite
That we do not destroy to r e m a i n
nitely
Souslin
trees,
M (~o)
to find
z E dom(~ 2)
element
b 2 E ~2
o
trivial.
number
any cardinals
so when we come
we require
in the
~
but not
I
.
11b2
and
the
x v y
such that
be that unique
e(bo)
describe
= {xEM(~o)
' let
this
|
of Souslin in the process
to deal with
the f o l l o w i n g
infi-
lemma:
3 (Solovay) M, ~ o ' ~I' ~ 2
(in
be related
M)II'~BI has
The obvious
Suppose
now we use lemma
of Souslin (~nl n ~ ) complete
trees
in
of
BA's
idea works.
M .
morph
embeddings
Then
~
~
Thus,
~
to form
We call
~
w
are in [Jell,
system for
(in
I='~ o has
~ '~2 has
with
we construct
is best
an
an
m~
is to regard the direct
union
86.1
~)
of is de-
with
this
as follows,
Iso-
function
~n"
Let •
Lemma
, enm
M) associated
of course.
the c.c.c."
w-sequence
n+1
described
c.c.cJ'
w-sequence
(enm I n ~ m ~
is the identity
algebra ~
M
M
successively
BA
enm
If
, then
(where,
This
is a boolean
(One way
= BA(~) ) .
in
A natural
so that each
= Un~w~ n
completion.
to deal
union.
2.
The details
enm: ~ n - , ~ m
is its direct the system
2
: ~
and a commutative
fined by composition). system
as in lemma
the c.c.c."l~o
Proof:
set
dom~B2)
for example,
of the proof
clearly
Let
simply
of
but for
and
e .
We shall
(in the sense
is obvious,
Let
and
(by normality)
b o E ~o
Lemma
~2
' use
llz = x v y
Given
Lemma
-
is just lemma 85 of [Jel].
construction
many
57
~w
on
be its
as a poset of the chain
and
-
(~n] n < w ) identity, plete
we call
the
embeddings
en
(~Bn)n~ here
In the case where BA
, will
.
the embeddings with
, the direct
Suppose
algebra
-
, together
:~n-~
~ (enm)n<m~)
as the limit
~
58
limit
then we take
(murderous)
were not
the
the c o r r e s p o n d i n g
in our iteration.
all of our previous
enm
of the system
(in If
com-
M) G
•
is
as defined M-generic
work be incorporated
for in
w
M[G]
?
lemma, Lemma Let
The positive
answer
in c o n j u n c t i o n
with
]Bo, ]B2
be
in
BA's
~ .
]~1 i s
in
part
[SoTe]
of lemma
by our next
2.
generic
~
Since
systems
of any
ultrafilters
(limit)
length,
chain bra of
BA's
~8
of the Proof:
such
union
~ ¥ 's .
that
Then
of
cf(~)
Theorem
the canonical ~o
~I
name
is obtained (in
M) for
M-
|
we state
and let
(a)
(~8
~ a
By a combinatorial when
speaking,
is g u a r a n t e e d
construction
ordinal,
' (b) y < a ~ ~ y
is the direct
(in
will work
by the next
equally
it in a fairly
well
general
for
way.
- Tennenbaum)
be any limit of
such that
em-
~ }~(]B2)
any cardinals
limit
be a complete
]B I c M (IBo)
Roughly
on
the above
5 (Solovay ~
M(]Bo)(]B1)
through
does not destroy
lemma.
Lemma
and
~2
e :]Bo-~]B 2
is an element
for details.
by f a c t o r i n g
That
M , and let
Then there
a BAI~O = ~
See
Proof:
Let
the second
is supplied
4 (Solovay)
bedding
M )
to this question
49.
¥ w I .
~ T
iff if
u
E u
the
point
of
.
A partial
map
Let
be
Claim
observe
p
Dx =
[p E P
Let
X = [D x I x E T] X-generic map
in
has
from
say
is s p e c i a l .
u
of
is a n e a t
T
, and
such in
~
into
p.e.'s
of
subtree
that:
T , then
conversely;
an e x t e n s i o n
subtree
on e v e r y
they
and level
Q
is an o r d e r - p r e -
T
into
ordered
Q .
by i n c l u s i o n .
c.c.c.
of this
claim
follows
I x E dom(p)}
set
u
of
of a l l
the t h e o r e m
let
tree
same h e i g h t
from a neat
the p r o o f
preserving
u
satisfies
how
the
(p.e.)
the p o s e t
~
Ignoring
of
embedding
serving ~
have
We
subtree
same h e i g h t
every u
tree.
is a f i n i t e
x,y
have (ii)
Then every Aronszajn
be a n y A r o n s z a j n
N
(i)
an
is a s t r i c t l y
is w e l l - d i s t r i b u t e d ) .
Proof:
of
There
.
Since G
for ~
~
into
for
the
from
it.
Clearly
time b e i n g , For Dx
IXI = w I < 2 w .
Clearly Q , so
~
each
let us x E T ,
is d e n s e , by
f = UG
MA
in there
~. is
is an o r d e r -
is s p e c i a l .
-
66
-
We turn n o w
to the p r o o f of the claim.
countable.
We show that
ible elements. mains
X
Firstly,
must
of
~) .
that if
p,q E X
of
Secondly, and
.
of
~
, y E dom(q) of
(Of course,
for example,
in some a r b i t r a r y ,
dom(p)
p,q
be the n u m b e r
Pick
k ~ n
largest
linearly
u°
If
k = n
is a n e a t
member
of
assume,
of
~
Let
m
k
U
p E X
of
X
U
orderings Since
determines, of the levels
e a c h level
every m e m b e r
of
of S
~]
E U
.
Let
such that
S~ ~
and taking
u
X k
of the do-
T-level unique
for that
(k+1)'st l e v e l
of
. of all dom(p)
section
~ ), a final
is countable,
of
we can assume
(5)
of
S
in
S . such
such that
By l e m m a 7, we can find
is w e l l - d i s t r i b u t e d .
Tm
that
w h i c h do not p r o v i d e
P i c k an a r b i t r a r y m e m b e r
for
our l i n e a r
S
has u n c o u n t a b l y m a n y e x t e n s i o n s
~ = hts((~) )
of
We may
o
of
X
X.
such that e v e r y
( k + 1 ) ' s t level
(k+1)'st l e v e l s
of
of
and that
(eg. u s i n g
Tm
Let
subtree w i t h
in a n a t u r a l way
(Throw away those m e m b e r s nice p o i n t s ~ )
of
be the c a r d i n a l i t y of the X
,
each level
k ~ n
levels
lies on a
be the set of all .
k
, that the
the d o m a i n of e a c h m e m b e r of Let
so a s s u m e
with
to
such
of any m e m b e r
a single n e a t
we are done,
by choice of
member.
ordering
has d o m a i n an e n d - e x t e n s i o n
m a i n of each m e m b e r
dom(g)
so that u n c o u n t a b l y m a n y m e m b e r s
subtree
X
and
these o r d e r i n g s . )
in the d o m a i n
have a d o m a i n w h i c h e n d - e x t e n d s levels.
correspond
but c o h e r e n t manner,
of l e v e l s
assume
, but we can e l i m i n a t e
just those i s o m o r p h i s m s w h i c h p r e s e r v e n
(as n e a t
there m a y be several
for each such pair
this a m b i g u i t y by,
are i s o m o r p h i c
x E dom(p)
then
isomorphisms
that the do-
we can ( e q u a l l y clearly)
the i s o m o r p h i s m
= q(y)
be un-
c o n t a i n a pair of c o m p a t -
X
one a n o t h e r u n d e r p(x)
X c ~
we can c l e a r l y assume
of all of the m e m b e r s
subtrees
Let
Pick extensions
B~a (51) ,
-
of
0]
is a set.
[I P E P o
&
Thus, in
Work in
q E Q & &
]P2 is a neatly
~-closed poset.
thus
(in
f :P2 " ]Pc
cover.
Define
]Pc in
sily seen that h
is the
(in
e
e-basic projection,
= p .
f
e
Clearly,
Clearly, for
to
]Bo
then
h~2
]PI"' so q E Q
of course. f
is a neat
p E]P o , e(p) = uniquely by the it is ea-
And clearly,
= f .
if
The rest of
I
and simplicity)
(hmnln<m<w>
and
=
is a neat cover,
and that, using lemma 2, we constructed <enm I n < m < w } ,
sequence from
is a complete embedding.
the lemma follows easily now.
0Bnl n < w > ,
]Bo of course),
by setting,
Since
Suppose now that (for definiteness
p =
This also proves ~
(and extending ]Bo).
if
using the fact that for each
enw: B n ~ w
projection of
into
fn (p) = Pn "
is a neat cover for
=
In order that
(iii), all that is required
define
Pw
and partially order
= BA(~ )
' condition
condition
; and for condition
tion argument,
We first of all set
iterated forcing, we must ensure
(Since
Pn E ~ n
the fact that the
It is easily verified
is completely embeddable
that
tion
which also adds no new subsets
n E ~ n & Pn =hn+1,n(pn+1))}
Wl-Closed poset.
of all define
--W
Can we define a limit oper-
Wl-happy.
be a suitable limit operation for that each
(Then
enm , hmn ) is al-
In fact we can do so very simply, utilising
entire
system.
Now, by Lemma I, we know that if we force with any of
ation , suitable for iterated forcing, of
~1-happy
en~
is a
en~ -basic
h~n~w
~n'S
= fn "
, but also for
~1-happy,
so that we can
, together with the embed-
en~ , n < ~ , the inverse limit of the system
((~n)n]
q = qwl
obtain
¢(v+I)
¢ : wi+I
If
tri-
and work along
a sequence
function
be a proper
E D v , and set
v ~ w 1, and
define
are
At limit
below in v e r i f y i n g
= max(dom(qo)) qv+1
u-sequence.
cofinality-sequence
it in the same way as d e s c r i b e d
q~+1
in the i n d u c t i o n
such that If
set
lim(~),
~(v) =sup~ 0 ; ~ ;
subalgebra
~
of
such that
= ~ , then
~ ~ , ~
;
= o~B
~o
Lemma)
Assume
, x ,
Then
, 0 ~ j < i ~ 2 , be the basic
be any S o u s l i n i s a t i o n
But clearly,
12
subalge-
9 2 .
T a° = h I o "T aI and ~ E A12 - T ~1 = h21 "T a2 "
Lemma
"
is a nice
•
such
is a that:
-
Proof:
8?
-
VJe c o n s t r u c t the sequence
(]B I v < w 2)
proceed,
we c o n s t r u c t
the f o l l o w i n g
(a)
h
:~
(b)
T~ ~ v
' an a r b i t r a r y
(c)
[~ :~
~ ~ , where
-~
also
(~
are o t h e r w i s e
T)
, the basic
by induction. sequences:
projections;
Souslinisation
~
As we
of
has d o m a i n
•
~I
but
V'
"J
arbitrary;
(~) (e)
C T
(v~)
, an a r b i t r a r y
such that for all Tv : h 'Je let
closed u n b o u n d e d
a 6 C
, ~vI~ = YvOa
set in
, ~[~=
wI
~
,
"T ~
earlier).
O.
.
O
Case
2.
Set
~v+l
Stage
v + I .
= o(~v'(]Bm IT < v>)
Condition
(iv) holds
by lemmal
and induction.
Case
3.
Let
~ = otp(Ax)
meration fine
~X
Stage
of
k , k < w 2 , lim(k)
, and let
AI .
from
Notice
, cf(k)
<X(~) I ~ ,
for some
c E C , y ~ ~X(~)c
Then there is
x' ~ ~k(~)c
~k(T),k(v)(x')
= y
By assumption
~Iv)(y)
(~,x>
and
~k(v)
k(T) (x) >X(T) © e -I
seen that
x
v ~ ~ < 8 and
x ~ yX(~) and y ~)ff~(~),X(~).
such that
ql )/y
lies above
are such that
x' ~k(T)x
and
X(T)(X)) hk(T) , k(~) (~-I Since
.
Hence
c E C , it is easily
~k(~)c (in terms of
as claim 3
is
(~,y , x) E U
= ~k(~(n)),k(~)(yn)
Then
Ta ' for each
Ta
such that
= y , and
with
such that
, is as required.
of
X t
(~,y,x>
For each
, s
9
satisfies
n < ~)
(**)
.
with
• < e .
.
is defined.
•
in
~(n) ~ T , all
a
2.
Tia
x
This is
z .
~(T)
, h k ( v ( n + 1 ) ) , k ( ~ ( n ) ) ( y n + I) = Yn
x n E T~(n)
s(~,y,x>
s
1 and
y ~ (~~ )
n < w , Yn,Xn
E U
claims
, and
< w)
for all
: (i)
To
and
that
the c o m p l e t e n e s s
B ° ~ B I ~ ..., we can pick a n o r m a l
Y
We say that a M
such
that
As before,
5
as in lemma 6
p E T
fixes
Ii
v
then
{~
~ w11A n v ~ w }
contains
B E M .
from lemma
by an argument
for the rest
Ti~
iff there
as in lemmaV]XI.5.|
of this proof.
is a normal
a-tree
t
in
I!
p II-TI~ = t .
for each
that every
set
-
a < wI
p E TB(a)
the closed u n b o u n d e d
there
fixes set
TI~
is a least •
Let
{~ E m I Iv < ~
ordinal
B(m)
- B(v)
(v)
h(<x,f>)
-- x iT x,
&
we shall assume
f muf ,
: x .
In order that our definition does not break down, we ensure that at every stage the following
two conditions hold: o
(*)
If
lim(a)
= sup[f(s)
(**) Let
and Is
(x,f> E ~a+1
> °t}
TX
' then for all
t E (Tx)Ya,
f(t)
.
<x,f> E T a + I , x' ~
<x,f>
and f'(ti) =
ZF
minus the power set axiom.
and
(N
I ~ < w I>
by a simultan-
as follows.
and for all is countable
LsEb,C qa~ (ii)
be such that
such
a
such that
b E W
Ls[
=
T
Na = N
°
Y~+2
[~l~,ml~+2,F~] .
Set
t o : {~
and
~I = {<x,> I X E T y I }
= ~
for convenience).
Suppose define
;
~+I
is defined and
~a+2
by forcing over
(where we have assumed that
~I(a+2) Na+2
"
satisfies
llTo= {0)II~
(*) and (**) .
We
-
Let
S = {<x,<x',f>>ix
For each
~ mya+2 &
105
-
<m
x
s = <x,<x' ,f>> E S , let
mya+1 & <x,,f> ~ ~I(~+2)}
x, e
ps = [P I P
.
is a finite function
&
dQm(p) ~ (T ° & ran(p) ~ Q & (Vt E dom(p))(Vs E (Tx,) (t
Na+2-generic subset of
into
~+2
It is obvious that
Suppose next that (*), (**).
For each
"
Note that
~I(G+3)
x E Tya , let
with
Put
p E Xs, p
( x , f U X s , p> ~
<x',f> .
still satisfies (*) and (**).
lim(a), a < m I , and
We construct
~s
~a
~la
is defined and satisfies
by forcing over
B x = {b I b
~
.
is a cofinal branch of
T°x such
o
that, for some extends
b}
For each ~
<x',f'> ~
Regard
ran(p)~ ~x
as
<x",f">& p2p'.
p x E N~ .
For each
x E T
follows.
Let
Xx, u .
which
.
a poset under
~la
y E Tya+1
Set
and each Xx, u
be an
u E ~x
, we define an element of
Na-generic subset of
fx,u = U{f' I (<x',f'>,~> EXx, u] .
~x
such that
~
as u E
Since (**) holds for
(and to some extent since (*) holds also), it is easily seen that
-
fx,u
is an o r d e r - p r e s e r v i n g
U[p
I (3d)( ~
.
suppose
, where
~.Ve define
For each
Ta+ I
x E T
lim(a), to make
.
TylC
from
?y,x,u(t)
that,
<X,fx,u>
and for each into
that
(y,}y,x,u > ~
~a
b E
Note that
(**) to consider here.
~l(a+1)
a < w I , and
is
defined
(as above).
(*) hold.
' Y Eb] TM[C][b]Ic
&
into
Q
~I
in
. in
Then
fb
M[C][b]
M[C][b]
] .
Clearly,
Tb =
is an orderpreserBut look,
, so, using
C
is a
fb ' we can
-
107
-
o
easily Q .
define,
Hence,
, an o r d e r - e m b e d d i n g
~ "T
speci ll
is
It remains
Le~a
NEC]Eb]
M[C]~b]
WII
second
in
to check
is special"
:
of all of
, whence,by
Tb
choice
into
of
b ,
.
that
~
of which may appear
is Souslin, rather
We require
strange
two lemmas,
the
at first glance.
7
Let
D E }~[C]
Set
~b = {(x,f> E ~ I x E b]
Proof:
be dense
Since
T
Thus,
if
and
D0~b
and where
Let
b
~"
MrC]
that
, b
is
in
~b
x'
in
~b
E T~ here
I~]B "<x',f'>
T .
"
T .
xo E b
&
<x,f)
is over
M[C], ]B
Pick
of
on
we can find
set term for here.
branch
M[C]-generic
the forcing
x = x°
Then
is dense
x o l~B"(x,f>
, where
assume
be a cofinal
D 0 ~b
is the generic
_(~ <x,f)
x' --
<x',f')
in
in
branch
of
b 1,...,b n
T , and set
be cofinal
M'[bl,...,bn]-generic M[C]
p : [bl,...,bn}
as above,
branches
subset
still.
- Q , and set
}~' = M[b]
of
, T ° = U{T x 1
of
T ° , and suppose
WlM
over
~M
, with
Set
~b = [(x,f> E ~ I x Eb] . n ~P = [(x,f> E ~ b I iA1(~qi < Q P ( b i ) ) (
o
VtETxlC)(tEb Then
Proof:
i ~ f(t) < Q q i ) ]
D 0 T~bb is dense
Let
P(bi)
in
T~
.
Let
D E M'[C]
be dense
in
~b
"
.
= r i , i = 1,...,n
~(x,f)~ i = [z E T° I htTo(z)
.
For each
= htT(x)
<x,f>
E ~b
& (3r.~ v
-
.
, we can apply Corollary in
M'
S ~(B) (z) is well-distributed)
we may assume that
.
& ht(
is well-distributed).
-
By Lemma
6, we can find
that for all that
Y~I
a normal
v < w I , Sl0(v)
= al
and
-
function
= S n V0( v
(VS_>~1)(p(ys)
val = 21
Let
a
Now,
Sa+ I J ~ , so by the construction
B > a •
By SyB
If follows,
by
that
< u , and
S
YS
u'
~
E ~b
of
~emma
for some
ht(u')
' u'
, u'
, which
such
~ < ~I
so
~a'
.
SyB+I
nature
D , contrary
the proofs
to
of lemmas
such
for all
8 > a+1
, if
D
is a
B > ~ •
nEu'~
being
u'
of
~,
6 (~b) ,
is well-distrubuted.
B = ht(u') Y~
NyB+I
of the construction
YS
Set
So, as
E ~B
S (~> n [u~
S
(and the first
u = (x,f) ~ u o
E NyB+I
B ) for all
is to say
~a+1
E S~+ I , (~) E ~u~
SyB,
E D .
a > h t ( u o) =
By
= ~ .
will be well-distrituted!
YS
can lie in
on
= B , then
< u
of
(~>
Hence,
induction
and
S °) we can find
SIyB+ I C WyB+1
$<x) ~ ~u'~
By examining
of
(3) and the generic
~
u
Pick
M
So, we have:
y~ = ~ ~ ao,al
E NyB+I
~ [U~
seen that
and,
(4),
(by a simple
Let
that
in the d e f i n i t i o n
ZF--model,
u'
such
u E (~b)a+1
Let
EVJ0(v)
in
(vBz~I)(SlYs(wyB)
be least
clause
o : w I ~ ~I
= YB ) "
(4)
that
&
109
dense
(2),
(~>
But we have
Hence in
E
just
no extension
~b "
|
4 to 8, we obtain
9
The conclusions
of lemmas
4 to 8
able
model
ZF- + "there
transitive
At last we can prove:
of
are valid w h e n e v e r
M
is an uncountable
is a countcardinal"
+
110-
-
Lemma
10
M[C~
I= "~
Proof:
is a S o u s l i n
Let
J
be
(J(a,~)
Let
X
there
I a E0n)
is a set
is c h o s e n
Let
To
be
set
TI
be l e a s t
such
lemma
we
the l e a s t
3
, and
setting
a = aN
(i)
~ , TI(~+I)
(ii)
C O a
(iii)
there
is
N(T)
= Tim
dom(w')
and
dom(N')
of
NKC 0 a ]
each
Tim
.
apply b x}
~I~
•
x E T a , set
Now, lemma
Tim 7
, to c o n c l u d e
that
that
the
,
Since
~,X
E M[C]
,
E L[Y,C]
and
(X,~>
.
T,T,W
We can as-
E L[Y]
= J(To, ~ I ~ set
E
~'(~)=
a maximal
I (BxEXa)(y~x)]
b x = [y E TIa I X < T Y ]
N[C 0 ~]
~
'
is a S o u s l i n to
set
, N ~H M , INI M = w , such that w2 t r a n s i t i v e set U E M , such that,
D = [yE~la subset
any
N E M
over
a] ~
, w(W)
Set
is a d e n s e
For
~ H M[C] w2 = X a = D e f X 0 (~la)
w'(X)
chain
that
~ = NN
N[CN
that for
.
~,X
w I = w~ [Y]
such
~'
M[C]
that
,
Ciearly,
and
in
, such
a countable
is a m a p
1i"'-1:
and
~
ordinal
U-generic
such
L[~]
of
so that
obtain
and
function
enumerates
Y ~ Wl, Y E M
that
< Y , T o , T I) E N
~I
antichain
sume
Applying
.
the u s u a l
be a m a x i m a l
Y
tree"
D N Tbx
is d e n s e
in
Tbx
of
can
I x'
, each x E T a.
-
Again,
for each
x E T
, let
111
-
Bx
be the set of all b r a n c h e s
b
of
o
Tx
of the form
w E (Ty)a
.
b = [z E T °y l w < T o z]
Let
arbitrary.
bl,...,b n E B x
By choice
of
for some
, and let
U , C qa
is
y E T~(a+1),
y ]
, where, f o r
each
~ ; ~i+I (p) = (ai(P)'Pi+1>
, define
p
Co(p),...,an(p)
"
similarly.
Recall now the proof of lemma VII.2. For each
n < ~ Set
'
let
~P# n
=
[P= I (Vi - Vl
such that
h(q2) = ~2"
On(
for some
finish by setting p~ E]P*n "
Since
qience from
p2
v1 = f(pO)
]P* n '
h(Pn+1) .
=
We may
pl E ]P* n
'
(in C) &
Let
v2=f(plo ).
Similarly, pick p2 E ]P* 2 - @.
fiX ~ ~I × ~II~ ~ = ~ v = ~,~
Then,
, so by construction,
IIX is speciall~* Thus
for
II~ ~ ~I × ~II~* Aronszajn
tree
= ~ , of
IIEvery Aronszajn tree |
Appendix ITERATED In [Jn Jo], Jensen constructible forcing.
and Johnsbr&ten
ing over
Jensen developed L
~(w)
give a generic
construction
of a non-
w-iteration
of Souslin
of an
is a specialisation
of an earlier
in order to show that iterated
must introduce
and because
cumbersome,
FORCING AND
A I3 set of integers by means
Their construction
tion which
der,
SOUSLIN
new reals.
the construction
Souslin
For the convenience
in [Jn Jo]
which
forc-
of the rea-
is (necessarily)
we outline here a simplification
construc-
fairly
just gives the above
result. In
L,
we define
a sequence
(i)
T°
is Souslin;
(ii)
if
bo
is an
define
(iii)
~I of
branch TI
of
in
Lib o]
if
is an
Lib o] - generic branch
define
a subtree
bI
is Souslin
if
(bo,b~,...)
C
of
T2
~I
is Sous-
~I , then we can cano-
in
L[bo,b I]
such that
L[bo,b q] ;
is any such sequence
T°,T I,...,
then
regardless
of branches
L[