er tpaat
a
j&tftfol
ft
C
fx
A *>
*
library of pbilosopb^
EDITED BY J.
H.
MUIRHEAD,
LL.D.
INTRODUCTION TO...
72 downloads
2881 Views
24MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
er tpaat
a
j&tftfol
ft
C
fx
A *>
*
library of pbilosopb^
EDITED BY J.
H.
MUIRHEAD,
LL.D.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL PHILOSOPHY
the
same j4uthor.
PRINCIPLES OF SOCIAL RECONSTRUC TION. yd Impression. Demy 8vo. 73. 6d. net.
"Mr
Russell has written a big
and
living
book."
The
Nation.
ROADS TO FREEDOM: ANARCHISM, AND SYNDICALISM.
SOCIALISM,
Demy
8vo.
7s. 6d. net.
An first
attempt to extract the essence of these three doctrines, then as guidance for the coming recon
historically,
struction.
London
:
George Allen
&**
Unwin, Ltd.
INTRODUCTION TO
MATHEMATICAL
PHILOSOPHY BY
BERTRAND RUSSELL
LONDON
:
GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN, LTD.
NEW YORK: THE MACMILLAN
CO,
May 1919 Second Edition April 1920
First published
[All rights reserved}
PREFACE " intended essentially as an Introduction," and does not aim at giving an exhaustive discussion of the problems
THIS book
with which
is
it
deals.
It
seemed desirable to
set forth certain
results, hitherto only available to those who have mastered logical symbolism, in a form offering the minimum of difficulty
to
the beginner.
The utmost endeavour has been made
to
avoid dogmatism on such questions as are still open to serious doubt, and this endeavour has to some extent dominated the choice of topics considered. The beginnings of mathematical logic are less definitely known than its later portions, but are of Much of what is set forth at least equal philosophical interest.
not properly to be called " philosophy," though the matters concerned were included in philosophy so long as no satisfactory science of them existed. The nature of infinity and continuity, for example, belonged in former days
in the following chapters
is
to philosophy, but belongs now to mathematics. Mathematical philosophy, in the strict sense, cannot, perhaps, be held to include
such definite
scientific
results
as
have been obtained
in
this
region ; the philosophy of mathematics will naturally be ex pected to deal with questions on the frontier of knowledge, as
which comparative certainty is not yet attained. But speculation on such questions is hardly likely to be fruitful unless the more scientific parts of the principles of mathematics to
A
known. book dealing with those parts may, therefore, claim to be an introduction to mathematical philosophy, though
are
can hardly claim, except where it steps outside its province, to be actually dealing with a part of philosophy. It does deal,
it
vi
Introduction
to
Mathematical Philosophy
however, with a body of knowledge which, to those
who
accept appears to invalidate much traditional philosophy, and even a good deal of what is current in the present day. In this way, as well as by its bearing on still unsolved problems, mathematical it,
logic is relevant to philosophy.
For
this reason, as well as
on
account of the intrinsic importance of the subject, some purpose may be served by a succinct account of the main results of
mathematical logic in a form requiring neither a knowledge of mathematics nor an aptitude for mathematical symbolism. Here, however, as elsewhere, the method is more important than the results, from the point of view of further research ; and the
method cannot
well be explained within the
framework
of such
be hoped that some readers following. be interested to advance to a study of the sufficiently may method by which mathematical logic can be made helpful in a
book as the
It is to
But that investigating the traditional problems of philosophy. is a topic with which the following pages have not attempted to deal.
BERTRAND RUSSELL.
NOTE
EDITOR'S
Mathematical relying on the distinction between this Philosophy and the Philosophy of Mathematics, think that book is out of place in the present Library, may be referred to what the author himself says on this head in the Preface. It is
THOSE who,
not necessary to agree with what he there suggests as to the readjustment of the field of philosophy by the transference from it to mathematics of such problems as those of class, continuity, infinity, in order to perceive the
discussions that follow on the
bearing of the definitions and
work
of
" traditional philosophy."
philosophers cannot consent to relegate the criticism of these at any categories to any of the special sciences, it is essential, If
know the precise meaning that the science these concepts play so large a part, which mathematics, other hand, there be mathematicians on the to them. If, assigns to whom these definitions and discussions seem to be an elabora rate, that
they should in
of
and complication of the simple, it may be well to remind them from the side of philosophy that here, as elsewhere, apparent tion
conceal a complexity which it is the business of whether philosopher or mathematician, or, like the somebody, author of this volume, both in one, to unravel. simplicity
may
vii
CONTENTS
........ ....... ....
CHAP.
PREFACE
EDITOR'S NOTE
PAGE
V vii
1.
THE SERIES OF NATURAL NUMBERS
2.
DEFINITION OF
3.
FINITUDE AND MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
4.
THE DEFINITION OF ORDER
29
5.
KINDS OF RELATIONS
42
6.
SIMILARITY OF RELATIONS
7. 8.
9.
NUMBER
12.
.
.
.
.
..... ...... ... ..... .... ...... .
.
.
AND CONTINUITY LIMITS AND CONTINUITY OF FUNCTIONS SELECTIONS AND THE MULTIPLICATIVE AXIOM .
.
.
I
,11
RATIONAL, REAL, AND COMPLEX NUMBERS INFINITE CARDINAL NUMBERS INFINITE SERIES AND ORDINALS
10. LIMITS 11.
.
.
2O
S2
63
77 89
97 107 IJ 7
.
14.
THE AXIOM OF INFINITY AND LOGICAL TYPES INCOMPATIBILITY AND THE THEORY OF DEDUCTION
15.
PROPOSITIONAL FUNCTIONS
155
16.
DESCRIPTIONS
167
17.
CLASSES
18.
MATHEMATICS AND LOGIC
194
INDEX
207
13.
.
.
..... ........ .... ...... .
Viii
.
131
144
l8l
Introduction to
Mathematical Philosophy CHAPTER
I
THE SERIES OF NATURAL NUMBERS MATHEMATICS
is
when we
a study which,
start
from
its
most
familiar portions, may be pursued in either of two opposite directions. The more familiar direction is constructive, towards
gradually increasing complexity real
:
numbers, complex numbers
plication to differentiation
mathematics.
The other
and
;
from integers to fractions, from addition and multi
and on to higher
integration,
direction,
which
is
less
familiar,
proceeds, by analysing, greater and greater abstractness and logical simplicity instead of asking what can be defined to
;
is assumed to begin with, we ask instead what more general ideas and principles can be found, in terms of which what was our starting-point can be defined or deduced.
and deduced from what
It is the fact of
pursuing this opposite direction that characterises mathematical philosophy as opposed to ordinary mathematics.
But
it
should be understood that the distinction
the subject matter, but in the state of
mind
is
one, not in
of the investigator.
Early Greek geometers, passing from the empirical rules of
Egyptian land-surveying to the general propositions by which those rules were found to be justifiable, and thence to Euclid's axioms and postulates, were engaged in mathematical philos ophy, according to the above definition ; but when once the axioms and postulates had been reached, their deductive employ ment, as we find it in Euclid, belonged to mathematics in the I
2
Introduction sense.
ordinary
The
Mathematical Philosophy
to
between
distinction
mathematics
and
one which depends upon the interest and the research, upon the stage which the research inspiring has reached ; not upon the propositions with which the research
mathematical philosophy
is
is
concerned.
We may state the same distinction in another way. The most obvious and easy things in mathematics are not those that come logically at the beginning they are things that, from ;
the point of view of logical deduction, come somewhere in the middle. Just as the easiest bodies to see are those that are neither very near nor very far, neither very small nor very great, so the easiest conceptions to grasp are those that are
"
"
neither very complex nor very simple (using in a simple And as we need two sorts of instruments, the logical sense). telescope
and the microscope, for the enlargement of our visual we need two sorts of instruments for the enlargement
powers, so
of our logical powers,
one to take us forward to the higher
mathematics, the other to take us backward to the logical foundations of the things that we are inclined to take for granted in mathematics. We shall find that by analysing our ordinary
mathematical notions we acquire fresh insight, new powers, and the means of reaching whole new mathematical subjects
by adopting It is the
fresh lines of
purpose of this
advance
after our
backward journey.
book to explain mathematical philos
ophy simply and untechnically, without enlarging upon those portions which are so doubtful or difficult that an elementary
treatment
is
in Principia
A
full treatment will be found scarcely possible. * the treatment in the present volume ;
Mathematica
intended merely as an introduction. To the average educated person of the present day, the obvious starting-point of mathematics would be the series of
is
whole numbers, i, 1
2,
3, 4,
Cambridge University Press,
By Whitehead and
Russell.
vol.
... i.,
1910
etc.
;
vol.
ii.,
1911
;
vol.
iii.,
1913.
The
of Natural Numbers
Series
3
Probably only a person with some mathematical knowledge would think of beginning with o instead of with i, but we will this degree of knowledge the series point
presume
;
we
take as our starting-
will
:
o,
and "
it
i,
2,
3,
this series that
is
series of natural
.
we
.
.
n,
shall
n+ 1,
.
.
.
mean when we speak
of the
numbers."
high stage of civilisation that we could take our starting-point. It must have required many ages to discover that a brace of pheasants and a couple of days were both instances of the number 2 the degree of abstraction It is only at a
this series as
:
from easy. must have been difficult.
involved
is
far
the Greeks and
And As
the discovery that I is a number for o, it is a very recent addition ;
Romans had no such
digit.
we had been earlier days, we If
embarking upon mathematical philosophy in should have had to start with something less abstract than the series of natural numbers, which we should reach as a stage on
our backward journey. When the logical foundations of mathe matics have grown more familiar, we shall be able to start further back, at what is now a late stage in our analysis. But for the
moment
the natural numbers seem to represent what
and most familiar
But though
in
is
easiest
mathematics.
familiar,
they are not understood.
Very few
people are prepared with a definition of what is meant by " " " I." It is not very difficult to see that, number," or o," or starting from o,
by
any other
repeated additions of
of the natural
numbers can be reached
I, but we shall have to define what " and what we mean
we mean by " adding I," These questions are by no means
by
repeated."
It was believed until easy. recently that some, at least, of these first notions of arithmetic
must be accepted as too simple and primitive to be defined. Since all terms that are defined are defined by means of other terms,
it is
to accept
clear that
some terms
human knowledge must always
be content
as intelligible without definition, in order
Introduction
4 to
to
Mathematical Philosophy
have a starting-point for its definitions. must be terms which are incapable
there
however
possible that, might go further
when
that,
still.
far
back we go in
On
It is not clear that
of definition
defining,
the other hand,
it
is
analysis has been pushed far enough,
:
it
is
we always
also possible
we can reach
terms that really are simple, and therefore logically incapable This is a of the sort of definition that consists in analysing. question which
purposes
it
is
not necessary for us to decide ; for our sufficient to observe that, since human powers it
is
known to us must always begin some for the moment, though perhaps undefined with terms where, not permanently. are finite, the definitions
All traditional pure mathematics, including analytical geom of propositions etry, may be regarded as consisting wholly
That is to say, the terms which means of the natural numbers, and occur can be defined by about the natural numbers.
the propositions can be deduced from the properties of the natural numbers with the addition, in each case, of the ideas
and propositions of pure logic. That all traditional pure mathematics can be derived from the natural numbers
long been suspected.
is
a fairly recent discovery, though it had who believed that not only
Pythagoras,
but everything else could be deduced from the discoverer of the most serious obstacle in was numbers, " " of mathematics. the way of what is called the arithmetising It was Pythagoras who discovered the existence of incommathematics,
mensurables, and, in particular, the incommensurability of the and the diagonal. If the length of the side is of inches in the diagonal is the square root number I inch, the
side of a square
of 2,
which appeared not to be a number at
all.
The problem
thus raised was solved only in our own day, and was only solved to logic, completely by the help of the reduction of arithmetic
be explained in following chapters. For the present, we shall take for granted the arithmetisation of mathematics,
which
will
though
this
was a
feat of the very greatest importance.
The Having reduced
5
traditional pure mathematics to the numbers, the next step in logical analysis
all
theory of the natural
was to reduce
of Natural Numbers
Series
this theory itself to the smallest set of premisses
and undefined terms from which
it
This work
could be derived.
was accomplished by Peano. He showed that the entire theory of the natural numbers could be derived from three primitive and
ideas
five primitive propositions in
These three ideas and
addition to those of
thus became, whole of traditional pure mathe If they could be defined and proved in terms of others, matics. " so could all pure mathematics. Their logical weight," if one
pure
as
logic.
five propositions
were, hostages for the
it
use such an expression,
may
is equal to that of the whole series have been deduced from the theory of the natural the truth of this whole series is assured if the truth
of sciences that
numbers
;
of the five primitive propositions is guaranteed, provided,
course, that there
of
nothing erroneous in the purely logical also involved. The work of analysing mathe is
apparatus which is matics is extraordinarily facilitated by this work of Peano's. The three primitive ideas in Peano's arithmetic are :
o,
By
number, successor.
" successor " he means the next number in the natural
That
order. I is 2,
to say, the successor of o
is
the class
is
I,
the successor of
" number " he means, in this connection, of the natural numbers. 1 He is not assuming that
and so on.
By
we know all the members of this class, but only that we know what we mean when we say that this or that is a number, just " as we know what we mean when we say Jones is a man," though we do not know all men individually. The five primitive propositions which Peano assumes are :
(1)
o
(2)
The
(3) 1
is
a number.
number is a number. No two numbers have the same successor. successor of any
We shall
use
wards the word
"
number "
will
in this sense in the present chapter.
be used in a more general sense.
After
6
Introduction
(4)
o
(5)
Any
is
to
Mathematical Philosophy
not the successor of any number.
property which belongs to o, and also to the successor number which has the property, belongs to all
of every
numbers.
The
We
the principle of mathematical induction.
last of these is
shall
have much to say concerning mathematical induction
in the sequel
for the present,
;
we
are concerned with
it
only
occurs in Peano's analysis of arithmetic. Let us consider briefly the kind of way in which the theory of the natural numbers results from these three ideas and five as
it
" the successor of o," begin with, we define I as " the successor of We can obviously go 2 as I," and so on.
To
propositions.
on as long as we (2),
like
with these definitions, since, in virtue of will have a successor, and, in
every number that we reach
virtue of
because, successor
(3), this if it ;
cannot be any of the numbers already defined,
were, two different numbers would have the
and
in virtue of (4)
in the series of successors can be o.
numbers we reach
Thus the
series of successors
gives us an endless series of continually of (5) all
numbers come
same
of the
none
in this series,
new numbers.
In virtue
which begins with o and
on through successive successors for (a) o belongs to this series, and (b) if a number n belongs to it, so does its successor, whence, by mathematical induction, every number belongs to travels
:
the series.
Suppose we wish to define the sum of two numbers. Taking any number m, we define m-\-o as m, and m-\-(n-{-i) as the successor of m-\-n.
the
sum
we can
of
m
and
In virtue of n,
(5)
this gives a definition of
whatever number n
define the product of
may
any two numbers.
be.
Similarly
The reader can
easily convince himself that
any ordinary elementary proposition can be proved by means of our five premisses, he has any difficulty he can find the proof in Peano.
of arithmetic
and
if
It is
time
now
make it Peano, who
to turn to the considerations which
necessary to advance beyond the standpoint of
The represents
the
of Natural Numbers
Series
last
perfection
mathematics, to that of Frege,
the
of
7
" arithmetisation "
who first succeeded in "
of
" logicising
mathematics, i.e. in reducing to logic the arithmetical notions which his predecessors had shown to be sufficient for mathematics.
We
shall not, in this chapter, actually give Frege's definition of
of particular numbers, but we shall give some of the Peano's treatment is less final than it appears to be. why In the first place, Peano's three primitive ideas namely, " o," " " " are capable of an infinite number number," and successor of different interpretations, all of which will satisfy the five
number and
reasons
primitive propositions.
We
will give
some examples.
" o " be taken " number " be to mean loo, and let (1) Let taken to mean the numbers from 100 onward in the series of
numbers.
natural satisfied,
99
99,
to the
is
Then
word " number."
our
all
even the fourth, " not a number "
are
propositions
primitive
though 100 is the successor of in the sense which we are now giving
It
for,
is
obvious that any number
may
be
substituted for 100 in this example. " " o have its usual meaning, (2) Let
but let " number " " mean what we usually call even numbers," and let the " successor " of a number be what results from adding two to it. Then " I " will stand for the number two, " 2 " will stand " numbers " for the number four, and so on ; the series of now will
be o,
two, four, six, eight
All Peano's five premisses are satisfied (3)
.
.
.
still.
Let " o " mean the number one,
let
" number " mean
the set !>
and
let
axioms
"successor"
will
fact,
1>
i TV
mean "half."
be true of this
It is clear that
In
i>
Then
all
Peano's
five
set.
such examples might be multiplied indefinitely.
given any series
Introduction
8
which
to
endless, contains
is
Mathematical Philosophy no
repetitions, has a beginning,
and
has no terms that cannot be reached from the beginning in a finite number of steps, we have a set of terms verifying Peano's This
axioms.
what
(2)
though the formal proof is some mean # let " number " mean the whole " successor " of # mean x the Then
easily seen,
" o" Let
long.
set of terms, (1)
is
and
let
,
n
n+l .
" o is a number," i.e. x is a member of the set. " The successor of any number is a number,"
any term xn " (3)
xn+l
in the set,
different
;
different
the same successor," i.e. if xm of the set, x m+l and xn+l are
members
from the fact that (by hypothesis) there
this results
are no repetitions in the set. " o is not the successor of any number," (4)
the set comes before x (5)
This becomes
no term
i.e.
in
.
Any
:
taking
also in the set.
is
No two numbers have
and xn are two
i.e.
property which belongs to x09 and belongs to xn belongs to all the x's.
belongs to xn+l provided it This follows from the corresponding property for numbers. series of the form ,
A
in
which there
there
is
no
is
a
term, a successor to each term (so that
first
last term),
no
repetitions,
reached from the start in a progression.
and every term can be
number
of steps,
is
called a
Progressions are of great importance in the princi
As we have
ples of mathematics. verifies
finite
Peano's five axioms.
just seen, every progression can be proved, conversely, Peano's five axioms is a pro
It
that every series which verifies Hence these five axioms gression. class of progressions
"
may "
be used to define the " those series which
are
progressions verify these five axioms." Any progression may be taken as we may give the name " o " the basis of pure mathematics :
:
name " number
"
to the whole set of its " successor " to the the name and next in the progression. terms, The progression need not be composed of numbers it may be to its first term, the
:
The composed
Series of
Natural Numbers
of points in space, or
terms of which there
is
an
progression will give rise to
moments
9
of time, or
any other
Each
different supply. a different interpretation of all the infinite
propositions of traditional pure mathematics
all
;
these possible
interpretations will be equally true. In Peano's system there is nothing to enable us to distinguish
between these It is
different interpretations of his primitive ideas.
meant by " o," and that symbol means 100 or Cleopatra's
assumed that we know what
we
is
shall not suppose that this Needle or any of the other things that it might mean. " " o" and " number " and "successor This point, that
cannot be defined by means of Peano's five axioms, but must be independently understood, is important. We want our numbers not merely to verify mathematical formulae, but to apply in the right
way
to
common
objects.
We
want
to
have "
A
"
I ten fingers and two eyes and one nose. system in which meant 100, and " 2 " meant 101, and so on, might be all right
pure mathematics, but would not suit daily life. We want " o " and " number " and " successor " to have meanings which
for
will give
We
us the right allowance of fingers and eyes and noses. (though not sufficiently " " " "
have already some knowledge
and 2 and what we mean by I numbers in arithmetic must conform to
articulate or analytic) of
so on,
and our use
of
We
cannot secure that this shall be the case knowledge. all method that we can do, if we adopt his method, Peano's ; by ' ' " we know what we mean * ' is to say by o and number and ' successor,' though we cannot explain what we mean in terms this
of other simpler concepts."
when we must, and object of
It is quite legitimate to
at some point
we
all
mathematical philosophy to put
as possible.
By
must
;
but
off
say this it is
it
the
as long
saying the logical theory of arithmetic we are able to
for a very long time. " " and o might be suggested that, instead of setting up " number " " " and as terms of which we know the successor
put
it off
It
meaning although we cannot define them, we might
let
them
io
Introduction
Mathematical Philosophy
to
stand for any three terms that verify Peano's five axioms. They will then no longer be terms which have a meaning that is definite
though undefined: they will be "variables," terms concerning which we make certain hypotheses, namely, those stated in the axioms, but which are otherwise undetermined. If we adopt our theorems will not be proved concerning an ascer " the natural tained set of terms called numbers," but concerning five
this plan,
all sets is
of terms
not fallacious
;
having certain properties. Such a procedure indeed for certain purposes it represents a
valuable generalisation.
But from two points
of
view
it
fails
In the first place, it to give an adequate basis for arithmetic. does not enable us to know whether there are any sets of terms verifying Peano's axioms
suggestion of
any way
;
it
does not even give the faintest whether there are such sets.
of discovering
In the second place, as already observed, we want our numbers to be such as can be used for counting common objects, and this requires that our
numbers should have a
definite
meaning, not
merely that they should have certain formal properties. This definite meaning is defined by the logical theory of arithmetic.
CHAPTER
NUMBER
DEFINITION OF
THE
" question
What
is
II
"
number
a
?
is
one which has been
often asked, but has only been correctly answered in our own time. The answer was given by Frege in 1884, in his Grundlagen
Although this book is quite short, not difficult, the very highest importance, it attracted almost no attention, and the definition of number which it contains re
der Arithmetik*
and
of
mained practically unknown
until
it
was rediscovered by the
present author in 1901. In seeking a definition of number, the
about
is
what we may
first
thing to be clear
grammar of our inquiry. attempting to define number, are call
the
Many
really philosophers, when setting to work to define plurality, which is quite a different Number is what is characteristic of numbers, as man thing. is
what
is
characteristic of
A
men.
plurality
is
not an instance
number, but of some particular number. A trio of men, for example, is an instance of the number 3, and the number of
an instance of number
3 is
;
but the
trio is
not an instance of
This point may seem elementary and scarcely worth mentioning ; yet it has proved too subtle for the philosophers,
number.
with few exceptions.
A
particular number is not identical with any collection of terms having that number the number 3 is not identical with :
1
The same answer
is
given more fully and with more development in
his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, vol.
i.,
1893.
12
Introduction
to
Mathematical Philosophy
The number
the trio consisting of Brown, Jones, and Robinson.
something which all trios have in common, and which dis tinguishes them from other collections. A number is something that characterises certain collections, namely, those that have 3 is
that number.
"
Instead of speaking of a collection," " set." " of a class," or sometimes a
mathematics fold."
We
we
shall as a rule speak Other words used in " and " mani
same thing are " aggregate have much to say later on about
for the
shall
the present,
we
will
say as little as possible.
classes.
For
But there are
some remarks that must be made immediately. A class or collection may be defined in two ways that at first We may enumerate its members, as sight seem quite distinct. when we say, " The collection I mean is Brown, Jones, and Robinson." Or we may mention a defining property, as when we speak of " mankind " or " the inhabitants of London." The definition
sion,"
which enumerates
is
called a definition
by
" exten
and the one which mentions a defining property is called " by intension." Of these two kinds of definition,
a definition
the one by intension is logically more fundamental. This is shown by two considerations (i) that the extensional defini :
tion can always be reduced to an intensional one; (2) that the intensional one often cannot even theoretically be reduced to
Each
the extensional one.
of
these points needs a
word
of
explanation.
Brown, Jones, and Robinson all of them possess a certain property which is possessed by nothing else in the whole universe, (i)
namely, the property of being either Brown or Jones or Robinson. This property can be used to give a definition by intension of
Brown and Jones and Robinson. Con " x is Brown or x is Jones or x is Robinson."
the class consisting of sider such a formula as
This formula will be true for just three x's, namely, Brown and Jones and Robinson. In this respect it resembles a cubic equa tion with its three roots. It may be taken as assigning a property
common
to the
members
of the class consisting of these three
Definition of
men, and peculiar to them.
A
Number
13
similar treatment can obviously
be applied to any other class given in extension. (2) It is obvious that in practice we can often
know
deal about a class without being able to enumerate
No
its
a great
members.
man
could actually enumerate all men, or even all the inhabitants of London, yet a great deal is known about each of
one
This
these classes.
enough to show that definition by extension
is
not necessary to knowledge about a class. But when we come to consider infinite classes, we find that enumeration is not even
is
who only live for a finite time. the natural numbers : they are o, I, 2,
theoretically possible for beings
We
cannot enumerate
3, and so on. " and so on."
numbers, or
all
At some point we must content ourselves with
We cannot enumerate all fractions or all irrational of
ledge in regard to definition
by
all
any other all
infinite collection.
Thus our know
such collections can only be derived from a
intension.
These remarks are relevant, when we are seeking the definition of number, in three different ways. In the first place, numbers themselves form an infinite collection, and cannot therefore be defined by enumeration. In the second place, the collections
having a given number of terms themselves presumably form an it is to be presumed, for example, that there
infinite collection
:
are an infinite collection of trios in the world, for
if
this
were
not the case the total number of things in the world would be In the third finite, which, though possible, seems unlikely. " number " we wish to define such a in place, way that infinite
numbers may be possible thus we must be able to speak of the number of terms in an infinite collection, and such a collection ;
must be defined by intension, i.e. by a property common to members and peculiar to them. For many purposes, a class and a defining characteristic
all
its
it
are practically interchangeable.
The
the two consists in the fact that there
is
vital difference
of
between
only one class having a
given set of members, whereas there are always many different characteristics by which a given class may be defined. Men
Introduction
14
to
Mathematical Philosophy
be defined as featherless bipeds, or as rational animals, or (more correctly) by the traits by which Swift delineates the
may
Yahoos.
It is this fact that a defining characteristic is
unique which makes
classes
useful
;
otherwise
never
we could be
the properties common and peculiar to their Any one of these properties can be used in place
content with
members. 1
whenever uniqueness is not important. Returning now to the definition of number, it
of the class
number
a
is
way
those that have a given all
couples in
way we
this
is
clear that
of bringing together certain collections, namely,
one bundle,
We
number
of terms.
all trios
in another,
can suppose In
and so on.
obtain various bundles of collections, each bundle have a certain number of
consisting of all the collections that
Each bundle
terms. i.e.
classes
;
a class whose
is
thus each
is
members are collections, The bundle con
a class of classes.
sisting of all couples, for example, is a class of classes is
couple
is
couples
which
is
How
each
a class with an infinite
number
of
members, each
of
a class of two members. shall
we
decide whether two collections are to belong ? The answer that suggests itself is " Find
same bundle
to the
:
a class with two members, and the whole bundle of
:
how many members
each has, and put them in the same they have the same number of members." But this presupposes that we have defined numbers, and that we know out
bundle
how
if
to discover
how many terms
a collection has.
We
are so
used to the operation of counting that such a presupposition might easily pass unnoticed. In fact, however, counting,
more complex operation means of discovering how many terms a collection has, when the collection is finite. Our defini tion of number must not assume in advance that all numbers are finite ; and we cannot in any case, without a vicious circle,
though over
familiar,
it is
is
logically a very
;
only available, as a
1 As will be explained later, classes may be regarded as logical fictions, manufactured out of denning characteristics. But for the present it will simplify our exposition to treat classes as if they were real.
Number
Definition of
1
5
use counting to define numbers, because numbers are used in counting. We need, therefore, some other method of deciding when two collections have the same number of terms.
In actual fact,
it is
simpler logically to find out whether two
have the same number
collections
what that number
is.
An
of terms
illustration
than
will
it is
make
to define
this
clear.
there were no
polygamy or polyandry anywhere in the world, it is clear that the number of husbands living at any moment would be exactly the same as the number of wives. We do If
not need a census to assure us of
this,
nor do
we need
to
know know
number of husbands and of wives. We number must be the same in both collections, because each husband has one wife and each wife has one husband. The " relation of husband and wife is what is called one-one." what
is
the actual
the
A
relation
is
said to be
"
one-one
"
when,
if
x has the relation
no other term x' has the same relation to y, and x does not have the same relation to any term y' other than y. When only the first of these two conditions is fulfilled, the relation is called " one-many " ; when only the second is
in question to y,
the
number
I is
"
many-one." It should be observed that not used in these definitions.
fulfilled, it is called
In Christian countries, the relation of husband to wife is one-one ; in Mahometan countries it is one-many ; in Tibet it is many-one. The relation of father to son is one-many ; that of son to father is
one-one.
one-one
;
so
is
many-one, but that of eldest son to father
If
n
is
the relation of n to 2n or to
is
any number, the
relation of
3.
n
to
-|-i
When we
considering only positive numbers, the relation of one-one ; but when negative numbers are admitted,
is
are 2
n
to
it
becomes
is
n have the same square. These instances two-one, since n and should suffice to make clear the notions of one-one, and many-one
relations,
one-many, which play a great part in the princi
mathematics, not only in relation to the definition of numbers, but in many other connections. Two classes are said to be " similar " when there is a one-one
ples of
1
6
Introduction
Mathematical Philosophy
to
which correlates the terms of the one
relation
one term of the other
class, in the
class
same manner
in
each with
which the
husbands with wives.
relation of marriage correlates
A
few
preliminary definitions will help us to state this definition more The class of those terms that have a given relation precisely. to something or other
domain
called the
is
of that relation
:
thus fathers are the domain of the relation of father to child, husbands are the domain of the relation of husband to wife,
wives are the domain of the relation of wife to husband, and husbands and wives together are the domain of the relation of marriage. The relation of wife to husband is called the converse of the relation of husband to wife. Similarly less is the converse of greater, later is the converse of earlier, and so on. Generally, the converse of a given relation
is
that relation which holds
between y and x whenever the given relation holds between x and y. The converse domain of a relation is the domain of its
converse
of the
:
thus the class of wives
husband to
relation of
definition of similarity as follows
One
class is said to be
"
if
similar
"
to
that
if
relation
a
is
is
is
when
a
(3)
the
(i)
similar to
j3
and
j8
said to be reflexive
it
is
that every class is similar to itself, similar to a class j3, then j3 is similar to a,
is
domain.
when
to y, then
when
it
a
(2)
A
similar to y. possesses the first of these is
possesses the second, and transi It is obvious that a relation possesses the third.
properties, symmetrical tive
another when there
the
prove
a class a
state our
domain, while
other is the converse
that
the converse domain
:
one-one relation of which the one class
It is easy to
is
We may now
wife.
it
is symmetrical and transitive must be reflexive throughout domain. Relations which possess these properties are an
which its
important kind, and it is worth while to note that similarity one of this kind of relations. It
is
obvious to
the same
The
number
common
of terms
if
is
sense that two finite classes have
they are similar, but not otherwise.
act of counting consists in establishing a one-one correlation
Definition of
Number
17
between the set of objects counted and the natural numbers (excluding o) that are used up in the process. Accordingly
common
sense concludes that there are as
many
objects in the
number we confine ourselves to finite numbers, there are just n numbers from I up to n. Hence it follows that the last number used in counting a collection is the number of terms in the collection, provided the collection is finite. But this result, besides being
set to
be counted as there are numbers up to the
used in the counting.
And we
also
know
last
that, so long as
only applicable to finite collections, depends upon and assumes the fact that two classes which are similar have the same number of terms
for
;
what we do when we count
show that the set of these I to 10. The notion of
is
objects
(say) 10 objects
similar to the set of is
similarity
logically
is
to
numbers
presupposed in
the operation of counting, and is logically simpler though less In counting, it is necessary to take the objects counted familiar. in a certain order, as first, second, third, etc., but order is not of the essence of
number
:
an irrelevant addition, an un
it is
The logical point of view. notion of similarity does not demand an order for example, we saw that the number of husbands is the same as the number necessary complication from the
:
without having to establish an order of precedence The notion of similarity also does not require
of wives,
among them.
that the classes which are similar should be
finite.
Take, for
example, the natural numbers (excluding o) on the one hand, and the fractions which have I for their numerator on the other
hand
:
it is
obvious that
we can
so on, thus proving that the
two
correlate 2 with J, 3 with J,
and
classes are similar.
thus use the notion of " similarity " to decide when two collections are to belong to the same bundle, in the sense
We may
which we were asking this question earlier in this chapter. We want to make one bundle containing the class that has no
in
members
:
this will
be for the number
of all the classes that
number
I.
o.
have one member
Then, for the number
2,
Then we want :
this will
we want
a bundle
be for the
a bundle consisting 2
1
Introduction
8
of all couples tion,
;
we can
to
then one of
Mathematical Philosophy all trios
define the bundle
of all those collections that are
to see that
;
it is
"
and so on.
Given any
collec
to belong to as being the class
similar
"
to it. It is very easy has three a collection members, the (for example) those collections that are similar to it will be the
if
class of all
class of trios.
And whatever number
terms a collection
of
may
"
"
similar to it will have the same have, those collections that are number of terms. We may take this as a definition of " having the same number of terms." It is obvious that it gives results
conformable to usage so long as we confine ourselves to
finite
collections.
we have not suggested anything in the slightest degree paradoxical. But when we come to the actual definition of numbers we cannot avoid what must at first sight seem a paradox, So
far
though this impression will soon wear off. We naturally think that the class of couples (for example) is something different from the number 2. But there is no doubt about the class of it couples the number :
is
indubitable and not difficult to define, whereas
any other sense, is a metaphysical entity about which we can never feel sure that it exists or that we have tracked it
down.
2, in
It is therefore
more prudent
to content ourselves with
the class of couples, which we are sure of, than to hunt for a problematical number 2 which must always remain elusive.
Accordingly
we
set
The number of a similar
up the following
definition
:
class is the class of all those classes that are
to it.
Thus the number
of a couple will be the class of all couples. In fact, the class of all couples will be the number 2, according to our definition. At the expense of a little oddity, this definition
secures definiteness
and indubitableness
;
and
it is
not
difficult
numbers so defined have all the properties that we numbers to have. expect We may now go on to define numbers in general as any one of the bundles into which similarity collects classes. A number will be a set of classes such as that any two are similar to each to prove that
Definition of
Number
1
9
any inside the set. which is In other words, a number (in general) any the number of one of its members or, more simply still and none outside the
other,
set are similar to
collection
is
:
;
A
anything which is the number of some class. Such a definition has a verbal appearance of being circular, " " the number of a given class but in fact it is not. We define without using the notion of number in general ; therefore we may " the number of a define number in general in terms of given " class without committing any logical error.
number
is
The class Definitions of this sort are in fact very common. be defined first of fathers, for example, would have to defining by what will
it is
be
all
to be the father of
those
who
to define square
mean by saying
somebody
;
then the class of fathers
are somebody's father.
that
Similarly if we want define what we
(say), we must first one number is the square
numbers
of another,
and
then define square numbers as those that are the squares of other numbers. This kind of procedure is very common, and it
is
important to
realise that it
is
legitimate and even often
necessary.
We
have now given a definition of numbers which
for finite collections.
for infinite collections.
by
"
finite
"
and "
It
remains to be seen
But
infinite,"
first
we must
how
will serve will serve
it
decide what
we mean
which cannot be done within the
limits of the present chapter.
CHAPTER
III
FINITUDE AND MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION
THE
numbers, as we saw in Chapter I., can all be defined if we know what we mean by the three terms " o," " " But we may go a step farther successor." number," and we can define all the natural numbers if we know what we mean " o " and " us to understand the successor." It will series of natural
:
by
help
difference
between
finite
and
infinite to see
and why the method by which beyond the cessor
"
We will not yet
finite.
these
this
can be done,
moment assume that terms mean, and show how thence all other
are to be defined
we know what
how
done cannot be extended " o " and " consider how suc
it is
we
:
will for the
natural numbers can be obtained. It is easy to see that
we can reach any
assigned number, say " as " the successor of o," then we " " " define 2 as the successor of I," and so on. In the case of 30,000.
We
first
define
"
I
an assigned number, such as 30,000, the proof that we can reach by proceeding step by step in this fashion may be made, if we
it
have the patience, by actual experiment
:
we can go on
until
But although the method of at 30,000. each for available particular natural number, it experiment the is not available for general proposition that all such proving
we
arrive
actually
is
numbers can be reached in this way, i.e. by proceeding from o Is there step by step from each number to its successor. any other way by which this can be proved ? Let us consider the question the other way round. What are "o" and the numbers that can be reached, given the terms
and Mathematical
Finitude
" successor " whole
class of
such numbers
the successor of
2, as
any way by which we can define the We reach I, as the successor of o ; ?
Is there
?
21
Induction
I
3,
;
as the successor of 2
;
and so on.
It
"
"
that we wish to replace by something less and so on this " and vague and indefinite. We might be tempted to say that " means that the process of proceeding to the successor so on is
be repeated any finite number of times
may
upon which we
but the problem ; " the problem of defining finite must not use this notion in our defini
are engaged
is
number," and therefore we Our definition must not assume that we know what a tion.
number is. The key to our problem lies in mathematical induction. It will be remembered that, in Chapter I., this was the fifth of the five primitive propositions which we laid down about the natural finite
numbers.
It stated that
to the successor of
any property which belongs to
o,
and
any number which has the property, belongs
This was then presented as a principle, but we shall now adopt it as a definition. It is not difficult to see that the terms obeying it are the same as the numbers to
the natural numbers.
all
that can be reached from o next, but as the point in
some
We
is
successive steps from next to important we will set forth the matter
by
detail.
shall
do well to begin with some
definitions,
which
will
be
useful in other connections also.
A
property
series
if,
is
said to be
whenever
in the natural-number hereditary belongs to a number , it also belongs to
it
n-j-i, the successor of n.
" tary
if,
whenever n
easy to see,
"
"
is
though we
"
heredi Similarly a class is said to be a member of the class, so is n+i. It is
are not yet supposed to know, that to say
a property is hereditary is equivalent to saying that it belongs to all the natural numbers not less than some one of them, e.g. it
must belong to
less
less
A
than 1000, or than o, i.e. to property
is
all it
all
that are not less than 100, or
may
be that
it
belongs to
without exception. " "
said to be
inductive
when
all
it is
all
that are
that are not
a
hereditary
22
Introduction
to
Mathematical Philosophy
" " inductive property which belongs to o. Similarly a class is when it is a hereditary class of which o is a member.
Given a hereditary that
I is
member
a
of
class of it,
which o
is
a member,
it
follows
because a hereditary class contains the
members, and I is the successor of o. Similarly, given a hereditary class of which I is a member, it follows that 2 is a member of it ; and so on. Thus we can prove by a stepsuccessors of
its
by-step procedure that any assigned natural number, say 30,000, a member of every inductive class. We will define the " posterity " of a given natural number with respect to the relation " immediate predecessor " (which
is
" successor ") as all those terms that belong to every hereditary class to which the given number belongs. It is again easy to see that the posterity of a natural number con is
the converse of
sists of itself
and
all
greater natural
numbers
do not yet officially know. By the above definitions, the posterity of o terms which belong to every inductive class. It is
o
now not same
difficult to
make
it
;
but
this also
we
will consist of those
obvious that the posterity of
terms that can be reached from o by successive steps from next to next. For, in the first place, o belongs to both these sets (in the sense in which we have defined is
the
our terms)
set as those
in the second place,
;
if
n belongs
to both sets, so does
be observed that we are dealing here with the n+i. kind of matter that does not admit of precise proof, namely, the It is to
comparison of a relatively vague idea with a relatively precise one. The notion of " those terms that can be reached from o " by successive steps from next to next is vague, though it seems " the as if it conveyed a definite meaning ; on the other hand, " is posterity of o precise and explicit just where the other idea is
hazy.
It
may
when we spoke
be taken as giving what we meant to mean terms that can be reached from o by
of the
successive steps.
We now
lay
down
the following definition
The " natural numbers " are
the -posterity of
:
o with
respect to the
Finitude
and Mathematical
" immediate relation predecessor " successor " ).
We
have thus arrived at a
Induction
" (which
is
two
As a
a
is
of
number and the one
result of this
namely, the one
of his primitive propositions
asserting that o
converse
definition of one of Peano's three
primitive ideas in terms of the other two. definition,
the
23
asserting mathematical
become unnecessary, since they result from the defini The one asserting that the successor of a natural number " is a natural number is every only needed in the weakened form natural number has a successor." We can, of course, easily define " o " and " successor " by means of the definition of number in general which we arrived at in Chapter II. The number o is the number of terms in a class induction tion.
which has no members,
By the general
class."
in the null-class i.e.
in the class
definition of
the set of
all
which
is
called the
number, the number
" null-
of
terms
classes similar to the null-class,
proved) the set consisting of the null-class all the class whose only member is the null-class. (This
(as is easily i.e.
alone, is
is
i.e.
not identical with the null-class
it
:
has one member, namely ?
the null-class, whereas the null-class itself has no members. class
which has one member
we
member,
as
classes.)
Thus we
o It
when we come
to the theory of have the following purely logical definition :
shall explain
whose only member is remains to define " successor." class
not a
A
never identical with that one
is the class
a be a is
is
the null-class.
Given any number n, let let x be a term which
which has n members, and
member
added on
will
definition
:
of a.
have
n-\-i
Then the members.
a with x Thus we have the following
class consisting of
The successor of the number of terms in of terms in the class consisting of term not belonging to the class.
a
Certain niceties are required to
but they need not concern us. 1 1
the class
a
is the
number
together with x, where x is any
make
It will
this definition perfect,
be remembered that
See Principia Mathematical, vol.
ii.
*
no,
we
Introduction
24
have already given
number
(in
to
Mathematical Philosophy
Chapter
of terms in a class,
II.)
a logical definition of the defined it as the set of all
namely, we
classes that are similar to the given class.
We
have thus reduced Peano's three primitive ideas to ideas we have given definitions of them which make them
of logic
definite,
:
no longer capable of an infinity of different meanings, when they were only determinate to the extent of
as they were
obeying Peano's five axioms. We have removed them from the fundamental apparatus of terms that must be merely appre hended, and have thus increased the deductive articulation of
mathematics.
As regards the five primitive propositions, we have already succeeded in making two of them demonstrable by our definition " natural number." How stands it with the of remaining three ? very easy to prove that o
not the successor of any number, and that the successor of any number is a number. But there is a difficulty about the remaining primitive proposition, namely, " no two numbers have the same successor." The It is
is
difficulty
number of individuals in the for given two numbers m and n, neither of universe is finite which is the total number of individuals in the universe, it is easy to prove that we cannot have m-\-i=n-{-i unless we have mn. But let us suppose that the total number of individuals does not arise unless the total ;
in the universe were (say) 10
;
then there would be no class of
and the number
1 1 would be the null-class. So Thus we should have 11 = 12 therefore the successor of 10 would be the same as the successor of n, although 10 would not be the same as n. Thus we should have two different numbers with the same successor. This failure of the third axiom cannot arise, however, if the number of indi
II individuals,
would the number
12.
viduals in the world
is
;
not
finite.
We
shall return to this topic
at a later stage. 1
Assuming that the number of individuals in the universe is not finite, we have now succeeded not only in defining Peano's *
See Chapter
XIH,
and Mathematical
Finitude
three primitive ideas, but in seeing propositions, ing to logic. as
by means
how
Induction
25
to prove his five primitive
and propositions belong
of primitive ideas
It follows that all
pure mathematics, in so far deducible from the theory of the natural numbers, is only
it is
The extension
a prolongation of logic.
modern branches
of
of this result to those
mathematics which are not deducible from
the theory of the natural numbers offers no difficulty of principle, as we have shown elsewhere. 1
The process of mathematical induction, by means of which we defined the natural numbers, is capable of generalisation.
We
defined the natural
numbers
as the
" posterity
" of o with
respect to the relation of a number to its immediate successor. If we call this relation N, any number will have this relation
m
A
w+i.
to
property
"
simply
m has
whenever the property belongs to a m-fi, i.e. to the number to which And a number n will be said to belong to
N-hereditary,"
number m,
it
"hereditary with respect to N," or
is if,
also belongs to
the relation N.
"
"
m
with respect to the relation N if n has every N-hereditary property belonging to m. These definitions can all be applied to any other relation just as well as to N. Thus
the
if
R
posterity
is
any relation whatever, we can lay down the following
definitions
A
2 :
property
a term x,
A
of
is
called
and x has the
class
is
"
"
R-hereditary relation
R
R-hereditary when
when,
to y, then its
it
defining
if it
belongs to
belongs to y.
property
is
R-
hereditary.
A
term x
said to be an
"
R-ancestor
"
of the term y if y has every R-hereditary property that x has, provided x is a term which has the relation R to something or to which something has the relation R. (This is only to exclude trivial cases.) is
1 For geometry, in so far as it is not purely analytical, see Principles of Mathematics, part vi. ; for rational dynamics, ibid., part vii. 2 These definitions, and the generalised theory of induction, are due to Frege, and were published so long ago as 1879 in his Begriffsschrift. In spite of the great value of this work, I was, I believe, the first person who ever read it more than years after its
twenty
publication.
26
Introduction
The " R-posterity "
Mathematical Philosophy
to
of
x
is all
the terms of which x
an R-
is
ancestor.
We
have framed the above
definitions so that
a term
if
is
the
ancestor of anything it is its own ancestor and belongs to its own This is merely for convenience. posterity. the relation " parent," It will be observed that if we take for " " ancestor " and " will have the usual meanings, posterity
R
except that a person will be included among his own ancestors and posterity. It is, of course, obvious at once that " ancestor " must be capable of definition in terms of " parent," but until Frege developed his generalised theory of induction, no one could have defined " ancestor " precisely in terms of " parent." A brief consideration of this point will serve to show the importance of the theory.
problem
A
person confronted for the first time with the " would " ancestor " in terms of " parent
of defining
A
naturally say that there are a certain
B
is
is
an ancestor of
number
a child of A, each
is
Z
if,
between
of people, B, C,
.
.
.,
a parent of the next, until the
A of
and
Z,
whom
last,
who
a parent of Z. But this definition is not adequate unless we add that the number of intermediate terms is to be finite. Take,
is
for example, such a series as the following I,
Here we have and then a
we say
first
f,
89
J,
.
:
g>
>
2?
M
a series of negative fractions with no end, with no beginning. Shall
series of positive fractions
that, in this series,
J
is
an ancestor of J
?
It will
be
so according to the beginner's definition suggested above, but it will not be so according to any definition which will give the
kind of idea that we wish to define.
For
this purpose, it is
essential that the number of intermediaries should be finite. " finite " is to be defined But, as we saw, by means of mathe
matical induction, and
it is
simpler to define the ancestral relation
case of the generally at once than to define it first only for the cases. it to other then extend n to and relation of Here, n-f-i, as constantly elsewhere, generality
from the
first,
though
it
may
Finitude
and Mathematical
Induction
27
require more thought at the start, will be found in the long run to economise thought and increase logical power.
The use
mathematical induction in demonstrations was, something of a mystery. There seemed no reason
of
in the past,
able doubt that
knew why
it
was a valid method
it
was
Some
valid.
of induction, in the sense in *
Poincare
considered
by means
ance,
of
it
of proof, but
believed
it
to be really a case
which that word
is
to be a principle of the
which an
logic.
number of syllogisms could be We now know that all such views is
a definition,
There are some numbers to which
applied, and there are others to which it cannot be applied. as those to
used in
utmost import
infinite
condensed into one argument. are mistaken, and that mathematical induction not a principle.
no one quite
(as
we
shall see in
it
can be
Chapter VIII.)
We define the " natural numbers "
which proofs by mathematical induction can be as those that possess all inductive properties.
It applied, follows that such proofs can be applied to the natural numbers, not in virtue of any mysterious intuition or axiom or principle, " but as a purely verbal proposition. If " quadrupeds are i.e.
defined as animals having four legs, that have four legs are quadrupeds
it will ;
follow that animals
and the case
numbers
of
that obey mathematical induction is exactly similar. " " shall use the phrase inductive numbers to
We
mean
the
same set as we have hitherto spoken of as the " natural numbers." The phrase " inductive numbers " is preferable as affording a reminder that the definition of this set of numbers
is
obtained
from mathematical induction. Mathematical induction the essential characteristic
from the
The
infinite.
affords, more than anything else, by which the finite is distinguished
principle
of
mathematical induction
" what can be might be stated popularly in some such form as inferred from next to next can be inferred from first to last." This
is
first
and
true
when the number
last is
finite, 1
of intermediate steps
not otherwise.
between
Anyone who has ever
Science and Method, chap.
iv.
28
Introduction
to
Mathematical Philosophy
watched a goods train beginning to move
will
have noticed how
the impulse is communicated with a jerk from each truck to the next, until at last even the hindmost truck is in motion.
When
the train
truck moves.
an
a very long time before the last If the train were infinitely long, there would be is
very long,
it is
infinite succession of jerks,
when the whole
train
and the time would never come
would be
in motion.
Nevertheless,
if
there were a series of trucks no longer than the series of inductive
numbers (which,
as
we
shall see, is
an instance of the smallest
would begin to move sooner or later if the engine persevered, though there would always be other trucks further back which had not yet begun to move. This image will help to elucidate the argument from next to next, and its connection with finitude. When we come to infinite of infinites), every truck
numbers, where arguments from mathematical induction will be no longer valid, the properties of such numbers will help to
make of
clear,
by
contrast, the almost unconscious use that
mathematical induction where
finite
is
made
numbers are concerned.
CHAPTER IV THE DEFINITION OF ORDER
WE have now carried our analysis of the series of natural numbers we have obtained
to the point where
members
of this series, of the
of the relation of a
number
must now consider the in the order o,
I,
whole to its
logical definitions of the
members, and immediate successor. We class of its
numbers
serial character of the natural .
2, 3,
.
.
We
ordinarily think of the
num
an essential part of the work " order " " series " of analysing our data to seek a definition of or bers as in this order,
and
it is
in logical terms.
The notion
one which has enormous importance
of order is
Not only the integers, but also rational frac tions and all real numbers have an order of magnitude, and this is essential to most of their mathematical properties. The
in mathematics.
order of points on a line slightly
is
essential to
more complicated order
of lines
geometry
;
so
is
the
through a point in a
Dimensions, in geometry, plane, or of planes through a line. are a development of order. The conception of a limit, which a serial conception. There are parts of mathematics which do not depend upon the notion of order, but they are very few in comparison with the parts
underlies
in
which
all
higher mathematics,
this
notion
is
is
involved.
In seeking a definition of order, the first thing to realise is that no set of terms has just one order to the exclusion of others.
A
set of
terms has
times one order
is
all
so
the orders of which
much more
it is
familiar
capable.
Some
and natural to our
Introduction
30
to
Mathematical Philosophy
thoughts that we are inclined to regard it as the order of that set of terms ; but this is a mistake. The natural numbers " inductive " or the numbers, as we shall also call them occur to us of
an
most readily infinite
in order of
number
magnitude
;
but they are capable
We might, for the odd numbers and then all the
of other arrangements.
example, consider first even numbers ; or first
all I,
then
all
the even numbers, then
all
the odd multiples of 3, then all the multiples of 5 but not of 2 or 3, then all the multiples of 7 but not of 2 or 3 or 5, and so
on through the whole series of primes. When we say that we " " the numbers in these various orders, that is an arrange inaccurate expression what we really do is to turn our attention to certain relations between the natural numbers, which them selves generate such-and-such an arrangement. We can no more " arrange " the natural numbers than we can the starry heavens ; but just as we may notice among the fixed stars :
either their order of brightness or their distribution in the sky, so there are various relations among numbers which may be
observed, and which give rise to various different orders among numbers, all equally legitimate. And what is true of numbers equally true of points on a line or of the moments of time one order is more familiar, but others are equally valid. We
is
:
might, for example, take first, on a line, all the points that have integral co-ordinates, then all those that have non-integral rational co-ordinates, then
rational co-ordinates, tions
we
please.
all
those that have algebraic non-
and so on, through any
The
resulting
set of
complica
order will be one which the
points of the line certainly have, whether we choose to notice or not ; the only thing that is arbitrary about the various
it
orders of a set of terms
have always
all
is
our attention, for the terms themselves
the orders of which they are capable. result of this consideration is that
One important
we must
not look for the definition of order in the nature of the set of
terms to be ordered, since one set of terms has many orders. The order lies, not in the class of terms, but in a relation among
The Definition of Order
3
.
1
members of the class, in respect of which some appear as The fact that a class may have many earlier and some as later. the
orders
among
due to the fact that there can be
is
the
members
one single
of
class.
many relations holding What properties must
a relation have in order to give rise to an order ? The essential characteristics of a relation which
is
to give rise
may be discovered by considering that in respect of such a relation we must be able to say, of any two terms in " " and the the class which is to be ordered, that one precedes " be able to use other order that we to order
follows."
Now,
in
may
which we should naturally understand them, we require that the ordering relation should have three these words in the
properties
way
in
:
This is an y, y must not also precede x. obvious characteristic of the kind of relations that lead to series. (1) If
x
If
x precedes
is less
time than
than y,
y
y is not also less than not also earlier than x.
y,
is
If
x.
If
x
x
is
is earlier
in
to the left of
y is not to the left of x. On the other hand, relations which do not give rise to series often do not have this property. If
y,
x
a brother or sister of y, y is a brother or sister of x. same height as y, y is of the same height as x. If
is
of the
different height
these cases,
all
from
y,
when the
holds between y and x.
cannot happen.
A
y
is
But with
relation
from
of a different height
relation holds
having
x
between x and
If
x
is
of a
is
x.
In
y, it
also
such a thing
serial relations
this first property is called
asymmetrical. (2)
may left
If x precedes y and y precedes z, x must precede z. This be illustrated by the same instances as before less, earlier, :
of.
But
as instances of relations
property only two
x
which do not have
this
of our previous three instances will serve.
brother or sister of y, and y of z, x may not be brother The same z, since x and z may be the same person. applies to difference of height, but not to sameness of height, which has our second property but not our first. The relation If
is
or sister of
"
father," on the
other hand, has our
first
property but not
Introduction
32
our second.
A
Mathematical Philosophy
to
relation having our second property
is
called
transitive.
Given any two terms of the class which is to be ordered, must be one which precedes and the other which follows. For example, of any two integers, or fractions, or real numbers, one is smaller and the other greater but of any two complex (3)
there
;
numbers must be
this is earlier
Of any two moments in time, one than the other ; but of events, which may be not true.
simultaneous, this cannot be said. Of two points on a line, one must be to the left of the other. A relation having this third property
called connected.
is
When
a relation possesses these three properties, it is of the sort to give rise to an order among the terms between which it holds
;
and wherever an order
exists,
some
three properties can be found generating
Before
illustrating
this
thesis,
we
relation having these
it.
introduce
will
a
few
definitions. (1)
A
relation
said to be an aliorelative, 1 or to be contained
is
in or imply diversity,
if
no term has
"
for example,
"
this
relation
different in size,"
to
itself.
"
brother," Thus, greater," " father " are aliorelatives " but " equal," " born ; husband," " dear friend " are not. of the same parents," (2)
The square
of a relation
when
is
that relation which holds between
an intermediate term y such that the given relation holds between x and y and between " " " y and z. Thus paternal grandfather is the square of father," " " " is the square of greater by I," and so on. greater by 2 of all those terms that consists a relation The of domain (3)
two terms x and
z
there
is
have the relation to something or other, and the converse domain consists of all those terms to which something or other has the relation.
These words have been already defined,
recalled here for the sake of the following definition
The field of a domain together. (4)
1
relation consists of its
This term
is
due to
but
are
:
domain and converse
C. S. Peirce.
The Definition of Order
One
(5) it
relation
is
33
said to contain or be implied by another
if
holds whenever the other holds.
be seen that an asymmetrical relation
It will
is
the same thing
whose square is an aliorelative. It often happens that a relation is an aliorelative without being asymmetrical, though an asymmetrical relation is always an aliorelative. For as a relation
" but is symmetrical, is an aliorelative, spouse the spouse of y, y is the spouse of x. But among
" example, since
x
if
transitive
is
relations,
aliorelatives
all
are asymmetrical
as
well
as vice versa.
From is
the definitions
one which "
tains
its
is
it will
implied by
square.
its
be seen that a
Thus " ancestor "
an ancestor's ancestor
is
an ancestor
;
transitive relation
we
square, or, as
one which contains
in diversity
or,
;
A transitive
is
transitive,
A
asymmetry
is
is
when
a relation
equivalent to being an aliorelative.
is
or between the second
that both
is
because,
connected when, given any the relation holds between the
relation
of its field,
square and is contained the same thing, one whose
its
what comes to it and diversity
square implies both
con
transitive, because " but " father is not
is
transitive, because a father's father is not a father.
aliorelative is
"
also say,
and the
may happen, though
first
two
different terms
first
and the second
(not excluding the possibility
both cannot happen
if
the relation
asymmetrical). " It will be seen that the relation ancestor," for example, an aliorelative and transitive, but not connected ; it is because
it is
not connected that
it
does not suffice to arrange the
human
race in a series.
The
"
less than or equal to," among numbers, is and connected, but not asymmetrical or an aliorelative. The relation " greater or less " among numbers is an alio relative and is connected, but is not transitive, for if x is greater
relation
transitive
or less than y, and y is greater or less than that x and z are the same number.
Thus the three properties
of
being
(i)
z, it
an
may happen
aliorelative,
3
(2)
34
Introduction
transitive,
and
a relation
may
Mathematical Philosophy
to
connected, are mutually independent, since have any two without having the third. (3)
We now lay down the following definition A relation is serial when it is an aliorelative, :
connected
or,
;
transitive,
is
when
equivalent,
it
the
same thing
and
asymmetrical,
as a serial relation.
might have been thought that a
should be the field
series
But
of a serial relation, not the serial relation itself.
be an
transitive,
is
and connected.
A series is It
what
error.
would
this
For example,
I, 2, 3
;
2
i, 3,
;
2, 3, I
are six different series which
;
2, i, 3
all
;
3, I,
2
;
have the same
3, 2, I
If
field.
the
were the series, there could only be one series with a given field. What distinguishes the above six series is simply the field
Given the ordering the field and order Thus the are both determinate. relation,
different ordering relations in the six cases.
the ordering relation cannot be so taken.
Given any
shall write
We
say P,
x " precedes " y
which P must have (1)
be taken to be the
serial relation,
of this relation,
which we
may
"
xPy
"
we if
shall
but the
The
in order to be serial are
i.e.
field
say that, in respect
x has the relation
for short.
must never have xPx,
series,
P
to y,
three characteristics
:
no term must precede
itself.
(2)
P 2 must imply precede
(3)
If
P,
i.e. if
x precedes y and y precedes
z,
x must
z.
x and y are two different terms in the field of P, we shall have xPy or yPx, i.e. one of the two must precede the other.
The reader can
easily convince himself that,
where these three
properties are found in an ordering relation, the characteristics are we expect of series will also be found, and vice versa.
We
therefore justified in taking the above as a definition of order
The Definition of Order
And
or series.
35
be observed that the definition
it will
is
effected
in purely logical terms.
Although a transitive asymmetrical connected relation always exists wherever there is a series, it is not always the relation which would most naturally be regarded as generating the series.
The natural-number relation we assumed
series
may
The
serve as an illustration.
numbers was
in considering the natural
the relation of immediate succession,
i.e.
the relation between
consecutive integers. This relation is asymmetrical, but not We can, however, derive from it, transitive or connected. " " mathematical ancestral the method of induction, the by relation
which we considered
relation will
This than or equal to " among
in the preceding chapter.
be the same as "
less
For purposes of generating the series of inductive integers. " less than," excluding natural numbers, we want the relation " This is the relation oimton when is an ancestor to." equal
m
of
n but not
comes to the same thing) an ancestor of n in the sense in which
identical with n, or (what
when the successor of m is a number is its own ancestor. the following definition : An inductive number
m is
That
is
to say,
we
shall lay
said to be less than another
down
number
n when n possesses every hereditary property possessed by the successor of m. It is easy to see,
"
and not
difficult to
prove, that the relation
asymmetrical, transitive, and con and has the inductive numbers for its field. Thus by nected, means of this relation the inductive numbers acquire an order less
than," so defined,
in the sense in is
is
which we defined the term " order," and
this order
the so-called " natural " order, or order of magnitude.
The generation
by means
of relations more or less The series of the common. very example, is generated by relations of each
of series
resembling that of n to n-j-i
Kings of England, for This
to his successor. applicable,
is
is
probably the easiest way, where In of a series.
of conceiving the generation
method we pass on from each term
it is
this
to the next, as long as there
Introduction
36
to
Mathematical Philosophy
is a next, or back to the one before, as long as there is one before. This method always requires the generalised form of mathe " " matical induction in order to enable us to define and earlier " later " in a series so " On the of generated. proper analogy " fractions," let us give the name proper posterity of x with respect " to R to the class of those terms that belong to the R-posterity of some term to which x has the relation R, in the sense which we gave before to " posterity," which includes a term in its own
Reverting to the fundamental definitions, we find that " proper posterity may be defined as follows " The proper posterity " of x with respect to R consists of
posterity.
the
"
:
terms that possess every R-hereditary property possessed by every term to which x has the relation R.
all
It is to
be observed that this definition has to be so framed
be applicable not only when there is only one term to which x has the relation R, but also in cases (as e.g. that of father and as to
child)
where there
We
R.
A
may be many
define further
term x
"
terms to which x has the relation
:
"
of y with respect to to the of x with belongs proper posterity respect to R. is
a
proper ancestor
"
We shall speak for short of " when
R-posterity these terms seem more convenient.
Reverting
now
to the generation of series
and connected.
if
y
and " R-ancestors "
by the
relation
between consecutive terms, we see that, if this method " " must be an possible, the relation proper R-ancestor tive, transitive,
R
is
R
to be
aliorela-
Under what circumstances
will
no matter what sort always be transitive " " and " proper R-ancestor " R-ancestor of relation R may be, But it is only under certain circum are always both transitive. stances that it will be an aliorelative or connected. Consider, this occur
?
It will
:
for example, the relation to one's left-hand neighbour at a
round
dinner-table at which there are twelve people. If we call this relation R, the proper R-posterity of a person consists of all who
can be reached by going round the table from right to
left.
This
includes everybody at the table, including the person himself, since
The Definition of Order
37
twelve steps bring us back to our starting-point. Thus in such " " is connected, a case, though the relation proper R-ancestor and though R itself is an aliorelative, we do not get a series " " is not an aliorelative. It is for because proper R-ancestor this reason that we cannot say that one person comes before " another with respect to the relation " right of or to its ancestral derivative.
The above was an instance
in
which the ancestral relation was
connected but not contained in diversity. An instance where it is contained in diversity but not connected is derived from the sense of the word " ancestor." If x is a proper ancestor ordinary of y, x and y cannot be the same person ; but it is not true that
any two persons one must be an ancestor of the other. The question of the circumstances under which series can be generated by ancestral relations derived from relations of consecutiveness is often important. Some of the most important cases are the following Let R be a many-one relation, and let us confine our attention to the posterity of some term x. When " " so confined, the relation proper R-ancestor must be connected of
:
;
therefore
all
that remains to ensure
be contained in diversity.
This
is
its
being serial
is
that
it
shall
a generalisation of the instance
Another generalisation consists in taking to be a one-one relation, and including the ancestry of x as
of the dinner-table.
R
well as the posterity. Here again, the one condition required " to secure the generation of a series is that the relation proper
R-ancestor
"
shall
The generation
be contained in diversity. of order
by means
own
ness, though important in its
method which uses a
of relations of consecutive-
sphere,
is less
general than the
transitive relation to define the order.
often happens in a series that there are an infinite
number of
It
inter
mediate terms between any two that near together these of
magnitude.
may be.
may be selected, however for Take, instance, fractions in order
Between any two
example, the arithmetic
no such thing as a pair
mean
fractions there are others
of the two.
for
Consequently there
of consecutive fractions.
If
is
we depended
Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy
38
upon consecutiveness
for defining order,
we should not be
able
magnitude among fractions. But in fact greater and less among fractions do not demand
to define the order of
the relations of
generation from relations of consecutiveness, and the relations of greater and less among fractions have the three characteristics
which we need
In
for defining serial relations.
the order must be defined
by means
all
such cases
of a transitive relation, since
only such a relation is able to leap over an infinite number of intermediate terms. The method of consecutiveness, like that of counting for discovering the
priate to the finite
;
it
may
number
of a collection, is
even be extended to certain
appro infinite
namely, those in which, though the total number of terms is infinite, the number of terms between any two is always finite ; series,
it must not be regarded as general. Not only so, but care must be taken to eradicate from the imagination all habits of
but
thought resulting from supposing it general. series in which there are no consecutive terms
and puzzling.
And
such
series are of vital
understanding of continuity, space, time,
There are
many ways
in
which
series
If this is
will
not done,
remain
difficult
importance for the
and motion.
may
be generated, but
depend upon the finding or construction of an asymmetrical Some of these ways have con
all
transitive connected relation.
siderable importance. tion of series
"
call
may
by means
We may
take as illustrative the genera
of a three-term relation
This method
which we
may
very useful in geometry, and serve as an introduction to relations having more than two
terms
between."
;
it
is
is
best introduced in connection with elementary
geometry.
Given any three points on a straight line in ordinary space, must be one of them which is between the other two. This
there will
not be the case with the points on a
circle or
any other closed
curve, because, given any three points on a circle, we can travel from any one to any other without passing through the third. " is characteristic of In fact, the notion " between open series or series in the strict sense
as opposed to
what may be
called
The Definition of Order
39
"
"
where, as with people at the dinner-table, a This sufficient journey brings us back to our starting-point. " between " as the fundamental notion chosen be notion of may of ordinary geometry ; but for the present we will only consider its application to a single straight line and to the ordering of the series,
cyclic
1 Taking any two points #, b, the line points on a straight line. : of three consists (ab) parts (besides a and b themselves)
(1)
Points between a and
(2)
Points x such that a
is
between x and
b.
(3)
Points y such that b
is
between y and
a.
Thus the
line
b.
can be defined in terms of the relation
(ab)
" between." " between " In order that this relation of the line in
an order from
left to right,
namely, the following If anything is between a and
tions,
may
arrange the points
we need
certain
assump
:
(1)
a and b are not identical.
b,
Anything between a and b is also between b and a. Anything between a and b is not identical with a
(2)
(3)
consequently, with If
(4)
x
If
x
is
(nor,
in virtue of (2)).
between a and
is
between a and (5)
b,
b,
anything between a and x
b,
and
is
also
b.
between a and
b is
between x and
y,
then b
between a and y. (6) If x and y are between a and b, then either x and y are identical, or x is between a and y, or x is between y and b.
is
If b is
(7) a:
b
and y are and #.
between a and x and identical, or x
is
also
between a and
between
and
y,
y, or y
then either is
between
These seven properties are obviously verified in the case of points on a straight line in ordinary space. Any three-term relation
which
verifies
them
gives rise to series, as
following definitions. 1
394
Cf (
.
For the sake
Rivista di Matematica, iv. pp. 55
375).
may
be seen from the
of definiteness, let us ft.
;
assume
Principles of Mathematics, p.
Introduction
4-O
that a
to the left of
is
Then the
b.
those between which and of a
;
(2)
a
itself
;
(3)
Mathematical Philosophy
to
lies
(ab),
we
When x and x and a
(2)
When
(3)
When
x x
y are both to the
to the left of a,
is a,
;
(5)
and y
left of a,
is
between
and y
is
and y
is
a or b or between a and
;
between a and b or
is
b or
is
to the
;
When x and # and b
(7)
(4) b itself
;
will call to the right
;
is
right of b
(6)
we
:
b or to the right of b
(5)
these
define generally that of two points x, y, on " to the left of " shall say that x is y in any
of the following cases
(4)
b
We may now
the line
(1)
lies
those between a and b
those between which and a of b.
a
b,
points of the line (ab) are (i) these we will call to the left
y are both between a and
,
and y
is
between
;
When x is between and b, and y is 3 or to the right of b When x is and y is to the right of b When x and y are both to the right of b and x is between 5
6>
we now have
the integers
9 I0 >
7> 8 >
These are the same as those we had before, except that I has been cut off at the beginning and II has been joined on at the ten integers they are correlated with the previous ten by the relation of n to n-{-i, which is a one-one relation. Or, again, instead of adding I to each of our original
There are
end.
ten integers,
still
:
we could have doubled each
of
them, thus obtaining
the integers 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 14, 16, 18, 20.
Here we
still
have
2, 4, 6, 8, 10.
The
five of
our previous set of integers, namely,
correlating relation in this case
is
the relation
number to its double, which is again a one-one relation. Or we might have replaced each number by its square, thus of a
obtaining the set i,
On I,
4, 9, 16, 25, 36, 49, 64, 81, 100.
only three of our original set are left, namely, Such 4, 9. processes of correlation may be varied endlessly. The most interesting case of the above kind is the case where this occasion
our one-one relation has a converse domain which
is
part, but
4
Introduction
50
Mathematical Philosophy
to
not the whole, of the domain. If, instead of confining the domain to the first ten integers, we had considered the whole of the inductive numbers, the above instances would have illustrated this case. We may place the numbers concerned in two rows, the correlate directly under the number whose correlate putting it is.
Thus when the
have the two rows
correlator
2,
3>4>
the correlator
we have
is
the two rows
6
5>
"+
>
the correlator
all
-
-
the relation of a
number
to its double,
5,
is
... n ... 2w ... .
the relation of a
.
.
number
to its square,
:
4,
5,
...
i, 4, 9, 1 6,
25,
..... n2 ...
i, 2, 3,
In
1
:
1, 2, 3, 4,
the rows are
we
... n ...
2, 4, 6, 8, 10,
When
the relation of n to n-{-i y
:
1, 2, 3, 4, 5,
When
is
these cases,
and only some
all
in the
inductive numbers occur in the top row,
bottom row.
" Cases of this sort, where the converse domain is a proper " of the domain (i.e. a part not the whole), will occupy us part again when we come to deal with infinity. For the present, we wish only to note that they exist and demand consideration.
Another
class
the class called
domain are
"
which are often important is permutations," where the domain and converse of
correlations
identical.
arrangements
Consider, for example, the six possible
of three letters
:
a,
b,
c
a,
c,
b
b,
c,
a
b,
a,
c
c,
a,
b
c,
b,
a
Kinds of Relations
51
Each of these can be obtained from any one of the others by means of a correlation. Take, for example, the first and last, Here a is correlated with c, b with itself, (a, b, c) and (c, b, a). and c with a. It is obvious that the combination of two permu tations class
is
again a permutation,
form what
is
called a
i.e.
the permutations of a given
" group."
These various kinds of correlations have importance in various connections, some for one purpose, some for another. The general notion of one-one correlations has boundless importance we have partly seen already,
in the philosophy of mathematics, as
but shall see will
much more
fully as
occupy us in our next chapter.
we
proceed.
One
of its uses
CHAPTER
VI
SIMILARITY OF RELATIONS
WE
saw
in Chapter II. that
when they
of terms
whose domain
relation
domain
are
similar," is
have the same number
classes
the one
when
i.e.
class
" one-one " between the two correlation
there
a one-one
is
and whose converse
we say
In such a case
the other.
is
two
"
that there
is
a
classes.
In the present chapter we have to define a relation between relations,
which
will
play the same part for them that similarity " We will call this
of classes plays for classes.
of relations," or different
relation
" likeness " when
it
word from that which we use
likeness to be defined
similarity
seems desirable to use a for classes.
How
is
?
We shall employ still the notion of correlation we shall assume that the domain of the one relation can be correlated :
with the domain of the other, and the converse domain with the converse domain ; but that is not enough for the sort of resem blance which we desire to have between our two relations.
What we
desire is that, whenever either relation holds between two terms, the other relation shall hold between the correlates The easiest example of the sort of thing of these two terms. is a map. When one place is north of another, the the to the one is above the place on map corresponding place on the map corresponding to the other when one place is west
we
desire
;
on the map corresponding to the one is the place on the map corresponding to the other ;
of another, the place
to the left of
and so on.
The
structure of the 52
map
corresponds with that of
Similarity of Relations
the country of which it " "
map have
We
space-relations in the
the space-relations in the country this kind of connection between relations that
likeness
It is
mapped.
we wish
The
a map.
is
53
to
to define.
may,
profitably introduce a certain will confine ourselves, in defining likeness, to
in the first place,
We
restriction.
such relations as have
"
fields," i.e. to such as permit of the formation of a single class out of the domain and the converse domain. This is not always the case. Take, for example, " the relation domain," i.e. the relation which the domain of a
This relation has
relation has to the relation.
domain, since every class it
has
all
is
the domain of
all
some
classes for its
relation
;
and
relations for its converse domain, since every relation
has a domain.
But
classes
gether to form a
new
"
We
types." doctrine of types, but
logical
and
relations cannot be
added to
single class, because they are of different
do not need to enter upon the it is
know when we
well to
difficult
are abstaining
it. We may say, without entering upon " " the the grounds for field assertion, that a relation only has a
from entering upon
what we call " homogeneous," i.e. when its domain and converse domain are of the same logical type and as a " what we mean a indication of rough-and-ready by type,"
when
it is
;
we may say between
that individuals, classes of individuals, relations
notion of likeness are not
is
between
relations
individuals,
classes,
relations
of
Now
and so on, are
classes to individuals,
different types. the not very useful as applied to relations that
homogeneous
we
;
shall, therefore, in defining likeness,
" " field of one of the simplify our problem by speaking of the relations concerned. This somewhat limits the generality of our definition, but the limitation tance.
And having been
We may having
define
two
" likeness,"
stated,
it
relations
when
there
is
not of any practical impor
need no longer be remembered.
P and Q is
as
"
similar," or as
a one-one relation S
domain is the field of P and whose converse domain of Q. and which is such that, if one term has the
is
whose
the field
relation
P
Introduction
54
Mathematical Philosophy
to
Q
to another, the correlate of the one has the relation
and
correlate of the other,
figure will
y >
.
w, such that x has the rela
tion S to
S to
Q
>
and
and
y,
as z
and w,
P
Q
w
Q if
to
zv,
z,
and
y has the relation z has the relation
If this
20.
happens with
.
every pair of
terms such as x
the converse happens with every pair of terms such clear that for every instance in which the relation
it is
holds there
and
holds,
this
terms having the relation P. Then there are to be two terms
.
z,
z
to the
make
Let x and v be two
clearer.
P
x,
A
vice versa.
a corresponding instance in which the relation and this is what we desire to secure by ;
is
vice versa
We
our definition.
can eliminate some redundancies in the
above sketch of a definition, by observing that, when the above conditions are realised, the relation P is the same as the relative product of S and Q and the converse of S, i.e. the P-step from x to y may be replaced by the succession of the S-step from
x to
w
z,
the Q-step from z to w, and the backward S-step from
to y. Thus we may set up the following definitions " correlator " or an " ordinal relation S is said to be a :
A
correlator
"
Q
field of
two
of
relations
for its converse
relative product of S
Two
relations
" likeness,"
there
These definitions
if
domain, and
S is
is
one-one, has the
such that
Q and the converse of S. Q are said to be " similar,"
P
is
the
and
P and
when
P and Q
will
is
at least one correlator of
or to have
P and
Q.
be found to yield what we above decided
to be necessary. It will
share
all
be found that, when two relations are similar, they properties which do not depend upon the actual terms
For instance,
in their fields.
the other nected, so
Again,
if
;
if
one
is
the other.
is
one
is
if
one implies diversity, so does is the other ; if one is con
transitive, so
Hence
one-many
one
so
is
the other.
or one-one, the other
is
one-many
if
is serial,
Similarity of Relations or one-one
;
and so on, through
all
55
the general properties of actual terms of the
Even statements involving the
relations.
field of a relation,
though they
may
not be true as they stand
when
applied to a similar relation, will always be capable of translation into statements that are analogous. are led
We
by such considerations to a problem which has, in mathematical philosophy, an importance by no means adequately recognised Our problem may be stated as follows
hitherto.
:
Given some statement in a language of which we know the grammar and the syntax, but not the vocabulary, what are the possible meanings of such a statement,
and what are the mean
unknown words that would make it true ? The reason that this question is important is that it represents, much more nearly than might be supposed, the state of our
ings of the
knowledge of nature.
We know
that
certain
scientific
pro which, in the most advanced sciences, are expressed in mathematical symbols are more or less true of the world, positions
we
are very much at sea as to the interpretation to be put the terms which occur in these propositions. We know upon much more (to use, for a moment, an old-fashioned pair of
but
about the form of
terms)
Accordingly, what we of nature
is
really
only that there
our terms which will
nature
make
than
about
know when we
the
matter.
enunciate a law
is probably some interpretation of the law approximately true. Thus to the question What are the
importance attaches meanings of a law expressed in terms of which we do not know the substantive meaning, but only the grammar and ? And this is the one syntax suggested above. question For the present we will ignore the general question, which
great
:
possible
will
occupy us again at a later stage; must first be further investigated.
the subject of likeness
itself
when two relations are similar, their same except when they depend upon the being composed of just the terms of which they are com
Owing
to the fact that,
properties are the fields
posed,
it
is
desirable to have a nomenclature which collects
Introduction
56
all
together
we
Just as
to
Mathematical Philosophy
the relations that are similar to a given relation. called the set of those classes that are similar to a
" number " of that class, so we may call the set given class the of all those relations that are similar to a given relation the " number " of that relation. But in order to avoid confusion with the numbers appropriate to classes, we will speak, in this case, of " relation-number." Thus we have the a following definitions " " The relation-number of a given relation is the class of all those relations that are similar to the given relation. " Relation-numbers " are the set of all those classes of relations :
that are relation-numbers of various relations
same
the
thing, a relation
number
of all those relations that are similar to
When
it
is
or,
what comes to
one member of the
class.
necessary to speak of the numbers of classes in makes it impossible to confuse them with relation-
way which numbers, we shall a
;
a class of relations consisting
is
them " cardinal numbers." Thus cardinal numbers are the numbers appropriate to classes. These include the ordinary integers of daily life, and also certain infinite call
numbers, of which we shall speak later. When we speak of " numbers " without qualification, we are to be understood as
meaning cardinal numbers. The definition be remembered, is as follows
it will
of a cardinal
number,
:
The "
cardinal
number "
of
a
given class
is
the set of
all
those classes that are similar to the given class.
The most obvious
application of relation-numbers
is
to series.
may be regarded as equally long when they have the same relation-number. Two finite series will have the same relation-number when their fields have the same cardinal
Two
series
number
of terms,
and only then
i.e.
a series of (say) 15 terms
have the same relation-number as any other series of fifteen terms, but will not have the same relation-number as a series
will
6 terms, nor, of course, the same relation-number as a relation which is not serial. Thus, in the quite special case
of
14 or
1
of finite series, there
numbers.
is
parallelism between cardinal
The relation-numbers
and
applicable to series
relation-
may
be
Similarity of Relations called
"
serial
numbers " are a sub-class in the field of a series
n
If
of these)
we know
determinate when
is
57
" ordinal " numbers (what are commonly called ;
number
thus a finite serial
number number in
of terms
the cardinal
having the
serial question. relation-number of a series the a finite cardinal number,
is
which has n terms
called the
is
"
ordinal
" number n.
(There
them we shall speak When the cardinal number of terms in
are also infinite ordinal numbers, but of in a later chapter.)
the field of a series
is infinite,
the relation-number of the series
not determined merely by the cardinal number, indeed an infinite number of relation-numbers exist for one infinite cardinal
is
as
number,
When its
we
a series
when we come to infinite, what we may
shall see is
may
relation-number,
number
We
but when a
;
can
numbers
define
series is finite, this
cannot happen.
and multiplication for relationcardinal numbers, and a whole arithmetic
addition
as well as for
of relation-numbers
be done
consider infinite series. " call its length," i.e. the without cardinal in change vary
The manner
can be developed.
in
which
easily seen by considering the case of series. Suppose, for example, that we wish to define the sum of two non-overlapping series in such a way that the relation-number this is to
is
sum shall be capable of being defined as the sum of the relation-numbers of the two series. In the first place, it is clear of the
that there
is
an order involved as between the two
series
:
one
them must be placed before the other. Thus if P and Q are the generating relations of the two series, in the series which
of
sum with P put before Q, every member of the field of precede every member of the field of Q. Thus the serial relation which is to be defined as the sum of P and Q is not " P or Q " simply, but " P or Q or the relation of any member of the field of P to any member of the field of Q." Assuming that P and Q do not overlap, this relation is serial, but " P or Q "
is
their
P
will
is
not
serial,
being not connected, since
member of the field the sum of P and Q, a
of
P and
as
above defined,
a
it
member is
does not hold between
of the field of Q.
what we need
Thus
in order
Introduction
58
sum
to define the
of
to
Mathematical Philosophy
two relation-numbers.
needed for products and powers. metic does not obey the commutative law
Similar modifica
The
tions are
:
the
resulting arith
sum
or product
two relation-numbers generally depends upon the order in which they are taken. But it obeys the associative law, one of
form of the distributive law, and two
of the formal laws for
powers, not only as applied to serial numbers, but as applied to relation-numbers generally. Relation-arithmetic, in fact, though recent, It
is
a thoroughly respectable branch of mathematics.
must not be supposed, merely because
series
afford the
most obvious application of the idea of likeness, that there are no other applications that are important. We have already mentioned maps, and we might extend our thoughts from this illustration to
geometry generally.
If
the system of relations
by which a geometry
is applied to a certain set of terms can be into relations of likeness with a system applying brought fully to another set of terms, then the geometry of the two sets is
indistinguishable from the mathematical point of view, i.e. all the propositions are the same, except for the fact that they are
applied in one case to one set of terms and in the other to another. illustrate this by the relations of the sort that may be
We may "
between," which we considered in Chapter IV. We there saw that, provided a three-term relation has certain formal
called
logical properties, it will give rise to series,
"
and may be
called
Given any two points, we can use the between-relation to define the straight line determined by those a
between-relation."
two points
;
it
consists of a
and
b together
with
all
points x,
such that the between-relation holds between the three points It has been shown by 0. Veblen a, b, x in some order or other.
we may
regard our whole space as the field of a three-term between-relation, and define our geometry by the properties we that
1 assign to our between-relation. 1
Now
likeness
is
just as easily
This does not apply to elliptic space, but only to spaces in which Modern Mathematics, edited by the straight line is an open series. " The Foundations of J. W. A. Young, pp. 3-51 (monograph by O. Veblen on
Geometry").
Similarity of Relations definable
59
between three-term relations as between two-term
B and B' are two between-relations, so that " means x is between y and z with respect to B," xB(y, z) we shall call S a correlator of B and B if it has the field of B' for its converse domain, and is such that the relation B holds relations.
If
"
"
7
between three terms when B' holds between their S-correlates, and only then. And we shall say that B is like B' when there is
at least one correlator of
B
with B'.
The reader can
easily
B' in this sense, there can be convince himself that, if B no difference between the geometry generated by B and that is like
generated by B'. It follows
from
this that the
mathematician need not concern
himself with the particular being or intrinsic nature of his points,
and planes, even when he
is speculating as an applied say that there is empirical evidence of the approximate truth of such parts of geometry as are not matters of definition. But there is no empirical evidence as to what a " point " is to be. It has to be something that as nearly " as possible satisfies our axioms, but it does not have to be very " " small or without parts." Whether or not it is those things
lines,
mathematician.
is
We may
a matter of indifference, so long as it satisfies the axioms. If can, out of empirical material, construct a logical structure,
we
no matter how complicated, which
will satisfy
our geometrical "
legitimately be called a point." must not say that there is nothing else that could legitimately be called a " point " ; we must only say : " This object we have
axioms, that structure
may
We
constructed
many
geometer ; it may be one of objects, any of which would be sufficient, but that is no is
sufficient for the
concern of ours, since this object is enough to vindicate the empirical truth of geometry, in so far as geometry is not a
matter of definition."
This is only an illustration of the general that what in mathematics, and to a very great matters principle extent in physical science, is not the intrinsic nature of our terms, but the logical nature of their interrelations.
We may
say, of
two similar
relations, that they
have the same
60
Introduction
Mathematical Philosophy
to
" structure."
For mathematical purposes (though not for those of pure philosophy) the only thing of importance about a relation is the cases in which it holds, not its intrinsic nature. Just as a
may be defined by various different but co-extensive concepts " man " and " featherless biped," so two relations which e.g.
class
may hold in the same set of instances. " instance " in which a relation holds is to be conceived as a
are conceptually different
An
couple of terms, with an order, so that one of the terms comes and the other second ; the couple is to be, of course, such that its first term has the relation in question to its second. Take (say) the relation " father " : we can define what we may first
the
call
" extension " of this relation as the
class of all
ordered
From y. couples (Xy y) the mathematical point of view, the only thing of importance " about the relation " father is that it defines this set of ordered which are such that x
Speaking generally, we say
couples.
The " extension " couples
(x, y)
of a relation
is
is
the father of
:
the class of those ordered
which are such that x has the relation
in question
to y.
We
can now go a step further in the process of abstraction, Given any relation,
and consider what we mean by " structure."
we
if it is
can,
For the sake extension and their product
By
these definitions
shall
we
is
two ordered couples
sum
is
to be the couple
to be the couple (xx
of real r
(x+x
,
f
yy', xy'-\-x'y).
our ordered couples For example, take the
shall secure that
have the properties we
desire.
product of the two couples (o, y) and (o, y'). This will, by the above rule, be the couple ( yy', o). Thus the square of the couple (o, i) will be the couple ( I, o). Now those couples in
which the second term
o are those which, according to the usual nomenclature, have their imaginary part zero ; in the notation is
x-\- yi,
they are x+oi, which
as
is
it is natural to write simply x. Just natural (but erroneous) to identify ratios whose de nominator is unity with integers, so it is natural (but erroneous) it
Introduction
j6
to
Mathematical Philosophy
complex numbers whose imaginary part is zero with numbers. Although this is an error in theory, it is a con " " " " venience in practice ; x-}-oi may be replaced simply by x " " " " and o-\-yi by yi," provided we remember that the x " is not really a real number, but a special case of a complex number. And when y is I, " yi" may of course be replaced by " *." Thus to identify
real
the couple
(o,
l) is I.
represented by *, and the couple (1, o) is Now our rules of multiplication make the
represented by square of (o, l) equal to is
what we desired
(1,
the square of
o), i.e.
to secure.
Thus our
i is
i.
This
definitions serve all
necessary purposes.
easy to give a geometrical interpretation of complex numbers in the geometry of the plane. This subject was agree It is
ably expounded by W. K. Clifford in his Common Sense of the Exact Sciences, a book of great merit, but written before the importance of purely logical definitions had been realised.
Complex numbers of a higher order, though much less useful and important than those what we have been defining, have certain uses that are not without importance in geometry, as may be seen, for example, in Dr Whitehead's Universal Algebra.
The
definition of
complex numbers
obvious extension of the definition
complex number
of order
we have
n
is
obtained by an
We
given.
define a
n as a one-many relation whose domain numbers and whose converse domain from I to n. 1 This is what would ordi
of order
consists of certain real consists of the integers
narily be indicated
by the notation
(x l9
x 2 #3 ,
,
.
.
.
x n), where the
denote correlation with the integers used as suffixes, and the correlation is one-many, not necessarily one-one, because xr
suffixes
and xa may be equal when definition,
and
s are not equal.
with a suitable rule of multiplication,
purposes for
We
r
which complex numbers
will serve all
of higher orders are needed.
have now completed our review
of those extensions of
number which do not involve infinity. The application to infinite collections must be our next topic. 1
Cf Principles of Mathematics, .
The above
360, p. 379.
of
number
CHAPTER
VIII
INFINITE CARDINAL
NUMBERS
THE
definition of cardinal numbers which we gave in Chapter II. was applied in Chapter III. to finite numbers, i.e. to the ordinary " inductive natural numbers. To these we gave the name
numbers," because we found that they are to be defined as numbers which obey mathematical induction starting from o.
But we have not yet considered collections which do not have an number of terms, nor have we inquired whether such This is an collections can be said to have a number at all.
inductive
ancient problem, which has been solved in our own day, chiefly by Georg Cantor. In the present chapter we shall attempt to explain the theory of transfinite or infinite cardinal numbers as it
results
from a combination of his discoveries with those of
Frege on the logical theory of numbers. It cannot be said to be certain that there are in fact any infinite collections in the world.
we
the
"
axiom
The assumption that
there are
is
what
Although various ways suggest themselves by which we might hope to prove this axiom, there is reason to fear that they are all fallacious, and that there is no conclusive logical reason for believing it to be true. At the same call
time, there
is
of infinity."
certainly
and we are therefore
no logical reason against infinite
collections,
justified, in logic, in investigating
the hypo
thesis that there are such collections. The practical form of this hypothesis, for our present purposes, is the assumption that, if n is any inductive number, n is not equal to w-j-i. Various
subtleties arise in identifying this 77
form of our assumption with
Introduction
78
Mathematical Philosophy
to
the form that asserts the existence of infinite collections
;
but
we will leave these out of account until, in a later chapter, we come to consider the axiom of infinity on its own account. For the present we shall merely assume that, if n is an inductive number, n
not equal to n-\-i. This is involved in Peano's that no two inductive numbers have the same suc assumption cessor ; for, if n=n-}-i, then n I and n have the same successor,
namely
n.
is
Thus we are assuming nothing that was not involved
in Peano's primitive propositions.
Let us now consider the collection of the inductive numbers This
themselves.
is
a perfectly well-defined class.
In the
first
place, a cardinal number is a set of classes which are all similar to each other and are not similar to anything except each other. We then define as the " inductive numbers " those among
cardinals which belong to the posterity of o with respect to the relation of n to w-f-i, *