Published 2001 by Humanity Books, an imprint of Prometheus Books
New Essays in Fichte's Foundation of the Entire Doctri...
10 downloads
476 Views
33MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Published 2001 by Humanity Books, an imprint of Prometheus Books
New Essays in Fichte's Foundation of the Entire Doctrine of Scientific Knowledge. Copyright © 2001 by Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, digital, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise or conveyed via the Internet or a Web site without prior written permission of the publisher, except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. Inquiries should be addressed to Humanity Books 59 John Glenn Drive Amherst, New York 14228-2197 VOICE: 716-691-0133, ext. 207 FA)(:716-564-2711 WWWPROMETHEUSBOOKS.COM 05 04 03 02 01
5 432 1
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data New essays in Fichte's Foundation of the entire doctrine of scientific knowledge / edited by Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore.
p. em. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 1-57392-916-)( (alk. paper) 1. Fichte,Johann Gottlieb, 1762-1814. Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre. 2. Knowledge, Theory of. 1. Breazeale, Daniel. II. Rockmore, Tom, 1942B2824 .N49 2001
193-dc21
2001024653 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper
INTRODUCTION Tom Rocl<more
T
his volume is the third in a series culled from the conferences organized by the North American Fichte Society. It contains a carefully selected series of fresh essays presented at a conference in Shakertown at Pleasantville, Kentucky, May 15-19, 1995, organized around J. G. Fichte's Foundation of the Entire Wissenschaftslehre (Grundlage der gesamten vVissenschaftslehre, 1794).1 Fichte's Grundlages der gesantten Wissenschaftslehre (1794) is the first of many versions, some sixteen in all, that he published during his lifetime or that were later found in his Nachlass. It is triply interesting as the first major text in the corpus of a philosopher of the first rank, as the first major text of what as the result of Fichte's intervention in the debate was to become post-Kantian German idealism, and as a work brimming with insights that even today retains much of its original interest. There is probably no typical scenario for the emergence of an important philosophical theory. The positions of the major philosophers arose in very different ways: for Plato through the reporting of the discussions led by his teacher, Socrates; for Kant through a series of writings composed over many years as a result of which he discovered the central insights of his mature theory; for Berkeley as early as his first important text when he was still in his early twenties, and so on. We know that Fichte's position arose when, while still a young man, he was mistakenly identified as the author of Immanuel Kant's long-awaited work on religion, which led to him being awarded a professorship at the University of Jena, at the time the most important German-speaking university. 7
o
INTRODUCTION
Fichte's characteristic doctrines were formulated when he was asked to review of book by a little-known contemporary skeptic, G. E. Schulze, who wrote under the pseudonym of Aenesidemus, the Greek skeptic of the Second Academy. The ideas stated in this review provided the basis for Fichte's rapid subsequent formulation of his position for contingent reasons. At that time Fichte began to teach, it was usual for philosophers to use manuals in teaching their classes. For this purpose, Kant used texts prepared by others. G. W F. Hegel wrote his own. The Encyclopedia ifthe Philosophical Sciences and the Philosophy if Right are manuals he composed for his students. Fichte, who needed such a text for his teaching, hurriedly composed his own from week to week in the form of handouts to students in his classes. When he learned he was to replace K. L. Reinhold in Jena, Fichte had never taught. On Johann Kaspar Lavater's invitation,2 Fichte gave a series of lectures from February 24 to April 26, 1794, in Zurich before a select audience of about half a dozen pastors and politicians. The rehearsal of the lectures Fichte planned to give in Jena was in fact the original version of the theory, but not its first published version. The first published version of the new position that he was quickly to expound in the Grundlage der gesamten Wissenscluiftslehre literally emerged page by page as Fichte frantically wrote the manual he thought he required at the beginning of his teaching career. Great philosophical treatises, those very few books whose ideas continue to resonate throughout the later debate, are sometimes written quickly, even very quickly. It is often said that Kant, who spent a dozen years thinking out his critical philosophy, wrote the Critique of Pure Reason much more rapidly, in something approaching six months. We know that the initial version of Fichte's Wissenscluiftslehre was composed page by page from June 14 until the end of July or the beginning of August 1795. It was originally printed in Leipzig in two installments in 1794 and in 1795. Since Fichte composed his book in great haste, it is not surprising that he was dissatisfied with the published version. Although he remarks in the preface that the book itself was not intended for the public, he allowed the book to reappear in 1802, in the same year that an improved version was also published. Fichte was disatisfied not only by the various editions of the published version of his position but also by his original position. Although he tried to improve its formulation, in an agonizing series of basic revisions he sought also to rework his position in a way that better corresponded to his conception of it.
Rockmore: Introduction 9
Other philosophers, dissatisfied with the results of even the most painstaking efforts over many years, have later rewritten their books. Kant revised the Critique (if Pure Reason in a second edition. Hegel twice revised the Encyclopedia. Yet in comparison, Fichte stands out for his persistent effort to perfect the basic statement of his position in a way that has no known philosophical precedent. From 1794 when the Wissenscl/(/ftslehre first began to emerge from the press until he died in 1814, Fichte steadfastly and somewhat obsessively attempted no less than fifteen more times to find a satisfactory way to express his central insights. Striving is a central Fichtean concept. To the best of my knowledge, the history of philosophy records no better instance of a philosopher striving to philosophize. Fichte's remark in passing that he needs half a lifetime of leisure to work out the Wissenschaftslehre proved to underestimate the difficulty of the task, which he was never able to complete. 3 The theory Fichte proposes in the various versions of the Wissensclwftslehre is from the beginning determined by two different elements that forever marked his life and thought: his Kantianism, which led him publically to confuse Kant's position with his own; and his equally public enthusiasm for the French Revolution. His Kantianism is a consistent, but easily misunderstood element in his writings from the Attempt At A Critique if All Revelation (versuch einer Kritik aller OjJenbanmg, 1792), his first important text, which brought him to the attention of his philosophical contemporaries, throughout all his later writings. Although deeply influenced by the critical philosophy, Fichte's position, which is never just a restatement of Kant's, is always very much his own. Fichte's identification with Kant, which he proclaimed loudly and endlessly, was personally useful, since it enabled an entirely unknown, obviously gifted, but penniless young man at a tender age to acquire an important position in the leading German university of the period. But it was also absurd by any standard, marked by characteristic hyperbole, for instance in his celebrated remark that "the majority of men could sooner be brought to believe themselves a piece of lava in the moon that the take themselves for a self,"4 which he uses to justifY the claim that he is the only one to have understood Kant. Fichte even goes so far as to assert that Kant's system is based on his own principles. 5 Fichte's Kantianism, even in its most extreme moments, is never uncritical but always critical. Fichte's own theory, as Kant soon recognized,6 is very different from Kant's. Indeed, it could hardly be otherwise, since Fichte, despite his claims to orthodoxy, is never, even at the begin-
o
INTRODUCTION
ning of his career, a mere disciple of Kant, any more than Friedrich Schelling, who early proclaimed his orthodox Fichteanism, was ever only a mere disciple of Fichte. Despite the proliferation of these and similar claims, from the beginning each was always a major philosopher, revolving in his own philosophical orbit. Although imbued with the spirit of Kant, Fichte and the other postKantian idealists are separated from him by the great French Revolution. The impact of this series of events, still the most important political cataclysm of modern times, continues to reverberate throughout modern society, including modern philosophy. When the Revolution broke out in 1789, Kant, who was sixty-five years old, had nearly finished his life's work. With the exception of the Critique