POSTMODER SOCIA THEOR .
George R
univers6
I I
r
t
1_
'
t.
\ .\\
t'iU~~_·""·~ lr;:_,,~.~;.,
"':g''1U/'' -n~""'...
245 downloads
2983 Views
6MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
POSTMODER SOCIA THEOR .
George R
univers6
I I
r
t
1_
'
t.
\ .\\
t'iU~~_·""·~ lr;:_,,~.~;.,
"':g''1U/'' -n~""'r :"":f:(·.iU.}d. \.;~ VI "lI
D lJdP~:,j."
!
-"'f i::>S/lDAI r"~ I;'L"'" i1 I"' If:... E'" .;, l _.
"
1 i.i9~
."
..) :,:
'.J
VO ,\
Uu",~~~st, Rd':.!~' I~, ~·rJ.: ;!·184·1;,~
~3·jL
Ilif'
Ko,poo';
Ko,M
001000160249N
THE McGRAW-HILL COMPA
~
l~ ')
h-
Montreal
New York SI. Louis San Francisco Auk Caracas Lisbon London Madrid Mexic New Delhi San Juan Singapore Sydney To
;'"lS-
A Division ofTheMcGrawBiUCampanies
PERMISSIO ACKNOWLEDGMEN
This book was set in Times Roman by Ruttle, Shaw & Wetherill, Inc.
The editors were Jill S. Gordon and Katherine Blake;
the production supervisor was Leroy A. Young.
The cover was designed by Caryl and Scott Silvers.
Project supervision was done by Hockett Editorial Service.
Quebecor Printing/Fairfield was printe ,and binder.
,;l.p-sO ~'
12/?"
.
~
I
~
' ~ES~
(
-1
':f .-$.-/
790"" j.
eUD
Baudrillard, Jean. The Transparency of Evil: Essays on Extreme Phenomena. London: V
0 \ Z.
i::t.Y~ ~~ , .
'0
0--
Chapter 1
/1
:@ .,. 2'·
~
....
•
Grateful acknowledgment is made for permission 10 quote from the following previous sources.
•./
Bauman, Zygmunt. Intimations of Postmodernity. London: Rout/edge, 1992. Reprinte sion of Rout/edge, UK.
i l
f,.,
Denzln, Norman. "Postmodernism and Deconstructionism." In Postmodernism and S edited by David R. Dickens and Andrea Fontana, 182-202. New York: Guilford Reprinted by permission of Guiiford Press.
;\[<j ~ S,O
Denzin, Norman. "Re-reading the Sociological Imagination." By Norman Denzin. The A ciologist (fall 1989): 238-282. Copyright © 1989 by Transaction Publishers; all righ Reprinted by permission ofTransaction Publishers.
POSTMODEJ;lN SOCIAL THEORY
Kellner, Douglas. "Introduction: Jameson, Marxism, and Postmodernism." In Postmode son: Critique, edited by Douglas Kellner. Washington, D.C.: Maisonneuve P Reprinted by permission of Masionneuve Press.
Copyright ©t 1'97 by The McGraw-Hill Companies, Inc. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of KrMrlca. Except as permitted unqer the United States Copyright Act of 1976, no part of this pUblication may be reproduced or distributed in any form or by any means, or stored in a data base or retrieval system, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
Spivak, Gayatri. ''Translator's Preface." In Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, ix-Ix:xxv The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974. Reprinted by permission ofThe Johns versity Press.
Permissions Acknowledgments appear on pages v-viii and on this page by reference. Chapter 2 This book is printed on acid-free paper.
Antonio, Robert J. "Nietzsche's Antisociology: Subjectified Culture and the End of His can Journal of Sociology 101 (1995): 1-43. Copyright © 1995 by The University of rights reserved. Reprinted by permission of The University of Chicago Press.
234567890FGRFGR90987
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Copyright © 1979 by Princeto Press. Reprinted by permission of Princeton University Press.
ISBN 0-07-053019-X
Spivak, Gayatri. ''Translator's Preface." In Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatofogy, ix-Ixxxvii. B Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974. Reprinted by permission of The Johns Hopk Press. Copyright © 1969 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Bo
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Ritzer, George. Postmodern social theory/George Ritzer. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-07-053019-X
1. Postmodernism-Social aspects. 2. Sociology-Philosophy. I. Title.
HM73.R534 1997
301'.01-dc20 96-21073
http://www.mhcollege.com
Chapter 3
Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of KnOWledge and the Discourse of Language Harper Colophon, 1971/1976, Copyright © 1969 by Editions Gallimard, Reprinte sion of Georges Borchardt, Inc. "
Foucault, Michel. The Birth of the Clinic, New York: Vintage, 1975. Translation copyrigh Tavistock Publications, Ltd. Reprinted by permission of Pantheon Books, a division House, Inc.
Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Vintage, right © 1975 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt,
Foucault, Michel. Madness and Civifization. London: Tavistock, 1967. Reprinted by p Tavistock Publications.
1976 by The University of Chicago. All rights reserved. Reprinted by permission of The Univer sity of Chicago Press. Farganis, Sondra. "Postmodernism and Feminism." In Postmodernism and Social Inquiry, edited by David R. Dickens and Andrea Fontana, 101-126. New York: Guiiford Press, 1994. Reprinted by permission of Guiiford Press.
AB
THE AUTH
Haraway, Donna. "A Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science, Technology, and Socialist Feminism in the 1980s." Reprinted from FeminismlPostmodenism, edited by Unda Nicholson (1990), 190-233, With permission of the pUblisher, Routledge: New York, and of the author. Irigaray, Luce. "The Sex Which Is Not One." In New French Feminism, edited by Elaine Marks and Isabelle de Courtivron, 99-106. New York: Schocken Books, 1981. Originally published in Ce sexe qui n'est pas un. Copyright © 1977 Editions de Minuit, Paris. Reprinted by permission of Editions de Minuil. Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, Copyright 1991 , Duke University Press, Durham, N.C. Reprinted with permission. Jameson, Fredric. "Postmodernism. Or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism." New Left Review 1~6 (1984): 59-92. Kellner, Douglas. "Introduction: Jameson, Marxism, and Postmodernism." In Postmodernism: Jame son: Critique, edited by Douglas Kellner. Washington, D.C.: Maisonneuve Press, 1989. Reprinted by permission of Maisonneuve Press. Kristeva, Julia. "Oscii/ation Between Power and Denial." In New French Feminism, edited by Elaine Marks and Isabeile de Courtivron, 165-167. New York: Schocken Books, 1981. Originaily pub lished in Telquel58 (summer 1974). Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt, Inc. Chapter 11 Lyotard, Jean-Franyois, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Translated by Geof Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984. English translation and Foreward copyright © 1984 by the University of Minnesota. Original, French-lan guage edition copyright © 1979 by Les Editions de Minuil. Reprinted by permission of the Uni versity of Minnesota Press, and Manchester University Press. Chapter 12 Bauman, Zygmunl. Intimations of Postmodernity. London: Routledge, 1992. Reprinted by permis sion of Routledge, UK. Best, Steven. "Jameson, Totality, and the Poststructuralist Critique." In Postmodernism: Jameson: Critique, edited by Douglas Kellner, 333-368. Washington, D.C.: Maisonneuve Press, 1989. Reprinted by permission of Maisonneuve Press. Deleuze, Giiles, and Felix GUMari. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. New York: Viking PengUin, 1972. Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Copyright 1991 , Duke
University Press, Durham, N.G. Reprinted with permission.
Kellner, Douglas. "Introduction: Jameson, Marxism, and Postmodernism." In Postmodernism: Jame son: Critique, edited by Douglas Kellner. Washington, D.G.: Maisonneuve Press, 1989. Reprinted by permission of Maisonneuve Press. Upovestky, Gilles, The Empire of Fashion: Dressing Modern Democracy Copyright ©1987 by Edi tions Gallimard (Paris) in L'Empire de I'ephemere. Gopyright © 1994 by Princeton University Press. Reprinted by permission of Princeton University Press.
GEORGE RITZER is Professor of Sociology at the University o major areas of interest are sociological theory and the sociology served as Chair of the American Sociological Association's Sectio cal Sociology (1989-1990) and Organizations and Occupations (1 fessor Ritzer has been Distinguished Scholar-Teacher at the Univ land and has been awarded a Teaching Excellence award. H UNESCO Chair in Social Theory at the Russian Academy of Sci bright-Hays Fellowship. He has been Scholar-in-Residence at the stitute for Advanced Study and the Swedish Collegium for Advan Social Sciences. Dr. Ritzer's main theoretical interests lie in metatheory as well of rationalization. In metatheory, his most recent book is Metatheo ogy (Lexington Books, 1991). Earlier books on this topic inclu Multiple Paradigm Science (1975, 1980) and Toward an Integra Paradigm (1981). He has written a number of essays on rationaliz The McDonaldization of Society (Pine Forge Press, 1996) and the McDonaldization Thesis: Explorations and Extensions (Sage). Pr also the author of another work in applied social theory, Expres Critique of the Global Credit Card Society (Pine Forge Press, Ritzer's work has been translated into a number of languages, inc Croatian, Danish, German, Farsi, Italian, Korean, Russian, and Spa In 1996 McGraw-Hill published the fourth edition of Professo text Sociological TheOl)', the fourth edition of his Modern Socio and the second edition of his Classical Sociological Theory.
Foucault, Michel. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Vintage, 1973. Copyright © 1966 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt, Inc. Chapter 4 Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality. Vol. 1, An Introduction, translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage, 1980. Copyright © 1976 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt, inc. Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality. Vol. 2, The Use of Pleasure. New York: Pantheon Books, 1985. Copyright © 1984 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt, Inc. Foucauit, Michel. The History of Sexuality. Vol. 3, The Care of the Self. New York: Pantheon Books, 1986. Copyright © 1984 by Editions Gallimard. Reprinted by permission of Georges Borchardt, Inc. Chapter 5 Baudtillard, Jean. For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign. United States: Telos Press, 1981. Reprinted by permission ofTelos Press. Baudrillard, Jean. Fatal Strategies. New York: Semiotext(e). Foreign Agent Series, 1990. Reprinted by permission of Semiotext(e). Baudrillard, Jean. The Mirror of Production. SI. Louis: Telos Press, 1975. Reprinted by permission of Telos Press. Baudrillard, Jean. Symbolic Exchange and Death. London: Sage, 1993. Reprinted by permission of Sage Publications. Baudrillard, Jean. The Transparency of Evil: Essays on Extreme Phenomena. London: Verso, 1993. Bauman, Zygmunt. Intimations of Postmodernity. London: Routledge, 1992. Reprinted by permis sion of Routledge, UK.
Chapter 7 Bowie, Malcolm. Lacan. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guallari. Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophren Penguin, 1972.
Derrida, Jacques. Writing and Difference. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Co University of Chicago. Reprinted by permission ofThe University of Chicago.
Jameson, Fredric. "Postmodernism, Or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism
146 (1984): 59-92.
Lyotard, Jean-Fran90is. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota P translation and Foreward copyright © 1984 by the University of Minnesota. guage edition copyright © 1979 by Les Editions de Minuit. Reprinted by pe versity of Minnesota Press, and Manchester University Press.
Lyotard, Jean-Fran90is. The Postmodern Explained: Correspondence 1982Don Barry, Bernadelle Maher, Julian Pefanis, and Morgan Thomas. Minn Minnesota Press, 1993. English translation copyright © 1992 by Power Australia. North American edition copyright © 1993 by the Regents of th nesota. Original, French-language edition copyright © 1988 by Edit Reprinted by permission of the University of Minnesota Press.
Spivak, Gayatri. "Translator's Preface." In Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974. Reprinted by permission ofThe versity Press. Chapter 8
Gane, Mike, ed. Baudrillard Live: Selected Interviews. London: Routledge, 1993. Reprinted by per mission of Routledge, UK.
Bauman, Zygmunt. Intimations of Postmodernity. London: Routledge, 1992. R sion of Routledge. UK.
Poster, Mark, ed. Jean Baudrillard: Selected Writings. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988. Reprinted by permission of Stanford University Press, and Blackwell Publishers.
Bauman, Zygmunt. Postmodern Ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1993. Reprin Blackwell Publishers.
Chapter 6
Beck, Ulrich. Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage, 1992. R sion of Sage Publications.
Baudrillard, Jean. For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign. United States: Telos Press, 1981. Reprinted by permission of Telos Press. Baudrillard, Jean. Fatal Strategies. New York: Semiotext(e). Foreign Agents Series, 1990.. Reprinted by permission of Semiotext(e).
Giddens, Anthony. The Consequences of Modernity. Stanford, Stanford Un Reprinted by permission of Biackwell Publishers.
Giddens, Anthony. Modernity and Self-Identity: Self and Society in the Late M Stanford University Press, 1991. Reprinted by permission of Biackwell Pub
Baudrillard, Jean. The Illusion of the End. Palo Alto: Stanford University Press, 1994. Reprinted by
permission of Stanford University Press.
Chapter 9 Baudrillard, Jean. The Mirror of Production. St Louis: Telos Press, 1975. Reprinted by permission of Telos Press. Baudrillard, Jean. Simulations. New York: Semiotext(e). Foreign Agents Series, 1983. Reprinted by permission of Semiotext(e). Baudrillard, Jean. Symbolic Exchange and Death. London: Sage, 1993. Reprinted by permission of Sage Publications. Baudrillard, Jean. The Transparency of Evil: Essays on Extreme Phenomena. London: Verso, 1993. Gane, Mike, ed. Baudrillard Live: Selected Interviews. London: Routledge, 1993. Reprinted by per mission of Routledge, UK.
Best, Steven, "Jemeson, Totality, and the Poststructuralist Critique:' In Postm Critique, edited by Douglas Kellner, 333-368. Washington, D.e.: Maison Reprinted by permission of Masionneuve Press.
Bordo, Susan. "Feminism, Postmodernism, and Gender-Skepticism Feminism/Postmodernism, edited by Unda Nicholson (1990), 122-156, w publisher, Routledge: New York.
Butler, Judith. "Contingent Foundations:' Reprinted from Feminist Contentions change, edited by Selya Benhabib, Judith Butler, Dricilia Cornell, and N 33-57, with permission of the publisher, Routledge: New York.
Cixous, Helene. ''The Laugh of the Medusa:' Signs 1 (4) (summer 1976): 8
CONTE
PREFACE POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY, SOCIOLOGY, AN SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
SOME FUNDAMENTAL DEFINITIONS WHAT IS POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY?
VULNERABILITY OF SOCIOLOGY AND SOCIOLOGICAL T INTIMATIONS OF POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY
IN SOCIOLOGY
2 THE DEVELOPMENT OF POSTMODERN SOCIAL T THE ARTS AND LITERARY CRITICISM
PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOLOGY, AND PSYCHIATRY: NIETZS RORTY, AND FREUDIAN THEORY Friedrich Nietzsche Richard Rorty Sigmund Freud STRUCTURALISM AND POSTSTRUCTURALlSM Sartre's Existentialism Phenomenology Structuralism Poststructuralism THE SOCIAL CONTEXT
3 MICHEL FOUCAULT: PART 1: ARCHAEOLOGY OF
KNOWLEDGE; GENEALOGY OF POWER ARCHAEOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE GENEALOGY OF POWER MADNESS AND CIVILIZATION THE BIRTH OFTHE CLINIC DISCIPLINE AND PUNISH
4
MICHEL FOUCAULT: PART 2: SEXUALITY, POWER, AND SELF
ZYGMUNT BAUMAN: FROM MODERN TO POSTMODERN
63
POWER AND SEXUALITY
SELF AND SEXUALITY
5
THE BREAK WITH MARX AND MARXISM SYMBOLIC EXCHANGE 6
CONTEMPORARY SOCIETY: ITS NATURE AND PROBLEMS The Code Fashion Simulacra The Fractal Order
Ecstasy
Death
America Other Issues ARE THERE ANY GROUNDS FOR HOPE? Seduction Fatal Strategies Other Ways Out
against Ambivalence Learning to Live with Ambivalence?
76
79
85
88
Postmodern Politics and Ethics DAVID HARVEY: POSTMODERNISM AND MARXISM
9
AMERICAN INTERVENTIONS: BELL, JAMESON,
FEMINISTS, AND MULTICULTURALlSTS DANIEL BELL: POSTINDUSTRIAL SOCIETY FREDRIC JAMESON: THE CULTURAL LOGIC OF LATE
CAPITALISM FEMINIST THEORY AND POSTMODERN THEORY
92
92
92
94
95
100
102
103
105
107
109
109
MULTICULTURAL THEORY
10
POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY AND CONTEMPO SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY IN THE POSTMODERN ERA Negative Lessons Positive Lessons
11
POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY: AN APPLICATIO CONSUMER SOCIETY A POSTMODERN ANALYSIS DEALING WITH THE NEW MEANS OF CONSUMPTION
112
115
OTHER FRENCH POSTMODERN THINKERS: DERRIDA, DELEUZE AND GUATIARI, LYOTARD, LACAN, VIRILlO
119
JACQUES DERRIDA: GRAMMATOLOGY AND WRITING
119
124
GILLES DELEUZE AND FELlX GUATTARI: TOWARD SCHIZOANALYSIS JEAN-FRANl;:OIS LYOTARD: THE DEATH OF THE GRAND NARRATIVE JACQUES LACAN: THE IMAGINARY, THE SYMBOLIC, THE REAL PAUL VIRILlO: DROMOLOGY 8
Postmodernity and the (Possible) End of the Wa
JEAN BAUDRILLARD: PART 2: PROBLEMS IN THE CONTEMPORARY WORLD AND THE POSSIBILITY OF DEALING WITH THEM
7
63
67
JEAN BAUDRILLARD: PART 1: THE BASIC THEORETICAL IDEAS CONSUMER SOCIETY
Legislators and Interpreters
Toward a Postmodern Way of Thinking Postmodern Sociology, Sociology of Postmoder
OTHER EUROPEAN PERSPECTIVES: GIDDENS, BECK, HABERMAS, BAUMAN, AND HARVEY ANTHONY GIDDENS: THE JUGGERNAUT OF MODERNITY ULRICH BECK: MODERNITY AND RISK JORGEN HABERMAS: MODERNITY AS AN "UNFINISHED PROJECT'
128
132
137
12
CRITICISMS OF, AND THE MOVE BEYOND,
POSTMODERNISM BASIC CRITICISMS BEYOND POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY
REFERENCES INDEXES
Name Index
143
143
149
152
Subject Index
POSTMOD!ERN THEORY, S,O',CIOLO SOCIOL"OGiliCAiL
SOME FUNDAMENTAL DEFINITIONS WHAT IS POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY? VULNERABILITY OF SOCIOLOGY AND SOCIOLO'GICAL THE INTIMATIONS OF POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY IN SOCIOL
SOCIOLO'GICAL theory (and, to a lesser extent, sociology m a situation today that a number of fields, mainly in the arts,. con two ago:!
The postmodern moment had arrived2 and perple~ed intellectuals, a trepreneurs wondered whether they should get on the bandwagon a sit on the sidelines until the new fad disappeared into the whirl of c
While some sociological theorists, and many sociologists, stil em social theory to be a fad, and it continues to look to some more like a cmnival (Norris, 1990) than a serious scholarly e fact is that sociological theorists 3 can no longer view postmode than an interesting side- (if not freak-) show. A good deal of and important contemporary social theory s'A'irls in and arou scene. Sociological theory must attend to this growing body of In fact, this book is premised on the idea that the landscape ory is being transformed by postmodern social theory. For one of postmodern social theorists are forcing many sociological th some of their most basic premises. For another, many of the t ated by postmodemists are in the process of being integrated of sociological theory.
1 Other fields that are only recently confronting the postmodern chall (Sass, 1994) and criminology (Schwartz and Friedrichs, 1994). 2 To at least some observers it has already passed. According to Malcolm modernism was the concept of the 1980s." Alexander (1995) argues that a de social theory is already underway. See also Frow (1991), lVhat Was Postmode 3 For a critique of sociological methodology, especially ethnography,. from tive, see Clough (1992), The Ends of Ethnography.
A number of European sociological theorists (e.g., Barry Smart [1993a], Mike Featherstone [1991]) have been on the postmodern bandwagon for some time and they have been joined by a few American sociological theorists (e.g., Charles Lemert [1994], Stjepan Mestrovic [1993], Steven Seidman [1994a], Richard Har vey Brown [1987]). However, almost all of the important postmodern social theo rists, virtually all of the people whose work will be treated in detail in this book, are not sociologists. Rather, they are most likely to be interdisciplinary social theo rists whose worK reflects input from a number of different fields. In some cases, their work is a kind of social theory that, in the main, seems very familiar to socio io i'cal theorists (Michel Foucault, for example), while in other cases their work appears to represent a profound assault on the basic premises of that theory (for ex ample, Jean Baudrillard). In either case, it is essential that sociological theorists, and students of the field, familiarize themselves with postmodern ideas. At the minimum, those ideas will continue to find their way into sociological discourse; at the maximum they will radically alter the nature of that discourse. Sociology is a latecomer to postmodernism, but in contemporary social theory postmodernism has been so hot (Kellner, 1989b:2), so debated, so analyzed and re analyzed that at least one sociological theorist has urged that we stop using the term because it has been "worn frail by overexertion" (Lemert, 1994: 142). That is, it has been abused and debased by both supporters and detractors in the course of the overheated debate between them over the merits of postmoderri social theory. While that may well be the case, sociological theory still has much to learn from postmodern social theory. Given its importance and the interest that it has generated, the objective in this book is to offer students of sociology (and other social sciences) an introduction to postmodem social theory. However, it should be pointed out that such an introduc tion is no easy matter because, among other things, there is great diversity among the generally highly idiosyncratic postmodern social thinkers, and it is difficult, if not impossible, to offer generalizations on which the majority would agree. In addi tion, it is difficult to tell a coherent story because one of the premises of postmod ernism is that distortion often occurs when efforts are made to make the incoherent seem coherent. As Bauman (1992:xxiv) puts it: "any narrative ... stands a risk of implying more coherence than the postmodern condition could possibly uphold." '. In fact, the vast majority of generalizations about post'modemism, whether they stem from supporters or detractors, are flawed, usually bearing little or no resem blance to what specific postmodernists have to say. Thus, instead of talking in global terms about postmodernism, the strategy throughout most of this book will be to discuss the ideas of specific thinkers associated in one way or another with postmodernism. (However, because of the need to orient the reader for the specifics to come, we are forced to offer, very cautiously, some generalizations about postmodern social thought as this chapter unfolds.) Ironically, virtually none of the thinkers discussed in this book would be happy being labeled a postmodernist. Many are avowedly modernists, others better thought of as poststructuralists (more on this below), and still others uncomfort able with, or downright resistant to, any label at all. Whatever they may think of
g
themselves or be thought of by others, the fact remains that their ide in one way or another to the current literature on postmodem social that reason that their ideas are covered in this book. Another problem here is that one of the basic tenets of postmod has been alternately called the death of "man" (including, of cour the subject, or of the author. While we will return to the meaning(s related ideas at a number of points in this book, for our purposes in can take this to mean that instead of focusing on authors of texts mean by them, postmodernism involves a focus on texts and their other texts (what the postmodemists call "intertextuality").4 Here vak (1974:liv) puts this issue: "counting the proper names of prede recognized as a convenient fiction. Each proper name establishes against the anonymity of textuality." While most of this book is d cussion of texts and how they relate to one another, the discussi under the heading of specific authors. In that sense, and many ot tinctly not a postmodern undertaking. However, it is my view that i senting the work of each author independently that we can beg sense at all out of postmodern social theory. It is difficult enough f tellectual twists and turns in the work of key thinkers like Foucaul let alone trying to unravel the spider's web of innumerable othe rounds each and everyone of their texts. That is not to say that I d importance of such intertextual analysis, but it is to say that I do n fective way of introducing the basic premises of postrnodem socia Some postmodemists would also object to a book devoted to " or not it is postmodern. As Best and Kellner (l991:x) put it, "post are directed against the notion of 'theory' itself ... a systematically ceptual structure anchored in the real." That is, there is opposition to be considered a theory, a body of systematic ideas must someho resent reality ("representationalism"). Much postmodern theoriz sightful, but it is often quite unsystematic, and very little of it model of reality. Indeed, some postmodemists might argue that th tional sociological theOlists to systematically model reality under ity to generate insights. Most sociological theory is guilty of wha would consider a false separation of the "real" from "theory,'" as oping theory that purports to represent something-the real-th ernists believe can only be known narrowly and interpretively. W be separated from the interpretation of it, and it is impossible to flicts between interpretations. However, in my view, bodies of ideas do not need to be either s resentations of the real to qualify as theories. While postmodernis ory, what most of them in fact do is to theorize, often about the of it). Perhaps they are haphazard at times, but the fact is that the part, social theories, and they are relevant to the concerns of socio 4
And, as we will see, on "readers" rather than authors.
This book on postmodem social theory employs the same definition of theory that I utilize in Sociological Theory (Ritzer, 1996b). That is, theories are sets of ideas that deal with centrally important social issues, have a wide range of appli cation, and have stood the test of time (or promise to). In addition, here as in the other text, I am concerned with theoretical work done by sociologists, or with that done in other fields, that has come to be defined as important in sociology. The ideas to be discussed throughout this book meet the criteria laid out in this defini tion of theory. They may not be systematic or represent the real, but that does not prevent them from being considered theories. To be clear, however, the theories to be discussed in this book are social theories and not nalTowly sociological theories. Above all, this means that while, like socio logical theories, they deal with social issues, they are generally interdisciplinary in nature, drawing on thought from a number of fields, and they are produced by thinkers who defy easy categorization. In fact, sociological theory has always been strongly affected by social theories. For example, Karl Marx was not a sociologist, but he developed a social theory that has had, and continues to have, a powerful impact on sociological theory. This book flies in the face of another tenet of P9stmodemism-its skepticism of grand narratives. Grand narratives, such as those offered in textbooks (like this one), which purport to tell the story of a field or discipline, are considered by post modernists to be myths that conceal many dimensions that do not fit into the story being told. A textbook, like this one, implies the privileging of certain ideas over others, valoriZing certain perspectives and marginalizing others. Since I am choos ing to tell the story of postrnodern social theory in one way (out of many possibili ties; for others, see Kroker, 1992; Hollinger, 1994; Bertens, 1995), I am valorizing some ideas and thinkers (especially those I choose to discuss in depth) and margin alizing others (those who receive little or no attention in these pages). Further more, this is a story told primarily from the perspective of a sociologist; other grand narratives told from other vantage points (literary criticism, linguistics) are not, to be found in these pages, even though they might make equally, if not more important, stories. While I recognize the problems involved in making these kinds of choices and, more generally, in the kind of modernist narrative offered here, such a story needs to be constructed and told to try to give at least some coherence to what is other wise an admittedly highly incoherent body of thought. An incoherent overview of an incoherent field is in nobody's interest, except perhaps those intellectuals who devote their lives to clarifying incoherent ideas. However, it is important to recog nize that I do not consider the story to be told in these pages to be the story of post modern social theory. Many such stories are possible, and this is just one of the possible narratives. Thus, it would be better and more accurate to view this book as offering one of many possible narratives and not a grand narrative. It is also likely that most postmodernists would be appalled at the idea of a text designed to introduce readers systematically to their basic ideas. They would see a textbook as a modem structure that seeks to impose itself on their ideas, attempts to give those ideas a rational ordering, and thereby does grave violence to them.
They would see a textbook as a kind of "prison house'l' (Jameson fines, and restricts the free play of, those ideas. No doubt violenc postmodem thinking in these pages, but as sensitive as I am to cerns, I will do my best to limit it as much as possible within the is, admittedly, a modernist project written by an author who" try a ues to think and write in (mostly) a modern way.s Most postmodemists (and many modernists as well) would u that instead of reading a text like this one, what readers should d in the original postmodern texts and make their own sense of that There is no question that they are right in making such an argum no question that if that was their only option, most readers wo nothing about postmodernism. Postmodern social theory is a hig gonistic, contradictory body of work that would put off an but th social thinkers. This book is designed for those who really wo what the noise surrounding postmodernism is all about but lack t the time to pore over the innumerable original texts. My hope is this introduction, the reader will have the background and inspira some of the original texts. If not, the reader will at least have s reasons for all the excitement about postmodem social theory.
SOME FUNDAMENTAL DEFINITIONS
Judith Butler (1995:51) speaks not only for many postmoderni modernists when she announces: "I don't know what postmodern concept has greater resonance today among scholars in a wide ra than "postmodemism," there is enormous ambiguity and controv what is meant by that notion and related terms. To add some cl useful to distinguish among postmodemity, postmodemism, and p theory.6
• Posnnodemity refers to a social and political epoch that is following the modem era in a historical sense (Kumar, 1995; Cro Waters, 1992). • Postlnodernism refers to cultural products (in art, movies, ar on) that are seen as different from modern cultural products (Ku son, 1991). • Postmoden~ social theory refers to a kind of social theory th modern social theory (Best and Kellner, 1991).
5 I am not alone in having this problem; others include Douglas KeIlner and Z Chapter 8). The reader might ponder what it means to have a book about postm modernist; what sorts of distortions are apt to be manifest in such a book? It about what a postmodernist text on postmodern theory might look like. One pos look something like MTV-one fragment after another with little or no connecti 6 Here I follow the distinction made by Best and Kellner (1991:5).
Thus, the idea of the postmodern encompasses a new historical epoch, new cul tural products, and a new type of theorizing about the social world. All of these el ements of the postmodern, of course, share the perspective that something new and different has occurred (socially, culturally, or intellectually) in recent years, and those new postmodern developments are coming to stand as alternatives to, or per haps to supplant, modem realities. The first point is that there is a widespread belief that the era of modernity is ending or has ended, and we have entered a new social epoch-postmodemity (Dunn, 1991). As we will see, there are many ways to characterize the difference between the modern and the postmodern world, but as an illustration, one of the best is the difference in viewpoints on whether it is possible to find rational (ratio nality is a concept closely associated with modernity [Dahrendorf, 1979]) solu tions to society's problems. For example, Lyndon Johnson's war on poverty in the 1960s was typical of the way those associated with a modern society believed they could discover and implement rational solutions to its problems. It could be argued that by the 1970s such programs had begun to lose favor, and the transition to a postmodern society was underway (Elazar, 1980). By the 1980s, the Reagan ad ministration and its general unwillingness to develop massive programs to deal with such problems was representative, at least in one sense, of a postmodern soci ety and the belief that there is no single rational answer to various problems.7 The Reagan administration was known for its postmodern use of the media to commu nicate using "soundbites," not by its efforts to develop massive programs to solve social problems. Thus, we might conclude that somewhere between the presiden tial, administrations of Lyndon Johnson and Ronald Reagan,8 the United States began moving from being a modern to a postmodern society. In the rnid-1990s, the even more extreme conservative position of Newt Gingrich with his Contract with America makes it clear that we have progressed even further into the postmodern world, in which we are progressively giving up hope of finding grand rational solu tions to our most pressing problems. Even a Democratic president, Bill Clinton, was forced to declare in his 1996 State of the Union address that "the era of big government is over." A word of caution is necessary here. Most postmodernists are uneasy and even unwilling to discuss an historical transition from modernity to postmodernity. For one thing, it constitutes the kind of grand narrative that we have already seen they reject. Second, it involves the kind of linear, chronological thinking that postmod emists associate with modernism and therefore also reject. To postmodemists, things rarely, if ever, progress in a simple, linear manner. Finally, it involves, in their view, far too neat and simplified a distinction between historical epochs. Thus, while it is possible to think of a transition from modernity to postmodernity, and much of this thinking has been given impetus by postmodem social theory, few, if any, postmodern theorists accept such a simple, linear, grand narrative. They
do agree that something has happened; something has changed, bu and it is not linear (Calhoun, 1993). Second, postmodemism relates to the cultural realm in which postmodern products have tended to supplant modem products Strinati, 1995). In architecture, we can, following Jean Baudrilla portant postrnodem social theorist (see Chapters 5 and 6), contras highly rational twin towers in New York City to the more playful tic, and nonrational creations of the postmodem architects. Archi son's AT&T building in New York is often cited as an example o chitecture since it includes both modem and traditional elements dwelling designed by Frank Gehry that involves a traditional clap rounded by an industrial-looking corrugated metal wall (Jameson, classical music would certainly be modem, while Shusterman music as postmodem because, among other things, of the fact that styles rather than creating new ones, eclectically mixes styles, an senting primarily the black community) rather than universal. In vision, the highly offbeat show Twin Peaks is generally taken to be of postmodernism, while Father Knows Best, with its highly ratio ily, is a good example of a modem television program. In the mo ner, showing a Los Angeles of the future combining highly futu traditional elements and peopled by "replicants" who often see than the humans, may be seen as a postmodern work, while the ments with its biblical grand narrative would certainly qualify as a Third, and of much more direct relevance to us here, is the em modern social theory and its differences from modem theory. In say that modern social theory tends to be absolute, rational, and t sibility of discovering truth, whereas postmodem social theory tivistic and open to the possibility of irrationality. However, as modem social theory, not all postmodem social theory is of o (1993a) has sought to bring some order to this area by articulating tal positions taken by postmodem social theorists. 9
• The first, or extreme postmodernist, position is that there h rupture, and modern society has been replaced by a postmodem is uncomfortable with such labels, it is clear that Jean Baudrillard ciety has changed radically. Another postmodem thinker who ho Paul Virilio (1991a; 1995); we will discuss his work briefly in Ch • The second, or more moderate, position is that while a c place, postmodernity grows out of, and is continuous with, mode tation is adhered to by such postrnodem Marxian thinkers as Fre well as Emesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe [1985] and David Ha
7 Pettegrew (1992) also focuses on the 1980s, but he sees MTV, not the Reagan administration, as the key development.
8 In using these examples, I am not implying that modernity is necessarily liberal and postrnoder nity necessarily conservative.
9 Other examples of typologies include Rosenau's (1992) distinction betwee mative postmodem thinkers and Kumar's (1995) differentiation between the pos tion and resistance.
postmodem feminists such as Nancy Fraser, Donna Haraway, and Linda Nicholson (see Chapter 9). • Finally, there is the theoretical position adopted by Smart himself that rather than viewing them as epochs, we can see modernity and postmodernity as engaged in a long-running relationship with one another, with postmodernity continually pointing out the limitations of modernity. Thus, they can be seen as alternative per spectives, not successive time periods. The most important representative of this point of view is Jean-Fran90is Lyotard (Chapter 7); this perspective will also in form the discussion in Chapter 11. While useful, it should be noted that postmodern social theorists would likely dismiss Smart's typology (they would also reject the distinction among post modernity, postmodernism, and postmodem social theory [Kumar, 1995]) as greatly simplifying the enormous diversity of their ideas and of distorting each in dividual's work in the process. In fact, while a useful orienting point for the reader, we will not use Smart's typology any further either. Rather, as pointed out above, we will concentrate (once we get past this introduction) on the ideas of specific thinkers and not on the broad categories of thought into which their ideas might be shoehorned. WHAT IS POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY?
A useful beginning toward gaining a greater understanding of postmodem social theory is provided by Pauline Rosenau (1992) who defines such theory largely in telms of the things to which it is opposed. Above all, and most obviously, post moc:iernism is critical of modern society and of its failur~ to deliver on its promises. In light of the horrors of the twentieth century (Auschwitz, the Gulag Archipel ago), postmodernists ask how anyone can believe that modernity has brought with it progress and hope for a still brighter future. Postmodemists tend to critique much associated with modernity: ... the accumulated experience of Western civilization, industrialization, urbanization, advanced technology, the nation state, life in the "fast lane." They challenge modern pri orities: career, office, individual responsibility, bureaucracy, liberal democracy, toler ance, humanism, egalitarianism, detached experiment, evaluative criteria, neutral proce dures, impersonal rules, and rationality. (Rosenau, 1992:5-6)
Second, as we have ah'eady mentioned, postmode~ theorists tend to reject what are alternatively called world views, metanarratives, grand narratives, totalizations, and so on. They tend to reject the idea that there is a single grand perspective or answer. As Baudrillard (1990/1993:72), for example, puts it, "The great drives or impulses, with their positive, elective, and attractive powers, are gone." Postmod ernists are generally content to live with more limited explanations (local narra tives) or with no explanations at all. However, it should be pointed out here that there is often a gap between what postmodernists say and what they do. As we will
see, at least some postmodemists do produce grand narratives of postmodemists are former Marxian theorists, and as a result they o tance themselves from the grand narratives that characterized that Third, postmodem thinkers tend to accord great importance to phenomena such as "emotions, feelings, intuition, reflection, spec experience, custom, violence, metaphysics, tradition, cosmology, ligious sentiment, and mystical experience" (Rosenau, 1992:6) .As is especially true of Jean Baudrillard, chiefly his thoughts on "sym Fourth, postmodem theorists reject the modem tendency to pu tween such things as academic disciplines, "culture and life" fic image and reality" (Rosenau, 1992:6). Thus, the work of most pos tends to break through one or more of these boundaries and to su might want to do the same. For example, we will see Baudrillard cial theories as a kind of fiction, science fiction, poetry, and so on. Fifth,many postmodemists reject the careful, reasoned style o mic discourse (Nuyen, 1992). The postmodem author's objective shock and startle the reader than to win the reader over with a logi gument. It also tends to be more literary than academic in style. Finally, instead of focusing on the core of modem society, post devote their attention to the periphery:
... on what has been taken for granted, what has been neglected, reg the forgotten, the irrational, the insignificant, the repressed, the border the sacred, the traditional, the eccentric, the sublimated" the subjugate nonessential, the marginal, the peripheral, the excluded, the tenuous accidental, the dispersed, the disqualified, the deferred, the disjointed.
In sum, as Rosenau (1992:8) puts it, the postmodem theorists "off rather than determinism, diversity rather than unity, difference rat sis, complexity rather than simplification."
VULNERABILITY OF SOCIOLOGY AND SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY
As we have seen, postmodern social theory developed . largely outs and sociological theory. However,· the social sciences in general, particular, are vulnerable to inroads from postmodern social theor grounds. Many of these vulnerabilities are traceable to the wide-sca the modern scientific model lO in the social sciences and in sociolog
10 Not all postmodern social theorists are opposed to science; see, for exampl gar (1979).
• First, many sociologists are growing impatient with the failure of their scien tifically inclined brethren to produce long-promised breakthroughs. • Second, there is growing awareness that the science that has been produced is most responsive to the needs of those with power and tends to buttress their posi tion in society. • Third, there is increasing research showing a huge discrepancy between the way science is supposed to operate and the way it actually functions (Knorr Cetina, 1981; Latour, 1981). • Fourth, the continuation, even acceleration, of many social problems makes it clear that science is not the answer. • Fifth, science minimizes, even trivializes, the importance of metaphysical and mystical aspects of social life. • Finally, science contributes little or nothing to normative or ethical questions or to what we ought to be doing (Rosenau, 1992). Relatedly, Fuchs and Ward (1994a) argue that sociology is one of a number of fields that is particularly vulnerable to the postmodern critique because it is multi paradigmatic (Ritzer, 1975), loosely coupled, decentralized, and dominated by texts and "conversations" among scholars. More specifically, Fuchs and Ward argue that fields like sociology are particularly vulnerable to a strong form of de constructionism. Deconstruction is one of postmodernism's key approaches to knowledge, hence theory. (This idea is most often associated with the work of Jacques Derrida; see Chapter 7 for a discussion of his sense of deconstructionism). Briefly, deconstructionists take a text apart to show its basic assumptions and con tradictions. Additionally, this "requires that traditional concepts, theory, and under standing surrounding a text be unraveled, including the assumption that an author's intentions and meanings can be easily determined" (Denzin, 1994: 185). More gen erally, deconstructionism "aims to clear away the wreckage of a cluttered theoreti cal past, which clings to preconceptions that are regarded as no longer workable in the contemporary world" (Denzin, 1994: 185). However, the goal of deconstruc tionism is not then to put it back together in a revised, improved, and truer form. Such a reconstmctive task is not undertaken because the deconstmctionist rejects the idea that there is some ultimate truth to be discovered. (In fact, the search for truth is seen as concealing a "will to power" [see discussion of this notion and other Nietzschean ideas in Chapter 2J, in this case a desire to establish the preemi nence of a particular perspective to the detriment of other viewpoints.!l) There are no ultimate answers; there are only more interpretations, more texts to be "read." In other words, there are only more phenomena to be deconstructed by the decon structionist. A textual field like sociology is particularly prone to this strong form of decon st11lction. While many postmodernists would disagree, there are, in Fuchs and Ward's (1994a:482) view, other types of fields that in addition to texts "use other means of intellectual production, such as mathematical symbolism, technical de I1
The
will to power can also be viewed in a more positive sense as the capacity for transcendence.
vices, experimental equipment, and the like."12 Such fields are, Fuchs and Ward, subject to a much weaker form of deconstmction is accepted that there is no one truth or plivileged epistemological nonetheless proceeds on the basis of ground rules and criteria. In like sociology subject to the strong form of deconstruction tend to in which "anything goes." Sociologists wIite texts (books and ar ple) about other texts (results of surveys or questionnaires) that people say and do (still more texts). Because all are texts, all are s stlLlction and reinterpretation. There is no single "tme" interpreta data derived from any of these texts. Here is Fuchs and Ward's des like sociology and why they are particularly prone to deconstmct generally to the postmodern critique:
Practitioners in textual fields read and write a lot, and they soon start b ing and writing is all one can do. They come to see the whole world ever doesn't really fit this metaphor becomes to them text-like, or 's semiotic transformation of the world is complete, there appears to be n text, and so the universal "crisis of reference and representation" c When commentaries OD commentaries on texts are piled up, anything must eventually disappear from sight.
(Fuchs and
While this describes the state in sociology, it is not the only field others include literature, art, and so on-fields in which, as we w ernism had its beginnings. Turning from the social sciences and sociology to sociologi specifically, Seidman (1991) associates sociological theory with attributes a number of modem characteristics to it-especially sc tionalism, totalization, essentialism, and insularity-that help ma to the attacks of postmodern social theorists. Let us look at each o First, sociological theory is accused of scientism. That is, most orists believe in universal ideas, if not social laws. They adopt the an accumulating body of theoretical knowledge and that the task practitioners is either to add to it or make breakthroughs that m plateau from which it can once again begin the process of accumu the absence of laws and the failure to make breakthroughs have o cal theory to the attacks of postmodernists. Second, sociological theory is seen as foundatiollal. Foundati base guidelines for social behavior and socIal analysis on a fir foundation (Gottdiener, 1993). Relatedly, Seidman (1991:133; i gues that sociological theory "intends to uncover a logic of societ cover the one true vocabulary that min'ors the social universe.. theory aims to denude itself of its contextual embeddedness; to a ity's universal condition." It has taken upon itself the responsibilit 12
Most postmodernists would also see these as texts and therefore subject to d
ogy. We have assumed the role of resolving disciplinary disputes and conceptual con flicts .... Sociological theorists have stepped forward as the virtual police of the socio logical mind. (Seidman, 1991: 132)
Sociological theorists see themselves as providing the foundation for the entire dis cipline of sociology. However, no such single foundation has been uncovered, cer tainly not one that the discipline as a whole would accept. Third, sociological theory tends to adopt a totalizing view of the world. To Seid man, this means the search for "an overarching totalizing conceptual framework that would be true for all times and all places" (Seidman, 1991:137). On the one hand, this is similar to foundationalism, but on the other to Seidman (1991:139) it means that sociological theorists developed grand narratives of the West's "progress," including "industdalization, modernization, secularization, democrati zation" and sought to apply them to the world as a whole. 13 The problem with these narratives is that they are unidimensional and ignore many other develop ments. They have little or nothing to say about many spheres and time periods in the West. As Seidman (1991:140) says, such theories "utterly fail to grasp the mul tisided, heterogeneous, morally ambiguous social currents and strains that make up the life of any society." Furthermore, such theories completely ignore much of the rest of the world and assume that they have undergone, or would soon undergo, the same progressive developments. For example, a simple model like Durkheim's mechanical-to-organic solidarity tends to "repress important differences between societies" (Seidman, 1991:139). The history of sociological theory has been char acterized by conflict among such competing totalizations 14 (for example, Marx's theory of processes leading to the proletarian revolution versus Weber's theory of progressive rationalization) for hegemony, and no single totalization has ever gained preeminence in sociological theory. Fourth, sociological theodes are seen as essentialist. That is, they tend to see humans as having basic, fixed, and unchanging characteristics. Social phenomena are viewed as expressions of those essences rather than as products of specific so cial conditions. A good example is Marx's sense of species being. Such essentialist concepts fail to take into account differences based on "gender, race, ethnicity, class, or sexual orientation" (Seidman, 1991:140). Further, those who adopt one essentialist view tend to disagree with those who adopt other essentialist views. Finally, sociological theory is viewed as being insular, that is, concerned with is sues that are of concern only to sociological theorists. To put it another way, the concerns and the disputes of sociological theory have become increasingly metatheoretical, that is in Seidman's (1991:133) terms "self-referential and episte mological." Seidman refers to the debates over micro-macro and agency-structure For a discussion of such a grand narrative in psychology, see Walkerdine (1993). These might better be seen as grand narratives. In fact, many of the terms associated with post model11 social theory tend to be used inconsistently, and this does not help in trying to gain a clear sense of the perspective. 113
14
integration (Ritzer, 1991) as examples of such insular issues tha ing to do with the social world and are of virtually no interest to Seidman proceeds to argue that social theory represents a v sociological theory. Social theories are social stories, or narra mately related to the pressing social issues of the day. Further ented not only to better understanding those issues but also to h social outcomes. They are not driven by insular theoretical inte political, and social COnCelTIS. It is Seidman~s thesis that for most of their histories, social a ories have been intertwined. For example, Durkheim did main The Division of Labor in Society and primarily sociological the Sociological Method. However, in recent years, and especially social theory has been devalued by mainstreanl sociologists b other things, ideological and nonscientific. As a result, socio been ascendent in the discipline. This has had a range of quences, and Seidman wants to see a return to a social theory consistent with the "postmodern turn" in the social sciences in g However, that social theory is not to be the grand social Durkheim, but it is rather to be "local" and "ethnocentric.'" The social theories because theorists are inevitably embedded in t social circumstances. is This prevents them from obtaining the viewpoint they would need to produce grand theories. When into producing such grand theories, sociological theorists hav are in Seidman's opinion "myths." For example, a number of th theories (for example, Marx and a number of neo-Marxists) th progress toward the salvation and liberation of people from an If sociological theorists are to avoid creating myths, they need that are restricted in terms of time and place. Seidman believe will be local, although it is possible to produce broader theories deeply embedded in the context from which they are drawn. In ern social theories must not be insular. Rather, they must be morally and politically significant. In fact, Seidman urges soci take into account the ethical and political implications of their o gage public issues as public defenders and advocates of partic ments. Even though Seidman urges the creation of postmodem soc not view these as scientific products. Rather, like the classic so modern social theorists are producing "social narratives," or th sive sounding "stories." To the postmodemist, social theorists this serves to demystify what theorists do and to eliminate the
15 However, Seidman (1991: 136) does not completely rule out the possibil genius comes along tomorrow and proves to the satisfaction of the social scie or she has succeeded in providing foundations, I will relinquish my standpoin propose that we renounce the quest for foundations in favor of local ration strategies."
their activities and those of laypeople. After all, we are all storytellers. Sociologi cal theorists, and sociologists more generally, are seen as having wrapped them selves in a cloak of scientific privilege to distance themselves from those -they are analyzing. By viewing the products of social theorists as stories, more people will be able to participate in the public dialogue over these matters. However, Antonio (1991) argues that from the point of view of postmodernism, or at least the most radical postmodernists, Seidman has not gone nearly far enough. In fact, from that vantage point, Seidman seems to be not so much a critic of the modernist project of sociological and social theory but rather another, albeit slightly different, practitioner of it. For example, "Seidman implies a normative vi sion emphasizing radically democratic, highly pluralistic, mutually tolerant, and autonomous subcommunities linked by uncoerced communication and coopera tion" (Antonio, 1991:157). Furthermore, Seidman's solution-local narratives does not go nearly far enough from the point of view of the radical postmodernists since even local narratives try to impose coherence on that which is inherently fragmented. As Antonio (1991: 157; italics added) puts it, "Worldwide, national, re gional, and local portrayals are all homogenizing totalizations. A consistent per spectivist method would decompose each into a myriad of inchoate subnarratives." If Seidman has not gone far enough, and he is already writing the obituary for sociological theory, where does that leave us? First, it still leaves us with need to survey the range of postmodern thinking. After all, postmodernists are saying things, things that sound like theory, and we need to know what they are. This is made even more necessary by the fact that postmodern theory involves a wide range of positions, many of which are in conflict with one another. There is a pressing need to sort out the various ideas that are included under the heading of postmodernism. Second, as pointed out previously, despite all their critiques of grand theories, many postmodernists are producing just that. Here is the way Anto nio (1991:161) makes this point: "Regardless of their relentless attacks on the to talizing tendencies of modem theory, postmodernist portrayals of epochal change and sweeping cultural disintegration revive the big discourse of the classical tradi tion [of sociological theory]."
INTIMATIONS OF POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY
IN SOCIOLOGY
In fact, postmodem social theory is, at least to some degree, part of the classical (and contemporary) sociological tradition. Take, for example, the recent reinterpre tation' of the work of Georg Simmel entitled Postmodern(ized) Simmel (Weinstein and Weinstein, 1993). Weinstein and Weinstein recognize that there is a strong case to be made for Simmel as a liberal modernist (Frisby, 1991) who offers a grand narrative of the historical trend toward the dominance of objective culture or the "tragedy of culture." However, they also argue that an equally strong case can be made for Simmel as a postmodernist. Thus, they acknowledge that both alterna tives have validity and, in fact, that one is no more "true" than the other. Weinstein and Weinstein (1993:21) argue: "To our minds 'modernism' and 'postmodemism' are not exclusive alternatives but discursive domains bordering each other." They
note they could be doing a modernist interpretation of Simmel but modernist explication is more useful. This leads to the very po "There is no essential Simmel, only different Simmels read thro positions in contemporary discourse formations" (Weinstein 1993:55). What sorts of arguments do Weinstein and Weinstein make in d of Simmel as a postmodernist? For one thing, Simmel is seen as opposed to totalizations; indeed he is inclined to de-totalize mod and aside from, the theory of the "tragedy of culture," Simmel was sayist and a storyteller, and he dealt primarily with a range of spec than with the totality of the social world. Simmel is also described by Weinstein and Weinstein, as he is flaneur, or someone who is something of an idler. More specificall scribed as a sociologist who idled away his time analyzing a wide phenomena. He was interested in all of them for their aesthetic q existed "to titillate, astonish, please or delight him" (Weinstein 1993:60). This approach led Simmel away from a totalized view o toward a concern for a number of discrete, but important, elements Bricoleur is another term used to describe Simmel (although it sociated with the work of the anthropologist, Claude Levi-Strauss a kind of intellectual handyman who makes do with whatever hap able to him. Available to Simmel was a wide range of fragmen world, or "shards of objective culture" as Weinstein and Weinste scribe them in Simmelian terms. As a bricoleur Simmel cobbled to ideas he could find to shed meaning on the social world. There is no need to go too deeply into the details of Weinstein interpretation of a postmodernized Simmel. The illustrative poi make it clear that such an interpretation is as reasonable as the m that is offered far more frequently in sociology. It would be far ha with similar postmodern views of the other major classical theoris could certainly find aspects of their work that is consistent with Thus, as Seidman makes clear, most of sociological theory is mod case of Simmel illustrates, there are postmodern intimations in modem of traditions. Another place to look for intimations of postmodernism is amo modem theory within sociological theory. As several observers 1991; Best and Kellner, 1991) have pointed out, a key position is Wright Mills (1959). For one thing, Mills actually used the term " describe the post-Enlightenment era that we were entering: "We a of what is called The Modem Age ... The Modem Age is being post-modern period" (Mills, 1959: 165-166). Second, he was a modern grand theory in sociology, especially as it was practiced sons. Third, Mills favored a socially and morally engaged sociolo he wanted a sociology that linked broad public issues to specific pr While there are suggestions of postmodernism in Mills's work that we find postmodern theory itself. For example, of Mills, B
(1991:8) contend that he "is very much a modernist, given to sweeping sociological generalization, totalizing surveys of sociology and history, and a belief in the power of the sociological imagination to illuminate social reality and to change society." Denzin (1989:279) goes further, calling Mills "America's preeminent 'classical the orist' of the contemporary age." His critiques are "cloaked in the languages and grand 'metanarratives' of the classic age: reason, freedom, democracy, enlighten ment and positive knowledge about men and their troubles." Mills is seen by Denzin as a modernist who wrote yet another "totalizing theory of early postmodern Ameri can society that would yield yet another version of the gemeinschaft-gesellschaft myth which haunted ... [modem] theorists" (Denzin, 1989:279). Mills does this be cause, in part, as Denzin puts it, he kept the wrong sociological company. That is, despite his criticisms of grand theory, Mills is also a part of that theoretical tradi tion. Even when he turns, as he often does, to Marx he is, in fact, turning to the thinker who is perhaps the premier modem grand theorist; the producer of the pre eminent grand narrative. While there are intimations of postmodenlism in the sociologies of Simmel and Mills (and many others; see the discussion of Daniel Bell's work on postindustrial society in Chapter 9), it is not there that we find postmodern theory itself. SUMMARY
-.J
.'
This chapter offers a brief introduction to postmodem social theory and its rela tionship to sociology and sociological theory. We distinguish between postmoder nity (as a social and political epoch), postmodernism (as a separate cultural form), and postmodern social theory (as a distinct kind of social theory). The latter is the focal concern in this book. Three types of positions are adopted by postmodem so cial theorists: extreme (there is a radical disjunction between modern and postmod ern society) and moderate (the postmodem is not discontinuous with the modern) positions as well as one that sees postmodern and modern social theory as alterna tive ways of looking at the social world. While one must be wary of generalizing about postmodem social theory since there are major differences among those associated with it, an effort was made to offer a broad portrayal of postmodem social theory. Among other things, it is char acterized by its critical approach to the modem world, its opposition to modern grand narratives and totalizations, an emphasis on more pre-modem emotions and feelings, a style that is often more startling than well reasoned, and a tendency to focus on the marginal rather than the central. Both sociology in general and sociological theory in particular are seen as being vulnerable to the postmodem critique. Much of the vulnerability of sociology is traceable to the failure of the scientific model to deliver on its promises. Postmod em social theory associates science with modernity and is highly critical of both. 'Sociology is also seen as the kind of multiparadigmatic, textual, conversational field that is most open to postmodern critique and analysis. More particularly, soci :. ological'theory is also open to postmodern attack on the basis of its scientism, foundati?nalism, tendency toward totalization, essentialism, and insularity. Given .l
these weaknesses, postmodem social theory is viewed by its adh native to modem sociological theory. As we will see in the next chapter, the main roots of postmo lie outside of sociological theory. However, there are some in modem social theory within sociology. For example, while there modernistic dimension to the classical theory of Georg Simmel terpreted as presaging many postmodern orientations. One can tions of postmodern social theory in the work of C. Wright M ployed the term postlnoden1 as early as 1959), but Mills is cle modernist than a postmodemist. Thus, it is outside of sociology for the main sources of postmodern social theory, and we will with those sources in the following chapter.
2 THE DEVELOPMENT
OF POSTMODERN
SOCIAL THEORY
THE ARTS AND LITERARY CRITICISM
PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOLOGY, AND PSYCHIATRY: NIETZSCHE, RORTY: AND FREUDIAN THEORY Friedrich Nietzsche Richard Rorty Siglllund Freud STRUCTURALISM AND POSTSTRUCTURALISM Sartre's Existentialism Phenomenology Structuralism Poststructuralism THE SOCIAL CONTEXT
POSTMODERN social theory is the product of an extremely diverse and com plex set of intellectual and soc;ial forces. It would require many volumes to do jus tice to that rich history. Thus, what follows is little more than a brief sketch offer ing a few glimpses of that history to orient the reader to the detailed discussions that follow in the rest of this book. It is also a highly selective sketch designed to introduce a few people and ideas with which the reader might not be familiar. Thus, for example, it will be assumed that the reader has some familiarity with the ideas ,of social theorists who played important roles, positive and negative, in the fonnation of postmodem social theory (Marx, Durkheim, and Weber). While such thinkers will not be discussed below, other figures less familiar to students of soci ology~Sontag, Venturi, Jencks, Nietzsche, Rorty, Freud, Sartre, Saussure, Levi Strauss~will be introduced to the r~ader, at least briefly. THE ARTS AND LITERARY CRITICISM
While, as we saw in the preceding chapter, there are intimations of postmodemism in sociological theory, the real roots of postmodern thinking lie in literature, archi tecture, theatre, painting, dance, and related fields. Many of the ideas developed in those fields, in interaction with the development of poststructuralism (to be dis18
cussed below), formed the base for the development of what we now modern social theory. In this section we will give a brief overview o postmodernism in the arts, relying heavily on Hans Betiens (1995), Postn1oden1 (see also Huyssen, 1990). The earliest uses of the term postlnoden~ date to the 1870s. Th its first appearance in the title of a book in 1926 and surfaced aga and 1940s. However, this early and isolated work had little in co literature on postmodernism that emerged in the 1960s. A key doc Sontag's (1964/1967) essay, "Against Interpretation," which as th viewed interpretation as stifling and oppressive. Instead of the "me from interpretations, Sontag underscored the importance of immed This essay is also noted for undercutting the distinction between hi ture. Another key figure during this period was Leslie Fiedler (1969 critic of modernism with its attendant rationalism and liberal hum that we were experiencing the death of modernity and the birth o characterized by, among other things, antirationality, romanticism tality. Fiedler also emphasized the importance of the local and triba the modernist emphasis on essential, timeless meanings. In addition to the work of such literary critics, Bertens also sees tions of postmodernism in the music of John Cage, Robert Raus lages of found objects, and the novels of Alain Robbe-Grillet, J Thomas Pynchon with their distrust of modernist ethics.O'v (1995:34) concludes: "It is remarkable how much of what is no\v the postmodern agenda was already in place by the end of the 1960s As the reader will see, this book sees poststructurali Sffi, a against modernist theory, as the most important and immediate c of postmodern social theory. However, Bertens (1955:35) argues ernist theory arises primarily as a response to contemporary artist and not, as is too often thought, to poststructuralist rereadings of th modernism." Postmodernism grew more widespread and explicit in the 1970s. this period was Inhab Hassan (1971), although his work is now vie historic importance than it is in terms of its influence on contempor thinking. There is, for example, his essay, "POSTmodernISM: A Pa ography" in which he underscores the anarchic character of postmo Hassan focuses on literature, he begins to move in the direction o larger culture, the focus of much of later postmodem social theory. tral figure during this period was William Spanos, especially his jou 2: A Journal of Posnnodern Literature and Culture. However, Span influenced by existentialism, and its foci prevented him from movi tion that was to become predominant in postmodern thinking-th guage. While existentialism privileged the human subject, the (Brown, 1990) proclaimed the end of such a subject. The more radi entation of Spanos's existential postmodemism was also not in
nihillsm of much of the postmodemism of the day. By the late 1970s Spanos and his existential brand of postmodernism had been marginalized. Turning from literary criticism to the field of architecture, Robert Venturi played a key role during the 1960s and 1970s, especially in Complexity and Con tradiction in Architecture (1966) and Learning from Las Vegas (1972), co-au thored with Denise Scott Brown and Steven Izenour. In fact, on receiving the pres tigious 1991 Pritzker Architecture Prize, Venturi was" 'generally acknowledged to have .diverted the mainstream of architecture away from Modernism'" (Bertens, 1995:53). Among other things, Venturi emphasized messiness, complex and contradictory architecture, a both/and rather than an either/or orientation, the impoliance of an architecture that learns from popular culture and art, the fact that there is not just one but rather multiple languages in architecture, and furthermore that architecture should not be isolated from the other "languages" extant in the environment. In the mid-1970s, Charles Jencks embarked on a body of work (including "The Rise of Post-Modern Architecture" [Jencks, 1975] and The Language of Post Modern Architecture [Jencks, 1977]) that led him to become "the acknowledged guru of Post-Modernism" (Bertens, 1995:57). Among other things, Jencks is known for the idea of "double coding," that is, for example, retaining architec ture's elitism and complementing it with the vernacular. Thus, he did not argue for dropping modernistic elements (produced by the field's elites) but rather for ex tending them to embrace elements not ordinarily included (such as the vernacu lar). In line with this, Jencks argued for the retention of architecture's representa tionalism (a view soon to be rejected by postmodemists); in fact, in his view architecture should be a kind of language that represents the tensions of everyday life. } encks also anticipated the poststructuralist orientation, at least to some de gree~ by adopting a semiotic view of architecture: seeing architecture as a kind of language. According to Bertens (1995:62), Jencks's perspective encompasses dou ble coding emphasizing plural meanings, the active involvement and participation of the viewer, and a complex mix of representations, ornaments, historical refer ence, symbolism, and hurnor. In the late 1970s, Bertens argued that the center of postmodern developments shifted from the literary field (and architecture) to a variety of other arts including photography, landscape sculpture, and sculpture. However, these developments strongly reflect the theoretical developments to be discussed below and in later chapters, that is, poststructuralism and the work of thinkers like Jacques Derrida, Roland Barthes, and Michel Poucault. Among other things, this means that the focus shifted to signs and their interrelationship rather than the material reality that they were supposed to represent. Involved here is a full-scale assault on the idea of art (and more generally culture) as representing reality; reality comes to be seen as unrepresentable, and signs are viewed as existing free of the real world. Thus, in photography, Douglas Crimp took the position that representation has always been an illusion since experience is inevitably mediated by language, and thus always coded ... all visual perception is coded in one way or the
other, that there is nothing outside precoded representation, that art is th copy of a copy, and that there is no subject in the traditional sense of the
(Berte
A striking example of this rejection of representing reality is Sherrie tographs, presented by her as her own, of canonical photographs by ies of the world of photography as Walker Evans. Then there is R rephotographing of advertising images as they appear in glossy mag In addition to their rejection of representationalism, such works ber of basic tenets of postmodernism. For example, they undermin ideas as originality and authenticity; they stand for such postmode propriation and hybridization. Perhaps most importantly, such phot sents the postmodern refusal of authorship-who is the photographe Sherrie Levine's photographs? Clearly, it is difficult to identify the a tographer in such cases. These attacks on authorship, origins, and representation also imp the traditional practices of art history as well as on the ways in w traditionally operate. This is related to a flowering of a more politi postmodernism in the late 1970s and early 1980s. These politically velopments offered a way out of the impasses-radical relativism that had been created by poststructuralism. For example, feminist authorship to patriarchy (after all, most canonical authors were mal ing and contesting authorship, postmodern feminists are in fact also triarchy (see Chapter 9). Another example is the more Marxian who attacked capitalistic control over art and culture. For exalnp artist Hans Hacke is designed to sho10.T the relationship between a general and, more specifically, of the power of museums and corpo collectors of art (Jameson, 1991). Work in the literature and arts that relates to postmodernism c day, and it continues to evolve. As Bertens (1995: 107) concludes, has never stayed long in one particular place." However,. we need cussion, as in fact Bertens does in his own work, to other, more th opments and the role they played in the emergence of postmodern PHILOSOPHY, PSYCHOLOGY, AND PSYCHIATRY: NIETZSCHE,
RORTY, AND FREUDIAN THEORY
Other fields, especially philosophy, psychology, and psychiatry, out of this account of the emergence of postmodem social theory ously impossible to detail the diversity of their inputs in this intro Thus, we will focus in this section on the work of a classical philos Nietzsche, who has had a powelful ilnpact on postmodem social t on that of a particularly important contemporary philosopher" Rich cially his book Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1979). In a offer a few of the basic premises of Freudian theory.
Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche (1992; 1887/1974) is a philosopher whose significance to soci ological, and even social, theory has never received the attention it deserves. How ever, that has changed because of, at least in part, the centrality of many of his ideas to both poststructuralism (Derrida and Foucault, for example) and postmod ernism (B audrillard, for one). It is difficult to summarize his contributions to these perspectives because "His fragmented, contradictory, and 'open' texts welcome di verse interpretations, selective appropriations, and disjunctive fusions" (Antonio, 1995:5). However, Robert 1. Antonio (1995; see also Zeitlin, 1994) has recently summarized not only Nietzsche's socially relevant ideas but also his impact on pbststructuralistn and postmodernism. Antonio'smost basic point is that in contrast to most of the classical sociologi cal theories of modernity, Nietzsche offers an "antisociology" in which he sees decadence, exhaustion, and regimentation where the classical theorists saw progress in the form of greater enlightenment and freedom. It is also an antisociol ogy in another sense-it is presented in a chaotic, aphoristic form rather than the systematic grand narratives produced by the modernists. Nietzsche takes on two of the most basic assumptions of modem social theory in his rejection of a focus on the "rational subject." First, this means that he rejects the emphasis on, and the positive evaluation of, reason, rationality, and the ratio nalization process. Instead, Nietzsche praises nonrational and irrational forces and blames the process of rationalization for having a stultifying effect on these im pulses. Second, this is linked to Nietzsche's rejection of the modern focus on sub jectivity, the soul, and the mind. Instead, Nietzsche concentrates on the body, phys iology, and so on. The nonrational impulses controlled and repressed by the rational society are derived from the body. In his view, these forces should be per mitted expression, although in a spiritualized way. A key concept in Nietzsche's work is ressentilnent, defined by Antonio (1995:7) as "the inclination of the weak to make their suffering meaningful by blaming oth ers and taking 'imaginary revenge'." The main objects of their blame, as well as the objects of control by the larger society, are those who are strong; those whose impulses have not been inhibited and domesticated. As a result of the subordina tion of such strong individuals, the world has come to be dominated by slaves and their morality rather than by the strong. In Nietzsche's view, Socrates, Catholi cism, Protestantism, and the Enlightenment all contributed to the slave morality and even helped to diffuse it more widely. Those who are imbued with the slave mentality are prone to uncertainty and therefore to desperate measures and fanatic prejudices. These forces have not only served to weaken strong individuals but also the larger culture. The state comes to regiment culture and to be the locus of ressenti ment. Nietzsche did not see a socialist revolution as the solution to this problem; in fact, he felt that it would only serve to amplify it. Despite his opposition to socialism, Nietzsche was no advocate of capitalism, which he saw as working against both cultural advancement and strong individuals. Those who participate in the capitalist economy are reduced to "industrious ants" while the capitalist
state is staffed by "the flies of the marketplace" (cited in Antonio, thermore, the "egalitarianism" that accompanies capitalism serves t thing to the lowest common denominator, thereby contributing to th culture. In the end, the particularities of individuals and cultures and leveled. Obviously, Nietzsche prizes those who have escaped these op those he calls "sovereign" individuals. These are unique individua the basis of their bodily intelligence and their vital instincts rather t totally to roles and to the expectations associated with them. Thro tion and self-mastery, they are able to avoid the homogenizing force Nietzsche tended to privilege culture and its "will to deceptio and its "will to truth." Science is associated with rationality and as culture is linked to irrationality and uninhibited play. Culture and a lated to greater freedom, more individuality, greater exuberance" a Nietzsche favors a world in which culture is dominant and the lea ture will be his sovereign individuals who have "the required stre and lack of inhibitions ... capable of resisting rampant demagogue toadyism, and coercion" (Antonio, 1995:20). Yet, these leaders had avoid excessive moralism and developing an obsession with contro Antonio demonstrates that Nietzsche's complex and often con have been significant to the development of modem social th Weber), to left-wing thinkers, to right-wing theorists, and to post the latter that is of greatest interest to us in this book, and Antonio rizes Nietzsche's impact on the thinking of several thinkers who w in depth in this book-Foucault and his "fundamental Nietzschean ple, his focus on the diffusion of power; the "micro-physics" of (for example, his attack on cultural homogenization and celebratio and Baudrillard (his focus on simulation, for example). More gene
Nietzschean themes are pervasive; postmodemists usually favor innov cordant, aesthetic styles of expression over conventional representa over objectivist theories of knowledge, and nonrational over rational Nietzschean motifs are prominent in their arguments about the role o tural domination, critiques of the therapeutic state, affirmations of m ences, and claims about problematic presuppositions, unexplored ar ized voices in social theory. Also, their playful attacks on mor positivism, parochial cultural biases, and intellectual canons have a N
(
However, that is not to say that there are not important diff Nietzsche and postmodern social theory. For one thing, many po tain a left-leaning, egalitarian, pluralist perspective. Second, th tivism sometimes mirrors that of liberal modernism critiqued by postmodernists tend to ignore his argument for new forms of auth domination. Finally, Nietzsche' s call for sovereign individuals is subject disappears into a postmodern world of signs.
While he subordinated science to culture, Nietzsche accorded importance to the will to truth, especially the willingness to see reality as it really is, "in all its multi plicity' chaotic uncertainty, and harshness, whatever the costs" (Antonio, 1995: 19). Thus, for the sovereign individual "passionate vision and disciplined truthfulness are both needed to face 'open seas' and great tasks" (Antonio, 1995:19).
Richard Rorty
Rarty began Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature with a brief overview of West ern philosophy from the seventeenth through the nineteenth century. Several domi nant ideas emerged during this period such as a focus on the human as the knower involved in the process of representing the world; a view of philosophy "as a tri bunal of pure reason, upholding or denying the claims of the rest of culture"; and "as a foundational discipline which 'grounds' knowledge claims" (Rorty, 1979:4). Over the years philosophy grew more and more rigorous, scientific, and self-con tained. In the process, it came to have less and less to do with all other cultural phenomena. In the twentieth century a number of philosophers, especially Ludwig Wittgen stein, Martin Heidegger,l and John Dewey, came to question this philosophical ori entation and to seek a new way of making philosophy foundational. Especially im portant to Rorty (1979:6) is the fact that, in his view, these thinkers were "in agreement that the notion of knowledge as accurate representation, made possible by special mental processes, and intelligible through a general theory of represen tation, needs to be abandoned." Given their lead, Rorty (1979:390) adopts the view that what is needed is to deconstruct the theory of representation, or in his terms, "deconstruct the image of the Mirror of Nature." More specifically, what Rorty cri tiques' and seeks to develop an alternative to, is the following philosophical orien tation: The picture which holds traditional philosophy captive is that of the mind as a great mir ror, containing various representations-some accurate, some not-and capable of being studied by pure, nonempirical methods. Without the notion of mind as mirror, the notion of knowledge -as accuracy of representation would not have suggested itself ... The story of the domination of the mind of the West by ocular metaphors. (Rorty, 1979: 12-13)
Ratty is not only opposed to a philosophy that accords center stage to representa tion, but he also attacks the ideas that philosophy should be some sort of ultimate tribunal and that it should be a foundational discipline (for a critique of this, see Norris, 1985). Rorty associates the ideas to which he is opposed with what he calls systematic philosophies. In addition to the ideas rejected above, systematic philosophies in volve a belief in the human subject as the knower of essences and the search for a single, all-encompassing vocabulary. Instead of systematic philosophies, Rorty is 1 Wittgenstein
and Heidegger are also of more direct importance to postmodem social theory.
an advocate of edifying philosophies (e.g., Dewey, Heidegger), wh cious of all the pretensions of systematic philosophy. Rorty offers a trasts between the two philosophies and in the process gives us a sen means by an edifying philosophy:
Great edifying philosophies are reactive and offer satires, parodies, a know their work loses its point when the period they were reacting again are intentionally peripheral. Great systematic philosophies, like great scie eternity. Great edifying philosophies destroy for the sake of their own g tematic philosophers want to put their subject on the secure path of sc philosophers want to keep space open for the sense of wonder which p times cause ... something which (at least for the moment) cannot be ex barely be described.
(Rorty,.
Clearly, an edifying philosophy is a far humbler undertaking th philosophy. It not only condemns the idea of having an idea,. but i avoid taking a position about having views, that is, it is a "nonepiste of philosophy" (Rorty, 1979:381). It does not favor the road taken its research programs because, in its view, there is no one right way reality. (Science is roundly attacked by Rorty (1979:384-385], "S program to put philosophy on the secure path of science succeeds, verts philosophy into a boring academic specialty.") The goal is n truth as it is in systematic philosophy (and science), but merely to co versation. In contrast, science seeks to close off conversation by find Lacking final answers, or the truth, edifying philosophies continue t descriptions and to strive toward the truth, a truth that is ever elusiv tained. As Rorty (1979:373) puts it, "edifying philosophy aims at co versation rather than at discovering truth." What is needed to keep t going is unconstrained discourse, undertaken at a leisurely pace. course that is most apt to generate abnormal discourse, that is, new i of edifying philosophy is not to find facts or the tluth but to keep t going, and it is through such continual conversations that new insigh tives are generated. Thus, edifying philosophy is distant from scien off such conversations, and is closer to poetry, novels, and most imp purposes, postmodern social theory. Edification, for ROlty (1979:36 of finding new, better, more interesting, more fluitful ways of speak
Sigmund Freud
Many poststructuralists and postmodernists sought to go beyond creator of psychoanalysis, Sigmund Freud. It is therefore useful to troduction to at least a few of Freud's ideas that were to prove relev or a negative sense in the development of poststructuralism and pos In some sense Freud was a structuralist tracing surface-leve problems to unconscious processes. Take, for example, the Oedipus mordial conflict that must be resolved adequately by the child or e
to produce psychological problems later in life (for a postmodem interpretation of this idea, see the discussion of the work of Deleuze and Guattari in Chapter 7). Freud believed that the four-to-five-year-old male child (the female child is in volved in a different dynamic) desires his mother and, as a result, is jealous of, and aggressive toward, hIs father, who possesses his mother. However, the child fears his father, especially being castrated by him. The resolution of this conflict lies in the child's internalization of the figure of the father, thereby reducing his anxiety. However, if the conflict is not resolved adequately, it represents a deep underlying problelTI that causes psychological problems in adulthood. To take one other example, Freud's structuralism is also reflected in his views on things like slips of the tongue and dreams. The meaning of such phenomena does not lie in what is manifest in them but rather in the fact that they are the ex pression of things that have been repressed by people. Thus, the psychoanalyst n1ust look beneath the surface to discover the underlying, and most important, real ities. The logic of the psychoanalyst is, for example, that speakers derive pleasure from slips of the tongue. The latter allow for the release of repressed ideas, but in the process they also serve to disrupt the manifest meaning of what is being said. Thus, the words uttered in slips of the tongue must be interpreted as symptoms of an underlying but unconscious reality. Some poststructuralists and postmodemists sought to distance themselves from this kind of thinking-for example, Freud's differentiation between pure human needs and actual desires. Baudrillard questioned this distinction as well as what he considered the fallacious idea that pure needs could be separated from desires. More generally, Foucault saw psychoanalysis (and many other "human sciences") as inyolved in a process of seeking to extend its knowledge of people to enhance its power over them. Freud produced a theory that was in many ways very modern. He believed that there were essential hluTIan characteristics. He adhered, for the most part, to a de terministic, scientific, positivistic perspective. And, in various ways, he adopted a totalistic view of childhood development, of societal repression of human needs and desires, and of the need for patients to solve their problems by talking them through with psychiatrists and allowing expression of their repressed needs, de sires, and experiences. Postmodernists are, of course, strongly opposed to such to talizations as being repressive, even terroristic. However, Freud's theories were, as we will see, instrumental in the development of poststructuralism, and many of the themes of postnl0dernism can be found in Freud's work. Among the ideas developed by Freud that were to prove relevant to postlnodernists were the views that modem society failed to fulfill its promises, that it is impossible to offer an undistorted representation of reality, that the mar ginal (e.g., dreams, slips of the tongue) are of central importance, and that the process of arriving at a "true" interpretation leads only to other interpretations. STRUCTURALISM AND POSTSTRUCTURALISM
Following Lash (1991:ix; see also Kurzweil, 1986), we take "the structuralism that swept through French social thought in the 1960s" as the proximate starting point
for the emergence of poststructuralism and postmodernism. Stluctu was a reaction against humanism, especially the existentialism of ph novelist Jean-Paul Satire, as well as phenomenology.
Sartre's Existentialism
In his early work, Sartre focused on the individual level, especially freedom. He adhered to the view that people are not subject to,. or d any social laws. In other words, man "cannot justify his actions b anything outside himself' (Craib, 1976:4).2 In Being and Nothingness, Sartre (1943) focuses on the free takes the view that "existence is defined by and through one's acts . one does" (Hayim, 1980:3). At the same time, Sartre attacks the soc of "objective structures as completely deterministic of behavior" (H For Salire, people are free; they are responsible for everything they no excuses if they do wrong. In some senses, these "staggering res freedom" are a tremendous source of anguish to people (Hayim, 19 senses, this can be a source of optimism-people hold their fate hands. In his later work-for exalnple, Critique of Dialectical (1963) devotes more attention to social structures,. but even here "the hUlnan prerogative for transcendence-the surpassing of the 1980: 16). In this, Satire is critical of various Marxists who overem and power of social structure. "Dogmatic Marxists have, in Sartr nated the humanistic component of Mal'x's original idea" (Hayim, was ultimately an existentialist, and as such he always retained th felt some Marxists had lost. It is against this kind of humanisn1, especially as it was manifes Sartre, who was one of the towering figures of French social thou that poststructuralists and postmodernists rebelled.3 They sought t cial thought, to move it away from a focus 011 "man" and toward o especially language.
Phenomenology
The leading phenomenologist, Edmund Husserl,4 was interested study of the basic stluctures of human consciousness. He was com trating the various layers constructed by actors in the real world to tial structure of consciousness. However, this is not easy to do si are always engaged in the active and highly complex process
2 Later in his career~ Satire was drawn more to Marxian theory, but he sought existentialism with his later Marxian approach by focusing on the ':free individu sive and oppressive social structure which lilnits and alienates his activities" (
added). 3 McBride (1991) argues that Satire anticipated Inany postmodernist ideas. 4 Husserl had great influence on Denida, among others.
world, they are most often unaware that they are ordering the world; hence, they do not question it. To Husserl, this is the general thesis of the "natural standpoint." To actors, the social world is naturally ordered, not ordered by them. Thus, the natural standpoint, or the "natural attitude," is an obstacle to the discovery of intentional
processes. Once the natural attitude is disconnected, or bracketed, the phenomenologist can begin to examine the invariant properties of consciousness (Schutz, 1973: 103). The phenomenologist must also set aside the incidental experiences of life that tend to dominate consciousness. Husserl's ultimate objective was to look beneath all the layers to see the basic properties of the "transcendental ego" in all its purity. Another way to put this is that Husserl was interested in the pure form of con sciousness stripped of all biographical and cultural content. The idea of the transcendental ego reflects Husserl's interest in the basic and in variant properties of human consciousness. Although he is often misinterpreted on this point, he did not have a mentalistic, metaphysical conception of conscious ness," For him, it was not a thing or a place but a process. Consciousness was found not inthe head of the actor but in the relationship between the actor and the objects in the world. Husserl expressed this in his notion of intentionality. -Por him, con sciousness is always consciousness of something, some object. Consciousness is found in this relationship: consciousness is not interior to the actor; it is relational. Furthermore, meaning does not inhere in consciousness or in objects but in the re lationship of actors to objects. This conception of consciousness as a process that gives meaning to objects is at the heart of phenomenology. Many of the characteristics of Husserlian phenomenology-its humanism, its focus on the subject, its essentialism (the transcendental ego)-came under attack by both structuralists and poststructuralists.
Structuralism At its most general level, structuralism can be defined as the effort to uncover the general structures that underly human activity. From this point of view, a structure may be defined as a unit composed of a few elements that are invariably found in the same relationship within the "activity" being described. The unit cannot be broken down into its single ele Inents, for the unity of the structure is defined not so much by the substantive nature of the elements as by their relationship. (Spivak, 1974:lv)
In addition to this concern for systems and relationships, structuralism is also char acterized by its search for the general laws that serve to define such structures. The structures of concern to structuralism are not in the main the same struc tures that have been of traditional concern to sociologists (such as those who adopt a structural-functional orientation). While the latter, indeed most sociologists, are concerned with social structures (e.g., social class, bureaucracies), what is of pri-
mary concern to structuralists are linguistic structures (or social structu
be interpreted as languages). This shift from social to linguistic structur what has come to be known as the linguistic turn, vihich dramatically nature of the social sciences (Lash, 1991:ix). The focus of a good man entists shifted from social structure (and froin individual human bei guage,5 or more generally to signs of various sorts (Gottdiener, 1995). Structuralism emerged from diverse developments in various fie source of modem structuralism and its strongest bastion to this day i The work of Ferdinand de Saussure (1857-1913) stands out in the dev structural linguistics and, ultimately, in various other fields (Saus Culler, 1976). Of particular interest is Saussure's differentiation bet and parole, a distinction which was to have enormous significance to ment of not only structuralism but also poststructuralism and pos Langue is the formal, grammatical system of language. It is a system ements whose relationships are governed, Saussure and his followers determinate laws. Much of linguistics since Saussure's time has bee the discovery of those laws. The existence of langue makes parole pos is actual speech, the way that speakers on a day-to-day basis use lan press themselves. Although Saussure recognized the significance of pe language in subjective and often idiosyncratic ways, he believed that day usage cannot be the concern of the scientifically oriented linguis guist must focus on langue, the formal system of language, not on t ways in which it is used by actors. Langue, then, can be viewed as a system of signs. A sign can whole, a structure that is composed of a signifier-the sound image t ent hears when a word is spoken, and a signified-what the sound im indicate: the meaning of the word that is called forth in the mind of Saussure was interested not only in the signifier and the signified bu relationship to one another. Somewhat surprisingly, at least from point of view, Saussure was little interested in the referent, the thing to, because it was extra-linguistic (Genosko, 1994).6 To Saussure, language is "a closed system in which all parts are (Marks and de Courtivron, 1981:3). Especially important are relat ence, including binary oppositions. Thus, for example, the meanin hot comes not from some intrinsic property of the "real" world word's relationship with, its binary opposition to, the word cold. mind, and ultimately the social world are shaped by the structure Thus, instead of an existential world of people shaping their sur have here a world in which people, as well as other aspects of the are being shaped by the structure of language and its code, or the for combining words.
5 See, for example, Habermas's work on communication or the conversational ethnomethodologists. 6 However, the term discourse often came to be used for "the relation between object to which it apparently refers" (Marks and de Courtivron, 1981:3).
Language came to serve as a model for all aspects of human life. In addition, the concern for structure was extended by Saussure, and more importantly by a range of other thinkers, beyond language to the study of all sign systems. This focus on the structure of sign systems has been labeled "semiotics" and has at tracted many followers (Eco, 1976; Hawkes, 1977; Gottdiener, 1995). Semiotics is broader than structural linguistics because it encompasses not only language but also other sign and symbol systems, such as facial expressions, body language, all forms of communication, and indeed all elements of culture. Roland Barthes (1964/1967; 1970/1982) is often seen as the true founder of semiotics. Barthes's greatest significance, from the point of view of this discus sion, waS to extend Saussure's ideas to all areas of social life. As Barthes put it, Semiology ... aims to take in any system of signs, whatever their substance and limits; images, gestures, musical sounds, objects, and the complex associations of all of these, which form the content of ritual, convention or public entertainment: these constitute, if not languages, at least systems of signification.
(Batthes, 1964/1967:9) Or, in more prosaic terms, "Not just language, but wrestling matches are also sig nifying practices, as are TV shows, fashions, cooking and just about everything else in everyday life" (Lash, 1991 :xi). The "linguistic turn" came to encompass all social phenomena, which are now reinterpreted as signs. Another central figure in French structuralism, indeed Kurzweil (1980:13) calIs him "the father of structuralism," is the French anthropologist Claude Levi Strauss. Levi-Strauss extended Saussure's work on language to anthropological is sues-':"for example, to myths in primitive societies. This helped to open the door to the broader application of structuralism to all forms of communication. His major innovation was to reconceptualize a wide array of social phenomena (for instance, kinship. systems) as systems of communication and thereby make them amenable to structural analyses (Burris, 1979; Levin, 1981:25). The exchange 'of spouses, for example, can be analyzed in the same way as the exchange of words. Both are so cial exchanges that can be studied through the use of structural anthropology. We can iIlustrate Levi-Strauss's (1967) thinking with the example of the simi larities between linguistic systems and kinship systems. First, to the structural an thropologist, terms used to describe kinship, like phonemes in language, are basic units of analysis. Second, neither the kinship terms nor the phonemes have mean ing in themselves. Instead, like Saussure's langue, both acquire meaning only when they are integral parts of a larger system. Levi-Strauss even used a system of binary oppositions in his anthropology (e.g., the raw and the cooked) much like those employed by Saussure in linguistics. Third, Levi-Strauss recognized that there is empirical variation from setting to setting in both phonemic and kinship systems, but he argued that even these variations can be traced to the operation of general, although implicit, laws. AIl of this is very much in line with the linguistic turn, but Levi-Strauss ulti mately went off in a number of directions that are at odds with that turn. Most im portant, he argued that both phonemic systems and kinship systems are the prod-
ucts of the structures of the mind. However, they are not the produ scious process. Instead, they are the products of the unconscious, lo of the mind. These systems, as well as the logical structure of the min they are derived, operate on the basis of general laws. Most of th been part of the linguistic turn have not followed Levi-Strauss in th defining the underlying structure of the mind as the most fundamenta Another variant of structuralism that enjoyed considerable succ (and many other parts of the world) was structural Marxism, especial Louis Althusser, Nicos Poulantzas, and Maurice Godelier. Although the case that modem structuralism began with Saussure's work in lin are those who argue that it started with the work of Karl Marx: "W sumes that structure is not to be confused with visible relations and hidden logic, he inaugurates the modern structuralist traditio 1972b:336). Although structural Marxism and structuralism in gener terested in "structures," they conceptualize structure differently. At least some Marxists share with structuralists an interest in the ture as a prerequisite to the study of history. As Maurice Godelier sa of the internal functioning of a stlucture must precede and .illumina its genesis and evolution" (1972b:343). In another work" Godelie said, "The inner logic of these systems must be analyzed before their alyzed." Another view shared by structuralists and structural Marxist turalism should be concerned with the structures, or systems, that a of the interplay of social relations. Both schools see structures as real ble), although they differ markedly on the nature of the structures sider real. For Levi-Strauss the real structure is the model" or perh whereas for structural Marxists it is the underlying structure of societ Perhaps most importantly, both structuralism and structural Marx piricism and accept a concern for underlying" invisible structu (1972a:xvii) argued: "What both structuralists and Marxists reject a cist definitions of what constitutes a social structure." Godelier a statement:
For Marx as for Levi-Strauss a structure is not a reality that is directly vi rectly observable, but a level of reality that exists beyond the visible re men, and the functioning of which constitutes the underlying logic of subjacent order by which the apparent order is to be explained.
(Gode
Godelier (1972a:xxiv) went even further and argued that such a purs science: "What is visible is a reality concealing anothel; deeper re hidden and the discovery of which is the very purpose of scientific co Despite these similarities, structural Marxism did not in the main the linguistic turn then taking place in the social sciences. For exam concern continued to be social and economic, not linguistic, structur 7
A concern for origins came to be rejected by postmodemists.
structural Marxism continued to be associated with Marxian theory, and many French social thinkers were becoming at least as impatient with Marxian theory as they were with existentialism. Poststructuralism
Structuralisms of various types came to dominate social thought, especially in France.. However, there soon developed a reaction against structuralism that came to be labeled poststructuralism. We can define poststructuralism as a school of thought that builds upon (Kroker and Levin, 1991), but seeks to distance itself from, the structuralism associated with thinkers like Ferdinand Saussure, Roland Barthes,iClaude Levi-Strauss, Louis Althusser, and so on. Of course, the poststruc turalists Were also shaped in a positive, but especiaIly a negative, sense by many of the theories discussed above-especialIy existentialism, phenomenology, and Freucliantheory (as well as Marxism). Poststructuralism is an extremely broad and amorphous school of thought. For example" it encompasses the work of a mainstream sociological theorist,8 Pierre Bourdieu (1977, 1984), as well as a thinker, Michel Foucault, who is decidedly outside the mainstremTI. Thus, while Bourdieu's work was dealt with in Modern Sociological. Theory (Ritzer, 1996c), Foucault's work will be discussed in this book on postmodern social theory. This leads to the issue: What is the difference between poststructuralism and postmodernism? In general, poststructuralism is treat~d as an intellectual precursor of postmodernism (Bertens, 1995); it is one of the strands of thought that fed into the development of postmodern social theory. In fact, it is the most important theoretical source of postmodern social theory. Certainly, the poststructuralist who we will deal with in depth in this book, Michel Foucault, played a key role, positive and negative (see Baudrillard's [1977] Ou blier Foucault ["Forget Foucault"], for example), in the formation of postmod emism. However, in many senses, as we will see in Chapters 3 and 4, Foucault can also be considered a postmodemist (Best, 1994). Thus, there is a flexible, quite porous, line separating poststructuralism and postmodemism. In fact, in the spirit of postmodernism, we will refuse to draw the line, especially in the rich and di verse work of someone like Foucault. One general distinction (with many exceptions) is that poststructuralism tends to be more abstract, more philosophical, and less political, than postmodemism. The work of J acques Derrida (1930- ), which will be discussed in more detail in Chapter 7, is a good example of poststructural thinking even though he, too, is sometimes thought of as a postmodemist. The latter is the case because, among other things, even in his highly theoretical musings he sees us undergoing a transi tion from the modern way of thinking to a mode of thought that is beyond modern (Derrida, 1967/1974:87). However; we can use Derrida here to illustrate what we mean by poststructural ism. A good starting point is Spivak's (1974:lvii) discussion of "Derrida's criticism 8
For a view of Bourdieu as more of a postmodernist, see Harrison (1993).
of 'structuralism,' even as he inhabits it." Thus, the poststructuralists embedded in structuralism at the same time that they are trying to d selves from it. To take a specific example, Derrida bases his thinking work on speech at the same time that he critiques Saussure for subo excluding that which was to become of central concern to Derrida-w led Derrida to the creation of a field, "grammatology," or the theoreti writing. While Derrida (1967/1974:42) critiques and moves beyond acknowledges the fact that .it is Saussure who made the field of gramm sible. It is the embeddedness in structuralism, as well as the simultan and movement beyond it, that defines poststructuralism. Another important body of poststructural work includes that of th choanalyst, J acques Lacan (1901- ), as well as the contributions of disciples, and sometime later clitics, especially Julia Kristeva, Luce Helene Cixous. Lacan, of course, was building upon Freudian theory ing it with other ideas, most notably from our point of view, Saussuri Thus, Lacan is noted for statements such as "the unconscious is str language" (in Kurzweil, 1995:98).While psychoanalysts privileged b argued that language and culture were central to the unconscious. M the individual was seen as being formed in language. Further, langu to the psychoanalytic session. To Lacan, language always operates on two planes. The task of p is to look for the cause of defective communication. It is the uncons language, that is the cause of defects in interpersonal communicatio structural regularity to these disruptions that makes them amenable and therapy. It is this kind of structural regularity that led Lacan to that it would be possible to mathematize psychoanalysis. Lacan's ideas were of great influence in a number of fields, includ Many of his disciples, especially Kristeva, Irigaray, and Cixous, have ful impact of their own. In Chapter 9 we will touch on the relatio ideas to American feminist postmodern theory. However, they also m tions to structural analysis. For example, Kristeva created "semanaly concerned not only with the communicative factors in language but material factors as its sounds, rhythms, and graphability. She also em importance of poetic language, which defies formalization. In link and psychoanalysis, Kristeva saw as paradigmatic the accepting, lo ship between analyst and patient. For her part, Irigaray argued, for schizophrenia has a language of its own and that its delirium is subj tive linguistic rules, even if they are often broken in practice. Poststructuralism provides the immediate background to, and in indistinguishable from, postmodern social theory. Most of the think cussed in this book were influenced by structuralism but sought to d selves from it. Once in place, poststructuralism itself had an impact o a majority of the theorists covered here. Given this background on 9 We
will explain what Derrida means by writing in Chapter 8.
and poststructuralisffi, indeed the background provided in these first two chapters, we are now ready to deal with postmodern social theory. However, before we do, there is one final issue that we need to cover. THE SOCIAL CONTEXT
Up to this point we have, in the main, focused on ideas-structural, poststructural, postlnodern, and so on. However, these ideas did not emerge in a social and intel lectual vacuum. In this section we need to survey at least a few of the contextual factors involved in the theoretical developments of concern to us here. To keep the discussion manageable, we will focus largely on France, since it is clear that it was the center of the theoretical developments of concern to us in this book. During and immediately after World War il, French intellectual life was domi nated by Marxian theory. However, as many intellectuals began to grow disillu sioned with Soviet-style communism, they became attracted to Sartre's existential ism, especially the promise of individual fulfillment in the modern world. But S~lftre's ideas began to lose favor because he continued to support the communists despite a growing recognition of the repressiveness of the Soviet Union. In their search for an alternative theoretical perspective, some scholars were drawn to structuralism, which permitted them to remain socialists while giving their work a non-Marxist theoretical underpinning. Structuralism also appealed to those who wanted to develop a science of human subjects. . The radical student revolution of 1968 was a watershed in French intellectual developlnent. The failure of that revolution, and the subsequent disbanding of stu dent groups, led to increasing disillusionment with Marxism and, more generally, to the abandonment of any hope of a grand revolutionary solution to society's problelTIs. Those feelings increased in the next few decades as communism pro gressively unraveled and then collapsed completely in the Soviet Union and else where. In France, the election of a socialist president, Fran~ois Mitterand, failed to bring with it the promised reforms. The social democracies throughout Europe that had instituted a variety of well-funded welfare programs began to discover that they could no longer afford such programs. All of these failures brought with them the sense that the old hopes for a grand solution had been illusory. In fact, as the excesses of the Soviet Union came to light, they pointed, as had the Nazi Holo caust, to the fact that such grand solutions could just as easily bring terror as hope. A wide range of other social changes made it clear that the old theoretical tools no longer sufficed; new theoretical ideas and perspectives were needed. The map of the world was being redrawn as colonial empires were dismantled, decolonial ism proceeded apace, and many new and independent nations came into existence. Led by the feminists, a variety of new social movements arose, and many new voices were being heard within France and throughout the world. These groups were clamoring for greater power over their lives as well as in the societies in which they lived. The economies of the advanced nations, including France, were growing, but poverty and other social ills showed no signs of disappearing. Furthermore, those economies were changing with many industries both retrenching and restructuring.
The result was that many people were out of work who never expect employed, and many more faced uncertain or disrupted careers. Overa omy was moving from the dominance of Fordist production jobs to service-type occupations. Furthermore, the emphasis seemed to be less tion and more on consumption; we were witnessing the emergence sumer society." Key to the consumer society was the growing importance of the mas pecially television. The latter not only serves to advertise all of the a consumer society, but it bombards people with a wide array of imag dramatically altered their lives. Television brought with it an explosion tion, albeit often in the form of infotainment. More generally, infor nologies grew and then exploded with the wide-scale availability of ho ers. Seemingly free-floating images, stemming from the telev computer, and elsewhere, were increasingly omnipresent and exerting tion for, and power over, people. We obviously cannot deal with anything approaching the full ran changes that affected the theoretical developments of concern to us he to say that there are many of them and that they profoundly shaped th and development of poststructural and especially postmodern thought.
SUMMARY
The roots of postmodem social theory lie in the arts and literary crit postmodemism developed in many different fields, some of the mo work, at least from the point of view of the development of postmode ory, took place in architecture, especially the ideas of Venturi and Jenc ernism remains a poweliul force in art and literary criticism today, b inputs into contemporary postmodern social theory are to be found els Three important thinkers in the development of postmodern soci the philosophers Friedrich Nietzsche and Richard Rorty and the p Sigmund Freud. Nietzsche has emerged as the dominant philosophi postmodem social theory. Theorists associated with the latter are dra aspects of his approach including the aphoristic, unsystematic cha work, his rejection of reason and rationality, his focus on ressentimen in the relationship between power and truth, and so on. There are imp ences between Nietzsche and postmodern social theorists, but the latt heavily on his work not only for their ideas but even for their style of Rorty's impact is traceable largely to his rejection of systematic philo acceptance of edifying philosophy, in which the goal is not to find th merely to keep the scientific conversation going. Freud also had a pr on postmodem social theory but more because that theory sought to from both Freud's modem grand narrative as well as many of his spec The humanism of Sartre's existentialism and Husserl's phenomeno a backdrop for the development of structuralism. Of particular impo latter is the work of the linguist Ferdinand de Saussure. His distinct
langue and parole, and signifier and signified, as well as his thoughts on binary op positions were to have a profound effect on both poststructuralism and postmod ernism. Roland Barthes is important for extending Saussure's ideas on language to the study of signs in general (semiotics). Levi-Strauss applied these ideas to his an thropological work, demonstrating that social behavior can be analyzed in much the! same way as language-another variant of structuralism built on the more structural ideas of Karl Marx. Poststructuralism may be seen as a school of thought that builds upon, but goes beyond, .structuralism. A good example is Derrida's effort to go beyond speech to focus on "writing." Lacan built upon structuralist ideas but sought to integrate them with the psychoanalytic perspective of Freud and others. Poststructuralism provides the immediate background for postmodem social theory and is, in many ways, indistinguishable from it. Many of the thinkers to be discussed in this book as posttriodem social theorists are also often labeled "poststructuralists." The chapter closes with some thoughts on the social changes that were impor tant in the development of poststructuralism and postmodernism.
MICHEL FOUC PART 1: ARCHAEOLO KNOWLEDGE; GENEA OF P ARCHAEOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE GENEALOGY OF POWER MADNESS AND CNILIZATION
THE BIRTH OF THE CLINIC DISCIPLINE AND PUNISH
MICHEL FOUCAULT'S work is dealt with in detail in this boo pending on one's perspective, it can be seen as either a forerunner to example of, postmodern social theory. In either case, subsequent po rizing has been powerfully affected by Foucault's thinking. Foucault offers a wide-ranging body of work that will require t cover adequately. In this chapter we deal with his methodological cault, 1969, 1971/1976) as well as specific empirical studies of th human sciences (Foucault, 1966/1973), madness and the asyl 1961/1967), medicine and the birth of clinical practice (Foucault, 1 crime and the carceral system (Foucault, 1975/1979). In Chapter with his later work on sexuality, especially the social control of cault, 1978/1980) and the self and sexuality (Foucault, 1984/1985, 1 The wide range of Foucault's work makes it difficult to summari it is also dense and subject to multiple interpretations. Further com ters is the fact that Foucault is purposely elusive: "Do not ask who I ask me to remain the same" (1969, 1971/1976:17). In fact, Foucault the same; his work shows important shifts over the course of his car Foucault's work also shows a variety of theoretical inputs (Sma variety makes it provocative and difficult to handle. Furthermore, th simply adopted from other thinkers but transformed as they are Foucault's innovative theoretical orientations. Thus, Weber's theory tion has an impact, but to Foucault rationalization is found only sites," and it is not an "iron cage"; there is always resistance. (Smart, 1983) are found in Foucault's work, but Foucault does not to the economy; he focuses on a range of social institutions. He is m
in the "micro-politics of power," a multiplicity of minor coercive techniques (Bog ard, 1991), than in the traditional Marxian concern with power at the societallevel. He practices hermeneutics to better understand the social phenomena of concern to him. However, Foucault has no sense of some deep, ultimate truth; there are sim ply ever more layers to be peeled away. There is a phenomenological influence, but Foucault rejects the idea of an autonomous, meaning-giving subject. There is a strong element of structuralism but no formal rule-governed model of behavior. Fi nally, and perhaps most important, Foucault adopts a number of Nietzsche's inter ests (see Chapter 2), most notably the relationship between power and knowledge (Smith, 1994), but that linkage is analyzed much more sociologically by Foucault. This multitude of theoretical inputs is one of the reasons that Foucault is thought of as a poststructuralist. As we will see, although he strongly rejected it, structuralism did influence Foucault's early work but tended to recede in importance in the later, even more poststructuralist, "vark. In his early writings, Foucault is doing what he calls an "archaeology of knowl edge" (Foucault, 1966/1973). However, he quickly not only refines his thinking on an archaeological approach but also lays the groundwork for a dramatic shift to ward a "genealogy of power" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976). Still later, we witness yet another change to a concern for the "techniques of the self." Before proceeding, we need to sort out the relationship between his archaeology and genealogy. The two processes are not distinct from one another in his work; rather, they are complementary. Archaeology focuses on a given historical "mo ment" (which, in fact, can be quite long), while genealogy is concerned with a his torical process. More specifically, "Genealogy offers us a processual perspective on the web of discourse, in contrast to an archaeological approach which provides us with a snapshot, a slice through the discursive nexus" (Bevis, Cohen, and Kendall, ·1993:194). It is worth underscoring the fact that in both, Foucault remains focused on discourse; the subject matter of concern to him throughout his work is discursive formations. ARCHAEOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
In his archaeology of knowledge, Foucault, reflecting the structuralist focus on language, is interested in studying discursive events, both spoken and written state ments.He is particularly interested in early statements in the history of a field. He wants to uncover the basic conditions that make a given discourse possible. The unity of such statements, the way that they come to form a science or a discipline, does not come from the human subject or the author (this rejection of the subject/author is central to Foucault's thinking and in line with later postmodern ideas) but rather from basic discursive rules and practices extant at a given time and place (Flynn, 1978). More specifically, Foucault is interested in the basic dis cursive practices that formed the base of scientific discourse, particularly in the human sciences. To Foucault, archaeology is concerned with objects, things without context, ar ticles left from the past, silent monuments. (This focus on objects, like the rejec-
tion of a spotlight on the subject, is also in line with the later thinking ernists, especially Baudrillard.) In focusing on objects, he wants to from the sovereignty of the subject that has reigned, in his view, si teenth century. In other words, the reign of the subject is coterminou modernity (Dean, 1986). This has been manifest especially in the d the human subject in anthropology and humanism. Thus, Fou 1971/1976:16) takes as his goal the creation of "a method of analysis anthropologism"; his position is anti-humanistic (Paden, 1987). In terms of his own work, Foucault (1969,1971/1976:17) seeks to avoid a human subject or author; he writes, he says, "in order to have no fac Instead of focusing on people and what they say, Foucault (1978 discourse as practice. In looking at discursive practice, Foucault beg existing unities (psychopathology, for example), but only to break t construct" them,l into their component parts. In doing so, he frees up
the totality of all effective statements (whether spoken or written), in thei events and in the occurrence that is proper to them ... a population o space of discourse in general. One is led therefore to the project of a pure discursive events as the horizon for the search for the unities that form wi (Foucault, 1969,
Although he describes discursive events, ultimately Foucault is looki of discourse, but they are not those that have been traditionally defin ties (e.g., psychopathology). And, he is looking for those unities in t of discursive events, not in people and what they say. In other words, gaged discursive events (as objects) from the people (subjects) who in them. Foucault outlines a five-step process for the analysis of a field events: 1 2 3 4 5
grasp the statement in the exact specificity of its occurrence determine its conditions of existence fix at least its limits establish its correlates with other statements that may be connected show what other forms of statement it excludes.
(Foucault, 1969,
In this process, Foucault is interested in getting, at least initially, at th that exist within discourse. He traces those regularities to several kind ships-relations between statements, between groups of statements, tions between statements and groups of statements and [more sociolo of a quite different kind (technical, economic, social, political)" (Fo 1971/1976:29).
1 Deconstruction is, as we have seen and will see further, of central concern to p theory.
Foucault could have examined any body of discourse, but he chose to focus on science, especially sciences of man such as biology (and medicine), economics, and grammar (language). He does so for the tactical reason that he believes that it is easier to study discourse in such well-defined disciplines. Specifically, he is interested in discursive fonnations where a system of disper sion exists among statements and where there is regularity among elements such as "objects, types of statement, concepts, or thematic choices" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:38; Brown and Cousins, 1980). All of these elements are, in his view, subject to rules of formation or the "conditions of existence (but also of coexis tence, maintenance, modification, and disappearance) in a given discursive divi sion" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:38). Alan Sheridan contends that Foucault's ar chaeology of knowledge involves a search for "a set of rules of formation that determine the conditions of possibility of all that can be said within the particular discourse at any given time" (1980:48). Foucault admits that this is a blank, un charted, indifferent space, but he is prepared to focus on it rather than the foci of most of his predecessors-authors, oeuvres (bodies of work), the origin of ideas, influences, traditions, and most generally the history of ideas. Thus, for example, there are rules for the formation of concepts. The concepts he is examining are not those found in specific individual texts or even in a science at a particular point in time. Rather, he is interested in the anonymous dispersion of concepts through a wide range of books, oeuvres, and texts. The rules of formation of these concepts "operate not only in the mind or consciousness of individuals, but in discourse itself, they operate ... on all individuals who undertake to speak in this discursive field" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:63). He looks at the three major fields mentioned above and is interested in both the similarities and differ ences·among concepts (as well as other elements of discourse) in these fields. Foucault's unit of analysis in such comparative studies is the statement (Mahon, 1993). Statements are better thought of as functions than structures (this is another orientation that helps to distance Foucault from structuralism, to help make him a poststructuralist). As a function, a statement "cuts across a domain of structures and possible unities, and ... reveals them, with concrete contents, in time and space" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:87). He takes as his task to describe this func tion "as such, that is, in its actual practice, its conditions, the rules that govern it, and the field in which it operates" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:87). In these terms, a discourse (or a discursive formation) can be defined as "the group of statements that belong to a single system of formation" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976: 107). In focusing on statements, Foucault is dealing with a different phenomenon than that of concern to those in linguistics, although he makes it clear that his approach is designed to complement, not replace, linguistic analysis. Foucault takes great pains to differentiate the archaeology of knowledge from the already well-established field known as the history of ideas (Lovejoy, 1936/1940, 1948). In his view, the great themes of the history of ideas are the gen esis/of ideas, their continuity over time, as well as totalizations such as the spirit of an age. In line with later postmodernists, Foucault rejects the search for the origin, or genesis, of ideas. Similarly, he is at least as interested in differences and contra dictions in ideas as he is in continuities. And, he prefers detailed analyses of state-
ments to global generalizations about totalities. (The rejection of yet another similarity between Foucault and later postmodernists.) I Foucault articulates four principles that distinguish the archaeology from the history of ideas:
1 Archaeology does not focus on the "thoughts, representa themes, preoccupations that are concealed or revealed in discourses concerned with "those discourses themselves . . . as practices o rules." To put it another way, archaeology does not treat "discourse a a sign of something else," but is rather concerned with discourse its ment." Archaeology "is not an interpretative discipline: it does no better-hidden discourse"2 (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976: 138-139). 2 Archaeology does not seek to rediscover the linear and gra characterizes discourses and their relationship to the other discourse surround, and succeed them. Rather, the goal "is to define discourse ficity ... a differential analysis of the modalities of discourse" (P 1971/1976: 139). 3 Archaeology is not concerned with individual bodies of wo Rather it is concerned with the "types of rules for discursive pra through individual oeuvres"; rules that govern them in whole or in p involves a rejection of a focus on the author of the oeuvre and does thor as the basis of the unity of that work (Foucault, 1969, 1971/197 4 Finally, archaeology does not involve a search for the origin but rather "it is the systematic description of a discourse-object" ( 1971/1976: 139-140).
In addition to their positive directions, the above can be read as rei entations Foucault rejects-the search for underlying structures, ideas, the focus on the subject, and a concern for origins. As pointed out above, Foucault is very interested in contradicti cursive formations, whereas he sees the history of ideas as involve suppress contradictions to show coherence and continuity in idea (1969, 1971/1976: 151), a contradiction is "the very law of its [d tence: it is on the basis of such a contradiction that discourse emer diction is ceaselessly reborn through discourse.... Contradiction, throughout discourse, as the principle of its historicity." The goa cover" contradictions but to describe them in themselves; they are o scribed through archaeological analysis. Rather than seeking to e dictions as does the history of ideas, "archaeology describes the dif dissension" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976: 152). In examining contra chaeologist is to look at their different types, the different level occur and can be mapped, and the various functions they can perf course is a "space of multiple dissensions; a set of different oppo 2 This is another clear indication of Foucault's poststructuralism; he is not inte structures.
42
POSTMODERN SOCIAL THEORY
CHAPTER 3:
task of the archaeologist is to map them, above all, to "maintain discourse in all its Inany hTegularities" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:155-156). Further, the goal is to compare contradictions; indeed archaeology is inherently comparative. Thus, archaeology is always plural looking at two or more discourses simultaneously. To put this another way, archaeology is inherently interdiscursive. Thus, it looks not for things like the "spirit" of a science, or a Weltanschauung, but rather the tangle of contradictions and analogies that make up one discourse in contrast to others. While Foucault is doing detailed examinations of statements and discourses, he is not unaware of their relationship to the larger social context: 1
The archaeological description of discourses is deployed in the dimensions of a general history; it seeks to discover that whole domain of institutions, economic processes, and social relations on which a discursive formation can be articulated. (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976: 164)
It is this that makes Foucault's work particularly interesting to sociology. Similarly, Foucault is interested in the changing nature of discourse, its se quence, and its succession. Unlike the history of ideas, archaeology is willing to acknowledge and study the changes, ruptures, discontinuities, and sudden redistri butions that characterize the history of discourse. In fact, the substitution of one discursive fonnation for another, while rare, is of the utmost importance, and only an archaeology of knowledge can deal adequately with such a dramatic change. In the end, what Foucault is trying to do is to define a new d071'zain of study in cluding objects, statements, rules of formation, discursive formations, and changes in them. He is interested in a "description of statements, of their formation, and of the regularities [as well as irregularities] proper to discourse" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:200). While it was written prior to The Archaeology of Knowledge, The Order of Things can be seen as an effort to apply at least an earlier conception of archaeol ogyto a specific set of intellectual issues- (Chua, 1981).. Foucault (1966/ 1973 :xi~xii) offers an excellent summary of what he sought to do in this historical study of what we would now call the human sciences (Christie, 1993)-the natural sc~ence of biology ("naturalists"), economics, and linguistics ("grammarians"): Unknown to themselves, the naturalists, economists, and grammarians employed the smne lules to define the objects proper to their own study, to form their concepts, to build their theories. It is these rules offormation which were never fOlmulated in their own right, but are to be found only in widely differing theories, concepts, and objects of study, that I have tried to reveal, by isolating, as their specific locus, a level that I have called, somewhat arbitrarily perhaps, archaeological. Taking as an example the period covered in this book, I have tried to determine the basis or archaeological system, com Inon to a whole series of scientific "representations" or "products" dispersed throughout natural history, econOlnics, and philosophy [or linguistics] of the Classical period. (Foucault, 1966/1973:xi-xii; italics added).
FOUCAULT 1: ARCHAEOLOGY; G
To put it succinctly and in terms of the title of his work, Foucault is scribe archaeologically the order among (discursive) things in the fi economics, and linguistics. The focus in his historical analysis is the two great changes in general form of thinking and theorizing establishing ideas, sciences Western culture, the first occuning in the mid-seventeenth century, i Classical Age, and the second at the beginning of the nineteenth ce the Modem Age into existence.3 He is quick to point out that this tra necessarily represent progress but merely a change in the way things Here, as in Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault rejects a focus or the author and, in the process, rejects a phenomenological approa a concern for transcendental consciousness. As is his pattern, Fou COnCelTI himself with discursive practice, and not the knowing subj cault wants to distance himself from phenomenology, but that is n parison to his desire to separate his approach from structuralism: " 'commentators' persist in labelling me a 'structuralist'. I have been into their tiny minds that I have used none of the methods, concept that characterize structural analysis" (Foucault, 1966/1973:xiv). Ye is obvious throughout his work, that there "may well be certain tween the works of structuralists and my own work" (Foucault, 1 This is clear, for example, when he says that in looking for "order i is looking for "buried similitudes [that] must be indicated on the su ... A knowledge of similitudes is founded upon the unearthing and these signatures" (Foucault, 1966/1973:26; italics added). Also rejected here is the focus on human beings as the subjects knowledge. Foucault argues that it was during the period of his strange figure of knowledge called man first appeared and revealed to the huma.n sciences" (Foucault, 1966/1973:xxiv). Foucault see humans as historically atypical and as distorting. Furthermore, he b are now beginning to witness the end of the dominance of human jects and objects of scientific study. In doing this analysis, Foucault (1966/1973:31) makes it clear t ing knowledge "at its archaeological level-that is, at the level o possible." He begins with sixteenth-century knowledge, which he s but poverty-stricken. However, in the seventeenth century, know take a very different form. Without going into a lengthy analysis sixteenth-century knowledge as characterized by the view that the e is composed of "a complex of kinships, resemblances, and affini 1966/1973:54), whereas in the seventeenth century representations blance: "It is through resemblance that representation can be know pared with other representations that may be similar to it, analyse
3 In Archaeology ofKnowledge, Foucault argues that in The Order of Things he mistaken impression that he is analyzing cultural totalities. Thus, he seems to rec bias in his earlier work, a bias which is also reflected in his periodization of the pro
sion.
(elements common to it and other representations), combined with those represen tations that may present partial identities, and finally laid out into an ordered table" (Foucault, 1966/1973:68; italics added). Foucault proceeds to analyze what were in the Classical Age (the seventeenth century) called natural history, the the ory of money and value (economics), and general grammar (linguistics) and con cludes that they indicate that the "centre of knowledge, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, is the table" (Foucault, 1966/1973:75). In fact, these three fields are little more than sub-regions of the tabular space that represented knowl edge in this period. Looking at specific fields of language during this period, Foucault (1966/ 1973:120) says, "The fundamental task of Classical 'discourse' is to ascribe a nalne to things, and in that nalne to name their being." Of biology (or natural his tory), he· contends that "a grid can be laid out over the entire vegetable or animal kingdom.'Each group can be given a name" (Foucault, 1966/1973:141). And, in his view, the "analysis of wealth obeys the same configuration as natural history and general grammar" (Foucault, 1966/1973:200). However, each of these domains, as well as the entire episteme on which they are based, changes again in the eighteenth century. Within less than twenty years, the classical episteme, with its great emphasis on tables, is toppled. And the effect oLthis fall is felt in all realms of knowledge. Representation has been displaced, and knowledge has "now escaped from the space of the table" (Foucault, 1966/1973:239). The new basis of knowledge is the "transcendental field of sub jectivity" (Foucault, 1966/1973:250). More specifically, "what matters is no longer identities, distinctive characters, permanent tables with all their possible paths and routes,· but great hidden forces developed on the basis of their primitive and inac cessible nucleus, origin, causality, and history" (Foucault, 1966/1973:251; italics added). These, of course, are all of the things that Foucault fought against in creat ing:his archaeology of knowledge, especially the emphasis on the human subject. Thus, .in the Modern Age, the human being is born and replaces the table as the center of our systems of knowledge. We are so accustomed to thinking in this modem way that we think human be ings have always been the center of thought. However, Foucault makes it clear that lnan, in this sense, did not exist before the eighteenth century. The classical age has "no epistemological consciousness of man as such ... [it] absolutely excludes any thing that could be a 'science of man' " (Foucault, 1966/1973:309-311). That is, unlike today, man did not occupy the center of the "human sciences"-economics, philosophy (linguistics), and biology. It was the table, and not the human being, that was the center of knowledge. With the eclipse of classical discourse, "man ap pears in his ambiguous position as an object of knowledge and as a subject that knows: enslaved sovereign, observed spectator, he appears in the place belonging to the king" (Foucault, 1966/1973:312). Foucault thinks that it is crucial that this anthropological focus, this anthropo logical prejudice, be recognized and destroyed. The focus on the human being has served to warp and distort our thinking. However, in the human sciences we are ex periencing yet another epistemic change (with thinkers like Foucault in the fore front), what many have termed the "linguistic turn," and the focus has shifted from
human beings to language. Foucault (1966/1973:387) concludes, "As ogy of our thought easily shows, man is an invention of recent date. haps nearing its end." Or, more graphically, "one can certainly wa would be erased, like a face drawn in the sand at the edge of the s 1966/1973 :387).
GENEALOGY OF POWER
Foucault's early archaeologIcal analysis of discourse was later aban even more poststructuralist approach because Foucault came to reali chaeology was silent on the issue of power as well as on the link be edge and power. Foucault's genealogy focuses on the origins (in conc conditions) and the (largely discontinuous) development of pow regimes. The most important source on Foucault's (1969, 1971/1976 the genealogy of power is his 1971 lecture and essay, "The Disco guage." Consistent with the emphasis he places on decentering the cault begins by once again seeking to avoid being considered the aut of the essay, describing himself as a "nameless voice" and saying " like to have slipped imperceptibly into this lecture" (Foucault, 1976:215). A dramatic shift in Foucault's thinking is indicated in this essay certainly was a critical edge to his earlier work, especially aimed a man and the human sciences, critique now becomes much more ce now is power and the way it is exercised over discourse:
I am supposing that in every society the production of discourse is at o selected, organized and redistributed according to a certain number whose role is to avert its powers and danger, to cope with chance even ponderous, awesome materiality.
(Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:21
The central point is that discourse is dangerous, and those in power se control over those forms of discourse that they consider a potential th Foucault identifies four domains in which discourse is considered larly dangerous: politics (or power), sexuality (or desire), madness, a erally, what is considered to be true or false. Foucault, following Nie fies the latter area as the "will to truth" or "the will to power." In Foucault (like Nietzsche) is linking knowledge to power; the idea th is pursued for its own sake, and not to gain power, is rejected by Fou is an example of a field engaged in an effort to differentiate true making such a differentiation, a scientific field is implicitly exclud bodies of knowledge as "false." In this way, the will to truth is tied power; one scientific field seeks to gain hegemony over other fields. is a historical trend in the direction of the linkage between the will the will to truth as the central problem confronting discourse in soc grows in strength, in depth and inlplacability" (Foucault, 1969, 19
Discourses on politics, sexuality, and madness are seen as oriented to attaining
power and are opposed by those with, or in, powel: Despite the growing impor tance of the will to power and truth, it is largely invisible in society as a whole; "we speak of it least" (FoucauIt, 1969, 1971/1976:219). Foucault intends to correct that problem by speaking (actually writing) about the will to power and tluth. Foucault (1969, 1971/1976:220) differentiates between systems of exclusion (like those discussed above) and "internal rules, where discourse exercises its own control; rules concerned with the principles of classification, ordering and distribu tion." That is, disciplines have their own rules that serve to control what is said in them. For example, they often represent closed communities, or fellowships of dis course, .that prevent those outside these realms from speaking, at least with any au thority; .For another, education and credentials are used as mechanisms to appropri ate discourse; those with the proper credentials may speak, others may not. Along with other intelnal mechanisms (e.g., verbal rituals), these devices are generally "linked together, constituting great edifices that distribute speakers among the dif ferenttypes of discourse" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:227). Thus, Foucault sees himself as undertaking two often (but not always) interre lated tasks. The first is the critical task of dealing with "forms of exclusion, limita tion and appropriation ... how they are formed, in answer to which needs, how they are modified and displaced, which constraints they have effectively exercised, to what extent they have been worked on" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:231). The second, or genealogical, task is to examine "how selies of discourse are formed, through, in spite of, or with the aid of these systems of constraint: what were the specific norms for each, and what were the conditions of appearance, growth and variation" (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:232). On the relationship between critical and genealogical analysis, Foucault says, The genealogical aspect concerns the effective formation of discourse, whether within the limits of control, or outside of them, or as is most frequent, on both sides of the de limitation. Criticism analyses the processes of rarefaction, consolidation and unifica tion in discourse, genealogy studies their formation, at once scattered, discontinuous and regular. (Foucault, 1969, 1971/1976:233; italics added)
Thus, genealogy is a historical analysis of the relationship between power and dis course, while criticism is aimed at the processes involved in the control of dis course. Overall, Foucault is concerned with how people regulate themselves and others through the production and control of knowledge. Among other things, he sees knowledge generating power by constituting people as subjects and knowledge being used to govern the subjects. He is critical of the hierarchization of knowl edge. Because the highest-ranking forms of knowledge (the sciences) have the greatest power, they are singled out for the most severe clitique. Foucault is inter ested in techniques, the technologies that are derived from knowledge (especially scientific knowledge), and how they are used by various institutions to exert power over people. Although he sees links between knowledge and power, Foucault does
not see a conspiracy by elite members of society. Such a conspirac conscious actors, whereas Foucault is more inclined to see structura especially between knowledge and power. Looking over the sweep cault does not see progress from plimitive brutishness to more m ness based on more sophisticated knowledge systems. Instead, Fou tory lurching from one system of domination (based on knowled Although this is a generally bleak image, on the positive side Fo that knowledge-power is always contested~ there is always ongoing Foucault looks at historical examples, but he is primarily interested power relations in the modern world (Donnelly, 1982). As he puts i the history of the present" (Foucault, 1975/1979:31). With this background on the archaeology of knowledge and th power, let us look at some of Foucault's specific substantive works.
MADNESS AND CIVILIZATION
In Madness and Civilization (1961/1967), Foucault is doing, at lea chaeology of knowledge, specifically of psychiatry or psychiatric makes it clear that he is not doing a history (or a history of ideas) b his archaeologies of knowledge. He says, "I have not tried to writ that language [psychiatryJ, but rather the archaeology of that sile 1961/1967:xi). In such an archaeology, while he is ultimately con present, he is examining the past ostensibly as it must have existed He begins with the Renaissance, when madness and reason wer when there was an incessant dialogue between madness and rea both spoke the same language. However, in the Classical Age (be 1800), distance between them was established, the dialogue began they began to speak different languages, and, ultimately, reason ca madness. In other words, one form of knowledge came to exert pow (madness). Foucault is describing "a broken dialogue" between r ness (Foucault, 1961/1967:x), one with the following end result:
Here reason reigned in the pure state, in a triumph arranged for it in ad zied unreason. Madness was thus tom from that imaginary freedom w it to flourish on the Renaissance horizon. Not so long ago, it had flo broad daylight, in King Lea1; in Don Quixote. But in less than a half-ce sequestered and, in the fortress of confinement, bound to Reason, to t ity and to their monotonous nights.
(Foucau
While the Renaissance is a period of a comparative lack of silence and the sane live in worlds of total silence (at least vis-a-vis one a
4 There is a clear Weberian, iron-cage imagery here-the "monotonous nights "mad" (the irrational) in the iron cage constructed by those with reason (rationality
no dialogue between them. Foucault is interested in what led not only to this sepa ration of sanity and madness but also to the subjugation of madness by the sane. 5 Foucault does not see what has happened to the mad as an isolated process. The same kind of thing was happening to others, including the poor, the unemployed, and prisoners. Thus, the Renaissance is the period of the founding of houses of confinelnent-madhouses, workhouses, and prisons. Just as the insane were rele gated during this period to the madhouse, the unemployed and poor were sent to workhouses and the prisoners to prison cells. Foucault (1961/1967:39-41) takes as a landlnark in this overall process the founding of the H6pital General in 1656 which he sees, not as a medical establishment, but as a "semijudicial structure"; a third-order of oppression (others were the police and the courts) that soon spread "its. network over the whole of France." Hospitals, madhouses, workhouses, and prisons·. are not to Foucault what they purport to be but rather part of a broad sys teln put in place during the Renaissance to judge and to oppress people. The rise of this system, and each of its components, is linked by Foucault to the economic crises of the day. To forestall agitation and uprisings, people were put to work. Those that could not be put to work were confined in places like hospitals, prisons, and mental institutions. In other words, these served as mechanisms of so cial control. While this system may not have succeeded in terms of its original purposes (after all, uprisings and even revolutions did occur), it did serve to define the lack of work, that is, idleness (later extended to all types of social uselessness), as an ethical and moral problem. And from the beginning the mad were linked to the poor and the idle. For the first time in history, institutions of morality were formed combining moral obligation and civil law. More generally, things like morality, virtue, and goodness became concerns of the state. Until the seventeenth century, what was considered to be evil was dealt with in public. The seventeenth century witnessed the beginnings of the rise of confine ment for those who were considered "evil." By the eighteenth century the process had reached such an extreme that it was believed that only oblivion, like that asso ciated with confinement, could suppress evil. Shame had come to be associated with that which was inhuman. There was one important difference, however, be tween the insane and the others who were confined. The insane were shown, dis played, and made a spectacle of even after confinement. One explanation for this difference is that during this period the mad came to be thought of as animals. This pennitted those in charge to exert discipline over them, even to brutalize them (we have not yet reached the stage of the medicalization of the treatment of the insane). More inlportant, at least for the purposes of this discussion, this helps to account for 'why the insane were displayed. That is, their display showed the population how close they were to animals and, implicitly, how close they were to being con fined if they stepped out of line. Despite the spectacles, the mad were still behind 5 It should be borne in mind that Foucault can be interpreted as not only writing about the madness of the insane but also of the "madness" of creative individuals like himself.
bars, separated from reason and those who were considered to poss be recalled that this situation stood in contrast to the Renaissance ness was everywhere; it mingled with everything. The scientific psychology and psychiatry of the nineteenth cen arose out of the separation of the mad from the sane, the "inventio in the eighteenth century. In line with his ideas on the end of the di the mad and the sane, psychiatry is described as a "monologue o madness" (Foucault, 1961/1967:xi). At first, medicine was in charg cal and moral treatment of the mad, but later scientific psycholo took over the moral treatment. It was the definition of madness as a that made psychology possible. "A purely psychological medicine w ble only when madness was alienated in guilt" (Foucault, 1961/ Later, Foucault says, "What we call psychiatric practice is a cert contemporary with the end of the eighteenth century, preserved in lum life, and overlaid by the myths of positivism" (1961/1967:276) cault, psychology (and psychiatry) is a moral enterprise, not a scie aimed against the mad who are progressively unable to protect t this "help." He sees the mad as being sentenced by so-called sci ment to a "gigantic moral imprisonment." A change in perceptual structure took place in the seventeenth centuries. Diseases that at one time were thought to be illnesses o hysteria, hypochondria) came to be viewed as diseases of the mind. thought to be corporeal was now thought to be mental and ther with immorality. Blame came to fall on those \\'ith these illness were now seen as the psychological effects of moral faults. This work for nineteenth-century scientific psychiatry and its moral me we are not yet at that stage. Medicine continued to be content w problems with the physical means (purification, immersion, regu ment) that had been used to exorcise sin. However, medicine wa nize the difference between physical medicaments and moral tre years, psychological attacks on mental problems and physical in juxtaposed; they complemented one another, but never again interp With this clear distinction there arose nineteenth-century ps moral methods, which "brought madness and its cure into the d (Folicault, 1961/1967: 182). The focus shifted to the interrogation sponsible for the "insane" thoughts or actions. With the separatio logical and the organic, and the delegation (usurpation) of unrea ogy, modern psychology came into being. Unreason had emerged from confinement in the eighteenth cen fear that mental disease was spreading in the houses of confinem "maleficent vapors" were pervading the institutions. While this ne medical terms, it was "animated, basically, by a moral m 1961/1967:202). In any case, "unreason was once more present; by an imaginary stigma of disease, which added its powers of t
1961/1967:205). Here Foucault once again attacks the idea of progress. This "new" view of the insane combined the fear of unreason with old spectres of dis ease. This wasn't progress but a regression involving the reactivation of images of itnpurity. It was this, more than improved knowledge, that led medicine to deal with mental illness. One example of such an "advance" was the great reform movement of the sec ond half of the eighteenth century in which houses of confinement were more completely isolated so that they could be surrounded by purer air. Such isolation was also designed to allow "evil" to vegetate in the asylums without spreading to the larger comlnunity. This served to eliminate, in the view of the day, the risk of contagion while at the same time retaining the asylum, and the mad contained in it, as an example for the spectators. It remained "a spectacle conclusively proving the drawbacks of imlnorality" (Foucault, 1961/1967:207). At the beginning of the nineteenth century the positivists claimed to have been the first to have freed the mad from being confused with criminals. However, Fou cault rejects this as he does most claims by the medical establishment. Rather than being brought about by advances in the humanitarianism of the medical profes sion, Foucault traces it to the mad themselves and their protests against their treat ment. It was the mad themselves who succesfully resisted the power of the con finements and those who supported them. In fact, in Foucault's view, the actions of the positivists did more to link madness to confinement than to separate the two. Needless to say, Foucault rejects the idea that over the years we have seen scien tific, medical, and humanitarian advances in the treatment of the mad. What he sees, .instead, are increases in the ability of the sane and their agents (physicians, psychologists, psychiatrists) to oppress and repress the mad who, we should not forget, had been on equal footing with the sane before the Renaissance. More re cently,· the mad have come to be less judged by these external agents and more by themselves; "madness is ceaselessly called upon to judge itself' (Foucault, 1961/1967:265). In many senses such internalized control is the most repressive forni of control. In this context, Foucault looks at the work of those, like William Tuke (1732-1822) and Philippe Pinel (1754-1826), who are generally considered to be the great reformers in the history of mental illness. He argues that we need to look beyond their self-serving justifications. Of Tuke, for example, Foucault (1961/ 1967:243) says that his action "was regarded as an act of 'liberation.' The truth was quite different." The result of Tuke's actions was that madmen came to be aware of, to feel guilty about, their own madness. Madmen were sentenced to a lifetime of anguish of responsibility and conscience. As a result, the mad were forever vul nerable to punishment not only by others but also by themselves. Thus, madness came to be "ceaselessly called upon to judge itself ... [and it also came to be judged] by a sort of invisible tribunal in permanent session" (Foucault, 1961/1967:265). Madmen were also forced to objectify themselves both in work and in observa tion, an observation that was, by the way, a one-way process. The madman is now piteously observed by himself. And "in the silence of those who represent reason,
and who have done nothing but hold up the perilous mirror, he recog as objectively mad" (Foucault, 1961/1967:264). Thus was born a scie illness that involved observation and classification without a dialo mad. It is a world of absolute silence between the mad and those with they no longer have a common language. Thus, Foucault (1961/19 cludes that rather than being therapeutic or humanitarian, PineI's as volved in the "conversion of medicine into justice, of therapeutics int Everything is now set up so that the madman now recognizes that he on all sides by a world of judgment; he is constantly being watched demned. In addition, the guilt is internalized and becomes part of the science. Most generally, the inmate is "imprisoned in a moral wor 1961/1967:269). Foucault (1961/1967:278) concludes by describing moral imprisonment which we are in the habit of calling, doubtless b the liberation of the insane by Pinel and Tuke." Foucault sees all of this manifest in the modern practice of medici ment of the mentally ilL The physician plays a central role in the asy where, not as a scientist but "as a juridical and moral guarante 1961/1967:270). Science is little more than a disguise, a justification role played by medical practitioners. In an excellent summation o Foucault (1961/1967:276) argues, "what we call psychiatric practi moral tactic contemporary with the end of the eighteenth century, pr rites of asylum life, and overlaid by the myths of positivism." Interestingly, Foucault gives Freud some credit for restoring the tween the mad and the sane:
Freud went back to madness at the level of its language . . . he resto thought, the possibility of a dialogue with um"eason ... It is not psycho volved in psychoanalysis: but precisely an experience of unreason that chology's meaning, in the modern world, to mask. (Foucault,
But, more important, Foucault was also critical of Freud for continuin trends discussed in this section. Thus, he saw Freud's psychoanalysis pure observation, pure and circumspect silence, and adopting a juri Most important, Freud is seen as having transferred to the physician a tures that Pinel, Tuke, and others had set up within the mental instit sult, Freud helped the psychoanalyst, as well as the physician, becom force that they have become in psychiatry and more generally in med Clearly, Foucault's archaeology of knowledge leads him to very clusions from those of traditional historians about the history and CU the mad and their relationship to the sane (and their agents). In addi
6 For a discussion of the influence of psychoanalysis on Foucault's work, see De Naas (1994).
be noted that in this analysis he is examining the roots of the human sciences (es pecially psychology and psychiatry) in the distinction between the mad and the sane and the exertion of moral control over the mad (Christie, 1993). This is part of his more general thesis about the role of the human sciences in the moral con trol of people. As for Foucault's structuralism in this early work, he argues that madness oc curs at two "levels," and at "a deeper level madness is a form of discourse" (1961/1967:96). Specifically, madness, at least in the Classical Age, is not mental or physical Changes; instead, "delirious language is the ultimate truth of madness" (Foucault, .1961/1967:97). Or, later, "Madness, in the Classical sense, does not des ignateso much a specific change in the mind or in the body, as the existence, under the body's alterations, under the oddity of conduct and conversation, of a delirious discour,~e.. . . Language is the first and last structure of madness" (Foucault, 1961/1967 :99~ 100). But there is an even broader structuralism operating in this early work: Letclassical culture formulate, in its general structure, the experience it had of madness, an experience which crops up with the same meanings, in the identical order of its inner logic, in both the order of speculation and in the order of institutions, in both discourse al1d decree, in both word and watchword-wherever, in fact, a signifying element can asSume for us the value of a language. (Foucault, 1961/1967: 116; italics added)
THE BIRTH OFTHE CLINIC
As the subtitle suggests, in The Birth of the Clinic.' An Archaeology of Medical Perception, Foucault continues to do an archaeology of knowledge. He is inter ested in studying a change in the basic structure of experience, and the change in medicine analyzed in this book is but one example of such a change. He also continues to utilize, at least in part, a structuralist approach focusing on medical discourse and its underlying structure. He argues that in doing history, we are doomed "to the patient reconstruction of discourses about discourse, and to the task of hearing what has already been said" (Foucault, 1963/1975:xvi). In the structural analysis of discourse, the meaning of a statement is derived not from the intentions of the person uttering it but from its relationship to other statements in the system of discourse. Also on structural analysis, Foucault says, "What counts in the things said by men is not so much what they may have thought or the extent to which these things represent their thoughts, as that which systematizes theln from the outset, thus making them thereafter endlessly accessible to new discourse and open to the task of transforming them" (Foucault, 1963/1975:xiv; italics added). Of great importance to Foucault in this analysis, as we will see, is perception, or the crucial concept of the gaze (Denzin, 1993). It is a historical shift in the gaze of medicine that is the focus of Foucault's archaeology. Furthermore, Foucault sees an analogy between seeing and speaking (to see is to say), and this serves to make the gaze subject to the same kind of structural analysis as the spoken language. As a structuralist, at least in part, Foucault saw the gaze as a kind of language, "a lan-
guage without words" (1963/1975:68), and he was interested in th of that "language." Thus, the gaze is the subject of both Foucault' and structural analyses. In the eighteenth century, medicine was largely a classificato focus was on the classificatory system (the "table" discussed abov genus, or species of a given disease. As yet, there was no clinical s cine. However, in the nineteenth century the gaze of the med shifted from the classificatory system, from the "table," to the pa tient's body. The key was the development of the clinic where p served in bed (Long, 1992). Here the gaze of the physician on the same time knowledge" (Foucault, 1963/1975:81). In other words, derived from what physicians could see in contrast to the classi they read about in books. Physicians were looking at patients and of classification, or table. The ability to see and touch sick people was a crucial change an important source of knowledge (and ultimately power). Of sp was the ability to examine, or gaze upon, dead bodies in autopsie of the autopsy, "The living night is dissipated in the brigh (1963/1975:146). In other words, the ability to study the dead i things about health, disease, and death. With the advent of the clinical gaze, death took center stage. "Death left its old tragic he the lylical core of man: his invisible tluth, his visible se 1963/1975:172). Because of the autopsy and its focus on things gans, the "being," the "essence," of disease disappears. We are lef tion that all that exists is a series of diseases caused by "a ce11ai ment of tissues in reaction to an irritating cause" (Foucault, 19 addition to the deromanticization of human life (and death), with of diseases ends and the medicine of pathological reactions begin From the point of view of the archaeology of knowledge, F anatomo-clinical gaze as the "great break" in Western medicine no gradual evolution of knowledge leading up to the gaze. Rathe cal gaze represented a fundamental epistemic change, a revol ment. After the change in the gaze, doctors were no longer game; it was a different game with different lules. In the new g tients), and not the disease as part of a broader classification sys the object of scientific knowledge and practice. In terms of a m turalist analysis, what had changed was the nature of discours names and groups of diseases, the field of objects, and so 1963/1975:54). As was the case with mental illness, Foucault rejects medicin an exercise in mythology. The gaze did not evolve, as medicine and effortlessly from prior developments in the field. What rea that the clinical relationship, once a universal relationship of hum came to be radically restructured and redefined in the last years century as the province of the medical' profession. Once this o change in medical knowledge took place: "A way of teaching an
way of learning and seeing" (Foucault, 1963/1975:64). Clinical practice made pos sible "the immediate communication of teaching within the concrete field of expe rience" (Foucault, 1963/1975:68). Seeing replaced dogmatic language as a way of learning the truth. The clinical gaze was seen, in good structuralist terms, as "a lan guage without words ... a language that did not owe its truth to speech but to the gaze alone" (Foucault, 1963/1975:68-69). More generally, the structuralist needed to focus on the codes of knowledge in which field and gaze were intertwined. In Madness and Civilization, medicine was an important precursor of the human sciences, and that is an even more central theme in The Birth of the Clinic. As Foucault clearly put it, "The science of man ... was medically ... based" (1963/1975:36). Up until the end of the eighteenth century, medicine was con celned with the issue of health, but from the nineteenth century, the focus of medi cine shifted more to the issue of normality and that which varies from it (the pathological). To put it another way, prior to the nineteenth century, as we have seen~ medicine was a classificatory science, and the focus was on a clearly ordered system of diseases. But in the nineteenth century, medicine came to focus on dis eases as they existed in individuals and the larger society (epidemics). Medicine came to be extended to healthy people (preventive care), and it adopted a norma tive posture distinguishing between healthy and unhealthy and, later, normal and pathological states. Clinical experience sees a new space opening up before it: the tangible space of the body, which at the same time is that opaque mass in which secrets, invisible lesions, and the very mystery of origins lie hidden. The medicine of symptoms will gradually recede, until it finally disappears before the medicine of organs, sites, causes, before a clinic wholly ordered in accordance with pathological anatomy. (Foucault, 1963/1975: 122; italics added)
Medicine had become, again, a forerunner of the human sciences that were to adopt this normal-pathological stance toward people. Medicine takes on the role of forerunner to the human sciences for another, more general reason: "It is understandable, then, that medicine should have had such importance in the constitution of the sciences of man-an importance that is notbnly methodological, but ontological, in that it concerns man's being an object of positive knowledge" (Foucault, 1963/1975:197). The shift in medicine to the in dividual as subject and object of his own knowledge is but one "of the more visible witnesses to these changes in the fundamental structure of experiences" (1963/1975:199). Clearly, the individual was to become the subject and object of the human sciences. DISCIPLINE AND PUNISH
Many of the themes discussed previously reappear in Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (Foucault, 1975/1979; Foucault and Simon, 1991; for a cri tique see Garland, 1990:131-175). However, now the genealogy of power (Wick ham, 1983) takes more of center stage, and much less attention is devoted to the
archaeology of knowledge, structuralism, discourse, and the lik plains his goal:
This book is intended as a correlative history of the modem soul and o genealogy of the present scientifico-legal complex from wh punish derives its bases, justifications and rules, from which it extends which it masks its exorbitant singularity.
judge~ a
(Foucault, 1975/1979
In the specific terms of the genealogy of power, Foucault (1975/19 clear here that "power and knowledge direct!y imply one another; power relation without the correlative constitution of a field of kno knowledge that does not presuppose and constitute at the same t tions." The focus here shifts away from those who created, or were power-knowledge nexus and toward that nexus itself: "it is not th subject of knowledge that produces a corpus of knowledge, usefu power, but power-knowledge, the processes and struggles that tr which it is made up, that determines the forms and possible dom edge" (Foucault, 1975/1979:28).7 Discipline and Punish is concerned with the period betwee 1830s, a period during which the torture of prisoners was replaced them by prison lules. Characteristically, Foucault sees this chang an irregular way; it does not evolve rationally or in a smooth, ev ion. The book opens in 1757 with an excruciating portrait of a publicly executed by being "torn," "burnt," and "quartered." The p the object of officials. The state of the body, after punishment is i strates that a crime has taken place and that the accused is guilty. monies involved in such torture are judicial and political rituals both that a crime has taken place and that power is being manife control it. Public ceremonies such as executions were great spec cent theatre," designed to demonstrate publicly that power existed torture not only showed the operation of power but also reveal that power. However, while the public torture and execution of prisoners m good public displays, it was "a bad economy of power" because tended to incite unrest among the viewers of the spec 1975/1979:79). Spectacles like executions also tended to lead to "c ity" (Foucault, 1975/1979:63). The taverns were full, stones were tioners, fights erupted, and spectators grabbed at the victims. F time, protests against public executions increased. For all of these needed to end public confrontations with the condemned.
7 Foucault is indicating a shift away from the focus on the human subject, a even more dramatic with later postmodemists, especially Baudrillard (see Chapte
Within less than a century a new system of punishment was in place. Torture disappeared as a public spectacle. Punishment became less physical and much more subtle. The body ceased to be the major target of punishment. Instead of im posing "unbearable sensations" on prisoners, the focus was on things like suspend ing their rights. Punishment came to be rationalized and bureaucratized. Bureau cratic restraint and control was reflected in the fact that "a whole army of technicians took over for the executioner, the immediate anatomist of pain: warders, doctors, chaplains, psychiatrists, psychologists, educationalists" (Fou cault, 1975/1979: 11). Instead of the earlier vagaries, punishment became far more predictable. Technologically, the far more efficient guillotine replaced the "hang ing machine." This led to greater efficiency; instead of a long, cruel process, death came in cl single blow from the blade of the guillotine. Anger and passion were re moved from the process; "the executioner need be no more than a meticulous watchmaker" (Foucault, 1975/1979:13). The law was applied, and people acted, impersonally. Even the condemned wore veils to conceal who they were. "The age of sobriety in punishment had'begun" (Foucault, 1975/1979:14). As in the case of madness, the general and accepted view is that all of the changes described above represented a humanization of the treatment of criminals; punishment had grown more kind, less painful, and less cruel. The reality, from Foucault's point of view, was that punishment had grown more rationalized and in many ways impinged more on prisoners as well as on the larger society. Punish ment may have grown less intense, but it was at the expense of greater intervention into peoples' lives. Foucault (1975/1979:78) describes "a tendency towards a more finely tuned justice, towards a closer penal mapping of the social body ... controls become more premature and more numerous." While the link between knowledge and power was clear in the case of torture and public executions, with the develop ment of a more rational system, that link became far less clear. The new system of rules was "more regular, more effective, more constant, and more detailed in its ef fects; in short, which increased its effects while diminishing its economic cost" (Foutault, 1975/1979:80-81). The new system was not designed to be more hu mane, "not to punish less, but to punish better; to punish with an attenuated sever ity perhaps, but in order to punish with more universality and necessity; to insert the power to punish more deeply into the social body" (Foucault, 1975/1979:82). In contrast to torture, this new technology of the power to punish occurred earlier in the deviance process, was more numerous, more bureaucratized, more efficient, more impersonal, more invariable, and more sober, and involved the surveillance not just of criminals but of the entire society. Thus, penal systems did not seek to eliminate punishments but simply to administer them differently. The criminal, and what is done to him, is a source of knowledge and informa tion for the larger public. As Foucault (1975/1979:112) puts it, the punishment of the criminal is "a living lesson in the museum of order." Thus, the new forms of punishment were less ceremonies and spectacles and more schools for the larger population. "Long before he was regarded as an object of science, the criminal was imagined as a source of instruction" (Foucault, 1975/1979:112). While in an ear lier time there were huge ceremonies involving torture and execution, in the mod ern world we have instead "hundreds of tiny theatres of punishment" (Foucault,
1975/1979: 113).8 More generally, the prison had replaced the sca signified, among other things, that power was inscribed into the ve state since the penal system was run by the state. Foucault relates this to the broader development of what he plines, which, in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, beca mechanism for exercising domination. The disciplines involve a ser designed to exert meticulous control over the body; "discipline pro and practised bodies, 'docile' bodies" (Foucault, 1975/1979: 138). not only occurred in prisons but also in public education (the Lan for example), hospitals, the workplace (especially Taylorism), an Discipline involves the distribution of individuals in space includin and partitioning of individuals and the development of functional "In organizing 'cells', 'places' and 'ranks', the disciplines create that are at once architectural, functional and hierarchical" (F 1979:148). This new technology, the technology of disciplinary power, w military model:
Historians of ideas usually attribute the dream of a perfect society to and jurists of the eighteenth century; but there was also a military dre fundamental reference was not to the state of nature, but to the meti nated cogs of a machine, not to the primal social contract, but to perm not to fundamental rights, but to indefinitely progressive fonns of tr general will, but to automatic docility.
(Foucaul
Foucault identifies three instruments of disciplinary power, deri from the military model. First is hierarchical observation, or the a to oversee all they control with a single gaze. The military camp model (another is the Panopticon discussed below). The goal is ob discreet, largely silent, and permanent. Here is Foucault's "physi volving things like lines of sight and control over various spaces. Second is the ability to make nonnalizing judgTnents and to p violate the norms. Thus, one might be negatively judged and sub penalties for violations relating to such things as time (for being l being inattentive), behavior (for being impolite), and body (adopt attitude). Such normalizing judgments serve to compare, differe calize, homogenize, and where necessary, exclude people. Third is the use of exaTnination to observe subjects and to m judgments about them (Meadmore, 1993). This third instrumen power involves the other two. That is, examinations involve hiera tion and normalizing judgments; they involve, in other words, gaze" (Foucault, 1975/1979:184). An examination "establishes o visibility through which one differentiates them and judges t 8
This idea is part of Foucault's thinking on the micro-politics of power; see b
1975/1979: 184).. An examination is a wonderful example of the power-knowledge those who have the power to give examinations gain additional knowledge and thereby more power through the imposition of examinations on subjects. As Foucault(1975/1979:185) puts it, "The superimposition of the power relations and knowledge relations assumes in the examination all its visible brilliance." While we usually associate the examination with schools, it is also manifest in psychiatry, medicine, personnel administration, and so on. Foucault offers several other important generalizations about the examination:
linkage~
• First, it "transfonned the economy of visibility into the exercise of power" (Foucault, 1975/1979:187). • Second, it "introduces individuality into the field of documentation" (Fou cault, 1975/1979: 189). As a result of its focus on the individual, Foucault (1975/1979:191) wonders "is this [the examination] the bitth of the sciences of man?" • Third, "the examination, surrounded by all docun1entary techniques, lnakes each individual a tease' " (Foucault, 1975/1979:191). As a case, the individual be comes both an object of knowledge and an object of control. And, of course, the two are linked in the power-knowledge nexus.
By way of summary, we can say that disciplines involve a series of procedures for distributing individuals, fixing them in space, classifying them, extracting from theln maximum time and energy, training their bodies, coding their continuous be havior, maintaining them in perfect visibility, surrounding them with mechanisms of observation, registering and recording them, and constituting in them a body of knowledge that is accumulated and centralized. Foucault does not simply adopt a negative view toward the growth of the disci plinary society; he recognizes that it has positive consequences as welL For exam ple, he sees discipline as functioning well within the military and industrial facto ries. However, Foucault communicates a genuine fear of the spread of discipline, especially as it moves into the state-police network for which the entire society be comes afield of perception and an object of discipline. Foucault does not see discipline sweeping uniformly through society. Instead, he sees elements of it "swarming" through society and affecting bits and pieces of society as it goes. Eventually, however, most major institutions are affected. Fou cault asks rhetorically, "Is it surprising that prisons resemble factories, schools, barracks, hospitals, which all resemble prisons?" (1975/1979:228). In the end, Foucault sees the development of a carceral archipelago in which discipline is transported "from the penal institution to the entire social body" (1975/1979:298; Dutton, 1992; Sewell and Wilkinson, 1992). Although there is an iron-cage image here, as usual Foucault sees the operation of forces in opposition to the carceral system; there is an ongoing structural dialectic in Foucault's work. Although Foucault's greater emphasis on power in Discipline and Punish is evi dent in the discussion to this point, he is also concerned in this work with his usual theme of the emergence of the human sciences. The transition ftom torture to prison rules constituted a switch in the object of punishment from the body to the
soul or the will. This, in turn, brought with it considerations of n morality. Judgment came to be passed "on the passions, instincts, an mities, maladjustments ... aggressivity ... perversions ... drives (Foucault, 1975/1979:17). Even the subject's will came to be judged tered the process, and this helped give officials greater control over n sive acts but over people, "not only on what they do, but also on wha be, may be" (Foucault, 1975/1979:18). In other words, officials cam right to judge people as a whole. In Foucault's (1975/1979:18) term system had gotten hold of the "offender's soul." And it is its effort souls of people that is one of the defining characteristics of the huma More generally, the modern human sciences have their roots in the of penal law; the human sciences and penal law have their roots in th temological-juridical" formation. Here is how Foucault bitterly depic the human sciences in the "disciplines": "These sciences, which hav our 'humanity' for over a century, have their technical matrix in th cious minutiae of the disciplines and their investigations" (1975/1 "humanization" of the penal system and the growth of the human from the same sources and both serve to extend discipline and pun deeply into the social fabric. The effort to control the soul also represented the base for a mass of the penal system. Those in power took to "judging something othe namely the 'soul' of the criminal" (Foucault, 1975/1979:19). Thing and madness came to be associated with crime with the result that now in the position to judge "normality" as well as to prescribe actio help bring about the normalization of those who were judged to Thus, one way that expansion took place in the penal system is that be judged was defined far more widely going to the very soul of the Expansion also took place in another sense; more people acquir render these kinds of judgments. Prison officials and the police cam normality and morality of the prisoner. Eventually, the ability to ma judgment was extended to other "small-scale judges" such as psychi ucators. As a result, "the whole penal operation has taken on extr ments and personnel" (Foucault, 1975/1979:22). The power and ab especially normality and abnormality, has been generalized and is stricted to the penal system. Out of this emerged new bodies of s knowledge, and these served as the base of the modern "scientific-l "A corpus of knowledge, techniques, 'scientific' discourse is fornled entangled with the practice of the power to punish" (Foucault, 1975 new mode of subjugation was that people were defined as the obj edge, of scientific discourse. Power now had a new body of knowled it. New personnel were in possession of this power, and they adopte tactics for using it. In the penal system, its extensions, and in the human sciences, t the subject in general, and specifically on the body. Human beings b jects of punishment and of scientific discourse. Scientific knowledg the body a political field and gave birth to political technologies de
trol the body. However, these technologies, and control more generally, were not centralized in the state or in any other structure or institution. Rather, they were diffused in bits and pieces, in a series of tools and methods, throughout society. Thus, rather than deal with power macroscopically as is usually the case in the (modem) social sciences, Foucault (1975/1979:26) is concerned with the "micro physics of power." As a result, he makes it abundantly clear that there are innumer able points of contact and confrontation between those with power and those on whom they seek to exercise that power. A focus on the micro-physics of power has several important implications. For one thing, it poses a major problem for the Marxian grand narrative of a revolution that would overthrow the entire power structure. Innumerable micro-centers of poWer do not lend themselves easily to destruction in a single stroke by a massive revolution. As Poucault (1975/1979:27) puts it, "The overthrow of these 'micro powers' does not, then, obey the law of all or nothing; it is not acquired once and for all by a new control of the apparatuses nor by a new functioning or a destruc tion of the institutions." For another, the operation of innumerable micro-sites of powermay easily avoid scrutiny or a general sense of their overall impact on soci ety.Thus, it is necessary to examine each of them in the context of the entire net work that they form. Even so, it is difficult to assess the overall impact of a large number of micro-sites of power. One other point, mentioned above, about Discipline and Punish is worth special attention. Poucault is generally interested in the way that knowledge gives rise to technologies that exert power. It is in this context that he deals with the Panopticon (Crossley, 1993; Lyon, 1991). A Panopticon is a structure that allows officials the possibility of complete observation of criminals; in other words, it permits a cer tain kind of gaze. With the Panopticon, officials are able to see constantly and to recognize immediately. Constant visibility traps the subjects in "so many cages, so many· small theatres, in which each actor is alone, perfectly individualized and constantly visible" (Foucault, 1975/1979:200). In .fact, officials need not always be present in the Panopticon; the mere existence of the structure (and the mere possi bility that officials n1ight be there) constrains criminals. Power functions in the Panopticon nearly automatically. Power here is visible, but it is also unverifiable in that the subjects never know at any given moment whether or not they are actually being observed by officials. The Panopticon helps to perfect the exercise of power. It reduces the number of people needed to exercise power, while at the same time it increases the number of people over whom power is exercised. Constant pressure is exerted on those ob served, even before an act is committed, and officials have the ability to intervene at any point in the process. The Panopticon itself is noiseless and unobtrusive. Using just architecture and geometry (physics, again), the Panopticon acts directly on the subjects; it actually involves the power of one mind (the designer of the Panopticon; the official) over another (the prisoner). One of the specific forms that the Panopticon can take is that of a tower in the center of a circular prison from which guards are able to see into all cells. More generaiIy, it is an architectural apparatus that permits officials to gather informa tion and exercise power. Thus, the power lies more in the structure, and in the sys-
tern of which it is part, than in the person who designs or occupies i con is a tremendous source of power for prison officials because it possibility of total surveillance. Among other things, it is certain an virtually eliminates the possibility of physical confrontation betwee inmates. More important, its power is enhanced because the pris control themselves; they stop themselves from doing various thing fear that they might be seen by the officials who 1night be in the Pan is a clear linkage here among knowledge, technology, and power. Furthermore, Foucault returns again to his concern for the huma he sees the Panopticon as a kind of laboratory (a laboratory of powe ering of information about people. It was the forerunner of the social oratory and other social-science techniques for gathering informat ple. This is true, at least in part, because the Panopticon came to b with a criminal but more generally with a "madman, a patient, a co a worker or a schoolboy" (Foucault, 1975/1979:200). At still another level, Foucault sees the Panopticon, or the panopt the base of "a whole type of society" (1975/1979:216), the disciplin society based on surveillance. It can be used not only to neutralize haviors but also to play a more useful role in places like factories an as well as in helping to make people contributing members of societ nisms of the disciplinary society can also be disassociated from s tions and broken down so that their component parts can be employ any social setting. Finally, and most globally, in the hands of the sta lice, the whole social body becomes the object of the disciplinary so Discipline may be found in such a wide array of settings becau identified neither with an institution nor with an apparatus; it is a ty modality for its exercise, comprising a whole set of instruments, tech dures, levels of application, targets; it is a 'physics' or an 'anatom technology" (Foucault, 1975/1979:215). Thus, the disciplinary sy supplant existing systems; rather it infiltrates all of them. The discip series of minute technical mechanisms that help to create micro-m power in whatever settings they infiltrate. The development of the disciplinary society corresponded with o changes such as large increases in population; increased numbers schools, hospitals, and the military; and the growth in the capita These increasingly large systems required cheaper, more efficient, an tive means of control, and those means were derived from the pano These new means of control were, in turn, applied to the production o factories, the production of knowledge and skills in the schools, the health in the hospitals, and the production of destructive force in the The prison is Foucault's paradigm for what is happening throu The prison is an "exhaustive disciplinary apparatus," on which all are modeled to one degree or another (Foucault, 1975/1979:235). T
9 For an interesting use of this idea, see Zuboff (1988), who views the compu Panopticon that gives superiors virtually unlimited surveillance over subordinates.
carceral system that sets the stage for society as a whole to become such a system. Processes begun in the prison, and more generally in the judicial system, spread throughout society producing a "carceral net" or a "carceral archipelago" that came to encompass the "entire social body" (Foucault, 1975/1979:298). The power to punish came to operate at every point within society. All sorts of positions have now acquired the capacity to judge us including physicians, teachers, social work ers, ·and the like. While he recognizes that there are forces operating against the carceral system (for example, illegalities on an international scale that are beyond the scope of current judges), the thrust of this work is to leave us with a sense that the carceral system is a Weberian iron cage (O'Neill, 1986). Actually, given Fou cault's commitment to the analysis of the micro-politics of power, the image is more of an enormous number of mini-cages in which our lives are even more con trolled and even more insufferable than they would be in Weber's society-wide iron·cage. SUMMARY
In this chapter we have examined the bulk of Foucault's published work. We began with his ideas on doing an archaeology of knowledge and then discussed how he did such an archaeology in his studies of several human sciences-biology, eco nomics, and linguistics. Foucault's work then shifted from an analysis of the ar chaeology of knowledge to the much more critical genealogy of power. Here, he is interested not only in the formation of knowledge but also in the role that power plays in that formation. The majority of the chapter was devoted to three case stud ies of the archaeology of knowledge and the genealogy of power-the separation and subordination of the mad by the sane (especially in psychiatry), the birth of the medical clinic as well as of the focus on (and control over) the human body through the autopsy, and the end of the torture of prisoners and the beginning of the carceral system of control and the panoptic principle. Running through much of this work is Foucault's interest in the role played by all of these developments in the birth of the human sciences and the power that they exert over·people. As we will see in the next chapter, in his later work, Foucault shifted to a focus on sexuality. While we began with an interest in the relationship between power and sexuality, he soon moved to a concern for the self.
MICHEL FOUC PART 2: SEXU POWER, AND POWER AND SEXUALITY SELF AND SEXUALITY
lllE
pick up the overview of Foucault's work here with a discu three major works on sexuality. They begin with Foucault's longin the power-knowledge nexus in the West, but in the last two work matic shift to ancient Greece and Rome and to a concern for the tween self and sexuality or, more generally, "the genealogy of the m (Foucault, cited in Miller, 1993:321).
POWER AND SEXUALITY
The emphasis in the fITst volume of The History of Sexuality is on t power (Foucault, 1978/1980). To Foucault sexuality is "an especia fer point for relations of power" (1978/1980: 103). His major object the regime of power-knowledge-pleasure that sustains the discours uality in our part of the world" (FoucauIt, 1978/1980:11). He ex that sex is put into discourse and the way that power permeates that fact, it permeates all discourse (Flynn, 1981). At the beginning of the seventeenth century, sex was largely o The conventional view is that Victorianism closed off sex and co home, the conjugal family, and ultimately to silence (much as the m lenced). Foucault takes issue with the view that Victorianism had l sion of sexuality in general and of sexual discourse in particular. In the opposite position-that Victorianism led to an explosion in disc ality. As he puts it, "since the end of the sixteenth century, the 'p course of sex,' far from undergoing a process of restriction, on t been subjected to a mechanism of increasing inciteme 1978/1980: 12). There were undoubtedly efforts in the seventeenth jugate sex at the level of language, to expunge it from things that eliminate words that made sex too visible. However, instead of e the last three centuries "one sees a veritable discursive explosion" sex. As a result of Victorianism, there was more analysis, stockta
tion, specification, and quantitative/causal study of sexuality. Said Foucault, "Peo ple will ask themselves why we were so bent on ending the nl1e of silence regard ing what was the noisiest of cur preoccupations" (1978/1980: 158). Sex was talked about in confessionals, and literature dealt increasingly, and increasingly explicitly, with sex. This increase was especially notable in schools, where instead of the re pression of sexuality, "the question of sex was a constant preoccupation" (1978/ 1980:27). Here is the way Foucault sums up the Victorian hypothesis and his alter native view: We must therefore abandon the hypothesis that modem industrial societies ushered in an age of increased sexual repression. We have not only witnessed a visible explosion of unorthodox sexualities ... never have there existed more centers of power; never more attention manifested and verbalized ... never more sites where the intensity of pleasures and the persistency of power catch hold, only to spread elsewhere. (Foucault, 1978/1980:49)
Contrary to received wisdom, Foucault sees those in power as deeply implicated in the overall tendency to incite discourse about sexuality. Using his now familiar concept, Foucault (1978/1980:24) argues that following the advent of Victorianism those in power devoted "a steady gaze to these [sexual] objects." Not only did those in power seek to analyze and study sex, they also sought to gain control over sex and sexual discourse by making it something to be administered, something to be policed. The policing of sex, and discourses about it, were certainly not taboo; indeed they seemed to escalate dramatically. FOl" example, those in power were faced with a series of economic and political problems caused by population growth. At the heart of these problems was sex, specifically things like the birth rate, age of marriage, legitimacy, and contracep tion. It became clear to those in power that the future of society depended on the sexuality of individuals and the ability of the powerful to control it. There resulted studies of, and efforts to intervene in, population growth. Sex became a public isslle. More generally, "through the political economy of population there was formed a whole grid of observations regarding sex" (Foucault, 1978/1980:26). As more and more attention was devoted to sex, "a whole web of discourse, special knowledges, analyses, and injunctions settled upon it" (Foucault, 1978/1980:26). Another example of increasing discourse about sex related to the sexuality of children. More and more was being "said" about this issue, although the "talk" took a variety of different forms. The statements and the documents on this issue were there, but there were also many other signs that needed to be read semioti cally~for example, the architectural design of schools reflected the preoccupation of those in power with children's sexuality. One had to study the meaning and in tent of that architecture (for example, structures that separated boys and girls) to understand what it was "saying." More and more people-educators, physicians, administrators, and others~became involved in the sexuality of children and the discourse about it. Foucault Inakes similar specific points about sexuality in medi cine, psychiatry, and criminal justice, but his overarching point is that in all of
these realms discourse on sexuality had become rampant. Furtherm dispersion of the centers of sexual discourse. Thus, Foucault conc peculiar to tIlodern societies, in fact, is not that they consigned sex istence, but that they dedicated themselves to speaking of it ad infi ploiting it as the secret" (1978/1980:35). Those in power concentrated more and more of their gaze on wasn't suppression that resulted from the increased gaze but rather of power and sexual pleasure. In fact, Foucault (1978/1980:44) des erotic terms, the way those in power approached the issue of s which thus took charge of sexuality set about contacting bodies, with its eyes, intensifying areas, electrifying surfaces, dranwtizin ments. It wrapped the sexual body in its elnbrace" (Foucault, 1978 added). A dialectic emerged between power and pleasure: "Pleasu power that han'ied it; power anchored the pleasure it uncove 1978/1980:45). Medical exams, psychiatric investigations, peda and family controls can all be seen as exertions of power that linked to pleasure, a "pleasure that comes of exercising a powe monitors, watches, spies, searches out, palpates, brings to light; a hand, the pleasure that kindles at having to evade this power, flee or travesty it" (Foucault, 1978/1980:45). Thus, Foucault sees p of power-pleasure enveloping parents-children, adults-adolesce students, doctors-patients, and psychiatrists-patients. The combin and pleasure virtually guaranteed that there would be more sex an gazing at it. Once again, Foucault devotes special attention to medicine, t courses on sexuality. It is clear above that medicine is deeply im power-pleasure nexus. In addition, Foucault challenges the gen idea that medicine is oriented to the scientific analysis of sexual Foucault sees much more morality than science in the sexual co cine. Foucault is characteristically hard on medicine, seeing the courses on sex "not to state the truth, but to prevent its v (1978/1980:55). He accuses medicine of a "will to nonknowie 1978/1980:55). Medicine is indicted for its systematic blindness, see and understand sex. Also involved in the morality of sexuality is religion, especially tianity, the confession (a kind of discourse), and the need for the s truth, especially about sexuality. In fact, as a result and more gen since become a singularly confessing society" (Foucault, 1978/19 sion about sex, and most other things, has found its way into med family relationships, love relationships, and so on. Power flows to a position to receive the information divulged in a confession, s ceive knowledge about individual sexuality. To Foucault, the wide confession comes down to the extortion of sexual knowledge fr was made peculiarly possible in the accident because science be in the sexual confession; those who received confessions were
They wrapped themselves in the cloak of science and came to see sex, and the dan gers flowing from it, everywhere. Because the dangers posed by sex were so ubiq uitous and because they were generally hidden, they had to be hunted down ruth lessly and tirelessly through such mechanisms as the confession. Further, those who listened to the confessions were supposed to be peculiarly endowed with the ability to interpret them. Therefore, it was the listener who "was the master of truth" (Foucault, 1978/1980:67). Once again, knowledge and power interpenetrate. Since it was deemed to be the possessor of the truth, science was in a position to determine what was normal and what was pathological sexuality. The sources of the, pathologies were hidden, and they needed to be ferreted out by the scientist (es'pecially psychoanalyst) empowered to listen to sexual confessions. Once the soutces of the sexual pathologies were uncovered, they were to be treated thera peutically by those very same scientists. All of this is related to the human sciences and their interest in gaining knowl edge of the subject. Subjects are asked to "confess" to social- scientists in inter views and in their responses to questionnaires. Social s-cientists have power over subjects, and the knowledge they obtain furthers that power. Based on their knowl edge, and the statistics they use to analyze it, the human sciences acquire the abil ity to distinguish between the normal and the pathological (or deviant). Thus, the human sciences can be traced in a variety of direct ways to the methods used by those in power to exercise control over sex. Foucault outlines a number of more general relations of power to sex that have a deleterious effect on sexuality. (However, Foucault recognizes that power also has a positive, constitutive effect on sexuality.) Power can insist on rules that limit sex uality by, for example, prescribing a specific order for sex. Power can prohibit sex and seek to have it renounce itself. Power can engage in censorship thereby silenc ing sex., Finally, the power apparatus operates in the same way at all levels and does not adapt itself to important differences in sexuality. Thus, even if it operates appropriately in one setting, the power apparatus will inevitably operate poorly in other settings. It is in this context that Foucault begins to clarify exactly what he means by power, or the "multiplicity of force relations imminent in the sphere in which they operate" (1978/1980:92). Thus, contrary to most established definitions, power is not an institution, a structure, a superstructure, or even a strength that people are endowed With. Power is omnipresent
riot because it has the privilege of consolidating everything under its invincible unity, but because it is produced from one moment to the next, at every point, or rather in every re lation from one point to another. Power is everywhere; not because it embraces every thing, but because it comes from everywhere.
Just as power is everywhere, the points of resistance to it are eve we are back again to the micro-politics of power. It is here (1978/1980:95-96) directly challenges Marx and the grand narrat "Hence there is no single locus of great Refusal, no soul of revolt, bellions, or pure law of the revolutionary. Instead there is a plurality each of them a special case." He is willing to admit that there are cal ruptures, but it is the small-scale eruptions that are much mor likely. Sex is an especially important area for the exercise of pow bursts of resistance to it. Starting in the seventeenth century, the power over life took tw The first, the anato1110-politics of the hUTnan body, involved the d body to optimize its capabilities and increase its use and its docili the bio-politics of population, involved the regulation of the popula and utilized controls to regulate biIths, mortality, level of health, witt, 1983). These two forms of control, taken together, repre change in that the sovereign powers switched from control through threat of it) to control through life. And, "it was taking charge of lif threat of death, that gave power its access even to the bo 1978/1980:143). Those in power sought the administration of bodi ment of life. Overall, "methods of power and knowledge assume for the life processes and undertook to control and modify th 1978/1980: 142). In other words, life itself had become an object trol. Thus, "sex was a means of access both to the life of the bod the species" (Foucault, 1978/1980: 146). But consistent with his orientation, Foucault argued that the control over sex and life wa whole series of specific tactics. Is there any hope of emancipation? Foucault seems to think so, one great revolutionary force but rather in a multiplicity of micro-f ing the importance of bodies and pleasure, rather than sex:
It is the agency of sex that we must break away from, if we aiIn-thro versal of the various mechanisms of sexuality-to counter the grips claims of bodies, pleasures, and knowledges, in their multiplicity and resistance. The rallying point for the counterattack against the deploy ought not to be sex-desire, but bodies and pleasures.
(Foucau
In the West, "the project of a science of the subject has gravitated ing circles, around the question of sex" (Foucault, 1978/1980:70). at ascertaining who we are have come to be increasingly directed sums this all up: "Sex, the explanation of everything" (1978/1980:
(Foucault, 1978/1980:93)
However, power does sometimes form comprehensive systems that can be ana lyzed and understood more or less independently, although it is often the case that no one planned them to operate in that way.
SELF AND SEXUALITY
Between the publication of the first volume of the history of sexu the publication of the later two volumes, The Use of Pleasure (198
Care of the Self (1984/1986), Foucault's substantive focus and theoretical orienta tion underwent another important shift (Bevis, Cohen, and Kendall, 1993; Harri son, 1987).1 Substantively, Foucault shifted from the modem West to Greco Roman culture between the fourth century B.C. and the second century A.D. Theoretically, Foucault (1984/1985: 12) moved from a genealogy of power to a ge nealogy of self~awareness, self-control, self-practices-as he puts it, a "genealogy of desiring man." He had grown afraid that had he stayed with the same period, he would have once again found a pattern of control and coercion, this time in the realm of sexuality. He concluded: "Rather than placing myself at the formation of the experience of sexuality, I tried to analyze the formation of a certain mode of re lation td the self in the experience of the flesh" (Foucault, in Miller, 1993:320). Here is the way Foucault describes his shift: I insisted maybe too much ... on techniques of domination ... other techniques [are im portant] ... techniques which permit individuals to effect a certain number of operations on the it own bodies, on their souls, on their own thoughts, on their own conduct, and this in a manner so as to transform themselves, modify themselves, or to act in a certain state of petfection, of happiness, of purity, of supernatural power, and so on. (Foucault, in Miller, 1993:321-322)
Before one could do a full-scale study of power in the later period, "it was es sential first to determine how, for centuries, Western man had been brought to rec ognize himself as a subject of desire" (Foucault, 1984/1985:6). As Foucault (1984/1985: 13; italics added) describes it, he was led "to substitute a history of ethical problematizations based on practices of the self, for a history of systems of morality based, hypothetically, on interdictions." Foucault also sees himself con tinuing to do an archaeology, this time of the problematization of sexuality, on how sexuality came to be a subject of concern. He makes it clear that his original plan was to study sexuality in modern West ern societies and to focus, among other things, on the "various mechanisms of re pression to which it [sexuality] was bound to be subjected in every society" (Fou cault, 1984/1985:4; italics added). He outlines three concerns in his overall study of sexuality: the formation of the sciences of sexuality, the power systems that reg ulate sexuality,2 and his focus in this later work, "the forms within which individu als are able, are obliged, to recognize themselves as subjects of this sexuality" (Foucault, 1984/1985:4). Thus, Foucault (1984/1985:6) changed his focus to "the slow formation, in an tiquity, of a hermeneutics of the self." He saw this as consistent with his long-term interest in the history of the truth, not "what might be true in the fields of learning, but an analysis of the 'games of truth' " (Foucault, 1984/1985:6). In fact, he claims that all his studies have been concerned with such "games." 1 A proposed fourth volume, The Confessions of the Flesh, concerned with the "formation of the doctrine and ministry concerning the flesh" (Foucault, 1984/1985:12), was never to be published. 2 Although, Foucault always recognizes that power is not simply one-way domination; it involves a variety of open strategies.
He takes as the key question in this research, "why is sexual con the activities and pleasures that attach to it, an object of moral solic cault, 1984/1985: 10). To put it another way, why has sexuality bec problematic"? In raising this question, Foucault makes it clear that s only a matter of power or of interdiction, but also a moral matter. The problematicization of sexuality is related to what Foucault ca existence," or the "techniques of the self":
those intentional and voluntary actions by which men not only set them conduct, but also seek to transfonn themselves, to change themselves i being, and to make their life into an oeuvre that carries certain aesth meets certain stylistic criteria. These "arts of existence," these "techniq no doubt lost some of their importance and autonomy when they were the exercise of priestly power in early Christianity, and later into educati psychological types of practice.
(Foucault, 1984/1985:10-11; italics added, ex
Thus, Foucault sees himself as writing a first chapter in the history of the self. Methodologically, Foucault focuses 110t on theoretical texts but scriptive, practical texts of the historical periods he is analyzing. Such individuals to question their own conduct, to watch over and give sha shape the11'lselves as ethical subjects" (Foucault, 1984/1985:13; italic Foucault often acknowledges continuity between the classical modem, Christian world. However, a key difference lies in the fac the modem world there is great compulsion surrounding sexual be classical world there was far less coercion. The classical world lack coherent, authoritarian moral system that was imposed on everyon manner" (Foucault, 1984/1985:21). Instead of focusing on the "inte manding sexual austerity, the focus instead in the classical world sh way sexual behavior came to be reflected on and became a subject o To Foucault, morality has two basic elelnents that can be disassoc another. The first are codes of behavior in which those in authority e tates of the code. The second are fonns of subjectivation, or practice is the latter that is focal in the classical world and of focal concer "Here the emphasis is on the forms of relations with the self, in th techniques by which he works them out, on the exercises by whic himself an object to be known, and on the practices that enable him his own mode of being" (Foucault, 1984/1985:30). Foucault identifies four central domains, four major areas of expe lationship to one's body, one's wife or maniage, boys, and the truth "stylization" are related to each of these focal concerns: body-diete economics, boys-erotics, truth-philosophy. More generally, Fo 1985:91) is concerned with aphrodisia, or "acts intended by nature nature with intense pleasure, and naturally motivated by a force that able to excess and rebellion."
Two Inajor variables are associated with aphrodisia in the classical world. First, there is a quantitative emphasis on things like moderation and excess and not a qualitative focus on the nature of the act. The issue was extent of involvement and not whether an act was good or bad. Excess was identified as a problem, and it was traced to a lack of self-restraint. Second, there is focus on role-polarity, especially active-passive, subject-object. The passive and object poles, identified with women, boys, and slaves, were more likely to be defined as problems. Men who were prone to excess and passivity were seen as immoral. Thus, sexual activity, and aphrodisia more generally, were not seen as problems in themselves. Indeed, they were viewed as natural and therefore incapable of being bad (this stood in stark contrast to the way sexuality came to be viewed in the modern Christian world). But while it was not condemned, sexuality was nonetheless a subject of moral concern. The moral concern, however, was the proper use of sexuality and not the sexual act per se. Thus, the focus was not on a moral code to prohibit certain actions but rather "to work out the conditions and modalities of a 'use,' that is, to define a style for ... the use of pleasures ... his way of conducting himself in such matters" (Foucault, 1984/1985:53; italics added). The issue was to carefully distribute and control one's acts; to be prudent, reflective, and calculating in how one behaved. Three issues were central in reflecting on the use of pleasure. The first was the individual's need. However, since individual needs vary, it was impossible to come up with a code or a law that applied to everyone, everywhere. Rather than being amenable to codification, moderation required "an art, a practice of pleasures that was capable of self-lin1itation" (Foucault, 1984/1985:57; italics added). The sec ond was timeliness, practices that took place at the right time and involved the right amount. The third was status; the proper use of pleasure varied with the user's social status. Again, it is clear that no code could be developed to handle di mensions with such a high degree of variation. Instead of the code, the focus in classical society was on one's attitude, espe cially the "domination of oneself by oneself' (Foucault, 1984/1985:65). This was perceived as a constant struggle. Foucault (1984/1985:73) also uses another con cept in this context, "care of the self," meaning the ability "to attend effectively to the self, and to exercise and transform oneself." This self-mastery was not only im portant to the individual but also the state. One who showed power over oneself, self-restraint, was seen as possessing the ability needed to rule over others. How could one rule others if one could not rule oneself? Such restraint was also seen as being "manly" or "virile," while immoderation was associated with femininity. However, the dividing line between manliness and femininity did not coincide, as it later came to, with the distinction between heterosexuality and homosexuality. Foucault offers a succinct contrast between classical and modem society. In the classical world, the control of aphrodisia was not defined by a universal legislation determining permitted and forbidden acts, but rather by a savoir-faire, an art that prescribed the modalities of a use that depended on different variables (need, time, status) ... In the Christian morality of sexual behavior
... Subjection was to take the form not of a savoir-faire, but of a recog and an obedience to pastoral authority.
(Foucault, 19
The way in which the classical Greeks handled dietetics (another closely tied to the way they dealt with sexuality. Especially importa opment of a diet, a regimen that ultimately led to "a whole art of liv 1984/1985:101). Dietetics served to problematize the body and help medicine. Importance was given to both care of the body and soul; the body (with medicines) was seen as necessary for care of the sou mens). Regimens required vigilance vis-a.-vis the self and led to "a of forming oneself as a subject" (Foucault, 1984/1985:108). Mode key to a regimen, and sex acts eventually came to be seen as a prop regimen and moderation. Two basic reasons were behind the vigilance associated with sex was concern over deleterious effects of excess on the body; less w sidered better than more. (This is one of the places where the classic ipates the modem: "In this dietetics . . . one perceives the emergen tendency toward a restrictive economy" [Foucault, 1984/1985:118 was concern about the well-being of the progeny. For example, if p old, or had poor diets, their offspring might suffer. Other anxieties were associated with the sex act. First, the form example, the violence of it) could be a problem. Second, there was cost, especially the expenditure of bodily fluids. Finally, there was with death, at least as contrasted to the life giving of procreation. important to reiterate that anxiety existed not because sex was seen
but because it disturbed and threatened the individual's relationship wit integrity as an ethical subject in the making; it was not properly meas uted, it carried the threat of a breaking forth of involuntary forces, a les and death without honourable descendants.
(Foucault, 198
FoucauIt (1984/1985: 153) also relates this to economics, whic "the practice of commanding." The economic art was practiced n ness but also in managing the city, the household, and even one's mastery was demonstrated, perhaps most elegantly, in having sexua with one's wife. This kind of self-mastery was seen as a mor for managing others. But again this was a matter of style, (1984/1985:181) does not "see in this the first outlines of an ethi conjugal fidelity, or the beginnings of a codification of married life tianity was to give a universal form, an imperative value, and th whole institutional system." In his discussion of erotics, defined as the "purposeful art of (1984/1985:229) focuses on relations with boys (with men), relat
Classical Age were not seen as the opposite of heterosexual relations. Thus, the moral issue was excess, whether it involved homosexual or heterosexual relation ships. Self-control involves the ability to abstain from either homosexual or hetero sexual relations. Nevertheless, the relationship between men did come to be defined as problem atic. It became a moral preoccupation, and a special style came to surround it, but it did not come to be prohibited. An issue was likely to arise when there was a great disparity in the ages of the participants. The passivity of at least one of the partners was also considered problematic. After all, a passive boy might well be come "a free man, master of himself and capable of prevailing over others" (Fou cault, 1984/1985:221). Boys were likely to be condemned if their style was bad; for example, -if they yielded too easily. Thus, homosexuality was accepted, but it certainly·was not a matter of indifference. The concern that existed was for the ob ject of pleasure, the boys. This was to stand in contrast to Christian society where the concern would focus on the subject and the question: How could a man desire a boy or another man? Finally, . Foncault turns to the issue of truth. He argues that it was around the love of boys "that the question of the relations between the use of pleasures and ac cess· to the truth was developed, in the form of an inquiry into the nature of true love" (Foucault, 1984/1985:229). Again, Foucault here sees a forerunner to mod ern Christian society in which questions of truth, love, and pleasure will come to be raised in the context of male-female relationships. It is with the issue of truth that Foucault begins The Care of the Self. Specifi cally, he undertakes a discursive analysis of Artemidorius's treatise on how to in terpret dreams, that is, on finding the truth that the dream reveals. More generally, we have here the beginnings of the search for truth within oneself. In those dream analyses, Foucault sees much consistency in the frrst two cen turies A.D. with what he found in the earlier time period (roughly the four cen turies B.C.) analyzed in The Use of Pleasure. For example, the code and its prohi bitions are of negligible importance in sexuality. There is also a focus not on the act but the actor (who dreams), the subject, and his style. As before, Foucault focuses on practical advice texts, and while there are revi sions in the doctrine of austerity from the earlier period, these are not radical changes; they do not represent a new way of experiencing pleasure. But there is a change in inflection, "a closer attention, an increased anxiety concerning sexual conduct, a greater importance accorded to maniage and its demands, and less value given to the love of boys: in short, a more rigorous style" (Foucault, 1984/1986:36). Furthermore, there is a change in "the way in which ethical thought de:(ines the relation of the subject to his sexual activity" (Foucault, 1984/1986:36). The literature of the first two centuries A.D. seemed to adopt a more severe attitude toward sexuality, and there was a more intense problematization of it. And it was froIn this that later, modern, Christian authors borrowed heavily. While there were changes, they did not represent a dramatic shift to a focus on interdictions, or a tightening of the code, but rather "an intensification of the rela tion to oneself by which one constituted oneself as the subject of one's acts" (Fou cault, 1984/1986:41). This, in turn, was to have a wide-ranging series of effects:
It also took the fonn of an attitude, a mode of behavior; it became in living; it evolved into procedures, practices and formulas that people re oped, perfected and taught. It thus came to constitute a social practice g tionships between individuals, to exchanges and communications, and stitutions. And it gave rise, finally, to a certain lnode of knowledge and a science.
(Foucault, 1984/1986
Force is now required to deal with sexual pleasure, but it is
forc~ that comes from within, through self-mastery, rather than f
new art of living is required. And this requires a greater importan self-knowledge:
The task of testing oneself, examining oneself, monitoring oneself in defined exercise, makes the question of truth-the truth concerning one does, and what one is capable of doing-eentral to the formation ject. Lastly, the end result of this elaboration is still and always defined individual over himself. But this rule broadens into an experience in w to self takes the form not only of a domination but also of an enjoym and without disturbance.
(Foucault, 1984/1986
While this is different from the earlier period studied by Foucault, ent from what is to come:
One is still far from an experience of sexual pleasure where the latter with evil, where behavior will have to submit to the universal form the deciphering of desire will be a necessary condition for acceding tence. Yet one can already see how the question of evil begins to work theme of force, how the question of law begins to modify the theme and how the question of truth and the principle of self-knowledge evo cetic practices.
(Fouca
The emergence of the new stylistics of existence, the cult of traced to changes in marriage and politics. Politics came to be see tice, and hence a linkage was established between oneself and poli government of others was equated with the rational government ability to govern oneself, to exercise self-restraint, came to be see site for a good politician. In the domestic relationship, Foucault sees a change toward gr and equality in husband-wife relationships. In fact, a more intense self is closely tied to the increased valorization of the other. Mor tention to oneself and devotion to conjugal life could be closely a cault, 1984/1986: 163). Marriage becomes more of an art and les power or mastery. In this art, sexual relations take on a greater ro
Greeks were comparatively silent on sex, especially in comparison to the "meticu lous attentiveness" of later Christians who "will then attempt to regulate every thing: positions, frequency" [Foucault, 1984/1986:165]). The Greeks did have principles related to matrimonial sexuality, but they did little to regulate and con trol those behaviors or to distinguish permitted from forbidden forms of sexuality. Ov~rall, Foucault sees an increase in the value accorded to sexual relations in mar riage, and this helps to contribute to an increased questioning of the love of boys. In this, power over oneself is dissociated from power over others. This helped lead to·asimilardissociation in social, civic, and political life. Medicine, with its focus on illness and the body, led to a way of living, to a way of reflecting upon oneself. People were urged to care for themselves, to follow a regimen in order to avoid needing to see a physician about illness. This led to a problematization of the body and its relationship to the environment. One was led to devote constant attention to oneself and one's body. It is in the context of the notion of a regimen that medicine framed the issue of sexual pleasure. Sexual abstinence and self-restraint, as far as sex is concerned (es pecially, with other men), were considered to be desirable. There· was an ambiva lent attitude toward sex since it was seen as both therapeutic and potentially patho logical. Care of one's body was seen as essential to avoiding the pathologies. AlTIOng the regimens to which sex was subjected were the ideas that there was an "auspicious occasion for procreation," that there was a proper "age of the subject" (not too old, for example), and that "individual temperament" was important (Fou cault, 1984/1986:125). However, not just the body, but also the soul was to be sub Jected to a regimen. Thus, people were to avoid being carried beyond the needs of the organiSlTI. For example, sex was never to be forced, and certain images were to be avoided. Foucault sees in this the beginning of the "pathologization" of sex, but again it was radically different from what was to take place later. For example, un like in modern times, sex was not regarded as an "evil" in Greco-Roman culture. In the first two centuries of our era, the love of boys continued to be seen as nat ural, although reflection on it lost some intensity, seriousness, vitality, and topical ity. What changed was not the taste for boys, or the value judgments aimed at those with such tastes, but rather "the way in which one questioned oneself about it" (Foucauit, 1984/1986:189). Most generally, the love of boys came to be seen as "incapable of defining a style of living, an aesthetics of behavior, and a whole modality of relation to oneself, to others, and to truth" (Foucault, 1984/1986:192; italics added). A boundary emerged between the two types of sex, a boundary that persists to this day. However, there was, as yet, no rigid line dividing heterosexual and homosexual acts. Love of boys and love of one's wife continued to exist as two different styles of life. In addition, different philosophies, or means of searching for the truth, accom panied them. Thus, "in the pederastic argumentation, pleasure with a woman can not be reciprocal because it is accompanied by too much falseness ... In contrast, pleasure with boys is placed under the sign of truth" (Foucault, 1984/ 1986:223-224; italics added). Overall, Foucault sees a strengthening of austerity themes around the first cen turies of our era, although in his earlier book he detailed similar themes in the four
centuries B.C. Again, however, such tightening does not stand at Christian ethics
when the sexual act itself will be considered evil, when it \vill no longe imacy except within the conjugal relationship, and when the love of demned as unnatural.
(Foucaul
Instead of increasing prohibitions, what marked this early era wa preoccupation. Foucault closes with a view of what is to come Christian world:
Those moral systems will define other modalities of the relation to se tion of the ethical substance based on finitude, the Fall, and evil; a mod the fornl of obedience to a general law that is at the same time the will a type of work on oneself that implies a decipherment of the soul hermeneutics of the desires; and a mode of ethical fulfillment that te nunciation ... a profoundly altered ethics and ... a different way of co as the ethical subject of one's sexual behavior.
(Policault, 19 SUMMARY
In this chapter we have examined Foucault's later work on sexualit three works, he continues his interest in the relationship between po edge, this time in the realm of sexuality. Contrary to popular belief plosion of interest in sexuality in seventeenth-century Victorian s power sought to incite such interest and in the process to gain con ity. Foucault does not see a single source of such power. Rather, the itics of power, which is often met with resistance at many points of In his last two books, Foucault's work underwent a dramatic looking at the West in the seventeenth to nineteenth centuries, Fou attention to Greece and Rome in the centuries immediately befo birth of Christ. Instead of a genealogy of power, he sought to do self-awareness, self-practices, and self-control in the realm of sexu he saw the need to discover how people came to see themselves as jects of sexuality, before undeltaking (although he obviously had such work) a study of how that desire was the subject of the exerc external agencies. Another way of putting Foucault's focal interes for how sexuality came to be considered a moral issue. Over th study, Foucault sees the emergence of the care of the self as far as cerned, but this is very different from the external and coercive con emerge with the rise of Christianity. While there is some increase i of attitudes toward sexuality in the Greco-Roman periods examin control still stemmed from the self rather than from external sour Foucault's last two books on sexuality constitute a "prequel" to th tory of Sexuality, Part 1.
cault) into a box, or according him a nice, comfortable label,
thing to do and flies in the face of much that postmodem social In fact, as we have seen, Foucault fought strenuously against ef
JEAN BAUDRILLARD:
him and his ideas. Much more important questions are: Has Bau
fluenced the thinking of those who regard themselves as postmod
PART 1:THE BAS\C
Baudrillard's ideas useful in thinking about postmodem societ
both of these questions is an unequivocal "yes," and it is for that r
THEORET\CAL \DEAS
consider Baudrillard to be a postmodern social theorist. Similarly, and perhaps equally wrongheadedly, others have w
drillard a sociologist? While Baudrillard taught sociology and s fies himself with sociology, he generally distances himself from
CONSUMER SOCIETY THE BREAK WITH MARX AND MARXISM SYMBOLIC EXCHANGE
I prefer singularities, exceptional events. Sociology is, I think, a redu I don't consider myself to be deeply sociological. I work more on sy on sociological data.
ALTHOUGH there are difficulties involved in categorizing Michel Foucault, Jean Baudlillard must surely and unequivocally be a postmodernist. After all, his work has had a profound effect on postmodem social theory, and it has influenced postmodernists in a wide range of fields (Bertens, 1995). In fact, most observers regard him as not only a postmodernist but the most important representative of that approach (e.g., Kellner, 1994). However, Baudrillard's status as a social thinker is not as clear-cut as many believe. Baudrillard himself rarelyl uses the term post1110dern and is sometimes even hostile to it as a description of his orienta tion (Gane, 1993). For example, Baudrillard says the following: there is no such thing as postmodemism. If you interpret it this way, it is obvious that I do not represent this emptiness ... It doesn't have anything to do with me ... I don't recognize myself in all this.
(Baudrillard,
I'm neither a sociologist nor an anti-sociologist. Sociology was wh university, certainly. But from the point of view of a discipline, I left i going into semiology, psychoanalysis, Marxism.
(Baudrillard,
Baudrillard's best-known statement on this issue is the following:
My point of view is completely metaphysical. If anything, I'm a meta a moralist, but certainly not a sociologist. The only "sociological" w my effort to put an end to the social, to the concept of the social.
(Baudrillard, in Gane, 1933:22-23)
(in Gane, 1993:
In fact, Gane (1991 b:55) goes even further and argues that "Baudrillard's whole ef fort is to combat [postmodernism]." For example, Baudrillard (1980-1985/ 1990: 150) sees postmodernity as the, "most degraded" historical phase. Postmod ern society is viewed as having closed off opportunities opened by the end of mod ernism. Thus, in Gane's view, Baudrillard is opposed to both modernism and post modernism. To further complicate matters, Kellner (1994: 14; italics added) says, "Gane is c0111pletely wrong to claim that Baudrillard's problematic should not be interpreted as concerned with the postmodern." And, as if the situation is not al ready confusing enough, according to Zurbrugg (1993), Baudrillard combines lnodern and postmodem approaches. While the debate over whether Baudrillard is, or is not, a postmodemist is inter esting, it raises perhaps the wrong question. After all, putting Baudrillard (or Fou 1 Although,
76
as we will see in Chapter 6, it does appear more often in his later work.
Despite the unequivocal character of this declaration, if we exami Baudrillard's statements on this issue, there is at least as much
whether or not he is a sociologist as there is over whether or not to think of him as a postmodernist. However, again we are prob wrong question. The real issue is: Have Baudrillard's ideas influ ing of sociologists? The fact is that while the thinking of many some of whom are sociologists, has been influenced by Baudrilla
2 He also distances himself from academia in general. Note the following acid could also analyze the academic congress (of scholars, of intellectuals, of sociolo transmission [of knOWledge], of hereditary reproduction of the intelligentsia and o munity on the basis of an agonistic debauch of signs. Conferences are almost as use ment of knOWledge as horse races and parimutuels to the advancement of the e drillard, 1972/1981:122).
mainstream sociologists are more or less oblivious to his ideas.3 However, it is possible, even likely, that Baudrillard's influence on sociology will grow in the coming years. It would be useful to pause here and attempt to deal with another question: What does Baudrillard mean in the quotation in the preceding paragraph by the end of the social? Fundamentally, he means that the social has dissolved, "imploded," into the mass. That is, key social factors like class and ethnic differences have disap peared with the creation of a huge, undifferentiated mass. We will have more to say about his ideas on the mass, especially in the next chapter, but at this juncture it is important to point out that to Baudrillard the mass is to be thought of as a statistical category and not as a social collectivity. Since the mass is a nonsocial (rather, a sta tistical) category, and since the social has imploded into it, the social is dead. If the social is dead, then sociology, which takes the social as its subject matter, must be dead from Baudrillard's point of view. Thus, we need a new way of thinking about the world and a whole new vocabulary to think about it. As we wiil see, Baudrillard goes a long way toward creating such a new way of thinking and such a new vocab ulflry (mass, for example, takes on a whole new [nonsocial] meaning in his work). Another, perhaps misguided, question: Is Baudrillard a theorist? On the surface it seelns abundantly clear that he is. After all, he is offering a series of general, ab stract ideas about the nature of society. However, there are problems involved in thinking about Baudrillard as a theorist. • For example, since theory is usually oriented to ascertaining truth, and Bau drillard makes it plain that truth does not exist, can we really think of him as a the orist? Rather than seek truth, "the only thing you can do [with theory] is play with some kind of provocative logic" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993:124). • Similarly, because he rejects the real, Baudrillard's approach is really an "an tisocial theory"4 in the sense that he has rejected the traditional end of social the ory "to represent or reflect the real, or to critically engage with the real" (Smart, 1993b:52). • Baudrillard (1990/1993: 110) also believes that it is impossible to predict what will happen with the result that "theory can be no more than this: a trap set in the hope that reality [which, contradictorily, Baudrillard has rejected] will be naive enough to fall into it." Baudrillard pushes theory to such an extreme, to pataphysics (an idea developed by Alfred Jan)'), that many do not consider it to be theory. Baudrillard (1976/1993:5) sees great importance in pataphysics, or " 'a science of imaginary solutions'; that is, a science-fiction of the system's reversal against itself at the ex trelne limit of simulation." He argues that pataphysics is the only way to combat the lnore real than real (the "hyperreal") system in which we live. Thus, 3 A few have been negatively affected by Baudrillard's assault on many of sociology's most basic beliefs. 4 As we saw in Chapter 1, Antonio (1995) has recently depicted Nietzsche, a powerful influence on Baudlillard, as doing an "antisociology." I
I'm not interested in realism ... My books are scenarios. I play out t It's a game, a provocation. Not in order to put a full stop to everyth trary, to make everything begin again. So you see, I'm far from being
(Baudrillard, in G
Or, "What I try to do is to issue a challenge to meaning and to them and to play with them" (Baudlillard, in Gane, 1993: 137 writing is a "fatal strategy,"5 which impels him to go to extreme tremity of his positions as a political act: "Indeed, writing is the that I am capable of' (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993: 181). In the v Turner (1993:xi), Baudrillard's pataphysical work is "closer to t sci-fi than those of -sociology [and sociological theory]." S (1994:13) says, "I prefer to read Baudrillard's work as a science ticipates the future by exaggerating present tendencies and thu warnings about what might happen if present trends continue." Or, is Baudrillard better thought of as a poet? (He did, in fact, admitted that,
behind all my theoretical and analytical formulations, there are al aphorism, the anecdote and the fragment. One could caU that poetry. (B audlillard,
But, if he is at times a poet, at other times he is more of a theorist. Thus, it is clearly hard to pin Baudrillard down. Postmodern Theorist? Science fiction writer? Poet? Baudrillard is all of those, those. How postmodern! It should come as no surprise that it is, if anything, even l110re d the nature of the work than it is to unambiguously identify the au least two reasons for this. First, Baudrillard often resists being other things, refusing to clearly define even his most fundament ond, over the years, Baudrillard's work has undergone many sig Thus, there are a number of different theoretical perspectives de drillard over the course of his career. While there is some continui work, there is also much change. CONSUMER SOCIETY
Baudrillard's (1968, 1970; Wernick, 1991) early work is heavily i Marxian perspective and its focus on the economy. However, whil traditional Marxists focused on production, Baudrillard concern consumption. By focusing on consumption, Baudrillard joined m his day, critical theorists in palticular, in moving in the direction o analysis. However, early in his career Baudrillard was more Marx hi~ peers: "Baudtillard remains in many senses on the ground of 5
See the next chapter for much more on what Baudrillard means by a fatal stra
giving more weight to economic and material processes in cultural analysis than otller Marxists of this period" (Gane, 1991a:70-71). Foreshadowing a lifelong interest, even preoccupation, with America as a para digITI for the rest of the world (one of his later books was entitled A111erica; see the following chapter), Baudri11ard sees America as the home of the consumer society. However, Europe is viewed as witnessing an "irreversible trend towards the Ameri can Inodel" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988: 11). Once Europe adopted the American consumption lTIodel, there would be a consolidation of consumption that would "hannoniously conform to the complete consolidation and control of production" (BaudrilIard, in Poster, 1988: 12). Thus, despite his focus on consumption, in the early stages of his career Baudrillard took a traditional Marxist position and con tinued to accord ultimate primacy to production. In fact, he sees the objects of con sumption as being "orchestrated by the order of production" (BaudrilIard, in Poster, 1988:22). Or, in other words, "needs and consumption are in fact an orga nizedextension ofproductive forces" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:43). Despite this apparent acceptance of a simple base-superstructure model (at least in this early stage of his work), BaudIillard accords considerable importance to consumption. As Gane (1991a:57) argues, consumption is not "some slight addition to the circuit of capital ... but [i]s a crucial productive force for capital itself." The young Baudrillard was also influenced by the structuralists, including the structural linguists. As a result, he sees the system of consumer objects and the comluunication system at the base of adveliising as forming "a code of significa tion," . which exerts control over both objects and individuals in society. As Genosko (1994:xiii) puts it, "Baudrillard's central claim is that objects have be come signs whose value is determined by a disciplinary code." This is our first en counter with the central, slippery, and changing concept of the "code" in Bau drillard's work. We will have much more to say about this concept throughout this chapter and the next, but for now we can, following Genosko, define it as a con trolling system of signs. To put it another way, "The code in its most general sense is a system of rules for the combination of stable sets of terms into messages" (Genosko, 1994:36). Objects, in this case objects of consumption, are part of this sign system. Thus, we can think in terms of a "discourse of objects," and, as a re sult, everyone is able to "read" and comprehend such communication (Baudrillard, 1972/1981 :37). When we consume objects, we are consuming signs, and in the process are defining ourselves. Thus, categories of objects are seen as producing categories of persons. "Through objects, each individual and each group searches out his or her place in an order, all the while trying to jostle this order according to a personal trajectory. Through objects a stratified society speaks ... in order to keep everyone in a certain place" (Baudrillard, 1972/1981:38). In other words, people are (to a large extent) what they consume and are differentiated from other types of people on the basis of consumed objects. Counterintuitively, what we consume is not so luuch objects, but signs. "Consumption ... is a systelnatic act of the manipulation of signs. ... In order to heeolne object of eonsulnption, the object Inust beeolne sign" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:22). In consuming certain objects we are signi fying (although not consciously) that we are similar to those who also consume
those objects and that we are different from those who consume oth tbe coue, then, that cantta\~ what we c\.a, a\lc\. c\.o \lot, COl\sume. To the layperson, the world of consuml1tion seems, on the surf free. After all, if we have the money (or better yet today, the credit to be free to buy whatever we want. But in fact we are free to con ginally different objects and signs. Further, in consumption w unique, but in fact we closely resemble everyone else in our social of that group consume much the same thing. Thus, it is clear that w as free as we think ,;ye are. In another counterintuitive idea, Baudrillard argues that in a wor the code, consumption ceases to have anything to do with the sati we conventionally think of as "needs." The idea of needs is derive separation of subject and object; the idea of needs is created to co end result is a tautology with subjects and objects defined in term .; (subjects need objects; objects are what subjects need). Baudrillard struct the subject-object dichotomy and, more generally, the notio do not buy what we need, but rather what the code tells us we sho needs themselves are determined by the code so that we end up "ne code tells us we need; "there are only needs because the system ne drillard, 1972/1981:82). Consumption also does not have anything to do with what we think of as "reality." Instead, consumption is about "the systemat possession of object-signs of consumption" (Baudrillard, in P These object-signs, and the code of which they are part, are not " point of view, when we purchase a Big Mac at McDonald's w mainly) buying food, but rather we are procuring what a Big Ma us (for example, that we are part of the fast-paced, mobile society not afford to eat filet mignon). In the consumer society controlled by the code, human relation transformed into relationships with objects, especially the consu objects. Says Baudrillard (in Poster, 1988:29), "we are living the p jects." These objects no longer have meaning because of their utility (or their "use value," in Marx's terms 6 ); nor do they acqu longer from concrete relationships between people. Rather, the me ject comes from its relationship to, and/or difference from, other o lection, or network, of objects comes to have a meaning and logic objects are signs (they have sign value rather than use or exchang consumption of those object-signs constitutes a language that we derstand. Commodities are purchased as an "expression and mar tige, luxury, power, and so on" (Kellner, 1994:4). Thus, we all kn
6 Marx privileges use value in comparison to exchange value, which is ab fetishistic. Baudrillard argues that use value has similar characteristics and therefo by political economists. He goes further to argue that because it is based on an ah thropology, "use value fetishism is indeed more profound, more mysterious than change value" (Baudrillard, 1972/1981:139). As a result, use value cannot be pos as an alternative to exchange value, as a revolutionary hope.
all know the "code") that a BMW is preferred to a Hyundai not because it is more useful but rather because in the system of car objects the BMW has far higher sta tus than the Hyundai. To Baudrillard (in Poster, 1988:29), following Thorstein Ve blen, we have become a society characterized by "conspicuousness of consump tion and affluence." Again, we seek to align ourselves with some and differentiate ourselves from others on the basis of the object-signs we consume. What we come to need in cap italism is not a particular object (say a BMW) but rather we seek difference, and by being different we acquire social status and social meaning. In consumption in modern capitalist society, it is not pleasure, not the pleasure of obtaining and using an object that we seek, but rather difference. This also leads to the view that when they are defined in this way, needs can never be satisfied; we have a contin uing, lifelong need to differentiate ourselves from those who occupy other posi tions in society. Baudrillard (in Poster, 1988:46) concludes, "consumption is a system which as sures the regulation of signs and the integration of the group: it is simultaneously a morality (a system of ideological values) and a system of communication, a struc ture of exchange ... this structural organization by far transcends individuals and [is] ilnposed on them." While there are a number of noteworthy aspects of this statelnent, the idea that consumption is a form of communication is worth under scoring. That is, when we consume something, we are communicating a number of things to others, including what groups we do and do not belong to. Others know the "language" with the result that they understand what we are saying when we purchase a BMW rather than a Hyundai. In these views on consumption, Baudrillard's (in Poster, 1988:46) linkages to structuraliSlTI are clear: "consumption is a system of meaning like language [Saus sure}, or like the kinship system in primitive societies [Levi-Strauss]." The follow ing is an even clearer articulation of Baudrillard's structuralism: Marketing, purchasing, sales, the acquisition of differentiated commodities and object/signs-all of these presently constitute our language, a code with which our en tire society communicates and speaks of and to itself. Such is the present day structure of COffilTIunication: a language (langue) in opposition to which individual needs and pleasures are but the effects of speech (parole). (in Poster, 1988:48)
While in this and many other ways Baudrillard uses structuralism, it should be made clear that in many more ways, especially in his later work, he is critical of, if not downlight hostile, to it. The central importance of consumption indicates a profound change in capital iSln. In the nineteenth century capitalists concentrated on regulating workers and left consumers largely on their own. In the twentieth century the focus shifted to consumers who could no longer be allowed to decide whether or not to consume or how much or what to consume. Capitalism has come to need to be sure that people participate, and participate actively and in particular ways, in the consumer society. Baudrillard goes so far as to view consumption as "sociallabor" and to compare its
control and exploitation to that of productive labor in the workpla other way, capitalism has created an exploitable "consuming 1991a:65). Not only is the system of consumption controlling, bu prevent the kind of collective revolutionary action hoped for by M are assigned collectively to a place in relationship to the code, "wit giving rise to any collective solidarity (but quite the opposite)" Poster, 1988:55). Thus, it is difficult to envision a social revolution those busy trying to acquire the money needed to be the consume ple, BMWs rather than Hyundais. As a result, it is worth noting has launched a critical analysis of, and assault on, consumer socie ing a revolutionary subject like Marx's proletariat to overthrow it. In this early work, Baudrillard still thinks in terms of social cla are defined not by objects or consumption but by their econom power and in their ability to manipulate signs and people. The H classes lack these powers with the result that they are left to dwel consumption. Furthermore, the code is not yet autonomous from conflict. The code works to the advantage of the ruling class; ind (1972/1981:119) sees the code as "the keystone of domination." In the code will become increasingly autonomous and, if anything, trolling. In fact, he concludes early on that class domination may h historical interlude and that society is coming again, as it was p dominated by signs and the code. Yet even at this early stage Baudrillard clearly wants to broaden cal economy and to integrate the consumption of signs, and mo code, into it. He contrasts this to the vulgar Marxian position that cu signs and the code) is an epiphenomenon controlled and manipulat nant class. Thus, in contrast to the vulgar Marxian view, to Baudril in the realm of production would not mean the downfall of culture a Baudrillard also uses the idea of "means of consumption" as Marxian concept of the means of production. While he has bee structuralism, it is once again clear that at least in his early work mains embedded, at least in part, in a Marxian material base. His p new means of consumption seems to be the distinctively French though he immediately offers the far more general and significant s an alternative model. To Baudrillard, the (French) drugstore (and the mall) is a synt sion and calculation ... mak[ing] possible the synthesis of all con not [the] least of which are shopping, flirting with objects, idle wa the permutations of these" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:31). The ke be "idle exploration," and in this sense the drugstore (and shoppin suited, in Baudrillard's view, to modern consumption than the which people are more likely to be task oriented and to shop for th that they need.
7 The French dlugstore is more like a miniature department store than what Am a drugstore (or phannacy).
However, in this analysis of the drugstore, Baudrillard not only retains some of his Marxian materialism, he also combines it with elements of his structuralist po sition. He does this by arguing that the function of the drugstore is different from that of the supermarket, where the objective is to allow the customer easy access to everyday consumables. Instead, the drugstore "practices an amalgalnation of signs where all categories of goods are considered a partial field in a general con sumeriSlTIof signs" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:32). Thus, already the focus is on the systenl of signs, the code, and not the specific commodity or the particular set ting in which the commodity is marketed and purchased. Baudrillard goes on to discuss the shopping mall more directly. While the con temporary terminology was not yet available to him, Baudrillard recognizes the importance of what the shopping center does to time and space (Giddens, 1984; Harvey, 1989). In terms of time, the mall is "completely indifferent to seasonal changes. creat[ing] a perpetual springtime ... one need not be the slave of time. The .mall, like every city street, is accessible seven days a week, day or night" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:34). The mall also eliminates space restrictions by of fering Jor sale a wide array of goods from virtually any place in the world. Bau ddllard concludes, "Here we are at the heart of consumption as the total organiza tion of everyday life, as a complete homogenization ... perpetual shopping ... the super.· shopping center, our new pantheon, our pandemonium, brings together all the gods, or delllons, of consumption" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:34-35). In this nearly hysterical world of consumerism, what is lost in the process is the possibil ity of obtaining any sort of meaning from consumption. Baudrillard recognizes at this early stage the importance of the credit card to the shopping mall, and more generally to the consumer society (Ritzer, 1995). As he puts it, "The card frees us from checks, cash, and even from financial difficulties at the end of the month" (Baudrillard, in Poster, 1988:34). Consumer society is a place where everything is for sale. Not only are all com lnodities signs, but all signs are commodities. Given the latter, all "objects, ser ~ices,bodies, sex, culture, knowledge, etc." are produced and exchanged (Bau driUard, 1972/1981:147-148). Signs, commodities, and culture are indissolubly intertwined. High art, corn flakes, the human body, sex acts, and abstract theory are all signs, and they are all for sale. Baudrillard is clearly critical of the consumer society, viewing it as creating a series of perverse desires and a generalized hysteria (Gane, 1991a). However, one is forced to wonder about the basis for such a critique. Without an "Archimedean point," how can Baudrillard make these kinds of negative judgments about the con sumer society? Bauman makes this point, at least in terms of changing the world, in reference to Baudrillard's work: 0
0
With all solid ground flushed away by the effluvia of decomposing reality, there is no Archimedes ' point left, either accessible or at least imaginable, on which one could pivot the lever needed to force the derailed world back on track. (Bauman, 1992:152)
This is a pressing issue because Baudrillard has rejected, especia work, "essentialist" theories (like Marxism) that would have give Archimedean point. Such theories are based on the idea that the cur distortion "of a real, and genuine l human form of consumption" (G For example, following Marx, Marcuse is seen as someone who identifiable set of essential, innocent, human needs which can be th lenge against the modern system" (Gane, 1991b:87). Baudlillard (in Gane, 1993:193) is left without any "criter whether the things people do are good or bad." As we will see, tempts to address this issue with his concept of "symbolic excha (1991b:81) puts it, symbolic exchange is "adopted as a basic univ substructural necessity, and therefore as a position from which a can be made to contemporary society." However, this raises the qu Baudrillard end up creating the kind of essentialist theory he wa when it was adopted by Marcuse and other Marxists? This is lent fact that Gane (1991a:76) describes sYlnbolic exchange as a ki communism." That the idea of symbolic exchange becomes Baudrillard's Arch at least for a time, is made clear by Gane (1991 b:7) who sees all work as based on his ideas on symbolic exchange: "His project mus an assault on the 'disenchanted' world [the modern world has lost i from the point of view of a militant of the symbolic (enchanted but More specifically, Baudrillard is engaged in a "general examinatio ences between symbolic and semiological order" (Gane, 1991a:7 more aggressive terms, we can say that Baudrillard's work invo against the dominance of signs in the name of symbolic exchange (G THE BREAKWITH MARX AND MARXISM
The Mirror of Production (Baudrillard, 1973/1975) is notable bec drillard makes a radical break with Marx and Marxian theory.8 Th as we have seen, that Baudrillard had not critiqued the Marxists ea ple, in a slightly earlier work he talks of "the Marxist vulgat 1972/1981: 145). However, it is in the Mirror that we find a full-blo The title of this work is of great significance. Baudrillard argu his theory of capitalism, had created a lnin·or image of theolies o capitalist society. While Marx may have produced an invelied imag it was nonetheless an image that was profoundly shaped and disto ism. Thus, Baudrillard accuses Marx (and implicitly himself in his not making a sufficiently radical break with capitalism and the the ism produced by the political econolnists and others: "Marx mad tique of political economy, but still in the fOIID of political econom
8 Baudrillard seeks a similar break with Freud and the psychoanalysts and Sa guists.
1973/1975:50). Marx is viewed as accepting the fundamental concepts and tenets of the supporters and theorists of capitalism~ he is seen as having "changed nothing basic" in that set of ideas (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:33). Thus, one of the most radi cal of thinkers is now seen as not being radical enough for Baudrillard's tastes. More generally, Marxism, as a school of thought, is seen as being infected by the "virus of bourgeois thought" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:39). F:urthermore, in continuing to mirror capitalism, later Marxists are accused of aiding and abetting that systen1: "Marxisn'l assists the cunning of capital" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:31). As a result of this unconscious complicity, Baudrillard (1973/1975:50) concludes that he wants to be "finished with a Marxism that has become more of a specialist in the impasses of capitalism than in the roads to revolution." In other words, his objective is to do what Marx and the Marxists failed to do-break the mirror of production to open up new, truly revolutionary possibilities (although, as we will see in the next chapter, Baudrillard ultimately comes to have no faith in a social revolution). Baudrillard argues that Marx could not have come up with a fully adequate cri tique because capitalism, and all its contradictions, was not yet fully developed. This reality served to weaken Marx's historical analyses, his analysis of the capi talism of his day, and his projections for the future of society. Above all, to Bau drilIard (1973/1975:36), Marx is guilty (as he is to Habermas) of the "aberrant sanctification of work." That is, Marx bought into the political economists' ideas on the central importance of work, especially creative work. Given the blinders de rived from the political economists, Marx was unable to think about a number of other things including "discharge, waste, sacrifice, prodigality, play and symbol ism ... the gratuitous festive energizing of the body's powers, a game with death, or the acting out of desire" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:42, 44). All of the latter are in cluded ~ithin what is, as we will see below, Baudrillard's central concept, syTn bolic exchange. To put the issue succinctly and directly, Mat·x's focus on economic exchange blinded him to the importance of symbolic exchange. The real problem in the social world, for Baudrillard, is the rupture between symbolic exchange and work and not, as Marx would have it, the split between "abstract" and concrete labor. That is, to Baudrillard work (and much else) in contemporary society has ceased to be a form of symbolic exchange. Such work has lost its symbolic, its en chanted, qualities. Bapdrillard identifies three phases in the history of political economy. In the first stage, involving archaic and feudal societies, only the surplus of material pro duction is exchanged. In the second, capitalistic stage, the one of central impor tance to Marx, the entire value of industrial production is exchanged. In the third stage, even that which was once thought to be inalienable is exchanged: "virtue, love, knowledge, consciousness" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975: 119). However, as is the case with economic exchanges, all such exchanges have lost their symbolic quali ties. In Baudrillard's view this third phase is at least as distinctive and as revolu tionary as the second phase, but it has been ignored by Marxists and political econ omists who continue to be obsessed with, and blinded by, the economic exchange predominant in the second phase.
Baudrillard also argues that we have moved beyond a society ch alienation (he sometimes also uses the Durkheimian term "anomie" context). He labels the era of alienation and anomie the political era one characterized by crisis, violence, and revolution. (There was no primitive societies, which were characterized by symbolic exchan we have moved beyond the political era and its alienation and now political era characterized by anomalies that he sees as aberrations consequence (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:26). (Alienation and anomie, i substantial and significant consequences.) As an example of such uses the hostages taken by terrorists. Hostage taking is an aberratio ever, has any larger consequences. The terrorists are not apt to achie tives in taking the hostages. Furthermore, since the status of the solutely arbitrary and random (anyone in the wrong place at the wro become a hostage), his existence indicates that there are "no longer for the game of his life or death ... he [the hostage] is beyond ali drillard, 1983/1990:35). However, Baudtillard (1983/1990:35) g argue: "We are all hostages." Hence, we are all beyond alienation; aberrations lacking in any meaning or consequence. Baudrillard plac his broader theoretical perspective:
We are all hostages, and we are all terrorists. This circuit has replaced master and slaves, the dominating and the dominated, the exploiters a Gone is the constellation of the slave and the proletarian: from now on and the terrorist. Gone is the constellation of alienation; from now on i It is worse than the one it replaces, but at least it liberates us from the and the ruses of history. It is the era of the transpolitical that is beginnin
(Baudrillard, 1983/1990:
Thus, the era of the meaningful capitalist-proletatiat relationship is been replaced by the utterly meaningless relationship betwee hostage. And, to Baudrillard, the latter is far "worse" than its prede It is worth noting that even though Baudrillard radically separat Marx, Kroker (in Featherstone, 1991:85) describes Baudrillard as " best of the Marxists." Nevertheless, Baudrillard leaves no doubt, e work, that he feels it necessary to move beyond Mm·x's theory: "th duction in which all Western metaphysics is reflected, must be drillard, 1973/1975:47). While Marxian concepts sought to destro ism of bourgeois concepts, Marxism did much the same thin thinking in creating "trans-historical" ideas and concepts. Thus, M just like bourgeois thinking, needs to be shattered. Having begun the process of shattering Marxian theory and it cepts, Baudrillm·d is confronted with the issue of finding an alterna That alternative begins to emerge more clearly in SY11'lbolic Exchan
9 This alternation of Marxian and Durkheimian terms reflects the fact, to be d chapter, that Baudrillard's thinking is affected by the ideas of these two very diffe
SYMBOLIC EXCHANGE
We have already seen the importance of Marx to Baudrillard's work, but with the concept of symbolic exchange we begin to see the powerful influence of the think ing of Emile Durkheim lO (as well as that of his disciple and nephew, Marce1 Mauss, and his thinking on the gift and Georges Bataille's [Richardson, 1994] thoughts on the relationship between excess, expenditure, and sovereignty as well as his effort to connect the gift to the larger society). Gane (1991 a, 1991b) argues that both Marx and Durkheim were strong influences on Baudrillard's thinking with the result that there was a powerful and unresolved tension in his thinking. Most generally, of course, the symbolic was of great importance to Durkheim and clearly to Baudrillard in his concept of symbolic exchange. More specifically, Baudrillard and Durkheim "adopt a two-phase world history: segmental (sym bolic) societies, superseded by organic (simulation) societies" (Gane, 1991b:200). Further, both have a strong sense of pathologies (e.g., Durkheim's anomie and Baudrillard's consumerism, hostage taking, terrorism, and so on) in the modem world. There are certainly many differences between Baudrillard and Durkheim (BaudriIlard's anti-rationalism versus Durkheim's rationalism, for example), but it is clear that Baudrillard's thinking on symbolic exchange is indebted to Durkheim's work on the symbolic and, more specifically, Mauss's and Bataille's work on the gift. While we have already encountered the concept of symbolic exchange, it is im portant that we discuss it in some depth before we proceed much further. Most generally, symbolic exchange involves the general and reversible processes of "taking and returning, giving and receiving ... [the] cycle of gifts and coun tergifts" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:83; see also Baudrillard, 1976/1993:136). Sym bolic exchange is based on a series of principles that stand in opposition to eco nomic exchange in capitalism: • symbolic exchange is nonproductive in contrast to the productive exchange found in the capitalist economy; 11 • it is aimed at its own destruction rather than creating a perpetual cycle of commodity exchanges; • reciprocity is continuous and unlimited rather than limited to a specific ex change of goods; • and there is strict limitation on the exchange of goods rather than the unlim ited production and exchange of goods. Baudrillard (1980-1985/1990: 127) privileges primitive societies in terms of sylnbolic exchange; such exchange is a primordial process (thus he is accused of having a "noble savage theme" [Levin, 1981:24]). In fact, he refuses to separate primitive society from the symbolic exchanges that occur within them: "Primitive 'society' does not exist as an instance apart from symbolic exchange" (Baudrillard, 10
Interestingly, Baudrillard rarely refers to Durkheim directly.
Lyotard (cited in Genosko, 1994:89) sees symbolic exchange (as well as seduction, to be dis cussed in Chapter 6) as part of Baudrillard's "hippie anthropology." II
1973/1975:78). For the primitives, acts such as eating, drinking, stances of symbolic exchange. As a result, Baudlillard (1973/19 such societies can serve as laboratories that can "teach us about t ation of social relations." (This is another similarity with Du primitive tribes as his laboratory for the study of the social origin It is wOlth noting that Baudrillard's praise for symbolic excha tive societies in which it occurs in its purest form is part of his br nonrationality. As such, it forms the base for his critique of our general and especially the rationality of capitalists, consumers, b tists, linguists, and Marxists. When we look at primitive societies we find that producti themselves, acts of symbolic exchange. For example, of art (1973/1975:98-99) says that they live their "work as a relation change." Baudrillard uses the idea of symbolic exchange to gene as it should be (this is Baudrillard's Archimedean point, at least work) rather than as it exists in its distorted form in capitalist soc
Work is a process of destruction as well as of "production," and in th bolic. Death, loss and absence are inscribed in it through this dispo ject, this loss of the subject and the object in the scansion of the exch
(Baudril
Given his concentration on production, Marx was unable to see dispossession, loss, and death are also integral parts of work. However, today we live in a world in which such work, an symbolic exchange, appear to be at an end. "In the immense p chine of contemporary capital, the symbolic (gift and countergif reversal, expenditure and sacrifice) no longer counts for anyth 1976/1993:35). To take a specific example froIn contemporary will be discussed in further detail in the next chapter, we no long .bolic exchange with the dead. In primitive societies death, as w sun·ounding it, was an integral part of life. Today, however, we death from life. This inability to engage in (symbolic) exchange the fact that, according to BaudIillard (1983/1990:47), "Exchange drillard (1983/1990:47) concludes, "We are living at the end of ever, only exchange protects us from destiny. Where exchange is ble, we find ourselves in a fatal situation, a situation of des exchange, what we have today is "mad speculation" (BaudIillard Taking hostages is for Baudrillard one example of such a mad spe To put this change another way, to Baudrillard, we have moved economy of the commodity (although commodities are signs) to t omy of the sign. "The commodity form has given way to the sign the code of equivalence has become more significant than the e modities" (Gane, 1991b: 111). That is, all values have become sig the code, and the code offers "a structure of control and of power m and more totalitarian than that of exploitation" (Baudrillard, 197
problem now, and it is a more radical one, is the structural manipulation of the sign, not the domination and exploitation of labor power. Thus, we are witnessing "the symbolic destruction of all social relations not so much by the ownership of the means of production but by the control of the code. Here there is a revolution of the capitalist system equal in importance to the industrial revolution" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:122). Further, Gane (1991a:72) argues that because the code is a struc ture that is free of doctrine, "no revolution against it can be mobilized." Thus, the contemporary, simulated world is destroying symbolic exchange. Yet, in the face of that, Baudrillard adheres "to the superiority of the symbolic cultures and the inevitable frailty and vulnerability of the orders of simulation found in the West ... The symbolic orders have a primordial nature which ultimately, accord ing to 13audrillard, will be revealed as a higher order" (Gane, 1991b:14). Thus, Baudrillard critiques capitalism from the outside, from the vantage point of sym bolic exchange. Marxism, on the other hand, can be seen as critiquing capitalism from within, from the vantage point of the exploited and alienated proletariat. 12 We could say, following Baudrillard, that symbolic exchange haunts the domi nance of signs and the code. Baudrillard recognizes that there is no returning to primitive society and its symbolic exchange. However, he does see it as a radical theoretical alternative to the contemporary world. In fact, he sees it as sufficiently radical to ultimately destroy the contemporary semiocracy, at least in theory (Genosko, 1994).13 As we have seen, in his earliest work BaudIillard was affected positively by Saussure's structural linguistics, but he later came to distance himself from llluch of that. Baudrillard discovered in that work a radical element that Saussure himself could not have seen. That is, a model of symbolic exchange can be found in lan guage itself, especially poetry, which is the rebellion of language against its own laws. There is nothing left over in poetry and therefore no possibility of accumula tion; there is just incessant give and take (symbolic exchange). "The poetic recre ate's the situation of primitive societies in linguistic mateIial: a restricted corpus of objects whose uninterrupted circulation in the gift-exchange creates an inex haustible wealth, a feast of exchange.... The poetic is the restitution of symbolic exchange in the very heart of words" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:203,205). In contrast to poetry where signs are generally highly limited, in language more generally we are suffering from an excess of signs, from sign pollution. Here we find a body of unexchanged language, and it is this that is studied by the traditional field of linguistics. Indeed, Baudrillard equates this body of language with the code. Thus, Saussure found both "the structural operation of representation by signs, but [also] exactly the opposite, the deconstruction of the sign and representa tion" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:195). As a result, Saussure may have laid the groundwork not only for linguistics but also "for a decentring of all linguistics" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 195). 12 However, in another sense Marxism also involves an external critique; a critique from the point of view of the yet-to-be-created world of communism and species being. 13 Of course, theoretical destruction is a long way from destruction in practice; see the discussion of the "strength of the weak" in the following chapter.
SUMMARY
This chapter has been devoted to a discussion of some of Baudrillar retical roots and ideas. Many of the early ideas-his focus on the c ety; objects, signs, and the code; symbolic exchange-had a powe his later work. The same is true of his intellectual roots in, and di Marxian, Durkheimian, and Saussurian theory. Certainly there are id ple, the means of consumption) that do not resurface much, if at work. However, even the ideas that have been jettisoned by Baud continue to be important to contemporary analysts of the social w for our purposes, what is impoliant is the continuity between these the later ones to be discussed in the following chapter. To take jus the idea of symbolic exchange will resurface as at least partly cot Baudrillard's later concept of "seduction."
6 JEAN BAUDRILLARD:
PART 2: PROBLEMS IN THE
CONTEMPORARY WORLD
AND THE POSSIBILITY OF
DEALING WITH THEM
CONTEMPORARY SOCIETY: ITS NATURE AND PROBLEMS
The Code
Fashion
Simulacra
The Fractal Order
Ecstasy
Death
America
Other Issues
ARE THERE ANY GROUNDS FOR HOPE?
Seduction
Fatal Strategies
Other Ways Out
'WE now turn to a discussion of Baudrillard's analysis of contemporary society as well as his thoughts on responses to the problems associated with it. CONTEMPORARY SOCIETY: ITS NATURE AND PROBLEMS The Code
As indicated in Chapter 5, Baudrillard sees us moving from a society dominated by signs and codes associated with commodities to one dominated by more general signs and codes; he sees us moving toward the universal "establishment of an ab stract and model system of signs" (Baudrillard, 1983:65). All exchanges, not just those associated with consumption, have come to be dominated by the code. It is now primarily the semiotic world of the code that is destroying symbolic exchange and engaging in symbolic violence aimed at those areas in which symbolic ex change still survives. This abstract code is a much more effective method of domi nance than the exploitative capitalist economic system. It is also much more subtle 92
and has far greater totalitarian implications. The structural manipul and the code is of far more radical significance than was the control o in capitalism. This is the case, if for no other reason, because all of and actions are affected by signs and the code, not just those assoc labor. It is those who control the code (a key role is played by the me and television in particular), and the code itself, that are destroying aspects of social relations, not the capitalists who own the means of is this change from the control of the means of production to the code that Baudrillard sees as a great social revolution, equal in magni dustrial revolution. At one time, signs related to objects, but now that linkage has be signs no longer designate any reality. What we have now is simply th nifiers ... in which the code no longer refers back to any subjectiv 'reality', but to its own logic" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:127). Signs other signs, and their meaning is found in that relationship. Signs are different, totally indeterminate, and totally relativistic. It is the existence of such a code that neither Marx nor even Sa pated. They both still operated under the assumption that there was tween signs and reality. However, to Baudrillard (1976/1993:7) tha now in shreds, and the real has died." With reality dead, all there are this world, signs exchange against other signs rather than against the death of the dialectic and the real has come the demise of the gre hopes. It is impossible to have such dreams in a relativistic world in thing is undecidable and substitutable for everything else. Thus, for example, in contrast to the Marxian position, money a float as signs rather than being material realities. Baudrillard (197 scribes modem capitalism as a "generalised brothel of capital, a b prostitution, but for substitution and commutation." Labor is no long simply one sign among many. Labor is no longer productive but mer tive (of signs, the code). Labor and the factory have disappeared bec everywhere (as we discussed in Chapter 5, even consumers can be se and, therefore, shopping malls can be viewed as factories). As a res no longer be a revolutionary force. While we no longer have the material, economic crises of interes ists, the capitalists create a "perpetual simulacrum of a crises" 1976/1993:32). Their objective in creating such simulated crises (for economic "war" with Japan) is to conceal the fact that the real prob now resides in the code and not in the economic system. To put it an capitalists simulate problems in production to conceal the fact that lem lies in reproduction. In fact, Baudrillard (1976/1993:33) prefers t atrocities of capital-profit, exploitation-than to face up to the sit in, where everything operates or breaks down with the effects of the c It could be argued that the code becomes modernity in Baudr Thus, a critique of the code is a critique of modem society. Howeve
can be criticized for isolating the code and, more importantly, for hypostatizing, or reifying, it (Genosko, 1994).
makes the refusal of fashion into a fashion feature-blue jeans are an his of this) ... one can never escape the reality principle of the code. Even against the content, one more and more closely obeys the logic of the co
(Baudrillard
Fashion
Baudrillard's concern with fashion is part of his broader switch from a focus on economic, social, and political issues to a concern for culture (the media are an other of Baudrillard's cultural concerns). Thus, Baudrillard is part of the broad "cultural turn" taking place in the social sciences. Baudrillard examines the world of fashion as a paradigm of the dominance of the code. In fashion, all we see is the "simple play of signifiers" and, as a result, "the loss of every system of reference" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:87). Not only does fashion not refer to anything real, but it doesn't lead anywhere either. Fashion does not produce anything, but merely reproduces the code. That is, fashion is produced not "according to its own determinations, but from the 1nodel itself-that is to say, that it is never produced, but always and immediately reproduced. The model itself has become the only system of reference" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:92). Fashion is, in a sense, the ultimate stage of the commodity form: "With the acceleration and proliferation of messages, information, signs and models, it is in fashion as a total cycle that the linear world of the commodity will reach completion" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 115). Fashion is also without values and morality. It tends to spread like a virus or a cancer. Fashion produces what postmodernists like to call a "pastiche": "Fashion cobbles together, from one year to the next, what 'has been', exercising an enormous combinatory freedom" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:89). Given all of these characteristics, it would seem clear that fashion is part of the postmodern world. But, despite fashion's many affinities with postmodernism, her~ as in many other places, Baudrillard (1976/1993:90) says he is dealing with modernity, not postmodernity: "For binary logic is the essence of modernity ... Modernity is not the transmutation but commutation of all values, their combina tion and their ambiguity. Modernity is a code and fashion is its emblem." Fashion exists in the world of "light signs," while "politics, morals, economics, science, culture, sexuality" are "heavy signs" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:87). But light or heavy, all of these worlds are dominated by signs. Further, light or heavy, these signs are all part of the code that serves to constrain people. While fashion reflects the dominance of the code, as well as of commodities and simulations, it also in a sense poses a threat to the system. Fashion is one of those areas characterized by "play" rather than "work"; it is a world of illusion. It plays with things like good and evil, rationality and irrationality. "This fashion is taken on by contemporary youth, as a resistance to every imperative, a resistance without an ideology, without objectives" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:98). Nevelthe less, those in power at times feel compelled to crush this play with signs to main tain the predominance of their own signs. In the end, however, fashion is seen as immune to subversion as the code:
The only real answer to the problem of fashion, and most other p contemporary world, lies in the deconstruction of the code. Simulacra
We have already mentioned the centrally important ideas of simula lacra1 in Chapter 5, but it is now time to deal with them more system drillard (1983:4) argues that we live in "the age of simulation." The fast-disappearing cultural worlds (symbolic exchange, seduction 2) t tends to prefer are enchanted worlds. However, a world of simulat disenchanted and ... almost shameful" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993 Baudrillard offers a wide array of examples of simulations:
• He regards the primitive Indian tribe, the Tasaday, at least as it a simulation since the tribe has been "frozen, cryogenized, sterilize death" (Baudrillard, 1983: 15). It may at one time have been a "real" but today what exists is nothing more than a simulation of what the t • A 1987 European Cup soccer match between Real-Madrid a place at night in a completely empty stadium. Fans were ban"ed be behavior by Madrid fans at an earlier match. No one (or almost no o perienced the match, but millions saw its televised (therefore si (Baudrillard, 1990/1993:79-80). • The caves of Lescaux have been closed, and an exact replica, the caves has been opened to the public. • Watergate is described as "a simulation of a scandal" (Baudril • The Gulf War with Iraq is viewed as a simulation of the nucle the United States and the Soviet Union that never occulTe 1992/1994). • Then there is Disneyland, "a pelfect model of all the entangle ulation" (Baudrillard, 1983:23). Take, for example, the simulated s which people flock to see simulated undersea life. Strikingly, man than the more "genuine" aquarium (itself, however, a simulation down the road.
The widespread existence of simulations is a major reason for t distinction between the real and the imaginary, the hue and the fa ingly difficult to distinguish the real from the fake; every contem mixture of the real and the imaginary. In fact, to Baudrillard, as we 1 These
there is no possible subversion of fashion since it has no system of reference to contra dict (it is its own system of reference). We cannot escape fashion (since fashion itself
are not new ideas; they are traceable to Plato, among others. Gane (l991b:58) argues that within contemporary culture, seduction is "a r to symbolic exchange processes." 2
before, the true and the real have ceased to exist, disappearing in an avalanche of simulations. This makes it dangerous to attempt to unmask simulations since what we are apt to find is that there is nothing to be uncovered, or what is there is unde cipherable~ there is no "reality" or "truth" behind the simulated exterior. Since there is no longer any truth or reality, signs no longer stand for anything. Thus, we can be said to live in one "gigantic simulacrum-not unreal, but a simu lacrum, never again exchanging for what is real, but exchanging in itself, in an un intenl.lpted circuit without reference or circumference" (Baudrillard, 1983: 11). As a result, among other things, simulations put "an end to meaning absolutely" (Bau drillard, in Gane, 1993:105). To give a specific example, Baudrillard argues that "all of Los Angeles and America surrounding it are no longer real, but of the order of the hyperreal and of simulation" (Baudrillard, 1983:25). Since the term "hyperreal" has already been used, we need to pause and clarify its meaning. The hyperreal involves simulations and is sometimes used cotermi nously with this concept; "the hyperreal is ... entirely within simulation" (Bau drillard, 1976/1993:73). The hyperreal is not produced but is "that which is always already reproduced" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:73). More specifically, it is a simula tion that is more real than real, more beautiful than beautiful, truer than true. In a hyperreal world there is no way of getting at the source, the original reality. A good example, one used frequently by Baudrillard, is pornography, which he views as "more sexual than sex ... hypersexuality" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 11). Rojek and Turner offer the following example of hyperreality: Scientists alleged that NASA's pictures of other worlds were being touched up. For ex ample, the drab colours of the planet Mars and the asteroid Gaspara had been enhanced to become more vivid and spectacular. (Rojek and Turner, 1993:xi)
More generally, and extremely, "today reality itself is hyperrealist" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:74)~ in other words, there is no more reality; all we are left with is hy perreality. Disneyland is often used by Baudrillard as an example of hypelTeality (for example, it is cleaner than the world outside its gates; its personnel friendlier than those in the "real" world). Many parts of the outside world are emulating Dis neyland (and other hyperreal institutions like fast-food restaurants) in a variety of ways and in that sense (and others) are growing increasingly hyperreal. Baudrillard sees the era of simulations and hyperreality as part of a series of successive phases of images (thereby, seeming to contradict the promise of post modernists not to offer grand narratives): 1 2 3 4
-it [the image] is the reflection of a basic reality -it masks and perverts a basic reality -it masks the absence of a basic reality -it bears no relation to any reality whatever: it is its own pure simulacrum.
(Baudrillard, 1983: 11)
Of these, the transition from the second to the third stage is crucial. Marxists oper ated in the second phase, Baudrillard in the third and fourth phases. Thus, Bau-
drillard (1983:48) contrasts his position to that of the Marxists doin analysis (in the second stage): "It is always the aim of ideological a store the objective process," but in his own analyses in the third and "it is always a false problem to want to restore the truth3 beneath the s In still another historical model (and yet another seeming grand na a postmodemist ostensibly opposed to such narratives), Baudrillard among three orders of simulacra, with each order submitting to the lows (we will discuss the later addition of a new, fourth order in the In the first order, roughly from the Renaissance to the beginning of Revolution, only frrst-order simulations-counterfeits of originals-w Baudrillard (1976/1993:52) gives as an example stucco imitations o tains, wooden cornices, and fleshy curves of the body." Counterfeits the possibilities of control over society that exist in simulacra, but t foreshadowed in counterfeits (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:53). The second order is th~ industrial era characterized by production a ries of reproductions of identical objects (automobiles, refrigerators repetition of the same qbject" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:56). Unlike stage, there is no original to be counterfeited~ "objects become indisti of one another and, along with objects, of the men that produce drillard, 1976/1993:55). Furthermore, there is no need to counterfeit trial era since the products are made on a massive scale and there i their origin or specificity. "In a series, objects become undefined sim the other" (Baudrillard, 1983:97). The third order, one that we have been discussing throughout much chapters, is dominated by the code and the generation of simulation rather than the industrial system. This era is characterized by reprodu production which dominated the industrial era. Baudrillard concludes,
We know that now it is on the level of reproduction (fashion, media, publ tion and communication networks), on the ievel which Marx negligen nonessential sectors of capital . . . that is to say in the sphere of simula code, that the global process of capital is founded. (Baudri
We have moved "from a capitalist-productivist society to a neo-cap netic order that aims now at total control" (Baudrillatd, 1983:111). Baudrillard describes this reality in various ways. For example, he we now live at the end of the age of interpretation, in "the black box (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:58). Thus, we can never truly understand wh ing in contemporary society. He also sees us as living at the "end evolution . . . there is no more finality, nor any determinacy"
3 And, if we want to seek out the truth, or something approximating it, we canno rectly by "shnply looking for it. The only strategy is the reverse one! ... illusion is get somewhere if something is to be found-but 'found' without being searched for" Gane, 1993:61). 4 Genosko argues that this should not be seen as a neat, unilinear historical model.
1976/1993:59). Since there is no more positivity in the world, negativity is no longer an option. To put it another way; there are no more adversaries to react against. We are in a black box. We may not understand or like it, but there is no other reality to hope for, no other place to which we can hope to go. This leads Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993:95) to an explicitly postmodem position: "So, all that are left are pieces. All that remains to be done is to play with the pieces. Playing with the pieces-that is postmodem." One means of control in this new world is the referendum. In fact, to Bau drillard since there is no longer any truth, no longer any referential, we live in the age of the referendum. Referenda, and tests more generally, are perfect simulations because, as mentioned before, the answers are designated in advance by the ques tiohs. "The irruption of the binary question/answer schema is of incalculable im portance. Dislocating all discourse in a now bygone golden age, this schema short circuits every dialectic of the signifier and the signified, a representative and a repre~ented" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:64). Furthermore, all alternatives are re duced to a binary code, with DNA serving as the prototype of this, indeed all, sim ulation. The model for today's world is DNA: "it is in the genetIc code that the genesis.of simulacra today finds its completed form" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:57). People are controlled by referenda (a referendum is to Baudrillard a kind of ulti matuln) in the sense that they must respond in ways predetermined by those who construct them. Referenda serve to short circuit genuine discourse. s The public opinion that emerges from such referenda is a simulation and is hyperreal, more real than peoples' beliefs. Those who respond often try to reproduce the question; "the ones questioned always pretend to be as the question imagines and solicits therri to be" (Baudrillard, 1983: 130). Thus, Baudrillard (1983: 128) describes political polls as "the political class' burlesque spectacle, hyper-representative of nothing at all." Polls represent nothing because, as we've seen, the masses respond with simulated replies: We record everything, but we don't believe it, because we have become screens our selves, and who can ask a screen to believe what it records? To simulation we reply by It is this that makes simulation; we have ourselves become systems of simulation good old critical and ironical judgment no longer possible there is no longer a uni . verse of reference ... polls will never represent anything. (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:87, 88)
The distortions associated with polls are pmt of a broader set of distortions, which means that even with non-stop polling total uncertainty "will never be lifted" (Bau drillard, 1983/1990:90). 5 Here, as elsewhere, Baudrillard is following Marshall McLuhan and his idea that the medium (the referendum in this case) controls the message. However, while McLuhan is ultimately optimistic about a future of a global village in which people are more in touch with one another, Baudrillard remains pessimistic about the media because they engage in one-way communication that is not reversible (it is not symbolic exchange). Nonetheless, McLuhan was "a decisive influence on Baudrillard" (Gane, 1991a:48). On the more general relationship between McLuhan and postmodernism, see Ferguson (1991).
Public opinion is also a simulacra. Public opinion polls lead respo produce what the pollsters are seeking; respondents do not produc their own. 6 Thus, public opinion polls are both the medium and the this, they resemble television and electronic media, which also invo or implicitly, a perpetual questioning and answering, a perpetual poll possible to obtain a non-simulated response to a direct question, apar reproducing the question . . . there is total circularity in every case tioned always behave as the questioner imagines they will and solici just hot air" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:67). Thus, Baudrillard conclud lem with opinion polls is not, as most believe, their objective influ such polls are a problem because they help lead to "operational s across the entire range of social practices." In one of his favori polls are a kind of "leukaemia infecting all social substance" 1976/1993:67). Politics and elections follow the same model. An election elicits sponse from the electorate. Parties do not stand for anything. Neve leaders oppose one another "creating a simulated opposition betwee ties" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:68). Baudrillard sees referenda, polls, and elections as examples of technologies" of control. As Gane (1993:7) puts it, Western societ "repressively tolerant." In the specific case of referenda and polls, th answer is gently controlled by the nature of the question. More gen gle, totalitarian, bureaucratic system of control is an
archaic rationality compared to simulation, in which it is no longer equivalent but a diffraction of models that plays the regulative role: no of the general equivalent, but the form of distinct oppositions. We pass to disjunction through the code, from ultimatum to solicitation, from ob ity to models constructed from the outset on the basis of the subject's "a and this subject's involvement and "ludic" participation, towards a to model made up of incessant spontaneous responses, joyous feedbac contacts.
(Baudrillard, 19
Baudrillard goes beyond referenda and polls to argue that the (e.g., the two-party system in politics) is always the most effective trol. He argues (writing during the Cold War with the Soviet Union) system of competing superpowers is a more effective device for world than a single superpower. (With the end of the Cold War Union we will be in a position to see whether or not Baudrillard wars like those in Bosnia seem to support his view.) Similarly, the tw cal system is a more effective means of control than totalitariani demise of the Soviet Union and its one-party system and the conti the United States and its two-party system seem to support his posit 6 For
a discussion of public opinion polls from a Foucauldian perspective, see Pe
Baudrillard takes the identical twin towers in New York City as a symbol of the centrality of the binary in the contemporary world. He argues that the twin towers superseded the earlier system of different and competing skyscrapers (the Chrysler Building and the Empire State Building, for example). The twin towers mark the end of the world of competition and of a world in which it is possible to represent some original phenomenon. Since the twin towers are identical, there is no origi nal tower. In the contemporary simulated world everything is collapsing into everything else; everything is iTnploding. Baudrillard (1983:57) defines implosion as "contrac tion into each other, a fantastic telescoping, a collapsing of the two traditional poles into one another." Since everything is simulation, everything can dissolve into' a single huge simulated mass. For example, in the case of contemporary talk shows, TV is dissolving into life and life is dissolving into TV. What happens on the TV shows is clearly a simulation, but life itself comes to be a simulation, often of what is seen on television. And~ in a world of total simulation, "absolute manip ulation" becomes possible. , The contemporary hyperreal world of signs that no longer refer to anything, in which the distinction between the real and the imaginary is effaced, in which "real ity is immediately contaminated by its simulacrum" (Baudrillard, 1983: 149), pro duces a kind of hysteria. For example, in the contemporary capitalist economy (politics offers another example) there is a hysterical effort to produce and repro duce the real through production, even overproduction. The latter leads to a hyper real capitalistic system which, through overproduction, is seeking desperately and ultimately unsuccessfully to deny its own dissolution into the code and the world of signs.
The' Fractal Order In the Transparency of Evil, Baudrillard (1990/1993) adds a fourth order of simu lacra.He labels it the fractal, viral, or cancerous stage; "the current pattern of our culture" (Baudrillard, 1990/1993:6). There is no transcendence here, or even hope of it~ merely endless proliferation. Everything, from DNA to AIDS to television images, follows this pattern. More generally~ the code is endlessly proliferating as is its hold on the social world. At the fractal stage we are at the end of difference; everything interpenetrates. We are in the era of the transpolitical, transsexual, transaesthetic. Thus, everything is political, sexual, and aesthetic, and, as a result, nothing is political, sexual, and aesthetic. A major force in this interpenetration in all realms is the media and com munication more generally. 7 For example, art is proliferating, but in the process it is losing its distinctive qualities, especially its capacity to negate and oppose reality. Then there is trans sexuality, involving the elimination of sexual difference, our new model of sexual ity. Transsexuality can be achieved surgically, but more importantly it can be 7 Thus, Baudrillard (1990/1993: 12) opposes Habermas, arguing that "there is no such thing as a communicational utopia."
achieved semiotically. Examples include Madonna and, especially, M son, the latter losing (abandoning) his sexual specificity both surgica otically. In the sexual realm we have ended up, after the sexual revo confusion of categories. In fact, Baudrillard (1990/1993:24) sees such "the problematic fate of all revolutions." Rather than providing gran the modernists believed, "revolution opens the door to indeterminacy confusion," or "the revolution of our time is the uncertainty revo drillard, 1990/1993:24, 43). In the end, we become not only undiff also indifferent. This lack of differentiation is reflected in the fact that our simul tirely positive; all negativity has been banished. Take the example surgery, which is aimed at eliminating all offensive characteristics, "beautiful." Now we are developing a v31iety of genetic tests and te that we can eliminate all undesirable characteristics before they co tence. All of this positivity, all of this elimination of negativity, leaves resembling "the smile of a corpse in a funeral home" (Baudrillard, 1 We all may look good, but we are dead. Death~ in this case, is a world itivity and no negativity. To help us achieve full positivity and eliminate negativity, we en activities as jogging. Jogging, to Baudrillard, is one of those proces proliferation. Like cancer, viluses, and communication, it is obse minable, and ultimately vacuous. Our efforts to eliminate all negativity have left us with a declining fend ourselves. We are as vulnerable as the "boy in the bubble" wa fact, Baudrillard (1990/1993:61) argues that "the extermination of ma the extermination of man's germs." Like the AIDS patient, we are immunodeficient. Because our defenses have disappeared, we are com stroyed by our own antibodies, by the leukemia of the organism. (C similarly vulnerable to their own information, their viluses.) Thus, (1990/1993:64), "Total prophylaxis is lethal." The turning of viruses against people and machines is one aspect others) of what Baudrillard calls the "principle of evil." Evil, to Bau not imply good and bad, morality or guilt. Here, the principle of e mous with reversibility, the turns of fate that, for example, turn b themselves in autoimmunological diseases. The principle of evil enc the best (the body, in this case) and the worst (the immune system body). In the main, however, Baudrillard (1990/1993:109) privileges associates with things he prizes-instability, seduction, ambivalenc disorder of the world."8
8 Another way of looking at evil is as the existence of others and the eternal ant self and other. We can never understand the other; the other is mysterious. Thus, it i the object of a process that, as we will see, Baudrillard values-seduction. In additio process, play, is only possible with the other. Alienation is only possible when there ever, with the end of difference, subjects are "doomed to self-metastases, to pure repe future which no longer involves "the hell of other people, but the hell of the Sa 1990/1993: 122).
These virulent, epidemic processes are capable of getting out of hand and lead ing us to catastrophe. We are threatened by excess: "runaway energy flows, chain reactions, or frenzied autonomous developments ... A full-blown and planet-wide schizophrenia now rules" (Baudrillard, 1990/1993:103, 104). The lack of differentiation is also reflected in our relations with television and computer screens. It is increasingly unclear where we end and such machines begin. This heralds the end of anthropology. It also marks the end of the alienation of people from machines. We now form integrated circuits with those machines, and "runaway energy flows" characterize those circuits. We have covered a wide range of issues, as does Baudrillard, under the heading of sitnulacra. Before we leave this topic, however, it should be mentioned that in his most recent book, The Illusion of the End, Baudrillard (1992/1994:54) offers us the concept of desilnulation. That is, we may be tiring of at least some of the simu lations he associates with modernity. Baudrillard (1992/1994:54) contends that there is evidence that we are ending "things which long ago ceased to have mean ing." One of his major examples is the end of the simulated form- of communism that existed in eastern Europe. While there may be some examples of desimulation, it seeIns unlikely the world as a whole is surrendering the simulacra that, in Bau drillard's view, go to its essence. Ecstasy
Baudrillard also sees the contemporary world as being ecstatic. Ecstasy implies unconditional metamorphosis, escalation for escalation's sake, a continuing process of spinning out of control until all senses are lost. Ultimately, this out-of control system reveals its emptiness and meaninglessness; it "shines forth in its pure and empty form" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:9). Baudrillard offers a number of examples of ecstatic phenomena. • Fashion, discussed above, can be viewed as the ecstasy of _the beautiful; a "pure and empty form of an esthetic spinning about itself' (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:9). • Adve11ising is described as "spinning of use-value and exchange-value into annihilation in the pure and empty form of the brandname" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 10). • Art is viewed as going beyond itself; "the more hyperreal it becomes and the more it transcends itself towards its empty essence" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 10). • Most important, the masses are seen as "the ecstasy of the social, the ecstatic form of the social" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 11). The masses, then, can be seen as a pure and empty form that is spinning out of control and in the process of reaching the limit of the social. In this ecstasy, the masses offer hope of overturning the system. However, this is not. a Marxian hope that the masses will ultimately come to understand and act on their historic role. Rather, as the masses roll blindly ahead doing what they do, they may well cause the ,system to fall. He concludes, "this revolution in things ... lies no longer in their dialectical transcendence (Aufhebung) but rather in their potentialization
(Steigerung), in their elevation to the second power, to the nth power 1983/1990:34). Dialectics no longer describes the situation, rather i is in process. Baudrillard sees cancer and obesity as ecstatic systems. That is, telic systems, having "no other end than limitless increase, without tion of limits" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:31). Of obesity, he argues "something of the systeln, of its empty inflation ... its nihilist exp the general incoherence of signs" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:27). S seen as being obese, and contemporary systems are viewed as being information" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:28). By overcoming the la growth, the system has grown obese, obscene. In sum, "obesity no meaning or direction either, it goes nowhere and no longer has anyth movement: it is the ecstasy of movement" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:3 Obesity without end resembles the metastases of cancer. Presen tion systems can be seen as cancerous; metastases "producing too m a production of superfluous meaning" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:32 and obesity, our CUITent world is in a state of total delirium. Baudrillard (1983) describes discourse in similar terms as being c lessly going round and round. He sees discourse as resembling a M you cut it in two, an additional spiral results. More specificall (1983/1990:44, 45) sees not only the political as hostages to the media as hostages to the polity. They are in a state of "circular black is no end to this chain of blackmail." The media play a key role in this kind of thinking. We are bomba less information from the media; floating signifiers circulate endles we have seen, we have become pmt of the media circuit represent than networks, or nodes, in the media system. Furthermore, the me role in the creation of a depthless, superficial world. 9 All things, gr are part of it, and it is impossible to differentiate among them. "In th everything circulate in one space, without depth, where all the objec to follow one after the other without slowing down or stopping the drillard, in Gane, 1993: 147). Everything is available for communica tion, commercialization, and consumption. Baudrillard is fascinated with double spirals (like DNA) for this is nothing to discover, there is a spiralling ... and regeneration." Th and round, but beneath it all there is no essential meaning to be disco Death
We live in a world in which we exclude minorities, and the paradigm exclusion of the dead and the dying; it is the model for all other exc "death exists when society [e.g., church, state] discriminates agai
9 Rojek (1993:117) offers the following quotation from Andy Warhol: " 'If you about Andy Warhol ... just look at the sUlface of my paintings and films and me, th nothing behind it'."
(Baudrillard, 1976/1993:144). In a sense, cemeteries were our first ghettos. Bau drillard sees a historical process here (another seeming grand narrative). In primi tive societies the dying and dead were part of society; they were involved in the process of symbolic exchange (during ceremonies, for example) and its reversibil ity. "Symbolic death ... is exchanged in a social ritual of feasting" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 147). Exchange does not come to an end just because ~ife has stopped. However, over time the dead have been progressively excluded (the Enlightenment and the rise of capitalism play crucial roles here) until now where they have ceased to t1xist; the symbolic exchange with the dead has been ruptured; we've ended "the symbolic reversibility of death" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:147). To be dead is no longer rtormal; indeed, it is an anomaly and nothing is more unthinkable than death. But our society is atypical: "Every other culture says that death begins be fore death, that life goes on after life, and that it is impossible to distinguish life from death" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:159). It is we (Westerners) who are the "primitives" when it comes to dealing with death. Baudrillard also sees the treatment of death as anticipating the way in which life will be treated. That is, death is controlled "in anticipation of the future confine ment of life in its entirety" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:130). The separation of the dead from the living anticipates a variety of other dichotomous separations ("The dead were the first to play this role" [Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 169])-subject/ob ject, conscious/unconscious, individual/social body, man/labor. Just as we have separated the dead, we have segregated the aged into ghettos (homes for old peo ple, retirement communities). We have segregated them to colonize and control them', In contrast, "In other social formations, old age actually exists as the sym bolic pivot of the group" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:163). Because we are separating the old, We are suffering an "early social death" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:163). In sum, contemporary society excludes rather than engages in symbolic exchange. Baudrillard also links the contemporary exclusion of death to capitalism. (Com munist societies are also indicted for seeking to abolish death.) At least in part be cause death was excluded, people in capitalism have become obsessed with death. In an effort to cope with this, they shifted their focus to the accumulation of money and goods. The contemporary treatment of death is also linked to rationalized, bureaucra tized societies. Baudrillard's (1976/1993:177) critique of the rational treatment of de~th is part of a broader critique of "a meticulously regulated universe." Life (and death) "is no longer anything but a doleful, defensive bookkeeping, locking every risk into its sarcophagus" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:178). All rational interventions in individual lives, by the state, medicine, reason, science, can be 'seen as terrorist acts. In fact, people seem to recognize this by engaging in such symbolic acts as refusing to wear seat belts (a fatal strategy [see below] undertaken by the object). But always, the contemporary world remains vulnerable to symbolic exchange in general, and death in particular: "An infinitesilnal injection ofdeath would immedi ately create such excess and ambivalence that the play of values would completely collapse" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 154). The denial of death has not eliminated death; on the contrary, Baudrillard be lieves that ours has become a death culture: "the law of symbolic exchange has not
changed one iota. We continue to exchange with the dead, even tho those for whom rest is prohibited. We simply pay with our own death ety about death for the rupture of symbolic exchanges with them" 1976/1993:134). Instead of symbolic exchange with the dead, we n alone. As a result, we've created "an anguish concerning death ... hell" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:146). Instead of dealing with the dead, we make the dead appear alive t nereal arts. The dead therefore become a "stuffed simulacrum of life 1976/1993: 181). Made into simulated life forms, the dead lose thei we all have) to difference. We have created the notion of "natural death," but this is a concep of meaning and leaves the social group without a role to play. Dea banal, commonplace, and policed. (In contrast, to "the primitives, th ural' death: every death is social, public and collective" [Baud 1993: 164].) Each of us buries our dead alone. "To us, the dead ha away and no longer have anything to exchange ... the dead are subtr total in an economic operation ... What banality!" (Baudrillard, 19 Because we have made everyday death banal, we focus instead on vi it, we see something like the primitive sacrifice: "The chance accide phe, which we therefore experience as socially symbolic events of t ' portance, as sacrifices" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 165). While Baudrillard is critical of the modem treatment of death praise cannibalism as a model of symbolic exchange: "This devour act, a sYl1'lbolic act, that aims to maintain a tissue of bonds with de very thing they devour.... Devouring ... is a social act ... the tran the flesh into a symbolic relation, the transmutation of the body change" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 138). In segregating death, contemporary society has robbed us of our engage in symbolic exchange with the system: "It is necesssary to ro the last possibility of giving thelTISelves their own death as the last from a life laid down by the system" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993: 177). America
As pointed out earlier, America is for Baudrillard a model of the ki porary world he is describing. lO Baudrillard (1986/1989:9) sees a tween the deserts of America's west and its western cities; the c "equally desert-like banality." Thus, America is characterized by bo social deserts:
• Most generally, "America is a desert" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:9 true of it culturally, intellectually, and aesthetically. • Los Angeles is described as "an inhabited fragment of the drillard, 1986/1989:53). 10
For a critique of America, see Vidich (1991).
• Califol11ia is described as "the world centre of the simulacrum and the inau thentic" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989: 102). • Californian "culture itself is a desert" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:126). Alnerica, its states, its cities, and its deserts seem to be devoid of meaning; they are all sites in which meaning has been exterminated. Baudrillard even finds a process of the "desertification of signs and men" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:63). Thus, in his travels in America, Baudrillard (1986/1989:5) "sought the finished form of the future catastrophe." Specifically, in the case of the New York marathon, Baudrillard finds a race that has lost the meaning of the original marathon; people are (ecstatically) running the race merely to do it; to feel alive; to say that they did it. He finds the same mean inglessness!! in the graffiti that defaces New York and many other cities. Graffiti artists seem to be doing little more than proving that they can do what they do. All of these signs are being produced by the graffiti artist, but there is no essence be neath the signs. As Baudrillard (1986/1989:27) puts it more generally, "For me there is no truth of America." Later, Baudrillard says: Alnerica is the original version of modernity ... no past and no founding truth ... it lives in a perpetual present. Having seen no slow, centuries-long accumulation of a prin ciple of truth, it lives in perpetual simulation, in a perpetual present of signs. (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:76)
Not only are there no truths in America, there are no lies either; all there are are simulations. The real and the imaginary have come to an end in America, and it is this Ifate that awaits European societies. America is a paradise, albeit a "moulllful, monotonous and superficial" paradise (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:98). Alnerica has all the characteristics Baudrillard associates with the contemporary (postmodern?) world: • "It is hyperreality" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:28); • it is "the perfect simulacrum" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:28); • it has depthless, empty emotion such as the smile of Ronald Reagan; • it is a world of superficial images seemingly "invented with the screen in mind" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:55), where "life is cinema" (Baudrillard, 1986/ 1989:101); • the "authentic" are things like Disneyland and TV (Kroker, 1985); • it possesses decentered cities where we can see "the whole of life as a drive in" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:66); • it is characterized by an absence of difference (the androgyny of Michael Jackson is used, again, as an example); • it is a world of kitsch in which the aesthetic and higher values have disap peared; 11
As we will see, Baudrillard also has a more positive view of graffiti and graffiti artists.
• it is a world of meaningless movement with traffic on Amer "coming from nowhere, going nowhere" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:12
These are America's problems, but because of the influence of Am becoming everyone's problems, and they will eventually be found rest of the world. Baudrillard closes by wondering whether the United States is as often assumed. He asks, "is it still really powerful or merely simul (Baudrillard, 1986/1989: 115). He gives the example of the invasio and describes it as a "risk-free scenario, calculated production, art success ensured" (Baudrillard, 1986/1989:109). He concludes th States is no longer a world power but merely a simulation of such a p If you think some or all of what Baudrillard has to say about many other things) is outrageous, you may not be far wrong. In a Anterica, Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993:132) says the following: "Let m Anterica should not be read as a realist text. Its subject matter being I've exaggerated this quality, without actually entering into science f it another way, since America is a hyperreal society, it takes a hyp analyze it critically. 12
Other Issues
There are many other issues that could be discussed in this section, b do with a few more derived from Baudrillard's (1992/1994) most rec Illusion of the End. One is his argument that we have become obses less perfection." He gives as an example what he calls the "stereop that is, as our stereo equipment grows increasingly sophisticated, the ten to has fewer and fewer flaws. However, we are led to wonder music? This is nowhere clearer than in the case of the compact disc it eliminates the flaws associated with audio tapes or records, produ in the view of many experts is not "really" music. Baudrillard sees this as but an illustration of the general principle we seem to get to the heart of things, the more those things seem to
Right at the heart of news, history threatens to disappear. At the hear threatens to disappear. At the heart of experimentation, the object of scie disappear. At the heart of pornography, sexuality threatens to disappear. find the same stereophonic effect, the same effect of absolute proximity same effect of simulation.
(B audrillar
12 Paradoxically, in another work, Baudrillard (1980-1985/1990:209) says, "1 s anyone who passes a condescending or contemptuous judglnent on America."
It is clear that Baudrillard links this general principle to his key concept of a simu lation. Thus, for example, a compact disc is a simulation, an increasingly perfect simulation (compared, say, to an LP, another simulation) in which the "real" grows even more remote. This leads Baudrillard to argue that we need to resist calling upon, and using, all of our resources. Great resources were brought to bear in the creation of CDs, but the net result was more and greater simulation. More generally, Baudrillard (1992/1994: 102) argues that when we draw upon and use all of our resources, the results kill "metaphors, dreams, illusions and utopias by their absolute realization." In another line of argument, Baudrillard sees us living in an era of nonevents; the age of epic events has passed. The irony is that while things no longer really occur, they still seem to happen (the Gulf War as a simulated nuclear war would be an example). Part of the reason for the dominance of nonevents is that we now live in an age of deterrence (Bogard, 1991). Rather than seeking to produce events, we are devoting increasing time and energy to causing a variety of things not to occur. For, example, we engage in a wide range of activities (jogging, for one) to ward off death by making ourselves more perfect, more immortal. We are also depicted as living in a nostalgic age, interested in reviving many things from our past. Instead of fomenting revolution, or creating grand new ideas, we focus on reanalyzing and reinterpreting the past. It is in the context of this issue that Baudrillard engages in one of his most sustained analyses of postmodemity, which he associates with this recycling of the past. Postmodernity involves repen tenance for the sins of modernity and "the recycling of past forms, the exalting of residues; rehabilitation by bricolage, eclectic sentimentality" (Baudrillard, 1992/1994:35). Beyond that, we are deconstructing our past in "almost a viral, epi demic form" (Baudrillard, 1992/1994:33). Thus, whereas modernity was con cerned with "the market, ideology, profit and utopia," postmodernity is "unreal and speculative, lacking even the notion of production, profit and progress" (Bau drillard, 1992/1994:36). Baudrillard is also led to reflect on postmodem individualism, which he gloomily associates with increased penetration and control of the individual at the micro-level: This "post-modern" individualism arises ... out of a liberalization of slave networks and circuits, that is, an individual diffraction of programmed ensembles, a metamorpho sis of the macro-structures into innumerable particles which bear within them all the stigtnata of the networks and circuits-each one forming its own micro-network and tnicro-circuit, each one reviving for itself, in its micro-universe, the now useless totali tarianislTI of the whole. (Baudrillarct", 1992/1994: 107)
Now little more than a node in a broader system, the individual can no longer be alienated from herself, can no longer even differ from herself. No longer different from other or self, the individual grows indifferent to time, space, politics, sex, and so on. We live in the age of terminal boredom.
ARETHERE ANY GROUNDS FOR HOPE?
Chastened by the failures of revolutionary movements, Baudrillard nothing, in the way of hope for a revolutionary solution to the prob ates with contemporary society. One place in his early work in wh come close is equating signification with telTorism against symboli concluding: "only total revolution, theoretical and practical, can r bolic in the demise of the sign and of value. Even signs must burn 1972/1981:163). In his later work, however, Baudrillard (in Gane, only rejects social revolution but comes to believe that "we can n fix the way things are going." Thus, even social reform seems to be tion. Not only that, the reader gets the clear sense that the efforts to temporary problems are as dangerous as the problems themselves all is to be done, it should not be rationally planned and organized. (1990/1993: 105) puts it, "we should entertain no illusion about the any kind of rational intervention." Why does Baudrillard hold out no hope for revolution, reform, rational intervention? The answer, at least in part, is traceable to h code. That is, because the code is omnipresent it will inform, con mately undermine any efforts to deal with cun"ent problems. In eff concludes that the code cannot be dealt with because it is everyw the efforts to deal with it. However, even if there are no rational responses, are there any no rational responses to our contemporary problems? As we will see Baudrillard does offer a number of such ideas on responding to t has described. Thus, we agree with Genosko (1944:103): "To con observers have] that Baudrillard's vision is dark, nihilistic and hop ranted." Seduction
The concept of seduction is a close relative to the idea of symboli deed, Genosko argues that it is with this concept that Baudrillard exchange a new face. As was pointed out earlier, symbolic exchan contemporary world as the nonrational alternative to it. In effec change plays much the same role in Baudrillard's work as does s Marx's work. That is, it is not only the base of Baudrillard's critique porary world but also at the root of his image of an alternative to bolic exchange plays these (and other) roles in Baudrillard's theory be seen, at least in part, as a way of responding to the problems that world. We ordinarily think that what we want is to attain complete cl Baudrillard rejects this, arguing that complete clarity is obscene, thing exhibited and visible. Rather, Baudrillard prefers the scene th sence and illusion. "For something to be meaningful, there has to
for there to be a scene, there has to be an illusion, a minimum of illusion, of imagi nary moment, of defiance to the real, which carries you off, seduces or revolts you" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:65). The scene can also be described as "enchanted space." Scenes are arenas of free play without the usual ludicrous restraints, but "with the irruption of obscenity, this scene is lost ..-. everything has its reasons.... There is no longer ... play" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993:61). While scenes may be visible, the obscene is hypervisible. Pornography in general is a good example of the obscene; a more specific instance offered by Baudrillard is the pornographic effort to show close-ups of the female orgasm. Passion is characteristic of a scene, but it disappears in the obscene, which is cool, white. Most generally, "obscenity takes on all the semblances of modernity" (Bau drillard; 1983/1990:58). Seemingly everything in the modem world is visible; everything is filmed, broadcast, videotaped, and so on. We have become voyeurists, obsessed with ourselves. We are subjected to "the rampant obscenity of uninterrupted social commentary" (Baundrillard, 1983/1990:59). And then, with "everything oversignified, meaning itself becomes impossible to grasp" (Bau drillard, 1983/1990:60). The social world has become promiscuous; social prosti tution is rampant. Polls, talk shows, and the media more generally force us to tell our secrets, even when there are none to tell. Baudrillard (1983/1990:68) talks of the "pornography of information and communication." We have become over-in formed; "buried alive under information" (Baudrillard, 1980-1985/1990:90). Instead, and as a response to the obscene contemporary world, Baudrillard ad vocates the "play and power of illusion" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:51). Illusion lies at the base of seduction, and for Baudrillard (1983/1990:51) the choice is between seduction and terror: "that which is no longer illusion is dead and inspires terror." Examples of things without illusion (in addition to pornography) are cadavers, clones, and, increasingly, much of the contemporary world. To ward off terror and death, we lTIUSt rediscover and remake illusion. We ordinarily associate seduction with women (and Baudrillard has been criti cized for this 13), but it is better to think of seduction as "games with signs" (Kell ner, 1994: 14). We tend to think of seduction and illusion as false and therefore to be rejected in our search for the "truth." However, to Baudrillard illusion is not false and does not involve false signs; rather it is senseless, involving senseless signs. "There is no real, there never was a real. Seduction knows this, and pre serves its enigma" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 108). More concretely, Baudrillard (1983/1990: 175) argues: "Our fundamental destiny is not to exist and survive, as we think: it is to appear and disappear. That alone seduces and fascinates us. That alone is scene and CerelTIOny." Baudrillard's focus on seduction is derived, at least in part, from a rejection of Freud and his focus on the desire of the subject. (Just as he sought to liberate Marx from the mirror of production, as pointed out earlier, he seeks to liberate Freud 13 Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993:86) says that there is a "privileged relation between femininity and seduction." However, he does make it clear that femininity is not restricted to worrien: "Femininity ap pears in certain individuals, men or women" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993:111). For some of the contro versy sUlTounding this, see Plant (1993).
from the "mirror of desire.") Rather than the desire of the subje (1983/1990: 139) offers a focus on the seductive power of the objec you exist is not the force of your desire (wholly a nineteenth-centu energy and economy), but the play of the world and seduction; it i playing and being played, it is the passion of illusion and appearanc The power (and the hope) of the masses (and more generally the from their ability to seduce the elites; "only the object is seductive and power are on the other side, the side of the object" (Bau 1990: 119). Further,
Is it not rather the seducer who is seduced, and does the initiative not the object? The seducer believes he envelopes it in his strategy, but he lure of his banal strategy and it is rather the object that envelopes him in
(B audrillard
Baudrillard (1983/1990:148) offers a fatal theory (more on this world prey to the law of things, that is, to total predestination." Furt
this is a world where there is no such thing as chance. Nothing is dead, nothing is disconnnected, uncorrelated or aleatory. Everything, on the co admirably connected-not at all according to rational relations (which nor admirable), but according to an incessant cycle of metamorphoses.
(B audrillard,
More specifically, Baudrillard (1983/1990:181) associates fatality w the masses: "the object is considered more cunning, cynical, talente ject, for which it lies in wait. The metamorphoses, the ruses, the s object surpass the subject's understanding." Fatality is the strategy masses. Baudrillard sees the world ruled by destiny, magic, seduction; th secret organization. The enemy of all of this is rationality. The effor and deal with the world rationally will end in catastrophe-"resolv into causality or probability. That is true entropy" (Baudrillard, 1 Instead, "Incalculable connections are the stuff of our dreams, but a bread" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 155). The power of seduction lies i ity. That is, in seduction signs are received, and they, in turn, are im back. To put this another way, seduction involves symbolic exchang A good example of seduction and what has happened to it in the is art. To Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993:144), the goal of art is to "pos illusion against reality ... it was always trying to seduce the rea However, art in the modern world is no longer involved in illusion but rather in simulation. More generally, in the hyperreal world of more and more difficult to find any illusion or seduction. Baudrillard (1983/1990:156) argues that we all welcome catastrop real pleasure in the world is watching things 'turn' into catastrophe, to from determinacy and indeterminacy, from chance and necessity, and of vertiginous connections." We want not the assurance of predictabil
of assurrance associated with vertigo. Seduction is one way of achieving vertiginous ness and thereby counteracting the numbing control of contemporary society. Fatal Strategies
As is clear above, seduction is one example of what Baudrillard describes as a se ries of fatal strategies. His thinking on such strategies is linked to his view that the social sciences have traditionally focused on the subject. Postmodern social theory in general, and Baudrillard in particular, seek to "decenter" the social sciences by focusing on the object. The social sciences have always seen the subject as essen tial, "the royal road of subjectivity" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 111), but to Bau drillard it is the object, and its fate, that is essential. While we usually think of sub jects as active and objects as passive, to Baudrillard the object "isn't passive and yet it isn't a subject" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993:51). The object can be almost anything (the consumer goods discussed in the previous chapter are objects), al though froIn a variety of sociological points of view, it is most often the "mass" that is considered the object. The masses do not want to be, and cannot be, liber ated. Their power lies in their silence, their absence of desire: atonal, amorphous, abysmal, they exercise a passive and opaque sovereignty; they say nothing, but subtly, perhaps like animals in their brute indifference (although the masses are "essentially" rather hormonic or endocronic-that is, antibodies), they neutralize the whole political scene and discourse. (B audrillard, 1983/1990:94)
The. masses absorb, feed off, the accelerating power of the system. Baudrillard (1983/1990:95) describes "the stupefying power of the mass-as-object ; .. an absolute power, a power of death over the social body." The masses are dangerous, dragging "power down to its fall" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:95). Thus, objects possess fatal strategies, and these stand in contrast to the banal strategies of the subject. In describ ing what he means by a fatal strategy, Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993:50) says, "some thing responds of its own accord, something from which it is impossible to escape." The power of the masses comes, ironically, from their lack of knowledge. For example, they leave it to advertising and information systems to persuade them, to make choices for them. But who has the power here? While we usually think the power resides with the systems, it could be argued that it is the masses who have the power. One can even view the masses as snobs delegating annoying choices to others; the elites in charge of advertising and other systems relieve the masses of the tiresolne process of needing to make choices. The masses have "the ironic power of withdrawal, of non-desire, non-knowledge, silence, absorption then ex pulsion of all powers, wills, of all enlightenment and depths of meaning" (Bau drillard, 1983/1990:99). Instead of looking at the masses as alienated, unconscious, and repressed, Baudrillard (1983/1990:99) argues that we can look at the masses "as possessing a delusive, illusive, allusive strategy, corresponding to an uncon scious that is finally ironic, joyous and seductive."
The silence of the masses is not a sign of their alienation but o "the silence was a massive reply through withdrawal, that the silenc egy ... they [the masses] nullify meaning. And this is truly a power. they absorb all systems and they refract them in emptiness" (Baudril 1993:87-88). In other words, the masses are the "black hole" of the The masses are silent because they are overwhelmed with informati case, there is no way of reversing the flow of that information from fact, we are not to think of the masses as a social phenomenon [after is dead] involving millions of people but rather an inertial "form" overwhelming flood of information.) Thus, a strategy of silence, of ops among the masses. The silence of the masses is fatal. It is one strategies, strategies that indicate that the "object is more subtle, m than the subject" (Gane, 1991b:174). Ultimately, these fatal strate world in the direction of a "downward spiral of the worst outcom strophic outcomes" (Gane, 1991b:207). Baudrillard has called the revenge of the masses, and of objects i "revenge of the crystal." Of the crystal, Baudrillard says, it is
the object, the pure object, the pure event, something which no longer re gin or an end ... There is today a possibility that the object will say some there is also above all the possibility that it will take its revenge! (B audrillard, in
Baudtillard sees objects in general, and the masses in particular nies." And these evil genies are, in Baudrillard's (1983/1990:7) view "victorious over ... the subject." The masses (and subjects) are "e they are unreasonable: "Unreason is victorious in every sense, whi principle of Evil" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:7). According to the pri "any order exists only to be disobeyed, attacked, exceeded, and dism drillard, 1983/1990:77). The mass is a "genie" in the sense that, mag mass and not those who supposedly dominate it who are likely to e ous. How are they going to win out?
Things have found a way of avoiding a dialectics of Ineaning that was be them: by proliferating indefinitely, increasing their potential, outbiddin an ascension to the limit, an obscenity that henceforth becomes their im and senseless reason.
(Baudrillard
The victory of the masses will not be a dazzling revolution "but obscu It won't be dialectical, it will be fatal" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:96). I
14 As we have seen in this chapter, BaudrilIard uses the concept "evil" in a variety and he does not take the time to reconcile these differences.
revolution, "but massive devolution, ... a massive delegation of power and re sponsibility massive de-volition and withdrawal of the will" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:97). More specifically, the masses are evil genies because, as we saw previously, they respond to the simulations of the polls with simulations of their own. "This is what we could call the evil genie of the object, the evil genie of the masses, eter nally blocking the truth of the social and its analyses" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:93). Because of the irony involved in this, Baudrillard sees hope in ironic theory rather than the critical theory that has been relied upon by Marxists. The answer to the ecstatic '~acceleration of networks" characteristic of contem porary society is not to try to be "faster" than them but to turn instead to the tor toise-like masses characterized by "insoluble immobility, the slower than slow: in ertia and silence, inertia insoluble by effort, silence insoluble by dialogue" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:8). The masses are always underestimated, but their "deep instinct remains the symbolic murder of the political class" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:94). One of the ways in which the masses do this is by challenging the subjecL and pushing "it back upon its own impossible position" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 113). The mass is also seen as a mirror, "that which returns the subject to its lTIortal transparency" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990: 113). For example, as we have seen, the general view is that the masses are being se duced by the media, but Baudrillard argues that it may well be the masses that are seducing the media. FU11her, the media may provide "the surface which the masses take advantage of to remain silent" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:80). While Baudrillard sees hope in the masses, he rejects the grand narrative of the Marxists (and others) who envisioned a grand conclusion culminating in the over throw of the capitalist system. More generally, "it is the end of linearity, the end of finality ... it is also the end of the origin, of the possibility of going back, in a lin ear fashion, to the origin" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993: 175). Baudrillard (1983/1990:24) concludes, "we are no longer in the age of grandiose collapses and resurrections, of games of death and eternity, but of little fractal events, smooth an nihilations and gradual slides." Thus, the current social world will end not with a bang but with a series of whimpers. The revolt of the masses will be much like the victory of cancer cells (another object) over the body. Both the masses and cancer cells can be seen as uncontrol lable, undisciplined, nondialectial, and subliminal. Both cancer and the masses are hypertelic. In their mindless, limitless increase the masses will destroy the social body in the same way that cancer cells destroy the physical body. Baudrillard believes that groups, even revolutionary groups, can attain their ends, but they c'annot attain them directly. Rather, he argues that groups must aim "to the side, beyond, off center"; in this way, "duplicity is strategic and fatal" (Baudrillard, 1983/1990:77, 78). More generally, Baudrillard (in Gane, 1993: 169) announces, "I'm on the side of the principle of evil." This is based on the premise that we live in a world of end less and hopeless repetition. In such a world, "We must ourselves inject some evil,
or at least some decay, some virulence, and forge another type of d haps to awaken all that a bit" (Baudrillard, in Gane, 1993:176),
Other Ways Out
Given the dominance of the code, revolutionary potential is seen, at drillard's early work, as lying among those who are excluded from t dents, blacks, females, and so on. They take as their objective the ab code. Given this new objective and the new revolutionary forces, class is no longer the gold standard of revolts and contradictions" 1973/1975: 140). Intellectuals need to adopt an ironic stance toward the contem This means that they should "embrace contradictions, to exercise iro opposite tack, to exploit rifts and reversibility, even to fly in the face and the factual" (Baudrillard, 1990/1993:39). The latter is related t and using science fiction to turn the system against itself. Obvious concrete revolutionary strategy here; theoretical rather than practic involved. Thus, there is no actual impact, but could we expect any in out reality? Baudrillard seems to hold out hope in speech as contrasted to di controlled by the code. Those excluded by the code, such as the grou above, can rebel through their use of speech. But, he is not arguing mate massive outpouring against the code. We ought not to wait for The utopia is here in a "Each man is totally there at each instant. that are raised against political economy Utopia ... wants on word; and it wants to lose itself in it" (Baudrillard, 1973/1975:166-1 Baudrillard also sees another fatal problem (other fatal problems w in the preceding section) within modem society dominated by the such societies are destined to symbolic disintegration; they are unabl themselves symbolically. Once again, Bauarillard (1973/1975: 147 society as being haunted by the spectre of symbolic exchange, wher be given without being returned, nothing is ever won without someth nothing is ever produced without something being destroyed, nothin ken without being answered." In contrast, the power of the code is t fact that it is capable of giving a variety of things but is incapable of thing; it allows no possibility of return. The gift (in this case, from t source of power, and the only way to undermine it is through a cou unable to be returned. Thus, instead of "direct, dialectical revolut "real" infrastructure, Baudrillard (1976/1993:36) urges the "reversal reversibility of the counter-gift and, conversely, the seizing of powe exercise of the gift." In sum,
the only solution is to turn the principle of its power back against the sy impossibility of responding or returning. To defy the syste111 with a gift to
respond save by its own collapse and death. Nothing, not even the system, can avoid the symbolic obligation, and it is in this trap that the only chance of a catastrophe for capital remains .... The system must itself cOlnlnit suicide in response to the multiplied chal lenge of death and suicide. (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:36-37)
Baudrillard sees the code as growing increasingly coherent, but as it does it si multaneously (dialectically?) grows progressively unstable. Thus, he sees a fatal, catastrophic flaw in the seemingly unassailable code: Every system that approaches perfect operativity simultaneously approaches its down fall. ... A gentle push in the right place is enough to bring it crashing down.... They collapse uhder the weight of their own monstrosity, like fossilized dinosaurs, and imme diately decompose. This is the fatality [italics added] of every system committed by its own logic to total perfection and therefore to total defectiveness, to absolute infallibility and therefbre irrevocable breakdown: the aim of all bound energies is their own death. This is Why the only strategy is catastrophic, and not dialectical at all. Things must be pushed to the limit, where quite naturally they collapse and are inverted. (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:4)
Given the transition from the dominance of capitalism to the dominance of the code, the latter cannot be destroyed by a direct dialectical revolution. The system cannot be confronted in the realm of the real but rather must be confronted in the sylnbolic realm. "The revolution is everywhere where an exchange crops up ... that shatters the finality of the models, the mediation of the code ... the revolution is symbolic or it is not a revolution at all" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:205). In that real1n, the answer lies in "reversal, the incessant reversibility of the counter-gift and, conversely, the seizing of power by unilateral exercise of the gift. ... We must therefore displace everything into the sphere of the symbolic, where challenge, re versaland overbidding are the law, so that we can respond to death only by an equal or superior death" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:36). We are, in a sense, reversing the power of the system, which is the fact that it gives gifts without the possibility of return. The objective is to "defy the systenl with a gift to which it cannot respond save its own collapse and death. Nothing, not even the system, can avoid the sym bolic obligation, and it is in this trap that the only chance of a catastrophe for capi tal remains" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:36-37). The only option open to the system in such a situation is to commit suicide. Power comes from unilateral giving; the abolition of power comes from the counter-gift, which cannot be returned. Reckless squandering, like the counter-gift, poses a threat to the system: "We would like to see a functional squandering everywhere so as to bring about sym bolic destruction.... Only sumptuous and useless expenditure has meaning" (Bau drillard, 1976/1993:94, 155-156). We can gain another sense of responses to contemporary realities in Bau dri11ard 's thinking on the contemporary city and the graffiti artists it has spawned (although, as we saw above, Baudrillard appears to give up on them later in his work). We have gone from the urban/industrial society to a society· and its cities
characterized by "a dot of signs." In other words, in one of Baud quotable (and famous) quotations, "metallurgy has become sem drillard, 1976/1993:77, 79). Similarly, the "city is no longer the pol zone that it was in the nineteenth century~ it is the zone of signs, the code" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:77). Based on signs, the city is vul level of signs. In this sense, graffitists represent a threat to the city verse the process of signs emanating from the city and respond wit own. Furthermore, they are revolutionary not because their signs revolutionary but because their "message is zero" (Baudrillard, More generally, Baudrillard (1976/1993:80) argues that we must "a of difference, dismantling the network of codes, attacking coded means of an uncodeable absolute difference, over which the syste and disintegrate." There is no need for organized masses and raise -, sciousness; what we need are graffitists "to scramble the signals of drillard, 1976/1993:80). Death takes on particular importance to Baudrillard (1976/1993: ing about an alternative to the dominance of the code: "Perhaps d alone, the reversibility of death, belongs to a higher order than symbolic disorder can bring about an intenuption in the code." He does not mean by death a real event that marks the end of a sub Rather, death is "a fonn in which the determinacy of the subject lost" (Baudrillard, 1976/1993:5). Thus, death is not only something the end of the system but is always stalking the code and threateni terminacy and symbolic extermination. As a system of symbols, th be combatted by symbols, specifically the reversed symbols of de bolic death in general poses a threat to the system. For example, in talism, "If political economy is the most rigorous attempt to put an is clear that only death can put an end to political economy 1976/1993: 187). More specifically, suicide,. because it is a form death, a way of giving our lives away (a gift) with no possibility threatens the system. One way of summing up much of what Baudrillard has to say a to the problems of the modern world is caught by the concept, "the weak" (Genosko, 1994:72; Genosko, 1992). All of the possibilities derive their strength from their weakness-objects, the masses, s artists, the dead, and so on. This is a stliking idea that, while not drillard, reaches its apogee in his work. Here is what Baudrillard h the strength of another weak group-children:
Whereas adults make children believe that they, the adults, are adults, part let adults believe that they, the children, are children. Of these second is the subtler ... their [children's] vitality and development an tual destruction of the superior-adult-world that sun·ounds them. Chil adult universe as a subtle and deadly presence.
(Baudrillard, 199
In a world in which it is no longer possible to believe in the powerful, Baudrillard sees hope in children, indeed all of those who are weak. In The Illusion of the End, Baudrillard (1992/1994: 120) discusses the possibil ity of a "poetic reversibility of events." Thus, there is hope in the weak poet and the enchantment of poetry: Against the simulation of a linear history "in progress," we have to accord a privileged status to these backfires, these malign deviations, these lightweight catastrophes which cripple an empire much more effectively than any great upheavals. (Baudrillard, 1992/1994:121; italics added)
OTHER FRENCH POSTMO THINKERS,: DERRIDA, DE AND GUATTARI, LY LACAN, JACQUES DERRIDA: GRAMMATOLOGY AND WRITING
SUMMARY
In this chapter, we picked up the review of Baudrillard's work by focusing on some of his major analyses and critiques of contemporary society as well as some of his thoughts on responding to those problems. Much attention was devoted to the code and its control over what transpires in society. Similarly important are Bau drillard's thoughts on the simulated, hyperreal character of society. One of Bau drillard's more recent views is that we have entered a new, fractal order character ized by meaningless and endless proliferation. This is a world that is ecstatic and resembles the hypertelic growth of cancer, AIDS, obesity, and the like. The way in which death has come to be treated can be seen as emblematic of the way in which many other matters are handled in contemporary society. Then we turned our attention to some of Baudrillard's thoughts on responses to thef problems he has described. It is important to reiterate that while Baudrillard is often thought of as a nihilist, he does have much to say about such coping meth ods. In this regard, Baudrillard accords great importance to seduction, which is closely related in his thinking on symbolic exchange. In a world in which signs are destroying symbols, Baudrillard sees great need for more symbolic behavior like seduction. Then there are a number of fatal strategies open to a wide range of ob jects. These are not rational in character, but they are likely to bring the. system ever closer to catastrophe. A number of other responses are detailed such as giving gifts to the system and the reckless expenditure of resources. Thus, there are things to be done, or that are being done unknown to those doing them, but it remains un clear whether the system will devolve as a result or whether the code will grow ever more powerful.
GILLES DELEUZEAND FELIX GUATTARI: TOWARD SCHIZOANA
JEAN-FRANc;OIS LYOTARD: THE DEATH OF THE GRAND NARRA
JACQUES LACAN: THE IMAGINARY, THE SYMBOLIC, THE REAL PAUL VIRILIO: DROMOLOGY
THE last four chapters have been devoted to the work of two F Michel Foucault and Jean Baudrillard-whose work is central to ing of the development of postmodern social theory. In this cha much less depth, with several other thinkers associated with Fre social theory. Although they are dealt with in less detail, that is no are of less importance to our understanding of postmodemism.
In previous chapters we have surveyed a wide range, even the e theorist's work. To make this book manageable, in this chapter w ourselves that luxury. In the main, we will need to settle for a di trally important pieces of work rather than an entire oeuvre. In this deal with key ideas associated with important French poststructu ernists-Jacques Derrida's work, especially his ideas on "gram "writing," Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari's work on "schizo Franc.;ois Lyotard's attack on the "grand narrative," Jacques Lacan choanalysis, and Paul Virilio's "dromology," or theory of speed. JACQUES DERRIDA: GRAMMATOLOGY AND WRITING
Charles Lemelt (1990) traces the beginning of poststructuralism postmodern social theory) to a 1966 speech by J acques Derrida knowledged leaders of this approach (Lamont, 1987), in which h dawn of a new, poststructuralist age. In contrast to the structur those who were involved in and followed the linguistic turn and fo Derrida focuses on writing. In fact, he created a "science" of writ gramlnatology (Denida, 1967/1974:4). While he thinks of gramm
. . . . . .III'r~!!
stage will become anarchic. What Derrida (197~:240) is not crystal clear about is the alternative stage he is espousing. However, we do get a hint vlhen he discusses the construction of a stage "whose clamor has not yet been pacified into words." Or, when he discusses a theatre of cruelty that "would be the art of difference and of expenditure without economy, without reserve, without return, \vithout history" (Derrida, 197B:247). Derrida's (1978:250) theatre would be marked by difference~ it would be characterized by what Artaud called "passionate overflowing." It is clear that Derrida is calling for a radical deconstruction of the traditional theatre. More generally, he is implying a critique of society in general, which is in the thrall of logocentrism. Just as he wants to free the theatre from the dictatorship of the writer, he wants to see society free of the ideas of all of those authors, the in tellectual authorities, \vho have created the dominant discourse. In a sense, Derrida wants the theatre to move a\vay from its traditional center-its focus on the writer (the authority)-and give the actors more free play. And, this point too is general izable to society as a vv'hole. Derrida associates the center with the answer, with a lack of different answers, and ultimately \vith finality and therefore with death. The center is linked with the absence of that which is essential to Derrida (1978 :297)-"play and difference." A theatre, and a world, without a center would be one which is infinitely open, ongoing, and self-reflexive. Derrida (1978:300) concludes that the future decentered theatre and world "is neither to be awaited nor to be refound." His point is that we are not going to find the future in the past, nor should we passively vlait for our fate to unfold. Rather, the future is to be found, is being made, in vlhat we are doing. We are all currently in the process of writing the future, but we do not know, cannot know, what that fu ture will be. Having debunked Western logocentrism and its intellectual authority, in the end Derrida leaves us without an answer; in fact, of course, there is no answer. The search for the answer, the search for the logos, has been destructive and enslaving. All we are left with is the process of doing, we are left with play and with differ ence. Writing is, once again, central here because it is both decentering and an af firmation of play and difference.
GILLES DELEUZE AND FELIX GUATTARI:TOWARD SCHIZOANALYSIS
One of the best-known \vorks in poststructuralis111 and postnl0dernisnl is Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari's (1972/1983) Anti-Oedipus: CapitalislJl and Schizo phrenia. The intellectual context of the book is well expressed by Michel Foucault in his preface to it: During the years 1945-1965 (I am referring to Europe), there \\'as a certain way of thinking correctly, a certain style of political discourse, a certain ethics of the intellec tual. One had to be on fanliliar terms with Marx, not let one's dreal11S stray too far fr0l11 Freud. And one had to treat sign-systenls-the signifier-with the greatest respect. (Foucault, 1983:xi)
Like Foucault, Deleuze and Guattari sought to fashion their th in reaction to the dominance of Marxian, Freudian psychoanal structuralist thinking. Foucault labels those who follow Freu perspectives "poor technicians of desire" who, given their focu symptom," "would subjugate the multiplicity of desire to the t ture and lack" (Foucault, 1983:xiii). Foucault also saw fascism as an enemy of the kind of Deleuze and Guattari. In fact, he thought that their book coul "Introduction to the Non-Fascist LIfe" (Foucault, 1983:xiii). H fascist political regimes that are opposed but also "the fasci heads and in our everyday behavior, the fascism that causes desire the very thing that dominates and exploits us" (Fouca Oedipus is both an effort by the authors to liberate themselves nant modes of thinking and to help free people from fascistic ternal and internal. The book's title and its focus on the Oedipus complex, of c centrality of Freud and psychoanalysis, at least as a person a well as the authors' desire to distance themselves from them lyst's famous couch, Deleuze and Guattari (1972/1983:334) pu "smells bad.... It reeks of the great death and the little ego." I resents an attack on the idea of the Oedipus complex and its family" of "daddy-mommy-me" (Deleuze and Guattari, 197 tion to its specific problems, the Oedipus complex is seen as the kind of totalizing idea from which people should be free and Guattari linked the Oedipus complex to capitalism and thu attack on the latter as welL At the heart of all of this is the idea that we have all been o neurotic by our families during the socialization process an come to want fascism. The goal is to free us from this yoke sires to run free~ the goal is a "desiring revolution." The mode free of the oedipal yoke, whose desires are running free, is th Deleuze and Guattari (1972/1983:2) put it, "A schizophrenic better model than a neurotic lying on the analyst's couch." H pointed out that it is more the schizophrenic process than the s development has been arrested) that is the model for Deleuze generally, what Deleuze and Guattari seek is "a collective subj subject-anti-oedipus" (Seem, 1983:xxiii). Such a subject, w run free, would be an explosive, even a revolutionary, force. As pointed out above, Deleuze and Guattari valorize schizo in contrast to Freud who, in their view, disliked schizophren sisted being oedipalized. More generally, the psychoanalysts production of desire, but then they had turned around and sou Deleuze and Guattari people are inherently desiring 111achines machines. They see these two types of "machines," as well a
machine" as part of "species life": "Schizophrenia is the universe of productive and reproductive desiring-machines, universal primary production as the 'essential reality of man and nature' " (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:5). Thus, schizo phrenia is seen as an inherent part of species life. Schizophrenics live intensely~ they come closer than most to being desiring-machines. However, psychoanalysts have opposed them, and by irnplication all of humanity, and have sought to repress their lives, their desires. Machine imagery runs through Anti-Oedipus. "Desire is a machine, and the object of desire is another machine connected to it" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:26). Another major machine is capitalism, and Deleuze and Guattari see it as an effort to repress the desiring machine: capitalism, through its process of production, produces an awesonle schizophrenic accu mulation of energy or charge, against which it brings all its vast powers of represssion to bear, but which nonetheless continues to act as capitalism's limits ... it continually seeks to avoid reaching its lirnit while simultaneously tending toward that limit.
Schizoanalysis, as a process, would help free the desiring-m is seen as a revolutionary force. It is an explosive force that ca established order. Snidely, Deleuze and Guattari (197211 983: 1 sire, not left-wing holidays," is the true revolutionary force. In as an inherently revolutionary force. As is true of much of poststructuralism and postmodernism, tral importance to Deleuze and Guattari. The code is viewed and in need of disruption, and it is the role of the schizoph code, especially one aspect of the code-Oedipus, that " (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:54). The schizophrenic f against syntax, a concerted destruction of the signifier, non flow, polyvocity that returns to haunt all relations" (Del 1972/1983: 133). Of course, it is not only the code that needs to be undermine italism and the family system (daddy-mommy-me) that was b help support it. Deleuze and Guattari clearly link capitalism an
(Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:34; see also 266)
Schizophrenia is capitalism's limit, and the schizophrenic is Deleuze and Guat tari's revolutionary agent: The schizophrenic deliberately seeks out the very limit of capitalism: he is its inherent tendency brought to fulfilIment, its surplus product, its proletariat, and its exterminating angel. He scrambles all the codes and is the transmitter of the decoded flows of desire. (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:35)
Currently, the desiring machine is forced to fit the "restricted code of Oedipus" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:47). What we need to do is to "schizophrenize" both society as a whole and the individual unconscious. Such a "schizophreniza tion" would allow us "to shatter the iron collar of Oedipus and rediscover every where the force of desiring-production" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:53). Through schizophrenization, we would be cured of the cure~ that is, we would be freed from the oppression of psychoanalysis. We would also, in the process, be freed of capitalism, "[fJor what is schizo, if not first of all the one who can no longer bear 'all that': money, the stock market, the death forces" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:341). We need to replace psychoanalysis, with all of its exclusions and restrictions (Deleuze and Guattari see the psychoanalyst in league with such social control agents as the police), with schizoanalysis. The goal of schizoanalysis is to undo the harm done by psychoanalysis~ to de-oedipalize the unconscious or undo the "daddy-mommy spider web" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983: 112). (Thus, in poststructuraIJpostmodern terms Deleuze and Guattari are interested in decon structing the oedipal conlplex.) In so doing, schizoanalysis would be better able to get at peoples' real problems. And at least one of those real problems is the desire of people for their own represssion.
families ... play at Oedipus . ... But behind all this, there is an e mother reduced to housework, or to a difficult and uninteresting jo dren whose future remains uncertain; the father who has had it mouths-in short, a fundamental relation to the outside of whi washes his hands, too attentive to seeing that his clients play nice g Deleuze and Gu
Oedipus is also seen as being more directly a product of the c Deleuzeand Guattari (1972/1983:267) graphically put it, "it shit or a wave of incest that Oedipus arrives, but via the decode money." Oedipus is used in capitalism to colonize our families selves. It also helps the family play its essential role in capitali duction and of reproduction" (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983 Yet we need to be cautious here because Deleuze and Guat structuralists and postmodernists, reject the idea of a grand nar lutionary subject that will solve all of our problems once and vivid image of our fragmented world: "We live today in the ag bricks that have been shattered to bits, and leftovers" (De 1972/1983:42). In a fragmented world it is impossible to gener about it or about overcoming it: "We no longer believe in a pr once existed, or in a final totality that awaits us at some future Guattari, 1972/1983:42). Instead of a single grand revolution, cault, in terms of microphysics and "infinitesimal lines of es Guattari, 1972/1983:280). Eschewing the Enlightenment, its p tions, Deleuze and Guattari refuse to offer a clear political pr fered one, it would have been "grotesque and disquieting (Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:380).
They are content to remain with schizoanalysis in which the objective is not the construction of a nc\v \A/orld but rather deconstruction: Dcstroy~ destroy. The task of schizoanalysis goes by way of destruction-a whole scour ing of the unconscious, a complete curettage. Destroy Oedipus, the illusion of the ego~ the puppet of the superego, guilt~ the law, castration.
(Deleuze and Guattari, 1972/1983:311; see also 381)
The goal of such destruction is to liberate schizoid flows that are inherent to desir ing-machines. In the end, Deleuze and Guattari oppose all grand narratives-capitalism, Marx ism, psychoanalysis-based on rational principles. Instead, they end up favoring the irrationality of schizophrenia and of desire. The solution to the problems posed by the rational systems put in place by the grand narratives lies in irrationality.
JEAN-FRAN