History Philosophy by
Julián
Marías
T r a n s l a t e d f r o m the Spanish b y Stanley
Appelbaum and
Clarence C.
...
304 downloads
2809 Views
9MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
History Philosophy by
Julián
Marías
T r a n s l a t e d f r o m the Spanish b y Stanley
Appelbaum and
Clarence C.
Strowbridge
Dover Publications, Inc. New York
Copyright © 1967 by Dover Publications, Inc. A l l rights reserved under Pan American and International Copyright Conventions.
History of Philosophy is a new English translation of the twenty-second Spanish edition of Historia de la Filosofía, © 1966 by J u l i á n Marias, published by Revista de Occidente, S.A., Madrid, i n 1966. T h i s edition is for sale i n the United States of America, its dependencies and the Philippine Islands only.
Library
Standard Book Number: 486-21739-6 of Congress Catalog Card Number: 66-29156
Manufactured in the United States of America Dover Publications, Inc. 31 East 2nd Street, M i n e ó l a , N . Y 11501
To the memory of my teacher MANUEL
GARCIA
MORENTE
who was dean and guiding spirit that Faculty of Philosophy
of
and Letters
where I was introduced to philosophy
Preface to the English
REFLECTIONS
ON ONE
OF M Y
Edition
BOOKS
As I take a fresh l o o k at this book w i t h t h e r a t h e r general t i t l e History of Philosophy, w h i c h , completed twenty-five years ago, is now to be published i n N e w Y o r k i n a n English t r a n s l a t i o n , I feel as i f I were seeing a c h i l d o f m i n e w h o has g r o w n u p a n d is a b o u t to set o u t o n a l o n g j o u r n e y . I t is the first o f m y books, a n d i t has also been the most successful. Since its i n i t i a l p u b l i c a t i o n i n M a d r i d i n J a n u a r y , 1941, i t has gone t h r o u g h t w e n t y - t w o Spanish editions. I t has become the stand a r d text i n the h i s t o r y o f philosophy for numerous classes i n Spanish a n d L a t i n A m e r i c a n universities. I n 1963 i t was translated i n t o Portuguese; n o w i t makes its appearance i n t h e English-speaking w o r l d . Is i t n o t e x t r a o r d i n a r y that a Spanish b o o k o f philosophy should have m e t w i t h such great success ? H o w d i d i t h a p p e n t h a t , despite the enormous prestige t h e n enjoyed b y G e r m a n philosophy i n Spain a n d L a t i n A m e r i c a , this book b y a n u n k n o w n twenty-six-yearo l d Spaniard was able t o supplant almost entirely the G e r m a n works t h a t h a d d o m i n a t e d the i n t e l l e c t u a l marketplace a n d universities o f the Spanish-speaking w o r l d ? A n d h o w was this possible w h e n , f r o m its opening page, the b o o k recalled the i n t e l l e c t u a l t r a d i t i o n o f the years f r o m 1931 to 1936, w h i c h was t h e n a l l b u t completely proscribed a n d condemned to ostracism a n d o b l i v i o n ? Perhaps a n e x p l a n a t i o n can be f o u n d t h r o u g h a n investigation o f the roots o f this History of Philosophy. I h a d been a student i n the F a c u l t y o f Philosophy a n d Letters o f the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d f r o m 1931 to 1936. T h e i n t e l l e c t u a l excellence w h i c h t h a t Faculty's courses vi'i
viii
Preface to the English
Edition
h a d a t t a i n e d was so superior to a l l t h a t h a d come before a n d , m o r e over, lasted such a short t i m e t h a t i t scarcely seems possible today t h a t i t ever existed. T h e D e p a r t m e n t o f Philosophy, especially, h a d acquired a b r i l l i a n c e a n d a precision u n k n o w n i n Spain either before or after. I t was i n s p i r e d a n d a n i m a t e d b y one o f the greatest creative geniuses i n the philosophy o f our age, w h o was at the same t i m e a n outstanding teacher: Ortega. F o r h i m , philosophy was a personal m a t t e r ; i t was his very life. W e M a d r i d students were t h e n present at the s p e l l b i n d i n g a n d almost unreal spectacle o f a philosophy t h a t was being shaped before o u r eyes. Those w e r e t h e last years o f one o f the most b r i l l i a n t a n d f r u i t f u l epochs o f E u r o p e a n t h o u g h t , the years between Husserl a n d Heidegger, f r o m D i l t h e y to Scheler, f r o m Bergson to U n a m u n o . W e were aware t h a t philosophy was discovering new possibilities, t h a t this was a g e r m i n a l p e r i o d . ( I t h i n k i t really was a n d t h a t i f its h o r i z o n seems less p r o m i s i n g today, i t is n o t because those possibilities were n o t real a n d are n o t still w i t h us, b u t because there have been certain failures o f the w i l l , slothfulness a n d e v i l passions w h i c h perhaps afflict m a n i n some eras.) There was a d a w n like atmosphere i n the M a d r i d F a c u l t y o f Philosophy ; w e were confirmed i n this feeling as we saw a n e w philosophy o f great i m p o r t being constructed l i k e a sailing vessel i n a s h i p y a r d . T h e image o f the shipyard is n o t i n a p p r o p r i a t e , because t h a t Faculty was b e g i n n i n g to be a school. Ortega's associates w e r e M a n u e l Garcia M o r e n t e , X a v i e r Z u b i r i a n d José Gaos, a l l p u p i l s o f h i s ; these m e n , together w i t h the older f e l l o w professors, w e r e a l l coll a b o r a t i n g o n t h e same task. W i t h o u t i n d u l g i n g i n excessively w i s h f u l t h i n k i n g , one c o u l d believe that perhaps the p r i m e m e r i d i a n o f E u r o pean p h i l o s o p h y w o u l d some day pass t h r o u g h M a d r i d for the first time i n history. T h e F a c u l t y o f Philosophy was convinced t h a t p h i l o s o p h y is inseparable f r o m its history, t h a t its i m m e d i a t e content is t h e achievements o f the philosophers o f the past t h a t are still v a l i d t o d a y ; i n other w o r d s , t h a t philosophy is h i s t o r i c a l a n d t h a t t h e h i s t o r y o f philosophy is strict philosophy: the creative i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the philosophic past f r o m the v i e w p o i n t o f a t h o r o u g h l y c o n t e m p o r a r y philosophy. Therefore, we studied the classic thinkers o f W e s t e r n culture w i t h o u t regard to epochs: Greeks, medieval w r i t e r s a n d moderns, f r o m the pre-Socratics to contemporaries, w e r e r e a d — almost always i n their o r i g i n a l languages—studied, c o m m e n t e d o n ; a l l this w i t h o u t a trace o f " n a t i o n a l i s m " or " p r o v i n c i a l i s m . " Spain, w h i c h between 1650 a n d 1900 h a d r e m a i n e d isolated f r o m E u r o p e i n m a n y respects—although not so completely as is sometimes t h o u g h t —
Reflections on One of My Booh
ix
h a d become one o f the countries i n w h i c h there prevailed a less n a r r o w v i e w o f the r e a l h o r i z o n o f c u l t u r e . Spanish t h o u g h t — p h i l o s o p h i c a l l y very modest u p to the present—was n o t given any special emphasis. I n every course the classic w r i t e r s were studied. Z u b i r i , i n his lectures o n the history o f philosophy, i n t r o d u c e d us to the pre-Socratics a n d A r i s t o t l e , to St. Augustine a n d O c c a m , to Hegel, Schelling a n d Schleiermacher, to L e i b n i z a n d the Stoics. M o r e n t e , w h o h e l d the chair o f ethics, expounded the ethical teachings o f Aristotle, Spinoza, K a n t , M i l l , Brentano. T h e courses i n logic a n d esthetics g i v e n b y Gaos l e d us to Plato, to Husserl. O r t e g a , l e c t u r i n g o n metaphysics, c o m m e n t e d o n Descartes, D i l t h e y , Bergson a n d the F r e n c h , E n g l i s h a n d G e r m a n sociologists. T h i s was the atmosphere i n w h i c h I received m y education, these were the presuppositions o f m y v i e w o f philosophy; i n short, these are the intellectual roots o f this book. B u t I d o n o t t h i n k they are sufficient to e x p l a i n , first, h o w I came to do something w h i c h neither m y teachers n o r m y classmates d i d : to w r i t e a History of Philosophy; a n d , secondly, h o w this book became the one w h i c h for a quarter o f a c e n t u r y has i n t r o d u c e d Spanish-speaking people to this discipline. T o e x p l a i n this I m u s t relate w h a t m i g h t be called the personal roots w h i c h m a d e this b o o k possible. T h a t a d m i r a b l e Faculty gave p e n e t r a t i n g a n d i l l u m i n a t i n g courses o n specific subjects, b u t there was n o general survey course o n the history o f p h i l o s o p h y ; there was n o t even a course t h a t studied any large p e r i o d as a whole. A n d yet a l l students, no m a t t e r w h a t t h e i r field o f specialization, h a d to pass a n e x a m i n a t i o n , t h e n called the examen intermedio ( " i n t e r m e d i a t e e x a m i n a t i o n " ) , i n w h i c h they were questioned o n the entire history o f philosophy a n d its m a j o r themes. Needless to say, this examination w o r r i e d everyone, p a r t i c u l a r l y those w h o h a d taken o n l y i n t r o d u c t o r y courses i n philosophy a n d were o b l i g e d , i n p r e p a r i n g for the e x a m i n a t i o n , to read l o n g a n d d i f f i c u l t books, almost always i n foreign languages a n d n o t always very clear. A g r o u p o f w o m e n students, f r o m eighteen to t w e n t y years o l d , classmates a n d very close friends o f m i n e , asked me to help t h e m p r e pare for this e x a m i n a t i o n . T h i s was i n O c t o b e r o f 1933; I was nineteen years o l d a n d i n m y j u n i o r year o f u n i v e r s i t y studies, b u t I h a d f o l l o w e d m y professors' lectures attentively a n d h a d voraciously read a large n u m b e r o f books o n philosophy. W e organized a small a n d u n o f f i c i a l course i n one o f the meeting halls o f the women's d o r m i t o r y , o f w h i c h M a r i a de M a e z t u was t h e n the d i r e c t o r . W e h e l d class whenever w e c o u l d , f r e q u e n t l y for t w o or three hours o n Sunday m o r n i n g s . T h e
X
Préface to the English
Edition
girls were quite successful i n t h e i r examinations, t o the r a t h e r great surprise o f the professors. T h e f o l l o w i n g year some other girls, w h o w e r e faced w i t h the same e x a m i n a t i o n , asked m e to give the course a g a i n ; b u t the girls w h o were most interested i n such a class were those w h o h a d already passed the e x a m i n a t i o n a n d w a n t e d to continue to a t t e n d those classes i n p h i l o s o p h y . A t the end o f each o f the t w o courses, t h e y showed their g r a t i t u d e w i t h a g i f t : Heidegger's Sein und £eit a n d N i c o l a i H a r t m a n n ' s Ethik i n 1934, a n d t w o volumes o f D i l t h e y ' s Gesammelte Schriften i n 1935. I s t i l l have these four volumes, inscribed w i t h the names o f the g i r l s ; I also still have a n i n d e l i b l e m e m o r y o f those classes a n d a g r a t i t u d e w h i c h they could n o t even have suspected. I have also kept u p m y f r i e n d s h i p w i t h almost a l l o f t h e m . T h e f o l l o w i n g academic year, 1935-1936, M a r i a de M a e z t u entrusted m e w i t h a f o r m a l course i n p h i l o s o p h y for the residents o f the d o r m i t o r y ; a n d thus, d u r i n g m y three undergraduate y e a r s — I received m y degree i n philosophy i n J u n e , 1936, one m o n t h before the C i v i l W a r — I f o u n d myself transformed i n t o a university professor. Those philosophy courses were unique i n m a n y respects, b u t part i c u l a r l y i n one: m y students were m y classmates, m y friends, girls o f m y o w n age. T h u s they d i d n o t automatically respect m y o p i n i o n . T h i s experience i n w h a t m i g h t be c a l l e d ' ' lectureship w i t h o u t respect'' was invaluable to m e . These y o u n g girls accepted n o t h i n g in verba magistri; they d i d not recognize the argument o f a u t h o r i t y . I n those days a boundless esteem for c l a r i t y a n d i n t e l l i g i b i l i t y prevailed t h r o u g h o u t the F a c u l t y o f Philosophy. Ortega often q u o t e d Goethe's verses: I c h bekenne m i c h z u dem Geschlecht, das aus dem D u n k e l ins Helle strebt. (I declare myself to be of those W h o from the darkness to the light aspire.)
A n d t i m e a n d t i m e again he s a i d : " I n philosophy, c l a r i t y is courtesy." T h e r e was no satisfaction w i t h w h a t Ortega h i m s e l f h a d once labeled " t h e l u x u r y o f i n t e l l e c t u a l o b s c u r i t y . " This means t h a t m y students insisted u p o n u n d e r s t a n d i n g everything I was t e a c h i n g t h e m , w h i c h was n o t h i n g less t h a n the e n t i r e history o f Western philosophy. T h e y asked m e to clarify e v e r y t h i n g , to justify e v e r y t h i n g ; to show w h y every philosopher t h o u g h t as he d i d a n d to show t h a t his t h o u g h t was coherent, or, i f i t was n o t , w h y n o t . B u t this means t h a t I h a d to unders t a n d i t myself, i f not beforehand, t h e n at least d u r i n g the progress o f t h e class. I have never h a d to w o r k harder, or m o r e r e w a r d i n g l y , t h a n i n f r o n t o f that class o f f o u r t e e n to sixteen y o u n g w o m e n ; s m i l i n g girls,
Reflections on One of My Books
xi
m o c k i n g at times, w i t h m i n d s as fresh as t h e i r complexions, f o n d o f discussion, eager to see clearly, inexorable. N o one else, not even m y professors, t a u g h t m e so m u c h philosophy. T o be perfectly fair, I ought to share the royalties f r o m m y books w i t h t h e m . A c t u a l l y , I a m sharing the royalties w i t h one o f t h e m . A t the close o f the C i v i l W a r i n 1939, the j o b possibilities open to a m a n like me, w h o h a d remained i n Spain a n d was resolved to be f a i t h f u l to the spirit o f t h a t university a n d to w h a t i t represented i n o u r n a t i o n a l life, were extremely l i m i t e d a n d u n c e r t a i n . I t was pointless to t h i n k about o b t a i n i n g a teaching position i n any o f the Spanish universities or even o f c o n t r i b u t i n g articles to magazines a n d newspapers. I was forced to undertake unusually significant tasks because the lesser jobs were a l l closed to m e . T h i s is one o f fate's m a n y ironies. O n e o f the girls w h o h a d taken the courses, and w h o t w o years later was to become m y wife, u r g e d m e to w r i t e a History of Philosophy. W h e n I pointed o u t to her the enormous difficulties o f the enterprise, she presented me w i t h a large stack o f notebooks: they contained her admirable, clear a n d extremely accurate notes o n m y i n f o r m a l lectures. I began to w o r k w i t h t h e m : they were the first draft o f this book. I h a d to fill i n m a n y i t e m s ; I h a d to r e t h i n k e v e r y t h i n g , f i n d a w r i t t e n instead o f o r a l expression for w h a t was said there. I n short, I h a d to w r i t e a book t h a t w o u l d really be a book. After a w h i l e I became discouraged ; I r a l l i e d a n d w e n t back to w o r k . I n December o f 1940 I wrote the last page. T h e r e was still t i m e , w h i l e correcting the proof, to a d d a reference to Bergson's death, w h i c h occurred i n the first days o f J a n u a r y , 1941.1 o u g h t to m e n t i o n t h a t O r t e g a , w h o was consulted b y his son about the a d v i s a b i l i t y o f p u b l i s h i n g this book, w h i c h i n every w a y represented a considerable risk, w i t h o u t h a v i n g read i t replied i n the affirmative f r o m his exile i n Buenos A i r e s ; a n d so the Revista de Occidente, the most respected publishing house i n Spain, published a book b y a n a u t h o r o f w h o m the most they c o u l d hope for was t h a t no one w o u l d k n o w h i m . Z u b i r i , w h o h a d been m y instructor i n the history o f philosophy for four years a n d w h o h a d t a u g h t me countless t h i n g s — h e was at this t i m e a professor i n B a r c e l o n a — w r o t e a preface to the book. * O n the seventeenth o f J a n u a r y I dedicated the first copy to that g i r l , whose n a m e was L o l i t a Franco a n d w h o a few months later was to change her n a m e to m i n e . I have related these details about the m a n n e r i n w h i c h this book came to be w r i t t e n because I t h i n k they are the r e a l reasons for its * Not included in the English edition.
Preface to the English
Edition
e x t r a o r d i n a r y success. Its readers have received the same impression f r o m i t t h a t m y first students h a d : the i n t e l l i g i b i l i t y o f philosophical doctrines, the h i s t o r y o f Western man's efforts to t h r o w l i g h t o n the deepest layers o f r e a l i t y ; a history i n w h i c h even error is explained a n d becomes i n t e l l i g i b l e a n d , to t h a t extent, j u s t i f i e d . One o f Ortega's central concepts, w h i c h permeated philosophical instruction i n M a d r i d d u r i n g m y student years, is t h a t o f historical reason. T h i s book, inspired b y t h a t p r i n c i p l e , takes i n t o account the total setting o f each philosopher, since ideas d o n o t derive solely f r o m other ideas, b u t also f r o m the overall w o r l d situation i n w h i c h each m a n must create his philosophy. T h u s , a h i s t o r y o f philosophy can be w r i t t e n o n l y philosophically, only b y r e c o n s t i t u t i n g the entire series o f past philosophies f r o m the standpoint o f a present philosophy t h a t is capable o f g i v i n g m e a n i n g to t h e m , one t h a t does n o t cast t h e m aside as obsolete errors, b u t acknowledges t h e m as its o w n roots. M a n y years have passed b y since 1941, a n d this b o o k has been enlarged, kept u p to date, polished a n d m a d e m o r e precise d u r i n g the course o f successive editions; b u t i t is the same book t h a t came i n t o being i n f r o n t o f a h a n d f u l o f y o u n g girls i n one o f the purest a n d most intense experiences o f that p h e n o m e n o n : philosophic c o m m u n i c a t i o n . JULIÁN
Madrid July, ig66.
MARÍAS
Contents
Introduction
page GREEK
PHILOSOPHY
T h e Suppositions o f Greek Philosophy T h e Pre-Socratics 1 2 3 4
i
9 11
The Milesian School, n The Pythagoreans, 15 Parmenides and the Eleatic School, ig From Heraclitus to Democritus, 25
T h e Sophists a n d Socrates
35
1 The Sophists, 35 2 Socrates, 38 Plato 1 2 3 4 5
42 The Ideas, 43 The Structure of Reality, 48 Problems Raised by the Theory of Ideas, 5/ Man and the City, 54 Philosophy, 56
Aristotle 1 The Levels of Knowledge, 2 Metaphysics, 64
59 62
Contents
xiv 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
The Modes of Being, 66 Substance, 6g Logic, 74 Physics, 77 The Theory of the Soul, 78 Ethics, 8o Politics, 82
T h e I d e a l o f the Wise M a n / 2 3 4
Ethical Philosophies in the Socratic Tradition, 88 Stoicism, go Epicureanism, g4 Skepticism and Eclecticism, g6
Neoplatonism CHRISTIANITY C h r i s t i a n i t y a n d Philosophy Patristic Speculation St. A u g u s t i n e 1 Life and Character, 113 2 Philosophy, 116 3 The Significance of St. Augustine, MEDIEVAL
ng
PHILOSOPHY
Scholasticism 1 The Era of Transition, 125 2 The Mature of Scholasticism,
127
T h e G r e a t Themes of the M i d d l e Ages 1 The Creation, 131 2 The Universals, 133 3 Reason, 136 T h e M e d i e v a l Philosophers 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
Scotus Erigena, 140 St. Anselm, 143 The Twelfth Century, 146 Eastern Philosophies, 152 The Spiritual World of the Thirteenth Century, 157 St. Bonaventure, 160 Aristotelico-Scholastic Philosophy, 163 Roger Bacon, 174 Christian Philosophy in Spain, 176
Contents
xv
10 Duns Scotus and Occam, 177 11 Meister Eckhart, 181 12 The Last Phase of Medieval Philosophy, MODERN
182
PHILOSOPHY
The Renaissance T h e Renaissance W o r l d
89
1 The Spiritual Circumstances, 2 Humanist Thought, ig2
18g 196
T h e B e g i n n i n g o f M o d e r n Philosophy 1 Nicholas of Cusa, igy 2 Giordano Bruno, 200 3 Modern Physics, 201 4 Spanish Scholasticism, 205 Seventeenth-Century Descartes 1 2 3 4 5
Idealism 210
The Cartesian Problem, 213 Man, 214 God, 216 The World, 221 Rationalism and Idealism, 222
Gartesianism i n France
224
1 Malebranche, 224 2 The Religious Thinkers, 227 Spinoza
231
1 Metaphysics, 232 2 Ethics, 234 3 Being as a Desire to Survive, 235 Leibniz 1 2 3 4
236
Leibniz' Philosophic Situation, 237 Leibniz' Metaphysics, 238 Theory of Knowledge, 242 Theodicy, 244 Empiricism
British Philosophy i Francis Bacon, 2 Hobbes, 250 3 Deism, 252
247 248
xv!
Contents 4 5 6 7
Locke, 254 Berkeley, 256 Hume, 258 The Scottish School,
25g
The Enlightenment 1 2 3 4
261
The Enlightenment in France, 262 The "Aufklärung" in Germany, 267 Vico's Doctrine of History, 268 Spanish Philosophers of the Enlightenment,
270
T h e F o r m a t i o n o f the M o d e m E p o c h 1 2 3 4 5
272
Philosophy and History, 272 The Rationalist State, 273 The Reformation, 274 Modern Society, 276 The Loss of God, 281 German Idealism
Kant
284
1 Transcendental Idealism, 285 2 The "Critique of Pure Reason," 3 Practical Reason, 2g3
287
T h e Problem o f K a n t i a n Philosophy 1 2 3 4
297
The Interpretations of Kant's Philosophy, Theory of Knowledge, 300 Being, 302 Philosophy, 305
Fichte
2g7
307
1 Fichte's Metaphysics, 308 2 Fichte's Idealism, 311 Schelling
313
The Phases of Schelling's
Philosophy,
314
Hegel 1 2 3 4 5
317 The The The The The
Outline of Hegel's Philosophy, 318 "Phenomenology of the Spirit," 31g "Logic," 320 Philosophy of Nature, 323 Philosophy of the Spirit, 324
T h e T h o u g h t o f the R o m a n t i c Age 1 The Literary Movements,
331
330
Contents 2 3 4 5
The School of Schleiermacher Derivations of Schopenhauer,
xvii
History, 331 and the Philosophy of Religion, Idealism, 333 338 Nineteenth-Century
332
Philosophy
T h e T r i u m p h over Sensationalism 1 Maine de Biran, 2 Spiritualism,
341
344
345
Comte's Positivism
348
1 History, 349 2 Society, 350 3 Science, 351 4 The Significance of Positivism, 353 Philosophy o f Positivist I n s p i r a t i o n
355
1 The French Thinkers, 355 2 English Philosophy, 356 3 The Positivist Era in Germany, 357 T h e Discovery o f Life 1 Kierkegaard, 2 Nietzsche,
360
361
362
T h e R e t u r n to T r a d i t i o n a l Metaphysics 1 The First Attempts, 2 Gratry, 368
365
366
Contemporary Philosphy Brentano 1 2 3 4
Brentano's Position in the History of Philosophy, Psychology, 373 Ethics, 375 The Existence of God, 377
The Idea of Life 1 2 3 4 5
371 371
378
Dilthey, 378 Simmel, 384 Bergson, 387 Blondel, 389 Unamuno, 390
English-Language Philosophy 1 Pragmatism, 393 2 Personalism, 398 3 Recent Trends, 399
393
XVI
Contents
ti
Husserl's Phenomenology 1 2 3 4 5 6
403
Ideal Objects, 404 Meanings, 406 The Analytic and the Synthetic, 407 Consciousness, 408 Phenomenology as a Method and as an Idealist Thesis, Phenomenological Philosophy, 411
418
Value Theory 1 The Problem of Value, 2 Scheler, 422 3 Hartmann, 423
410
418
Heidegger's Existential Philosophy
425
1 The Problem of Being, 427 2 The Analysis of Dasein, 429 3 "Existentialism," 435 O r t e g a a n d His Philosophy o f V i t a l Reason 1 2 3 4 5 6
Ortega's Personality, 442 The Genesis of Ortega's Philosophy, Vital Reason, 451 Human Life, 455 Historical and Social Life, 458 The School of Madrid, 462
442
446
Bibliography
469
Index
489
History Philosophy
Introduction
P H I L O S O P H Y . Philosophy has been understood to mean p r i n c i p a l l y t w o t h i n g s : knowledge a n d a way of life. T h e w o r d " p h i l o s o p h e r " contains the t w o different meanings o f " the m a n w h o possesses a certain k n o w l e d g e " a n d " t h e m a n w h o lives a n d acts i n a p a r t i c u l a r w a y . " Philosophy as knowledge a n d philosophy as a w a y o f life—these are t w o ways o f i n t e r p r e t i n g the w o r d , a n d the t w o interpretations have alternated a n d at times even existed simultaneously. Ever since the first philosophical speculation i n Greece, a certain theoretic life has been spoken of, a n d at the same t i m e philosophy has meant k n o w l edge, speculation. I t is necessary to understand the w o r d " p h i l o s o p h y " i n such a w a y t h a t i n our idea o f i t there is r o o m for b o t h meanings at the same time. B o t h interpretations are v a l i d , inasmuch as they have constituted philosophic reality itself. A n d one can discover the full m e a n i n g o f the w o r d a n d the reason for the d u a l i t y only i n the t o t a l comprehension o f t h a t philosophic r e a l i t y , t h a t is, i n the history o f philosophy.
T h e r e is a n i n d u b i t a b l e connection between the t w o ways o f understanding philosophy. A l t h o u g h the p r o b l e m o f e x p l a i n i n g this connection is i n large p a r t the p r o b l e m o f philosophy itself, we can understand that the t w o interpretations are i n t i m a t e l y connected, a n d i n fact have never been completely separated. Philosophy is a way of life— an essential way—that consists precisely of living according to a certain knowledge; therefore, this way of life postulates and requires this certain knowledge. It is thus knowledge which determines the meaning of the philosophic life. B u t w h a t k i n d o f knowledge ? W h a t is the n a t u r e o f philosophic i
2
Introduction
knowledge ? T h e i n d i v i d u a l sciences—mathematics, physics, history — a f f o r d us a c e r t a i n t y i n regard to some t h i n g s — a partial certainty, w h i c h does n o t exclude d o u b t outside the r e a l m o f its concern. M o r e over, the various certainties afforded us b y these i n d i v i d u a l sciences contradict one another a n d d e m a n d a h i g h e r a u t h o r i t y t o a r b i t r a t e a m o n g t h e m . I n order to k n o w precisely w h a t t o r e l y o n , m a n needs a f u n d a m e n t a l a n d universal certainty, b y means o f w h i c h he can l i v e a n d arrange the other p a r t i a l certainties i n a h i e r a r c h i c a l perspective. R e l i g i o n , a r t a n d philosophy give m a n a t o t a l c o n v i c t i o n r e g a r d i n g the whole o f r e a l i t y — b u t n o t w i t h o u t essential differences. R e l i g i o n is a certainty w h i c h is received b y m a n , g i v e n g r a t u i t o u s l y b y G o d : i t is revealed. M a n does n o t achieve this c e r t a i n t y b y himself; h e does n o t conquer i t , a n d i t is n o t o f his o w n c r e a t i o n : r a t h e r , j u s t t h e opposite is true. A r t also indicates a certain c o n v i c t i o n b y means o f w h i c h m a n finds himself, a n d f r o m w h i c h he interprets the sum t o t a l o f his life. B u t this b e l i e f — w h i c h is, o f course, o f h u m a n o r i g i n — d o e s n o t j u s t i f y itself; i t cannot account for itself; i t does n o t possess i n t r i n s i c evidence. I t is, i n short, unable to answerfor its own consequences. Philosophy, o n the other h a n d , is a f u n d a m e n t a l , universal c e r t a i n t y w h i c h is also autonomous; t h a t is, p h i l o s o p h y justifies itself; i t constantly demonstrates a n d proves its o w n v a l i d i t y ; i t thrives exclusively o n evidence. Philosophy is always r e n e w i n g the reasons for its c e r t a i n t y ( O r t e g a ) . T H E I D E A O F P H I L O S O P H Y . I t is useful t o d i r e c t our a t t e n t i o n for a m o m e n t to a few historical h i g h points i n order to see h o w the i n t e r pretations o f p h i l o s o p h y as knowledge a n d as a w a y o f life have been expressed simultaneously. For A r i s t o t l e , philosophy is a rigorous science, wisdom o r knowledge par excellence: the science o f things as they are. H o w e v e r , w h e n he speaks o f the various ways o f life, he includes a m o n g t h e m , as a n exemplary f o r m , a theoretic life w h i c h is precisely the life o f the philosopher. A f t e r A r i s t o t l e , i n t h e Stoic a n d Epicurean schools a n d the like, t h a t o v e r r u n Greece f o l l o w i n g the death o f A l e x a n d e r — a n d later the entire R o m a n E m p i r e — p h i l o s o p h y empties itself o f scientific content. M o r e a n d m o r e i t is converted i n t o a w a y o f l i f e — t h e life o f the serene a n d i m p e r t u r b a b l e wise man, w h i c h is, i n fact, the h u m a n i d e a l o f the epoch.
W i t h i n the C h r i s t i a n era, philosophy is to St. Augustine a question o f the even m o r e p r o f o u n d contrast between a vita theoretica a n d a vita beata. A n d several centuries later, St. T h o m a s is concerned w i t h a scientia theologica a n d a scientia philosophica; the d u a l i t y has passed f r o m the sphere o f life itself to the sphere o f the various forms o f knowledge. For Descartes, w h o l i v e d at the b e g i n n i n g o f the m o d e r n era, p h i losophy is no longer a question o f knowledge, o r at least n o t exclusively
Introduction
3
so; i t m i g h t perhaps be called a knowledge for life. I t is a question o f l i v i n g , o f l i v i n g i n a certain way, k n o w i n g w h a t one does a n d especially w h a t one o u g h t to do. T h u s , philosophy appears as a w a y o f life w h i c h postulates a science. B u t at the same t i m e , the highest standards o f i n t e l l e c t u a l precision a n d absolute c e r t a i n t y become a p a r t o f this science. T h e history does n o t end here. A t the m o m e n t o f m o d e r n Europe's m a t u r i t y , K a n t speaks to us ( i n his Logic a n d at the end o f the Critique of Pure Reason) of scholastic a n d worldly concepts o f philosophy. A c c o r d i n g to his scholastic concept, philosophy is a system o f a l l philosophic k n o w l edge. B u t i n its w o r l d l y sense (the m o r e p r o f o u n d a n d f u n d a m e n t a l i n t e r p r e t a t i o n ) philosophy is the science o f the relationship between a l l knowledge a n d the essential goals o f h u m a n reason. T h e philosopher is no longer the artificer o f reason, b u t r a t h e r the legislator o f h u m a n reason. A n d i n this sense, K a n t says, one m a y be p r o u d to call oneself a philosopher. T h e u l t i m a t e goal is m o r a l destiny; therefore, the concept o f the moral person is the c u l m i n a t i o n o f K a n t i a n metaphysics. Philosophy i n its w o r l d l y sense—as a n essential w a y o f life o f m a n — i s w h a t gives m e a n i n g to philosophy as a science. F i n a l l y , i n o u r day, w h i l e Husserl insists once more o n presenting philosophy as a strict and rigorous science a n d D i l t h e y links i t essentially to h u m a n life a n d history, Ortega's idea of'vital reason restates the very nucleus o f the question i n a f u n d a m e n t a l w a y a n d establishes a n intrinsic a n d necessary relationship between r a t i o n a l knowledge a n d life itself. T H E O R I G I N O F P H I L O S O P H Y . W h y d i d m a n begin to philosophize? R a r e l y has this question been raised a n d discussed adequately. Aristotle's t r e a t m e n t o f i t was such t h a t i t decisively influenced the entire subsequent development o f philosophy. T h e opening section o f his Metaphysics is a n answer to t h a t q u e s t i o n : All men desire naturally to know. F o r A r i s t o t l e , the reason for man's desire to k n o w is n o t h i n g less t h a n t h a t i t is his n a t u r e . A n d the n a t u r e o f a t h i n g is its substance, t h a t o f w h i c h i t r e a l l y consists; therefore, knowledge seems to define m a n ; man's v e r y essence moves h i m to k n o w . H e r e again we f i n d a m o r e evident l i n k between knowledge a n d life, whose meaning w i l l become more a n d m o r e clear d u r i n g the course o f this book. B u t A r i s t o t l e says something else. A l i t t l e further o n i n the Metaphysics, he w r i t e s : It is because of awe that men begin to philosophize—now and in the beginning. At fast, men were awed by strange things that were closer to hand; later, pushing forward little by little in this manner, men investigated the most important things, such as the movements of the moon, sun and stars and the generation ofeverything. T h u s w e f i n d the most concrete r o o t o f the process o f p h i l o s o p h i z i n g to
4
Introduction
be a h u m a n a t t i t u d e — a w e . F i r s t m a n wonders a b o u t n e a r b y things, a n d t h e n about the sum t o t a l o f a l l t h a t exists. Instead o f c i r c u l a t i n g a m o n g things, using t h e m , e n j o y i n g t h e m or fearing t h e m , m a n stands apart f r o m t h e m , alienated f r o m t h e m ; he inquires w i t h awe a b o u t these nearby, everyday things w h i c h n o w for the first t i m e appear to be opposite h i m a n d therefore alone, isolated b y the q u e s t i o n : " W h a t is this ? " Philosophy begins at this m o m e n t . T h i s is a completely new h u m a n a t t i t u d e , w h i c h Z u b i r i has called theoretic i n contrast to mythic attitudes. T h i s n e w h u m a n o u t l o o k appears i n Greece one d a y for the first t i m e i n h i s t o r y , a n d f r o m t h a t m o m e n t there is something r a d i c a l l y new i n the w o r l d , something w h i c h makes philosophy possible. T o m y t h i c m a n , t h i n g s are p r o p i tious or h a r m f u l powers w h i c h he lives w i t h a n d w h i c h he uses or shuns. T h i s is the p r e - H e l l e n i c a t t i t u d e and one w h i c h the people to w h o m the b r i l l i a n t Greek discovery has n o t penetrated c o n t i n u e to share. T h e o r i z i n g consciousness, o n the other h a n d , sees things where previously i t saw o n l y powers. T h i s constitutes the great discovery o f things, a discovery so p r o f o u n d t h a t today i t is d i f f i c u l t for us to realize t h a t i t actually was a discovery or to imagine t h a t i t c o u l d have happened any other w a y . I n order to realize its significance, w e must m a k e use o f forms o f t h o u g h t w h i c h , w h i l e d i f f e r i n g f r o m the m o d e r n W e s t e r n a t t i t u d e , r e t a i n a remote analogy w i t h the m y t h i c a t t i t u d e : for example, t h a t o f the i n f a n t i l e consciousness, t h e a t t i t u d e o f the c h i l d w h o finds h i m s e l f i n a w o r l d f u l l o f b e n i g n o r hostile powers or persons, b u t n o t , s t r i c t l y speaking, o f things. W h e n m a n begins to theorize, instead o f b e i n g among the things, he is opposite t h e m , alienated f r o m t h e m , a n d thus they acquire a m e a n i n g o f t h e i r o w n w h i c h previously they d i d n o t have. T h e y seem to exist for themselves, apart f r o m m a n , a n d to have a d e t e r m i n e d consistence: t h a t is, they possess a n u m b e r o f properties, something o f their o w n , s o m e t h i n g t h a t belongs to t h e m alone. T h e n the things are seen as realities t h a t exist, t h a t have a special content. A n d o n l y i n this sense can one speak o f t r u t h or falsity. M y t h i c m a n moves outside the r e a l m o f this discovery. O n l y as something existing can things be true or false. T h e oldest f o r m o f this awakening to the t r u t h o f the things is awe. A n d therefore i t is the r o o t o f philosophy. P H I L O S O P H Y A N D I T S H I S T O R Y . Philosophy's relationship to its history is unlike t h a t o f science, for example, to its o w n history. I n the l a t t e r case, the t w o things are d i s t i n c t : science, o n the one h a n d , a n d o n the other, w h a t science was, t h a t is, its history. T h e t w o are independ e n t o f one another, a n d science can exist a n d be understood a n d c u l t i v a t e d separate f r o m the history o f w h a t i t has been. Science is
Introduction
5
constructed f r o m a n object a n d f r o m the knowledge w h i c h at a particu l a r m o m e n t is available a b o u t t h a t object. I n philosophy, the p r o b l e m is philosophy itself ; moreover, i n every instance this p r o b l e m is stated according to the historical a n d personal situation i n w h i c h the philosopher finds himself, a n d this situation is i n t u r n d e t e r m i n e d i n large measure b y the philosophic t r a d i t i o n to w h i c h the p a r t i c u l a r philosopher belongs. T h e entire philosophic past is i n c l u d e d i n every act o f philosophizing. I n the t h i r d place, the philosopher m u s t investigate the philosophic p r o b l e m i n its t o t a l i t y and, therefore, philosophy itself f r o m its o r i g i n a l root. H e cannot start f r o m a n d accept a readym a d e (de facto) state o f knowledge ; rather, he must start at the b e g i n n i n g a n d at the some time f r o m the historical s i t u a t i o n i n w h i c h he finds himself. T h a t is, philosophy must establish a n d f u l f i l l itself w h o l l y i n every philosopher, n o t i n j u s t any m a n n e r , b u t i n every philosopher i n a u n i q u e l y a p p r o p r i a t e w a y : the w a y i n w h i c h he has been conditioned b y a l l previous philosophy. Therefore, a l l philosop h i z i n g includes the entire history o f philosophy; i f i t d i d n o t , i t w o u l d n o t be i n t e l l i g i b l e a n d , w h a t is more, i t c o u l d n o t exist. A t the same t i m e , philosophy possesses o n l y t h a t reality w h i c h i t achieves h i s t o r i c a l l y i n each philosopher. T h e r e is, then, an inseparable connection between p h i l o s o p h y a n d the history o f philosophy. Philosophy is historical, a n d its history is a n essential p a r t o f i t . M o r e o v e r , the history o f philosophy is n o t a mere e r u d i t e account o f the opinions o f philosophers, b u t the t r u e exposition o f the real content o f philosophy. T h e n i t is, i n a l l t r u t h , philosophy. Philosophy does n o t exhaust itself i n a n y one o f its systems; rather, i t consists o f the true history o f a l l philosophic systems. A n d , i n t h e i r t u r n , none o f these systems can exist independently, for each one requires a n d involves a l l previous systems. T h e r e is still another p o i n t : each system o f philosophy achieves m a x i m u m reality, f u l l truth, o n l y outside o f i t s e l f — t h a t is, i n the t h o u g h t o f those philosophers w h o are to succeed i t . A l l philosophizing originates f r o m the t o t a l i t y o f the past a n d projects itself t o w a r d the f u t u r e , thus advancing the history o f philosophy. T h i s is, briefly, w h a t one means w h e n one says t h a t philosophy is historical. T R U T H A N D H I S T O R Y . T h e foregoing account does n o t m e a n t h a t truth is n o t o f interest i n philosophy, t h a t philosophy is to be considered m e r e l y as a historical p h e n o m e n o n unconcerned w i t h t r u t h a n d falsity. E v e r y philosophic system claims to be true ; o n the other h a n d , contradictions between systems are evident a n d far f r o m c o i n c i d e n t a l ; b u t these contradictions do n o t b y a n y means signify complete i n c o m p a t i b i l i t y . N o system o f philosophy c a n c l a i m absolute a n d exclusive v a l i d i t y ,
6
Introduction
because none exhausts r e a l i t y ; t o t h e extent t h a t any system c l a i m s to be the o n l y t r u e system, i t is false. E v e r y philosophic system apprehends a p o r t i o n o f reality—precisely t h a t p a r t w h i c h is accessible f r o m its p o i n t o f v i e w or perspective. N o r does the t r u t h o f one system i m p l y the falsity o f other systems, except o n points w h i c h a r e f o r m a l l y c o n t r a d i c t e d . A c o n t r a d i c t i o n arises o n l y w h e n a philosopher affirms m o r e t h a n he actually sees. T h u s a l l philosophic visions are t r u e ( I m e a n , o f course, p a r t i a l l y true) a n d i n p r i n c i p l e do n o t e x c l u d e one another. M o r e o v e r , every philosopher's p o i n t of v i e w is c o n d i t i o n e d b y his historical situation, a n d therefore every system, i f i t is t o be f a i t h f u l to its o w n perspective, must i n c l u d e a l l previous systems as p a r t o f its o w n composition. T h u s , t h e various true philosophies are n o t i n t e r c h a n g e a b l e ; rather, they are rigorously determined a c c o r d i n g to t h e i r sequence i n h u m a n history. * * See
my Introducción a la Filosofía
[Reason
and Life],
ch.
XII.
GREEK
PHILOSOPHY
i
The Suppositions of Greek
Philosophy
I f we ignore t h e obscure p r o b l e m o f O r i e n t a l ( I n d i a n , Chinese) philosophy, i n w h i c h w h a t is most p r o b l e m a t i c is the m e a n i n g o f the w o r d " p h i l o s o p h y " itself, a n d focus o u r a t t e n t i o n o n w h a t philosophy has been i n the West, w e w i l l find t h a t its first stage is the philosophy o f the Greeks. T h i s i n i t i a l phase, w h i c h lasted for more t h a n a m i l l e n n i u m , differs f r o m a l l later phases i n t h a t i t does n o t have a philosophic t r a d i t i o n b e h i n d i t ; t h a t is, Greek philosophy emerges f r o m a concrete h u m a n s i t u a t i o n — t h a t o f " a n c i e n t " m a n — w h i c h contains n o p h i l o sophical element o r ingredient. T h i s circumstance has t w o i m p o r t a n t consequences: i n the first place, the b i r t h o f philosophy i n Greece has a p u r i t y a n d o r i g i n a l i t y superior t o a l l t h a t is t o come l a t e r ; secondly, ancient man's v i t a l a n d historical s i t u a t i o n d i r e c t l y conditions H e l l e n i c speculation t o the p o i n t t h a t the m a j o r theme o f the history o f Greek p h i l o s o p h y consists i n d e t e r m i n i n g w h y m a n , u p o n r e a c h i n g a certain stage i n his development, f o u n d h i m s e l f compelled t o f u l f i l l a completely n e w a n d u n k n o w n need, w h i c h today w e call philosop h i z i n g . W e cannot discuss this p r o b l e m here, b u t w e m u s t at least p o i n t o u t some o f the historic suppositions w h i c h made p h i l o s o p h y possible a n d necessary i n the H e l l e n i c w o r l d . * A w a y o f life is defined above a l l b y its r e p e r t o r y ofbeliefs. N a t u r a l l y , beliefs change, as O r t e g a has shown, f r o m generation to g e n e r a t i o n — this is w h a t constitutes historical m u t a t i o n . B u t a certain basic core o f beliefs endures t h r o u g h several generations a n d gives t h e m the h i g h e r * Cf. my Biografía de la Filosofía, I . " L a filosofía griega desde su origen hasta P l a t ó n . " ( E m e c é , Buenos Aires, 1954). [Obras, vol. I I . ] 9
lO
The Suppositions of Greek Philosophy
u n i t y w h i c h we designate b y such words as epoch, era or age. W h a t are the basic beliefs h e l d b y Greek m a n w h i c h l i m i t a n d give f o r m to his philosophy? H e l l e n i c m a n finds h i m s e l f i n a world w h i c h has always existed a n d w h i c h is therefore never a p r o b l e m ; a l l q u e s t i o n i n g presupposes this w o r l d , takes i t for g r a n t e d . T h e w o r l d is i n t e r p r e t e d as nature a n d , therefore, as a n o r i g i n a l principle, or as t h a t f r o m w h i c h a l l concrete r e a l i t y emerges o r issues. T h u s the w o r l d appears t o be endowed w i t h potentiality, w i t h p r o d u c t i v e capacity. B u t at the same t i m e i t is a multiplicity ; the w o r l d contains m a n y things w h i c h are capable o f changing a n d are defined b y opposites. E v e r y one o f these t h i n g s has a n independ e n t consistency, b u t the things themselves are n o t permanent. T h e y change, a n d their properties are understood i n terms o f opposites: c o l d is the opposite o f w a r m , even the opposite o f o d d , a n d so o n . T h i s p o l a r i t y is characteristic o f the ancient m i n d . T h e properties inherent i n the things p e r m i t t h e m to be used i n a technic basically different f r o m magical procedures, i n w h i c h things are t r e a t e d as powers. T h e Greek's w o r l d is intelligible. I t can be understood, a n d comprehension consists i n seeing or c o n t e m p l a t i n g t h a t r e a l i t y a n d of explaining it. Theory, logos a n d being are the three decisive terms o f H e l l e n i c t h o u g h t , a n d they are r o o t e d i n this p r i m a r y a t t i t u d e t o w a r d the w o r l d . As a consequence, the w o r l d appears as something w h i c h is ordered a n d subjected to l a w : this is the n o t i o n o f the cosmos. Reason is inserted i n t o this l a w f u l order o f the w o r l d , w h i c h can be governed a n d directed, a n d the concrete f o r m o f this l a w f u l o r d e r i n h u m a n affairs is the p o l i t i c a l coexistence o f m e n i n cities. I t is necessary to keep this basic outline o f ancient beliefs i n m i n d i n o r d e r t o understand the historical fact o f Greek philosophy.
The
i.
T H E
Pre-Socratics
MILESIAN
SCHOOL
T h e Greek philosophers p r i o r to Socrates are called thepre-Socratics. T h i s n a m e has, to begin w i t h , a chronological value: these are the thinkers w h o l i v e d f r o m the end o f the seventh century to t h e close o f the fifth century before Christ. However, the t e r m also has a more p r o f o u n d m e a n i n g : the earliest beginnings o f Greek philosophy can be considered true philosophy because after t h e m there existed a f u l l a n d indisputable philosophy. E x a m i n e d i n the l i g h t o f m a t u r e p h i l o s o p h y — f r o m Socrates o n w a r d — t h e first H e l l e n i c speculations are seen to be philosophic, a l t h o u g h n o t a l l o f t h e m w o u l d m e r i t this designation were they n o t the b e g i n n i n g a n d promise o f s o m e t h i n g to come later o n . By being pre-Socratics, b y a n n o u n c i n g a n d p r e p a r i n g a philosophic m a t u r i t y , the first thinkers o f I o n i a a n d M a g n a Graecia are themselves already philosophers. O n e must n o t forget t h a t i f i t is t r u e t h a t the present depends o n the past, t h e n the present sometimes redounds on the past a n d colors i t as w e l l . Specific affirmations o f the oldest I n d i a n a n d Chinese thinkers are often similar to those o f the Greeks; the m a j o r difference between these t w o philosophies is t h a t after the pre-Socratics came Socrates, whereas the s t a m m e r i n g O r i e n t a l speculation was n o t followed b y a philosophic fullness i n the sense w h i c h this phrase has taken o n i n the West. T h i s explains the f u n d a m e n t a l difference w h i c h we notice between the earliest t h i n k i n g o f the H e l l e n i c people a n d t h a t o f the Orientals. T h e last pre-Socratics do n o t predate Socrates; they are his c o n t e m poraries i n the second h a l f o f the fifth century. However, they r e m a i n ii
12
The Pre-Socratics
p a r t o f t h e g r o u p t h a t antedates h i m because o f t h e theme a n d character o f their speculation. Mature ( lived, i n H o l l a n d . T h i s country's t r a n q u i l l i t y , liberal atmosphere a n d independence appealed to h i m . T h i s was Descartes' most f r u i t f u l p e r i o d , i n w h i c h he w r o t e a n d p u b l i s h e d his most i m p o r t a n t works. H e established contact w i t h E u r o p e a n p h i losophers a n d m e n of science a n d at the same t i m e was deeply h u r t b y attacks o n his doctrines; these attacks w e r e l e d p r i n c i p a l l y b y the Jesuits, i n spite o f his still being a C a t h o l i c . A t this t i m e a few o f his pupils deceived a n d disappointed h i m , a n d as a result of this he c u l t i vated his epistolary friendship w i t h the Princess Elizabeth w i t h greater intensity t h a n ever. W h e n Descartes m e t her i n 1643, he realized t h a t E l i z a b e t h , a p r e t t y g i r l of twenty-five years, h a d studied his works w i t h interest a n d intelligence; he mentions this fact w i t h e m o t i o n i n the dedication to his Principles of Philosophy. A f t e r this, t h e friendship became even m o r e p r o f o u n d a n d i n t e l l e c t u a l l y r e w a r d i n g . o n
n
e
Descartes left H o l l a n d only to make short trips, one of t h e m t o D e n m a r k . L a t e r he made more frequent excursions i n t o France, where he had become famous. I n 1646 he began corresponding w i t h Q u e e n Christina o f Sweden, w h o later i n v i t e d h i m to come to S t o c k h o l m ; Descartes accepted a n d a r r i v e d i n the Swedish capital i n O c t o b e r o f 1649. I n spite o f his friendship a n d a d m i r a t i o n for C h r i s t i n a , whose conversion to C a t h o l i c i s m his conversations helped to effect, Descartes d i d not feel a t ease i n her c o u r t . A few m o n t h s later, i n F e b r u a r y , 1650, the cold S t o c k h o l m w i n t e r b r o u g h t o n a n attack o f p n e u m o n i a , a n d Descartes d i e d t h a t very m o n t h . T h u s ended this exemplary life o f a searcher after t r u t h . W O R K S . Descartes' l i t e r a r y w o r k is q u i t e extensive. H i s w r i t i n g s are not restricted to philosophical works, b u t also comprise basic books i n the fields o f mathematics, biology a n d physics, a n d a n extensive correspondence. H i s p r i n c i p a l works are Discours de la méthode, p u b lished i n 1637, together w i t h the Dioptrique, the Météores a n d the Géométrie; the Meditations
on First Philosophy
(1641), together w i t h the
Objections b y A r n a u l d , Gassendi, H o b b e s a n d others, a n d Descartes' Replies to t h e m ; the Principia philosophiae de l'áme (1649),
a
n
d
( 1 6 4 4 ) ; the Traite des passions
the Regulae ad directionem ingenii (Rules for the
Direction of the Mind), published after his d e a t h , i n 1701. A m o n g his n o t strictly p h i l o s o p h i c a l works are the above-mentioned Géométrie analy¬ tique a n d the Traitéde Vhomme. Descartes w r o t e i n L a t i n , as d i d p r a c t i cally a l l the thinkers of his d a y — b u t also i n F r e n c h ; he was one o f the
The
Cartesian
Problem
first F r e n c h prose writers a n d one o f the first to discuss philosophy i n the vernacular. i.
T H E CARTESIAN PROBLEM
D O U B T . I n his development as a philosopher, Descartes realizes t h a t he is deeply insecure. N o t h i n g seems t r u s t w o r t h y to h i m . T h e past history o f philosophy is completely c o n t r a d i c t o r y ; m e n have c h a m p i o n e d the most d i a m e t r i c a l l y opposed theses. T h i s m u l t i p l i c i t y of opinions gives rise to skepticism (the so-called historical Pyrrhonism). O u r senses often deceive us a n d we are also subject to dreams a n d hallucinations. O u r thought processes are u n t r u s t w o r t h y because we f o r m u l a t e paralogisms and frequently f a l l i n t o error. T h e o n l y sciences t h a t seem to have a secure basis, mathematics and logic, are n o t real sciences; they d o n o t aid us to k n o w reality. W h a t are we to do i n this s i t u a t i o n ? Descartes wishes to c o n s t r u c t — i f this is possible—a c o m pletely c e r t a i n philosophy, one w h i c h cannot be d o u b t e d , a n d he finds h i m s e l f t o t a l l y overwhelmed b y d o u b t . T h u s i t is precisely his d o u b t w h i c h must be the f o u n d a t i o n o n w h i c h to b u i l d ; o n b e g i n n i n g to philosophize, Descartes starts w i t h the o n l y t h i n g he possesses: his o w n d o u b t , his p r o f o u n d u n c e r t a i n t y . I t is necessary to cast d o u b t o n all things at least once i n one's l i f e t i m e , Descartes says. H e must n o t accept a single " t r u t h " that is open to d o u b t . I t is not sufficient t h a t he does n o t a c t u a l l y d o u b t t h a t " t r u t h " ; there must not be r o o m even for the possibility o f a d o u b t . Therefore Descartes makes d o u b t the very m e t h o d o f his philosophy. O n l y i f he finds some p r i n c i p l e w h i c h i t is impossible to d o u b t w i l l he accept i t for his philosophy. I t should be kept i n m i n d t h a t he has rejected the presumptive evidence o f the senses, the r e l i a b i l i t y o f the t h o u g h t processes a n d , of course, t r a d i t i o n a l a n d received knowledge. Therefore, Descartes attempts first of all to r e m a i n completely alone; this is, i n effect, the situation i n w h i c h m a n finds himself at the close o f the M i d d l e Ages. Starting w i t h this solitude, Descartes must t r y to reconstruct certainty, a security t h a t is unassailable b y d o u b t . As a p r i m a r y goal, Descartes attempts not to err. T h i s is the b e g i n n i n g of the p h i l o s o p h y o f caution. A n d , as we shall see, there arise the three great questions of medieval p h i l o s o p h y — a n d perhaps of all p h i l o s o p h y : the w o r l d , m a n a n d G o d . T h e o n l y t h i n g t h a t has changed is their order a n d the role each one plays. T H E O L O G Y . W i t h regard to theology, w h i c h had always afforded a greater c e r t a i n t y , Descartes begins b y a f f i r m i n g that separation o f p h i l o s o p h y f r o m theology w h i c h he f o u n d before h i m . O n e should n o t
zi4
Descartes
concern oneself w i t h theology, h i g h l y respectable t h o u g h i t m a y b e — precisely because i t is too respectable a n d lofty. T h e reasons he gives are s y m p t o m a t i c o f the e n t i r e w a y o f t h o u g h t o f t h e close o f the Scholastic era. " I revered our theology a n d h o p e d as m u c h as anyone else to a t t a i n heaven ; b u t h a v i n g learned, as a v e r y sure fact, t h a t the r o a d t o heaven is no less open to the most i g n o r a n t t h a n to the most l e a r n e d , a n d t h a t the revealed truths w h i c h lead us there are above the level o f our i n t e l ligence, I w o u l d n o t dare t o s u b m i t these truths t o m y w e a k powers o f reasoning, a n d I t h o u g h t t h a t i n order to t r y to e x a m i n e t h e m a n d succeed one w o u l d need to have some e x t r a o r d i n a r y assistance f r o m heaven a n d to be m o r e t h a n m a n " (Discourse on Method, P a r t I ) . Descartes emphasizes the p r a c t i c a l , devout side of t h e o l o g y . W h a t is i n v o l v e d is to a t t a i n h e a v e n ; b u t i t happens t h a t this c a n be done w i t h o u t k n o w i n g a n y t h i n g a b o u t theology, a n d this makes its uselessness manifest. I t should be observed t h a t Descartes does n o t present this as a discovery of his o w n , b u t j u s t the opposite : i t is s o m e t h i n g he has learned. Therefore, i t is a fact already k n o w n , h a n d e d d o w n a n d , i n a d d i t i o n , perfectly c e r t a i n ; i t is thus current opinion. Secondly, this is a m a t t e r o f revelation w h i c h is b e y o n d the level o f h u m a n intelligence. Reason can accomplish n o t h i n g w i t h the great topic o f G o d ; i t w o u l d be necessary to be more than man. I t is clearly a question o f j u r i s d i c t i o n : o n one side, m a n w i t h his reason; o n the other, G o d — o m n i p o t e n t , inaccessible, higher t h a n a l l r e a s o n — w h o occasionally deigns to reveal himself to m a n . I t is n o t m a n w h o practices t h e o l o g y , b u t G o d ; m a n has n o t h i n g to do w i t h this m a t t e r : G o d is too e x a l t e d . 2. M A N
T H E " C O G I T O . " W i t h the first steps he takes, Descartes must renounce the w o r l d . N a t u r e , w h i c h showed itself so j o y o u s l y to Renaissance m a n t h r o u g h the agency o f his senses, is s o m e t h i n g completely u n c e r t a i n . H a l l u c i n a t i o n s , the deceitfulness of our senses, o u r errors i n j u d g m e n t — a l l o f these m a k e i t impossible to f i n d the least c e r t a i n t y i n the w o r l d . Descartes prepares h i m s e l f to t h i n k t h a t e v e r y t h i n g is false, b u t he finds t h a t there is one t h i n g w h i c h cannot be false: his o w n existence. " W h i l e I wished to t h i n k thus, t h a t e v e r y t h i n g was false, i t necessarily h a d to be t r u e t h a t I , w h o was t h i n k i n g this, was somet h i n g ; a n d , observing t h a t this t r u t h — / think, therefore I am—was so firm a n d so sure t h a t a l l the most extravagant suppositions o f the skeptics were incapable o f shaking i t , I j u d g e d t h a t I c o u l d accept i t w i t h o u t a scruple as the first p r i n c i p l e of the philosophy I was seeking " (Discourse
on Method, P a r t I V ) .
Man
zij
I n effect, i f I a m i n e r r o r , i t is / w h o a m i n e r r o r ; i f I a m mistaken, i f I feel a d o u b t , / a m the mistaken one, / a m the d o u b t e r . I n order to be w r o n g i n declaring t h a t / am, I w o u l d need first o f a l l to be; t h a t is, I cannot be w r o n g a b o u t this. T h i s first t r u t h o f m y existence, the cogito, ergo sum o f the Meditations, is the first i n d u b i t a b l e t r u t h , w h i c h I cannot d o u b t even i f I wish t o . T h e r e is n o t h i n g c e r t a i n except myself. A n d I a m n o t h i n g more t h a n a thing that thinks: mens, cogitatio. Ego sum res cogitans, Descartes says t e x t u a l l y : je ne suis qu'une chose qui pense. T h e r e f o r e , I a m n o t even a
b o d i l y m a n , I a m o n l y reason. F r o m w h a t we have seen, i t is impossible to h o l d o n t o the w o r l d : i t slips a w a y ; n o r is i t possible to retain the b o d y ; the o n l y t h i n g t h a t is secure and c e r t a i n is the t h i n k i n g subject. M a n is left alone w i t h his thoughts. Philosophy is to be based o n " m e " as a consciousness, as reason; b e g i n n i n g n o w a n d for centuries to come, philosophy w i l l be idealism—Descartes' great discovery a n d great error. T h i s solution is consistent. G o d had been left o u t because H e was no longer an object o f reason; this was the decisive factor. Thus, i t is n o t surprising t h a t reason is f o u n d to be the o n l y solid p o i n t on w h i c h t o base philosophy. Despite a l l appearances, this is n o t h i n g new; w h a t occurs n o w is t h a t reason is a h u m a n m a t t e r ; therefore, philosophy is not merely rationalism, b u t idealism as w e l l . T h e r e w i l l be an a t t e m p t t o base a l l metaphysics o n m a n , or rather o n the ego; the history o f this a t t e m p t is the history o f m o d e r n philosophy. T H E C R I T E R I O N FOR T R U T H . T h e w o r l d d i d n o t w i t h s t a n d Descartes'
d o u b t ; o n its first contact w i t h this d o u b t , the w o r l d was lost a n d o n l y the ego stood f i r m . B u t Descartes has o n l y j u s t b e g u n his philosophy, setting his foot on solid g r o u n d . Descartes is interested i n the w o r l d ; he is interested i n the things a n d i n t h a t n a t u r e w h i c h is the concern of the science of his day. B u t he is a prisoner o f his o w n consciousness, locked u p i n his t h i n k i n g ego, a n d he is unable t o take the step w h i c h w i l l lead h i m to the things. H o w can he emerge f r o m this subjectivity? N o w t h a t he has f o u n d his i n d u b i t a b l e p r i n c i p l e , h o w can he continue his philosophy ? Before seeking a second t r u t h , Descartes lingers over the first. I t is a very h u m b l e t r u t h , b u t i t w i l l help h i m see w h a t a t r u t h is like. T h a t is, before u n d e r t a k i n g the quest for n e w truths, Descartes examines the o n l y one he possesses i n order to see w h a t its truthfulness consists of, w h a t there is about i t t h a t makes h i m k n o w i t is true. H e thus seeks a criterionfor certainty i n order to recognize the truths he m a y come across ( O r t e g a ) . H e finds t h a t the t r u t h o f the cogito consists i n his being unable t o d o u b t i t ; a n d he cannot d o u b t i t because he sees t h a t i t must be so, because i t is self-evident. T h i s self-evidence consists i n
2l6
Descartes
the absolute clearness and distinctness w h i c h this idea possesses. T h a t is the criterion for t r u t h : self-evidence. I n possession of a f i r m t r u t h a n d a sure criterion, Descartes prepares himself for the reconquest o f the w o r l d . B u t to accomplish this he must take a long, circuitous route. A n d , strange to say, Descartes' r o u n d a b o u t p a t h for g e t t i n g f r o m the ego to the w o r l d passes t h r o u g h G o d . H o w is this possible ?
3.
GOD
T H E " M A L I G N A N T GENIUS. " W e have seen t h a t Descartes abandons theology, t h a t G o d is incomprehensible; a n d n o w , surprisingly, the D e i t y interposes itself between m a n a n d the w o r l d , and Descartes has to concern h i m s e l f w i t h i t . I t is necessary to explain this. Descartes knows t h a t he h i m s e l f exists, a n d he knows i t because he clearly a n d distinctly perceives the t r u t h o f i t . I t is a t r u t h w h i c h justifies itself; whenever he comes across something s i m i l a r , he w i l l of necessity have to accept i t as t r u t h — u n l e s s he is i n a s i t u a t i o n where he is being deceived, unless he is the v i c t i m of a n i l l u s i o n , unless there is someone w h o makes h i m see as self-evident t h a t w h i c h could not be m o r e false. I n that case self-evidence w o u l d be o f no use at a l l , a n d he c o u l d n o t affirm any t r u t h other t h a n t h a t he himself existed; this w o u l d still be possible because, n a t u r a l l y , i f someone deceives me, I a m the deceived or, w h a t amounts to the same t h i n g , I , the deceived, am. I n this situation m a n w o u l d definitely r e m a i n a prisoner w i t h i n himself, a n d could not w i t h certainty k n o w a n y t h i n g other t h a n his o w n existence. W h o w o u l d be able to deceive me i n such a w a y ? G o d , i f H e exists; we d o not know t h a t H e does exist, b u t neither do we k n o w t h a t H e does n o t . ( I t is understood t h a t this argument is based o n the v i e w p o i n t o f rational philosophic knowledge, a n d is considered apart f r o m revelat i o n , w h i c h Descartes excludes f r o m the r e a l m o f d o u b t . ) B u t i f G o d were to deceive m e i n this way, m a k i n g me believe i n something t h a t does not exist, p l u n g i n g me i n t o error, n o t because of m y weakness or because of m y rashness, b u t because of m y o w n feeling of self-evidence, H e w o u l d n o t be G o d ; the m i n d shrinks f r o m i m a g i n i n g such deceitfulness o n the p a r t o f the D e i t y . I do n o t k n o w t h a t G o d exists, b u t i f H e exists, H e cannot deceive me. O n e w h o c o u l d do this w o u l d be some powerful malignant genius. I n order to be sure o f the self-evident, i n order to be able to trust i n the t r u t h w h i c h presents itself as t r u t h accompanied b y clear a n d distinct proofs, w e w o u l d have to d e m o n strate the existence of G o d . Otherwise, we cannot take another step i n philosophy or seek any t r u t h other t h a n t h a t the ego exists. T H E D E M O N S T R A T I O N OF T H E EXISTENCE OF G O D .
I n effect, Descartes
God proves the existence o f G o d . H e does this i n several ways, w i t h a r g u ments v e r y different i n scope. O n the one h a n d , Descartes says, I f i n d w i t h i n m y m i n d the idea o f God, t h a t is, o f a n e n t i t y w h i c h is i n f i n i t e , completely perfect, o m n i p o t e n t , a l l - k n o w i n g a n d so o n . N o w , this idea cannot come f r o m nothingness, nor can i t o r i g i n a t e w i t h i n myself. I a m finite, imperfect, weak a n d f u l l o f d o u b t a n d ignorance, a n d i f the idea o r i g i n a t e d w i t h i n me, the effect w o u l d be superior to the cause. T h i s is impossible. Consequently, the idea o f G o d must have been placed w i t h i n me b y some h i g h e r entity w h i c h attains the perfection o f t h a t i d e a ; that is, b y G o d Himself. This proves H i s existence. T h e other d e m o n s t r a t i o n is the one w h i c h since K a n t is generally k n o w n as the ontological proof, that is, the a r g u m e n t used b y St. A n s e l m i n his Proslogium (see above). Nevertheless, there are p r o f o u n d differences between the m e a n i n g o f St. Anselm's a r g u m e n t and Descartes' proof. Descartes says: I possess the idea o f a completely perfect e n t i t y , w h i c h is G o d ; n o w , existence is an element o f perfection, and I f i n d t h a t existence is i n c l u d e d essentially i n the concept o f this e n t i t y ; thus, i t is necessary for G o d to exist. T h e t w o Cartesian proofs, w h i c h are closely related to each other, have a factor i n c o m m o n : /possess the idea of a perfect entity, therefore it exists. T h e difference b e t w e e n the two proofs is
i n the reasons Descartes gives, that is, i n the m a n n e r i n w h i c h the c o n cept proves existence: the first p r o o f declares t h a t o n l y G o d can place the idea o f H i m s e l f w i t h i n m e ; the second p r o o f shows that this idea o f G o d w h i c h I possess implies H i s existence. Therefore, the t w o proofs m u t u a l l y r e q u i r e a n d support each other. S t r i c t l y speaking, the p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e for Descartes' demonstrat i o n is the r e a l i t y o f the ego, taken together w i t h a clear a n d distinct concept o f the D e i t y . M y finiteness a n d i m p e r f e c t i o n are contrasted w i t h the i n f i n i t y a n d perfection of G o d , the idea of w h o m I f i n d w i t h i n myself. B y raising to the infinite w h a t is positive i n me a n d r e m o v i n g a l l limits, I raise myself intellectually to G o d . I n other words, m a n has w i t h i n h i m the image o f G o d , w h i c h permits h i m to arrive at the k n o w l edge o f G o d . " T h i s idea [ o f G o d ] , " Descartes says at the end o f his t h i r d Meditation, " w a s b o r n a n d p r o d u c e d together w i t h me at the m o m e n t o f m y c r e a t i o n , j u s t as the idea I have o f myself was. A n d i n t r u t h i t should n o t be a cause for surprise i f G o d , w h e n creating m e , placed t h a t idea w i t h i n m e so t h a t i t m i g h t be like the artisan's mark stamped on his product; n o r is i t necessary for this m a r k to be something different f r o m the p r o d u c t itself; on the c o n t r a r y , b y the very fact t h a t G o d created me, i t is easy to believe t h a t i n a certain manner H e p r o duced m e i n H i s image and likeness, a n d t h a t I conceive this likeness, i n
zi8
Descartes
w h i c h the idea o f G o d is contained, b y means o f the same f a c u l t y w i t h w h i c h I conceive o f myself; t h a t is, t h a t w h e n I reflect u p o n myself, I not only k n o w t h a t I a m a n imperfect t h i n g , one t h a t is incomplete a n d dependent u p o n s o m e t h i n g else and t h a t unceasingly reaches and aspires t o w a r d something better a n d greater t h a n w h a t I a m , b u t I also k n o w at the same time t h a t t h a t u p o n w h i c h I a m dependent possesses w i t h i n itself all those great things to w h i c h I aspire, the ideas of which I find within myself, and possesses t h e m n o t i n an indefinite m a n n e r or o n l y i n p o t e n t i a l i t y , b u t enjoys t h e m effectually, actually and unlimitedly, a n d t h a t therefore i t is G o d . A n d the entire force o f the a r g u m e n t w h i c h I have used here to p r o v e the existence of G o d consists i n m y recognizing t h a t i t w o u l d n o t be possible for m y n a t u r e to be the w a y i t is, t h a t is, for me to possess w i t h i n myself the idea o f a G o d , i f G o d d i d n o t t r u l y exist." But the key to Descartes' p r o o f is the significance w h i c h he a n d , together w i t h h i m , almost a l l seventeenth-century philosophers, give to the w o r d " i d e a . " A n idea is not merely s o m e t h i n g w h i c h occurs to m a n ; nor is i t s o m e t h i n g w h i c h m a n thinks a n d w h i c h m u s t coincide w i t h r e a l i t y . I t is r e a l i t y itself, seen. L'idée
est la chose même conçue,
Descartes says t e x t u a l l y . T h i s is the decisive p o i n t , t h e basis o f his t w o f o l d proof; at the same t i m e , i t is the most questionable p a r t o f the proof, b u t this is n o t the place for an extended investigation o f the problem involved. W e have seen the necessity for G o d and the reasons w h i c h Descartes adduces to prove H i s existence, and n o w one m a y w e l l ask w h a t is the ontological m e a n i n g o f t h a t strange a r g u m e n t a b o u t the " m a l i g n a n t genius. " T H E C O M M U N I C A T I O N B E T W E E N T H E SUBSTANCES.
I f we are deceived
b y some perverse p o w e r , i f o u r strongest self-evidence is m e r e l y error, this means that m y ideas have no t r u t h , t h a t they are merely " ideas, " corresponding to n o t h i n g outside o f themselves. T h e n I w o u l d be a prisoner w i t h i n myself, a t h i n k i n g substance w h i c h c o u l d n o t reach the other things—specifically, the extended substance w h i c h is the w o r l d . This p r o b l e m o f t r u t h and knowledge, stated i n Cartesian terms, is the p r o b l e m o f the c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances, w h i c h proves to be so difficult w h e n the s t a r t i n g p o i n t is m y ego, a t h i n k i n g t h i n g w h i c h is absolutely heterogeneous a n d different f r o m every extended t h i n g , even f r o m the extremely close r e a l i t y o f m y o w n body. " F r o m this I k n e w t h a t I was a substance the entire essence or n a t u r e of w h i c h is m e r e l y to t h i n k and w h i c h i n order to exist has no need o f any place n o r is dependent u p o n a n y m a t e r i a l t h i n g ; so t h a t
God this ego, t h a t is, the soul, t h r o u g h w h i c h I a m w h a t I a m , is completely distinct f r o m the b o d y " (Discourse on Method, Part I V ) . R E A S O N A N D B E I N G . Descartes has t a k e n such great care to e m p h a size the separateness or independence o f his reasoning soul t h a t n o w he cannot emerge i n t o the w o r l d . Despite a l l their self-evidence, the ideas of the res cogitans m a y be pure chimeras, lacking the least connection w i t h the res externa, w h i c h is separated f r o m t h e m b y a metaphysical g u l f : they m a y be clear and distinct fantasies. But, serious as this m a y be, i t is n o t the most serious p r o b l e m . T h i s impossibility o f the ego's t r u l y k n o w i n g the w o r l d has an effect n o t o n l y o n this knowledge o f the w o r l d b u t also o n the very nature o f the res cogitans. Reason is n o t the faculty for p r o d u c i n g ideas w i t h o u t t r u t h a n d w i t h o u t r e a l i t y ; i f i t is incapable o f g a i n i n g possession o f the w o r l d , i f i t does n o t p e r m i t the ego to envelop the entire extension o f the things t h r o u g h t h a t strange process called " k n o w i n g " and to possess the t r u t h of the things, i t does not deserve to be called reason. Therefore, i f m a n is to be i n r e a l i t y w h a t he is for Descartes—a t h i n k i n g t h i n g , a r a t i o n a l e n t i t y — h e must achieve a knowledge o f the things, he must transcend himself a n d be capable o f t r u t h . A n d i t is God w h o furnishes the certainty t h a t this is so; H e does n o t deceive m a n ; t h a t is, H e causes man's clear a n d dist i n c t ideas to be true. I n other words, G o d brings i t about t h a t w h e n man's ideas are completely clear a n d distinct, they are more than ideas a n d reflect the r e a l i t y of the things. G o d is the i n f i n i t e substance w h i c h is the basis for the being o f the extended substance and the t h i n k i n g substance. T h e t w o are separate a n d heterogeneous, b u t they have something i n c o m m o n : they b o t h have being, i n the same basic sense o f created being. A n d this c o m m o n r o o t w h i c h the t w o finite substances f i n d i n G o d is the basis for the possibility o f t h e i r coinciding, a n d , i n short, for the possibility o f t r u t h . G o d , the ontological basis o f the ego a n d o f the things, makes i t possible for m a n to know the w o r l d . O n l y f r o m this p o i n t of view do Descartes' proofs acquire t h e i r f u l l m e a n i n g . T h e ideas w h i c h I possess o f the things, he says, m a y very w e l l be no m o r e t h a n something I have produced, something dependent u p o n m y nature as a thinker, a n d n o t h i n g m o r e ; a n d therefore, these ideas m a y be true or false. N o t h i n g assures me t h a t w h a t they signify really exists, that they correspond to a n y t h i n g outside o f m y subjectivity, w h i c h is t h i n k i n g t h e m . O n the other h a n d , the idea o f G o d is one o f such perfection a n d so foreign to m y nature a n d m y possibilities t h a t i t cannot originate w i t h i n m e ; I receive i t f r o m w i t h o u t , a n d therefore f r o m another t h i n g w h i c h is not I , v i e w i n g a r e a l i t y w h i c h is different f r o m myself. Therefore, the idea o f G o d exerts a
220
Descartes
l i b e r a t i n g action u p o n m a n a n d makes h i m emerge f r o m his o w n self a n d come face to face w i t h the actual reality o f t h a t w h i c h is n o t himself. T H E P R O B L E M OF SUBSTANCE. Here, however, there arises a n e x t r e m e l y serious question w h i c h affects Descartes' o n t o l o g y at its r o o t . T h e ego a n d the w o r l d are t w o created, finite substances, a n d t h e i r ontological basis is G o d , t h e infinite substance; b u t n o w one must ask: W h a t is res, w h a t is substance ? Per substantiam, Descartes says (Prin¬ cipia,
I , 51),
nihil aliud intelligere possumus,
nulla alia re indigeat ad existendum
quam rem quae ita existit, ut
(By substance w e
can
understand
n o t h i n g other t h a n a t h i n g w h i c h exists i n such a m a n n e r t h a t i t has need o f n o other t h i n g for its existence). Thus, substance is defined b y independence; to be a substance means not to need another t h i n g i n order to exist; this involves a negative d e t e r m i n a t i o n w h i c h does n o t tell us positively w h a t i t is to be a substance. O n the other h a n d , Descartes observes t h a t , s t r i c t l y speaking, the o n l y independent entity is G o d , since the created entities have need o f H i m , a n d the w o r d " s u b s t a n c e " is n o t applied to G o d a n d to the created entities univocally, b u t o n l y analogically. I t is precisely here however, that the difficulty begins. T h e m i n d a n d the w o r l d are called substances because they need only G o d i n order to exist, Descartes says; thus, they possess a relative, a t t e n u a t e d independence. B u t Descartes adds t h a t we cannot k n o w substance alone, as p u r e substance, because i t does n o t affect us, a n d t h a t w e apprehend i t o n l y b y means o f some a t t r i b u t e , such as extension o r t h o u g h t . T h e n we m u s t ask a g a i n : W h a t is there i n c o m m o n between G o d and the created entities t h a t p e r m i t s us to call t h e m b o t h substances ? (
Descartes explains t h a t they are so called merely b y a n a l o g y ; b u t , as A r i s t o t l e showed i n the past, a n analogy requires a basis that must, n a t u r a l l y , be univocal. W h a t c a n be the c o m m o n basis for Descartes' analogical conception of substance? A c c o r d i n g to Descartes, the o n l y d e f i n i n g t r a i t of substance is independence. B u t this is also an analogical conception, since the independence o f the created substances is o n l y r e l a t i v e . T h e basis o f the p r e s u m p t i v e analogy is i n t u r n a n a l o g i c a l ; this amounts to saying t h a t for Descartes the n o t i o n o f substance is ambiguous. A c t u a l l y , Descartes does n o t have a sufficiently strict conc e p t i o n of being; he considers i t something so obvious t h a t he believes he can neglect to define i t precisely a n d can concern h i m s e l f d i r e c t l y w i t h entities. This is the basic defect of Descartes' metaphysics, the consequences of w h i c h affect a l l t h e t h o u g h t of the m o d e r n age. F r o m the foregoing we see t h a t before Descartes can concern h i m -
The
World
zzx
self w i t h the w o r l d , he must first consider G o d , a n d t h a t even t h o u g h he has renounced theology, there comes a time w h e n he must concern h i m s e l f intellectually w i t h G o d . B u t i t is certainly n o t necessary for h i m to construct a theology; he need o n l y prove the existence o f G o d , a n d this he does by means o f the ontological proof. T h e ontological a r g u m e n t allows the idealist, w h o h a d lost G o d a n d t h e n also the w o r l d , to recover the one a n d , consequently, the other. Cartesian p h i l o s o p h y a n d , as we shall see, a l l o f idealism u p to L e i b n i z are based o n the ontological argument.
4.
T H E WORLD
T H E " R E S E X T E N S A . " I n Descartes, the physical w o r l d is determ i n e d b y extension. T h e res infinita, w h i c h is G o d , is accompanied by t w o f i n i t e substances : the t h i n k i n g substance (man) a n d the extended substance (the w o r l d ) . These t w o spheres of reality do n o t have any c o n t a c t w i t h each other a n d are completely dissimilar. T h i s situation gives rise to the p r o b l e m o f the c o m m u n i c a t i o n between t h e m ; this d i l e m m a , w h i c h is a consequence o f idealism, becomes the chief p r o b l e m o f the seventeenth century. T h e v e r y fact of knowledge o r o f man's b e i n g already poses this question. H o w can I come to k n o w the w o r l d ? H o w can t h a t w h i c h is extended penetrate to me, w h o a m unextended a n d non-spatial ? W h a t is m o r e , i f m y body a n d I are t w o different realities w i t h o u t any possible i n t e r a c t i o n , how can I govern m y body a n d m a k e i t move? I t must be G o d , the ontological basis o f the t w o f i n i t e substances, w h o effects this impossible c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances. T h e p r o b l e m w h i c h Descartes poses has three possible solutions ; these are given b y Descartes himself (and m o r e clearly by M a l e b r a n c h e ) a n d b y Spinoza a n d L e i b n i z . T h e w o r l d is pure extension. E n e r g y is not a clear idea to Descartes a n d so he does n o t consider i t . Cartesian physics is g e o m e t r y ; L e i b n i z w i l l correct this n o t i o n b y p l a c i n g the concept of energy i n the foreg r o u n d a n d by changing static physics i n t o dynamics. Descartes' and L e i b n i z ' t w o great m a t h e m a t i c a l discoveries—analytical geometry a n d the infinitesimal calculus—correspond to these t w o conceptions. A n a l y t i c a l geometry consists o f the a p p l i c a t i o n o f analysis, o f operat i o n a l calculus, to g e o m e t r y — a n d , therefore, i n Descartes, to physical r e a l i t y itself; the infinitesimal calculus makes possible the calculation o f v a r i a t i o n s and the development o f dynamics. M a t t e r a n d space are one a n d the same; spatiality is the p r i n c i p a l q u a l i t y o f m a t t e r . T h e w o r l d c o u l d be explained b y means o f a series o f w h i r l w i n d motions, a n d after being created c o u l d develop i n a p u r e l y mechanical fashion.
222
Descartes
T h i s is a n echo o f the theory t h a t God's maintenance o f t h e w o r l d — continuous creation—is unnecessary, a n d that, once created, the w o r l d is self-sufficient. B I O L O G Y . Descartes applies this mechanistic theory to a l l o f physics, to his studies i n the fields o f optics a n d meteorology, a n d even to biology. F o r h i m , animals are s i m p l y automatic machines, res externa. Since they are the w o r k o f God's hands, they are, o f course, absolutely perfect machines, b u t they have n o t h i n g i n c o m m o n w i t h t h e s p i r i t u a l a n d t h i n k i n g substance w h i c h is m a n . I n m a n , the p i n e a l b o d y — t h e o n l y o r g a n i n the area o f the b r a i n w h i c h occurs singly a n d f u r t h e r m o r e one whose f u n c t i o n is u n k n o w n — i s the p o i n t at w h i c h the soul a n d the b o d y can affect one another. F r o m the p i n e a l b o d y the soul directs the a c t i v i t y of the animal spirits, a n d vice versa. L a t e r Descartes realized the impossibility o f e x p l a i n i n g the c o m m u n i c a t i o n w h i c h obviously takes place. I n his Treatise on the Passions Descartes begins a series o f attempts to explain the mechanism o f the h u m a n psyche by means o f a c o m b i n a t i o n o f a few f u n d a m e n t a l operations o f the m i n d . T h i s concludes a basic sketch o f Descartes' theory of the w o r l d .
5.
RATIONALISM A N D IDEALISM
Descartes bases his speculation o n the c r i t e r i o n o f self-evidence. T h i s self-evidence does n o t relate either to perception or t o the senses w h i c h f r e q u e n t l y deceive us, b u t to the clearness a n d distinctness o f ideas; i t is the self-evidence of reason. Therefore, Descartes' m e t h o d is r a t i o n a l i s m . M a n ' s only v a l i d c r i t e r i o n is reason, w h i c h is c o m m o n to a l l m e n . M a n is a t h i n k i n g substance, raison; and reason i s one o f the roots o f the a p r i o r i science o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y . Cartesian r a t i o n a l i s m is also the cause o f the equally a p r i o r i a n d a n t i h i s t o r i c a l spirit t h a t shapes the entire f o l l o w i n g century a n d c u l m i n a t e s i n d r a m a t i c fashion i n the French R e v o l u t i o n . O n the other h a n d , Descartes' m e t h o d is also idealist. H o w can this be ? T h e thesis o f idealism is i n d i r e c t opposition to m e t a p h y s i c a l realism. As represented i n ancient Greece and the M i d d l e Ages, realism is the belief that the things have a being of t h e i r o w n , that the ego exists merely as one t h i n g a m o n g others, a n d t h a t t r u e reality consists o f the things, res. T o be means to be (or exist) separately, to have a being that is independent of me. I d e a l i s m , o n the contrary, is t h e belief t h a t the ego has no sure knowledge o f a n y t h i n g other t h a n itself (the cogito); t h a t I k n o w the things only w h i l e I a m seeing t h e m , t o u c h i n g t h e m , t h i n k i n g o f t h e m , desiring t h e m , a n d so forth. (The w o r d cogitatio does not m e a n o n l y thought; i t also includes a l l mental processes.) I n other
Rationalism
and Idealism
223
w o r d s , I know the things o n l y w h i l e I have dealings w i t h t h e m and witness t h e m . I do not a n d cannot k n o w w h a t the things are like w h e n they are apart f r o m m e — n o t even i f they exist i n m e , since I k n o w n o t h i n g o f t h e m w i t h o u t b e i n g present. T h a t is, the things appear as existing or being/or me; thus, they are provisionally ideas o f m i n e and the r e a l i t y that corresponds to t h e m is a n ideal r e a l i t y . T h e being o f things is based on the ego, a n d resembles ideas on the p a r t o f the ego: this is idealism. Since i n Descartes' t h o u g h t reason is o f course no longer the p o i n t i n w h i c h m a n links himself w i t h the supreme reality o f G o d b u t rather s o m e t h i n g exclusively man's o w n , something restricted to his subject i v i t y , rationalism is necessarily changed i n t o i d e a l i s m ; thus later o n i t becomes necessary for G o d to save this subjectivism a n d assure the transcendency o f the t h i n k i n g subject. Descartes bases his philosophy o n these t w o principles o f rationalism a n d idealism, a n d w i t h rare exceptions, f r o m his t i m e u n t i l o u r o w n , philosophy is b o t h o f these things. O n l y i n recent years has metaphysics reached conclusions w h i c h , although d e r i v i n g f r o m the great p a r t i a l truths that the t w o Cartesian principles c o n t a i n , correct t h e element of error t h a t affects t h e m . Recent metaphysics on the one h a n d points out that the ego is i n t u r n essentially dependent on the things i t encounters constantly d u r i n g its life; a n d o n the other h a n d transforms the exclusively speculative a n d m a t h e m a t i c a l conception o f reason. Ortega took a decisive step i n this d i r e c t i o n w i t h his metaphysics o f v i t a l reason. * * Cf. "Los dos cartesianismos" in Ensayos de Uoria [Obras, I V ] .
Cartesianism
in
France
Descartes shapes a l l the p h i l o s o p h y o f the seventeenth century on the C o n t i n e n t . H i s influence is seen n o t o n l y i n his p u p i l s a n d i m m e diate followers, b u t also i n the independent thinkers a n d even the theologians Pascal, Fénelon a n d Bossuet. I n France i t is especially apparent i n M a l e b r a n c h e , a n d outside o f France i n the g r e a t figures o f Spinoza a n d L e i b n i z . L e t us see h o w this philosophy develops. i.
MALEBRANCHE
Nicolas de Malebranche was b o r n o f a p r o m i n e n t f a m i l y i n Paris i n 1638 a n d d i e d i n 1715. As he was always i n very poor h e a l t h he endured great suffering a n d had to be extremely cautious. H e s t u d i e d p h i losophy at the Collège de l a M a r c h e , b u t felt deceived, j u s t as Descartes h a d at L a Flèche; later he studied theology at the Sor¬ bonne, b u t the intellectual methods there d i d not satisfy h i m either. I n 1660 he j o i n e d the Congregation o f the O r a t o r y , an o r g a n i z a t i o n t h a t has given France a great m a n y m e n o f superior m e n t a l i t y , f r o m M a l e b r a n c h e himself to F a t h e r G r a t r y i n the n i n e t e e n t h century. Fontenelle r e m a r k e d t h a t M a l e b r a n c h e h a d been raised t o the priesthood " b y n a t u r e and grace." T h e members o f the C o n g r e g a t i o n h a d great i n t e l l e c t u a l restlessness a n d studied Plato and St. A u g u s t i n e at the same t i m e t h a t they investigated Descartes' philosophy. I n 1664, M a l e b r a n c h e b o u g h t a copy o f Descartes' Traité de l'homme i n a bookstore ; i t m a d e a tremendous impression o n h i m and he discovered i n i t the m e t h o d w h i c h he had always secretly looked and l o n g e d for. F r o m 224
Malebranche
t h a t t i m e o n his p r e d i l e c t i o n for philosophy was decided, a n d he began to study Descartes' p h i l o s o p h y seriously. H e completed his education b y s t u d y i n g the w o r k o f St. Augustine i n p a r t i c u l a r a n d also that o f A r n o l d Geulincx, a t h i n k e r f r o m the Netherlands as w e l l as that o f others w h o were concerned w i t h advancing the progress o f n a t u r a l science : Francis Bacon, Hobbes, Gassendi, a n d so o n . T e n years later M a l e b r a n c h e began his l i t e r a r y p r o d u c t i o n . A t the same t i m e he established cordial and/or dissentious relationships w i t h most of the great contemporary figures: A r n a u l d , Fénelon, Bossuet, L e i b n i z , L o c k e , Berkeley. M a l e b r a n c h e was very m u c h d r a w n to the quiet life a n d to solitary m e d i t a t i o n , a n d his life i n the bosom of the c o m m u n i t y of the O r a t o r y was as r e t i r i n g a n d silent as he could make i t . H e died at the age o f seventy-seven, f u l l o f t r a n q u i l l i t y a n d p r o f o u n d religious feeling. WORKS.
M a l e b r a n c h e ' s p r i n c i p a l w o r k is the Recherche de la vérité.
A f t e r w a r d he published the Conversations chrétiennes, a n d later the Méditations chrétiennes. S t i l l l a t e r he w r o t e the
Traité de la nature et de la
grâce, a w o r k that occasioned a violent controversy a n d was included i n the I n d e x b y the R o m a n I n q u i s i t i o n . H e also w r o t e a very i m p o r t a n t dialogue called Entretiens sur la métaphysique et sur la religion, and a Traité de morale. These are the most i m p o r t a n t items o f Malebranche's philosophie p r o d u c t i o n . OCCASIONALISM. T h e core o f Malebranche's philosophy is his t h e o r y o f occasionalism, w h i c h h a d been begun b y A r n o l d Geulincx, a professor at L o u v a i n a n d later, after his conversion to Calvinism, at L e i d e n . Malebranche's p r o b l e m , w h i c h arises f r o m the Cartesian s i t u a t i o n , is t h a t o f the transcendency o f the t h i n k i n g subject and, i n general, o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances. Descartes h a d already attempted to m a k e allowance o f a sort for the interaction between the substances b y reducing i t to the t i n y motions and changes o f the pineal body. M a l e b r a n c h e affirms textually t h a t there is n o t , nor can there be, any c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the m i n d a n d corporeal bodies. " I t is self-evident t h a t bodies are n o t visible i n themselves, that they cannot act u p o n our spirit or manifest themselves to i t " (Recherche de la vérité, explanation X ) . D i r e c t knowledge of the w o r l d is therefore absolutely impossible; however, there is something that makes knowledge o f the w o r l d possible: God has w i t h i n H i m s e l f the ideas o f a l l the created entities ; this is p a r t o f the e x p l a n a t i o n ; f u r t h e r m o r e , " G o d is very closely u n i t e d to our souls b y His presence, so t h a t i t can be said t h a t H e is the site o f spirits, j u s t as space is i n a sense the site o f bodies. Given these t w o things, i t is certain t h a t the spirit can see w h a t there is i n G o d t h a t manifests the
22Ô
Cartesianism
in
France
created beings, since this is v e r y s p i r i t u a l , v e r y i n t e l l i g i b l e a n d v e r y m u c h present t o the s p i r i t . " A n d a few pages f u r t h e r o n , M a l e b r a n c h e adds : " I f we d i d n o t see G o d i n some m a n n e r , we w o u l d n o t see anyt h i n g " (Recherche de la vérité, book I I I , p a r t 2, chapter V I ) . T h e d i f f i c u l t y is f o u n d i n the phrase " i n some m a n n e r . " G o d is k n o w n i n d i r e c t l y ; H e is reflected i n the created things, as i n a m i r r o r ; according t o t h e text o f St. Paul ( R o m a n s 1:20) : Invisibilia Dei. . .per ea quae facta sunt intellecta conspiciuntur ( T h e invisible things o f h i m . . .
are clearly seen, being understood b y the things t h a t are m a d e ) . M a l e b r a n c h e strives to r e t a i n a correct a n d admissible i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of the vision o f G o d , b u t he does n o t succeed i n a v o i d i n g e r r o r . H e freq u e n t l y inverts the terms o f the Paulist f o r m u l a a n d affirms t h e direct knowledge o f G o d a n d o f the things i n H i m . T h i s error has h a d repercussions, especially on A n t o n i o R o s m i n i - S e r b a t i a n d V i n c e n z o G i o b e r t i , I t a l i a n " ontologists " o f the n i n e t e e n t h century. I t is G o d w h o makes i t possible for m e to k n o w the inaccessible things. H i s s p i r i t u a l i t y carries w i t h i n i t the ideas o f t h e c o r p o r e a l things created b y H i m . A l l things have i n c o m m o n the fact t h a t they are created beings. Being is present i n the things a n d i n a sense unifies t h e m , i n spite o f their basic diversity. T h i s complete o n t o l o g i c a l l i n k is w h a t p e r m i t s us to speak m e a n i n g f u l l y oîreason. F r o m the c o n d i t i o n o f a subjectivity w i t h o u t reference to r e a l i t y , one w o u l d n o t be able t o say t h a t r e a l i t y existed. T h e things are extended a n d corporeal, foreign to m y s p i r i t ; b u t God's ideas, the models a c c o r d i n g to w h i c h the things are created—a u n i o n of A u g u s t i n i a n i s m a n d Cartesianism—are spiritual, adapted to the t h i n k i n g being, a n d G o d is the site o f the spirits. M a n partakes o f G o d , a n d through Him o f the things, a n d thus the m e t a physical g u l f is b r i d g e d . T h e r e is n o d i r e c t i n t e r a c t i o n between the substances; the h a r m o n y between t h e m is achieved b y G o d ; this is the theory o f the occasional causes : I do n o t perceive the things ; rather, on the occasion o f a movement o f the res externa, G o d arouses i n me a certain idea ; o n the occasion of a v o l i t i o n o n m y p a r t , G o d moves the extended b o d y t h a t is m y a r m . W h a t is decisive is the h u m a n spirit's relationship w i t h G o d , and w i t h the things o n l y t h r o u g h h i m . M a l e branche is f u l l y aware o f this: " T h e r e is no one w h o does n o t agree that a l l m e n are capable o f k n o w i n g t r u t h ; a n d even t h e least enlightened philosophers agree t h a t m a n partakes o f a c e r t a i n reason w h i c h they d o n o t specify. Therefore, they define m a n as animal RATiONis particeps : for there is no one w h o does not k n o w , at least confusedly, t h a t the essential characteristic o f m a n consists i n the necessary u n i o n t h a t he has w i t h universal r e a s o n " (Recherche de la vérité, e x p l a n a t i o n X ) .
The Religious
Thinkers
22J
Malebranche's w o r d s are so clear a n d m e a n i n g f u l t h a t I prefer to quote t h e m t e x t u a l l y , r a t h e r t h a n c o m m e n t u p o n t h e m . I n God we see a l l the things ; this is the necessary c o n d i t i o n for a l l knowledge a n d a l l t r u t h . M a l e b r a n c h e takes l i t e r a l l y a n d s t r i c t l y St. John's words i n the f o u r t h Gospel : G o d
is lux vera quae illuminât omnem hominem venientem in
hunc mundum (the T r u e L i g h t , w h i c h l i g h t e t h every m a n that cometh i n t o the w o r l d ) . Therefore, G o d is absolutely necessary; a l t h o u g h the t o t a l i t y o f the essence o f G o d is not k n o w n , i t is necessary to k n o w at least that H e exists. Malebranche's philosophy also requires p r o o f o f the existence o f G o d , a n d finds its basis i n this. M a l e b r a n c h e carries Cartesianism to its u l t i m a t e consequences i n the d i r e c t i o n indicated by its founder. O t h e r philosophers w i l l begin at the same p o i n t b u t w i l l follow different paths.
2.
T H E RELIGIOUS THINKERS
I n the seventeenth c e n t u r y and i n the first years o f the eighteenth there is i n France a series o f Catholic thinkers, m o s t l y theologians a n d even mystics, w h o are p r o f o u n d l y influenced b y Cartesian philosophy. There thus originates a n extremely f r u i t f u l i n t e l l e c t u a l current t h a t characterizes F r e n c h s p i r i t u a l life for a c e n t u r y a n d conditions the subsequent destiny o f F r e n c h philosophy. I n other countries theological t h o u g h t remains attached to the m e n t a l a n d even expository forms of Scholasticism, w h i l e m o d e r n philosophy follows a separate course w i t h o u t even t o u c h i n g t h e m . T h e French religious thinkers follow i n the medieval t r a d i t i o n , w h i c h is composed of t w o p r i n c i p a l p a r t s — t h e philosophy o f St. Augustine a n d t h a t o f St. T h o m a s ; b u t they are influenced b y Cartesianism, especially i n regard to Descartes' m e t h o d , a n d f r o m this synthesis there arises a new f o r m o f t h o u g h t w h i c h could perhaps be called " Cartesian t h e o l o g y " or even modern theology. T h e general architecture o f T h o m i s m is m a i n t a i n e d over a base of August i n i a n presuppositions b u t , at the same t i m e , Descartes' philosophic discoveries are u t i l i z e d , as are his methods o f investigation and l i t e r a r y exposition. I n this w a y the Hellenic a n d m e d i e v a l traditions are salvaged a n d are studied i n the l i g h t of m o d e r n t h o u g h t ; thus i n France Catholic t h o u g h t retains a v i t a l i t y that i t soon loses i n other places. O n the other h a n d , these theologians constantly t o u c h o n philosophic problems, a n d f r e q u e n t l y they b r i n g to bear o n philosophy the precision and h i g h standards w h i c h theology has always c o n t r i b u t e d to metaphysical t h o u g h t . T H E JANSENISTS. Cornells Jansen or Jansenius, bishop o f Ypres, w h o was closely connected w i t h the A b b é de S a i n t - C y r a n , t r i e d to
228
Cartesianism
in France
create a theological i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f h u m a n n a t u r e a n d grace based o n the t h o u g h t o f St. Augustine a n d the Fathers o f the C h u r c h . I n 1640, shortly after the author's death, Jansen's Augustinus was p u b lished; i t was c o n d e m n e d three years later. T h e Jansenist s p i r i t i n f i l t r a t e d i n p a r t i c u l a r the abbey o f P o r t - R o y a l , w h i c h was r u n b y M o t h e r A n g é l i q u e A r n a u l d . I n France, t h e c o n d e m n a t i o n o f the Augustinus a n d the condensation o f Jansenist d o c t r i n e i n t o five p r o p o sitions, w h i c h w e r e also condemned, l e d t o a l o n g a n d l i v e l y c o n t r o versy, the details o f w h i c h do n o t p e r t a i n t o this discussion. I n brief, the Jansenists opposed the m o r a l casuistry o f t h e Jesuits, w h o m they accused o f l a x i t y . T h e most i m p o r t a n t t h i n k e r s o f the P o r t - R o y a l g r o u p were A n t o i n e A r n a u l d (1612-1694) a n d Pierre N i c o l e (1625¬ 1695). A p a r t f r o m t h e i r theological w o r k s , they are together t h e authors o f the famous book e n t i t l e d La logique ou Vart depenser, k n o w n b y the t i t l e o f Logic of
Port-Royal.
PASCAL. Blaise Pascal (1623-1662), a b r i l l i a n t m a t h e m a t i c i a n o f exceptional p r e c o c i t y a n d a mystic a n d polemicist w i t h a p r o f o u n d a n d passionately religious spirit, m a i n t a i n e d close ties w i t h the recluses o f P o r t - R o y a l . A p a r t f r o m his physical a n d m a t h e m a t i c a l treatises, Pascal w r o t e the Lettres a un Provincial or Lettresprovinciales, b y means o f w h i c h he took p a r t i n the anti-Jesuit polemics, a n d above a l l , his Pensées sur la religion, a f r a g m e n t a r y w o r k o f e x t r a o r d i n a r y religious a n d philosophic interest; a c t u a l l y i t consists o f o n l y r a n d o m notes for a book t h a t was never w r i t t e n . Seemingly, Pascal is opposed to Cartesianism, to its confidence i n reason, a n d is almost a skeptic. B u t i n r e a l i t y Pascal is i n large measure Cartesian, even w h e n he opposes Descartes. P r i m a r i l y he is rigorously m o t i v a t e d b y C h r i s t i a n presuppositions, a n d his t h o u g h t evolves f r o m t h e m . I f on the one h a n d Pascal, like Descartes, apprehends m a n i n his t h i n k i n g d i m e n s i o n , o n the other h a n d he is acutely aware o f m a n ' s f r a i l t y , dependence a n d misery: m a n is a t h i n k i n g reed (un roseaupensant). A n d one rises f r o m this misery o f m a n separated f r o m G o d to the greatness o f m a n together w i t h G o d , w h o is great because he recognizes his dependence a n d can have knowledge o f the D e i t y . Pascal's a n t h r o p o l o g y is o f v e r y great interest. W i t h r e g a r d t o t h e p r o b l e m o f Pascal's a t t i t u d e t o w a r d reason, i t is necessary to emphasize t h a t he distinguishes between w h a t he calls raison—which is generally understood to m e a n reasoning p o w e r o r s y l l o g i s m — a n d w h a t he calls cceur, heart. " T h e h e a r t , " he says, " h a s its reasons o f w h i c h reason knows n o t h i n g . " A n d he adds, " W e k n o w t r u t h not o n l y t h r o u g h reason, b u t also t h r o u g h the h e a r t ; w e k n o w the first principles b y the latter way, a n d i n v a i n does reasoning, w h i c h
The
Religious
Thinkers
zzg
does n o t p a r t a k e o f t h e m , t r y to discredit t h e m . . . . O u r knowledge o f the first principles is as f i r m as any knowledge t h a t reasoning furnishes us. A n d i t is o n knowledge obtained t h r o u g h the heart a n d the i n s t i n c t t h a t reason must depend a n d o n w h i c h i t m u s t base a l l its discourse. " Cœur has n o t h i n g to d o w i t h sentiment; r a t h e r , for Pascal i t is a f a c u l t y for o b t a i n i n g knowledge of the p r i n c i p a l t r u t h s w h i c h are the basis for reasoning. Pascal seeks G o d , b u t since he is basically a religious m a n , he wants to seek G o d i n C h r i s t , a n d n o t o n l y i n m e r e reason; he writes these words, w h i c h echo A u g u s t i n i a n t h o u g h t : " T r u t h itself is m a d e a n i d o l . B u t t r u t h separated f r o m c h a r i t y is n o t G o d ; i t is H i s image, a n i d o l w h i c h one need n o t love o r w o r s h i p . " A n d he sums u p his w h o l e philosophic attitude i n a phrase w h i c h illuminates its t r u e m e a n i n g : " T w o excesses: to exclude reason; to a d m i t n o t h i n g but reason." BOSSUET. O n e o f the major figures o f t h a t theological c u r r e n t i n fluenced b y Descartes' philosophy was Jacques Bénigne Bossuet (1627-1704), bishop o f M e a u x . Bossuet was a n i m p o r t a n t personality of his day, a n d the soul o f the C h u r c h i n France for h a l f a century. H e was a great religious orator, historian, t h e o l o g i a n a n d philosopher. I n association w i t h L e i b n i z , he was very active i n the trente negotiations aimed at r e c o n c i l i n g the Protestant a n d C a t h o l i c Churches; i n this c o n n e c t i o n , he w r o t e his History of the Variations in the Protestant Churches.
His most significant philosophical works are the treatise De la connaissance de Dieu et de soi-même a n d the Discours sur l'histoire universelle, a t r u e
philosophy o f h i s t o r y w h i c h relates to St. Augustine's City of God a n d w h i c h , i n a c e r t a i n m a n n e r , prepares the w a y for the w o r k o f V i c o , H e r d e r a n d especially Hegel. F É N E L O N . A n o t h e r great ecclesiastical figure i n France is Fénelon (1651-1715), the A r c h b i s h o p o f C a m b r a i . Fénelon engaged i n a c o n troversy w i t h Bossuet over quietism, the heresy w h i c h was i n t r o d u c e d b y the S p a n i a r d M i g u e l de M o l i n o s , a u t h o r o f the Guia espiritual, a n d was spread a b r o a d i n France by M a d a m e G u y o n . C e r t a i n propositions i n Fénelon's Histoire des maximes des saints were condemned ; as a faithful C h r i s t i a n , he retracted his error. H i s most interesting p h i l o sophical w o r k is the Traité de l'existence de Dieu.
I n a c e r t a i n sense, Fénelon represents a c o n t i n u a t i o n o f Bossuet's t h o u g h t , b u t he carries i t even further. N o t o n l y does he adopt a series of Descartes' discoveries, such as his d u a l i s m a n d the conception o f m a n as a t h i n k i n g e n t i t y ; he also makes Descartes' m e t h o d his o w n : universal d o u b t . S t a r t i n g w i t h the i n d u b i t a b l e self-evidence o f the ego, he attempts to reconstruct reality a n d to a r r i v e at G o d . T h e second
2JO
Cartesianism
in
France
p a r t o f his treatise is u n a d u l t e r a t e d Cartesianism. B u t whereas Descartes is purely a n d s i m p l y a philosopher, Fenelon is above a l l a theol o g i a n ; i n the last analysis, therefore, the o r i e n t a t i o n o f his t h o u g h t is v e r y different.
Spinoza L I F E A N D W O R K S . Baruch de Spinoza was b o r n i n A m s t e r d a m i n 1632. H e came f r o m a family o f Spanish Jews w h o years before h a d e m i g r a t e d to P o r t u g a l and afterward to the Netherlands. H i s religious opinions caused his expulsion f r o m the synagogue, a n d f r o m t h a t t i m e o n he was m o r e closely associated w i t h C h r i s t i a n circles, a l t h o u g h he d i d n o t profess Christianity. H e L a t i n i z e d his given n a m e B a r u c h (blessed), using the f o r m Benedictus. H i s life was spent i n H o l l a n d , especially i n the c i t y o f his b i r t h a n d i n T h e H a g u e ; he was always poor a n d w i t h d r a w n , a n d he earned his l i v i n g b y polishing lenses. Spinoza (or perhaps he m i g h t be called b y the Spanish f o r m o f his n a m e , Espinosa, w h i c h his f a m i l y p r o b a b l y used o r i g i n a l l y ) was always sickly a n d felt a great need o f independence. W h e n offered a professorship at the U n i v e r s i t y o f H e i d e l b e r g , he refused i n o r d e r n o t to compromise his freedom. Spinoza was a loyal friend o f J a n de W i t t . H e was still y o u n g when he d i e d i n 1677.
H i s w r i t i n g s , w i t h the exception o f a few works i n D u t c h , are almost a l l i n L a t i n . T h e most i m p o r t a n t w o r k s are the Tractatus de intellects
emendatione, the Brief Treatise on God, Man and His Happiness (in D u t c h ) , the Tractatus theologico-politicus, the Tractatus politics (an exposition o f Descartes' Principia), the Cogitata metaphysica a n d , above a l l , his masterw o r k , p u b l i s h e d after his death: the Ethica ordine geometrico demonstrata. T h i s w o r k follows the manner o f exposition customary i n books o n mathematics, w i t h axioms, definitions, propositions w i t h t h e i r proofs, scholia a n d corollaries. I t is an example o f the rationalistic a n d m a t h e m a t i c a l tendencies carried to their extreme a n d b y this t i m e affecting even the e x t e r n a l f o r m o f philosophy.
Spinoza
2J2 i.
METAPHYSICS
T H E P O I N T O F D E P A R T U R E . Spinoza appears as the heir o f several philosophical traditions. First o f a l l a n d most d i r e c t l y , he follows i n the p a t h recently established b y Descartes; i n a d d i t i o n , he has ties w i t h Scholasticism, p a r t i c u l a r l y w i t h Scotism a n d O c c a m i s m ; he has studied the w o r k o f Suarez. H e also has contact w i t h Jewish sources: first, w i t h the Bible a n d the T a l m u d ; secondly, w i t h medieval Jewish philosophers, p r i n c i p a l l y M a i m o n i d e s and those o f the C a b b a l a . A n o t h e r influence should be n o t e d : the Greek t r a d i t i o n , especially Stoicism. A n d , o f course, there is the influence o f the n a t u r a l science o f Spinoza's day a n d the philosophy o f G i o r d a n o B r u n o , as w e l l as H o b b e s ' theories of the State a n d politics. These are the p r i n c i p a l roots o f Spinoza's t h o u g h t ; f r o m t h e m he derives his u n i q u e p h i l o sophical personality w i t h i n seventeenth-century metaphysics. S U B S T A N C E . Spinoza adopts Descartes' situation as his starting p o i n t . For Descartes, substance was understood as t h a t w h i c h has need o f n o t h i n g else i n order to exist; strictly speaking, o n l y G o d c o u l d be substance. A f t e r w a r d Descartes came across other substances w h i c h d i d n o t need other creatures i n order to exist, a l t h o u g h they d i d need G o d ; these were the res cogitans a n d the res extensa. Spinoza accepts this q u i t e rigorously, and defines substance i n this w a y : Per substantiam
intelligo id quod in se est et perse concipitur ; hoc est, id cujus conceptus non indiget conceptu alterius rei, a quo formari debeat ( " B y substance I understand t h a t w h i c h exists i n itself a n d is conceived t h r o u g h itself; t h a t is, t h a t t h i n g the concept of w h i c h does not have need o f the concept o f any other t h i n g , by w h i c h i t must be f o r m e d " ) . Therefore, Spinoza w i l l o n l y recognize a single substance. W h a t , then, are a l l the other things ? T h e y are not substances, b u t attributes; an a t t r i b u t e is t h a t w h i c h the m i n d perceives i n substance as a constituent o f its essence. T h e r e are a n i n f i n i t e n u m b e r o f attributes, b u t the intellect knows o n l y t w o : cogitatio a n d extensio, t h o u g h t a n d extension, t h a t is, Descartes' res cogitans a n d res extensa, n o w demoted i n the ontological h i e r a r c h y ; they are no longer substances, b u t merely attributes o f the one substance. T h e individual things—which Descartes h a d already deprived o f t h e i r t r a d i t i o n a l nature as p a r t o f substance, reserving the name o f substance for his t w o res—are modes o f substance, t h a t is, affections o f substance; they are t h a t w h i c h exists i n some other t h i n g a n d is conceived through some other t h i n g . These modes affect substance according to its different attributes. G O D . Spinoza defines G o d as the absolutely infinite e n t i t y , t h a t is, the
Metaphysics substance w h i c h consists o f i n f i n i t e attributes, each one o f w h i c h expresses a n eternal a n d i n f i n i t e essence. T h i s e n t i t y coincides w i t h the single possible substance. G o d is the necessary e n t i t y , the e n t i t y a se, a n d is synonymous w i t h substance ; the attributes o f substance are the i n f i n i t e attributes o f G o d . A n d this G o d o f Spinoza's, w h o is equated w i t h substance, is nature. Deus sive natura (God, or n a t u r e ) , Spinoza says. Substance—or G o d — i s everything that exists, a n d a l l the things are affections o f H i m . Therefore, H e is nature i n a double sense. I n one sense, a l l things proceed f r o m G o d a n d G o d is the o r i g i n o f a l l things; this is w h a t Spinoza calls natura naturans. B u t , o n the other h a n d , G o d does n o t create a n y t h i n g w h i c h is different f r o m Himself, so t h a t H e is n a t u r e i n another sense : H e is the emerging, b u d d i n g things t h e m selves; this is w h a t Spinoza calls natura naturata. T h u s , Spinoza's system is pantheistic. Spinoza's G o d is expressed t h r o u g h the i n d i v i d u a l things i n the t w o basic attributes w h i c h m a n knows : t h o u g h t a n d extension. T h u s , this is a reappearance o f Descartes' o u t l i n e , b u t w i t h a n essential change: o f Descartes' three substances, one infinite and t w o finite, o n l y the first is s t i l l characterized as substance, w h i l e the other t w o are n o w a t t r i butes o f substance. C O M M U N I C A T I O N B E T W E E N T H E S U B S T A N C E S . W e have seen h o w the p r o b l e m o f the c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances made its appearance w i t h i n Descartes' metaphysics, a n d we have observed the first s o l u t i o n to i t as p r o v i d e d b y occasionalism. M a l e b r a n c h e denies t h a t there is any actual c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances. Spinoza's doctrine is m u c h m o r e r a d i c a l : he f r a n k l y a n d openly denies a l l p l u r a l i t y o f substance. T h e r e is o n l y one substance, w i t h t w o a t t r i butes ; there can be no communication, b u t only correspondence. T h e r e is a strict parallelism between the t w o attributes o f the single substance w h i c h m a n knows, extension a n d t h o u g h t , and therefore, between the m i n d a n d corporeal things : Ordo et connexio idearum idem est, ac ordo et connexio rerum (The order a n d connection o f ideas are the same as the order a n d connection o f the t h i n g s ) . A n d i t is precisely b y his d e p r i v i n g extension a n d thought ( i n short, the world'm. its broadest sense) o f their s t a n d i n g as substances, w h i c h they still retained for Descartes, and r e d u c i n g t h e m to mere attributes o f the single substance, t h a t Spinoza is compelled to identify substance w i t h God, o n the one h a n d , and w i t h n a t u r e , on the other : Deus sive substantia sive natura ( G o d , or substance, or n a t u r e ) . I t is at this p o i n t that Spinoza's p a n t h e i s m arises. H i s p h i l o s o p h y is scarcely concerned w i t h a n y t h i n g else b u t G o d , b u t a l t h o u g h this w o u l d seem to be a new theology, i t is o n l y the metaphysical study o f substance a n d , at the same t i m e , the r a t i o n a l
Spinoza consideration o f nature, understood as Descartes unders t o o d i t , geometrically. I n Spinoza's system, as i n a l l o t h e r seventeenth-century systems, i t is necessary to establish the existence o f G o d , b u t here i n a perhaps even m o r e extreme sense, since i t is necessary to a t t r i b u t e to nature itself n o t o n l y the standing o f substance b u t godhood as w e l l . F o r Spinoza, being does not m e a n being that is created by God, b u t s i m p l y
God's being. 2.
ETHICS
T H E P L A N O F T H E " E T H I C S . " Spinoza's metaphysics culminates i n his ethics. Therefore, his m a j o r w o r k , i n w h i c h he expounds the general content o f his philosophy, bears that title. T h e Ethics (Ethica ordine geométrico demonstrata) is d i v i d e d i n t o five parts: I . O f G o d ; I I . O f the N a t u r e a n d O r i g i n o f the M i n d ; I I I . O f the O r i g i n a n d N a t u r e o f the Passions; I V . O f H u m a n Bondage, or O f the Force o f the Passions; a n d V . O f the Power o f the Intellect, o r O f H u m a n F r e e d o m . First o f a l l , therefore, he expounds his o n t o l o g y : the theory o f G o d , or substance. Secondly, he studies the structure o f the m i n d a n d takes u p the p r o b l e m o f knowledge. T h e n he enumerates a n d defines the passions, w h i c h he interprets i n a naturalistic a n d geometrical fashion: he wishes to speak a b o u t h u m a n actions a n d drives " as i f discussing lines, planes or solid b o d i e s . " Lastly, he expounds his theory o f h u m a n slavery or freedom, depending o n w h e t h e r man's passions o r his reason p r e v a i l ; i t is i n these final sections, i n w h i c h he states his ethical p r o b l e m p r o p e r , t h a t the meaning o f his whole p h i losophy is s u m m e d u p .
M A N . F o r Spinoza, everything is n a t u r e ; i t makes no sense to contrast something else, such as spirit, w i t h nature. M a n is cogitatio, t h o u g h t , b u t this thought is j u s t as m u c h nature as a stone is. M a n is a mode o f substance, a mere m o d i f i c a t i o n o f G o d i n the t w o attributes o f extension a n d t h o u g h t ; i n this consists the u n i q u e s t a n d i n g o f m a n , w h o has a b o d y and a soul; the soul is the idea o f the b o d y . A n d j u s t as there is a n exact correspondence between ideas a n d things, so there is a strict parallelism between the soul a n d the body. E v e r y t h i n g t h a t happens to or affects m a n , a n d especially his o w n passions, is n a t u r a l a n d follows the necessary course o f nature. For Spinoza, " t h a t t h i n g is called free w h i c h exists only b y necessity o f its nature a n d determines its actions b y i t s e l f " ; this is a concept o f freedom w h i c h allows freedom o n l y to G o d . Spinoza is a d e t e r m i n i s t : " M a n cannot be considered as a n e m p i r e w i t h i n another e m p i r e . " Therefore, m a n is n o t free a n d the w o r l d does n o t have a teleological e n d ; everything is necessary a n d
Being as a Desire to Survive causally determined. M a n is a slave because he believes he is free w h i l e being d r a w n a l o n g b y necessity. O n l y one type o f freedom remains open : knowledge. W h e n m a n knows w h a t he is, he knows t h a t he is not free a n d does n o t feel constrained or coerced, b u t determ i n e d according to his essence; therefore, reason is freedom. T h e being o f m a n , w h o is a m o d e o f substance, a mens a n d a corpus, consists i n n o t being free a n d k n o w i n g i t , i n l i v i n g w i t h i n n a t u r e , i n G o d . T h i s is a n echo o f the Stoic p r i n c i p l e -.parère Deo libertas est, obedience to G o d is freedom. Philosophy, the knowledge concerning b e i n g a n d substance, is a knowledge of G o d . A n d this highest type o f knowledge, i n w h i c h freed o m a n d happiness reside, is amor Dei intelleclualis, the intellectual love o f G o d , w h i c h for Spinoza represents the c u l m i n a t i o n o f b o t h p h i losophy a n d h u m a n life. 3.
B E I N G AS A
DESIRE
TO
SURVIVE
I n the t h i r d p a r t o f his Ethics, Spinoza expounds a conception o f being as a longing to go o n l i v i n g forever; i t is i m p o r t a n t to touch on this conception, i f only v e r y briefly. Every t h i n g , says Spinoza, i n so far as i t exists i n itself, tends to persevere i n its being, a n d this desire is n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n the a c t u a l essence o f the t h i n g ; i t is a desire i n v o l v i n g a limitless, i n f i n i t e t i m e ; i t is a l o n g i n g to continue to exist forever. T h e h u m a n m i n d wishes to endure w i t h o u t l i m i t a t i o n i n t i m e a n d is aware of this desire, w h i c h , w h e n referring to the m i n d alone, is called the will, and w h e n r e f e r r i n g to the m i n d a n d the body together, is called an urge. T h i s urge to live is n o t h i n g other t h a n the very essence o f m a n : his wish is the awareness o f his urge. W e do not seek after things, Spinoza says, we do n o t w a n t or l o n g for something because we believe i t is good, b u t j u s t the reverse: we t h i n k something is good because we seek i t , w a n t i t , l o n g for i t or desire i t . This cupiditas (longing) is man's p r i n c i p a l e m o t i o n ; there are t w o other major emotions, j o y a n d sadness, w h i c h correspond to an i n crease or a d i m i n u t i o n , respectively, of being a n d perfection. A l l the other emotions are d e r i v e d f r o m these three, as is man's entire psychic life : love, hate, and so f o r t h . Therefore, w h a t constitutes the being o f things for Spinoza is a desire, a striving, a n d this desire is a yearning to l i v e forever. Thus, for Spinoza, to be means to want to be forever, to have a longing for eternity or at least for a lasting existence. T h e essence o f m a n is wishing : m a n consists i n the wish to l i v e forever and the knowledge that he wishes i t . T h i s is the deep-rooted f o r m i n w h i c h the problems o f being a n d i m m o r t a l i t y are l i n k e d together i n Spinoza's philosophy.
Leibni^
L I F E A N D C H A R A C T E R . G o t t f r i e d W i l h e l m L e i b n i z was b o r n i n L e i p z i g i n 1646 a n d died i n H a n o v e r i n 1716. His family- was Protestant, a n d m a n y o f his forebears h a d p r a c t i c e d law. L e i b n i z devoted himself to intensive study f r o m a v e r y early age. H e learned the classical languages, Greek a n d L a t i n ; the literatures of a n t i q u i t y ; Scholastic philosophy, o f w h i c h he acquired a v e r y good knowledge; a n d , afterw a r d , m o d e r n p h i l o s o p h y — F r a n c i s Bacon, Campanella, Descartes, Hobbes. H e became acquainted w i t h the mathematics a n d physics o f his day, a n d studied the works o f K e p l e r a n d Galileo. I n a d d i t i o n , he seriously p o n d e r e d questions o f l a w a n d history, took u p the study o f alchemy a n d felt a boundless curiosity for a l l forms of knowledge.
L e i b n i z soon began to p a r t i c i p a t e i n the life o f his age. H e sent papers to the E u r o p e a n learned societies; he went to France as p a r t o f a d i p l o m a t i c mission, and made the acquaintance of the greatest intellectuals o f t h a t t i m e ; he also visited L o n d o n . L a t e r , i n 1676, he invented the infinitesimal calculus, le calcul des infiniment petits, at the same t i m e t h a t N e w t o n invented the same discipline, a l t h o u g h N e w t o n developed i t i n a different f o r m a n d called i t the method of fluxions. A great controversy raged between the partisans o f b o t h m e n — g r e a t e r than t h a t between the t w o originators themselves—but i t appears t h a t each one developed the calculus independently, w i t h o u t reciprocal influences. W h e n L e i b n i z r e t u r n e d to G e r m a n y , the D u k e o f B r u n s w i c k appointed h i m l i b r a r i a n of the d u c a l l i b r a r y at H a n o v e r , where he lived almost constantly f r o m t h a t t i m e o n , except when he was t r a v 236
Leibniz^ Philosophic Situation eling. A t H a n o v e r he was engaged i n intense i n t e l l e c t u a l , d i p l o m a t i c a n d p o l i t i c a l activities ; he also busied himself as a historian, c o m p i l i n g the Annales Brunswicenses. O n his o w n i n i t i a t i v e he founded the B e r l i n A c a d e m y o f Sciences i n 1700, m o d e l i n g i t o n those o f Paris a n d L o n d o n ; he was its first president. A n i m p o r t a n t figure o f his t i m e , he also traveled i n I t a l y , A u s t r i a a n d H o l l a n d . H e was actively concerned w i t h his p l a n to u n i f y t h e Catholic a n d Protestant Churches. L e i b n i z was very m u c h a t t r a c t e d t o Catholicism, b u t d i d n o t wish to renounce his background a n d be converted ; he wished instead to reconcile t h e t w o creeds. Despite his efforts a n d those o f Bossuet a n d Rojas Spinola, the project failed. L e i b n i z d i e d i n obscurity, almost totally neglected after an intense life f u l l o f marvelous i n t e l l e c t u a l achievement. W O R K S . L e i b n i z w r o t e numerous books o n mathematics, physics, history a n d especially philosophy. N e a r l y a l l his works are w r i t t e n i n French or i n L a t i n , a n d o n l y a very few, secondary ones i n G e r m a n . N o one h a d yet c u l t i v a t e d G e r m a n as a language suitable for p h i losophy; i t was L e i b n i z ' p u p i l W o l f f w h o first d i d this. L e i b n i z ' entire personality reveals a strong French influence, a n d alongside the i n t e r national l a n g u a g e — L a t i n — h e preferred to use French, the civilized language o f the era. L e i b n i z ' p r i n c i p a l philosophical works are t w o l o n g books, the Nouveaux essais sur l'entendement humain a n d the Théodice'e. T h e first o f these, directed against the English philosopher Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding, was n o t published d u r i n g L e i b n i z ' lifetime, because Locke died w h i l e i t was being prepared for p u b l i c a t i o n . T h e Theodicy poses the p r o b l e m o f the justification of God's ways, t h a t is, the p r o b l e m o f reconciling God's goodness and o m n i p o tence w i t h the existence o f evil a n d w i t h h u m a n freedom. I n a d d i t i o n , L e i b n i z produced several b r i e f writings, i n p a r t i c u l a r the Discours de métaphysique, perhaps his most systematic a n d interesting philosophical
exposition ; the Système nouveau de la nature ; the Principes de la nature et de la grâce, fondés en raison ; a n d the Monadologie, w r i t t e n for Prince Eugene of Savoy. Besides these, L e i b n i z left a great deal o f correspondence o n intellectual matters w i t h A r n a u l d , Clarke a n d others ; most o f this is still unpublished. 1.
LEIBNIZ'
PHILOSOPHIC SITUATION
L e i b n i z represents t h e end of the period o f p h i l o s o p h y w h i c h began w i t h Descartes a n d w h i c h more or less corresponds to the Baroque age. T h i s means that L e i b n i z appears at the end o f a seldom equaled epoch of intense metaphysical speculation; indeed, w h e n Leibniz reached his intellectual m a t u r i t y this metaphysical o u t b u r s t h a d already been going o n for sixty years. T h e rationalist systems h a d succeeded one
Leibniz^ another r a p i d l y — t h o s e o f Descartes, M a l e b r a n c h e , Spinoza, the thinkers o f P o r t - R o y a l , the Jansenists. T h i s era h a d also witnessed a great outburst o f theological speculation: Spanish Scholasticism, w h i c h i n c l u d e d Suarez, M e l c h o r Gano, Banez, M o l i n a a n d a l l the speculation centered o n the C o u n c i l o f T r e n t . L e i b n i z is aware o f this double c u r r e n t m a d e u p o f rationalism, o n one h a n d , a n d Scholastic i s m — p a r t i c u l a r l y Spanish Scholasticism—on the other. H i s pages are sprinkled w i t h Spanish names, precisely the names o f those i n d i viduals w h o possessed true intellectual w o r t h a n d c o m m a n d places i n the l i v i n g h i s t o r y o f t h o u g h t , those w h o have affected philosophy a n d been i n t e l l e c t u a l l y precise; this is c o m f o r t i n g to anyone w h o keeps the meaning o f t r u t h alive a n d does not d e l i g h t i n easy praise w h e r e i n a l l clarity a n d c r i t i c a l j u d g m e n t are lost. L e i b n i z rose completely above that disdain o f Scholasticism w h i c h characterized the superficial thinkers o f the Renaissance and w h i c h the earliest rationalists retained, at least e x t e r n a l l y ; he once more e x p l i c i t l y makes use of A r i s t o t e l i a n ideas, as w e l l as numerous medieval ideas a n d m a n y o f the acute theological concepts p u t forth at T r e n t . I n a d d i t i o n , he devotes h i m self intensely to mathematics and the new n a t u r a l science, a n d a d v a n ces b o t h to a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y degree. I n this w a y he unites a n d c o m pletely dominates a l l philosophic, theological a n d scientific traditions. Leibniz is the e p i t o m e o f the entire age. T h e specific b a c k g r o u n d against w h i c h L e i b n i z moves is the p h i l o sophic s i t u a t i o n bequeathed by Descartes a n d Spinoza. L e i b n i z is perhaps the first idealist i n the strict sense o f the w o r d ; i n Descartes, idealism is still weighed d o w n w i t h realism a n d Scholastic ideas, a n d Spinoza is n o t really a n idealist w i t h r e g a r d to w h a t is most characteristic or personal i n his t h o u g h t , a l t h o u g h perhaps the ideological tenor o f his t i m e , w i t h i n w h i c h he stated his problems, was idealistic. Leibniz w i l l see h i m s e l f obliged to set f o r t h w i t h precision the great questions o f the epoch, a n d he w i l l have to alter essentially the conception o f physics a n d the very idea o f substance, i n w h i c h philosophy since Aristotle has always been centered.
2.
LEIBNIZ'
METAPHYSICS
D Y N A M I S M . F o r Descartes, being was either res cogitans o r res extensa. T h e physical w o r l d was extension, something at rest. T h e concept o f force was foreign to h i m ; he found i t confusing a n d obscure, a n d d i d not see how i t c o u l d be translated i n t o geometrical concepts. Descartes understood m o t i o n as a change of position o f a m o v i n g b o d y i n respect to a p o i n t o f reference; the t w o points are interchangeable: to say t h a t
Leihniz^ Metaphysics A moves i n respect to B is the same as saying t h a t B moves i n respect to A; physics is interested o n l y i n change o f position. Descartes believed that the q u a n t i t y o f m o t i o n i n the universe (mv) remains constant. Leibniz shows t h a t w h a t is constant is the kinetic energy, vis viva (\mv ). Descartes' static, geometrical concept o f physics seems absurd to L e i b n i z . M o t i o n is n o t mere change o f position, b u t something real, something p r o d u c e d b y a force. I f one b i l l i a r d b a l l collides w i t h another, the l a t t e r is sent off; this is so because there is a force, a vis, w h i c h sets the second b i l l i a r d b a l l i n m o t i o n . T h i s concept o f force, vis, impetus, conatus, is the basis o f L e i b n i z ' physics—and his m e t a physics as w e l l . Descartes'notion o f static a n d i n e r t nature is replaced by a dynamic concept o f n a t u r e ; a physics based o n energy is set u p i n opposition to a physics based on e x t e n s i o n — i n short, a physical rather t h a n a geometrical concept o f n a t u r e . O n e must not forget that since the days o f Greece nature was the principle of motion. N o w Leibniz must a r r i v e at a new idea o f substance. 2
T H E M O N A D S . F o r L e i b n i z , the metaphysical structure o f the w o r l d consists o f the monads. M o n a d ( i n Greek, /¿ovas) means unity. T h e monads are basic substances, substances w i t h o u t component parts, w h i c h g r o u p to f o r m complex things; they are the elements o f the things. Since they are not made up o f parts, they are strictly indivisible —atoms—and therefore unextended, for atoms cannot have extension, inasmuch as extension is always divisible. A " m a t e r i a l a t o m " is a c o n t r a d i c t o r y expression: the m o n a d is aformal atom. These elemental monads cannot decay or perish t h r o u g h disintegration, nor can they be b u i l t u p f r o m parts. Therefore a m o n a d comes to be only t h r o u g h creation a n d ceases to be only t h r o u g h a n n i h i l a t i o n . Thus a m o n a d comes i n t o being tout d'un coup and n o t b y a process of generation. Leibniz says t h a t these monads are " w i n d o w l e s s " ; that is, t h a t n o t h i n g can issue f r o m one m o n a d a n d pass o n and affect another. T h e monads possess qualities and are different f r o m one a n o t h e r ; moreover, they change continually. H o w e v e r , this changing is n o t extrinsic; r a t h e r i t is the u n f o l d i n g o f the monad's internal possibilities.
T h e m o n a d is vis, force; a vis repraesentativa, or force o f representat i o n . E v e r y m o n a d actively represents o r reflects the entire universe from its own perspective. Therefore, the monads are irreplaceable, since each one reflects the universe i n its o w n special way. L e i b n i z ' m e t a physics shows t h a t he is a pluralist a n d t h a t he believes the things actually exist, even w h e n no perceiver is present. T h e monads are n o t all o f equal r a n k ; they reflect the universe w i t h v a r y i n g degrees o f clarity. F u r t h e r m o r e , n o t a l l monads are conscious o f their power o f
2^0
Leibniz^
reflection. W h e n monads have this consciousness a n d also m e m o r y , i t is possible to speak n o t o n l y oí perception b u t also oí apperception : such is the case w i t h the h u m a n monads. A n d this representation o f the universe is active : i t is the monads' purpose, t e n d e n c y — a desire t h a t arises f r o m the monad's ontological basis itself, f r o m its o w n reality. E v e r y t h i n g t h a t happens to a m o n a d arises f r o m its o w n being, f r o m its internal possibilities; the monads are completely insensitive to external influences. Thus Leibniz does j u s t the opposite o f S p i n o z a ; Spinoza reduces substance to a single e n t i t y — n a t u r e or G o d — w h e r e a s L e i b n i z restores to substance the character o f an individual thing w h i c h i t h a d h a d since Aristotle. I n a c e r t a i n sense this represents a r e t u r n to the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of the concept o f substance as a thing's property or goods (ovala, i n Greek), instead o f stressing the significance o f the independence—as d i d Descartes and, even m o r e so, S p i n o z a — w h i c h i n Greek metaphysics was always a consequence o f the character o f substance i n the sense o f ousia. Aristotle said t h a t substance is what is peculiar to each thing. L e i b n i z , w h e n faced w i t h the Cartesian d u a l i s m o f the res extensa a n d the res cogitans governed b y the res infinita, w h i c h is G o d , returns to the idea o f an absolute m u l t i p l i c i t y o f substantial monads w h i c h contain strictly w i t h i n themselves a l l their ontological possibilities. Substance o r nature is again the p r i n c i p l e o f m o t i o n i n the things themselves, as i n Aristotle. I n spite o f his apparent close relationship w i t h Plato because of the theory o f innate ideas, L e i b n i z is the most A r i s t o t e l i a n o f the rationalist metaphysicians ; f r o m this he derives i n p a r t his i n comparable fecundity, a q u a l i t y w h i c h philosophy has always possessed when i n live contact w i t h Aristotle. P R E - E S T A B L I S H E D H A R M O N Y . Since the m a n i f o l d monads t h a t make u p the w o r l d are windowless, the p r o b l e m o f the impossibility o f c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances no longer involves only the source o f knowledge, b u t above a l l , the very order a n d congruency o f the w o r l d as a whole. H a p p e n i n g s i n the universe can be explained o n l y b y starting w i t h the supposition that everything emerges f r o m the depths o f a l l the i n d i v i d u a l monads. H o w does i t h a p p e n , t h e n , t h a t the monads f o r m a w o r l d t h a t is full o f coherent relationships, t h a t i t is possible to k n o w the things, a n d that everything happens i n the w o r l d as i f there existed t h a t chimerical c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances w h i c h we find i t necessary to reject ? O n e must acknowledge for each m o n a d a previously established order t h a t sees to i t t h a t as i t unfolds its possibilities, i t coincides w i t h a l l the other monads, so t h a t they a l l find themselves i n h a r m o n y w i t h one another, thus constit u t i n g a w o r l d i n spite o f their essential solitariness a n d independence.
Leibniz^ Metaphysics A n d this o r d e r c a n o n l y have been m a d e b y G o d i n his g r a n d design w h e n c r e a t i n g the monads, w h i c h are at once solitary a n d u n i t e d . " T h u s i t is necessary to say that G o d first created the soul, or some other r e a l u n i t y , i n such a way t h a t e v e r y t h i n g w o u l d evolve f r o m its o w n depths w i t h perfect spontaneity w i t h respect to itself, a n d nevertheless i n perfect c o n f o r m i t y w i t h the things outside itself" (Système nouveau, 14). T h i s is w h a t Leibniz called pre-establishedharmony. T h u s there are three possible solutions to the idealist p r o b l e m o f the c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the substances : occasionalism, m o n i s m a n d pre-established h a r m o n y . A c c o r d i n g to the famous comparison, the p r o b l e m is equivalent to that o f s y n c h r o n i z i n g several clocks. I n Descartes' a n d Malebranche's solution, the clockmaker (God) constantly synchronizes the two clocks ( t h o u g h t and extension) w h i c h have no d i r e c t relationship whatsoever. Spinoza denies the p r o b l e m ; t h a t is, i n his philosophy there are n o t t w o clocks, b u t only one w i t h t w o faces : t w o aspects o f the same r e a l i t y , t w o attributes o f the same substance, w h i c h is synonymous w i t h G o d . I n Leibniz, there are n o t t w o clocks, b u t m a n y ; they do n o t have a n y interrelationship either, nor does the clockmaker constantly synchronize t h e m : this w o u l d be a p e r p e t u a l m i r a c l e a n d i t seems absurd to L e i b n i z ; however, the clockmaker has constructed the clocks i n such a w a y that they keep perfect t i m e w i t h o u t affecting one another a n d w i t h o u t His t o u c h i n g t h e m ; independently, a n d b y v i r t u e o f their previous construction, the clocks keep t i m e w i t h one another, r e m a i n h a r m o n i o u s . This constitutes p r e established h a r m o n y . T H E R O L E O F G O D . I f we t u r n o u r a t t e n t i o n to the p r o b l e m o f knowledge, w e f i n d t h a t i n L e i b n i z , too, G o d assures the correspondence between m y ideas a n d the r e a l i t y o f the things w h e n H e makes the development o f m y t h i n k i n g m o n a d coincide w i t h a l l the universe. I f i n M a l e b r a n c h e a l l the things are seen and k n o w n in G o d , i t can p r o p e r l y be said t h a t i n L e i b n i z they are k n o w n o n l y through G o d . L e i b n i z expresses this i n extremely clear t e r m s : " A c c o r d i n g to strict metaphysical t r u t h , there is no external cause t h a t actuates us b u t G o d alone, a n d H e communicates w i t h us d i r e c t l y o n l y b y v i r t u e o f our continuous dependency o n H i m . F r o m this i t follows t h a t there is n o other external object t h a t touches o u r soul a n d directly stimulates o u r perception. T h u s , w e have the ideas o f a l l the things i n o u r soul o n l y b y v i r t u e o f God's c o n t i n u a l a c t i o n o n us . . . " (Discours de métaphysique, 28). I n other words, the monads do i n fact have w i n d o w s , b u t instead o f p u t t i n g the monads i n c o m m u n i c a t i o n w i t h one another, these w i n d o w s a l l open o u t o n t o the D e i t y .
2^2
Leibniz^
T h u s i n the midst o f L e i b n i z ' m a t u r e philosophy w e see once again the necessity for establishing the existence o f G o d . G o d is a basic supposition i n a l l L e i b n i z ' metaphysics, since i t is H e w h o makes possible the existence o f the monads, understood as t h a t a u t o n o m o u s a n d spontaneous force o f representation w h i c h m i r r o r s the universe f r o m the i n f i n i t e p l u r a l i t y o f the m o n a d s ' i n d i v i d u a l perspectives. T h u s L e i b n i z must philosophically p r o v e the existence o f G o d , a n d to d o this he too employs as a tool the often used ontological a r g u m e n t . H e modifies i t , a n d t h e n i t becomes a m a j o r tenet o f all rationalist metaphysics o f the seventeenth century. A c c o r d i n g to L e i b n i z , i t is necessary to prove the possibility of God, a n d o n l y t h e n is His existence assured b y v i r t u e o f the ontological proof, since G o d is the ens a se. I f G o d is possible, H e exists. L e i b n i z says t h a t the D i v i n e Essence is possible because, since G o d does n o t contain any n e g a t i o n , H e cannot c o n t a i n a n y c o n t r a d i c t i o n whatsoever; therefore, G o d exists (cf. Discours de métaphysique, 23, and
Monadologie, 4 5 ) . N o w L e i b n i z goes f u r t h e r : he also attempts a n a p o s t e r i o r i a n d experimental proof. I f the ens a se is impossible, so also are a l l the entities ab alio, since these exist only t h r o u g h this aliud w h i c h is, precisely, the ens a se; therefore, i n such a case n o t h i n g w o u l d exist. I f the necessary entity does n o t exist, there are no possible entities ; however, these exist, since we see t h e m ; therefore, the ens a se exists. These t w o propositions taken together comprise L e i b n i z ' p r o o f o f t h e existence of
God. If the necessary entity is possible, it exists; if the necessary entity does no exist, there are no possible entities. T h i s reasoning is based o n t h e existence ( k n o w n a posteriori) o f the possible a n d c o n t i n g e n t entities. T h e simplest expression o f this a r g u m e n t w o u l d be : Something exists, therefore
God exists.* 3.
THEORY
OF
KNOWLEDGE
P E R C E P T I O N A N D A P P E R C E P T I O N . T h e monads have perceptions. H o w e v e r , these perceptions are not always the same ; they can be clear o r obscure, distinct o r confused. Things have insensible perceptions, perceptions w i t h o u t consciousness, and m a n also has such perceptions, i n v a r y i n g degrees. A sensation is a confused idea. W h e n perceptions have c l a r i t y and consciousness a n d are accompanied b y m e m o r y , they are apperceptions, a n d these are peculiar to souls. T h e r e is a hierarchy a m o n g souls, a n d h u m a n souls come to k n o w u n i v e r s a l a n d necessary truths ; then i t is possible to speak o f reason, a n d the soul is spirit. A t the
* For an analysis of the problems posed by this proof, see my essay " E l problema de Dios en la filosofia de nuestro tiempo" in San Anselmoy el insensate- [Obras, I V ] .
Theory of Knowledge
H3
s u m m i t o f the hierarchy o f the monads is G o d , w h o is p u r e a c t u a l i t y . T R U T H S O F R E A S O N A N D T R U T H S O F F A C T . L e i b n i z distinguishes between w h a t he calls vérités de raison a n d vérités de fait. T h e t r u t h s o f reason are necessary ; i t is inconceivable t h a t they do n o t exist ; t h a t is, they are based on the p r i n c i p l e o f contradiction. Therefore they are evident f r o m a p r i o r i knowledge, apart f r o m a l l experience. T r u t h s o f fact, o n the contrary, c a n n o t j u s t i f y themselves o n a p r i o r i knowledge alone. T h e y cannot be based solely on the principles o f i d e n t i t y a n d contradiction ; rather, they require the p r i n c i p l e o f sufficient reason. T w o and t w o are f o u r ; this is a t r u t h o f reason, a n d is based o n w h a t t w o is and w h a t f o u r is ; t w o and t w o cannot n o t be four. C o l u m b u s discovered A m e r i c a ; this is a t r u t h o f fact, a n d requires e x p e r i m e n t a l c o n f i r m a t i o n ; i t is conceivable t h a t i t is n o t t r u e ; t h a t is, i t is not self-contradictory t h a t Columbus d i d n o t discover A m e r i c a . T H E I N D I V I D U A L N O T I O N . H o w e v e r , this idea is not as simple as i t appears. W e must not forget that the m o n a d contains w i t h i n itself a l l its r e a l i t y , a n d that n o t h i n g outside i t can influence i t ; therefore, e v e r y t h i n g t h a t happens to i t is i n c l u d e d i n its essence a n d , conseq u e n t l y , i n its complete notion. C o l u m b u s discovered A m e r i c a because the act o f discovering A m e r i c a was i n c l u d e d i n Columbus' being, i n the complete n o t i o n of Columbus. I n a famous example L e i b n i z says t h a t i f Caesar h a d not crossed the R u b i c o n he w o u l d n o t have been Caesar. Therefore, i f we could k n o w the complete i n d i v i d u a l notions we w o u l d see t h a t truths o f fact are i n c l u d e d i n the essence o f the m o n a d , a n d t h a t their absence is self-contradictory. T h e n a l l truths are vérités de raison, that is, necessary a n d a p r i o r i . B u t w h o possesses the complete n o t i o n o f the monads ? O n l y G o d ; therefore, this d i s t i n c t i o n between t r u t h s o f reason and truths o f fact disappears o n l y for H i m , a n d still exists for m a n .
S t r i c t l y speaking, then, L e i b n i z does n o t allow accidental occurrences ; he says that every true p r e d i c a t i o n is based on the n a t u r e o f things. T h u s a l l j u d g m e n t s are analytic j u d g m e n t s : they o n l y m a k e explicit the n o t i o n o f the subject. L a t e r K a n t , using metaphysical suppositions different f r o m those o f L e i b n i z , w i l l p o i n t out the i m p o r t a n t d i s t i n c t i o n between analytic a n d synthetic judgments. I N N A T I S M . I n L e i b n i z , all ideas proceed f r o m the i n t e r n a l a c t i v i t y o f the monads ; n o t h i n g is received f r o m outside. Leibniz is a h u n d r e d leagues r e m o v e d f r o m every type o f e m p i r i c i s m , w h i c h is f o r m a l l y impossible i n his metaphysics. T h u s the ideas are innate i n this concrete sense. I t is m o r e a metaphysical t h a n a psychological p r o b l e m . T h e ideas have t h e i r o r i g i n — w h i c h is a c t i v e — i n the m i n d itself, i n the vis
Leibni^ repraesentativa that produces t h e m . T h u s Leibniz is completely opposed to L o c k e a n d a l l the B r i t i s h e m p i r i c i s m that influences the C o n t i n e n t greatly a n d comes to d o m i n a t e the eighteenth c e n t u r y . L e i b n i z amends the t r a d i t i o n a l p r i n c i p l e t h a t there is n o t h i n g i n the understanding that has not been previously i n the senses b y excepting f r o m this statement the u n d e r s t a n d i n g itself: Nihil est in intellectu quod prius
nonfuerit in sensu... nisi intellects ipse. L O G I C . T r a d i t i o n a l , demonstrative logic does n o t satisfy L e i b n i z . H e thinks i t is useful o n l y i n p r o v i n g already k n o w n t r u t h s , a n d o f no use i n discovering new t r u t h s . T h i s objection, as w e l l as the tendency t o w a r d innatism, appeared as far back as Descartes, a n d i n L e i b n i z b o t h ideas find their fullest expression. Leibniz w a n t e d to create a t r u e ars inveniendi, a logic t h a t w o u l d be useful i n discovering t r u t h s , a universal combinatory system t h a t w o u l d study the possible combinations o f concepts. Such a system c o u l d investigate t r u t h as i f i t were a m a t h e m a t i c a l p r o b l e m , a n d c o u l d supply an a p r i o r i a n d certain knowledge. This is the famous Ars magna combinatoria, inspired i n p a r t b y R a i m u n d u s L u l l u s ' w o r k ; f r o m i t is derived the idea o f the mathesis universalis, w h i c h has recently demonstrated its f e c u n d i t y i n the fields o f phenomenology a n d m a t h e m a t i c a l logic.
4.
THEODICY
L e i b n i z ' Theodicy carries as a subtitle " Essays o n the Goodness o f G o d , the Freedom of M a n a n d the O r i g i n o f E v i l , " thus revealing the m e a n i n g a n d scope o f this " j u s t i f i c a t i o n o f G o d . " O n one h a n d , G o d is defined as o m n i p o t e n t a n d i n f i n i t e l y good, b u t evil exists i n the w o r l d . O n the other h a n d , i t is said t h a t m a n is free a n d responsible, b u t L e i b n i z o n the contrary points o u t that everything t h a t occurs is previously included i n the m o n a d . T h e problem is, h o w can these ideas be m a d e compatible ? M E T A P H Y S I C A L O P T I M I S M . E v i l can be metaphysical (the imperfect i o n a n d finiteness o f the w o r l d a n d m a n ) , physical ( p a i n , misfortune, a n d the like) or m o r a l (wickedness, sin, and so o n ) . M e t a p h y s i c a l evil derives f r o m the impossibility o f the world's being i n f i n i t e l i k e its Creator. Physical evil has its j u s t i f i c a t i o n i n t h a t i t gives rise to higher values (for example, adversity gives rise to the o p p o r t u n i t y for such virtues as fortitude, heroism a n d self-sacrifice to a p p e a r ) ; f u r t h e r m o r e , L e i b n i z believes that life as a whole is not evil, a n d t h a t pleasure is m o r e prevalent than p a i n . F i n a l l y , m o r a l evil, w h i c h is w h a t constitutes the most serious p r o b l e m , is actually a deficiency, something negative. G o d does not desire m o r a l e v i l ; he simply p e r m i t s i t to exist
Theodicy
H5
because i t is a c o n d i t i o n for other, greater good. Facts cannot be j u d g e d singly, for we do not k n o w God's total p l a n ; i n order to be understood, facts w o u l d have to be viewed w i t h knowledge o f God's complete design. Since G o d is o m n i p o t e n t a n d good we can rest assured t h a t the w o r l d is the best of all possible worlds: t h a t is, t h a t i t contains the m a x i m u m good a n d the m i n i m u m evil proper for the good o f the whole. T h i s is called the principe du meilleur, and is connected w i t h arguments used b y Scotus to prove the I m m a c u l a t e C o n c e p t i o n . G o d does e v e r y t h i n g for the best because H e can and because H e is g o o d ; i f H e c o u l d n o t , H e w o u l d n o t be G o d , since H e w o u l d n o t be o m n i p o t e n t ; i f H e could b u t d i d n o t w i s h to, H e w o u l d also n o t be G o d , since H e w o u l d n o t be infinitely good. " H e could do i t , i t was f i t t i n g to d o i t , a n d so H e d i d i t , " Scotus concluded. I n an analogous w a y L e i b n i z bases his metaphysical o p t i m i s m on the a f f i r m a t i o n t h a t the w o r l d is the best o f a l l possible w o r l d s . F R E E D O M . A l l the monads are spontaneous because n o t h i n g outside t h e m can coerce or compel t h e m at a l l ; b u t this is n o t e n o u g h to make t h e m free. I n a d d i t i o n to spontaneity, freedom requires d e l i b e r a t i o n a n d decision. M a n is free because he chooses between possibilities after d e l i b e r a t i n g o n t h e m . B u t the D i v i n e Prescience introduces itself as a d i f f i c u l t y ; G o d sees the b e i n g o f the monads f r o m the beginning, a n d the monads contain w i t h i n themselves a l l t h a t is to h a p p e n to t h e m a n d everything t h a t they are to do. T h e n h o w is freedom possible ?
I n order to interpret God's knowledge, Leibniz makes use of certain subtle distinctions o f Catholic theology, especially some points advanced b y the Spaniard M o l i n a . G o d has three kinds o f knowledge: ( i ) knowledge of pure intellection, (2) knowledge of v i s i o n , ( 3 ) m i d d l e knowledge. By the first k i n d G o d knows a l l possible t h i n g s ; b y k n o w l edge o f vision H e knows a l l real or future things; b y m i d d l e k n o w l edge H e knows the " f u t u r i b l e s , " t h a t is, the c o n d i t i o n e d future, the things t h a t w i l l come to be i f c e r t a i n conditions arise, a l t h o u g h i t is n o t d e t e r m i n e d t h a t such conditions shall arise. God knows h o w free w i l l w o u l d act, w i t h o u t its being d e t e r m i n e d that i t must act i n this way a n d therefore that these must be f u t u r e events, j u s t as C h r i s t knew that i f miracles h a d been performed i n T y r e and Sidon the people w o u l d have repented ( M a t t h e w 11:21). Contingent things are n o t necessary; necessity accrues to t h e m only i n a n a posteriori way, f o l l o w i n g a decision o f the D i v i n e W i l l , subsequent to knowledge of simple intellection a n d m i d d l e knowledge. G o d creates m e n a n d H e creates t h e m free. T h i s means t h a t they d e t e r m i n e their o w n actions freely, a l t h o u g h G o d has d e t e r m i n e d t h a t
2^6
Leibniz^
they s h o u l d exist. G o d wishes m a n to be free, a n d H e allows h i m t o sin because the freedom to sin is preferable to the lack o f such freedom. T h u s sin is a possible evil t h a t p e r m i t s a higher g o o d : to w i t , h u m a n freedom. G O D I N S E V E N T E E N T H - C E N T U R Y P H I L O S O P H Y . W e h a v e seen t h a t despite the separation of theology f r o m philosophy i n this p e r i o d , G o d was n o t lost. A l l rationalistic a n d idealistic philosophy f r o m Descartes to L e i b n i z can be established because G o d is t h e r e — a t a distance, i t is t r u e , b u t surely there. Perhaps reason cannot gain knowledge o f God's essence a n d is n o t able to practice theology, b u t i t does k n o w w i t h c e r t a i n t y t h a t G o d exists. T h e philosophers o f this p e r i o d , I repeat, possess a G o d w h o is somewhat remote, somewhat inaccessible a n d w i t h o u t direct effect o n i n t e l l e c t u a l activity, b u t w h o nevertheless surely exists. G o d provides these philosophers w i t h a sure f o o t i n g , even t h o u g h H e is n o t a prospect o n w h i c h their eyes rest w i t h steady interest. H e ceases to be the ever-visible horizon a n d becomes the solid ground beneath eighteenth-century E u r o p e a n philosophic speculation. T h i s is w h a t gives the p e r i o d o f the history o f philosophy w h i c h runs f r o m Descartes to L e i b n i z its essential u n i t y . T h i s g r o u p o f p h i l o sophic systems appears as i f enveloped i n a c o m m o n atmosphere, w h i c h reveals a similar i n t e r r e l a t i o n s h i p o f ideas. A basic coherence can be observed among a l l the philosophic constructions t h a t are clustered together i n these few decades. A n d taken as a g r o u p , these systems w i l l appear as i f i n contraposition to another g r o u p o f lofty metaphysical edifices: the so-called G e r m a n idealism w h i c h o r i g i nates i n K a n t a n d culminates i n Hegel. T h e philosophers o f the R o m a n t i c age w i l l h u r l a r e p r o a c h at the metaphysics o f the entire Baroque era. I n this objection the seventeenth-century systems w i l l be g r o u p e d together i n t o one complex a n d w i l l n o t be treated separately as i n d i v i d u a l constructions. I t is interesting to n o t e the significance o f q u a l i f y i n g t h e m as a single complex. This Baroque philosophy is called dogmatic. W h a t does this mean? F o r a n answer we shall have to see w h a t the fate o f the p r o b l e m o f G o d w i l l be at the hands o f the G e r m a n idealists. T h i s p r o b l e m w i l l be s u m m e d u p i n t h e question o f the ontological a r g u m e n t and w i l l reveal to us the m e t a physical s i t u a t i o n of the new stage i n m o d e r n p h i l o s o p h y . * * See my essay " L a perdida de Dios" in San Anselmoy el insensato [Obras, I V ] .
EMPIRICISM
British
Philosophy
F r o m the sixteenth to the eighteenth centuries, r u n n i n g parallel w i t h C o n t i n e n t a l rationalistic idealism, a p h i l o s o p h y w i t h clearly developed characteristics o f its o w n develops i n B r i t a i n . Between Francis Bacon a n d D a v i d H u m e there extends a series o f thinkers w h o i n a certain measure oppose the philosophers we have j u s t studied, the g r o u p f r o m Descartes to L e i b n i z . British p h i l o s o p h y presents t w o features w h i c h distinguish i t f r o m C o n t i n e n t a l t h o u g h t : a lesser concern w i t h strictly metaphysical questions, accompanied b y a greater concern w i t h theory o f knowledge ( w h i c h , n a t u r a l l y , always presupposes a metaphysics) a n d the philosophy o f the State; and, as regards m e t h o d , a sensationalist empiricism as contrasted w i t h an a p r i o r i , m a t h e m a t i c a l l y i n c l i n e d rationalism. B r i t i s h philosophy has a tendency to become psychology and to grant first place to sensory experience as a source o f knowledge. T h i s British philosophy o f the m o d e r n age is u n d e n i a b l y i m p o r t a n t , b u t perhaps more because o f its influence a n d h i s t o r i c a l consequences t h a n i n consideration o f its strictly philosophical significance. Despite t h e i r great r e n o w n a n d the widespread influence w h i c h they exerted, the B r i t i s h philosophers o f these three centuries d o n o t have the significance o f those e x t r a o r d i n a r y British thinkers o f the M i d d l e Ages, R o g e r Bacon, Duns Scotus a n d W i l l i a m o f O c c a m , n o t to m e n t i o n others w h o are somewhat less i m p o r t a n t t h a n these b u t whose i m p o r tance is still very great. B r i t a i n ' s great c o n t r i b u t i o n to philosophy must therefore be sought i n the medieval p e r i o d , at least as m u c h as i n the m o d e r n age. 247
148
British Philosophy
A n d yet i t was the British thinkers o f the sixteenth t o eighteenth centuries w h o furnished the ideas w h i c h perhaps most intensely i n fluenced the transformation o f E u r o p e a n society: sensationalism; the c r i t i q u e o f the cognitive faculty, w h i c h i n some cases a r r i v e d at skepticism; the ideas o f tolerance; l i b e r a l p r i n c i p l e s ; the s p i r i t o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t ; deism, or n a t u r a l r e l i g i o n ; a n d finally, as a p r a c t i c a l m i n d e d r e a c t i o n to metaphysical skepticism, the philosophy o f comm o n sense, u t i l i t a r i a n ethics a n d p r a g m a t i s m . A l l these elements, o f e x t r a o r d i n a r y influence o n the structure o f Europe i n t h e eighteenth a n d nineteenth centuries, have their o r i g i n i n the ideological systems w h i c h were d o m i n a n t i n B r i t a i n i n the preceding centuries. These systems have p r o f o u n d repercussions i n the nations of the C o n t i n e n t , especially i n France a n d Germany.
i.
FRANCIS
BACON
L I F E A N D W O R K S . Bacon was b o r n i n 1561 a n d died i n 1626. H e is thus a couple o f generations earlier t h a n Descartes. H e was L o r d Chancellor o f E n g l a n d and was ennobled as B a r o n V e r u l a m ; he was a great p o l i t i c a l figure i n Elizabethan a n d Jacobean E n g l a n d . L a t e r he was shorn o f his offices and i n his r e t i r e m e n t devoted h i m s e l f to i n t e l lectual labors. T h e a t t r i b u t i o n to Bacon o f the works of Shakespeare is highly improbable.
Bacon's m a j o r w o r k is the Novum Organum, w h i c h presents a n i n d u c tive logic, as opposed to Aristotle's deductive a n d syllogistic logic. H e also w r o t e , a l l u n d e r the general t i t l e o f Instauratio magna ( T h e Great R e n e w a l ) , the treatise Dedignitate et augmentisscientiarum ( T h e A d v a n c e ment o f L e a r n i n g ) a n d numerous essays o n different subjects: Filum Labyrinthi ( T h e T h r e a d T h r o u g h the L a b y r i n t h ) , De interpretatione naturae et regno hominis ( O n the I n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f N a t u r e a n d the R e i g n
of M a n ) , Temporis partus masculus sive instauratio magna imperii humani in universum ( T h e M a l e C h i l d o f T i m e , or the Great R e n e w a l o f M a n ' s E m p i r e i n the Universe), Cogitata et visa (Things T h o u g h t a n d Seen), a n d so o n . W e note that a l l these titles are positive i n o u t l o o k a n d herald the t r i u m p h a n t beginning o f a new science. D O C T R I N E . Bacon's fame has been greater t h a n his t r u e m e r i t . F o r a l o n g t i m e he was considered the renewer o f m o d e r n philosophy, equal or superior to Descartes. T h i s v i e w has l i t t l e f o u n d a t i o n , a n d i t has been necessary to l i m i t Bacon's achievement to the i n t r o d u c t i o n o f empiricism a n d the inductive m e t h o d . B u t even here i t is n o t possible to forget the role played by his fellow c o u n t r y m a n and namesake o f
Francis Bacon three centuries earlier, R o g e r Bacon, w h o was m o r e o r i g i n a l t h a n the Renaissance chancellor a n d w h o to a great extent prepared the w a y for h i m , even t h o u g h the consequences o f R o g e r Bacon's w o r k were i n c o m p a r a b l y less noticeable. Francis Bacon represents the c u l m i n a t i o n o f the Renaissance, w h i c h i n philosophy is n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n the l o n g stage o f indecision reaching f r o m the last of the o r i g i n a l a n d lively Scholastic systems—Occamism — u p to the first m a t u r e a n d clear f o r m u l a t i o n o f the t h o u g h t o f m o d e r n times—Cartesianism. Bacon combines speculative w i t h techn i c a l concerns: knowledge is power. F r o m the v e r y outset o f his Novum Organum, he places o n the same plane doing a n d understanding, the h a n d a n d the m i n d ; hence the v i t a l new m e a n i n g w h i c h he gives to A r i s totle's m e t a p h o r o f the organon, or tool, as a designation o f logic. N e i t h e r the bare h a n d n o r the isolated a n d u n a i d e d m i n d can dominate the things; m a t e r i a l a n d m e n t a l tools together l e n d h a n d a n d m i n d their true efficacy. A n d j u s t as the craftsman does, so the thinker must s u b m i t to the exigencies o f r e a l i t y : natura non nisi parendo vincitur, i t is possible to conquer n a t u r e o n l y by obeying her. Bacon believes t h a t philosophic investigation requires a previous e x a m i n a t i o n o f the prejudices (idols) w h i c h c a n conceal t r u t h . As i n Cartesianism, so here concern w i t h c r i t i c i s m a n d fear o f error make their appearance. Bacon speaks of four i d o l s : i . Idola tribus. These are the prejudices o f the tribe, the h u m a n species, a n d are inherent i n the nature o f m a n : illusions o f the senses, the tendency to personify i n a n i mate objects, a n d so f o r t h . 2. Idola specus. These arc the prejudices o f the cave i n w h i c h each m a n finds himself ( a n allusion to the Platonic m y t h ) : i n d i v i d u a l tendencies and predispositions w h i c h m a y lead m e n i n t o error. 3 . Idola fori. These are the idols o f the marketplace, o f h u m a n society a n d o f the very speech w h i c h w e use. 4 . Idola theatri. These are the prejudices o f authority, based o n the prestige w h i c h a few m e n enjoy o n the stage o f public life; these prejudices m a y h i n d e r men's direct a n d personal vision of the things a n d lead their opinions o f f the true p a t h . I n a d d i t i o n , Bacon criticizes the syllogistic m e t h o d . T h e presumptive logical r i g o r w h i c h gives the syllogism its demonstrative value is nullified because the major premise o f a syllogism is a universal p r i n c i p l e w h i c h is n o t itself o b t a i n e d syllogistically, b u t f r e q u e n t l y by means o f a n inexact a n d superficial apprehension o f things. T h e rigor and cert a i n t y o f inference are p u r e l y formal and have n o pertinence i f the major premise is n o t c e r t a i n . T h i s leads Bacon to establish his theory o f induction: f r o m a series o f individual facts, g r o u p e d i n a suitable system a t i c way, one obtains b y abstraction, after f o l l o w i n g a rigorous
British Philosophy experimental a n d logical procedure, the general concepts o f the things a n d the laws o f nature. This i n d u c t i o n o f Bacon's, w h i c h is also called incomplete i n d u c t i o n i n contrast to i n d u c t i o n based on all the p e r t i n e n t i n d i v i d u a l cases, does not afford a n absolute certainty, b u t i t does p r o v i d e sufficient certainty for the purposes o f science w h e n c a r r i e d out scrupulously. I n a certain sense, this m e t h o d is opposed to the m e t h o d of philosophic rationalism a n d even to the m e t h o d o f m o d e r n m a t h e m a t i c a l physics w h i c h began w i t h Galileo. Bacon was n o t clearly aware o f the value o f mathematics a n d a p r i o r i reasoning, a n d his e m p i r i c i s m was m u c h less f r u i t f u l t h a n the nuova scienza of the Renaissance physicists or the rationalism o f the philosophers w h o based their systems o n t h a t o f Descartes.
2.
HOBBES
Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) is another interesting E n g l i s h t h i n k e r . H e enjoyed a l o n g life a n d outlived even Spinoza, b u t , as c a n be seen f r o m the date o f his b i r t h , actually belonged to the generation before Descartes. H o b b e s m a i n t a i n e d close contact w i t h France, a n d there he became a c q u a i n t e d w i t h Descartes a n d i m b u e d w i t h the m e t h o d o f the m a t h e m a t i c a l a n d physical sciences. F o r several years i n his y o u t h he was secretary to Bacon, a n d he shares Bacon's concerns; b u t Hobbes applies the n a t u r a l i s t i c m e t h o d o f m o d e r n physics to the study o f m a n k i n d . M a n as a n i n d i v i d u a l and i n society, a n d thus psychology, anthropology, politics, the science o f the State a n d society: these are Hobbes' themes. H e w r o t e i n L a t i n a n d E n g l i s h ; his p r i n c i p a l works are De corpore, De homine, De cive a n d Leviathan, w h i c h contains his theory of the State a n d is named after the beast m e n t i o n e d i n the Book of J o b . Hobbes, too, is a n empiricist. For h i m , knowledge is based o n experience, a n d his concern is to instruct m e n for practical purposes. O n the other h a n d , he is a nominalist, a n d thus a continuer of the medieval O x f o r d t r a d i t i o n . T h e universals exist neither outside t h e m i n d n o r even w i t h i n i t , because our representations are i n d i v i d u a l ; t h e u n i v e r sals are merely names, signs for the things, a n d t h o u g h t is a symbolic operation, a sort o f calculus, closely l i n k e d to speech. Hobbes' metaphysics is naturalistic. H e seeks causal explanations, b u t eliminates f i n a l causes a n d wishes to e x p l a i n phenomena m e c h a n i cally, on the basis o f motions. Descartes, too, a d m i t t e d m e c h a n i c a l explanations w i t h regard to the res extensa, b u t contrasted w i t h this the i m m a t e r i a l w o r l d o f t h o u g h t . Hobbes believes t h a t the processes o f the
Hobbes
zjl
soul a n d the m i n d have a material a n d corporeal basis; according to h i m , the soul cannot be i m m a t e r i a l . Hobbes is a materialist a n d denies the freedom o f the w i l l . A n a t u r a l d e t e r m i n i s m prevails i n e v e r y t h i n g that happens. T H E D O C T R I N E O F T H E S T A T E . Hobbes' theory of the State presupposes the e q u a l i t y o f all men. H e believes t h a t a l l m e n aspire t o w a r d the same goal a n d t h a t w h e n they fail to achieve i t , enmity a n d hate spring u p . W h o e v e r does not o b t a i n his desire distrusts the m a n w h o has met w i t h success a n d , i n order to w a r d off a possible attack, attacks h i m . Hence arises Hobbes' pessimistic conception o f m a n k i n d : homo homini lupus, m a n is a w o l f to m a n . M e n have no direct interest i n the company o f t h e i r fellows, except to the extent that they can reduce them to submission. T h e three motives o f discord a m o n g h u m a n beings are c o m p e t i t i o n , w h i c h provokes aggression w i t h gain as a n object; mistrust, w h i c h makes m e n attack each other i n order to achieve security; a n d v a n i t y , w h i c h creates e n m i t y between rivals for fame. This natural s i t u a t i o n defines a state o f p e r p e t u a l struggle, o f a w a r of all against a l l (bellum omnium contra omnes), to use Hobbes' awesome phrase. T h i s does n o t m e a n isolated outbursts o f warfare, b u t a state o f w a r — a time o f w a r , Hobbes calls i t — i n w h i c h m a n k i n d exists, a permanent c o n d i t i o n i n w h i c h no one can be sure o f peace. M a n is endowed w i t h a power w h i c h he uses as he sees f i t ; he has certain passions a n d desires w h i c h cause h i m to seek for things a n d want to acquire t h e m for himself at everyone else's expense. Since everyone is aware o f this attitude, m e n distrust one another; man's n a t u r a l state is one o f aggression. B u t m a n realizes that this s i t u a t i o n of insecurity is u n t e n a b l e ; his life is w r e t c h e d i n this state o f struggle and he is compelled to seek peace. Hobbes distinguishes between jus, or r i g h t , w h i c h he interprets as freedom, a n d lex, or law, w h i c h signifies obligation. M a n has the f r e e d o m — t h a t is, the r i g h t — t o do a n y t h i n g he can or desires to d o ; b u t three things can be done w i t h a r i g h t : i t m a y be exercised, renounced or transferred. T h e m u t u a l transfer o f a right is called a pact, contract or covenant. T h i s leads to the idea o f a political c o m m u n i t y . I n order to g a i n security, m a n tries to substitute a status civilis for the status naturae t h r o u g h a covenant by w h i c h each m a n transfers his rights to the State. S t r i c t l y speaking, this is n o t a covenant w i t h the person or persons charged w i t h the a d m i n i s t r a t i o n of the State, b u t o f each m a n w i t h every other m a n . T h e sovereign merely represents the force established b y the covenant; a l l the other m e n are his subjects. N o w , the State as thus constituted is absolute: j u s t as f o r m e r l y the
British Philosophy power o f the i n d i v i d u a l knew no restriction, so i t is now w i t h the a u t h o r i t y o f the State—it is coextensive with its might. W h e n the State strips the i n d i v i d u a l m e n o f their power, i t assumes a l l o f i t itself a n d governs w i t h o u t l i m i t a t i o n s . T h e State is a m i g h t y machine, a monster w h i c h devours the i n d i v i d u a l s , and f r o m w h i c h they cannot appeal to any higher a u t h o r i t y . Hobbes finds no m o r e suitable name for this monster t h a n t h a t o f the great beast of the B i b l e : Leviathan; this is the State, superior to a l l else, a m o r t a l G o d , as i t were. Hobbes' State decides u p o n everything, n o t o n l y politics, b u t also m o r a l i t y and r e l i g i o n ; i f r e l i g i o n is not recognized b y the State, i t is merely superstition. T h i s system, acute a n d p r o f o u n d i n m a n y points, represents the a u t h o r i t a r i a n a n d absolutist conception o f the State, based simultaneously o n the p r i n c i p l e o f e q u a l i t y a n d o n a t h o r o u g h l y pessimistic view o f h u m a n nature. A l t h o u g h H o b b e s speaks o f G o d at times, the outlook o f his w o r k is basically atheistic. I n contrast to the ideas ofspirituality a n d freedom, Hobbes' p o l i t i c a l system is d o m i n a t e d b y naturalistic mechanics a n d the a f f i r m a t i o n o f the universal power o f the State. T h i s doctrine, w h i c h was extremely i n f l u e n t i a l i n the eighteenth century and h a d l o n g - r a n g i n g historical consequences w h i c h are still felt today, aroused t w o kinds o f reaction i n its o w n day. O n e type o f reaction was t h a t o f Sir R o b e r t Filmer, a u t h o r o f The Patriarch, w h o t r i e d to salvage the absolute monarchy o f the Stuarts b y means o f the theory o f the d i v i n e r i g h t o f kings; the basis o f this theory is t h a t m a n is n o t b o r n free, b u t is subject to his father's a u t h o r i t y , f r o m w h i c h is derived the legitimacy o f the paternal a n d p a t r i a r c h a l rule o f kings. T h e other type o f r e a c t i o n , w h i c h was opposed to F i l m e r as w e l l as to Hobbes, was t h a t o f Locke, w h o upheld the principles o f l i b e r t y a n d parliamentarianism, t h a t is, the principles o f the second English revolution, t h a t o f 1688. 3.
DEISM
T h e naturalism o f the m o d e r n age leads as a m a t t e r of course to the concept o f natural religion. T h i s is also called deism, as distinguished f r o m theism. Theism is the belief i n G o d , t h a t is, i n the supernatural G o d o f religion w h o is k n o w n t h r o u g h revelation. Deism, o n the other h a n d , arises as a reaction to the atheism t h a t creeps into English philosophy, b u t i t remains w i t h i n the r e a l m o f the strictly n a t u r a l . G o d is k n o w n b y means o f reason, w i t h o u t any supern a t u r a l aid. N a t u r a l r e l i g i o n is merely w h a t o u r reason tells us a b o u t G o d and our relationship w i t h H i m . Therefore, i t is a religion w i t h o u t revelation, w i t h o u t dogmas, w i t h o u t churches a n d w i t h o u t f o r m a l NATURAL RELIGION.
Deism w o r s h i p . T h e entire eighteenth-century E n l i g h t e n m e n t , w i t h its idea o f the " Supreme B e i n g , " is d o m i n a t e d b y deism. D e i s m thus appears i n the w r i t i n g s o f the English t h i n k e r E d w a r d H e r b e r t o f C h e r b u r y (1581-1648), whose major works are De veritate,
prout distinguitur a revelatione, a verisimile, apossibili, et afalso ( O n T r u t h , as D i s t i n g u i s h e d f r o m Revelation, P r o b a b i l i t y , Possibility a n d Falsity)
a n d De religione gentilium, errorumque apud eos causis ( O n the R e l i g i o n o f the Heathens, a n d the Causes o f T h e i r E r r o r s ) . T h e content o f n a t u r a l r e l i g i o n — a very scanty c o n t e n t — i s universally a d m i t t e d b y a l l m e n , because i t proceeds solely f r o m n a t u r a l reason. T h i s content can be reduced to the belief i n the existence o f a " Supreme B e i n g , " to w h o m we owe a veneration consisting o f v i r t u e a n d piety, the belief t h a t m a n m u s t repent for his sins a n d , lastly, the belief i n a life to come i n w h i c h man's c o n d u c t w i l l receive its j u s t r e w a r d or j u s t p u n i s h m e n t . T h e revealed religions, according to H e r b e r t , have a historical o r i g i n a n d are d e r i v e d f r o m poetical imaginings, philosophical ideologies or the interests o f priestly classes. A c c o r d i n g to h i m , C h r i s t i a n i t y , especially i n its p r i m i t i v e f o r m , is the purest revealed religion a n d the closest to natural religion. H e r b e r t ' s argument, o f course, loses sight o f m a n y things. T h e universal agreement as to the content o f n a t u r a l r e l i g i o n is n o t so assured as he claims, nor d i d religions really originate i n the w a y he states. Besides, he overlooks the a u t h e n t i c content o f r e l i g i o n , religio, the bond between G o d and m a n . N A T U R A L M O R A L I T Y . I n a m o v e m e n t t h a t parallels deism, the E n g l i s h moralists o f the seventeenth century attempt to base m o r a l i t y o n n a t u r e a n d to make i t independent o f a l l religious or theological content. T h i s a t t e m p t is made b y the bishop R i c h a r d C u m b e r l a n d (162 2-1718), author of the book De legibus naturae, i n w h i c h he asserts t h a t m a n k i n d has a peaceful a n d benevolent social i n s t i n c t , j u s t the opposite o f Hobbes' conception. A c c o r d i n g to C u m b e r l a n d , m o r a l i t y is based o n the experience o f n a t u r e a n d h u m a n behavior; the good is t h a t w h i c h proves to be useful for the c o m m u n i t y . T h u s , there appears here a n early manifestation o f the social u t i l i t a r i a n i s m w h i c h is to c u l m i n a t e i n the nineteenth c e n t u r y i n the w o r k o f J e r e m y B e n t h a m a n d J o h n Stuart M i l l . O t h e r B r i t i s h moralists f i n d the basis for m o r a l i t y , n o t i n experience, b u t i n the direct, a p r i o r i self-evidence o f reason. M o r a l i t y consists i n a d j u s t i n g oneself to the true n a t u r e o f the things and r e l a t i n g oneself to t h e m a c c o r d i n g to their m a n n e r o f b e i n g ; direct i n t u i t i o n shows us this n a t u r e o f the things. This m o v e m e n t is chiefly represented b y R a l p h C u d w o r t h (1617-1688) a n d S a m u e l Clarke (1675-1729). C u d w o r t h
British Philosophy w r o t e The True Intellectual System of the Universe a n d A Treatise Concerning Eternal and Immutable Morality. Clarke was also a n o t a b l e metaphysic i a n , w h o meditated p r o f o u n d l y o n the p r o b l e m o f the D e i t y a n d c a r r i e d o n a discerning correspondence w i t h L e i b n i z . H i s most i n teresting w o r k is A Discourse Concerning the Being and Attributes of God. B u t the most interesting a n d characteristic f o r m o f B r i t i s h m o r a l philosophy is t h a t o f Shaftesbury ( A n t h o n y Ashley C o o p e r , t h i r d earl o f Shaftesbury, 1671-1713), a u t h o r ofCharacteristics of Men, Manners,
Opinions, and Times. H i s is the ethics o f the moral sense: m a n has a n i n n a t e faculty for j u d g i n g behavior a n d personality ( a n d this j u d g m e n t is v a l i d ) a n d for deciding o n t h e i r m o r a l qualifications, a p p r o v i n g o r rejecting them. I t is this d i r e c t m o r a l sense w h i c h influences men's decisions a n d guides t h e m , especially i n evaluating a t y p e o f personality i n its t o t a l i t y , a b e a u t i f u l a n d harmonious f o r m o f h u m a n soul. Shaftesbury is influenced b y Greek a n d Renaissance ideas, a n d his ethics is deeply tinged w i t h estheticism. Shaftesbury's influence i n a r t a n d l i t e r a t u r e was very widespread i n B r i t a i n , a m o n g the thinkers o f the F r e n c h E n l i g h t e n m e n t a n d a m o n g the G e r m a n classicists f r o m H e r d e r t o Goethe. 4.
LOCKE
J o h n L o c k e was b o r n i n 1632 a n d d i e d i n 1704. A t O x f o r d he studied philosophy, medicine and the n a t u r a l sciences; later a n d w i t h greater interest he studied Descartes a n d B a c o n ; he also established contact w i t h R o b e r t Boyle, the great E n g l i s h physicist a n d chemist, a n d w i t h T h o m a s S y d e n h a m , the physician. I n the househ o l d o f the first earl o f Shaftesbury (the grandfather o f the abovem e n t i o n e d moralist) he h e l d the position o f counselor, physician a n d t u t o r o f the earl's son a n d grandson. This connection l e d L o c k e i n t o politics. H e emigrated d u r i n g the r e i g n o f James I I a n d later took p a r t i n the second English r e v o l u t i o n o f 1688. H e l i v e d i n H o l l a n d a n d F r a n c e for a number o f years. Locke's influence has been extremely i m p o r t a n t , greater t h a n t h a t o f any other E n g l i s h philosopher. T h r o u g h his leadership, e m p i r i c i s m , w h i c h found i n h i m its most able a n d fortunate expounder, came to dominate eighteenth-century thought. L I F E A N D WORKS.
Locke's most i m p o r t a n t w o r k is the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, published i n 1690. H e also wrote p o l i t i c a l w o r k s — T w o Treatises on Government—and the Letters on Toleration, w h i c h defined his position o n religious matters. T H E I D E A S . Locke, also, is a n empiricist: the o r i g i n o f knowledge is experience. As is customary w i t h English thinkers, he uses the w o r d
Loch
" idea " i n a very b r o a d sense: i t includes everything t h a t one thinks or perceives, the whole content o f consciousness; understood i n this way, i t conies close to the m e a n i n g o f the Cartesian cogitatio, to w h a t today w e w o u l d call representation or, better yet, percepts. A c c o r d i n g to Locke, ideas are n o t i n n a t e , as C o n t i n e n t a l r a t i o n a l i s m h a d thought. T h e soul is tamquam tabula rasa, like a clean slate o n w h i c h n o t h i n g has been w r i t t e n . T h e ideas come f r o m experience, w h i c h can be o f two classes: external perception o b t a i n e d b y means o f the senses, or sensation; a n d i n t e r n a l perception o f psychical states, or reflection. I n either case reflection operates o n m a t e r i a l i n t r o d u c e d b y sensation. T h e r e are two kinds o f ideas: simple ideas a n d complex ideas. T h e f o r m e r result directly f r o m a single sense or f r o m several senses simultaneously, f r o m reflection, or, finally, f r o m a c o m b i n a t i o n of sensation a n d reflection. Complex ideas are the result of the a c t i v i t y of the m i n d , w h i c h combines or associates simple ideas. Locke distinguishes a m o n g simple ideas those w h i c h have objective v a l i d i t y ( p r i m a r y qualities) f r o m those w h i c h have o n l y subjective v a l i d i t y (secondary qualities). T h e p r i m a r y qualities ( n u m b e r , figure, extension, m o t i o n , solidity, a n d so on) belong to the bodies a n d cannot be separated f r o m t h e m ; the secondary qualities (color, odor, taste, temperature, a n d the like) are subjective sensations o f the m a n w h o perceives t h e m . T h i s d i s t i n c t i o n is n o t o r i g i n a l w i t h L o c k e — i t dates f r o m ancient philosophy, figuring i n philosophic t h o u g h t f r o m the t i m e o f the Greek atomists to t h a t o f Descartes—but i n Locke's p h i losophy i t plays an i m p o r t a n t role. M e m o r y is the basis o n w h i c h complex ideas are f o r m e d . Simple ideas are n o t instantaneous; rather, they leave a n impression i n the m i n d ; thus they can be c o m b i n e d or associated w i t h other ideas. This concept o f association is o f great importance i n E n g l i s h psychology. T h e modes, the notions o f substance and r e l a t i o n are complex ideas a n d result f r o m the associative a c t i v i t y of the m i n d . T h u s , i n the final instance a l l these ideas, i n c l u d i n g the ideas of substance a n d the very idea o f G o d , proceed f r o m experience, b y means o f successive abstractions, generalizations a n d associations. Locke's empiricism l i m i t s the possibility of knowledge, especially i n r e g a r d to the great t r a d i t i o n a l themes of metaphysics. W i t h h i m there begins the distrust o f the cognitive faculty t h a t is to c u l m i n a t e i n H u m e ' s skepticism a n d w h i c h w i l l oblige K a n t to f o r m u l a t e the crux o f the p r o b l e m of the v a l i d i t y a n d possibility of r a t i o n a l knowledge. E T H I C S A N D T H E S T A T E . Locke's ethics presents c e r t a i n inconsistencies. I n general, he is a determinist, a n d does n o t g r a n t t h a t h u m a n w i l l is free; however, he a d m i t s a certain freedom of indifference w h i c h
British Philosophy allows m a n to decide. M o r a l i t y , i n d e p e n d e n t o f r e l i g i o n , consists o f a c c o m m o d a t i n g oneself to a n o r m , w h i c h can be d i v i n e l a w , the l a w o f the State, or the n o r m o f c o m m o n social o p i n i o n . W i t h respect to the State, Locke is the t y p i c a l representative o f l i b e r a l ideology. H e returned to E n g l a n d f r o m H o l l a n d o n the same boat w i t h W i l l i a m o f O r a n g e — t h e k i n g o f the l i m i t e d m o n a r c h y accompanied b y the theoretician o f the l i m i t e d m o n a r c h y . Locke rejects Filmer's advocacy o f a p a t r i a r c h a l i n s t i t u t i o n a n d his d o c t r i n e o f the d i v i n e r i g h t a n d absolute p o w e r o f kings. Locke's p o i n t o f departure is analogous to t h a t o f H o b b e s : the n a t u r a l state. For L o c k e , however, this t e r m ( w h i c h he considers t o include equality a n d l i b e r t y , since a l l m e n have the same experience o f b i r t h a n d possess the same faculties) does n o t have an aggressive tinge. O b l i g a t i o n is b o r n o u t o f l i b e r t y ; there is a master a n d l o r d o f a l l things, w h o is G o d , a n d H e imposes a natural law. I n Hobbes, e q u a l i t y gave rise to a fierce a n d aggressive independence, whereas i n L o c k e i t promotes love for one's fellow m a n ; m e n ought never to b r e a k this n a t u r a l l a w . S t r i c t l y speaking, m e n are n o t b o r n in a state o f l i b e r t y (therefore t h e parents w h o have to raise t h e m exercise a l e g i t i m a t e j u r i s d i c t i o n over t h e m ) , b u t are indeed b o r nfor liberty. A n d so the k i n g does n o t h a v e absolute a u t h o r i t y ; rather, he receives his a u t h o r i t y f r o m the people. T h u s the proper f o r m o f the State is t h a t o f a constitutional a n d representative m o n a r c h y , independent of the C h u r c h , tolerant o n matters o f r e l i g i o n . Such is Locke's t h o u g h t , w h i c h corresponds to the f o r m o f g o v e r n m e n t adopted i n E n g l a n d as a result o f the r e v o l u t i o n o f 1688, w h i c h e l i m i n a t e d c i v i l wars a n d revolutions f r o m the previously t u r b u l e n t English history a n d established a p e r i o d o f i n t e r n a l peace t h a t has already lasted for more t h a n a q u a r t e r o f a m i l l e n n i u m . U s i n g Ortega's t e r m i n o l o g y , we could say t h a t a skinlike State replaced one that h a d been i n the nature o f a n o r t h o p e d i c apparatus.
5.
BERKELEY
L I F E A N D W O R K S . George Berkeley was b o r n i n I r e l a n d i n 1685. H e studied at T r i n i t y College i n D u b l i n , a n d later became d e a n o f D r o more a n d o f D e r r y . Still later he w e n t o f f to A m e r i c a w i t h visions o f f o u n d i n g a great missionary college i n the Bermudas. A f t e r r e t u r n i n g to I r e l a n d he was named A n g l i c a n bishop o f Cloyne. T o w a r d the end o f his life he m o v e d to O x f o r d , where he d i e d i n 1753. Berkeley was f u l l o f a religious spirit t h a t p r o f o u n d l y influenced b o t h his p h i l o s o p h y a n d his life. H i s philosophic f o r m a t i o n depends o n Locke especially; he is a n actual c o n t i n u e r o f Locke's t h o u g h t even t h o u g h he presents a
Berkeley
2
J7
m u c h more intense a n d d i r e c t preoccupation w i t h metaphysical questions t h a n does his predecessor. Berkeley was v e r y greatly influenced b y the Platonism t h a t was t r a d i t i o n a l i n E n g l a n d ; his spiritualist philosophy was shaped b y his religious convictions, w h i c h he attempts to defend against attacks b y skeptics, materialists a n d atheists. T h u s he arrives at one o f the most extreme forms o f i d e a l i s m ever k n o w n . H i s p r i n c i p a l works are Essay Towards a Mew Theory of Vision; Three
Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous; Principles of Human Knowledge; Alciphron, or the Minute Philosopher, a n d the Siris, i n w h i c h along w i t h metaphysical a n d m e d i c a l reflections he expounds the virtues o f pine tar. M E T A P H Y S I C S . Locke's theory o f ideas leads Berkeley i n t o the r e a l m o f metaphysics. Berkeley is a n o m i n a l i s t ; he does n o t believe that general ideas exist; for example, there cannot be a general idea o f a triangle, because any t r i a n g l e i m a g i n e d is necessarily either equil a t e r a l , isosceles or scalene, whereas the general idea o f the triangle does n o t i n v o l v e such distinctions. Berkeley refers to the intuition o f the triangle, b u t he does n o t believe i n the concept or t h o u g h t o f the triangle, w h i c h is t r u l y universal.
Berkeley professes a n extreme f o r m o f s p i r i t u a l i s m a n d idealism. F o r h i m , m a t t e r does n o t exist. P r i m a r y qualities are j u s t as subjective as secondary qualities; extension or solidity are ideas, j u s t as color is an i d e a ; they are a l l the content o f m y p e r c e p t i o n ; there is no material substance behind the ideas. T h e i r being is exhausted i n being perceived : esse estpercipi; this is Berkeley's basic p r i n c i p l e . T h e entire m a t e r i a l w o r l d is b u t a representation or perception o f m i n e . T h e only t h i n g t h a t exists is the s p i r i t u a l Self, o f w h i c h we have a n i n t u i t i v e certainty. Therefore i t is senseless to speak o f causes o f physical phenomena a n d to give real m e a n i n g to t h a t expression; there are o n l y concordances, relations between ideas. Physical science establishes these laws o r connections between phenomena, w h i c h are understood as ideas. These ideas proceed f r o m G o d ; H e puts t h e m i n o u r spirit: the r e g u l a r i t y o f these ideas, w h i c h is based o n God's w i l l , causes to exist for us w h a t we call a corporeal w o r l d . O n c e a g a i n a n d under very different circumstances we f i n d G o d as the basis o f the w o r l d i n this new f o r m o f idealism. A c c o r d i n g to M a l e b r a n c h e or L e i b n i z , we can see a n d k n o w the things o n l y i n or t h r o u g h G o d ; according to Berkeley, there are o n l y the spirits and G o d , w h o is the O n e who acts u p o n the spirits a n d creates a " m a t e r i a l " w o r l d for t h e m . W e do not o n l y see the things i n G o d ; rather, l i t e r a l l y , " w e l i v e , move and exist in God."
2J<S
British Philosophy 6.
HUME
D a v i d H u m e is the philosopher w h o carries to its u l t i m a t e consequences the empiricist d i r e c t i o n i n i t i a t e d by Bacon. H u m e was b o r n i n Scotland i n 1 7 1 1 a n d d i e d i n 1776. H e studied l a w a n d p h i l o s o p h y ; at various times he l i v e d i n France for a n u m b e r o f years, a n d he h a d a great influence o n the Encyclopedists a n d E n l i g h t e n m e n t circles. H e was secretary to the English embassy, a n d his fame spread q u i c k l y t h r o u g h o u t E n g l a n d , France a n d G e r m a n y . LIFE A N D WORKS.
His most i m p o r t a n t w o r k is the Treatise on Human Nature. H e also wrote several recastings o f different parts o f this w o r k , such as An
Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, An Inquiry Concerning the Principles ofMorals a n d the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. I n a d d i t i o n to his philosophical w o r k , H u m e was extremely p r o d u c t i v e i n the field o f historiography, the most i m p o r t a n t w o r k i n this field being his great History of England. S E N S A T I O N A L I S M . I n H u m e e m p i r i c i s m reaches an extreme a n d becomes sensationalism. A c c o r d i n g to h i m , ideas are necessarily based on i n t u i t i v e impressions. Ideas are pale a n d lifeless copies o f direct i m pressions ; the belief i n the c o n t i n u i t y o f r e a l i t y is based on this capacity to reproduce experienced impressions a n d to create a w o r l d o f representations. Berkeley h a d made a general c r i t i q u e o f the concept o f substance, b u t he h a d restricted i t to m a t e r i a l a n d corporeal substance. T h e " t h i n g s " have a being that is exhausted i n being perceived; b u t the spiritual r e a l i t y o f the Self t h a t does the perceiving remains f i r m . H u m e makes a new c r i t i q u e of the idea o f substance. A c c o r d i n g to his theory, perception a n d reflection p r o v i d e us w i t h a number of elements w h i c h we a t t r i b u t e to substance, w h i c h acts as a basis or support for t h e m ; b u t nowhere do we find the impression o f substance. I encounter impressions o f color, consistency, taste, odor, extension, roundness, smoothness, a l l o f w h i c h I refer to a n u n k n o w n something t h a t I call a n apple, a substance. Sensible impressions have more v i t a l i t y t h a n imagined impressions, a n d this causes us to believe i n the reality o f w h a t is represented. T h u s , H u m e explains the n o t i o n o f substance as the result o f a n associative process, w i t h o u t observing that a c t u a l l y the opposite is t r u e : m y direct a n d i m m e d i a t e perception is o f the apple, a n d the sensations are abstract elements w h i c h appear o n l y as I complete m y perception o f the thing.
There is another aspect to this p r o b l e m . H u m e does n o t l i m i t his criticism to m a t e r i a l substances, b u t extends i t to the ego itself. T h e ego is also a b u n d l e or collection o f perceptions or contents o f consciousness that succeed one another c o n t i n u a l l y . T h u s the ego does n o t have
The Scottish School
ZJ9
substantial r e a l i t y ; i t is a result o f the i m a g i n a t i o n . H u m e forgets t h a t i t is / w h o have the perceptions, t h a t i t is / w h o f i n d myself facing t h e m a n d t h a t therefore I a m distinct f r o m t h e m . W h o unites this collection o f states o f consciousness a n d makes t h e m constitute a soul ? W h e n form u l a t i n g his sensationalist criticism, H u m e does not even touch u p o n the p r o b l e m o f the ego; apart f r o m the p r o b l e m o f its nature, substant i a l or not, the ego is something basically distinct f r o m its representations. Together w i t h the c r i t i q u e o f the concepts o f substance and the soul, H u m e makes a c r i t i q u e o f the concept o f cause. A c c o r d i n g to h i m , the causal connection signifies only a relationship o f coexistence and succession. W h e n a p h e n o m e n o n repeatedly coincides w i t h another o r succeeds i t i n t i m e , b y v i r t u e o f an association of ideas we call the first " c a u s e " a n d the second " e f f e c t , " a n d we say t h a t the latter occurs because the former takes place. N o m a t t e r h o w m a n y times this succession is repeated, i t does not afford us the c e r t a i n t y o f its indefinite rei t e r a t i o n , a n d i t does not allow us to a f f i r m a causal l i n k i n the sense o f a
necessary condition. S K E P T I C I S M . I n H u m e , empiricism reaches its ultimate consequences a n d becomes skepticism. K n o w l e d g e c a n n o t achieve metaphysical t r u t h . T h e i n t i m a t e a n d immediate convictions b y w h i c h m a n lives cannot be p r o v e d or refuted. T h e reason for this is that, as n o m i n a l i s m long ago p o i n t e d o u t , i n this instance knowledge is not knowledge o f the things. As a result, reality becomes perception, experience, idea. T h e c o n t e m p l a t i o n o f these ideas, w h i c h do not succeed i n b e i n g things, w h i c h are n o t h i n g b u t subjective impressions, is skepticism. W e see w h a t happens to idealism w h e n G o d is n o t present to assure transcendency, to save the w o r l d a n d m a k e the ideas be ideas of the things a n d cause there to be something t h a t merits the name of reason. K a n t , f o l l o w i n g i n Hume's footsteps, w i l l have to investigate this p r o b l e m f r o m its roots; and his philosophy w i l l consist of precisely a
Critique ofPure Reason.
7.
T H E
SCOTTISH
SCHOOL
W i t h i n the scope o f British philosophy, a n d more precisely i n Scotl a n d , there arises i n the eighteenth century a n d at the beginning o f t h e nineteenth a reaction to Hume's skepticism. T h i s movement constitutes the so-called " S c o t t i s h S c h o o l , " w h i c h h a d considerable i n fluence o n the C o n t i n e n t . T h e chief thinkers o f this school are T h o m a s R e i d (1710-1796) a n d D u g a l d Stewart (1753-1828). R e i d w r o t e An Inquiry into the Human
z6o
British Philosophy
Mind on the Principles of Common Sense, Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, Essays on the Active Powers of Man; Stewart w r o t e Elements of the Philosophy of the Human Mind, Outlines of Moral Philosophy, The Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers. T h e i r p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e is always e m p i r i c a l ; experience is the o r i g i n of knowledge. B u t this experience is understood as s o m e t h i n g direct a n d i m m e d i a t e t h a t gives us the r e a l i t y o f the things as they are understood b y sane reason. T h e p h i losophy o f the Scottish School consists o f an appeal t o c o m m o n sense. C o m m o n sense is the m a x i m u m source o f c e r t a i n t y ; a l l c r i t i cism leaves its i m m e d i a t e self-evidence beyond d o u b t . T h i s acceptat i o n places us d i r e c t l y i n the midst o f the things, a n d a g a i n anchors us i n their reality. B u t the philosophical insufficiency o f t h e Scottish School d i d n o t p e r m i t i t to solve, or even to state i n a m a t u r e m a n n e r , the p r o b l e m w i t h w h i c h i t was concerned. I n spite of this, the Scottish School exercised p r o l o n g e d influence i n France (Pierre P a u l R o y e r - C o l l a r d , a n d so on) a n d i n S p a i n , especially i n Catalonia, where its i m p r i n t is seen i n J a i m e L u c i a n o Balmes a n d i n M a r c e l i n o M e n é n d e z y Pelayo.
The
Enlightenment
T h e complex intellectual m o v e m e n t called the E n l i g h t e n m e n t cannot be considered a mere manifestation o f empiricism. I t is m a d e u p of various other elements—many o f w h i c h derive f r o m idealist r a t i o n a l ism a n d , i n the final analysis, f r o m Gartesianism. H o w e v e r , there are t w o reasons for our i n c l u d i n g the t h o u g h t o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t i n the c u r r e n t o f e m p i r i c i s m : i n the first place, as we have seen, B r i t i s h e m p i r i c i s m depends i n large p a r t o n C o n t i n e n t a l r a t i o n a l ism, a n d does n o t exclude ( b u t , o n the contrary, presupposes) the influence o f this school o f t h o u g h t ; secondly, the E n l i g h t e n m e n t , i n the scant measure i n w h i c h i t is philosophy, is more concerned w i t h the problems of knowledge t h a n w i t h metaphysical questions, a n d follows e m p i r i c a l paths, c a r r y i n g t h e m to the extreme o f absol u t e sensationalism. O n the other h a n d , the most i m p o r t a n t elements o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t — d e i s m , p o l i t i c a l ideology c h a m p i o n i n g freed o m a n d representative government, tolerance, the economic doctrines, a n d the l i k e — h a v e t h e i r o r i g i n i n the empirical t h o u g h t o f t h e sixteenth to eighteenth centuries. T h e epoch o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t , the eighteenth century, represents the e n d o f the metaphysical speculation o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y . A f t e r almost a century of intense a n d p r o f o u n d philosophical a c t i v i t y , we encounter a new hiatus i n w h i c h philosophic thought loses m o m e n t u m a n d becomes t r i v i a l . T h i s is a n epoch i n w h i c h the ideas o f the preceding p e r i o d are disseminated. A n d dissemination always has the f o l l o w i n g consequence: i n order to act u p o n the masses, i n order to t r a n s f o r m the face o f history, ideas must necessarily become t r i v i a l , z6i
The Enlightenment
z6z
lose t h e i r precision a n d d i f f i c u l t y , become superficial images o f t h e m selves. T h e n , i n r e t u r n for ceasing to be w h a t they r e a l l y are, they are spread about a n d the general p u b l i c shares t h e m . I n the eighteenth c e n t u r y , a group o f able a n d ingenious writers w h o w i t h as m u c h insistence as i m p r o p r i e t y c a l l themselves " p h i l o s o p h e r s " e x p o u n d , i n t e r p r e t a n d popularize a series o f ideas c o n c e i v e d — i n a different f o r m a n d a different scope—by the great European m i n d s o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y . After a few years these ideas permeate the atmosphere, become p a r t o f the a i r one breathes, suppositions w h i c h everyone takes for granted, a n d t h e n we find ourselves i n a different w o r l d . E u r o p e has changed completely i n a r a p i d , almost brusque, revolutionary manner. A n d this t r a n s f o r m a t i o n o f p o p u l a r t h o u g h t w i l l soon shape the radical a l t e r a t i o n o f history that we k n o w as the F r e n c h Revolution.
i.
T H E ENLIGHTENMENTI N FRANCE
I n the last years o f the seventeenth century a n d t h r o u g h o u t the eighteenth, France u n d e r w e n t a change i n ideas a n d convictions w h i c h altered the character o f its politics, social o r g a n i z a t i o n a n d s p i r i t u a l life. T h e most substantial changes took place between 1680 a n d 1715; a l l that followed was a process o f dissemination a n d p r o p a g a t i o n o f the new ideas, b u t b y t h a t t i m e the o u t l i n e o f F r e n c h history h a d already changed. T h e r e was a transition f r o m the notions o f discipline, hierarchy, a u t h o r i t y a n d dogma to those o f independence, e q u a l i t y a n d n a t u r a l r e l i g i o n , even a decided opposition to C h r i s t i a n i t y . I t was the transition f r o m the m e n t a l i t y of Bossuet to t h a t o f V o l t a i r e : the c r i t i q u e o f a l l t r a d i t i o n a l convictions, f r o m the C h r i s t i a n f a i t h to absolute monarchy, b y means o f a review o f history a n d social norms. I t was, i n effect, a r e v o l u t i o n i n the intellectual presuppositions o f F r a n c e a n d , since France was t h e n the g u i d i n g n a t i o n i n the E u r o p e a n c o m m u n i t y , o f all Europe. (See Paul Hazard's m a g n i f i c e n t book, The European Mind, 1680-1715.)
The Encyclopedia P I E R R E B A Y L E . T h e E n l i g h t e n m e n t wishes to gather together a l l scientific knowledge a n d m a k e i t available to a w i d e p u b l i c . S t r i c t l y philosophical problems, n o t to m e n t i o n theological ones, are relegated t o a secondary level. " P h i l o s o p h y " at this t i m e refers p r i n c i p a l l y to the findings o f n a t u r a l science a n d the e m p i r i c a l a n d deistic doctrines o f the B r i t i s h ; i t is a p o p u l a r i z a t i o n o f the less metaphysical portions o f Cartesianism a n d , at the same t i m e , o f British t h o u g h t . F o l l o w i n g the
The Enlightenment in France
263
Cartesian t r a d i t i o n , the t h o u g h t o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t is rationalistic a n d , consequently, r e v o l u t i o n a r y : i t attempts to state a n d solve p r o b lems once a n d for a l l , m a t h e m a t i c a l l y , w i t h o u t t a k i n g historical circumstances i n t o account. F o l l o w i n g the British t r a d i t i o n , the prev a i l i n g theory o f knowledge is sensationalist empiricism. These t w o philosophic currents, the C o n t i n e n t a l a n d the British, converge i n the Enlightenment. T h e suitable organ for this p o p u l a r i z a t i o n of philosophy a n d science is the " e n c y c l o p e d i a , " a n d , i n fact, the first typical representative o f this movement, Pierre Bayle (1647-1706), d i d w r i t e one, the Dictionnaire historique et critique. Bayle subjected numerous questions to keen negative criticism. A l t h o u g h he d i d n o t deny the truths o f r e l i g i o n , he m a d e t h e m completely independent o f reason, a n d even c o n t r a r y to reason. H e was a skeptic w h o believed that reason can comprehend n o t h i n g o f dogma. I n a n age t h a t d o t e d o n reason, this v i e w p o i n t h a d to end i n a complete estrangement f r o m religion ; abstention becomes resolute denial, and the enemies of C h r i s t i a n i t y later make copious use o f Bayle's ideas. T H E E N C Y C L O P E D I S T S . M u c h m o r e i m p o r t a n t t h a n Bayle's w o r k , however, was the so-called Encyclopedia, or Rational Dictionary ofSciences,
Arts and Trades (Encyclopédie, ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers), issued f r o m 1750 to 1780, despite attempts to prevent its p u b l i c a t i o n . T h e general editors o f the Encyclopedia were Denis D i d e r o t a n d Jean L e R o n d d ' A l e m b e r t ; the contributors i n c l u d e d the greatest figures o f the t i m e : V o l t a i r e , Montesquieu, Rousseau, A n n e R o b e r t Jacques T u r g o t , P a u l - H e n r i H o l b a c h a n d m a n y others. T h e Encyclopedia, w h i c h at first glance seemed n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n a dict i o n a r y , was the greatest vehicle for Enlightenment ideas. W i t h considerable circumspection a n d skill, i t interpolated c r i t i c a l thoughts a n d attacked the C h u r c h a n d most p r e v a i l i n g convictions. D ' A l e m b e r t was a great m a t h e m a t i c i a n ; besides his scientific c o n t r i b u t i o n s to the
Encyclopedia, he wrote its Preliminary Discourse (Discours préliminaire), w h i c h is a n attempt to classify the sciences. D i d e r o t was a prolific w r i t e r , a novelist, p l a y w r i g h t a n d essayist, whose m a t u r e o r i e n t a t i o n was almost totally materialistic a n d atheistic. S E N S A T I O N A L I S M A N D M A T E R I A L I S M . T h i s t r e n d i n the E n l i g h t e n m e n t originates w i t h a C a t h o l i c priest, the A b b é Étienne de C o n d i l l a c , w h o was b o r n i n 1715 a n d d i e d i n 1780. H i s major w o r k is the Traité des sensations, i n w h i c h he expounds a purely sensationalistic theory. C o n d i l l a c imagines a statue w h i c h w o u l d be endowed, one b y one, w i t h a l l the senses, f r o m the sense o f smell to that o f t o u c h . W h e n the statue possessed all the senses, i t w o u l d have full h u m a n consciousness
The Enlightenment a n d , therefore, f u l l cognitive powers. Condillac, w h o was a C h r i s t i a n , excludes f r o m his sensationalism the era previous to the f a l l o f A d a m , as w e l l as the life beyond the grave, a n d speaks o f G o d a n d o f the simple soul as a u n i t o f consciousness. B u t later this exclusion is n o t m a i n t a i n e d . Whereas the so-called ideologues, especially the C o u n t Destutt de T r a c y (1754-1836), i n d u l g e according to their m e t h o d s i n psychology o r logic, Condillac's sensationalism is c o n t i n u e d b y the most extreme g r o u p among the Encyclopedists, who t u r n i t i n t o a mere atheistic m a t e r i a l i s m . T h e p r i n c i p a l thinkers o f this g r o u p are the physician J u l i e n de L a M e t t r i e (1709-1751), a u t h o r o f a book w i t h a very e l o q u e n t t i t l e : L'homme machine; C l a u d e - A d r i e n Helvétius (1715-1771), w h o w r o t e De l'Esprit; a n d , i n p a r t i c u l a r , a G e r m a n w h o resided i n Paris, B a r o n P a u l - H e n r i H o l b a c h (1723-1789), a u t h o r o f the Système de la nature a n d La morale universelle. A l l these w r i t e r s believe t h a t the o n l y means of knowledge is sensory perception ; t h a t everything i n n a t u r e is m a t t e r , i n c l u d i n g the foundation o f psychical life ; that religions a r e a decept i o n a n d t h a t , n a t u r a l l y , i t is impossible to speak o f the existence o f G o d or the i m m o r t a l i t y of the h u m a n soul. T h e p h i l o s o p h i c a l value o f t h e i r r a t h e r u n o r i g i n a l works is v e r y slight. M u c h g r e a t e r interest attaches to those E n l i g h t e n m e n t thinkers w h o are o r i e n t e d t o w a r d history a n d the theory o f society a n d the State, especiaLly V o l t a i r e , M o n t e s q u i e u a n d Rousseau, a n d also T u r g o t and A n t o i n e - N i c o l a s de Condorcet, the theorists o f the idea o f progress. V O L T A I R E . François A r o u e t de V o l t a i r e (1694-1778) was a great figure o f his age. His fame was e x t r a o r d i n a r y and w o n h i m the friendship o f Frederick the Great o f Prussia and Catherine t h e Great o f Russia. H i s success and influence were u n m a t c h e d i n t h e eighteenth c e n t u r y . N o other w r i t e r was so w i d e l y read, commented o n , discussed, or a d m i r e d . Voltaire's actual value does not measure u p t o his r e n o w n . I n considering his w o r k we m u s t distinguish three aspects : its r e l a t i o n to l i t e r a t u r e , to philosophy a n d to history.
V o l t a i r e is a n excellent stylist. I n his works F r e n c h prose reached one o f its peaks; he is enormously keen, w i t t y and a m u s i n g . H i s short stories a n d novels, especially, reveal a splendid l i t e r a r y talent. H i s p h i l o s o p h i c a l m e r i t is something q u i t e different. H e is neither an o r i g i n a l n o r a profound t h i n k e r . H i s Dictionnaire philosophique is saturated w i t h the philosophic ideas o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y , w h i c h he adopts i n their most superficial guise: e m p i r i c i s m , d e i s m a n d a p o p u l a r i z a t i o n o f the physical i m a g e o f the w o r l d . T h u s V o l t a i r e has n o real philosophical interest. H i s antireligious ideas, "which were devastating i n his o w n age, appear ingenuous a n d harmless to us
The Enlightenment in France t o d a y . H e h a d a complete lack o f comprehension for religion a n d Christianity, a n d i n his hostility he reveals most clearly the inconsistency o f his thought. I t is n o t merely that he attacks Christianity, b u t t h a t he does i t i n so supremely superficial a w a y , t a k i n g a n anticlerical position w i t h o u t even a n awareness o f the real issue. Voltaire's most interesting a n d p r o f o u n d c o n t r i b u t i o n to the development o f t h o u g h t is his historical w o r k . H e w r o t e a book o n the great age p r i o r to his o w n , called Le siècle de Louis XIV. B u t his p r i n c i p a l historical p r o d u c t i o n is the Essai sur les mœurs et l'esprit des nations. I n this w o r k there appears for the first t i m e a new conception o f history. H i s t o r y is no longer a chronicle, a mere n a r r a t i o n o f deeds or events; instead, its object becomes the customs a n d spirit o f nations. T h u s the nations appear as historical units, each w i t h its o w n spirit a n d customs : the G e r m a n concept o f Volksgeist, " national s p i r i t , " is, as O r t e g a has shown, merely a translation o f this esprit des nations. V o l t a i r e finds a new object for history, a n d i n his hands i t takes the first step t o w a r d becoming a n authentic science, although i t does n o t succeed i n overc o m i n g naturalism. M O N T E S Q U I E U . B a r o n Montesquieu (Charles de Secondât, 1689¬ 1755) made a different sort o f c o n t r i b u t i o n to the thought o f the E n l i g h t e n m e n t . H e , too, is a w i t t y w r i t e r ; this is most evident i n his Lettres persanes, a graceful a n d i r o n i c critique o f F r e n c h society of his day. B u t , above a l l , he is a p o l i t i c a l a n d historical w r i t e r . H i s major w o r k is Uesprit des lois ( T h e S p i r i t o f the L a w s ) . H i s thesis is t h a t the laws o f each c o u n t r y are a reflection o f the people w h o live b y t h e m ; the n a t u r a l i s m o f the age causes M o n t e s q u i e u to emphasize especially the influence o f climate. M o n t e s q u i e u recognizes three types o f constitutions w h i c h are repeated i n history. First o f a l l , there is despotism, w i t h no place for a n y t h i n g b u t fearful obedience; then there are t w o types o f States i n whose history he discovers a guiding motive, different for each. I n a monarchy the p r i n c i p a l m o t i v e is honor; i n a republic, virtue. W h e n these qualities are l a c k i n g i n their respective forms o f government, a n a t i o n does not f u n c t i o n as i t should. W i t h this theory Montesquieu furnishes a decisive c o m p l e m e n t to Voltaire's i d e a o f history : a d y n a m i c element w h i c h explains historical events. (Cf. Ortega : Guillermo Diltheyy la idea de la vida [ W i l h e l m D i l t h e y a n d the Idea o f L i f e ] . )
Rousseau Despite his connections w i t h the Encyclopedists, Rousseau merits a place o f his o w n i n the history o f thought. Jean-Jacques Rousseau was
266
The
Enlightenment
b o r n i n Geneva i n 1712, the son o f a Protestant watchmaker. H i s c h i l d h o o d was one of precocious i n t e l l e c t u a l s t i m u l a t i o n ; his later life was t h a t o f a n u n h a p p y wanderer, a n d frequently revealed traces o f a b n o r m a l i t y . H i s Confessions, a book i n w h i c h he r o m a n t i c a l l y exhibits his inmost feelings, is the best account o f his life. H e w o n a prize offered b y the A c a d e m y o f D i j o n w i t h his Discours sur les sciences et les arts, i n w h i c h he denied t h a t the sciences a n d arts h a d c o n t r i b u t e d t o w a r d the p u r i f i c a t i o n o f manners. This study m a d e h i m famous. Rousseau believes t h a t m a n is good b y nature, a n d t h a t i t is c i v i l i z a t i o n w h i c h ruins h i m . H i s i m p e r a t i v e is the return to nature. This is Rousseau's famous naturalism, w h i c h is based o n religious ideas proceeding f r o m his o r i g i n a l C a l v i n i s m . Rousseau denies o r i g i n a l sin a n d affirms the n a t u r a l goodness o f m a n , to w h i c h m a n o u g h t to r e t u r n . These ideas inspired another w o r k of his, the Discours sur V origine de V inégalité parmi les hommes (Discourse o n the O r i g i n o f I n e q u a l i t y a m o n g M e n ) ; he applied his ideas to the field o f education i n his famous book Emile. Rousseau represents a strong sentimental reaction against the c h i l l y rationalistic a r i d i t y o f the Encyclopedia ; he w r o t e a passionate, tearful novel w h i c h was immensely successful : Julie, ou la Nouvelle Héloïse. T h i s n a t u r a l i s m is l i n k e d w i t h the idea o f r e l i g i o n . Rousseau converted to Catholicism, then back to C a l v i n i s m a n d ended u p a deist; his religion is sentimental ; he finds G o d i n n a t u r e , for w h i c h he feels a deep a d m i r a t i o n . B u t i t is Rousseau's social philosophy t h a t has h a d the most i m p o r tant consequences. H i s w o r k o n this subject is the Contrat social. M e n , i n their state o f n a t u r e , make a tacit c o n t r a c t . T h i s is t h e o r i g i n o f society a n d the State, w h i c h , according t o Rousseau, are thus based o n a v o l u n t a r y agreement; the i n d i v i d u a l is p r i o r to society. I t is man's w i l l t h a t determines the State ; b u t , aside f r o m the w i l l of the i n d i v i d u a l , Rousseau distinguishes between t w o collective wills : the volonté générale a n d the volonté de tous. T h e latter is t h e s u m o f the wills o f all the i n d i viduals, a n d is almost never u n a n i m o u s ; t h e volonté générale is the one w h i c h has p o l i t i c a l importance : i t is the w i l l o f the m a j o r i t y , which is the will of the State. T h i s is the i m p o r t a n t element. T h e w i l l of the m a j o r i t y , j u s t because i t is the w i l l of the m a j o r i t y , is the w i l l of the c o m m u n i t y as such, t h a t is, even of those w h o disagree ; for such people, i t is t h e i r w i l l not as i n d i v i d u a l s , b u t as members o f the State. T h i s is the p r i n c i p l e o f democracy a n d o f universal suffrage. W h a t is significant here is, o n the one h a n d , respect for minorities, w h o have the r i g h t t o a t t e m p t t o make their w i l l p r e v a i l , a n d , a t the same t i m e , acceptance b y t h e minorities o f the general w i l l as a n expression o f the w i l l o f the p o l i t i c a l c o m m u n i t y . T h e consequences of these ideas were p r o f o u n d . Rousseau
The "Aufklärung"
in Germany
z6y
died i n 1778, before the beginning o f the F r e n c h R e v o l u t i o n , b u t his ideas were a n essential element i n the b a c k g r o u n d o f the R e v o l u t i o n a n d influenced E u r o p e a n political history for a l o n g t i m e .
2.
T H E "AUFKLÄRUNG" I N GERMANY
Corresponding to the E n l i g h t e n m e n t i n France there was a similar, b u t not i d e n t i c a l m o v e m e n t i n G e r m a n y , w h i c h is also called a n " e n l i g h t e n m e n t " or " i l l u m i n a t i o n " : Aufklärung. H e r e , too, i t consisted o f a p o p u l a r i z a t i o n o f philosophy, especially t h a t o f L e i b n i z , as w e l l as o f B r i t i s h t h o u g h t . B u t i n Germany this spirit o f enlightenment is less r e v o l u t i o n a r y a n d less i n i m i c a l to r e l i g i o n ; the R e f o r m a t i o n h a d already achieved the transformation o f the content o f G e r m a n r e l i gion, a n d the Aufklärung does not come face to face w i t h a Catholic t r a d i t i o n o f l o n g s t a n d i n g , as d i d the E n l i g h t e n m e n t i n France. O t h e r wise, the same rationalistic a n d scientific spirit prevails i n G e r m a n y , a n d the Prussian c o u r t o f Frederick the Great, a l o n g w i t h the B e r l i n A c a d e m y o f Sciences, is a great center o f E n l i g h t e n m e n t ideology. W O L F F . T h e p o p u l a r i z e r o f L e i b n i z ' philosophy was C h r i s t i a n W o l f f (1679-1759), a professor at H a l l e . A f t e r w a r d , expelled f r o m the U n i v e r s i t y o f H a l l e , he t a u g h t at M a r b u r g , b u t was later reinstated at H a l l e w i t h great honors b y Frederick. W o l f f , a rather u n o r i g i n a l thinker, w r o t e m a n y works i n L a t i n a n d even m o r e i n G e r m a n ; the general title o f these w o r k s is frequently Rational Thoughts on Wolff i n t r o d u c e d the G e r m a n language i n t o the universities a n d i n t o p h i l o sophic w r i t i n g s . H i s t h o u g h t consisted o f the p o p u l a r i z a t i o n a n d dissemination o f L e i b n i z ' philosophy, especially its less p r o f o u n d aspects. F o l l o w i n g the precedents set b y J o h a n n C l a u b e r g a n d Jean Leclerc at the end o f the seventeenth century, he i n t r o d u c e d the division o f metaphysics i n t o ontology (or general metaphysics), r a t i o n a l theology, rational psychology a n d r a t i o n a l cosmology ( t h a t is, the ontology o f G o d , m a n a n d the w o r l d ) . T h e philosophy studied as a m a t t e r o f course i n G e r m a n y i n the eighteenth c e n t u r y was t h a t o f W o l f f ; i t is thus W o l f f ' s philosophy t h a t K a n t w i l l have to deal w i t h most d i r e c t l y
i n his Critique of Pure Reason. E S T H E T I C S . A philosophical discipline w h i c h is established independently i n the G e r m a n E n l i g h t e n m e n t is esthetics, the science o f beauty, w h i c h is here treated autonomously for the first time. T h e founder o f esthetics was a p u p i l o f W o l f f , Alexander B a u m g a r t e n (1714-1762), whose Aesthetica was published i n 1750. Also related to these problems is the historical a c t i v i t y o f J o h a n n J o a c h i m W i n c k e l m a n n , a contemporary o f B a u m g a r t e n , w h o w r o t e the famous History of the Art of
i68
The Enlightenment
Antiquity, w h i c h is so i m p o r t a n t for t h e study o f the a r t a n d c u l t u r e o f Greece. L E S S I N G . T h e w r i t e r w h o most clearly represents the spirit o f the Aufklärung is G o t t h o l d E p h r a i m Lessing (1729-1781). H e was a great l i t e r a r y figure, a poet, dramatist a n d essayist. H e was deeply concerned w i t h philosophic questions, especially w i t h the m e a n i n g o f history a n d the quest for knowledge. Lessing is the a u t h o r o f the famous saying t h a t i f G o d were to show h i m t r u t h i n one h a n d a n d i n the other the p a t h t h a t leads t o t r u t h , he w o u l d choose the second. H i s study o f the L a o c o ö n sculpture is another i m p o r t a n t step t o w a r d the u n d e r standing o f Greek a r t . Lessing's r a t i o n a l i s m — w i t h Spinozistic tendencies—is t o l e r a n t , n o t aggressive like V o l t a i r e ' s , a n d does n o t include Voltaire's hostility t o w a r d the C h r i s t i a n religion. T H E T R A N S I T I O N T O G E R M A N I D E A L I S M . T h e G e r m a n religious currents o f the eighteenth century—specifically t h e Pietism founded b y P h i l i p p J a k o b Spener a n d August H e r m a n n F r a n c k e — a n d the i n terest i n history lead the G e r m a n E n l i g h t e n m e n t onto different paths. Great value is once more attached t o s e n t i m e n t — a p h e n o m e n o n w h i c h appears i n France w i t h Rousseau; there is a n a t t e m p t to find the m e a n i n g o f the great stages o f history; there is a renewed a d m i r a t i o n for the M i d d l e Ages a n d G e r m a n c u l t u r e , as a reaction t o the Aufklärung, w i t h its c o l d rationalism. T h e r e appears the movement called Sturm und Drang. H e r d e r is perhaps the b r i d g e between the t w o trends. L a t e r there appears a group o f writers w h o prepare the w a y for o r accompany G e r m a n idealism, the great phase o f philosophy w h i c h extends f r o m K a n t to Hegel.
3. Vico's D O C T R I N E O F H I S T O R Y
A n o u t l i n e o f the intellectual p a n o r a m a o f the eighteenth c e n t u r y should n o t o m i t t h e figure o f the N e a p o l i t a n philosopher G i a m b a t tista V i c o (1668-1744), w h o stands somewhat a p a r t f r o m t h e rest. A l t h o u g h , strictly speaking, his t h o u g h t does n o t f i t exactly i n t o t h e forms a n d suppositions of the E n l i g h t e n m e n t , his historical position is determined b y s i m i l a r conditions, a n d his philosophy is frequently related to t h a t o f the founders o f t h a t i n t e l l e c t u a l movement. V i c o was b o r n d u r i n g the period w h e n Naples was a Spanish vicer o y a l t y . H e was a j u r i s t and a philologist. H e was the first to cast d o u b t o n the existence o f H o m e r (formerly there h a d merely been c o n t r o versies over t h e place o f his b i r t h ) . F o r V i c o , H o m e r , Zoroaster a n d Hercules are n o t persons, b u t personified epochs o r c u l t u r a l cycles. After p u b l i s h i n g several works i n L a t i n — D e antiquissima Italorum
Vico's Doctrine of
History
269
sapientia ex linguae Latinae originibus eruenda ( O n the M o s t A n c i e n t W i s d o m o f the I t a l i a n s as Discovered i n the O r i g i n s o f the L a t i n L a n g uage), De uno universi juris principio etfine uno ( O n the One P r i n c i p l e a n d the O n e E n d o f U n i v e r s a l L a w ) , De constantia jurisprudentis ( O n the Constancy o f the J u r i s t ) — V i c o w r o t e his famous Scienza nuova, the f u l l title o f w h i c h is Principii di scienza nuova d'intorno alia comune natura delle nazioni (Principles o f a N e w Science Concerning the C o m m o n N a t u r e o f the N a t i o n s ) ; the first e d i t i o n o f this w o r k dates f r o m 1730, a n d the definitive edition (called the Scienza nuova seconda) f r o m 1744. Vico's p h i l o s o p h y — o n e o f great c o m p l e x i t y a n d confused structure —considers a series o f nations as the protagonists o f universal history. V i c o establishes a series o f p r i o r axioms (degnita) a n d remarks t h a t , whereas philosophy studies m a n as he o u g h t to be, l a w considers h i m as he is. Legislators take man's vices a n d t r a n s f o r m t h e m i n t o useful activities: f r o m savagery is derived the m i l i t a r y ; f r o m avarice, c o m merce ; f r o m a m b i t i o n , the life o f the c o u r t i e r . W e are halfway between the idea o f n a t u r e a n d the idea o f history. H u m a n customs have a cert a i n nature, a structure w h i c h is manifested i n language (therefore he calls history " p h i l o l o g y " ) a n d especially i n proverbs. T h e historical e v o l u t i o n o f the nations, w h i c h are the subjects o f history, occurs i n accordance w i t h an alternate r h y t h m o f corsi a n d ricorsi ( " c y c l e s " a n d " r e - c y c l e s " ) . T h e corso consists o f three phases: (a) T h e first phase, characterized b y the d o m i n a n c e o f the imagination over the reasoning f a c u l t y ; this i m a g i n a t i o n is creative. V i c o calls i t divine, because i t creates gods. M e n are savage, b u t they revere the gods they have created; i t is the era o f theocracy, (b) T h e heroic age: there is a belief i n heroes or demigods o f d i v i n e o r i g i n ; the f o r m o f government is aristocracy, (c) T h e human age: people are k i n d , i n t e l l i gent, modest a n d reasonable; government is based on equality, a n d appears i n the f o r m o f monarchy. T h e m e n o f the first of these ages are religious a n d pious; those o f the second are litigious and irascible; those o f the t h i r d are a c c o m m o d a t i n g a n d d i l i g e n t , their manners h a v i n g been f o r m e d b y civic duties. T o these three stages correspond three languages: one for silent religious acts (mental language), another for the exercise o f arms (language o f words o f c o m m a n d ) , a t h i r d for conversing (language for u n d e r s t a n d i n g one another). V i c o ' s ideas present an o u t l i n e o f a theory o f the functions of speech. W h e n a n a t i o n has passed t h r o u g h the three stages, the cycle begins a n e w ; this is the ricorso. I t is a p e r i o d n o t o f decadence, b u t o f r e b a r b a r i z a t i o n . These ideas are echoed i n Comte's theory o f the three states, b u t i n Comte's theory the positive state is the
The Enlightenment
270
definitive one, i n contrast to w h a t happens w i t h the h u m a n age i n Vico's outline.
4.
SPANISH PHILOSOPHERS
OF T H E E N L I G H T E N M E N T
I n Spain the E n l i g h t e n m e n t h a d characteristics o f its o w n : its p r i n c i p a l accomplishment was to b r i n g Spain u p to the level o f the era by i n t r o d u c i n g the science a n d philosophy t h a t h a d been developed elsewhere since the seventeenth c e n t u r y ; i n other words, to Europeanize Spain (despite the opposition o f the partisans o f n a t i o n a l p u r i t y ) . T h e m e n o f the Spanish E n l i g h t e n m e n t were n o t irreligious, b u t they c o m b a t e d the abuses o f the C h u r c h a n d the lack of freedom, w h i l e r e m a i n i n g l o y a l to their f a i t h . T h e y were champions o f p o l i t i c a l a n d social r e f o r m , b u t n o t revolutionaries; the great m a j o r i t y o f t h e m were dismayed b y the violence a n d suppression of freedom d u r i n g the F r e n c h R e v o l u t i o n . T h e reigns o f Fernando V I (1746-1759) a n d Carlos I I I (1759-1788), especially, represent an i n t e l l i g e n t transformation o f Spanish society. T h i s social progress was p a r t i a l l y undone d u r i n g the r e i g n o f Carlos I V , i n w h i c h a strong r e a c t i o n set i n , a n d finally destroyed b y the Napoleonic invasion w i t h its p o l i t i c a l struggles a n d b y the absol u t i s m o f Fernando V I I (1814-1833). T h e Spanish E n l i g h t e n m e n t was a t i m e o f assimilation o f ideas rather t h a n o f c r e a t i v i t y , a n d thus is n o t of great philosophical i m p o r t a n c e ; i t m e r e l y signifies the i n c o r p o r a t i o n o f m o d e r n t h o u g h t at a time w h e n Scholasticism h a d become least p r o d u c t i v e . A leadi n g figure was the Benedictine Benito Jerónimo Feijoo (1676-1764), a G a l i c i a n , w h o was a professor at O v i e d o and the a u t h o r o f the Teatro critico universal i n eight volumes a n d the Cartas eruditas y curiosas, i n five volumes. A great essayist whose works were w i d e l y read, he was understanding a n d tolerant and concerned w i t h r o o t i n g o u t mistaken beliefs a n d superstitions. O t h e r i m p o r t a n t thinkers were Feijoo's friend a n d collaborator, Father M a r t í n Sarmiento (1695¬ 1771); the philosopher a n d physician Andrés Piquer (1711-1772),
author o f Lógica moderna a n d Filosofía moral para la juventud española; the doctor M a r t í n M a r t i n e z , w h o w r o t e Filosofía escéptica; a n d A n t o n i o X a v i e r Pérez y L ó p e z , a u t h o r o f Principios del orden esencial de la naturaleza. A n o t h e r interesting personality was the Jesuit J u a n Andrés, a u t h o r o f Origen, progreso y estado actual de toda la literatura, a ten-volume w o r k t h a t perfectly reflects the temper a n d accomplishments o f the era. T w o other Jesuit writers were Esteban de Arteaga (La belleza ideal) a n d L o r e n z o Hervás y P a n d u r o (Historia de la vida
Spanish Philosophers of the Enlightenment
2 j i
del hombre, Catálogo de las lenguas de las naciones conocidas). T h e greatest t h i n k e r o f the century was Gaspar M e l c h o r de Jovellanos ( 1 7 4 4 ¬ 1811), a u t h o r o f i n n u m e r a b l e essays a n d monographs. H i s most b r i l l i a n t insights are contained i n his Diarios (Journals).* * See my books Los Españoles (1962) and La España posible en tiempo de Carlos I I I (1963) [Obras, V I I ] .
The Formation
i.
of the Modern
PHILOSOPHY AND
Epoch
HISTORY
Ideas are conceived i n the r e a l m o f philosophy b u t end u p h a v i n g historical consequences. Concepts become generalized a n d are slowly converted i n t o a n a c t i v a t i n g force t h a t reaches d o w n to the masses. T h i s phenomenon has always taken place, b u t occurs to a greater degree t h a n ever i n the epoch w h i c h we are n o w considering. T h e entire eighteenth c e n t u r y , a l l t h a t we k n o w as the E n l i g h t e n m e n t , consisted of a process i n w h i c h ideas conceived i n previous centuries a c q u i r e d influence a n d social r e a l i t y . A n d this circumstance is n o t coincidental. T o a c e r t a i n extent, a l l eras exist on ideas; however, i t is n o t necessary for ideas to show themselves as ideas, as theories; i n fact, ideas generally o b t a i n force b y disguising themselves—for example, as t r a d i t i o n a l forms. B u t i n the eighteenth century ideas have i m p o r t a n c e precisely because they are ideas; people endeavor to live a c c o r d i n g to those ideas, according to raison. T h e ideas do n o t have to disguise t h e m selves, a n d thus acquire m a x i m u m force. Precisely the same t h i n g happens i n regard to the metaphysical ideas, a n d the religious a n d theological ideas related to t h e m , t h a t I have a t t e m p t e d to set f o r t h i n the preceding chapters. T h e ideas g r a d u a l l y spread to a n d exercise influence over w i d e r a n d w i d e r circles. Slowly, everyday life a n d the sciences become shaped b y the results w h i c h philosophy o b t a i n e d for t h e m previously. A n d i n this fashion the face of the w o r l d is changed. T h e deep-rooted reasons for the change are p r i o r a n d r e m a i n h i d d e n ; w h a t manifests itself is the complete alteration o f the surface o f life. B u t this change can o n l y be 2JZ
The Rationalist State
z
73
understood properly a n d i n its entirety i f one recognizes the subt e r r a n e a n forces that are i n operation. W e must investigate p h i losophy's place i n history after this change, and see h o w its character is shaped b y its very s i t u a t i o n .
2.
T H E RATIONALIST
STATE
T h e epoch subsequent to the Renaissance is characterized b y the discovery o f m a t h e m a t i c a l reason—rationalism. I t was d u r i n g the sixteenth a n d seventeenth centuries t h a t the great r a t i o n a l systems of physics a n d philosophy were constructed: those o f Galileo, N e w t o n , Descartes, Spinoza, L e i b n i z . T h i s rationalism has obvious historical consequences. A B S O L U T I S M . F r o m the v e r y b e g i n n i n g of the m o d e r n State, the absolute State, people commence to discuss reason, the reason o f the State: Machiavelli's ragione di Stato. T h e State n o w has a personality, a n d also its reasons; therefore, i t operates like a m i n d . T h i s rationalist personification of the State makes its appearance at the same t i m e as the m o d e r n nations. Descartes mentions politics o n l y i n passing; he says t h a t things are better made w h e n they are made according to reason a n d b y o n l y one person, rather t h a n b y several. T h i s is the r a t i o n a l j u s t i f i c a t i o n of absolute monarchy, a n d f r o m this same p r i n c i p l e there emerges, later o n , the revolutionary spirit. T h e States created d u r i n g the Renaissance become powerful units o f absolute power. D I P L O M A C Y . A t this m o m e n t , a new concept o f d i p l o m a c y makes itself evident. I t amounts to n o t h i n g more t h a n the s u b s t i t u t i o n o f an abstract personal relationship for the direct relationship between States; this diplomacy results f r o m the unification t h a t the nations have achieved; previously i t existed only i n the m e d i e v a l I t a l i a n States—precisely those states w h i c h most resembled nations i n the m o d e r n sense o f the w o r d . ( T h i s m a y be the reason w h y i t took I t a l y so l o n g to become a unified c o u n t r y . ) Thanks to d i p l o m a c y , a consequence o f unification, the u n i t y itself becomes accentuated. France as France begins to exist for F r e n c h m e n a n d for people o f other countries w h e n they see i t represented a n d personified, c a r r y i n g o n relations w i t h other countries. T h e change can be demonstrated b y c o m p a r i n g the consciousness of Spanishness o f a subject of the C a t h o l i c Kings w i t h t h a t o f a subject o f P h i l i p I I . A t Isabella's death, F e r d i n a n d of A r a g o n c a n still " r e t u r n to his States"; i n the t i m e o f P h i l i p I I this w o u l d n o longer have been possible. A n a t i o n is personified by its absolute k i n g ; relations between nations are c a r r i e d o u t a n d
The Formation of the Modern Epoch personalized i n the conversation o f a few men. T h e various States begin to be factors i n the consciousness o f all individuals.
3.
T H E
REFORMATION
T h e R e f o r m a t i o n has a s t r i c t l y religious dimension, t h e o r i g i n o f w h i c h c o u l d easily be traced t h r o u g h the M i d d l e Ages to L u t h e r . H o w e v e r , we are not going to consider this aspect, b u t the v i t a l a n d historical dimension of the R e f o r m a t i o n — t h a t is, the s p i r i t u a l situat i o n t h a t m a d e i t possible a n d the new situation t h a t i t created. F R E E D O M O F I N T E R P R E T A T I O N . T h i s most i m p o r t a n t element i n the R e f o r m a t i o n is the concept o f freedom o f i n d i v i d u a l i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f religious texts. This concept assumes t h a t , instead o f there being a C h u r c h a u t h o r i t y to i n t e r p r e t the sacred texts, each i n d i v i d u a l must i n t e r p r e t t h e m for himself. T h i s is p u r e r a t i o n a l i s m ; there is a presentim e n t here o f Descartes' statement, " G o o d sense is the most w i d e l y d i s t r i b u t e d t h i n g i n the w o r l d . " B u t L u t h e r is the least r a t i o n a l m a n i n the w o r l d , a n enemy of reason a n d o f philosophy. W h a t does this m e a n ? I t is one more p r o o f t h a t , i n spite o f his o w n i n d i v i d u a l ideas, a m a n is oriented b y the beliefs o f the epoch i n t o w h i c h he is b o r n , a n d t h a t the p r e v a i l i n g suppositions o f the epoch influence h i m m u c h m o r e t h a n his o w n ideas do ( O r t e g a ) . T h e destruction of the C h u r c h is the necessary consequence o f this spirit o f free i n t e r p r e t a t i o n ; as soon as one says, ' m a n a n d G o d a l o n e , " the C h u r c h becomes an obstacle placed between m a n a n d G o d . T h e C h u r c h has always kept very close w a t c h over mystical positions because they skirt this danger. A C a t h o l i c mystic's awesome statement is w e l l k n o w n : " G o d and I , a n d no w o r l d at a l l . " M a n is alone w i t h G o d . Protestant f r a c t i o n i z a t i o n is the result o f this concept; p l u r a l i t y is o f the essence o f Protestantism. L e t us investigate t w o aspects o f the reformed c h u r c h — t h e " n a t i o n a l " C h u r c h (for example , the A n g l i c a n ) a n d that characterized b y the Augsburg Confession—in o r d e r to see h o w they contain w i t h i n themselves the seed o f their o w n dissolution. 1
T h e n a t i o n a l c h u r c h revolves a r o u n d the person o f the k i n g . T h e k i n g o f E n g l a n d or some G e r m a n p r i n c e is the head o f the C h u r c h , w h i c h is n a t i o n a l , political. A f u n d a m e n t a l l i n k between r e l i g i o n a n d politics, between the C h u r c h a n d the State, is thus created. T h e State becomes a religious state, b u t something quite different f r o m w h a t a religious state was i n the M i d d l e Ages. T h e medieval State assumes a n d accepts the Church's religious p r i n c i p l e s ; now, r a t h e r the o p p o site o c c u r s — r e l i g i o n is affected b y n a t i o n a l principles; the cujus regio,
The Reformation ejus religio f o r m u l a is established. T o a certain extent, this spirit penetrates the Catholic countries also, a n d i n Protestant a n d Catholic countries alike people speak o f the " a l l i a n c e between the throne a n d the a l t a r , " forgetting those extremely clear words i n the Gospels: My kingdom is not of this world. T h e various m o d e r n inquisitions—so unlike the medieval I n q u i s i t i o n — a r e really instruments o f the State rather t h a n organs of the C h u r c h . T h i s nationalization o f the C h u r c h leads to the loss o f its religious c o n t e n t a n d its absorption w i t h temporal interests. O u r era is n o t witnessing the disappearance o f Protestantism, b u t i t does indeed witness frequent shortcomings o f the " n a t i o n a l churches." O n the other h a n d , the A u g s b u r g Confession, for example, assumes a n agreement on matters o f f a i t h . People subscribe to i t because they are i n agreement w i t h its d o g m a t i c content. I t is a n association of isolated i n d i v i d u a l s ; the i n d i v i d u a l s constitute a C h u r c h , b u t they are not within a Church, as Catholics are ; the distinction is obvious. However, a comm u n i t y founded on c o n c o r d a n t o p i n i o n is subject to change. Governed b y the spirit o f i n d i v i d u a l i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , o p i n i o n evolves i n m a n y ways a n d becomes d i v i d e d ; the single Confession is succeeded by various sects ; these i n t u r n splinter even more, a n d thus we arrive at the i n d i v i d u a l creed. So-called l i b e r a l Protestantism consists o f the suppression of almost a l l d o g m a t i c content, to such a degree that the w o r d " C h r i s t i a n i t y " is p r a c t i c a l l y a mere anachronism w h e n applied toit. T H E P R O B L E M O F T H E R E F O R M A T I O N . T h e Catholic countries undertake the C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n , t h a t is, a R e f o r m a t i o n i n reverse. I n this w a y a schism is created between the Protestant a n d Catholic countries, a n d E u r o p e , w h i c h was handed d o w n to us as a u n i t , appears to be split i n t w o . C o n t e m p l a t i n g these t w o halves into w h i c h Europe has been d i v i d e d , we can believe ( i ) t h a t u n i t y is m a i n t a i n e d b y Catholicism, a n d t h a t the R e f o r m a t i o n is a t r a n s i t o r y a n d u n a d u l terated e r r o r ; (2) t h a t Protestantism represents Europe's destiny, and t h a t the Catholic populations are reactionaries (Hegel a n d François G u i z o t h i n t at this, a n d i t is France t h a t precludes t h e m f r o m accepting this historical i n t e r p r e t a t i o n ) ; or (3) that b o t h w i l l subsist a n d that Europe's u n i t y is a dialectical u n i t y , a tense, d y n a m i c u n i t y made u p o f those t w o halves. Observe t h a t this latter position does not touch u p o n the question o f the i n h e r e n t t r u t h o f C a t h o l i c i s m ; the Christian m i n d finds itself facing the fact t h a t G o d has allowed the Reformation to take place, j u s t as, o n the other h a n d , H e has a l l o w e d more t h a n t w o religions to coexist. O n e cannot ignore the fact o f the R e f o r m a t i o n , a n d the C h u r c h has not i g n o r e d i t ; note t h a t the C h u r c h does not take the
276
The Formation of the Modern Epoch
same position w h e n faced w i t h the b r e a k w i t h the O r t h o d o x Eastern C h u r c h a n d w h e n faced w i t h the Protestant m o v e m e n t : i n the first instance, the C h u r c h loses the obedience o f a l l the Eastern countries a n d remains u n c h a n g e d ; i n the second instance, i t conducts a CounterReformation : the existence o f the C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n demands the existence o f the R e f o r m a t i o n , no mere schism, w h i c h p r o v o k e d the Counter-Reformation. T h i s position creates a new p r o b l e m for us: W h a t is the n a t u r e o f the i n t e r a c t i o n between the Catholic a n d Protestant worlds ? W h a t is the nature of the u n i t y t h a t these t w o w o r l d s establish ? A n d , f i n a l l y , w h a t must the synthesis be like t h a t resolves this a n t i n o m y ? W e c o u l d t h i n k — a n d this idea, welcome to a C a t h o l i c m i n d , is seen not to be c o n t r a dicted b y the evidence o f our a g e — t h a t the synthesis m i g h t consist o f the u l t i m a t e reabsorption o f Protestantism b y Catholicism after the former comes to the end of w h a t is erroneous i n its p a t h a n d reaches its u l t i m a t e consequences. Perhaps Protestantism w i l l refute itself historically a n d f i n d itself i n a superior t r u t h . T h e resultant u n i t y o f the C a t h o l i c C h u r c h w o u l d n o t b y a n y means be the same as t h a t u n i t y w h i c h i t h a d p r i o r to the R e f o r m a t i o n ; i t w o u l d n o t be as t h o u g h the R e f o r m a t i o n had never t a k e n place. Rather, i t w o u l d be preserved i n this concrete f o r m o f its absorption.
4.
MODERN
SOCIETY
W e have seen the roles played b y t w o m a j o r elements o f the m o d e r n age: r a t i o n a l i s m a n d the R e f o r m a t i o n . N o w we must see h o w these elements influence the era's social structure, how, by v i r t u e o f p h i losophy a n d theology, a l l m o d e r n l i f e — f r o m the intellectual to the social a n d p o l i t i c a l — a c q u i r e s a new air t h a t culminates i n the eighteenth c e n t u r y w i t h the t w o great historical facts o f the E n l i g h t enment a n d the French R e v o l u t i o n .
Intellectual Life T H E C H A R A C T E R O F T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L . W h a t kinds o f intellectuals do these centuries produce ? W h a t characterizes a n intellectual m a n o f this p e r i o d , a n d to w h a t purpose is his l a b o r ? W h a t does being a n intellectual i n the seventeenth century i n v o l v e , and how does i t differ f r o m being a n intellectual i n the M i d d l e Ages, i n the Renaissance or i n the eighteenth century ?
D u r i n g the M i d d l e Ages, the true i n t e l l e c t u a l is the cleric, especially the m o n k . T h e w o r k o f Scholasticism, w i t h its connotation o f a school, a c o l l a b o r a t i o n , is carried out b y m e n w o r k i n g j o i n t l y w i t h i n the
Modern Society O r d e r or the U n i v e r s i t y . T h e philosopher o f this p e r i o d is a m a n o f the monastery, o f the c o m m u n i t y , or rather a magister. H e is the Scholastic —scholasticus—who collaborates on the great collective w o r k . D u r i n g the Renaissance, the intellectual is a humanist. H e is a m a n o f the w o r l d , a l a y m a n , w h o cultivates his personality, chiefly i n the dimensions o f a r t a n d literature, b o t h o f w h i c h are saturated w i t h the essence o f classical c u l t u r e . T h e Renaissance intellectual had a certain freshness i n his m a n n e r o f v i e w i n g nature a n d the w o r l d . Pietro Bembo is t y p i c a l , i n spite o f his cardinal's hat, a n d so also are Thomas M o r e , Erasmus, G u i l l a u m e Bude (Budaeus) a n d Vives. N o w we find a different type o f i n t e l l e c t u a l : Galileo, Descartes, Spinoza. T h e i n t e l l e c t u a l of this epoch, as O r t e g a has pointed out, is the m a n o f m e t h o d . H e does n o t h i n g b u t seek for methods, open new roads t h a t a l l o w h i m to reach the things, new things, new regions. H e is the m a n w h o , using the essential i m p e r a t i v e o f r a t i o n a l i t y , constructs his science. T h e m a n o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y has an effective a n d precise awareness o f m o d e r n i t y . I t was Renaissance m a n w h o h a d symptoms, signs o f m o d e r n i t y , who went a b o u t f i n d i n g ancient things, w h i c h seemed new precisely because they were so o l d . I f the Renaissance is seen i n d e t a i l , i t becomes clear t h a t i n m a n y ways i t was a negative movement. T h e things that the m o d e r n age accomplishes are anchored more i n the M i d d l e A g e s — i n O c c a m , E c k h a r t , the school o f P a r i s — t h a n i n the Renaissance. T h e Renaissance is dazzling, b u t i t has little intellectual p r o f u n d i t y . Renaissance m e n such as Vives a n d R a m u s t u r n their backs o n the M i d d l e A g e s — a n d their a t t i t u d e endures: a century later, w h i l e people's very lives derive f r o m medieval roots, the M i d d l e Ages a n d Scholasticism are still t h o u g h t to be completely false. L e i b n i z is the first m a n to possess a sense o f history a n d recognize Scholasticism's value as w e l l as the value o f the new science. T H E T H E M E O F N A T U R E . T h e R e f o r m a t i o n split Europe i n t o two halves—not one reformed a n d one u n r e f o r m e d , b u t b o t h reformed, although i n different senses. There is one exception: France, w h i c h is not a country o f the R e f o r m a t i o n , b u t neither, perhaps, of the CounterR e f o r m a t i o n . France does combat the Calvinists, a n d even goes to the extreme o f St. Bartholomew's Eve, b u t i t also indulges i n politics cont r a r y to t h a t o f A u s t r i a a n d , d u r i n g the T h i r t y Years' W a r , makes political alliances w i t h o u t regard for religious ties. F u r t h e r m o r e , France promulgates the E d i c t o f Nantes a n d establishes the G a l l i c a n C h u r c h , still R o m a n Catholic, still subordinate to the Pope i n r e l i gious matters, b u t w i t h a strong nationalistic tinge. I t is perhaps for this reason t h a t L e i b n i z , w h e n a t t e m p t i n g to reunite the Catholic a n d Protestant Churches, approached neither the hierarchs o f the Spanish
276
The Formation of the Modern Epoch
C h u r c h (except the bishop Rojas Spinola) n o r R o m e d i r e c t l y , b u t instead, Bossuet i n p a r t i c u l a r — t h e spokesman o f the G a l l i c a n C h u r c h . W e find a very i m p o r t a n t difference between those E u r o p e a n countries w h i c h l i v e u n d e r the C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n a n d the rest o f E u r o p e : i n the C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n lands there are p r a c t i c a l l y no investigators o f n a t u r a l science, except for the I t a l i a n physicists, the chief o f w h o m , Galileo, became e m b r o i l e d w i t h the ecclesiastical authorities. T h e C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n countries do cultivate another discipline w h i c h is very i m p o r t a n t : jus naturae. Instead o f physics, they practice n a t u r a l law, a j u r i d i c a l science o f m a n . B u t there is a s i m i l a r i t y u n d e r l y i n g the differences: the l a w t h a t is studied is natural law, a n d the theme o f nature reappears here, too. T h i s theory o f law, as developed b y the Spanish theologians, is still based on G o d ; b u t at the hands of the D u t c h a n d E n g l i s h — H u g o Grotius, Shaftesbury, H u t c h e s o n — i t becomes strictly n a t u r a l l a w , a theory o f l a w o f h u m a n nature. Philosophers speak o f n a t u r a l r e l i g i o n , or deism, a n d o f a n a t u r a l G o d . T h i s is a l l p a r t of the naturalistic movement t h a t c u l m i nates i n Rousseau. T h e C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n r a n a strange course: i t r e m a i n e d i n t e l lectually self-contained a n d isolated, a n d d i d n o t f o r m ties w i t h the new philosophy a n d the new science. Descartes a n d L e i b n i z are acquainted w i t h the Spanish theologians, b u t the Spanish themselves do not establish connections w i t h the m o d e r n philosophers; they are interested o n l y i n their o w n k i n d o f philosophy. T h e y r e m a i n outside the new E u r o p e a n intellectual c o m m u n i t y , a n d thus the splendid Spanish flowering is soon cut off and does n o t have direct f r u i t f u l consequences. B u t i t must be noted that the w o r k o f the Spanish thinkers f r o m V i t o r i a to Suarez was not sterile; i t is j u s t t h a t its effectiveness became evident at a far remove f r o m w h a t was seemingly its con-
tinuation. T H E I N T E L L E C T U A L U N I T Y O F E U R O P E . I n the seventeenth century there is a s p i r i t u a l c o m m u n i t y i n Europe w h i c h is guided b y philosophy a n d n a t u r a l science a n d even by theology. O n e element o f this comm u n i t y has disappeared today, b u t possibly i t w i l l reappear before long, after these years of crisis: the intellectuals o f the seventeenth century used to w r i t e each other l o n g letters. A considerable p a r t o f the works o f Galileo, Descartes, Spinoza, L e i b n i z , A r n a u l d , Clarke a n d a l l the representative m e n o f the age consists o f their scientific correspondence. T h i s means t h a t they were interested i n each other's endeavors a n d , w h a t is more, corrected each o t h e r ; this exchange of objections gave a n enormous precision to the works o f the p e r i o d . I t is the age i n w h i c h m e n publish b r i e f pamphlets w h i c h transform p h i -
Modem Society
¿79
losophy w i t h fifty l u c i d l y w r i t t e n pages : Discours de la méthode, Discours
de la métaphysique, Monadologie. Social Transformation T h e profession o f " i n t e l l e c t u a l " d i d n o t yet exist as such i n the seventeenth century. Descartes, m u c h to the chagrin o f his f a m i l y , d i d n o t choose a profession—the m i l i t a r y , l a w or the C h u r c h : gens de robe etgensd'épée—but shut himself u p w i t h his w o r k a n d studies. H e was a m a n o f independent means a n d good social standing, un homme de bonne compagnie, a n d devoted himself to intellect u a l pursuits w i t h o u t becoming a cleric o r a professor. As the seventeenth century proceeds, the type o f m a n w h i c h Descartes inaugurated becomes more prevalent. THE
N E W CLASSES.
O n the one h a n d , the intellectual clears a p a t h for himself, w h i l e , o n the other, the n o b i l i t y become dependents o f the r o y a l palace. E v e n at the end o f the eighteenth century the intellectual class has n o t yet become completely established. Stendhal quotes a nobleman's r e m a r k
about Rousseau : Cela veut raisonner de tout etríapas quarante mille livres de rente ( T h a t fellow wants to philosophize a b o u t everything a n d his income isn't even forty thousand livres). B u t at the same t i m e a m i d d l e class is i n f o r m a t i o n ; this bourgeoisie w i l l have a share i n intellectual pursuits, because one o f its higher strata is composed o f m e n o f science. T h e traces o f feudalism die out a n d the independence o f the n o b i l i t y comes to a n end. T h e final active manifestations o f feudalism are the Fronde i n M a z a r i n ' s France a n d , i n Spain, the rising o f A n d a l u s i a u n d e r the D u k e o f M e d i n a Sidonia d u r i n g the reign o f P h i l i p I V . T h e nobles have to f o r m ties w i t h the other t w o forces, the t h i r d estate a n d the m o n a r c h y . T h e y become courtiers o f the k i n g , while at the same time establishing contact w i t h the bourgeoisie. T h e n o b i l i t y is supp o r t e d b y these t w o social elements, a n d its situation is very difficult after the French R e v o l u t i o n . T h e bourgeoisie, on the other h a n d , becomes stronger l i t t l e b y little. T h e m o n a r c h y has reached its absolute c u l m i n a t i o n — r e g a l i s m — a n d has achieved a complete organization o f the State, w h i c h begins to be a perfect machine. A u t o m a t i c a l l y , a series o f matters w h i c h h a d been considered i n d i v i d u a l a n d p r i v a t e concerns become concerns o f the State. T h e State furnishes m o r e a n d m o r e services, takes m o r e problems o n its shoulders a n d also makes its weight felt m o r e a n d more. T h i s is w h a t is k n o w n as i n t e r v e n t i o n i s m o f the State; this p r o cess expands constantly a n d today the State enters i n t o every p a r t o f o u r lives.
z8o
The Formation of the Modern Epoch
N A T U R E A N D G R A C E . W e have seen h o w R e f o r m a t i o n t h o u g h t a n d r a t i o n a l i s m involve a n interest i n nature, a p a r t f r o m G o d . I n the M i d d l e Ages, the t w o concepts o f n a t u r e a n d grace were contraposed, a n d i n the Renaissance, m a n flung himself i n t o the p u r s u i t o f nature, neglecting grace a n d forgetting the o l d C h r i s t i a n p r i n c i p l e : gratia naturam non tollit, sedperficit (grace does n o t remove n a t u r e , b u t perfects i t ) . Nineteenth-century philosophers so completely forget t h a t grace was once the c o m p a n i o n o f nature t h a t they o n l y contrast culture w i t h nature, a n d this effectively transforms the idea o f nature. T o d a y p h i losophers prefer to speak o f spirit—a w o r d r i c h i n m e a n i n g , b u t also i n a m b i g u i t y — a n d , f r o m another p o i n t o f view, ofhistory.
W i t h the Renaissance the natural mode o f t h o u g h t t r i u m p h s . T h e world ceases to be C h r i s t i a n , a l t h o u g h i n d i v i d u a l people still a r e — something very different. M a n is now a mere n a t u r a l e n t i t y . Protest a n t i s m started out w i t h a completely pessimistic conception o f m a n : i t considered h i m a fallen being whose n a t u r e was essentially corr u p t e d b y o r i g i n a l sin a n d whose justification c o u l d be achieved o n l y through faith, b y the a p p l i c a t i o n o f the merits o f C h r i s t ; works are i n o p e r a t i v e : m a n is incapable o f earning his o w n salvation. I n the face o f this view, the C o u n c i l o f the C o u n t e r - R e f o r m a t i o n at T r e n t proclaims as its theme faith and works. I n the Renaissance, m a n becomes progressively m o r e estranged f r o m G o d as a consequence o f God's inaccessibility to reason. F o r the Protestant, God's works have n o t h i n g to do w i t h grace; they are merely works o f nature, w h i c h dominate the w o r l d i n accordance w i t h physical laws; thus, m a n drifts away f r o m G o d a n d f r o m grace. T h e consequence o f this is t h a t w h e n m a n remains alone w i t h the w o r l d , accomplishing great things w i t h i t , a n d loses interest i n the p r o b l e m o f grace, he no longer considers himselfevil. Pessimism was based o n the viewp o i n t o f grace, b u t i f m a n is a natural entity a n d is enjoying great success w i t h his rationalistic physics, w h y should the o l d o u t l o o k continue ? Protestant pessimism, finding itself i n the r e a l m o f mere nature, becomes the o p t i m i s m o f Rousseau. M a n forgets a b o u t o r i g i n a l sin a n d considers himself to be naturally good. T H E F R E N C H R E V O L U T I O N . W h a t results w i l l this s i t u a t i o n have i n the eighteenth c e n t u r y ? T h e eighteenth century is the era w h i c h makes use o f the t h o u g h t o f the seventeenth. I n history there are periods o f intense c r e a t i v i t y a n d others w h i c h m a k e use o f w h a t has gone before t h e m , w h i c h d o n o t themselves grapple w i t h i m p o r t a n t o r i g i n a l problems, b u t o n l y a p p l y a n d p u t i n t o effect p r i o r discoveries. E v e r y t h i n g is o n a lower level. T h u s , i n place o f the seventeenthcentury intellectual there is the Encyclopedist, w h o is essentially a
The Loss of God
281
manifestation o f j o u r n a l i s m , b u t for w h o m science is still a l i v i n g t h i n g , even t h o u g h , i n general, i t has been previously worked out. These m e n disseminate the t h o u g h t o f the seventeenth century, o n w h i c h the f o l l o w i n g century lives. I f an idea is to f o r m the basis for l i v i n g , i t is necessary for t i m e to elapse a n d for the masses to receive the idea, not as some i n d i v i d u a l ' s conviction, b u t as a p r e v a i l i n g belief. T h i s is a slow process; as O r t e g a points out, the tempo o f the life o f a c o m m u n i t y is m u c h slower t h a n t h a t o f the life o f an i n d i v i d u a l . T h u s , i n the eighteenth century, the ladies o f Versailles discuss the themes w h i c h i n the seventeenth h a d been the p r i v a t e d o m a i n o f the most acute t h i n k e r s : Newton's physics a n d Monsieur Descartes' w h i r l w i n d s , w h i c h V o l t a i r e had made accessible to the Court. A l l this leads to the French R e v o l u t i o n . T h e Renaissance b r o u g h t us t w o things: r a t i o n a l i s m a n d the R e f o r m a t i o n . These h a d t w o results : n a t u r a l i s m a n d o p t i m i s m . W e have seen t h a t rationalism produces absolute m o n a r c h y i n a very direct m a n n e r ; b u t absolute m o n a r c h y is a phase i n a process that began i n the M i d d l e Ages. T h e medieval p e r i o d created a m i l i t a r y s p i r i t — k n i g h t h o o d — a n d the m o n a r c h is a leader w i t h pronounced m i l i t a r y traits. D u r i n g the entire course o f the seventeenth century, preparations are m a d e for a struggle between t w o forces, the m i l i t a r y a n d the i n t e l l e c t u a l . T h e concept o f m i l i t a r y c o m m a n d becomes more adapted to c i v i l i a n p o l i t i c a l life; i t becomes intellectualized. A n d since reason is essentially one and the same, a n d since w h a t reason arranges is therefore t h a t w h i c h ought to beforever, a revolutionary state o f m i n d is engendered. M e n w h o are rational a n d naturally good find themselves i n a society w h i c h was created historically, l i t t l e b y l i t t l e , i n an imperfect fashion, a n d w h i c h is based o n a m o n a r c h i c concept t h a t is no longer alive a n d o n a religious t r a d i t i o n t h a t has lost social v a l i d i t y . These m e n decide to tear d o w n the entire system i n order to create a better one r a t i o n ally, perfectly, once and for a l l : thus, they demand the " rights o f m a n a n d o f the c i t i z e n " a n d make no concessions to history. W e find ourselves i n the F r e n c h R e v o l u t i o n . T h e w o r l d is to be organized i n a definitive, geometrical way. Raison is to govern f r o m n o w o n . 5. T H E Loss o r G O D I do not wish to i m p l y that the e v o l u t i o n o f the p r o b l e m o f G o d , w h i c h I have studied i n detail i n the preceding pages, was the only i n t e l l e c t u a l cause o f a l l the changes i n Europe at this time. T h a t w o u l d be a n exaggeration; b u t i t is true t h a t a very i m p o r t a n t g r o u p o f these changes consists o f the transition f r o m a situation based o n C h r i s t i a n i t y , w i t h the idea o f G o d as the f o u n d a t i o n o f all the sciences a n d w i t h a
The Formation of the Modern Epoch d i v i n e l a w a n d religious m o r a l i t y based o n dogma a n d theology, to another t o t a l l y different s i t u a t i o n , i n w h i c h G o d is replaced b y h u m a n reason a n d nature. T h e r e is a factor w h i c h accelerates the t r i u m p h a n d dissemination o f these ideas w h i c h do a w a y w i t h G o d a n d d r i v e H i m o u t o f the sciences a n d intellectual researches. I t is the p r i m a c y w h i c h the m o d e r n age grants to negative concepts. I n d e e d , i n the m o d e r n p e r i o d , the s t a r t i n g hypothesis is t h a t i t is necessary to j u s t i f y a positive outlook, whereas a negative o u t l o o k is v a l i d f r o m the outset. T h u s , one must make a n effort to demonstrate freedom as opposed to determ i n i s m , or the existence o f the external w o r l d or the possibility o f knowledge. I do not m e a n to say t h a t i t is n o t really necessary to prove these things; I a m referring to the tendency, the a t t i t u d e w h i c h is today's p o i n t o f departure. Fontenelle has a p a r t i c u l a r l y expressive passage i n this connection: " T h e testimony o f those w h o believe a n established t h i n g carries no w e i g h t as a support o f their belief; b u t the testimony o f those w h o do n o t believe i t is strong enough to destroy i t — s i n c e those w h o believe i t m a y n o t be i n f o r m e d about the reasons for n o t believing i t , b u t i t is n o t possible that those w h o do n o t believe i t are n o t i n f o r m e d about the reasons for believing i t . " T h u s , b y v i r t u e o f this supremacy o f the negative, the progressive secularization o f sciences acquires more strength. T h i s explains w h y , j u s t as i n the past p a r t i c u l a r reasons were n o t given for each o f those sciences to justify their b e i n g based o n the D e i t y , so n o w sufficient proofs are n o t given to e x p l a i n the exclusion o f G o d f r o m i n t e l l e c t u a l disciplines. O u r age, w i t h its i m p e r a t i v e o f starting o u t f r o m neither one o f these t w o attitudes a n d o f j u s t i f y i n g things, w i l l have to come to a decision o n such a serious question. I have tried to show to w h a t unknown and impenetrable skies, i n Paul Hazard's phrase, G o d has been relegated. B u t we have also seen t h a t , despite everything, G o d r e m a i n e d secure a n d f i r m i n seventeenthc e n t u r y philosophy. H o w d i d people forget this dimension a n d concern themselves only w i t h the other, w h i c h separates us f r o m the Deity? I said above t h a t G o d ceases to be the h o r i z o n o f the thinkers a n d becomes the g r o u n d beneath their feet. I n fact, H e is no longer the d i v i n e object o f speculation a n d science, b u t only their presupposition. M a n goes to G o d , n o t because G o d interests h i m , b u t because the w o r l d concerns h i m . G o d is o n l y the necessary c o n d i t i o n for the reconquest o f the w o r l d . O n c e the w o r l d is securely i n man's grasp, G o d has no further i m p o r t a n c e . N o t h i n g is o f less interest to m a n t h a n the g r o u n d beneath h i m ; precisely because i t is solid a n d secure, he
The Loss of God neglects i t a n d gives his a t t e n t i o n to other things. T h u s , m o d e r n m a n forgets G o d a n d gives his a t t e n t i o n to nature. I n the t r a n s i t i o n f r o m the M i d d l e Ages to m o d e r n times we see an outstanding example o f t h a t historical d y n a m i s m w h i c h , i n a l t e r n a t i o n , converts w h a t was f o r m e r l y man's h o r i z o n i n t o a presupposition w i t h a q u i t e different role. B u t , above a l l , there is another, m u c h more decisive reason. T h e process w h i c h we have briefly witnessed does not end here. T h e metaphysics of the p e r i o d f r o m Descartes to Leibniz is o n l y a first stage i n the process. W e have yet to see h o w G e r m a n idealism, i n the philosophy o f K a n t , completes the loss o f G o d i n speculative reason b y declaring the ontological p r o o f impossible. Therefore, this expulsion o f G o d , w h o is lost to theoretic reason, is i n the m a k i n g f r o m O c c a m to G e r m a n idealism. By the time o f L e i b n i z we are o n l y halfway a l o n g the p a t h . W h a t is t h e n i n the forefront, w h a t is carried o n most vigorously, w h a t is being effected, is the banishment o f G o d ; the ontological bridge w h i c h still j o i n s us to H i m is o n l y a vestige w h i c h defines a phase. T h i s is w h a t gives the years of change w h i c h we have been considering their fundamental u n i t y and makes t h e m , i n spite of their extreme complexity, constitute a real stage i n history.
GERMAN IDEALISM
Kant
W e have seen w h a t happens i n the seventeenth a n d eighteenth centuries, the f u n d a m e n t a l s i t u a t i o n w h i c h faces m a n as a consequence o f r a t i o n a l i s m . T h e explanations set f o r t h i n the preceding section h a d a d o u b l e purpose: first, they were a n a t t e m p t to explain the historical r e a l i t y o f those t w o centuries; secondly, they represented a n endeavor to establish rather precisely the i n t e l l e c t u a l e n v i r o n m e n t i n w h i c h K a n t a n d the other G e r m a n idealists are to move. I t is useful t o emphasize t w o i m p o r t a n t aspects o f the t h o u g h t o f those t w o centuries: one is the physical image o f the w o r l d w h i c h m o d e r n p h y s i c s — m o r e specifically, N e w t o n — h a s given us; the other is the subjective a n d psychological c r i t i q u e w h i c h L o c k e , Berkeley a n d H u m e — p a r t i c u l a r l y H u m e — h a v e made. W i t h these elements i n view, we c a n u n d e r take a n explanation o f K a n t i a n i s m , one o f the most difficult things one c a n a t t e m p t to do. I t w i l l be necessary to give a p r e l i m i n a r y b r i e f a n d simple exposition o f the content o f this philosophy, so t h a t later we can discuss the significance o f the K a n t i a n p r o b l e m .
Kantian Doctrine I m m a n u e l K a n t was b o r n i n K ö n i g s b e r g i n 17 2 4 ; he d i e d i n the same c i t y i n 1804 after h a v i n g passed his e n t i r e l o n g life there. K a n t was always a sedentary person; he never t r a v e l e d b e y o n d the boundaries o f East Prussia a n d r a r e l y w e n t o u t side K ö n i g s b e r g itself. K a n t ' s father was a master saddler; the f a m i l y was o f modest means, a n d K a n t grew u p i n a n atmosphere o f honest artisanship a n d deep Pietistic religiosity. H e studied at the u n i v e r s i t y K A N T ' S LIFE A N D WORKS.
264
Transcendental
Idealism
i n his n a t a l city, gave p r i v a t e lessons a n d later t a u g h t at the university; however, not u n t i l 1 7 7 0 was he n a m e d Privatdozent o f logic a n d metaphysics, a position he h e l d u n t i l 1 7 9 7 w h e n , seven years before his death, he abandoned i t because o f age and weakness. K a n t ' s health was always very delicate, b u t i n spite o f this he a t t a i n e d the age o f eighty a n d led a life o f e x t r a o r d i n a r y exertion. H e was p u n c t u a l , m e t h o d i c a l , serene a n d u n c o m m o n l y k i n d . H i s w h o l e life was a quiet b u t passionate quest for t r u t h . W e can distinguish t w o epochs i n K a n t ' s w o r k , a n d also i n his p h i l o s o p h y : that w h i c h is called the pre-critical p e r i o d — p r i o r to the p u b l i c a t i o n of the Critique of Pure Reason—and the later, critical period. T h e most i m p o r t a n t works o f the earlier phase are Allgemeine Naturgeschichte und Theorie des Himmels (General N a t u r a l H i s t o r y a n d T h e o r y o f the Heavens) a n d Der einzig mögliche Beweisgrund zu einer Demonstration des Daseins Gottes ( O n l y Possible G r o u n d o f P r o o f for the Existence o f God) (1763). I n 1 7 7 0 K a n t published his L a t i n dissertat i o n , De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis causa etprincipiis ( O n the F o r m a n d Principles o f the Sensible a n d I n t e l l i g i b l e W o r l d ) , a w o r k w h i c h marks the transition to the c r i t i c a l period. I t was f o l l o w e d b y a long silence lasting ten years, at the end o f w h i c h , i n 1781, there appeared the first e d i t i o n o f Kritik der reinen Vernunft ( C r i t i q u e o f Pure Reason). L a t e r , i n 1 7 8 3 , K a n t p u b l i s h e d the Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik, die als Wissenschaft wird auftreten können (Prolegomena to any F u t u r e Metaphysics W h i c h W i l l Be A b l e to Come F o r t h as Science), i n 1 7 8 5 the Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten ( F u n d a m e n t a l P r i n ciples o f the Metaphysics o f Ethics), and i n 1 7 8 8 the w o r k t h a t completes his ethics, the Kritik der praktischen Vernunft ( C r i t i q u e o f Practical Reason). F i n a l l y , i n 1 7 9 0 , he published his t h i r d book o f criticism, the Kritik der Urteilskraft ( C r i t i q u e o f J u d g m e n t ) . K a n t ' s most i m p o r t a n t works are grouped i n a space o f ten years. Also o f great i m p o r t a n c e are Die Metaphysik der Sitten (1797), Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vernunft (Religion w i t h i n the Boundaries o f Pure Reason), the Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht a n d the Lectures on Logic, w h i c h were edited b y G o t t l o b B e n j a m i n Jäsche i n 1800. K a n t ' s works also i n c l u d e m a n y more o r less b r i e f w r i t i n g s o f e x t r a o r d i n a r y interest a n d some others published after his death (see Kants Opus postumum, edited b y E r i c h Adickes a n d later b y A r t u r Buchenau) t h a t are essential for the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f his thought.
1. KANT'S
SOURCES.
TRANSCENDENTAL
IDEALISM
T h e p r i n c i p a l source of K a n t i a n philosophy is to
be f o u n d i n Cartesian p h i l o s o p h y a n d , consequently, i n r a t i o n a l i s m u p
ı86
Kant
to L e i b n i z a n d W o l f f . O n the other h a n d , K a n t says t h a t H u m e ' s criticisms awakened h i m f r o m his d o g m a t i c slumbers. ( W e shall presently see w h a t this adjective means.) I n Descartes the res cogitans a n d t h e res extensa have something i n c o m m o n : being. As w e have seen, this b e i n g w h i c h is based o n G o d is w h a t creates the u n i t y between the t w o res, a n d w h a t makes knowledge possible. I n Parmenides, w h o represents the b e g i n n i n g o f metaphysics, b e i n g is a real q u a l i t y o f the things, something t h a t is in them, as a color can be, b u t i n such a w a y t h a t i t is p r i o r to a l l other possible qualities. I n short, i n Parmenides the things are real. I n idealist philosophy, the case is different. B e i n g is n o t real, b u t transcendental. " I m m a n e n t " means w h a t remains i n , immanet, manet in. " T r a n s c e n d e n t " refers to w h a t exceeds or transcends something. " T r a n s c e n d e n t a l " means neither transcendent n o r i m m a n e n t . A table has the q u a l i t y of being, b u t a l l the table's other qualities also have b e i n g ; the q u a l i t y o f b e i n g permeates a n d envelops a l l the rest b u t does not become i n t e r m i n g l e d w i t h a n y o f t h e m . A l l the things are r o o t e d i n being, a n d therefore being serves as a bridge between the things. This is transcendental
being. T R A N S C E N D E N T A L K N O W L E D G E . T h i s concept, however, does n o t satisfy K a n t . K n o w l e d g e cannot be explained simply b y i n t e r p r e t i n g being as transcendental; i t is necessary to create a transcendental theory o f knowledge, a n d this knowledge is to be the b r i d g e between the ego a n d the things. A c c o r d i n g to the realist, knowledge is k n o w l edge o f the things, and the things transcend me. A c c o r d i n g to the idealist (Berkeley), w h o says t h a t for m e there is n o t h i n g b u t m y ideas, the things are i m m a n e n t , a n d knowledge is knowledge o f m y o w n ideas. B u t the situation is very different i f I believe t h a t m y ideas are of the things. T h e things do not t h e n appear to m e as objects t h a t are independent o f m e ; the things occur to me in my ideas; b u t these ideas are n o t o n l y m i n e , they are ideas of the things. T h e y are things t h a t appear to m e , phenomena i n the l i t e r a l sense o f the w o r d .
I f knowledge were transcendent, i t w o u l d k n o w external things. I f i t were i m m a n e n t , i t w o u l d k n o w o n l y ideas; t h a t is, w h a t is i n me. B u t knowledge is transcendental: i t knows the phenomena, t h a t is, the things in me (emphasizing equally b o t h parts o f this expression). H e r e there arises the K a n t i a n distinction between the phenomenon a n d the thing-in-itself. T h e things-in-themselves are inaccessible; I cannot k n o w t h e m because i n so far as I k n o w t h e m they are in me, affected b y m y subjec t i v i t y ; the things-in-themselves (noumena) are neither spatial nor t e m p o r a l , a n d I cannot conceive o f any t h i n g t h a t is outside o f time a n d
The "Critique
of Pure Reason"
z8y
space. T h e things i n the f o r m i n w h i c h they manifest themselves to me, as they appear to me, are phenomena. K a n t distinguishes t w o elements of knowledge: w h a t is given a n d w h a t is posited b y the t h i n k i n g subject. Something occurs to me (a chaos o f sensations) a n d I posit something (the space-time reference, the categories), a n d f r o m the c o m b i n a t i o n o f these t w o elements there arises the known thing or phenomenon. T h u s , w h e n t h o u g h t orders the chaos o f sensations i t makes the things; consequently K a n t says t h a t t h o u g h t does not adapt itself to the things, b u t the other w a y a r o u n d , a n d t h a t his philosophy represents a " Copernican r e v o l u t i o n . " B u t t h o u g h t does n o t create the things a l l b y itself; i t makes use o f given m a t e r i a l . T h u s , the things, w h i c h are distinct f r o m the unknowable things-in-themselves, arise o u t of the act o f transcendental knowledge. P U R E R E A S O N . K a n t distinguishes three modes o f knowledge: sensib i l i t y (Sinnlichkeit), reflective understanding (Verstand) a n d reason (Vernunft). T o the n o u n " r e a s o n " K a n t adds the adjective " p u r e . " Pure reason is based o n a p r i o r i principles; i t is independent o f experience. I n K a n t , " p u r e " means a p r i o r i , b u t n o t only that:pure reason is n o t the reason o f a n y one m a n , nor even h u m a n reason, b u t simply t h a t of the rational being. Pure reason is equivalent to the rational conditions of rational beings in general. However, the titles o f K a n t ' s works can be misleading. H e calls one the Critique of Pure Reason a n d the other the Critique of Practical Reason. Practical seems to be i n opposition to pure, b u t this is n o t so. Practical reason is also pure, a n d is the opposite o f speculative or theoretic reason. T h u s the f u l l expression w o u l d be speculative (or theoretic) pure reason a n d practical p u r e reason. B u t since i n the first Critique K a n t studies the general conditions o f pure reason a n d i n the second the practical aspect o f the same reason, he adopts a n abbreviated f o r m i n his titles.
Speculative reason refers to a theory, to a p u r e knowledge o f the things; i n contrast, p r a c t i c a l reason refers to a c t i o n , to a d o i n g , i n a sense close to the Greek praxis, and is the focal p o i n t o f K a n t i a n ethics.
2.
T H E
" C R I T I Q U E OF P U R E
REASON"
K a n t writes his Critique as a propaedeutic to or p r e p a r a t i o n for metaphysics, w h i c h is understood as a p r i o r i philosophical knowledge. H e must determine the possibilities o f knowledge a n d the basis o f its v a l i d i t y . This is the general p r o b l e m . T h e Critique was published i n 1781, a n d K a n t altered i t significantly i n the second e d i t i o n o f 1787;
z88
Kant
b o t h editions are o f great interest i n the history o f philosophy. T h e f o l l o w i n g is a n o u t l i n e of the Critique ofPure Reason: Introduction I.
(statement of the p r o b l e m a n d the theory of j u d g m e n t s ) .
The Elements of Transcendentalism. 1. Transcendental esthetics (theory of space and time). 2. Transcendental logic. (a) Transcendental analytics (possibility of pure physics). (b) Transcendental dialectics (problem of the possibility of metaphysics).
I I . Method 1. The 2. The 3. The 4. The
of Transcendentalism. discipline of pure reason. canon of pure reason. architectonic of pure reason. history of pure reason.
Judgments K n o w l e d g e can be either a p r i o r i or a posteriori. T h e former is knowledge whose v a l i d i t y is n o t based o n experience; t h e latter is knowledge whose v a l i d i t y derives f r o m experience. A posteriori k n o w l edge cannot be universal or necessary; therefore, science requires a p r i o r i knowledge, t h a t is, knowledge t h a t is n o t l i m i t e d b y the c o n t i n gencies of experience i n the here a n d now. K a n t finds several kinds of a p r i o r i k n o w l e d g e : mathematics; physics; t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics, w h i c h claims to k n o w its three o b j e c t s — m a n , the w o r l d a n d G o d . These objects are beyond experience because they are " i n f i n i t e syntheses." I cannot have an i n t u i t i o n o f the w o r l d , for example, because I a m p a r t o f i t a n d i t does n o t appear to me as a thing. K a n t wonders i f metaphysics is possible; he finds t h a t the o t h e r sciences (mathematics a n d physics) travel along a sure path, b u t i t seems to h i m t h a t metaphysics does not. So K a n t formulates his three m a j o r questions: H o w is mathematics possible ? (Transcendental esthetics) H o w is p u r e physics possible? (Transcendental analytics) Is metaphysics possible ? (Transcendental dialectics). Observe t h a t the t h i r d question differs i n f o r m f r o m the other t w o ; K a n t does not assume the possibility o f metaphysics. (Esthetics does n o t here refer to w h a t is beautiful, b u t to sensibility, i n its Greek sense o f aisthesis.) T r u t h a n d knowledge, therefore, occur i n j u d g m e n t s . A science is a systematic complex o f j u d g m e n t s . K a n t must first o f a l l establish a logical theory o f j u d g m e n t . A N A L Y T I C J U D G M E N T S A N D S Y N T H E T I C J U D G M E N T S . A n analytic j u d g m e n t is one whose predicate is contained i n the n o t i o n of t h e subject. A synthetic j u d g m e n t , o n the c o n t r a r y , is one whose predicate is n o t
The "Critique
of Pure Reason"
i n c l u d e d i n the n o t i o n o f the subject b u t is joined or added to i t . F o r example: bodies have extension, a sphere is r o u n d ; b u t o n the c o n t r a r y , a table is w o o d e n , lead is heavy. Extension is i n c l u d e d i n the n o t i o n o f a b o d y a n d roundness i n t h a t o f a sphere; b u t woodenness is n o t i n c l u d e d i n the n o t i o n o f a table, n o r is heaviness i n c l u d e d i n t h a t o f lead. ( O n e should observe t h a t i n L e i b n i z ' philosophy a l l j u d g ments are analytic j u d g m e n t s , since a l l the determinations of a t h i n g are necessarily i n c l u d e d i n the complete n o t i o n o f the t h i n g ; however, o n l y G o d possesses the complete n o t i o n o f a t h i n g . ) A n a l y t i c j u d g m e n t s explicate the concept o f the subject, whereas synthetic j u d g m e n t s amplify i t . T h u s synthetic j u d g m e n t s augment o u r knowledge a n d are the ones t h a t have value for science. A P R I O R I A N D A P O S T E R I O R I J U D G M E N T S . W e have already alluded to another d i s t i n c t i o n , one w h i c h deals w i t h a p r i o r i j u d g m e n t s a n d j u d g m e n t s based o n experience. A t first glance i t seems t h a t analytic j u d g m e n t s are a p r i o r i j u d g m e n t s , t h a t they are obtained p u r e l y b y analysis o f the concept o f the subject, a n d t h a t synthetic judgments are a posteriori j u d g m e n t s . T h e first statement is t r u e , a n d i n general a posteriori j u d g m e n t s are synthetic j u d g m e n t s ; however, the converse is n o t t r u e ; there are a priori synthetic judgments, even t h o u g h this m a y seem to be a c o n t r a d i c t i o n i n terms, a n d these are the j u d g m e n t s t h a t are o f interest to science because they f u l f i l l the t w o required c o n d i tions : they are o n one h a n d a p r i o r i , t h a t is, universal a n d necessary, a n d o n the other, synthetic, t h a t is, they effectively augment our k n o w l edge. T h e equation 2 + 2 = 4 , statement t h a t the sum of the three angles o f a triangle is equal to t w o r i g h t angles—these are a p r i o r i synthetic j u d g m e n t s ; t h e i r predicates are n o t contained i n the subjects, a n d the j u d g m e n t s are n o t based o n experience. W e find a p r i o r i synthetic j u d g m e n t s outside o f mathematics also, i n physics a n d metaphysics: " e v e r y p h e n o m e n o n has its cause," " m a n is free," " G o d exists." T h u s , the question o f the possibility o f these sciences is reduced to this other question: H o w are a p r i o r i synthetic j u d g m e n t s possible — i f indeed they are p o s s i b l e — i n each one o f these sciences ? t n e
Space and Time P U R E I N T U I T I O N S . E v e r y t h i n g I k n o w is m a d e u p o f t w o elements: t h a t w h i c h is given a n d t h a t w h i c h I posit. T h a t w h i c h is given is a chaos o f sensations, a n d chaos is precisely the opposite o f knowledge. I do something w i t h t h a t chaos o f sensations. W h a t do I do ? I order i t — first, i n space and t i m e , t h e n , as we shall presently see, according to the categories. T h e n , u t i l i z i n g the chaos o f sensations, I make things—not
Kant things-in-themselves, b u t phenomena, things subject to space a n d t i m e . N o w , are space a n d t i m e things-in-themselves ? N o , they are not. T h e n w h a t are they ? K a n t says t h a t they are pure intuitions. T h e y are the a priori forms of sensibility. Sensibility is n o t o n l y receptive, b u t also active; i t leaves its i m p r i n t on everything t h a t i t apprehends; a n d i t possesses its forms i n a n a p r i o r i way. Space a n d t i m e are forms w h i c h sensibility gives to the things w h i c h occur to i t f r o m outside; these forms are necessary conditions i f I a m to perceive; a n d I posit these conditions. I have a p r i o r i knowledge o f space a n d t i m e ; I do n o t k n o w t h e m f r o m experience, b u t rather j u s t the opposite: they are indispensable c o n d i tions to m y h a v i n g experience. I t is i n these forms that m y perception resides. T h u s they are p r i o r to the things a n d belong to the r e a l m o f p u r e subjectivity. M A T H E M A T I C S . I k n o w space a n d t i m e i n a n absolutely a p r i o r i way. T h u s j u d g m e n t s t h a t relate to the forms o f sensibility are a p r i o r i j u d g m e n t s , even t h o u g h they m a y be synthetic j u d g m e n t s as w e l l . Therefore such j u d g m e n t s are possible i n mathematics, a science t h a t is based on constructions of concepts. T h e v a l i d i t y o f mathematics is based o n the a p r i o r i i n t u i t i o n o f relationships between spatial figures a n d numbers w h i c h are based o n the temporal succession o f units. Conseq u e n t l y , space a n d t i m e constitute the logical—-not p s y c h o l o g i c a l — basis o f mathematics, a n d synthetic a p r i o r i j u d g m e n t s are possible. Transcendental esthetics solves the first p a r t o f the p r o b l e m .
The Categories Space a n d t i m e separate us f r o m the r e a l i t y o f the things-in-themselves. Sensibility presents to our u n d e r s t a n d i n g only phenomena, things w h i c h i t has already " d e f o r m e d " or operated o n . As O r t e g a has shown so w e l l , t h i n k i n g is essentially a process o f transforming. B u t the understanding, l i k e sensibility, also possesses a p r i o r i forms b y means of w h i c h i t apprehends a n d understands the things: these forms
are the categories. I n Aristotle, the categories were modes or inflections o f being to w h i c h the m i n d adapted itself. I n K a n t , conversely, the m i n d already contains the categories, a n d the things c o n f o r m to the m i n d ; this is the concept K a n t referred to as a "Copernican revolution.'''' T h e categories are i n our u n d e r s t a n d i n g a n d not d i r e c t l y i n the being o f the things. N o longer are we separated f r o m r e a l i t y in itself only b y space a n d t i m e ; now there is a second " d e f o r m i n g ' ' factor, the categories. T H E JUDGMENTS A N D T H E CATEGORIES.
K a n t begins w i t h the logical
The "Critique of Pure Reason" classification o f the j u d g m e n t s , as m o d i f i e d b y h i m , i n accordance w i t h four points o f v i e w : q u a n t i t y , q u a l i t y , r e l a t i o n and m o d a l i t y . I.
Quantity Universal Particular Singular 3Relation
2.
Quality
Affirmative Negative Infinite
Categorical Hypothetical Disjunctive 4Modality
Problematical Assertory Apodictic F r o m these j u d g m e n t s , each one o f w h i c h is a mode o f synthesis, the categories are derived. Since the subdivision o f the j u d g m e n t s is completely a p r i o r i , the categories derived f r o m t h e m are modes o f p u r e a p r i o r i synthesis, the modalities of the concept of a n object i n general. I n this w a y we get the f o l l o w i n g table o f pure concepts of the under-
standing, or categories: I.
Quantity Unity Plurality Totality 3Relation Substance Causality C o m m u n i t y or reciprocal action
Quality
Reality Negation Limitation 4Modality
Possibility Existence Necessity T h e close relation between the classes of j u d g m e n t s a n d the categories is evident. T h e categories are relationships a m o n g objects, corresponding to those a m o n g thejudgments.
ZQZ
Kant
P U R E P H Y S I C S . U s i n g space, t i m e a n d the categories, the understanding fashions the objects o f p u r e physics; the category o f substance a p p l i e d to space gives us the concept of matter; the category o f causality taken together w i t h the f o r m o f t i m e gives us the physical concept o f cause a n d effect, a n d so f o r t h . Since we always r e m a i n entirely w i t h i n the r e a l m o f a p r i o r i thought, i n w h i c h experience plays n o p a r t , the v a l i d i t y o f p u r e physics does n o t depend o n experience, a n d a p r i o r i synthetic j u d g m e n t s are possible w i t h i n the d o m a i n o f p u r e physics. T h i s is the result o f transcendental analytics.
The Critique of Traditional Metaphysics T r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics, i n its medieval forms a n d especially i n the generalized f o r m u l a t i o n o f W o l f f i n the eighteenth century, consisted o f t w o p a r t s : a metaphysica generalis, or ontology, a n d a metaphysica specialis, w h i c h was concerned w i t h the three great areas o f b e i n g : m a n , the w o r l d a n d G o d ; this gives us three disciplines: r a t i o n a l psychology, r a t i o n a l cosmology a n d r a t i o n a l theology. K a n t is faced w i t h these sciences a n d their r e p e r t o r y o f problems (the i m m o r t a l i t y o f the soul, freedom, the finiteness or infiniteness o f the w o r l d , the existence o f G o d , a n d so o n ) , a n d i n his transcendental dialectics attacks the p r o b l e m of whether this m e t a p h y s i c s — w h i c h does n o t seem to have set o u t u p o n the sure path ofscience—is possible. METAPHYSICS. F o r K a n t , metaphysics is i d e n t i c a l w i t h p u r e , a p r i o r i knowledge. B u t real knowledge is possible only w h e n sensory perception o r experience is added to the f o r m a l principles. N o w , the principles we have obtained are f o r m a l a n d a p r i o r i ; i n order to have knowledge o f reality, i t w o u l d be necessary to supplement t h e m w i t h a posteriori elements, w i t h experience. T r a d i t i o n a l speculative metaphysics is the a t t e m p t to acquire, b y a p r i o r i t h o u g h t , a real knowledge o f objects—the soul, the w o r l d , G o d — w h i c h are beyond any possible experience. Therefore, i t is a v a i n a t t e m p t . These three objects are " i n f i n i t e syntheses," and one cannot posit the necessary conditions for i n t u i t i n g t h e m ; therefore, i t is impossible to acquire this knowledge. K a n t examines i n t u r n the paralogisms contained i n the demonstrations o f r a t i o n a l psychology, the antinomies o f r a t i o n a l cosmology a n d the arguments o f r a t i o n a l theology (the ontological proof, the cosmological p r o o f a n d the physico-theological p r o o f o f the existence o f G o d ) , a n d concludes t h a t these disciplines are i n v a l i d . W e cannot go i n t o the details of this c r i t i q u e , since this w o u l d take us too far afield. A l l t h a t is o f interest here is to indicate the basis of K a n t ' s c r i t i q u e o f the ontological argument, since this c r i t i q u e is the key to his whole philosophy.
Practical
Reason
2-93
T H E ONTOLOGICAL A R G U M E N T . K a n t shows that the a r g u m e n t t h a t originates w i t h St. A n s e l m is based o n a n o t i o n o f b e i n g w h i c h he rejects: the n o t i o n o f b e i n g as a real predicate. T h i s is m o r e true o f Descartes' f o r m of the proof, w h i c h is the f o r m K a n t is concerned w i t h . T h i s p r o o f understands existence to be a perfection t h a t cannot be l a c k i n g i n the most perfect E n t i t y . T h a t is, existence is i n t e r p r e t e d as something t h a t is in a thing. B u t K a n t declares t h a t b e i n g is n o t a real p r e d i c a t e : Sein ist kein reales Prädikat. T h e t h i n g w h i c h exists contains n o t h i n g t h a t the t h i n g w h i c h is o n l y t h o u g h t o f does n o t c o n t a i n : i f i t were otherwise, the concept i n question w o u l d n o t be o f t h a t t h i n g . A h u n d r e d real crowns (coins), K a n t says i n his famous comparison, c o n t a i n n o t h i n g t h a t is n o t contained i n a h u n d r e d possible crowns. Nevertheless, he adds, i t makes a difference to me w h e t h e r I have a h u n d r e d possible or a h u n d r e d real crowns; of w h a t does the difference consist? T h e actual crowns are connected w i t h sensory p e r c e p t i o n ; they are present, along w i t h a l l the other things, i n the t o t a l i t y o f experience. T h a t is, existence is n o t a p r o p e r t y of the things, b u t their relationship w i t h a l l the other things, the positive position o f the object. Being is n o t a real, b u t a transcendental predicate. Seventeenth-century metaphysics understood i t to be real, a n d therefore accepted the ontological p r o o f ; this is the m e a n i n g o f the epithet w h i c h K a n t applies to Baroque t h o u g h t : dogmatism, ignorance of the transcendental nature ofbeing. T H E I D E A S . T h e three disciplines o f t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics are, a c c o r d i n g to K a n t , n o t v a l i d . Metaphysics is not possible as a speculative science. Its themes have n o t h i n g to do w i t h science, b u t r e m a i n as objects o f f a i t h , a n d as such cannot be refuted. " I h a d to suppress k n o w l e d g e , " K a n t says," i n order to make w a y for b e l i e f . " B u t metaphysics continues to exist as a natural predisposition of m a n t o w a r d the absolute. A n d the objects o f metaphysics are those w h i c h K a n t calls Ideas; they are like new, higher categories corresponding to the syntheses of j u d g m e n t s i n p u r e reasoning. Since these Ideas are not open to i n t u i t i o n , they can o n l y have a regulative use. M a n o u g h t to behave as if his soul were i m m o r t a l , as if he were free, as if G o d existed, even t h o u g h theoretic reason cannot prove a l l this. B u t this is n o t the o n l y role o f the Ideas. A l o n g w i t h this h y p o t h e t i c a l v a l i d i t y for speculative reason, the transcendental Ideas also possess another v a l i d i t y o f a different k i n d , one w h i c h is absolute a n d u n c o n d i t i o n a l ; they reappear i n the deepest layer of K a n t i a n philosophy as postulates of practical
reason. 3.
PRACTICAL
REASON
N A T U R E A N D FREEDOM. K a n t distinguishes between t w o w o r l d s : the
Kant
w o r l d of n a t u r e a n d the w o r l d o f freedom. T h e former is d e t e r m i n e d b y n a t u r a l causality, b u t alongside this, K a n t allows the existence o f a causality
through freedom,
w h i c h governs the other d o m a i n . O n the
one
h a n d , m a n is a psychophysical subject, r u l e d b y the physical a n d psychical laws o f n a t u r e ; this is w h a t K a n t calls the empirical ego. Just as the b o d y obeys the l a w o f g r a v i t y , the w i l l is shaped b y s t i m u l i , a n d i n this e m p i r i c a l sense i t is n o t free. B u t to this e m p i r i c a l ego K a n t contraposes a pure ego, w h i c h is n o t d e t e r m i n e d n a t u r a l l y , b u t o n l y b y the laws o f freedom. M a n , as a rational person, belongs to this w o r l d o f freedom. B u t w e have already seen t h a t theoretic reason does n o t extend this f a r ; w i t h i n its o w n field i t is incapable of k n o w i n g freedom. W h e r e d o we encounter freedom ? O n l y i n the fact of morality; here there appears practical reason, w h i c h is n o t concerned w i t h being b u t w i t h how one ought to be; here i t is n o t a question o f speculative k n o w l edge b u t o f m o r a l knowledge. A n d j u s t as K a n t studied the possibilities of the f o r m e r i n the Critique of Pure Reason (theoretic reason), he must n o w w r i t e a Critique of Practical Reason. T H E '' F A C T U M '' OF M O R A L I T Y . I n discussing p r a c t i c a l reason, K a n t accepts postulates w h i c h are n o t demonstrable w i t h theoretic reason, but w h i c h possess a direct a n d absolute self-evidence for t h e t h i n k i n g subject. Therefore, they are postulates a n d their acceptance is r e q u i r e d and u n c o n d i t i o n a l l y imposed, a l t h o u g h n o t speculatively. K a n t is faced w i t h a fact, &factum, w h i c h is the p o i n t o f departure for his ethics: m o r a l i t y , the consciousness o f d u t y . M a n has a feeling o f responsib i l i t y , o f d u t y . T h i s is a p u r e fact, i n d i s p u t a b l e a n d self-evident. N o w , d u t y a n d the consciousness of responsibility presuppose t h efreedom o f m a n . B u t freedom is not demonstrable b y theoretic reason; f r o m the speculative p o i n t of view, i t is merely a regulative Idea: one o u g h t to act as if one were free. O n the other h a n d , freedom n o w appears as somet h i n g absolutely certain a n d r e q u i r e d b y the consciousness o f d u t y , even t h o u g h theoretic reason does n o t t e l l us how i t is possible. M a n , i n so far as he is a moral person, is free, a n d his freedom is a postulate o f p r a c t i c a l reason. T H E OBJECTS O F METAPHYSICS. A n a l o g o u s l y , the i m m o r t a l i t y o f the
soul a n d the existence of G o d , w h i c h i t was n o t possible to p r o v e i n the Critique
of Pure
Reason,
reappear as postulates i n t h e o t h e r Critique.
The
objects o f t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics are v a l i d i n a d o u b l e sense: as regulative Ideas i n the r e a l m o f theoretic reason, a n d as postulates w i t h absolute v a l i d i t y i n the r e a l m o f p r a c t i c a l reason. T h i s is to be the basis o f K a n t ' s ethics. THE
CATEGORICAL IMPERATIVE.
Metaphysics
of Morals,
I n t h e Fundamental
Principles
of the
K a n t formulates the p r o b l e m o f ethics as the
Practical
Reason
zoj
question o f the highest good. G o o d things may be good for something else or good i n themselves. K a n t says t h a t the only t h i n g t h a t is good i n itself, w i t h no restrictions, is a good will. T h e p r o b l e m o f m o r a l i t y is thus b r o u g h t i n t o relation n o t w i t h actions, b u t w i t h the w i l l w h i c h motivates t h e m . K a n t wishes to create a n ethics t h a t w i l l state h o w m a n ought to be. T h i s ethics must also be i m p e r a t i v e , obligatory. T h u s K a n t seeks an imperative. B u t the m a j o r i t y o f imperatives are not suitable as a basis for ethics, because they are hypothetical, t h a t is, they depend u p o n a c o n d i t i o n . I f I say: nourish yourself, a c o n d i t i o n is u n d e r s t o o d : if you want to live; b u t for a m a n w h o wants to die, such a n i m p e r a t i v e has no v a l i d i t y . K a n t has need o f a categorical i m p e r a t i v e w h i c h w i l l be u n c o n d i t i o n a l l y and absolutely a u t h o r i t a t i v e . T h e categorical i m p e r a tive's obligatory power must be f o u n d w i t h i n itself. Since the highest good is a good w i l l , the m o r a l evaluation o f a n action is based o n the w i l l t h a t m o t i v a t e d the a c t i o n , n o t o n the action itself. A n d a good w i l l is one w h i c h wills w h a t i t wills purely out of regard to duty. I f I p e r f o r m a good action because i t pleases m e to do so, or o u t o f sentiment, fear, a n d the like, it has no moral value. ( H e r e K a n t raises the t h o r n y p r o b l e m o f whether regard to d u t y is n o t itself a sentiment.) T h e categorical i m p e r a t i v e is expressed i n different ways; its basic m e a n i n g is the f o l l o w i n g : Act in such universal
a way that you can will
what you are doing
to be a
law of nature.
I n effect, the m a n w h o commits a w r o n g action does it as a mistake, as a n exception, a n d is a f f i r m i n g the universal m o r a l l a w at the very m o m e n t w h e n he is i n f r i n g i n g i t . I f I lie, I cannot w i l l t h a t l y i n g should be a universal law, since this w o u l d destroy the meaningfulness of w h a t people say, a n d w o u l d even make impossible the effect of m y o w n lie ; l y i n g presupposes, precisely, t h a t the universal l a w is to tell the t r u t h . A n d a similar t h i n g occurs w i t h every other instance o f wrongdoing. T H E M O R A L PERSON. K a n t i a n ethics is autonomous, not heteronomous; t h a t is, its laws are dictated b y the m o r a l conscience itself, not b y a n a u t h o r i t y outside the ego. T h e ego is a legislator in the kingdom of ends, i n the w o r l d o f m o r a l freedom. F r o m another v i e w p o i n t , this ethics is formal, not material, because i t prescribes n o t h i n g concrete, no action t h a t is determined as to c o n t e n t ; i t prescribes o n l y the form of a c t i o n : keep d u t y i n m i n d , whatever y o u d o ; act o u t of regard to d u t y , do w h a t you
will.
Strictly speaking, the last-mentioned expression is accurate: y o u ought to d o w h a t y o u w i l l ; n o t w h a t y o u desire, l o n g for or f i n d suitable, b u t w h a t y o u r r a t i o n a l w i l l is able to will. K a n t asks m a n to be
2Q6
Kant
free, to be autonomous, not to let himself be determined b y any m o t i v e alien to his w i l l , w h i c h makes its o w n laws. I n this way, K a n t i a n ethics culminates i n the concept o f the moral person. A n ethics is always an ontology o f m a n . K a n t asks m a n to realize his essence, to be w h a t he t r u l y is, a rational being—because K a n t i a n ethics is not concerned w i t h the e m p i r i c a l ego, o r even w i t h the h u m a n c o n d i t i o n , b u t w i t h a p u r e ego, a purely r a t i o n a l being. O n the one h a n d m a n , as a n e m p i r i c a l ego, is subject to n a t u r a l causality; b u t o n the other h a n d he belongs to the k i n g d o m o f ends. K a n t says t h a t each and every man is an end in himself. I m m o r a l i t y consists i n t r e a t i n g a m a n — o n e ' s o w n self or one's fellow—as a means for something else, whereas m a n actually is a n end i n himself. T h e m o r a l l a w s — t h e categorical i m p e r a t i v e — a r e derived f r o m the legislation o f one's o w n w i l l . Therefore, the i m p e r a t i v e a n d m o r a l i t y are o f interest to us, because they are a t h i n g o f o u r o w n m a k i n g . T H E P R I M A C Y OF P R A C T I C A L REASON. P r a c t i c a l reason, as contrasted
w i t h theoretic reason, possesses direct v a l i d i t y o n l y for the ego, a n d consists i n d e t e r m i n i n g one's o w n actions. B u t K a n t affirms the p r i m a c y o f p r a c t i c a l over speculative reason, t h a t is, its p r i o r i t y a n d superiority. T h e p r i m a r y aspect o f h u m a n life is n o t theoria, hut praxis, action. K a n t ' s philosophy culminates i n the concept o f the m o r a l person, understood as a free person. K a n t was not able to perfect his metaphysics f u l l y , a n d left o n l y an o u t l i n e o f i t , because his whole life was taken u p b y the task o f criticism w h i c h h a d to be completed first. B u t i t is necessary to take as a p o i n t o f departure the p r i m a c y o f practical reason a n d o f these notions oifreedom a n d a c t i o n , i f one is to understand the philosophy o f G e r m a n idealism, w h i c h is b o r n i n K a n t a n d ends i n Hegel. T E L E O L O G Y A N D ESTHETICS. For o u r present purpose, we can o m i t a n exposition o f the content o f the Critique of Judgment, w h i c h is concerned w i t h problems o f teleology i n the biological organism a n d i n the field o f esthetics. K a n t ' s d e f i n i t i o n o f the beautiful is w e l l k n o w n ; he calls i t a finality end, t h a t is, something w h i c h contains a finality w i t h i n itself, b u t w h i c h is n o t subordinated to any end alien to esthetic pleasure. K a n t also distinguishes between the beautiful, w h i c h produces a pleasant feeling a n d is accompanied b y the consciousness o f l i m i t a t i o n , a n d the sublime, w h i c h causes a pleasure t h a t is m i n g l e d w i t h h o r r o r a n d a d m i r a t i o n — a storm, a lofty m o u n t a i n or a tragedy is s u b l i m e — because the sublime is accompanied b y the impression o f i n f i n i t y o r limitlessness. These K a n t i a n ideas h a d i m p o r t a n t repercussions i n nineteenth-century t h o u g h t . without
The Problem of Kantian
i.
T H E INTERPRETATIONS
OF K A N T ' S
Philosophy
PHILOSOPHY
M E T A P H Y S I C S . K a n t is a n unusual philosopher, because he represents a n essential r e v o l u t i o n i n philosophic t h o u g h t . H e himself uses a n expressive metaphor i n presenting his philosophy: he says t h a t i t is l i k e a Copernican revolution. Therefore, i t is something essentially new, w h i c h opens different paths. T h i s w o u l d be sufficient to explain the difficulty o f K a n t ' s t h o u g h t . B u t i n a d d i t i o n i t so happens t h a t K a n t d i d not achieve the creation o f a complete system, the f u l l realization o f his system. W e need o n l y observe the titles o f his basic w o r k s : they are Critiques, something b y means o f w h i c h he sets certain limits to reason a n d delimits its objects; b u t i t seems t h a t after these critiques was to come his positive d o c t r i n e — w h i c h never came. T h e r e are o n l y fragments w h i c h p o i n t i n this d i r e c t i o n . T h i s is t r u e , b u t o n l y h a l f true. I t w o u l d n o t be p r o p e r to state b l u n t l y t h a t K a n t d i d not create his metaphysics, because a metaphysics is contained i n his Critiques, even (in fact, especially) i n the Critique of Pure Reason. A n d here the difficulty begins: since this metaphysics was n o t created as s u c h — i n d e e d , i t is n e g a t e d — i t is very easy to overlook i t or to misunderstand i t . T h e case of K a n t , as O r t e g a has very r i g h t l y observed, is similar to t h a t of Plato. T h e problems w h i c h the things created for Plato led h i m to the discovery o f the Ideas; a n d w h e n a m a n has discovered the Ideas, he has already done q u i t e a b i t . Plato r e m a i n e d i n the r e a l m o f the Ideas, amidst the difficulties that they caused h i m , a n d h a d no t i m e left to r e t u r n to the things. I n his o l d age he longed to solve these 297
zg8
The Problem
of Kantian
Philosophy
difficulties—as i n his dialogue Parmenides—and to r e t u r n t o the things, to create his metaphysics. Something similar occurs w i t h K a n t . H e was a slow m a n , n o t at a l l p r e c o c i o u s — h a r d l y anyone i n the history o f philosophy w a s — a n d w h e n he a r r i v e d at o l d age, he h a d yet to accomplish the constructive p a r t o f his w o r k ; b u t his metaphysics was already created i n its essentials: the Critique of Pure Reason is already metaphysics (see O r t e g a : Filosofiapura a n d , f r o m another standpoint, Heidegger: Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik). B u t this is already a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n : K a n t himself nowhere states t h a t i t is metaphysics; instead, he says t h a t metaphysics is not possible. Therefore, t o say t h a t i t is ontology requires some justification. T h i s has n o t always been affirmed. W e can consider three major phases o f K a n t ' s influence o n subsequent p h i losophy: G e r m a n idealism, n e o - K a n t i a n i s m a n d the philosophy o f the present t i m e . T H E PHILOSOPHIC PAST. Before I b e g i n this discussion, I must make a p r e l i m i n a r y r e m a r k . Some people m a y t h i n k t h a t the ideas people have h a d of K a n t are not i m p o r t a n t to us, a n d t h a t the o n l y t h i n g t h a t matters is w h a t K a n t ' s philosophy means today. T h i s v i e w p o i n t is w r o n g . W h e n I speak o f K a n t ' s philosophy, I c l a i m to speak of somet h i n g t h a t has reality. A t h i n g is real w h e n i t affects me, w h e n I must take account of i t . W h e n I speak o f K a n t i a n i s m , I speak o f something t h a t is r e a l : I a m using the present i n d i c a t i v e o f the v e r b to be. T o be real means to be real now. I take the past i n t o account, for example, i n so far as I a m r e m e m b e r i n g i t n o w , at the present t i m e . R e m e m brance consists of the presence of the past as the past. Likewise, the hope o f a future consists o f the presence of the future as the future. T h u s we see t h a t the present lends reality to b o t h the past a n d the future. I f I ignore the present, the past no longer exists a n d the future does n o t yet exist. F u r t h e r m o r e , w h e n we say t h a t the past was, we m e a n t h a t i t once was the present; a n d w h e n we say t h a t the future w i l l be, we mean t h a t the future w i l l be the present. W h a t does a l l this signify ? T h a t the past as the past does n o t exist except i n a present t h a t gives i t reality a n d i n r e l a t i o n to w h i c h i t is the past. L e t us keep these ideas clearly i n m i n d a n d r e t u r n to the case o f K a n t i a n i s m . K a n t i a n i s m has reality; b u t K a n t i a n i s m as i t was t h o u g h t of back i n the eighteenth century is n o w a t h i n g of the past. Therefore i t receives reality o n l y f r o m the present—for example, w h e n I t h i n k o f i t now. T h u s we f i n d t h a t w h a t is the present today was n o t the present t h i r t y years ago. Therefore, the reality of K a n t i a n i s m is g i v e n b y each present i n w h i c h K a n t i a n i s m is actualized, a n d we see t h a t , far f r o m its
The
Interpretations
of Kant's
Philosophy
299
b e i n g u n i m p o r t a n t to us, w h a t interests us is w h a t K a n t i a n i s m has been i n each m o m e n t . A n appeal to K a n t i a n i s m as such, d i v o r c e d f r o m w h a t i t m e a n t to K a n t ' s followers, is basically false, because i t is based o n a pure i l l u s i o n , namely, t h a t I can r e t u r n to K a n t i a n i s m in itself, w h e n actually the most I can do is reactualize K a n t i a n i s m i n my present, not i n t h a t o f K a n t . I actualize i t i n a present, a n d I also take t h a t present to be K a n t ' s present; here lies the error. K a n t i a n i s m is K a n t i a n i s m as i t has been active i n the various philosophies—and n o t h i n g else; i t is K a n t i a n i s m i n the f o r m i n w h i c h I find i t i n me as the p a s t — a n d n o t h i n g else. T h i s does n o t mean t h a t I cannot discover new a n d unrealized elements i n i t , b u t o n l y t h a t such elements have h a d no a c t u a l r e a l i t y u n t i l n o w . T h i s discussion m i g h t be a p p l i e d to the entire history of philosophy. W h a t justifies its b e i n g raised i n connection w i t h K a n t is t h a t K a n t i a n ism has been a c h a n g i n g concept a n d has h a d very different i n t e r pretations ; there have been several different K a n t i a n i s m s , a l l m o r e or less authentic. L e t us n o w consider the three p r i n c i p a l interpretations o f K a n t ' s philosophy. 1. G E R M A N I D E A L I S M . K a n t is recognized as the father of a splendid philosophical m o v e m e n t : G e r m a n idealism. T h i s is t r u e to such a degree t h a t the idealists begin b y presenting t h e i r o w n philosophies as interpretations o f K a n t ' s . Fichte actually says: " K a n t has n o t been p r o p e r l y understood; I understand h i m , perhaps better t h a n he understood h i m s e l f . " W h i l e t r y i n g to explain K a n t , Fichte adopts a p o i n t o f v i e w t h a t differs f r o m K a n t ' s , a n d t h e n he a n d the other idealists create t h e i r o w n philosophies. A c t u a l l y , they create t h e i r o w n p h i losophies along K a n t i a n lines a n d , s t a r t i n g f r o m K a n t ' s w o r k , complete w h a t K a n t left undone. Expressed i n general terms, the three great idealists—Fichte, Schelling a n d H e g e l — a t t e m p t to create the metaphysics t h a t K a n t never got a r o u n d to creating. W e w i l l presently see the extent to w h i c h this is t r u e . 2. N E O - K A N T I A N I S M . L e t us consider the second manifestation o f K a n t i a n i s m . I t is h e l p f u l to fix o u r a t t e n t i o n o n the name i t s e l f — n e o Kantianism. T h i s m o v e m e n t is a n express a c t u a l i z a t i o n of the past, for these m e n are n o t K a n t i a n s , b u t /wo-Kantians. Therefore, K a n t i a n i s m is n o t something t h a t is i n the present, b u t something t h a t needs to be renewed, actualized. T h e neo-Kantians become the exegetes o f K a n t i a n i s m : H e r m a n n Cohen a n d P a u l N a t o r p , especially. T h e y do not c l a i m to present K a n t , b u t a ««o-Kant. T h e i r position i n r e l a t i o n to t h a t o f the G e r m a n idealists is: K a n t ' s philosophy is n o t as y o u have presented i t ; i t is something different, w h i c h we w i l l n o w e x p o u n d . N e o - K a n t i a n i s m is n o t merely K a n t i a n i s m , a n d so something m u s t
300
The
Problem
oj Kantian
Philosophy
have taken place somewhere along the l i n e to justify the p r e f i x . W h a t can have happened? Positivism ( f r o m 1835-40 to 1880, a p p r o x i m a t e l y ) . T h e neo-Kantians are positivista w h o cease to b e positivists, w h o derive f r o m p o s i t i v i s m ; this is w h a t determines the character o f n e o - K a n t i a n philosophy. K a n t i a n i s m has the f o l l o w i n g characteristics: (1) t h e denial o f metaphysics i n any f o r m ; (2) a very p r o n o u n c e d tendency to become a theory o f knowledge; (3) a great interest i n the. positive sciences a n d (4) the tendency to understand philosophy as a t h e o r y o f positive science. As for the Critique of Pure Reason, (1) i t attempts t o determine the possibilities o f knowledge; (2) i t attempts to establish a philosophic theory of the science o f its d a y — m a t h e m a t i c s a n d N e w t o n i a n physics; (3) i t comes to reject t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics as impossible. A l l this is p a r t of the Critique of Pure Reason, a n d this is w h a t the positivists see i n K a n t ; b u t the Critique contains a great deal more, a n d m u c h m a t e r i a l o f greater i m p o r t a n c e . N e o - K a n t i a n i s m is colored b y p o s i t i v i s m a n d tends to become a theory o f science, a philosophic reflection o n knowledge a n d the positive sciences. Therefore, i t is s o m e t h i n g very different f r o m G e r m a n idealism. 3. PRESENT-DAY P H I L O S O P H Y . W e n o w come d o w n t o the present t i m e . K a n t ' s w o r k can m e a n something q u i t e different t o us because m a n y very significant events separate us f r o m the n e o - K a n t i a n s : (1) the elaboration o f a philosophy o f life o f a metaphysical character, w h i c h began w i t h K i e r k e g a a r d , Nietzsche, D i l t h e y a n d Bergson; (2) the establishment o f Husserl's phenomenology, for w h i c h Brentano prepared the w a y , a n d (3) most recently, the d e v e l o p m e n t of a metaphysics of h u m a n life or rather of v i t a l reason ( O r t e g a ) , o r a n ontology o f existence (Heidegger). W e have therefore r e t u r n e d to metaphysics. I t has once again been clearly perceived t h a t p h i l o s o p h y is metaphysics a n d n o t h i n g else, a n d t h a t theory of knowledge is metaphysics a n d cannot be considered a n autonomous a n d p r i o r discipline. T h u s , the n e o - K a n t i a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of K a n t seems to us to be i n c o m p l e t e — t h a t is, false—because i t emphasizes o n l y w h a t is least i m p o r t a n t . For us, K a n t is first o f all a metaphysician, one w h o d i d n o t elaborate his philosophy systematically b u t w h o nevertheless left i t t o u s — i n the pages w h i c h the neo-Kantians f o u n d o f least interest. A n d K a n t ' s metaphysics has to be such t h a t i t makes clear h o w the other metaphysical systems o f G e r m a n idealism arose o u t o f i t . (For further discussion o f a l l these questions, see the above-mentioned essay b y O r t e g a : Filosofía
pura.) 2.
T H E O R Y OF
KNOWLEDGE
L e t us a t t e m p t a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f K a n t ' s c o n t r i b u t i o n b y con-
Theory of
Knowledge
sidering t w o aspects o f his w o r k : the d o c t r i n e o f being a n d the d o c t r i n e o f knowledge. These t w o aspects, w h i c h are i n t i m a t e l y i n t e r connected, can lead us to a n u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f K a n t ' s basic concept, t h a t o f the m o r a l person a n d p r a c t i c a l reason. W h e n we achieve t h a t understanding we w i l l f i n d ourselves at a h i g h p o i n t o f K a n t i a n philosophy, a n d f r o m there w e w i l l be able to view subsequent developments. T h e t w o aspects o f the p r o b l e m are inseparable. K a n t r a d i c a l l y alters the concept o f knowledge. T h i s subject is w h a t is k n o w n as criticism a n d w h a t interested the neo-Kantians. W e are g o i n g to emphasize a different aspect i n o u r discussion, one w h i c h w i l l reveal K a n t ' s idea o f being. L e t us keep i n m i n d the K a n t i a n d o c t r i n e o f the phenomenon a n d the thing-in-itself. O f this, w h a t n o w interests us is the f o l l o w i n g : K n o w l e d g e is a n active f u n c t i o n o f the t h i n k i n g subject; i t does n o t consist o f receiving something t h a t happens to be at h a n d , b u t o f creating something t h a t is k n o w n ; i n K a n t i a n terms, the subject posits something. K a n t says t h a t we k n o w o f the things o n l y w h a t we have posited i n t h e m ; thus, for K a n t the things are n o t at h a n d ; rather, the t h i n k i n g subject creates t h e m u p o n k n o w i n g t h e m . T h i s must be understood l i t e r a l l y , for otherwise i t m i g h t be t h o u g h t t h a t the o n l y t h i n g t h a t exists i n itself is the ego, t h a t the o n l y t h i n g - i n itself is the ego, a n d t h a t the other things are in me. B u t this is n o t so; I a m n o t i n myself a thing-in-itself because I a m a t h i n g to myself o n l y i n so far as I k n o w myself. W e are going to emphasize the opposite aspect: the objective aspect. O n e must a v o i d possible subjectivist interpretations o f K a n t i a n i s m . I neither create n o r i n v e n t the things; instead, there is something t h a t is essentially given to me, a n d u p o n this I posit the a p r i o r i forms o f sensibility a n d the categories. O n l y after I have applied these forms to w h a t is given is i t m e a n i n g f u l to speak o f k n o w n things or o f the being o f the things. H o w e v e r , the situation is n o t such t h a t there is o n one h a n d w h a t is given, w h a t K a n t calls the chaos o f sensations, a n d o n the other the ego w i t h its subjective determinations. T h i s w o u l d m e a n t h a t there were t w o things-in-themselves a n d t h a t knowledge arose f r o m t h e i r u n i o n or contact; the t r u t h is t h a t the chaos o f sensations c a n occur o n l y i n m y subjectivity, because i n order to exist i t must occur i n space a n d t i m e a n d , therefore, i n m e ; a n d , conversely, the ego exists o n l y i n r e l a t i o n to w h a t is given. T h u s i t happens t h a t knowledge, far f r o m being the result o f the contact or u n i o n o f w h a t is g i v e n a n d w h a t is posited, is rather the superior fact o n w h i c h is based the very possibility o f speaking o f w h a t is given a n d w h a t is posited.
J02
The
Problem
of Kantian
3.
Philosophy
BEING
W e have seen t h a t K a n t ' s idea o f knowledge is r a d i c a l l y n e w ; i t constitutes a " Copernican r e v o l u t i o n " because i t is accomplished b y a new idea of being. O r t e g a has seen this w i t h e x t r a o r d i n a r y c l a r i t y . B E I N G A N D E N T I T Y . M a n has always asked himself what is being; this question embodies t w o meanings. W e must distinguish between t w o essentially different things : being a n d entity. These terms are generally used as synonyms, a n d there are languages such as F r e n c h i n w h i c h there is b u t one w o r d to convey b o t h meanings : l'être (the w o r d étant has recently been i n t r o d u c e d i n order to preserve the d i s t i n c t i o n w h e n translating G e r m a n expressions). I n scholastic L a t i n we have esse a n d ens; i n Greek, etvai a n d 6v; i n Spanish, ser a n d ente; i n G e r m a n , das Sein a n d das Seiende. I t is n o t a n accident t h a t these words have been generally confused, because i t has n o t been realized t h a t they deal w i t h t w o different things. Being is something t h a t belongs to the things t h a t exist, or something t h a t happens to t h e m a n d t h a t allows i t to be said of t h e m t h a t they are entities. A p a r t f r o m the question of w h a t — o r rather who—is the e n t i t y , o f w h a t things are, there exists the f u r t h e r a n d more p r o f o u n d question o f w h a t we m e a n w h e n we say t h a t things are. A r i s t o t l e , w h o i n his Metaphysics studied the e n t i t y as an entity, at least glimpsed this fundamental problem.
T h e e n t i t y has been spoken o f almost always, a n d i t has been understood as substance, subsistence; thus, w h e n Descartes affirms his idealist thesis, he affirms the ego, b u t the ego as a n e n t i t y , as a p r i m e substance : ego sum RES cogitans. A n d so idealism does not t o u c h u p o n the question o f w h a t is m e a n t b y substance, o f w h a t substance ( a n d therefore being) is. As l o n g as idealism is n o t h i n g b u t idealism, i t does n o t come to grips w i t h the basic p r o b l e m o f philosophy ; i t merely deals w i t h the relative r a n k of substances. T h e prôte ousia becomes the ego. W h a t the ego does is cogitare ; thus, w h a t actually exists a n d is the basis for the being of the other things is the cogitatio or idea. T h i s , therefore, is idealism. I n realism, i t is the res t h a t p r i n c i p a l l y exists, whereas i n idealism i t is the idea ; however, the idea is also res, res cogitans. T h e Cartesian concept o f substance is based o n the n o t i o n o f independence w h i c h h a d been t r a d i t i o n a l since A r i s t o t l e . T h i s i n dependence, this self-sufficiency, this subsistence, is in se. L e t us recall the difference between being in se a n d being a se. Being in se is this independence of the substance; o n l y G o d is a being a se. A n e n t i t y can be in se or in alio a n d , o n the other h a n d , a se or ab alio. T h e independence o f a color, a horse a n d a G o d , for example, are v e r y different.
Being
O n e cannot conceive o f a color b y itself, alone; not to be independent, to be i n association w i t h extension—this is p a r t o f the essence o f c o l o r ; color is ab alio, b u t i t is also in alio. A horse does n o t need anyt h i n g else i n order to be a horse; i t is independent in se. T h i s is i n reference to its essence—but w h a t a b o u t its existence? I n order to exist i t needs to be somewhere, for this is the m e a n i n g o f the w o r d " e x i s t . " Even i f we ignore the question o f the Creation, a horse or a stone or any finite e n t i t y cannot be said to exist independently, because o f the very significance o f the v e r b " t o exist." T o exist is ex-sistere; i n G e r m a n , da-sein. B o t h words c o n t a i n an obvious reference to place: ex, da, to be there, outside something. A c t u a l l y , i t is n o t a question o f place. L e t us recall K a n t ' s explanation o f the difference between one h u n d r e d possible crowns and one h u n d r e d real crowns; there is no difference i n the concept o f t h e m , b u t the one h u n d r e d real crowns exist n o t o n l y i n m y t h o u g h t , as do the possible crowns, b u t also outside i t , a m o n g the things. Therefore, they have need o f the existence o f other t h i n g s ; there must at least exist something in w h i c h the crowns can exist. W h a t is r e q u i r e d is a w o r l d i n w h i c h crowns and horses a n d stones can exist. T h u s , even i f we ignore the question o f w h e t h e r or n o t these things are independent o f G o d , they are still dependent o n the w o r l d . T h e horse a n d the stone are independent as regards essence, b u t dependent as regards existence; they are in se, b u t ab alio. O n l y G o d , whose essence contains H i s existence, is a n ensase. T R A N S C E N D E N T A L B E I N G . I t is here t h a t we f i n d K a n t ' s metaphysics. Its o r i g i n a l i t y derives f r o m this r a d i c a l i n t u i t i o n : being is not a real predicate. A real predicate w o u l d be something t h a t the things possessed i n themselves; t h a t is, the one h u n d r e d crowns w o u l d have something i n themselves t h a t w o u l d make t h e m be r e a l ; K a n t sees t h a t they d o not have a n y t h i n g i n themselves t h a t makes t h e m different f r o m the one h u n d r e d possible crowns. T h e difference is one of position, i n t h a t the real crowns are o u t there; they are placed a m o n g the things a n d are i n association w i t h the t o t a l i t y of experience. ( I n K a n t , this continuous connection w i t h experience is also a sign o f reality as opposed to dreams.) T h e character o f t h a t w h i c h exists is n o t a n i n t r i n s i c character; i t is a transcendental character: i t consists of a being in; i t is something t h a t transcends each t h i n g a n d is based o n each thing's r e l a t i o n to a l l the other things. A t this p o i n t there enters i n t o p l a y K a n t ' s extremely i m p o r t a n t d i s t i n c t i o n between t h i n k i n g a n d k n o w i n g . K n o w l e d g e is knowledge o f something, knowledge o f things; thus i t is n o t l i m i t e d to m y ideas, b u t involves a t r u e reference to the things. B u t one must distinguish
The
Problem
oj Kantian
Philosophy
between this idea o f k n o w i n g a n d the one w h i c h a realist w o u l d have. A realist w o u l d say t h a t m y knowledge knows things, b u t things t h a t are there, things-in-themselves. F o r K a n t , this is n o t the case; i t is n o t t h a t there are t w o things-in-themselves—the ego a n d the k n o w n t h i n g — a n d t h a t the ego knows the things, b u t t h a t i t is precisely i n the k n o w i n g t h a t the things are things a n d the ego is the ego. I t is n o t t h a t the things simply transcend me, for w i t h o u t m e there are no things; rather, knowledge is the basis for the being o f the k n o w n things a n d o f the ego t h a t knows t h e m . K n o w l e d g e is n o t something t h a t intervenes between the things a n d the ego, b u t neither are the things ideas o f m i n e ; knowledge makes the things be things w h i l e they are k n o w n to the ego, a n d the ego be the ego w h i l e i t knows the things. I n this way, knowledge gives the things a n d the ego their respective being, b u t does not become i n t e r m i n g l e d w i t h either. B u t this is n o t h i n g more t h a n w h a t we have called transcendental; we have thus explained w h y knowledge a n d being are b o t h called transcendental. G O D . T h e foregoing section explains K a n t ' s position r e g a r d i n g the ontological argument. T h i s p r o o f presupposed t h a t b e i n g was a real predicate and existence a n intrinsic perfection w h i c h G o d h a d to possess. B u t i f being is transcendental, m e r e l y to possess the idea o f G o d is n o t sufficient p r o o f t h a t H e exists; the existence o f G o d w o u l d o n l y be assured b y H i s position. A n d since G o d , b y H i s very n a t u r e as a n i n f i n i t e E n t i t y , does n o t furnish m e w i t h the possibility o f positing the conditions necessary to i n t u i t H i m , the result is t h a t G o d remains b e y o n d any possible experience. Since real things are distinguished f r o m possible things precisely b y their o c c u r r i n g to m e i n connection w i t h experience, neither the existence nor the non-existence o f G o d can be demonstrated. T h i s refutation o f the ontological a r g u m e n t shows t h a t i t is not j u s t a n y a r g u m e n t whatever, t h a t i t is n o t a piece o f reasoning o f the sort i n w h i c h one must observe whether or n o t i t is conclusive, b u t t h a t i t is a thesis w h i c h involves a n idea o f being, a n d thus a metaphysics; i t is possible to raise objections to i t o n l y b y starting o u t w i t h a different idea o f being. A n d any objection raised against this c r i t i q u e o f K a n t ' s must necessarily be raised against K a n t i a n metaphysics as a whole. N o w we can understand i n its entirety the p r o b l e m o f G o d i n the philosophy o f idealism. I n K a n t , speculative reason must renounce the intellectual possession o f G o d , a n d can no longer use H i m as a basis. As a result o f this, metaphysics is r a d i c a l l y changed. T h e metaphysics j u s t before this, seventeenth-century r a t i o n a l i s m , was based o n the presupposition o f the certainty o f God's existence. T h i s is n o w impossible. Being is i n t e r p r e t e d i n a different sense, a n d i n contrast to
Philosophy
the dogmatic idealism, f r o m w h i c h K a n t , according to his famous phrase, had awakened, philosophy becomes a transcendental idealism. T h i s changes the situation o f G o d vis-à-vis the m i n d , the entire p r o b l e m o f b e i n g a n d , w i t h i t , philosophy. T h i s change is also occasioned b y the fact t h a t the ontological argument is no longer considered v a l i d a n d conclusive. T h u s begins the last stage of idealism ; the b o n d w h i c h has u n t i l n o w c o n t i n u e d to u n i t e G o d w i t h theoretic reason is b r o k e n , a n d the metaphysical process w h i c h began at the close o f medieval Scholasticism is completed. I n this last stage, G o d reappears i n a new guise i n the r e a l m o f p r a c t i c a l reason, a n d i n a different f o r m i n a l l metaphysics subsequent to K a n t , especially t h a t o f Hegel. A t t h a t p o i n t the ontological a r g u m e n t acquires new p h i l o sophical v a l i d i t y . 4.
PHILOSOPHY
K a n t i a n metaphysics reaches its c u l m i n a t i o n i n the concept o f the m o r a l person a n d i n the theory of p r a c t i c a l reason. W e have seen t h a t K a n t f o u n d metaphysics to be impossible as a science; b u t t w o i n d u b i t a b l e facts imposed themselves o n K a n t : the fact o f metaphysics as a natural predisposition of m a n a n d the fact of m o r a l i t y . K a n t asked himself whether metaphysics was possible as a science, b u t n o t whether i t was possible as a y e a r n i n g , as a n a t u r a l predisposition, because i t has existed as such for centuries a n d centuries. I t is necessary to take l i t e r a l l y the expression natural predisposition (Naturanlage), something w h i c h is i n n a t u r e . T h i s means t h a t m a n has i n his very n a t u r e the predisposition to practice metaphysics. W O R L D L Y CONCEPT OF PHILOSOPHY. K a n t gives certain reasons to e x p l a i n w h y m a n philosophizes ; he is n o t content merely to say t h a t i t is a n a t u r a l predisposition. T r u e philosophy is n o t philosophy i n a scholastic sense (Schulbegriff), b u t i n a w o r l d l y sense (Weltbegriff). In this sense, philosophy is the system o f the u l t i m a t e ends o f reason; b y means o f philosophy m a n chooses the u l t i m a t e ends. T h e u l t i m a t e problems of w o r l d l y philosophy are four i n n u m b e r : ( 1) (a) (3) (4)
What What What What
can I k n o w ? (Metaphysics) o u g h t I to do ? (Ethics) m a y I hope for ? (Religion) is m a n ? ( A n t h r o p o l o g y )
" B u t b a s i c a l l y , " K a n t says, " a l l o f this can be left to a n t h r o pology, because the first three questions a l l refer to the last." P h i losophy becomes anthropology. T h e u l t i m a t e end o f philosophy is t h a t m a n should k n o w himself. T h e highest object o f metaphysics is the h u m a n person.
Jo6
The Problem
of Kantian
Philosophy
I t happens that the knowledge o f w h a t a h u m a n person is involves m a n y questions : W h a t is the w o r l d i n w h i c h this person is located ? W h a t is a person ? W h a t m a y he hope for a n d , thus, w h a t can he k n o w a b o u t G o d ? T h i s brings us back to the three themes o f classical metaphysics. W h a t does this m e a n ? H o w is K a n t able to r e t u r n t o these inaccessible objects ? H e r e they do n o t appear as objects o f theoretic, b u t o f p r a c t i c a l reason. These objects are n o t a t t a i n e d b y means o f speculative knowledge ; rather, m a n apprehends himself as a moral person i n a w a y w h i c h is not open to p r o o f b u t w h i c h is d i r e c t l y self-evident to the subject. A n d this factum o f m o r a l i t y requires a n e x p l a n a t i o n . W h a t are the things w h i c h make i t possible for m a n to be a m o r a l person? T h e y are the freedom o f the w i l l , i m m o r t a l i t y a n d the existence o f G o d . Practical reason places us i n e x t r e m e l y close, u n c o n d i t i o n a l a n d absolute contact w i t h these things, w h i c h are its postulates. Practical reason consists i n the absolute self-determ i n a t i o n o f the m o r a l subject. T h i s is the f u n d a m e n t a l m e a n i n g o f K a n t ' s pure reason.
Fichte
L I F E A N D W O R K S . J o h a n n G o t t l i e b Fichte was b o r n at R a m m e n a u i n 1762. H e was o f h u m b l e o r i g i n , the son o f a weaver. By chance, a focal n o b l e m a n recognized Fichte's e x t r a o r d i n a r y capabilities w h e n he was l i t t l e m o r e t h a n a c h i l d , a n d enabled h i m to pursue his studies. Despite great economic difficulties F i c h t e studied theology at the U n i v e r s i t y o f Jena, a n d then devoted himself to private t u t o r i n g . I n 1791 he met K a n t , w h o was already a n o l d m a n , and the next year, t h r o u g h the good offices o f the great philosopher, he published his Versuch einer Kritik aller Offenbarung (Essay towards a C r i t i q u e o f A l l R e v e l a t i o n ) , w h i c h appeared w i t h o u t his name a n d was a t t r i b u t e d to K a n t . W h e n the t r u e author became k n o w n , the a t t e n t i o n aroused b y the book was directed t o w a r d Fichte a n d q u i c k l y made h i m famous. F r o m 1794 to 1799 he was a professor at Jena, where his a c t i v i t y as a w r i t e r was also great. H e had a clash w i t h the government concerning a n article published i n his review t h o u g h n o t w r i t t e n b y h i m , w h i c h was accused o f atheism; the philosopher's arrogance caused h i m to lose his position. H e moved o n to B e r l i n , where he became a m e m b e r o f the R o m a n t i c circles, at the same t i m e g i v i n g private classes w i t h great success. W h e n the French u n d e r N a p o l e o n invaded G e r m a n y , Fichte was active i n the campaign to arouse the G e r m a n s p i r i t ; i n the years 1807 a n d 1808 he delivered his famous Addresses to the German Nation (Reden an die deutsche Nation), w h i c h were one o f the decisive contributions t o w a r d the f o r m a t i o n o f Germany's n a t i o n a l consciousness. I n 1811 he was rector o f the U n i v e r s i t y o f B e r l i n , w h i c h h a d been f o u n d e d j u s t the year before. I n 1813 he took p a r t i n the Napoleonic 3°7
jo8
Fichte
c a m p a i g n as a n orator, w h i l e his wife w o r k e d as a nurse i n the hospitals of B e r l i n . A n infection w h i c h his wife contracted a n d w h i c h F i c h t e caught caused his death i n J a n u a r y , 1814. Fichte's o u t p u t is extensive. H i s p r i n c i p a l works are a series o f elaborations, each more m a t u r e t h a n the last, of one m a j o r w o r k t i t l e d Wissenschaftslehre ( T h e o r y o f Science). I n a d d i t i o n , he w r o t e Die Bestimmung des Menschen ( T h e V o c a t i o n o f M a n ) , Die Bestimmung des Gelehrten ( T h e V o c a t i o n o f the Scholar), the First a n d Second Introduction to the Theory of Science—four books w h i c h are useful as a n i n t r o d u c t i o n to Fichte's difficult philosophy—as w e l l as the Anweisung zum seligen Leben ( W a y to a Blessed Life) a n d , aside f r o m the abovem e n t i o n e d Addresses, several lectures o n the philosophy o f history t i t l e d Die Grundzüge des gegenwärtigen Zeitalters ( T h e Characteristics o f the Present A g e ) . Fichte was a personality o f exceptional vividness. H e always h a d a leaning t o w a r d p u b l i c a n d o r a t o r i c a l a c t i v i t y , a n d his c o n t r i b u t i o n to the f o r m a t i o n of the G e r m a n n a t i o n was very great. Fichte's l i t e r a r y style is energetic, lively a n d expressive.
1.
FICHTE'S
METAPHYSICS
K A N T A N D F I C H T E . Fichte's philosophy is directly derived f r o m K a n t ' s . A t the beginning, he presents his philosophy as a m a t u r e a n d p r o f o u n d exposition o f K a n t i a n i s m . B u t i t is difficult to see this philosophical genesis i f we adhere to the p o p u l a r image o f K a n t handed d o w n to us b y the nineteenth century. I t is necessary to r e t u r n to the p o i n t at w h i c h K a n t s u m m e d u p the m e a n i n g of his philosophy. T h e c u l m i n a t i o n of K a n t i a n philosophy was p r a c t i c a l reason. K a n t ended b y a f f i r m i n g the p r i m a c y o f p r a c t i c a l over theoretic reason, a n d the m o r a l person, K a n t ' s pure ego, d e t e r m i n e d himself p r a c t i c a l l y a n d u n c o n d i t i o n a l l y . T h e self-determination o f the ego b y p r a c t i c a l reason is very clearly seen i n the f o r m t h a t c o u l d be given to the categorical i m p e r a t i v e : do what you will, emphasizing the will; do w h a t y o u are able to w i l l . For Fichte, the m o r a l i m p e r a t i v e consists i n saying: become the man you are (werde, der du bist), a n d i n this sense Fichte's i m p e r a t i v e is n o t far removed f r o m K a n t ' s , because w h e n K a n t says, " D o w h a t y o u w i l l " or " B e f r e e , " he asks m a n to act i n accordance w i t h w h a t he u l t i m a t e l y is, to determine himself, w i t h freedom. I n this w a y the e m p i r i c a l ego, w h i c h is d e t e r m i n e d by m a n y things, o u g h t to act, according to K a n t , as i f i t were free, or, expressed differently, the e m p i r i c a l ego o u g h t to a i m to be the p u r e ego t h a t i t is essentially. T h u s Fichte tells m a n : " Be the m a n y o u a r e , " a i m to be the m a n y o u
Fichte
s
Metaphysics
are essentially. I n Fichte (as i n K a n t , w h e n a l l is summed up) m o r a l i t y consists i n adjusting to w h a t one t r u l y is, i n n o t falsifying oneself. T h e t w o positions have a presupposition i n c o m m o n : t h a t h u m a n matters can have v a r y i n g degrees o f r e a l i t y . T o say, " Become the m a n y o u a r e , " is to m a i n t a i n the w e i g h t y hypothesis that h u m a n m a t e r i a l admits o f degrees o f reality, that i t is possible to be m a n i n v a r y i n g degrees of greater or lesser imperfection. T H E EGO. I t was n o t a n a r b i t r a r y choice to begin this very b r i e f exposition o f Fichte's t h o u g h t w i t h his ethical doctrine. T h e p o i n t o f departure of his metaphysics—and at the same t i m e the p o i n t at w h i c h i t is affiliated w i t h K a n t i a n i s m — i s this self-determination o f the ego. A t the same t i m e we see w i t h c l a r i t y t h a t ethics is n o t h i n g other t h a n metaphysics, a major aspect o f a l l o f metaphysics a n d even, perhaps, its c u l m i n a t i o n . T h e ego is the basis o f Fichte's philosophy. W e must direct o u r a t t e n t i o n for a m o m e n t to this concept, w h i c h we have been enc o u n t e r i n g w i t h increasing frequency a n d w h i c h has been becoming m o r e a n d m o r e central to philosophy. O r t e g a l i k e d to relate the marvelous story of the ego. A t the outset, i n Greece, the ego was practically non-existent or else was a secondary t h i n g . For a Greek, the ego was a t h i n g ; i t h a d certain i n d i v i d u a l traits, b u t i t was after a l l j u s t another t h i n g . W h e n the G r e e k s — m e n of i n v o l v e d a n d tortuous m e n t a l i t y , w h o carried their u r b a n i t y even i n t o m e t a p h y s i c s — h a d to speak o f the ego, they used the p l u r a l a n d said " w e , "
rj/xe
Is.
A f t e r the Greeks, the ego acquires a new a n d extraordinary r a n k . I n the C h r i s t i a n M i d d l e Ages, i t becomes the subject of a mission, o f a destiny; the ego is a creature, b u t one created i n the image a n d likeness o f G o d , a n d the subject of a destiny, o f a personal mission. L a t e r , after the Renaissance, i n the Baroque age, the ego's career is i n the ascendant. " A s i n O r i e n t a l tales, the m a n w h o was a beggar awakens as a prince. L e i b n i z is so b o l d as to call m a n un petit Dieu. K a n t makes the ego the supreme legislator of nature. Fichte, immoderate i n this as i n a l l else, w i l l n o t be content w i t h less t h a n saying: the Ego is everyt h i n g " ( O r t e g a : Las dos grandes metdforas [ T h e T w o Great M e t a phors]). I t is necessary to a d d that the idea o f man has undergone very p r o f o u n d changes. I n a n t i q u i t y , m a n is a distinctive e n t i t y w h o possesses the strange property o f k n o w i n g the other things, a n d since he is one t h i n g a m o n g the others, i n a certain sense he envelops t h e m a l l . I n the M i d d l e Ages, m a n is a creature made i n the image a n d likeness o f G o d ; as a result of this, G o d is i n v o l v e d i n the p r o b l e m o f
J20
Fichte
m a n (this, let i t be said i n passing, shows the impossibility o f u n d e r standing C h r i s t i a n ethics as heteronomous, since G o d is never s o m e t h i n g alien t o m a n b u t , o n the c o n t r a r y , his exemplary I d e a ) . B u t i n Greece there h a d already occurred something analogous, a l t h o u g h very different: the " d i v i n e s o m e t h i n g " w h i c h m a n possesses i n Aristotle's philosophy. I n the m o d e r n age, something t o t a l l y new occurs. U p to n o w philosophers have spoken o f m a n , b u t i n the m o d e r n age i t seems t h a t m a n himself vanishes, leaving a token o f himself i n his p l a c e ; i n effect, we see t h a t people speak a b o u t the ego, the w i l l , reason, n a t u r a l l i g h t a n d so f o r t h , b u t n o t a b o u t m a n . W h e n Descartes says ego sum res cogitans, he does n o t say man is, b u t lam; therefore, i t is meaningless t o raise objections to Descartes f r o m the standpoint o f A r i s t o t l e , o r vice versa, because Descartes a n d K a n t speak a b o u t the ego whereas A r i s t o t l e speaks a b o u t m a n . N a t u r a l l y , m a n contains a n element o f egoity, b u t m a n a n d the ego are n o t identical. N o r is the fullness o f h u m a n life exhausted i n the ego. * T h i s digression allows us t o understand the basis o f Fichte's p h i losophy. Fichte says t h a t the ego posits itself and in so doing posits the nonego. W h a t does this mean? I n the first place, the non-ego is s i m p l y everything t h a t is n o t the ego, e v e r y t h i n g t h a t the ego encounters. F i c h t e returns energetically to K a n t ' s concept of position. T h e ego posits itself; this means t h a t i t posits itself as existing, t h a t i t affirms itself as existing. T h e ego posits itself i n an a c t i o n , and i n every a c t i o n there is i m p l i c i t the position o f the ego w h i c h executes i t . L e t us a p p r o a c h this f r o m the other d i r e c t i o n . I n K a n t , position was the positing or p l a c i n g o f oneself a m o n g the things. T h u s , i n F i c h t e , w h e n the ego posits itself, i t posits t h a t w h i c h is other t h a n the ego, i n contrast to w h i c h i t posits itself. T h e position of the ego cannot occur i n i s o l a t i o n ; i t must be a position along with the " o t h e r . " Beginning w i t h Brentano, philosophers have once again defined h u m a n actions as intentional actions; t h a t is, a n action is always directed t o w a r d a n object, the object o f t h a t action. A n a c t i o n presupposes the f o l l o w i n g : a subject t o execute i t , the action itself a n d the object t o w a r d w h i c h the a c t i o n is directed. T h i s idea o f the f u n d a m e n t a l i n t e n t i o n a l i t y of m a n has shaped a l l of present-day philosophy. A n d i t is not strange t h a t this philosophy has looked back to F i c h t e as a classic forerunner o f its position. REALITY. The
thing—results,
p o s i t i o n o f the ego a n d the n o n - e g o — t h a t is,
every-
according to Fichte, i n a n action. R e a l i t y is thus p u r e
*See my anthology of philosophical writings, El tema del hombre, particularly the Introduction (Madrid, Revista de Occidente, 1943).
Fichte
s
Idealism
activity, liveliness, n o t substance or a t h i n g . T h i s is decisive, a n d constitutes the most p r o f o u n d a n d o r i g i n a l aspect of Fichte's metaphysics. A n d since this r e a l i t y is based o n a n action o f the ego, Fichte's p h i losophy is also idealism. For Fichte, this transcendental idealism is the o n l y philosophy proper to free m a n , a n d he says i n a famous sentence: " T h e type of philosophy one chooses depends o n the type of m a n one is."
2.
FICHTE'S IDEALISM
" T A T H A N D L U N G . " W e have seen t h a t for Fichte the position of the ego a n d the non-ego is reduced to p u r e action, p u r e a c t i v i t y ; true r e a l i t y is far f r o m being substance; i t is Tathandlung, w h i c h means a c t i v i t y , liveliness, deed. R e a l i t y loses its character as a substance a n d becomes p u r e d y n a m i s m . T h i s is the p r o f o u n d i n t u i t i o n o f Fichte's t h o u g h t , as O r t e g a has seen. I N T U I T I O N A N D CONCEPT. I n t u i t i o n , however, is one t h i n g , a n d concept or t h o u g h t another. K a n t said t h a t t h o u g h t w i t h o u t i n t u i t i o n was b l i n d , b u t t h a t i n t u i t i o n w i t h o u t t h o u g h t was n o t science. I n t u i t i o n m u s t raise itself to concepts. H o w e v e r , Fichte is n o t able to express his i n t u i t i o n conceptually a n d adequately because he is a prisoner o f the K a n t i a n i s m w h i c h he strives to continue. T h i s makes h i m r a t h e r uneasy, a n d thus his entire w o r k is a series of re-elaborations of his basic book. T h e w o r d " i n t u i t i o n " comes f r o m intueri, to see, a n d " c o n c e p t " comes f r o m concipere, capere cum, to grasp w i t h . Fichte does not have the intellectual tools w i t h w h i c h to grasp w h a t he has seen, a n d he does n o t succeed i n t a k i n g possession of i t . Therefore he carries on w i t h i n the l i m i t s o f K a n t i a n philosophy, and his metaphysics is idealist. O f w h a t does Fichte's idealism consist ? I D E A L I S M . T o begin w i t h , the p r i m a r y reality is the ego. Fichte does not say t h a t there is a reality one o f whose elements is the ego, a n d t h a t the ego is necessarily opposed b y the non-ego (this expresses his p r o f o u n d i n t u i t i o n ) ; instead he says t h a t the ego posits itself a n d u p o n d o i n g so posits the non-ego. T h a t is, the non-ego necessarily accompanies the ego, b u t this non-ego is n o t o r i g i n a l ; rather, i t is posited o n l y i n so far as the ego posits i t . Therefore, the non-ego is rooted i n the ego, a n d i t is the ego t h a t posits the non-ego. W h a t is i m p o r t a n t and positive i n Fichte is t h a t this position is n o t secondary; in order to be the ego, the ego must co-posit or compose the n o n ego. H o w e v e r , the ego is the basis for the non-ego, a n d i t has a basic p r i o r i t y . A n d this is still idealism. T h e non-ego's function is to l i m i t the ego; u p o n l i m i t i n g i t , i t gives
Fichte
the ego its t r u e reality. A p u r e ego, one t h a t exists u n c o n d i t i o n a l l y a n d separately, w o u l d be indefinite a n d u n r e a l . T h e ego affirms itself as the ego i n contrast to the non-ego i n a position w h i c h is p u r e a c t i v i t y , a n d w h i c h consists ofactively doing. ( I n this exposition o f t h e p r o b l e m o f Fichte's idealism I have f o l l o w e d , i n general, the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of m y teacher, Ortega.) K N O W L E D G E . T h e ego posits i t s e l f — i t affirms itself as ego—as i d e n t i c a l to itself. Its position is t h a t A = A , ego = ego. T h i s is n o t j u s t a t a u t o l o g y ; rather, i t expresses the f o r m a l character of t h e ego: the ego recognizes itself. M a n c a n enter i n t o himself a n d recognize h i m s e l f as something w h i c h is n o t i d e n t i c a l w i t h the non-ego. T h e synthesis of the thesis'' ego = ego'' a n d the antithesis'' non-ego ^ ego'' is measure. H e r e Fichte is i n the most classical t r a d i t i o n , one t h a t dates f r o m Greece. Measure, the one, is w h a t makes the things be. T h e synthesis o f the ego a n d the non-ego is effected b y knowledge.
K n o w l e d g e is the
transcendental
unity of the ego and the non-ego. A n d Fichte says: " W e d o n o t possess knowledge, rather knowledge possesses us. K n o w l e d g e is n o t i n us, rather we are i n k n o w l e d g e . " T h i s is the precise m e a n i n g o f the expression to be in truth.
Schilling
L I F E A N D WORKS. F r i e d r i c h W i l h e l m Joseph v o n Schelling was b o r n i n W ü r t t e m b e r g i n 17 75 a n d d i e d i n 1854. H e was one o f the very few philosophers w h o were e x t r a o r d i n a r i l y precocious. H e studied theology at T ü b i n g e n w i t h Hölderlin a n d Hegel, w h o were friends o f his. Schelling also devoted himself intensely to studies i n philosophy, a n d i n 1795, w h e n he was t w e n t y years o l d , he published his book Vom Ich als Prinzip der Philosophie ( O n the Ego as a Principle of P h i l o s o p h y ) , a w o r k w h i c h was greatly influenced b y Fichte. T w o years later Schelling w r o t e the Ideen zu einer Philosophie der Natur (Ideas for a N a t u r a l Philosophy), a n d the f o l l o w i n g year he was a p p o i n t e d a professor at Jena. T h e r e he established ties w i t h the R o m a n t i c circles ( L u d w i g T i e c k , the h i s t o r i a n o f Spanish l i t e r a t u r e ; Novalis, the brothers Schlegel). L a t e r he m a r r i e d Caroline Schlegel, a n interesting personality w i t h i n the R o m a n t i c m o v e m e n t a n d the former wife of August W i l h e l m Schlegel. A t Jena Schelling w r o t e one o f his major works, System des transzendentalen Idealismus (System o f Transcendental I d e a l i s m ) , the Bruno a n d the Darstellung meines Systems der Philosophie (Exposition o f M y System o f Philosophy). T h e n he w e n t to W ü r z b u r g a n d , i n 1806, to the A c a d e m y o f Sciences i n M u n i c h . H e was a professor at E r l a n g e n f r o m 1820 to 1827 a n d at M u n i c h f r o m 1827 to 1841. F r o m 1841 he was a professor at the U n i v e r s i t y o f B e r l i n . T o complete the list o f his most i m p o r t a n t works we must a d d his investigations Über das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit (On the N a t u r e o f H u m a n Freedom) (1809). I n the f i n a l p e r i o d of his life he w r o t e p r i n c i p a l l y o n the philosophy o f r e l i g i o n :
Schelling
3H
der Mythologie und Offenbarung (Philosophy o f M y t h o l o g y and Revelation). Schelling, w h o h a d a very acute u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f the n a t u r a l sciences a n d , at the same t i m e , o f beauty a n d a r t , is a representative figure of the R o m a n t i c age. H i s influence o n the science o f esthetics has been p r o f o u n d . H e also devoted m u c h a t t e n t i o n to p r o b l e m s o f r e l i g i o n a n d history.
Philosophic
THE
PHASES O F S C H E L L I N G ' S
PHILOSOPHY
P H I L O S O P H I C PERSONALITY. T h e r e have been v e r y few precocious philosophers, a n d Schelling is the most spectacular example. B y the time he was t w e n t y he h a d w o r k e d o u t a system o f p h i l o s o p h y ; however, since he l i v e d to be almost eighty, he m a d e u p f o u r distinct systems. A l l four systems are i n reality b u t the i n t e r n a l e v o l u t i o n o f a single system w h i c h develops a n d matures over this p e r i o d of t i m e ; b u t the phases differ f r o m one another enough so t h a t one can speak of f o u r different systems: those of'the philosophy of nature and spirit, oiidentity, of freedom,
a n d o f p o s i t i v e religious
philosophy.
Philosophically, Schelling derives f r o m K a n t a n d F i c h t e , a n d f r o m the latter i n very direct fashion. Hegel, w h o was a f r i e n d o f his, represents a later m o m e n t i n metaphysics, a m o m e n t o f f u l l m a t u r i t y , even t h o u g h Schelling was somewhat the younger o f the t w o . G e r m a n idealism culminates i n Hegel, a n d achieves its p l e n i t u d e a t the t i m e o f his death. A c t u a l l y , Schelling's longevity represents n o t h i n g b u t mere survival. N A T U R E A N D SPIRIT. W e saw t h a t Fichte began w i t h t h e position o f the ego, w h i c h established the basic d u a l i s m o f the ego a n d the n o n ego. I n G e r m a n idealism this division gives rise to the p r o b l e m o f the distinction between the k i n g d o m o f n a t u r e a n d the k i n g d o m o f freed o m . T h e idealists must establish a relationship b e t w e e n these t w o very different modes o f b e i n g : nature a n d spirit. T h i s is t h e p r o b l e m w i t h w h i c h Schelling is concerned, a n d i t culminates i n H e g e l i a n philosophy. T h e first phase o f Schelling's t h o u g h t makes considerable use o f the n a t u r a l science o f t h a t day, especially o f chemistry a n d biology, w h i c h Schelling frequently interprets w i t h too m u c h freedom a n d i m a g i n a t i o n . E l e c t r i c i t y h a d o n l y j u s t been discovered—the d i s p r o p o r t i o n ate use o f the adjective " e l e c t r i c " i n the l i t e r a r y works o f this era is w e l l k n o w n — a n d i n this w a y N e w t o n i a n mechanics h a d been c o m pleted. O n the other h a n d , evolutionary ideas were m a k i n g t h e m selves felt i n the field o f biology. Schelling's p h i l o s o p h y o f nature,
The
Phases
of Schelling's
Philosophy
w h i c h sometimes abandons itself to p u r e i m a g i n a t i v e speculation w i t h o u t contact w i t h reality, greatly influenced psychology a n d also, i n p a r t i c u l a r , medicine i n the R o m a n t i c age. N a t u r e is intelligence i n the process o f " b e c o m i n g , " Schelling says—spirit w h i c h is c o m i n g to be. A c t u a l l y , i t occurs as a slow awakening of the spirit. T h i s explains the connection between n a t u r e a n d spirit w h i c h is especially m a n i fested i n the l i v i n g organism or i n works o f art, each one i n its respective sphere. T h e absolute w h i c h is at the base o f b o t h is revealed i n history, a r t a n d r e l i g i o n . W e see i n these ideas e m b r y o n i c forms o f elements t h a t w i l l appear f u l l y developed i n Schelling's later systems. I D E N T I T Y . T h e second system, t h a t o f i d e n t i t y , consists i n establishing a bridge between n a t u r e a n d spirit b y means o f s o m e t h i n g t h a t m a y be b o t h spirit a n d n a t u r e , a m o m e n t at w h i c h n a t u r e a n d spirit are identical. I n the previous system, spirit is the u l t i m a t e phase of the e v o l u t i o n o f nature. H e r e there is a c o m m o n , i d e n t i c a l zone i n w h i c h nature is spirit a n d spirit, n a t u r e . T h i s i d e n t i t y , Schelling says, cannot be expressed conceptually; i t can o n l y be k n o w n b y intellectual intuition (intellektuelle Anschauung). H e g e l said that this was " like a pistol s h o t " ; a n d t h a t i d e n t i t y , w h i c h according to Schelling is a n indifference, was like the n i g h t " w h e r e i n a l l cats are g r a y . " T h i s system o f i d e n t i t y is pantheistic. As Hegel demonstrated, any system a f f i r m i n g t h a t being is always being a n d nothingness always nothingness is pantheistic, because i n such systems the p r i n c i p l e ex nihilo nihil fit is i n t e r p r e t e d i n a n absolute way, a n d the C r e a t i o n is impossible. I n this phase o f Schelling's t h o u g h t being is i d e n t i c a l w i t h itself and nothingness is also i d e n t i c a l w i t h itself. T H E METAPHYSICS O F FREEDOM. I n his t h i r d system, Schelling renounces the system o f i d e n t i t y . H e explains r e a l i t y as a n u n f o l d i n g , a n e v o l u t i o n b y means o f w h i c h i t develops b y degrees a n d manifests itself i n successive stages. I t changes f r o m i n o r g a n i c n a t u r e i n t o organic n a t u r e , a n d f r o m organic nature i n t o spirit. T h i s theory is connected to the movement o f the n a t u r a l sciences (especially biology) i n the d i r e c t i o n o f e v o l u t i o n a r y ideas at the b e g i n n i n g o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y . A c c o r d i n g to Schelling, reality evolves u n t i l i t reaches the highest f o r m , h u m a n freedom. N a t u r e awakens a n d raises itself by degrees u n t i l i t reaches freedom. T h i s idea h a d great beauty a n d a p o w e r f u l esthetic effect w h i c h was g r a t i f y i n g to the R o m a n t i c s p i r i t ; however, i t exasperated Hegel's rigorously logical a n d metaphysical mind. P O S I T I V E R E L I G I O N . T h e last phase o f Schelling's t h o u g h t denotes an a p p r o x i m a t i o n o f positive C h r i s t i a n religion, a l t h o u g h i t does not achieve o r t h o d o x y . Schelling creates a theistic metaphysics based on
Schelling
the idea o f h u m a n f r e e d o m ; its a c t i v i t y is oriented i n p a r t i c u l a r t o w a r d the theological i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f religion. A t t h a t m o m e n t speculative theology was b e i n g c u l t i v a t e d intensely i n G e r m a n y , a m o n g the Hegelians j u s t as m u c h as a m o n g the followers o f Schleiermacher. Schelling devoted p a r t i c u l a r a t t e n t i o n to the study o f m y t h o l o g y . I n his last years he was s u m m o n e d to B e r l i n to c o m b a t " H e g e l i a n p a n t h e i s m , " b u t as we have seen Hegel's p a n t h e i s m was never as complete a n d real as t h a t o f Schelling i n a n earlier p e r i o d . T h i s final stage o f Schelling's philosophy was regarded w i t h s y m p a t h y b y o r t h o d o x Protestants a n d even, i n a certain l i g h t , b y his Catholic contemporaries.
Hegel
L I F E A N D WORKS. Georg W i l h e l m F r i e d r i c h Hegel, a Swabian, was b o r n i n S t u t t g a r t i n 1770. H e came f r o m a middle-class Protestant f a m i l y . H e g e l was a serious student at the Gymnasium i n S t u t t g a r t a n d t h e n studied theology a n d philosophy at T ü b i n g e n . T h e r e he was an i n t i m a t e friend o f Schelling a n d Hölderlin; his friendship w i t h the l a t t e r was the longer-lasting, because Hegel a n d Schelling clashed on the question o f greatest i m p o r t a n c e to t h e m b o t h : philosophy. Afterw a r d , f r o m 1793 to 1800, H e g e l was a p r i v a t e t u t o r , a n d l i v e d i n Bern a n d i n F r a n k f u r t a m M a i n . I n 1801 he was a Privatdozent at Jena, b u t there his scant gifts as a n o r a t o r a n d the difficulty o f his classes failed to w i n h i m very m a n y students. H e was already f u l l y m a t u r e w h e n i n 1807 he published his first major w r i t i n g , one w h i c h contains a personal philosophy a n d n o t j u s t a p r o g r a m : the Phänomenologie des Geistes (Phenomenology o f the S p i r i t ) . Germany's economic situation was at t h a t t i m e affected b y w a r , a n d this circumstance obliged Hegel to accept a position as editor o f a newspaper published i n B a m b e r g i n order to l i v e ; however, he considered this a t e m p o r a r y a n d p a i n f u l task. T w o years later he was n a m e d dean o f the Gymnasium at N u r e m berg, a n d he remained there u n t i l 1816, w h e n he o b t a i n e d a university chair at H e i d e l b e r g . Hegel's stay i n N u r e m b e r g was very f r u i t f u l and busy; he m a r r i e d there i n 1811, a n d f r o m 1812 to 1816 he published his m a j o r w o r k , Wissenschaft der Logik (Science o f L o g i c ) . I n 1818 he was called to the U n i v e r s i t y o f B e r l i n ; he was a professor there u n t i l his death, a n d i n his last years he was also dean. W h i l e i n B e r l i n he p u b lished the Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften (Encyclopedia 3'7
Hegel
of the Philosophical Sciences) a n d gave enormously successful lectures w h i c h made h i m the m a j o r figure i n G e r m a n philosophy a n d even i n all philosophy at t h a t t i m e . H e d i e d o n N o v e m b e r 14, 1 8 3 1 , d u r i n g a cholera epidemic w h i c h ravaged B e r l i n . T h i s date marks the end of a b r i l l i a n t stage of philosophy a n d perhaps also of a n epoch of history. Besides the above-mentioned works, we must m e n t i o n several very i m p o r t a n t ones w h i c h were published as his course lectures. These i n c l u d e the
Philosophy
(Vorlesungen
iiber
of
Right,
die Philosophic
the der
Philosophy Weltgeschichte),
of
Universal the
History
Philosophy
of
a n d the History of Philosophy, the first exposition of this subject f r o m a strictly philosophical p o i n t of view. H e g e l was i n essence a philosopher. H i s entire life was consecrated to a m e d i t a t i o n t h a t left a p r o f o u n d stamp o f wear o n his face. " H e was w h a t his philosophy w a s , " Z u b i r i writes. " A n d his life was the history o f his p h i l o s o p h y ; everything else was for h i m his counterlife. F o r h i m , n o t h i n g h a d personal m e a n i n g unless i t c o u l d acquire m e a n i n g b y being relived philosophically. T h e Phenomenology did and does represent his awakening to p h i l o s o p h y — p h i l o s o p h y itself, the intellectual r e l i v i n g o f his existence as a manifestation o f w h a t he called absolute spirit. T h e h u m a n element i n Hegel, w h i c h is so quiet and foreign to philosophy o n the one h a n d , acquires, o n the other h a n d , the r a n k of philosophy b y raising itself to the highest celebration of w h a t is conceived. A n d , reciprocally, his conceptual t h o u g h t occurs i n the i n d i v i d u a l w h o was Hegel w i t h a force conferred o n i t b y the absolute essence o f spirit a n d the intellectual sediment o f a l l history. Therefore, i n a certain sense Hegel represents Europe's m a t u r i t y . " Religion
Hegel's t h o u g h t is as difficult as i t is i m p o r t a n t . I t is the c u l m i n a t i o n of a l l G e r m a n idealism i n its most rigorous a n d m a t u r e f o r m . O n e o f the most fertile attempts to understand a n d i n t e r p r e t Hegel's p h i losophy has been made b y m y teacher, Z u b i r i , w h o m I have q u o t e d above. T h e stamp of his i n t e r p r e t a t i o n is evident i n the discussion t h a t follows.
1.
T H E O U T L I N E OF H E G E L ' S
PHILOSOPHY
F o r Hegel philosophy is a p r o b l e m a n d therefore he feels t h a t i t must justify itself. Hegel f o u n d himself i n the midst of a philosophy a n d a theology w h i c h sought " n o t so m u c h for self-evidence as for e d i f i c a t i o n . " Philosophy h a d become more a n d more colored b y vague generalities a n d sterile profundities u n t i l i t h a d t u r n e d i n t o a mere hazy enthusiasm. T h i s seemed intolerable to H e g e l : n o t the leaning t o w a r d a n i n d e t e r m i n a t e enthusiasm, a vague sentiment of God, b u t the
The
"Phenomenology
of the
Spirit"
w i s h to make this i n t o philosophy or, since this is of course impossible, to make i t pass for philosophy. " P h i l o s o p h y must a v o i d the desire to be e d i f y i n g . " I n discussing the thinkers to w h o m he refers, Hegel says t h a t " t h e y believe they are a m o n g the elect to w h o m G o d grants w i s d o m w h i l e they slumber, b u t w h a t they actually conceive a n d give b i r t h to thus i n their slumbers are nonetheless o n l y d r e a m fantasies." But Hegel is n o t content w i t h mere reproaches. These words are f o l l o w e d b y the h u n d r e d s o f pages o f the Phenomenology
of the
Spirit.
H e g e l explains his purpose: " T h e true f o r m i n w h i c h t r u t h exists can o n l y be the scientific system o f t r u t h . T o c o n t r i b u t e t o w a r d m a k i n g philosophy a p p r o x i m a t e the f o r m of science—toward enabling i t to shed its name ' love o f k n o w l e d g e ' a n d be a real k n o w l e d g e — t h i s is w h a t I propose to d o . " I n the Phenomenology of the Spirit Hegel expounds the stages o f the m i n d u p to its a t t a i n m e n t o f absolute knowledge a n d the practice o f philosophy. O n l y f r o m this p o i n t on can a philosophy be created. T h e n he writes the Science of Logic, and later the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, i n w h i c h we find this o u t l i n e : L o g i c , Philosophy of N a t u r e , Philosophy o f the S p i r i t . Philosophy o f the S p i r i t includes i n t u r n the phenomenology o f the spirit, w h i c h we saw at the outset. W h a t m e a n i n g does this have? T w o very different viewpoints are i n v o l v e d : the Phenomenology contains the exposition o f the successive stages o f the spirit u p to its a t t a i n m e n t of absolute knowledge; b u t once philosophy has been practiced, this absolute knowledge embraces and comprehends everything, a n d the h u m a n spirit w i t h a l l its stages becomes p a r t o f i t . T h e spirit appears as an element of philosophy. F o r Hegel, reality is the absolute, w h i c h exists i n a dialectical e v o l u t i o n t h a t is logical a n d r a t i o n a l i n character. A c c o r d i n g to his famous statement, e v e r y t h i n g t h a t is real is r a t i o n a l a n d everything t h a t is r a t i o n a l is real. E v e r y t h i n g that exists is a n element o f this absolute, a stage i n the dialectical evolution w h i c h culminates i n philosophy, where the absolute spirit possesses itself i n knowledge.
2.
T H E "PHENOMENOLOGY
OF T H E
SPIRIT"
A B S O L U T E K N O W L E D G E . I n the Phenomenology of the Spirit Hegel explains the i n t e r n a l dialectic o f the spirit u p to its a r r i v a l at the b e g i n n i n g of philosophy. H e g e l re-examines the modes of knowledge. ( T h i n k i n g is different f r o m k n o w i n g . T o k n o w is to k n o w w h a t the things a r e ; k n o w i n g has a n essential element w h i c h refers to the things; we have already seen t h a t this was w h a t K a n t called " t r a n s cendental k n o w l e d g e . " ) Hegel distinguishes mere i n f o r m a t i o n
3
Hegel
2 0
(history) f r o m conceptual knowledge, i n w h i c h I possess t h e concepts o f the things (this w o u l d be the situation i n the sciences i n w h i c h there is a real knowledge). B u t a n absolute knowledge is still r e q u i r e d . Absolute knowledge is a n all-inclusive knowledge. I f i t is to be absolute, i t cannot leave a n y t h i n g outside itself, n o t even error. I t includes error as error. H i s t o r y must be this w a y : i t m u s t include a l l the elements o f the h u m a n spirit, even the elements o f e r r o r , w h i c h appear as such f r o m the standpoint of t r u t h . D I A L E C T I C S . T h i s dialectic o f the spirit i n H e g e l is logical, i t is a dialectic of pure reason. T h i s is w h a t casts d o u b t today o n Hegel's p h i losophy o f history. T h e spirit passes t h r o u g h a series o f stages before i t reaches absolute knowledge. A t the outset o f p h i l o s o p h y is being. Philosophy begins here. T h u s , philosophy begins w i t h b e i n g .
3.
T H E "LOGIC"
T H E M E A N I N G OF T H E " L O G I C . "
T h e p r o b l e m " W h a t is dialectic ? "
is ancient a n d c o m p l e x ; this question, w h i c h has been a concern o f philosophy f r o m the t i m e o f Plato, reaches its greatest urgency i n H e g e l , since i t constitutes the core o f his system. D i a l e c t i c is n o t a passage o f the m i n d t h r o u g h various stages, b u t a movement of being. T h e r e is a necessary t r a n s i t i o n f r o m one stage to another, a n d each stage contains the truth o f the one before. (One should r e m e m b e r the significance o f " t r u t h " i n Greek—aletheia—patency.) I n each stage, the previous one is manifested a n d made evident, a n d this is its t r u t h . E a c h stage includes the one before i t , w h i c h is absorbed w i t h i n i t , t h a t is, preserved and superseded at the same t i m e . Hegel's Logic is thus a dialectic o f being, a logos o f the on, of the e n t i t y ; thus, onto-logy. Hegel's logic is metaphysical. THE
STAGES OF H E G E L I A N T H O U G H T . S u m m i n g u p w h a t we
have
said a b o u t Hegel's conception of knowledge, we find t h a t i t fits i n t o the f o l l o w i n g o u t l i n e ; i t should be noted t h a t this is n o t a division b u t , once a g a i n , a m o v e m e n t o f being. Phenomenology of the spirit (beginning of philosophy) Knowledge
Science of logic < Philosophy (the Encyclopedia) J Philosophy of the spirit Philosophy of nature
{
Doctrine of being Doctrine of science Doctrine of concept
The
"Logic"
W i t h i n being we distinguish the f o l l o w i n g three elements: i . Determinateness (quality) 2. Quantity 3. M e a s u r e
{
W i t h i n quality—to f o l l o w the example o f H e g e l i a n d i a l e c t i c — w e distinguish three stages: 1. Being (Sein) 2. Existence (Dasein) 3. Being for oneself (Fiirsichsein)
{
W i t h i n the first o f these t h r e e — t h i s being distinguish:
without
quality—we
1. Being (Sein) 2. Nothingness (Nichts) 3. Becoming (Werderi)
{
A l l this, I repeat, is n o t a logical division, b u t the m o v e m e n t o f the absolute itself. Hegel's Logic w i l l have to pass t h r o u g h these stages i n reverse; t h a t is, i t w i l l b e g i n w i t h simple being w i t h o u t q u a l i t y a n d w i l l ascend to each h i g h e r v i e w p o i n t . T h u s we see t h a t Hegel's dialectic has a t e r n a r y s t r u c t u r e , i n w h i c h the thesis is opposed b y the antithesis a n d b o t h are u n i t e d i n the synthesis. T h e synthesis, however, is n o t a mere conciliation; r a t h e r , the thesis leads necessarily t o the a n t i thesis, a n d vice versa, a n d this movement of being leads i n e x o r a b l y to the synthesis, i n w h i c h the thesis a n d the antithesis are preserved and superseded—aufgehoben, t h a t is, absorbed, according to the translation p r o posed b y Ortega. E a c h stage finds its truth i n the one t h a t follows. T h i s is the n a t u r e o f the dialectical process. W e shall a t t e m p t to e x p l a i n the principles o f the first elements o f this dialectical m o v e m e n t o f being. T H E PROGRESS OF D I A L E C T I C S . A t the end of'the phenomenology
of the
spirit we a r r i v e at the absolute b e g i n n i n g o f p h i l o s o p h y — b e i n g . T h i s b e i n g is p u r e being, absolute being. Being is indefinable because i n this case the t e r m to be defined w o u l d have to enter i n t o the d e f i n i t i o n ; b u t i t is possible to make some statements about i t . A c c o r d i n g to Hegel, b e i n g is the indeterminate
immediate
(das unbestimmte
Unmittelbare).
I t is
free f r o m a l l determinateness as regards essence; i t s i m p l y is; i t is n o t this or the other.
T h i s b e i n g has n o t h i n g to differentiate i t f r o m w h a t is n o t itself, since i t has no determinateness; i t is pure indeterminateness a n d emptiness. I f w e t r y to i n t u i t or t h i n k o f being, we i n t u i t n o t h i n g ; i f i t were otherwise, we w o u l d i n t u i t something (Etwas) a n d this w o u l d n o t be pure b e i n g . W h e n I t r y t o t h i n k o f being, w h a t I t h i n k o f is nothingness. T h u s , f r o m b e i n g we pass t o nothingness. B u t n a t u r a l l y , i t is b e i n g itself t h a t
322
Hegel
makes the transition, a n d n o t the ego. Being, the i n d e t e r m i n a t e i m m e d i a t e , is i n fact nothingness, n o t h i n g m o r e or less t h a n n o t h i n g . W e have seen i n being these t w o characteristics w h i c h H e g e l gives us at the outset: immediacy a n d indeterminateness. T h e characteristic of indeterminateness is being nothing; t h a t o f i m m e d i a c y is being first. F r o m being we were h u r l e d i n t o nothingness. B u t w h a t is n o t h i n g ness? I t is perfect emptiness, the absence o f determinateness a n d content, the incapacity to be separate f r o m itself. T o t h i n k o f or to i n t u i t nothingness is j u s t t h i s : to i n t u i t nothingness; this is p u r e i n t u i t i o n , pure thought. T h u s we see t h a t to i n t u i t nothingness is the same as to i n t u i t being. Pure b e i n g a n d p u r e nothingness are one and the same thing. Being, t h r o u g h its i n t e r n a l movement, has h u r l e d us i n t o nothingness, a n d nothingness i n t o being, a n d we cannot r e m a i n stationary i n either o f the t w o . W h a t does this m e a n ? W e were i n q u i r i n g after t r u t h . T r u t h is patency, the state o f being uncovered, exhibited. W e have seen t h a t the m a n n e r o f being w h i c h " b e i n g " has is t h a t o f ceasing to be " b e i n g " a n d c o m i n g to be " nothingness" ; a n d t h a t the m a n n e r of b e i n g w h i c h " n o t h i n g n e s s " has is, likewise, t h a t o f i n a b i l i t y to r e m a i n w i t h i n itself a n d c o m i n g to be " b e i n g . " T h e t r u t h is t h a t being has passed i n t o nothingness a n d nothingness has passed i n t o being. T h i s is becoming (Werden, fieri, yiyveaOaC).
I n this dialectic, I repeat, each stage contains the t r u t h o f the one before a n d finds its o w n t r u t h i n the one t h a t follows. T h u s , the t r u t h of b e i n g was i n nothingness, a n d t h a t of nothingness i n becoming. T h e t r u t h o f b e c o m i n g w i l l not be patent w i t h i n itself, either; a n d the m o v e m e n t o f being, f o l l o w i n g its inexorable ontological necessity, continues i n this w a y i n the f u r t h e r stages of the dialectic. T H E P R O B L E M OF PANTHEISM. Hegel recalls three earlier elements i n the history o f philosophy: the philosopher Parmenides, w h o makes being the absolute, the o n l y t r u t h , i n contrast to the O r i e n t a l systems ( B u d d h i s m ) , w h i c h take nothingness as their p r i n c i p l e ; Heraclitus, w h o contraposes to this abstraction the total concept o f b e c o m i n g ; a n d the p r i n c i p l e o f medieval metaphysics, ex nihilo nihil fit. Hegel distinguishes between t w o meanings o f this statement: one w h i c h is a p u r e tautology, a n d another w h i c h presupposes the i d e n t i t y o f being w i t h itself a n d o f nothingness w i t h itself. I f being is always being a n d nothingness is always nothingness, there is no b e c o m i n g ; this is the system o f i d e n t i t y (an allusion to Schelling). T h i s i d e n t i t y , Hegel says, is the essence o f pantheism. W e thus see t h a t Hegel is opposed to this pantheism because o f the w a y i n w h i c h he understands the dialectical m o v e m e n t o f being.
The
Philosophy
of
Nature
3*3
Being had passed i n t o nothingness, and vice versa. As a result of this there appears the p r o b l e m o f oppositeness. Hegel speaks o f a certain disappearance o f being i n t o nothingness a n d o f nothingness i n t o being. B u t since these are t w o opposites, the mode o f being w h i c h each one has is the exclusion o f the other, the removal o f the other. T h e G e r m a n w o r d aufheben, like the L a t i n w o r d tollere, has as one o f its meanings to raise up; to be raised u p as a n opposite o f something else is a higher m o d e o f being. W h e n t w o things are necessary, they exclude each o t h e r ; b u t they exclude each other w i t h i n a u n i t y , i n a genus. Oppositeness occurs w i t h i n a u n i t y , Aristotle said. T h i s m a n n e r o f e x c l u d i n g one another w h i c h being a n d nothingness have is a mode o f b e i n g preserved a n d raised u p i n t o the higher u n i t y o f becoming, where they exist i n a state o f m u t u a l exclusion. B u t a l t h o u g h Hegel rejects the pantheism o f i d e n t i t y a n d affirms the t r a n s i t i o n f r o m nothingness to being, i n another sense he is n o t exempt f r o m pantheism. Hegel does n o t believe that the r e a l i t y o f the w o r l d is d i v i n e , t h a t this pan is theds; b u t f r o m another v i e w p o i n t we see t h a t Hegel's G o d , the absolute, exists o n l y i n a state o f becoming. A c c o r d i n g to Hegel's o w n expression, H e is a G o d w h o becomes (Gott im Werden). T h e finite entities are n o t strictly different f r o m G o d , b u t are aspects o f this absolute, stages i n its dialectical movement. Lastly, the Hegelian Creation is not so m u c h the p l a c i n g i n t o existence o f a n e n t i t y different f r o m G o d t h r o u g h a free act o f the divine w i l l , as i t is a necessary p r o d u c t i o n w i t h i n the dialectic o f the absolute. H E G E L I A N O N T O L O G Y . W e thus see t h a t Hegel's Logic, w h i c h starts out w i t h being, w i t h the absolute beginning o f philosophy, is true ontology. T h e logic must be understood, Hegel says, as the system of pure reason, as the r e i g n o f p u r e t h o u g h t . T h i s reign is truth. Therefore, Hegel concludes, i t can be said t h a t the content o f the Logic is the exposition
of God as He is in His eternal
essence,
before
the Creation
of
nature
T h i s first stage w i l l thus be followed b y the other t w o parts o f the philosophy: the Philosophy of Nature a n d the Philosophy and any finite spirit.
of the
Spirit.
4. T H E P H I L O S O P H Y
OF
NATURE
N A T U R E . Greek philosophy understood nature to be the s u m total o f a l l existing things, w i t h a p r i n c i p l e or source (arkhe) a n d a n end or goal (te'los). Aristotle defines nature as the p r i n c i p l e o f m o t i o n . Physis is thus a c o m i n g to be. Something is called n a t u r a l i f i t moves itself. Those things are n a t u r a l , A r i s t o t l e says, w h i c h c o n t a i n w i t h i n t h e m selves the p r i n c i p l e o f t h e i r o w n m o t i o n . I n contrast to Plato, w h o
Hegel
affirmed n a t u r e t o be a n Idea, A r i s t o t l e says t h a t t h e n a t u r e o f each t h i n g is its ousia, its arkhe, the i n t e r n a l p r i n c i p l e o f its transformations.
I n H e g e l , n a t u r e has a clearly d e t e r m i n e d character as a n aspect o f the absolute. T h i s aspect o f the a b s o l u t e — n a t u r e — i s characterized as a being for
another, a being there. N a t u r e is w h a t is other, w h a t is not oneself.
T H E STAGES. T h i s n a t u r e is a n aspect o f the I d e a , w h i c h has different stages: 1. Mechanics. T h i s , in turn, has three aspects: (A) Space and time: the abstract aspect of being outside. (B) Matter and motion: finite mechanics. ( C ) Free matter: absolute mechanics. 2. Physics. T h i s , too, has three aspects: (^1) Physics of general individuality. (B) Physics ofparticular individuality. ( C ) Physics oftotal individuality. 3. Organic physics, also w i t h three aspects: (A) Geologicalnature. (B) Vegetable nature. ( C ) T h e animal organism.
T h i s is the end o f the e v o l u t i o n o f the stages o f n a t u r e . 5. T H E PHILOSOPHY OF T H E S P I R I T
S P I R I T I N H E G E L . W e have already discussed the significance o f the
w o r d physis i n Greece. Greek philosophy asked itself: " W h a t is t h a t w h i c h is ? " T h i s is the same as asking, " W h a t is n a t u r e ? " T h e Greeks d i d n o t ask a b o u t the spirit. T h e n o t i o n o f spirit first appears persistently outside the r e a l m o f philosophy, i n the w r i t i n g s o f St. Paul (irveviia), a n d t h e n somewhat later i n St. Augustine's t h o u g h t : spiritus sive
animus.
I n H e g e l , spirit
is being for
itself, self-identity. S p i r i t is a m o m e n t i n
the e v o l u t i o n o f the absolute, a n d i t is defined as the entrance into oneself, self-identity,
being for itself. H e g e l makes a new o u t l i n e o f s p i r i t .
STAGES OF T H E SPIRIT. L e t us p o i n t o u t the d i a l e c t i c a l a r t i c u l a t i o n
o f the stages o f spirit, so t h a t later we can briefly e x a m i n e the most i m p o r t a n t moments i n this process. 1 . Subjective spirit. (A) Anthropology: the soul. (B) Phenomenology of the spirit: consciousness. ( C ) Psychology: the spirit. 2. Objective spirit. (A) R i g h t . (B) Morality. ( C ) Social ethics.
The 3. Absolute
Philosophy
of the
Spirit
32-J
spirit.
(A)
Art.
(B)
Revealed religion.
(C)
Philosophy.
Subjective
Spirit
" S u b j e c t i v e s p i r i t " strikes us as b e i n g a f a i r l y easy-to-understand t e r m . I t is spirit a n d i t is subjective; therefore, i t is a subject, a subject t h a t knows itself, t h a t is itself, t h a t has inferiority a n d intimacy. Subj ective s p i r i t can be perceived i n so far as i t is u n i t e d w i t h a body i n a v i t a l u n i t y , i n so far as i t is a soul. A t such a m o m e n t spirit is soul a n d constitutes the subject o f the science o f anthropology. B u t subjective s p i r i t is n o t only soul ; r a t h e r , i t knows itself a n d , b y passing t h r o u g h a l l levels o f consciousness, reaches absolute knowledge ; i t becomes spirit i n so far as i t knows itself. T h i s is the w a y i n w h i c h the phenomenology of the spirit develops ; i t is the study of the consciousness, and i t prevails u n t i l being, or absolute knowledge, is a t t a i n e d . Lastly, spirit is n o t o n l y consciousness ; i t knows a n d desires. Hegel calls this m o m e n t spirit, a n d i t is the subject of psychology. T h e foregoing constitutes a n overall description o f subjective spirit.
Objective
Spirit
A new a n d more serious difficulty arises f r o m the very concept o f objective spirit: i t is spirit (being for itself, self-identity), b u t at the same t i m e i t is objective, a spirit w h i c h exists out there, a spirit w i t h o u t a subject. I t is not n a t u r e , b u t i t has nature's characteristic o f " being at h a n d . " N o t to have a subject seems to be c o n t r a d i c t o r y t o the very concept o f spirit. Objective spirit is comprised o f three forms, each one superior to the previous : right, morality a n d social ethics (objective ethics or Sittlichkeit, as opposed t o
Moralitdt).
R i g h t is based o n the idea o f the person. A person is a r a t i o n a l entity, a n e n t i t y w i t h free w i l l . R i g h t is the most elementary f o r m o f relationships a m o n g persons. A n y t h i n g t h a t is not a person is the p r o p e r t y of a person. T h i s is the character o f the f o r m o f r i g h t ; the concept o f the State does n o t enter i n t o i t a t a l l . T h e r e can be infractions o f r i g h t w h i c h do n o t i n v o l v e persons as persons b u t as things ; for example, slaves were once considered things, n o t persons. K a n t h a d already said, " A l l m e n are ends i n themselves. " M a n can never be a means to a n y t h i n g , a thing : he is a n end i n himself. Therefore, Hegel proposes t h a t transgressions o f l a w f u l order be punished, a n d his RIGHT.
32.6
Hegel
consists o f n o t h i n g b u t a r e t u r n to the previous state o f r i g h t . I n H e g e l , to p u n i s h a person is t o treat h i m once m o r e as a person. I n short, the punished person is one w h o has a r i g h t to p u n i s h m e n t . T h e c r i m i n a l has the r i g h t to be castigated, t o be treated a c c o r d i n g to r i g h t a n d thus as a person. M O R A L I T Y . T h e r e is a second stage, m o r a l i t y . I n H e g e l , m o r a l i t y is based o n intentions or purposes. A n i n d i v i d u a l ' s purpose determines the m o r a l i t y o f his action. T h u s , m o r a l i t y is subjectivized, m a d e c o m pletely non-objective, a n d so the development of the idea passes f r o m the stage o f m o r a l i t y to the stage o f social or objective ethics. I n this latter stage the development o f the m o r a l idea is seen i n the various institutions o f social life: the f a m i l y , society a n d , above a l l , the State.
punishment
S O C I A L ETHICS. Social ethics is the realization of objective spirit, the o f subjective a n d objective spirit. T h e family is the i m m e d i a t e or natural phase o f the ethical substance; society is everything p e r t a i n i n g to relationships between i n d i v i d u a l s as independent persons; a n d the State is spirit developed i n a n organic reality. T h e l a t t e r phase is the one w h i c h interests us the most. truth
T H E S T A T E . T h e State is the f i n a l f o r m o f objective s p i r i t . Hegel constructed w h a t was perhaps the first ontology o f the State. T h e State is a r a t i o n a l creation a n d the highest f o r m i n w h i c h the idea o f m o r a l i t y is developed. Hegel does n o t v i e w the State i n the r a t h e r disinterested w a y i n w h i c h Rousseau views i t . I t is a n objective r e a l i t y ; i t is a construction, a n d has the highest r a n k i n the ontological hierarchy. H o w e v e r , the idea o f the State is n o t f u l l y realized i n a n y a c t u a l state. T h e idea o f the State can o n l y be realized i n the total development o f universal history. Universal history is the u n f o l d i n g o f t h e i n t e r n a l dialectic o f the idea of the State. U N I V E R S A L HISTORY. C e r t a i n characteristics of Hegel's t h o u g h t are m o r e clearly seen i n his Lectures on the Philosophy of Universal History, one o f the most b r i l l i a n t books ever p r o d u c e d i n Europe, t h a n i n any other p o r t i o n o f his w o r k . H i s systemization is strict and complete. I n Hegel, system has a very concrete m e a n i n g : i t is the way i n w h i c h truth exists: there are no independent t r u t h s , a n d n o t h i n g is true b y itself, alone; rather, every t r u t h is sustained b y a n d based o n a l l other t r u t h s . T h i s is w h a t constitutes the systematic structure o f philosophy, i n contrast to w h a t m i g h t be called the linear s t r u c t u r e — o f mathematics, for example. T h i s systemization leads H e g e l to overlook c e r t a i n facts a n d occasionally to misrepresent r e a l i t y . Hegel tries to explain the dialectical evolution o f m a n k i n d . H i s t o r y is the realization o f the d i v i n e p l a n , a revelation o f G o d . Weltgeschichte, Weltgericht: universal history is universal j u d g m e n t . For H e g e l , every-
The
Philosophy
of the
Spirit
t h i n g t h a t is real is r a t i o n a l a n d everything t h a t is r a t i o n a l is real. Therefore, his dialectic is logic. H u m a n history is reason, p u r e reason. T h u s Hegel's philosophy o f history becomes a n a t t e m p t to explain a l l history as a n absolute knowledge t h a t does n o t o m i t a n y t h i n g , t h a t even includes error as error. H e g e l distinguishes four moments i n the historical evolution o f peoples, and he compares these moments to the stages of h u m a n life: the O r i e n t ( c h i l d h o o d ) , i n w h i c h government is i n the f o r m o f a p a t e r n a l relationship; Greece (adolescence), o r the r e a l m o f " b e a u t i f u l f r e e d o m " ; R o m e ( m a n h o o d ) , the phase o f universality, o f the R o m a n E m p i r e ; a n d the R o m a n - G e r m a n i c peoples (old age), i n w h i c h there is a contraposition o f a profane a n d a spiritual empire. I n history Hegel sees the progress o f freedom: i n the O r i e n t there is b u t one free m a n , the despot; i n Greece a n d R o m e there are several free m e n (the citizens); a n d i n the m o d e r n C h r i s t i a n w o r l d all m e n are free. H e g e l made grandiose syntheses of universal h i s t o r y : I n d i a , or the r e a l m o f the d r e a m i n g absolute s p i r i t ; Greece, or the realm o f grace; R o m e , or the r e a l m o f power, a n d so f o r t h . Hegel's w o r k represents the p r i n c i p a l attempt thus far to make a philosophy o f history. F o l l o w i n g beginnings b y St. Augustine (De civitate Dei), Bossuet (Discours sur l'histoire universelle) a n d V i c o (La scienza nuova), Hegel, i n his Philosophy ofHistory, grapples w i t h the theme o f history b r i l l i a n t l y and o n a g r a n d scale. However, o u r o w n era must seriously question t w o p r o b l e m a t i c a l points i n Hegel's t h o u g h t . O n e o f these points involves the d e n o m i n a t i o n o f objective spirit, a p p l i e d to the State, to history, a n d so o n . S p i r i t is the entrance i n t o oneself, b u t then we also find spirit w i t h o u t a subj ect. Something similar occurs i n connection w i t h social life; i t is n o t the life o f any p a r t i c u l a r person, b u t life is characterized b y being my life or the life of someone. W e glimpse a c o n t r a d i c t i o n i n this. T h e second t r o u b l i n g p o i n t is Hegel's i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the historical evolution o f m a n k i n d as pure reason, as a logical dialectic. T o w h a t extent is this so ? (See Ortega y Gasset: La "Filosofía de la historia" de Hegel y la historiologia.)
Absolute
Spirit
Absolute spirit is a synthesis o f subjective a n d objective spirit, a n d also o f nature a n d spirit. F o r Hegel, the i d e n t i t y between nature a n d s p i r i t is n o t a v o i d , a n indifference, as i t is for Schelling; rather, Hegel says t h a t nature a n d spirit require a common base. T h e i r c o m m o n base is the base of everything else, o f the absolute, w h i c h is in itself a n d for itself. Hegel calls this absolute spirit.
3
z8
Hegel
W e have seen t h a t this i d e n t i t y involves searching f o r a c o m m o n base w h i c h can make things be either n a t u r e or spirit. S u c h a base w o u l d be the fundamental reality. H o w e v e r , i t is not clear w h y this is t o be called spirit, for spirits are t r a d i t i o n a l l y entities w h i c h enter i n t o themselves. T h i s absolute is systematic t h o u g h t i n w h i c h each t h i n g is t r u e o n l y as a f u n c t i o n o f the system. N o w we can fully u n d e r s t a n d t h a t system is t h e a r t i c u l a t i o n o f each thing's being w i t h i n t h e absolute spirit. W e are n o t concerned w i t h a n absolute thing, b u t w i t h the absolute, t h a t w h i c h is the base o f the other things. T h e absolute is n o t a n aggregate, any m o r e t h a n the w o r l d is the aggregate o f the t h i n g s ; r a t h e r , the absolute is where the things occur (and this " w h e r e " is n o t p r i m a r i l y spatial). T H E A B S O L U T E A N D T H O U G H T . T h e absolute is present
t o itself; a n d
this being present to itself is thought. " B e i n g present t o i t s e l f " means being patent, alétheia. I t is n o t a question of starting w i t h t h o u g h t a n d t h e n c o m i n g to possess the absolute. R a t h e r , the absolute is patent t o itself, a n d its i m m e d i a c y to itself is t h o u g h t . W h i l e I a m n o t t h i n k i n g this, i t is n o t a being. T h o u g h t constitutes the actual b e i n g o f the things. Being is n o t latent being, b u t p a t e n t being, alétheia, t r u t h . A l l attempts to define the absolute fall short of the m a r k ; one must find oneself d i r e c t l y i n the absolute; i t is p u r e being. As w e have seen, w h e n I t h i n k o f p u r e being i t becomes absolute negation. Becoming represents t h e absolute's a t t e m p t t o a v o i d nothingness a n d t o m a i n t a i n itself i n being. T h e absolute c a n exist o n l y i n becoming. B y becoming, the absolute spirit comes t o be something. I n Greece this was called " being i n itself." N o t h i n g is self-sufficient; r a t h e r , to be something is to become somet h i n g , a n d this presupposes a b e g i n n i n g . T h e t r u t h o f a t h i n g consists i n its being i n itself w h a t i t already was i n its absolute b e g i n n i n g . T h i s is w h a t has been called essence. Essence is w h a t makes i t possible for a t h i n g to be. A n d absolute self-understanding is absolute b e i n g , concept. T h e absolute, w h i c h is the source o f a l l action, becomes b y itself; therefore, the I d e a is freedom. L a s t l y , philosophy is the absolute's knowledge of itself. Philosophy is n o t t h o u g h t a b o u t the absolute; r a t h e r , i t is the absolute
in so far
as it knows
itself
(cf. Z u b i r i : Hegel
y el
problema
metafisico). T H E STAGES OF A B S O L U T E S P I R I T . A S w e have seen, t h e t h r e e stages o f
absolute spirit are a r t , revealed r e l i g i o n a n d philosophy. A r t involves the sensible manifestation o f the absolute; here t h e absolute idea is intuited. I n religion, o n the other h a n d , the absolute idea is represented. Hegel's philosophy o f religion is enormously i m p o r t a n t , b u t we cannot discuss i t i n d e t a i l here. Hegel is opposed to Schleiermacher's r e l i g i o n
The Philosophy of the
Spirit
o f feeling, a n d his t h o u g h t gives rise to a n i m p o r t a n t t r e n d w h i c h dominates theology a n d the history o f r e l i g i o n i n the nineteenth c e n t u r y . Hegel makes a new i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the ontological a r g u m e n t , a n d thus restores to i t the v a l i d i t y w h i c h K a n t ' s c r i t i c i s m has t a k e n f r o m i t . For o u r purposes i t is sufficient to p o i n t out t h a t H e g e l distinguishes between the v i e w p o i n t o f understanding—the viewpoint f r o m w h i c h K a n t ' s c r i t i c i s m w o u l d be v a l i d — a n d the v i e w p o i n t o f reason. T h e relationship between t h o u g h t a n d the absolute allows H e g e l to give new m e a n i n g to the ontological proof, w h i c h is thus able to reassume its role i n the history of philosophy. T h e final stage o f absolute spirit is philosophy. H e r e the absolute idea is no longer either i n t u i t e d or represented, b u t conceived, raised to a concept. Philosophy is the absolute's knowledge o f itself; i t is n o t t h o u g h t about the absolute; r a t h e r , i t is the explicit f o r m of the absolute itself. I t is for this reason t h a t the history o f philosophy is a n essential p a r t of philosophy itself ( Z u b i r i ) . H e g e l was the first person to make a n a c t u a l History of Philosophy. H e interprets the subject i n a dialectical m a n n e r , as a series o f m o m e n t s w h i c h preserve a n d supersede one another. Hegel believes t h a t philosophy reaches its maturity a n d attains its final f o r m i n his w o r k , that his philosophy is the c o m p l e t i o n o f philosophy. H e is acutely aware t h a t he represents the c u l m i n a t i o n and close of a n epoch, the M o d e r n E r a . Therefore, at the end o f his History of Philosophy he is able to m a k e a sweeping evaluation a n d w r i t e a Conclusion o f i n c o m p a r a b l e grandeur. " P h i l o s o p h y is the t r u e theodicy," he says. A n d he adds these words, w h i c h t h r o b w i t h a l l the majestic g r a v i t y o f the history o f philosophy a n d express i t better t h a n i t has ever been expressed, either before or after his t i m e : " T h e universal s p i r i t has come this far. T h e most recent philosophy is the outcome o f a l l previous philosophies; n o t h i n g has been lost, a l l the principles have been retained. T h i s concrete idea is the consequence o f the spirit's efforts d u r i n g almost 2500 years [Thales was b o r n i n 640 B . C . ] , o f the spirit's most earnest labor to make itself objective to itself, to k n o w itself: ' T a n t a e molis erat, se ipsam cognoscere m e n t e m . ' "
The Thought of the Romantic Age
T h e r e is a n intense intellectual a c t i v i t y i n G e r m a n y f r o m the t i m e o f K a n t u n t i l the first h a l f o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y ; we have already studied the most p r o f o u n d l y philosophical s t r a t u m o f this t h o u g h t : K a n t , Fichte, Schelling a n d H e g e l . H o w e v e r , there are at the same t i m e other philosophers o f somewhat lesser stature w h o nevertheless are o f the greatest interest to philosophy a n d to other disciplines; i t is i m p o r t a n t to note briefly the character o f this group o f thinkers. First o f a l l , we must take notice of t w o movements w h i c h arise i n the eighteenth c e n t u r y a n d w h i c h emphasize sentiment a n d the life based o n the emotions. O n e of these movements is p r i m a r i l y l i t e r a r y , the so-called Sturm undDrang ( S t o r m a n d Stress), a n d the other is p r i m a r i l y religious, Pietism. A n o t h e r m o v e m e n t , Romanticism, appears at the end o f the eighteenth a n d the b e g i n n i n g o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y ; i t derives p r i n c i p a l l y f r o m the Sturm und Drang movement. A t the same t i m e there is a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y f l o w e r i n g o f studies i n history, a n d this leads to the f o r m a t i o n o f the circle k n o w n as the " G e r m a n school o f h i s t o r y . " N a t u r a l science becomes definitely established w i t h the discovery o f electricity ( L u i g i G a l v a n i a n d Alessandro V o l t a i n I t a l y ; M i c h a e l Faraday i n E n g l a n d ) a n d the development o f b i o l o g y (Georges B u f f o n , fitienne B o n n o t de Condillac a n d J e a n Baptiste L a m a r c k i n France). Lastly, i n the field o f philosophy w e f i n d alongside the great figures we have already studied the names o f F r i e d r i c h Schleiermacher a n d A r t h u r Schopenhauer, especially, b u t also F r a n z v o n Baader, F r i e d r i c h J a c o b i a n d K a r l Krause. W e shall n o w t r y t o sketch these various currents o f t h o u g h t . 33°
The School of
1.
T H E LITERARY
History
MOVEMENTS
As a reaction against the cold rationalist spirit o f the Aufklärung, G e r m a n y produces a new literature whose greatest figures are n o t l a c k i n g i n philosophic ideas a n d a deep interest i n idealism. C h i e f o f these is J o h a n n W o l f g a n g v o n Goethe (1749-1832), w h o l i v e d l o n g enough to p a r t i c i p a t e i n every movement f r o m Classicism to R o m a n t i c i s m ; his i n c o m p a r a b l e l i t e r a r y b r i l l i a n c e was combined w i t h a remarkable f e r t i l i t y i n scientific a n d esthetic t h o u g h t . Others were F r i e d r i c h Schiller, F r i e d r i c h Hölderlin, Novalis ( F r i e d r i c h v o n H a r d e n b e r g ) , J o h a n n G o t t f r i e d v o n H e r d e r a n d the R o m a n t i c writers p r o p e r l y so-called: L u d w i g Tieck, the t w o brothers Schlegel ( F r i e d r i c h a n d A u g u s t W i l h e l m ) , the brothers H u m b o l d t (Alexander a n d W i l h e l m ) , a n d H e i n e as w e l l . R o m a n t i c i s m , as we have seen, signifies a n esthetic o f feeling. B u t i n a d d i t i o n i t involves a p a r t i c u l a r e m o t i o n for the past. Just as the E n l i g h t e n m e n t , w h e n t h i n k i n g o f the past, r e t u r n e d to the classical w o r l d , to Greece a n d R o m e , the Romantics have a n obvious preference for the M i d d l e Ages. T h i s leads m a n y o f t h e m to a p r i m a r i l y artistic a n d historical appreciation o f C a t h o l i c i s m t h a t brings t h e m close to the R o m a n C h u r c h . I n m a n y cases there takes place, i n a d d i t i o n , a n actual religious rapprochement; b u t there is always at least a n a d m i r a t i o n for the Catholic f o r m o f w o r s h i p , for the c o n t i n u i t y o f the Pontificate a n d for the splendid historical r e a l i t y w h i c h the C h u r c h is—even t h o u g h i t is so o n l y secondarily. T h i s interest i n the medieval past leads the R o m a n t i c s to cultivate the study o f history also.
2.
T H E SCHOOL OF
HISTORY
W e have already seen t h a t i n the eighteenth century i n France ( V o l t a i r e a n d M o n t e s q u i e u , f o l l o w i n g Bossuet's precedent) historical studies took a decisive step f o r w a r d . T h e results o f the French movem e n t are adopted a l o n g w i t h the contributions o f certain Englishmen ( H u m e , G i b b o n ) b y the G e r m a n school of history. A distinction is made between nature a n d spirit, as we saw, a n d spirit is interpreted historically. General history, the history o f l a w , the history o f religions, linguistics, Classical p h i l o l o g y , R o m a n c e p h i l o l o g y , a n d the like, are c u l t i v a t e d intensively b y a g r o u p o f p r o d u c t i v e scholars. F r i e d r i c h K a r l v o n Savigny, L e o p o l d v o n Ranke, Franz B o p p , B a r t h o l d Georg N i e b u h r a n d , later, T h e o d o r M o m m s e n engage i n a labor o f great i m p o r t a n c e a n d v o l u m e . T h e school o f history invents the technique o f historical research, c r i t i c a l d o c u m e n t a t i o n a n d the study o f p r i m a r y
The
Thought
of the Romantic
Age
sources, b u t i t soon shows a lack o f adequate intellectual constructiveness a n d tends to go no f u r t h e r t h a n the a c c u m u l a t i o n o f data. T h e example o f Classical p h i l o l o g y , w h i c h amassed an enormous a m o u n t o f scholarly m a t e r i a l b u t was u n a b l e to furnish a n adequate p i c t u r e o f Greece, is especially clear. Hegel reacted energetically to this tendency, a l t h o u g h perhaps he sinned i n the d i r e c t i o n o f a n excessively logical construction of history. 3.
SCHLEIERMACHER
A N D T H E PHILOSOPHY
OF R E L I G I O N
S C H L E I E R M A C H E R ' S L I F E A N D W O R K S . F r i e d r i c h D a n i e l Schleier-
macher was b o r n i n 1768 a n d d i e d i n 1834. H e was educated i n the schools o f the M o r a v i a n b r o t h e r h o o d , a n d his p r i n c i p a l a c t i v i t y t h r o u g h o u t his life was p r e a c h i n g a n d the study o f r e l i g i o n a n d the philosophy o f r e l i g i o n . For several years he was the pastor o f the Charité H o s p i t a l i n B e r l i n ; a f t e r w a r d he t a u g h t at H a l l e , a n d later, u n t i l his death, at the U n i v e r s i t y o f B e r l i n . H i s most i m p o r t a n t works are Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre (Basis o f a C r i t i q u e o f Ethics to the Present T i m e ) , Ethik, Der christliche Glaube nach den Grundsätzen der Evangelischen Kirche ( C h r i s t i a n D o g m a A c c o r d i n g to the F u n d a m e n t a l Principles o f the Evangelical C h u r c h ) , Hermeneutik and the Reden über die Religion (Addresses o n R e l i g i o n ) . I n a d d i t i o n , he made a splendid translation of Plato. R E L I G I O N . F o r several years Schleiermacher was the o u t s t a n d i n g figure i n G e r m a n Protestant theology. H e g e l opposed Schleiermacher's i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f r e l i g i o n , a n d f r o m t h a t t i m e o n the p h i losophy o f r e l i g i o n was strongly influenced b y the conceptions of b o t h men. Schleiermacher considers possible neither a r a t i o n a l theology nor a revealed theology nor even a m o r a l theology like K a n t ' s , w h i c h was based o n the postulates o f p r a c t i c a l reason. T h e object o f Schleiermacher's speculation is n o t so m u c h God as religion; rather than theology, i t is philosophy o f r e l i g i o n t h a t he practices. H e interprets this r e l i g i o n as afeeling. His is the philosophy of'religiousfeeling. O f w h a t does this feeling consist ? I t is the feeling of absolute dependence. M a n feels needy, insufficient, dependent. T h i s state o f subjection gives rise to man's awareness o f being a creature. T h u s i n Schleiermacher's w o r k the dogmatic content of r e l i g i o n is, i n effect, deprived o f its force a n d relegated to a lower plane ; r e l i g i o n becomes p u r e l y a m a t t e r of feeling. Schleiermacher forgets the f u n d a m e n t a l m e a n i n g oîreligio as religatio, a n d thus changes its basic significance. L A T E R THEOLOGIANS. T h r o u g h o u t the nineteenth c e n t u r y
Ger-
Derivations
of
Idealism
333
m a n y is the scene o f intensive theological a c t i v i t y , p a r t i a l l y influenced b y Schleiermacher, b u t chiefly f o l l o w i n g i n the steps of H e g e l ; o u t standing i n this respect is the so-called T ü b i n g e n school. O n e o f the most i m p o r t a n t theologians o f this p e r i o d is C h r i s t i a n B a u r ; despite his greater superficiality, D a v i d Strauss also a c q u i r e d m u c h fame. O n the other h a n d , C a t h o l i c theology was represented i n G e r m a n y b y the great figure o f M a t h i a s Josef Scheeben ( d i e d 1888), whose major w o r k Die Mysterien des Christentums (The Mysteries o f Christianity) was a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y c o n t r i b u t i o n to speculative theology. 4.
DERIVATIONS
OF
IDEALISM
I n the last t h i r d o f the eighteenth c e n t u r y a n d the first h a l f o f the nineteenth several interesting thinkers flourished; their fame has been somewhat obscured b y the great philosophers o f G e r m a n idealism, b y w h o m they were influenced to a greater o r lesser extent, a n d w h o m they i n t u r n influenced. Some of these m e n opposed idealism, b u t they a l l moved w i t h i n the m i l i e u of its problems a n d were conditioned b y the philosophic position o f the age. L e t us consider briefly the most i m p o r t a n t of these m e n . H E R D E R . J o h a n n G o t t f r i e d v o n H e r d e r (1744-1803), w h o is to be considered p a r t i a l l y w i t h i n the framework o f the Aufklärung b u t was already o n the w a y t o w a r d R o m a n t i c t h o u g h t , is one of the thinkers w h o i n i t i a t e the u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f historical r e a l i t y i n the eighteenth century. H e r d e r takes i n t o account the differences between nations a n d the influence o f geographical factors, b u t he considers m a n k i n d as a t o t a l i t y subject to e v o l u t i o n ; his desideratum was a " h i s t o r y o f the h u m a n soul, b y epochs a n d b y peoples." H i s p r i n c i p a l writings are Auch eine Philosophie der Geschichte zur Bildung der Menschheit (Another Philosophy o f H i s t o r y for the E d u c a t i o n o f H u m a n i t y ) , w h i c h appeared i n 1774, a n d the Ideen zur Philosophie der Geschichte der Menschheit (Ideas o n the Philosophy o f the H i s t o r y of M a n k i n d ) , 1784-91. J A C O B I . F r i e d r i c h H e i n r i c h Jacobi (1743-1819), a friend o f Goethe i n his y o u t h a n d a representative of the p r i n c i p l e o f religious feeling, opposed r a t i o n a l i s m i n r e l i g i o n (Moses Mendelssohn) and appealed to f a i t h , w h i c h he likened to society: m a n was b o r n w i t h i n a n d must r e m a i n w i t h i n the one a n d the other. J a c o b i produced a c r i t i q u e o f K a n t i a n i s m a n d o f c e r t a i n points i n Schelling's philosophy. H i s most i m p o r t a n t w r i t i n g s are David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus ( D a v i d H u m e o n F a i t h , or I d e a l i s m a n d Realism) a n d Von den göttlichen Dingen und ihrer Offenbarung ( O n D i v i n e Things a n d T h e i r Revelation).
The
334
Thought
of the Romantic
Age
HERBART. Johann Friedrich Herbart (17 76-1841), a contemporary o f the great figures o f G e r m a n idealism a n d i m b u e d despite h i m s e l f w i t h t h e i r s p i r i t , opposed the p r e v a i l i n g tendency o f his age a n d , d r a w i n g o n eighteenth-century t h o u g h t a n d u l t i m a t e l y o n L e i b n i z , created a personal philosophy—less b r i l l i a n t t h a n t h a t o f his contemporaries F i c h t e , Schelling a n d H e g e l — w h i c h c l a i m e d to be realism.
H e r b a r t w r o t e the Lehrbuch
zur Einleitung
in die
Philosophie
( I n t r o d u c t o r y M a n u a l of Philosophy), Hauptpunkte der Logik (Principal Points of L o g i c ) , Hauptpunkte der Metaphysik ( P r i n c i p a l Points o f M e t a physics), Allgemeine Metaphysik (General Metaphysics), Theoriae de attractione
elementorum
principia
metaphysica
(Metaphysical Principles of
the T h e o r y o f A t t r a c t i o n o f the Elements), Lehrbuch zur Psychologie ( M a n u a l o f Psychology), Psychologie als Wissenschaft (Psychology as a Science), Allgemeine praktische Philosophie (General P r a c t i c a l P h i losophy) a n d Allgemeine Pädagogik (General Pedagogy). For H e r b a r t , philosophy is the e l a b o r a t i o n o f concepts; i t acts u p o n a p r i m a r y knowledge, w h i c h is experience; i t must therefore start o u t w i t h w h a t is " g i v e n , " w h a t is impressed u p o n us, w h e t h e r m a t t e r o r f o r m . T h e m a t e r i a l a n d f o r m a l aspects o f experience pose p r o b l e m s : the given is o n l y a starting p o i n t , necessary to make the problems r e a l , a n d i t obliges us to philosophize i n order t o make experience c o m prehensible ; experience alone is n o t comprehensible. Metaphysica est ars experientiam recte intelligendi (Metaphysics is the art o f u n d e r s t a n d i n g experience c o r r e c t l y ) . O n e must make t h e transition f r o m a p r o b l e m concept to a s o l u t i o n concept, a n d for this purpose there come i n t o p l a y certain c o n t i n g e n t modes o f considering the things w h i c h H e r b a r t calls zufällige Ansichten (contingent views) or modi res considerandi (modes o f considering the t h i n g s ) ; thus one arrives at the m e t h o d of " i n t e g r a t i o n o f the concepts." H e r b a r t distinguishes t h a t w h i c h is f r o m b e i n g itself, the quale w h i c h is being. T h e l a t t e r is understood as absolute position, i n d e p e n d e n t o f us; H e r b a r t calls this the " R e a l , " t h a t is, the e n t i t y — h e n c e his a t t e m p t e d r e t u r n to realism. T h e d o c t r i n e o f the Reals is based o n L e i b n i z ' t h e o r y o f the monads. O f the R e a l as a n absolute, one c a n k n o w o n l y t h a t i t exists, t h a t i t is simple, t h a t i t is n o t q u a n t i t y a n d t h a t m u l t i p l i c i t y of being ( a l t h o u g h n o t w i t h i n being) is possible; t h a t is, t h a t there c a n be one o r m o r e Reals. B u t viewed i n the l i g h t o f our forms of t h o u g h t , i t becomes a n image w i t h contingent traits w h i c h d o not c o n t r a d i c t those essential characteristics: w h a t the R e a l is for us. I n short, H e r b a r t relapses i n t o idealism. T h e ego is one o f the Reals; f o l l o w i n g u p this idea, H e r b a r t develops his psychology, w h i c h like his pedagogy is intellectualistic: the o n l y o r i g i n a l f u n c t i o n o f the soul is
Derivations
oj
Idealism
335
representation. L a s t l y , ethics is i n t e r p r e t e d as a Geschmackslehre, a theory o f taste or science o f estimative sensibility; the good is the q u a l i t y o f that w h i c h compels our a p p r o v a l , j u s t as evil compels o u r disapproval. H e r b a r t here comes very close to the idea of value w h i c h was to attain m a t u r i t y a century later. T h e good cannot be defined or discovered: one recognizes i t , accepts i t , esteems or approves i t ; ethics appears w i t h i n a n esthetic m i l i e u ; i t is related t o a m o r a l beauty w h i c h is distinct f r o m the beauty o f music or the visual arts. The. practical ideas are the f u n d a m e n t a l relations that are w o r t h y o f esteem, the exemplary valuations; these are the idea o f i n t e r n a l freedom, the idea o f perfect i o n , the idea of benevolence, the idea o f r i g h t a n d the idea of r e t r i b u t i o n or equity (cf. O r t e g a : Obras Completas, V I , 265-291). K R A U S E . K a r l C h r i s t i a n F r i e d r i c h K r a u s e (1781-1832) belongs to the g r o u p of younger idealist thinkers; strongly rooted i n religion a n d ethics, he achieves a certain o r i g i n a l i t y i n his efforts to reconcile theism w i t h the prevalent pantheistic tendencies o f his age. H i s panentheism declares t h a t a l l things are in God. Krause affirms the existence of destiny a n d the value of the person, understood i n a m o r a l sense, a n d f r o m this v i e w p o i n t he interprets l a w a n d society; m a n k i n d is a federation o f autonomous associations w i t h universal or p r i v a t e goals. Krause's p r i n c i p a l works are Entwurf des Systems der Philosophic (Sketch of the System o f Philosophy), Das Urbild der Menschheit (The I d e a l of M a n k i n d ) , System der Sittenlehre (System o f Ethics), Vorlesungen über das System der Philosophie (Lectures o n the System of Philosophy) a n d Vorlesungen über die Grundwahrheiten der Wissenschaften (Lectures o n the F u n d a m e n t a l T r u t h s o f the Sciences). K r a u s e left behind m a n y unpublished works, some of w h i c h have since been published. Despite the confused a n d somewhat vague style o f his w r i t i n g s , he exerted a considerable influence. H i s system was developed b y some o f his G e r m a n pupils, like R ó d e r a n d L e o n h a r d i , b u t even more so i n B e l g i u m by H e i n r i c h Ahrens a n d T i b e r g h i e n a n d i n Spain, where Krause's philosophy enjoyed an unexpected v i t a l i t y w h i c h i t is o f interest to examine. S A N Z D E L R I O . J u l i á n Sanz del R i o (1814-1869) was the founder and p r i n c i p a l figure i n the Spanish K r a u s i a n school. J a i m e L u c i a n o Balmes a n d h e — c o n t e m p o r a r i e s even t h o u g h Sanz del R i o o u t l i v e d Balmes b y twenty-one years—are the t w o most i m p o r t a n t names i n nineteenth-century Spanish philosophy. I n 1843 Sanz del R i o was a p p o i n t e d professor o f the history o f philosophy at the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d a n d was sent to study i n G e r m a n y . A t Heidelberg he was a p u p i l o f L e o n h a r d i a n d R ó d e r a n d l i v e d at the home o f his history professor G e o r g Weber, where he was a c o m p a n i o n o f H e n r i
336
The
Thought
of the Romantic
Age
Frédéric A m i e l . O n his r e t u r n to Spain he inspired the c r e a t i o n o f a philosophical circle of great v i t a l i t y w h i c h influenced i n t e l l e c t u a l a n d political life for a l o n g t i m e , almost t h r o u g h o u t the entire century. Despite this, his philosophical value is scanty; at the m o m e n t o f coming i n t o contact w i t h G e r m a n philosophy, these Spanish thinkers chose i n K r a u s e a secondary t h i n k e r , one m u c h less f r u i t f u l t h a n the great figures o f the age. Perhaps Sanz del Rio's predilection for Krause was influenced b y the religious a n d m o r a l character o f the latter's philosophy. T h e best historian of the Spanish K r a u s i a n m o v e m e n t , Pierre J o b i t , * interprets i t as apremodernist movement, an a n t i c i p a t i o n i n the nineteenth century of the heterodox t r e n d t h a t arose i n certain Catholic groups a r o u n d 1900. Sanz del Rio's w r i t i n g s were h a r d l y circulated b e y o n d the entourage o f his pupils, p a r t l y because o f his obscure a n d unpleasant style, b u t also because of the real difficulties o f his t h o u g h t , w h i c h signifies a considerable philosophic effort w i t h i n the potentialities o f the Spain of his t i m e . Sanz del Rio's p r i n c i p a l works, w h i c h he presented as expositions o f Krause, are Ideal de la Humanidad Sistema
para
la vida
( M a n k i n d ' s I d e a l o f Life) ; Lecciones
de filosofía analítica
de Krause
A n a l y t i c a l Philosophy) ;
Sistema
parte,
parte,
Análisis
and
Segunda
sobre
el
(Lectures on Krause's System o f de la Filosofía
Síntesis;
Análisis
: Metafísica
:
del pensamiento
Primera racional
(Analysis o f R a t i o n a l T h o u g h t ) ; Filosofía de la muerte (Philosophy o f Death) ; and El idealismo absoluto (Absolute I d e a l i s m ) . SOCIALISM. T h e influence of the G e r m a n idealists, especially Hegel, and also t h a t o f L u d w i g Andreas Feuerbach (1804-1872), a H e g e l i a n critic o f theology i n the d i r e c t i o n o f a n atheistic a n t h r o p o l o g i s m , and D a v i d F r i e d r i c h Strauss, c o m b i n e d w i t h that o f Charles D a r w i n , were exerted o n the theoreticians o f G e r m a n socialism. ( O n e should not forget the different roots t h a t the contemporary o r slightly earlier F r e n c h socialism had.) T h e most i m p o r t a n t G e r m a n socialists were K a r l M a r x (1818-1883), F r i e d r i c h Engels (1820—1895) and F e r d i n a n d Lassalle (1825-1864). I n 1848 M a r x a n d Engels published the Communist Manifesto; they were the founders o f the I n t e r n a t i o n a l . M a r x w o n his doctorate w i t h a dissertation o n Democritus a n d E p i c u r u s , a n d later p u b l i s h e d Thesen uber Feuerbach (Theses o n Feuerbach), Die heilige Familie ( T h e H o l y F a m i l y ) , La misère de la philosophie ( i n answer to Pierre Joseph Proudhon's La philosophie
de la misère),
Z
u r
Kritik
der politischen
Okonomie
C r i t i q u e o f P o l i t i c a l Economy) a n d his major w o r k ,
(Toward Das
a
Kapital.
*Les Krausistes by the A b b é Pierre Jobit (Paris-Bordeaux, 1936). Cf. my essay " E l pensador de Illescas" in Ensayos de teoría [Obras, I V ] . See also El krausismo español by J u a n López-Morillas (Mexico, 1950).
Derivations
Lassalle w r o t e Die
Philosophie
of
Idealism
des Herakleitos
337
des Dunklen
von
Ephesos
( T h e Philosophy o f Heraclitus the Obscure o f Ephesus) and the System der erworbenen Rechte (System o f A c q u i r e d R i g h t s ) . T h e point o f d e p a r t u r e o f these thinkers is the idea o f dialectics, derived f r o m Hegel. T h i s dialectics was "speculative," idealistic; i t started out f r o m p u r e thought, Engels says, a n d was to come f r o m the most s t u b b o r n facts (von den hartnäckigsten Tatsachen). There was no place here for a m e t h o d that " w e n t f r o m n o t h i n g t h r o u g h n o t h i n g to n o t h i n g " (von nichts durch nichts zu nichts kam), as Engels remarked i r o n i c a l l y , q u o t i n g Hegel's Logic. I t was necessary to subject this dialectics to a penetrating analysis, b u t M a r x and Engels recognized " t h e enormous historical significance" o n w h i c h i t was based. This grandiose a n d epoch-making conception o f history " w a s the direct theoretic presupposition of the new materialistic i n t u i t i o n . " I n their hands Hegel's idealist dialectic becomes a materialist dialectic w h i c h leads these m e n to w h a t is called—somewhat i m p r o p e r l y — a m a t e r i a l i s t i c i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f h i s t o r y ; i t is actually a n economic i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f history. P o l i t i c a l economy thus becomes the basic d i s c i p l i n e ; Engels, for his p a r t , m a d e a searching c o m m e n t a r y on M a r x ' s treatise Z Kritik der politischen Ökonomie. P o l i t i c a l economy begins w i t h commodities ( W a r e ) , at the m o m e n t w h e n products are exchanged. T h e product i n v o l v e d i n the exchange is a c o m m o d i t y . A n d i t is a c o m m o d i t y s i m p l y because the thing, the p r o d u c t , creates a relationship between t w o persons or communities, t h a t is, between the producer and the consumer, w h o are no longer the same person. ur
T h i s is the c r u x o f M a r x ' s conception: " E c o n o m y does n o t deal w i t h things, b u t w i t h relationships between persons and, i n the f i n a l analysis, between classes; however, these relationships are always bound to things a n d appear as things." H e r e w e see h o w a thought w h i c h f o r m e r l y stressed personal relationships comes, w i t h o u t clear j u s t i f i c a t i o n , to emphasize the things. M a r x insisted o n the importance o f the economic factor i n history w i t h great insight a n d indisputable genius, b u t t h e n wished to base history completely o n this economic factor and, b y means o f an untenable a r b i t r a r y construction, to consider e v e r y t h i n g else as a superstructure o f economics. C u l t u r e , religion, philosophy, man's entire life, w o u l d be explained b y the economic component o f l i f e — a real b u t p a r t i a l component; one n o t t o be overlooked, b u t secondary i n a complete perspective. O n the other h a n d , the p o l i t i c a l ideology associated w i t h this philosophical d o c t r i n e led to a substantification o f the idea o f social "classes," to the f i x i n g o f the t w o types " b o u r g e o i s " a n d " p r o l e t a r -
338
The
Thought
of the Romantic
Age
i a n " as standard concepts. These terms were relatively useful i n explaining t h e social situation i n E u r o p e a t t h e b e g i n n i n g o f the i n d u s t r i a l age, b u t are absolutely inadequate w h e n a p p l i e d t o other eras or other countries; i n such cases they v i o l e n t l y distort r e a l i t y , w h i c h cannot be adapted t o the f r a m e w o r k they impose o n i t . M a r x was a v e r y i m p o r t a n t economist, b u t is even m o r e i m p o r t a n t as a p o l i t i c a l theorist, the founder o f one o f the greatest mass movements i n history. However, this does n o t signify philosophical importance. T h e so-called " M a r x i s t t h o u g h t " o f later times has been restricted b y a very n a r r o w discipline, t o t h e extent t h a t i t constitutes a f o r m o f Scholasticism i n w h i c h t h e most f r e q u e n t l y quoted philosophical authorities, along w i t h M a r x and (secondarily) Engels, have been L e n i n a n d Stalin (the a u t h o r i t y o f the l a t t e r was quickly cancelled after his death). T o d a y the most interesting M a r x ist thinkers are the H u n g a r i a n G y ö r g y Lukäcs (b. 1885), a u t h o r o f Die
Theorie
des Romans
(Theory
o f t h e N o v e l ) , Geschichte
und
Klas-
( H i s t o r y a n d Class Consciousness), Essays über den Realismus, Die Zerstörung der Vernunft ( T h e Destruction o f Reason); and the G e r m a n Ernst Bloch, at present a professor i n West G e r m a n y , w h o has w r i t t e n Das Prinzip Hoffnung ( T h e Principle o f H o p e ) a n d Naturrecht und menschliche Würde ( N a t u r a l L a w a n d H u m a n D i g n i t y ) .
senbewusstsein
T h e d o g m a t i c materialism a n d atheism professed as principles b y M a r x i s m have given this movement a n extremely r i g i d character. Its quasi-religious features have very l i t t l e t o d o w i t h t h e o r i g i n a l core o f M a r x ' s t h i n k i n g , especially t h a t o f his y o u t h , w h i c h is today studied w i t h greater interest a n d academic freedom t h a n the forms dictated b y a n inflexible organization alien t o the a t t i t u d e o f perenn i a l restlessness, quest and j u s t i f i c a t i o n proper t o philosophy.
5.
SCHOPENHAUER
L I F E A N D W O R K S . A r t h u r Schopenhauer was b o r n i n D a n z i g i n 1788 a n d d i e d i n F r a n k f u r t a m M a i n i n 1860. H i s father was a w e a l t h y businessman a n d his mother a n i n t e l l i g e n t , c u l t u r e d novelist. A f t e r a n i n t r o d u c t i o n i n t o t h e business w o r l d , he studied philosophy i n Göttingen a n d B e r l i n . H i s d o c t o r a l thesis was his book Über die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde ( O n the F o u r f o l d R o o t o f the P r i n c i p l e o f Sufficient Reason). I n 1818 he finished his major w o r k , Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung ( T h e W o r l d as W i l l a n d Representation), w h i c h d i d n o t receive m u c h notice. A f t e r 1820 he was Privatdozent i n B e r l i n , b u t he h a d scarcely a n y students i n his classes, w h i c h were announced a t the same t i m e as Hegel's. W h e n
Schopenhauer
339
the cholera epidemic struck B e r l i n i n 1831, Schopenhauer fled the city and settled for good i n F r a n k f u r t ; thus he escaped the epidemic w h i c h k i l l e d H e g e l . Schopenhauer's later books were m o r e successful : Ober den Willen in der Natur ( O n W i l l i n N a t u r e ) , Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik ( T h e T w o F u n d a m e n t a l Problems o f E t h i c s ) , Aphoristnen zur Lebensweisheit (Aphorisms o n the W i s d o m o f L i f e ) , and
Parerga
und
Paralipomena.
T h r o u g h o u t his life, Schopenhauer was b i t t e r l y hostile to the postK a n t i a n idealist philosophers, especially H e g e l , w h o m he disparaged, sometimes w i t h w i t , b u t often w i t h l i t t l e j u s t i f i c a t i o n and poor insight. H i s failure to achieve success a n d fame as a professor a n d w r i t e r accentuated the b i t i n g a n d aggressive pessimism t h a t characterizes his philosophy. Schopenhauer was keenly interested i n art, music a n d literature. H e was a n a d m i r e r a n d translator o f Baltasar G r a c i a n , whose sententious a n d aphoristic style appealed to h i m . T h e strongest influences o n Schopenhauer were Plato, K a n t , the p o s t - K a n t i a n idealists—even t h o u g h he disagreed w i t h t h e m — a n d on the other h a n d , I n d i a n t h o u g h t a n d B u d d h i s m . Ever since the last years o f Schopenhauer's life, a n d p a r t i c u l a r l y since his death, his t h o u g h t has been very i n f l u e n t i a l , t h o u g h its effect has been felt more i n the realms o f literature, theosophy, and the like, t h a n i n the r e a l m o f philosophy itself. T H E W O R L D AS W I L L A N D R E P R E S E N T A T I O N . T h e title o f Schopen-
hauer's masterwork contains the c e n t r a l thesis o f his philosophy. T h e w o r l d is a " p h e n o m e n o n , " a representation or idea; Schopenhauer makes no d i s t i n c t i o n between a p h e n o m e n o n a n d an appearance; he says that the t w o are i d e n t i c a l . T h e w o r l d as we k n o w i t is a n appearance or deception. Space, time a n d causality are the forms w h i c h change this w o r l d i n t o a w o r l d of objects; they order and arrange the sensations. T h e K a n t i a n roots i n this theory are evident. However, there is a n aspect o f the w o r l d w h i c h we do not apprehend as pure p h e n o m e n o n ; this is the ego, w h i c h is apprehended i n a m o r e p r o f o u n d a n d d i r e c t manner. O n the one h a n d , the ego can be perceived as a b o d y ; b u t i t can also be perceived as something non-spatial a n d beyond t i m e a n d , w h a t is m o r e , as s o m e t h i n g free, a n d this is called the will. I n his deepest level, m a n apprehends himself as the will to live. Every object i n the w o r l d manifests itself as a longing o r w i l l to b e ; this is as t r u e w i t h respect to i n o r g a n i c things as w i t h respect to organic things a n d i n the r e a l m o f consciousness. T h u s , reality is w i l l . However, i n a s m u c h as desire presupposes insatiability, the w i l l is constant p a i n . Pleasure, w h i c h can o n l y be transitory, consists o f a cessation o f p a i n ; f u n d a m e n t a l l y , life consists o f p a i n . Thus, Schopen-
340
The
Thought
of the Romantic
Age
hauer's philosophy is rigorously pessimistic. T h e never-quenched w i l l to live is a n e v i l ; a n d , therefore, the w o r l d a n d man's life are also evils. Schopenhauer's ethics derives f r o m this idea. T h e m o r a l emotions are compassion a n d the desire to alleviate the p a i n w h i c h other beings feel. K n o w l e d g e , a r t a n d especially music also tend to do this, b u t they are fleeting remedies. T h e o n l y p e r m a n e n t salvation consists i n conquering the will to live. W h e n this w i l l is subdued, one enters nirvana; and this, w h i c h appears to be mere a n n i h i l a t i o n , is actually the greatest good, the t r u e salvation, the o n l y t h i n g w h i c h can end the p a i n a n d discontent o f the never-satisfied desire to live. Schopenhauer's ethics also has a deterministic feature, i n t h a t m a n is good or b a d essentially a n d for always; there is, for example, no possibility o f a b a d man's changing for the good. Schopenhauer opposes Socrates' d o c t r i n e a n d believes t h a t v i r t u e cannot be t a u g h t ; r a t h e r , a person is good or bad a radice. Schopenhauer's philosophy is perspicacious, ingenious a n d frequently p r o f o u n d ; i t is expressed w i t h m u c h l i t e r a r y skill a n d is animated b y his strong and fertile personality. However, i t does n o t have a solid basis i n metaphysics a n d i t has l e d m a n y thinkers to lose themselves i n a t r i v i a l dilettantism i m p r e g n a t e d w i t h theosophy, l i t e r a t u r e and I n d i a n " p h i l o s o p h y , " i n w h i c h the m e a n i n g o f p h i l o s o p h y is actually lost. W e have seen t h a t the p e r i o d o f G e r m a n idealism really ends w i t h H e g e l ; the subsequent thinkers represent the consequences o f this idealism i n t h a t they give themselves u p to a speculation w h i c h loses contact w i t h the a u t h e n t i c problems o f metaphysics. T h e vagueness, haziness a n d fantastic constructions w h i c h Hegel p o i n t e d o u t i n his o w n time reappear w i t h greater force after his death. This provokes a reactionary m o v e m e n t w h i c h sinks p h i l o s o p h y i n t o one o f its most p r o f o u n d crises: w h a t is k n o w n as positivism.
NINETEENTH-CENTURY PHILOSOPHY
The Triumph
over Sensationalism
A history o f c o n t e m p o r a r y philosophy made i n the m i d d l e years o f the t w e n t i e t h c e n t u r y must place the thinkers o f the last c e n t u r y i n a new perspective, one w h i c h does n o t coincide w i t h the w a y i n w h i c h these figures are usually represented. I n d e e d , w h e n i n t e r p r e t i n g the philosophy o f the recent past, we must follow t w o r u l i n g ideas: one, the comprehension o f a t i m e w h i c h is different f r o m o u r o w n , even t h o u g h n o t far removed f r o m i t ; t w o , the necessity o f e x p l a i n i n g h o w our o w n p h i l o s o p h y derives f r o m the earlier philosophy a n d h o w i t happens t h a t the earlier epoch has been succeeded by the one i n w h i c h we live. T h i s necessitates, first o f a l l , a n a p p r e c i a t i o n o f the significance o f the nineteenth-century philosophers w h i c h does not correspond to the one w h i c h prevailed at that t i m e . A few obscure thinkers w h o were misunderstood i n their o w n day are seen today to represent the most substantial a n d efficacious aspects o f the philosophy of the last century. A n d we note t h a t often w h a t were t h e n the least k n o w n parts o f their w o r k are n o w v i e w e d as decisive a n d even as anticipations o f the most p r o f o u n d discoveries o f our o w n epoch. T h e nineteenth century is characterized b y a certain i r r e g u l a r i t y w i t h respect to p h i l o s o p h y ; actually, nineteenth-century philosophy does n o t begin u n t i l after Hegel's death i n 1831. T h e first t h i r d o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y a n d the last t h i r d o f the eighteenth f o r m a c o m pletely separate p e r i o d d o m i n a t e d b y G e r m a n idealism. A phase o f philosophy exhausts itself at Hegel's death, a n d a deep crisis t h e n overwhelms philosophy and causes i t to a l l b u t disappear. T h i s is n o t surprising, because the history o f philosophy is discontinuous, a n d 34'
The
Triumph
over
Sensationalism
epochs o f m a x i m u m creative tension are always followed b y l o n g years o f relaxation, d u r i n g w h i c h the m i n d does n o t seem capable o f s u p p o r t i n g the effort w h i c h metaphysics involves. B u t i n the n i n e teenth century, philosophy is also f o r m a l l y denied, a n d this is evidence o f a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y abhorrence o f p h i l o s o p h i z i n g t h a t is at least p a r t i a l l y p r o d u c e d b y the abuses o f the dialectical m e t h o d w h i c h characterize the later phases o f the once b r i l l i a n t G e r m a n idealism. M e n feel a n u r g e n t need to concern themselves w i t h the things, w i t h reality itself, to divorce themselves f r o m m e n t a l constructions i n order to come to terms w i t h r e a l i t y as such. T h e E u r o p e a n m i n d o f 1830 finds i n the i n d i v i d u a l sciences the model w h i c h m u s t be transferred i n t o the r e a l m of philosophy. Physics, biology a n d history come t o represent the exemplary modes o f knowledge. T h i s a t t i t u d e gives rise to positivism.
T h e i n i t i a l p r o p o s i t i o n — t o concern oneself w i t h r e a l i t y itself—is irreproachable a n d constitutes a p e r m a n e n t philosophical i m p e r a t i v e . B u t this is precisely where the p r o b l e m begins: W h a t is r e a l i t y ? W e have seen t h a t philosophy cannot set bounds for itself or define itself extrinsically; r a t h e r , its very d e l i m i t a t i o n supposes a p r i o r question o f metaphysics. W i t h excessive haste, the n i n e t e e n t h century thinks t h a t i t can suppress this question, a n d affirms t h a t r e a l i t y consists of sensible facts. This is the error w h i c h invalidates positivism. I t w o u l d n o t be going too far to i n t e r p r e t philosophy f r o m C o m t e to the present as a n effort to re-establish t h a t postulate actually, to make itself t r u l y positive or, i n other words, to discover w h a t a u t h e n t i c r e a l i t y really is, w i t h o u t using m e n t a l constructions or exclusions, i n order t h a t i t m a y concern itself faithfully w i t h reality. O f course, r e a l i t y is d i l u t e d as m u c h b y additions as b y omissions. W h a t t h o u g h t superposes o n the things changes a n d falsifies t h e m ; b u t p a r t i a l i t y , to take the p a r t as the whole, to believe that something which is real is i n itself reality, does not signify a n y lesser degree o f falsity. Philosophy has repeatedly identified p o r t i o n s or elements o f w h a t exists as the s u m t o t a l o f reality, a n d i t has constantly h a d to exert itself i n order to correct this error b y i n c o r p o r a t i n g i n t o its vision o f reality elements w h i c h have been left outside i t a n d w h i c h have falsified i t b y t h e i r absence. However, the error c o m m i t t e d at the b e g i n n i n g o f the nineteenth century is m o r e serious because i t defines r e a l i t y — i t formulates a metaphysical thesis—and at the same t i m e is so unaware o f this fact t h a t i t denies the possibility o f its existence; t h a t is, i t does not u n d e r stand its i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f reality as sensible facts for w h a t i t is, a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , b u t takes i t to be r e a l i t y itself. I t builds u p o n this
The
Triumph
over
Sensationalism
343
supposition w i t h o u t even being aware of i t . Therefore, after positivism, a double p r o b l e m w i l l confront p h i l o s o p h y : first, philosophy w i l l have to discover the n a t u r e of authentic r e a l i t y , w h a t w i l l later be called the fundamental reality, a n d secondly, i t w i l l have to re-establish the necessity for a n d possibility of metaphysics. These t w o tasks are undertaken simultaneously and along p a r a l l e l paths, b u t n o t b y means of a speculation o n philosophy itself, b y v i r t u e of w h i c h the v a l i d i t y o f metaphysical knowledge is shown, i n order later, once this tool has been o b t a i n e d , to be able to investigate the structure of reality. O n the contrary, the v e r y effort of philosophizing w i l l lead to the evidence that positivism was already p r a c t i c i n g metaphysics at the v e r y m o m e n t w h e n i t c l a i m e d to have e l i m i n a t e d i t . Positivism practiced metaphysics w i t h o u t realizing i t , that is, i n a not very positive m a n n e r a n d , therefore, erroneously and faultily. O n one h a n d , the a t t e m p t to lead philosophy to t r u e positiveness w i l l oblige thinkers to notice realities w h i c h have s t u b b o r n l y been overlooked: specifically, the r e a l m of ideal objects a n d the reality of human life, w i t h its special modes o f being a n d a l l t h e i r ontological consequences. O n the other h a n d , i n order to conceive the above-mentioned realities i t w i l l be necessary to use new i n t e l l e c t u a l tools, a n d these w i l l give us a new conception of knowledge a n d of philosophy itself. T h u s o u r o w n age finds itself i n the situation of having to create a new metaphysics, one w h i c h t h o u g h new is rooted i n the entire t r a d i t i o n o f the philosophic past. F o l l o w i n g the anticipations o f a few b r i l l i a n t thinkers o f the nineteenth century, phenomenology, existent i a l philosophy a n d the philosophy o f v i t a l reason have created a m e t h o d o f knowledge a n d have t u r n e d man's attention to the ideal w o r l d a n d the r e a l i t y o f life. T h u s the philosophy o f our t i m e feels obliged to delve to the roots of the u l t i m a t e questions, and i n this w a y acquires its greatest o r i g i n a l i t y . Intensity returns to philosophic life i n France d u r i n g the first h a l f of the nineteenth century. After the r i c h epoch of the E n l i g h t e n m e n t there appears a g r o u p of interesting F r e n c h thinkers; they are related to the ideologists w h o l i v e d at the end o f the seventeenth c e n t u r y a n d are p r i m a r i l y concerned w i t h problems related to psychology a n d the o r i g i n of ideas. T h i s philosophy, w h i c h invokes Condillac's sensationalism as its direct antecedent, initiates a g r a d u a l change f r o m this p o i n t of view a n d ends b y tackling metaphysical questions; i n a real sense this constitutes a n i m p o r t a n t phase i n the prehistory of the philosophy oflife. T h e t w o p r i n c i p a l figures representing this tendency are Pierre
The
344
Triumph
over
Sensationalism
Laromiguière a n d Joseph M a r i e Degérando, forerunners o f the major thinker of the epoch, M a i n e de B i r a n , w h o later gives rise to the g r o u p of spiritualists. Laromiguière ( i 756—1837) w r o t e the Leçons de philosophie, w h i c h are sensationalist i n t h e i r b r o a d outlines b u t w h i c h nevertheless distinguish between reception a n d reaction, a f f i r m the a c t i v i t y of the ego as manifested i n attention, a n d thus represent a first a t t e m p t to supersede p u r e sensationalism. Degérando (1772-1842), b o r n a generation later, was also a sensationalist ; he was influenced b y the w o r k o f Bacon, Locke a n d Condillac, b u t was also w e l l acquainted w i t h G e r m a n idealism, a n d this circumstance unsettled his p h i l o sophical position. H e w r o t e a long b o o k i n four volumes e n t i t l e d Des signes et de l'art dépenser considérés dans leurs rapports mutuels, a n d t h e n the Histoire
comparée des systèmes de philosophie,
relativement
aux principes
des
i n three volumes. Degérando postulates a philosophy of experience ; he affirms a d u a l i s m of t w o elements, the ego a n d contiguous existences, w h i c h are revealed b y the fact of resistance. A t the same time he attempts to u n i t e r a t i o n a l i s m a n d e m p i r i c i s m ; this a t t i t u d e anticipates eclecticism. connaissances
humaines,
1.
M A I N E DE
BIRAN
P H I L O S O P H I C S I T U A T I O N . T h e most p r o f o u n d a n d o r i g i n a l o f the French philosophers o f this t i m e was M a i n e de B i r a n (1766-1824). H i s p r i n c i p a l w o r k is the Essai sur lesfondements de la psychologie et sur ses rapports
avec
décomposition
l'étude
de la nature
de la pensée a n d
( 1 8 1 2 ) ; the
Influence
Journal,
de l'habitude
Mémoire
sur la faculté
sur de
la
penser
also figure a m o n g his most interesting w r i t i n g s . M a i n e de B i r a n , w h o was influenced b y Destutt de T r a c y a n d b y Laromiguière a n d w h o engaged i n polemics w i t h Joseph de M a i s t r e a n d Louis de B o n a l d , occupies a position somewhat analogous to t h a t of Fichte i n G e r m a n y . H e begins w i t h a sensationalist a t t i t u d e , is t h e n led to the first r a t h e r m a t u r e comprehension o f h u m a n life, a n d ends u p as a theistic a n d Catholic t h i n k e r . P a r t l y because of the o r i g i n a l i t y o f his p o i n t of view a n d p a r t l y because of his obscure a n d inconsistent w r i t i n g s , M a i n e de B i r a n was misunderstood i n his o w n t i m e , a l t h o u g h later F r e n c h thinkers referred to h i m as their master. T o this day his philosophy is not sufficiently u t i l i z e d , i n spite of efforts m a d e i n the present century. M E T A P H Y S I C S . A c t i n g o n sensationalist suppositions, M a i n e de B i r a n seeks the primitive fact o n w h i c h science must be founded. H o w ever, i t cannot be sensation, because sensation is not even afact. I n order to be a fact, a t h i n g must be k n o w n , i t must exist for someone ; a fact requires contact between the sensory impression a n d the ego. Consciousness implies a d u a l i s m o f terms, a coexistence, a n d this i n t u r n requires
Spiritualism
345
a p r i o r milieu i n w h i c h the ego finds itself together w i t h w h a t is k n o w n . W h a t is k n o w n is always known jointly, because to k n o w means my knowing myself together with the object. E v e r y fact supposes a d u a l i s m o f terms w h i c h cannot be conceived separately, for one is a f u n c t i o n o f the other : the ego exists o n l y as i t exercises itself w h e n facing a n object of resistance. M a i n e de B i r a n converts objective concepts i n t o functional concepts; coexistence becomes a d y n a m i c a l r e a l i t y , a " d o i n g " — a c t i v i t y ; the ego a n d the object o f resistance are o n l y elements o f t h a t active reality. * T h i s results i n something quite f u n d a m e n t a l : the ego is not a thing; m a n constitutes a n antithesis to the entire universe; neither is a c t i v i t y a thing, nor are its terms, w h i c h constitute themselves as terms o n l y w h e n i n t e r a c t i n g . M a i n e de B i r a n understands life as an active tension between a n ego a n d a w o r l d w h i c h are o n l y elements i n the p r i m a r y r e a l i t y of a c t i v i t y . T h e ego becomes, i t constitutes itself i n a c t i v i t y , a n d thus m a n can i n i t i a t e series of free acts a n d lead a personal, h u m a n life. I n the t h o u g h t o f M a i n e de B i r a n w e d i m l y glimpse an i n c o n sistent and confused v i s i o n — b a d l y expressed b u t nevertheless a c c u r a t e — o f the r e a l i t y we call human life. 2.
SPIRITUALISM
T H E ECLECTICS. T h e movement k n o w n as F r e n c h spiritualism, which d o m i n a t e d official philosophy for fifty years, tooks its inspiration f r o m M a i n e de B i r a n , b u t w i t h o u t a t t a i n i n g great p r o f u n d i t y , w i t h o u t a d o p t i n g the most valuable aspects o f his t h o u g h t . T h e i n i t i a t o r o f F r e n c h s p i r i t u a l i s m was Pierre Paul R o y e r - C o l l a r d (1763-1845), a n i m p o r t a n t figure i n p o l i t i c a l d o c t r i n a i r i s m , w h o adopted the teachings of the Scottish school o f Thomas R e i d a n d D u g a l d Stewart. T h é o d o r e J o u f f r o y (1796-1842) was related to this movement. B u t the most i m p o r t a n t t h i n k e r o f the g r o u p was V i c t o r Cousin (1792-1867), founder o f eclecticism, the official p h i l o s o p h y o f the Université de France d u r i n g the reign o f Louis P h i l i p p e . Cousin was an u n o r i g i n a l philosopher w h o t r i e d to reconcile the various systems; his w o r k reveals shifting influences reaching f r o m the Greeks to the G e r m a n idealists, especially Schelling, a n d o f course the Scottish philosophers and M a i n e de B i r a n . Cousin actively s t i m u l a t e d the study o f the history o f philosophy, w h i c h he h i m s e l f practiced intensively. H e published various Cours d'histoire de la philosophie, the Fragments philosophiques,
the
Du
vrai,
du beau
et du bien
and
several h i s t o r i c a l
and
b i o g r a p h i c a l works, especially studies o f the P o r t - R o y a l circle. * Cf. my study " E l hombre y Dios en la filosofía de Maine de B i r a n " in San Anselmo y el insensato [Obras, I V ] .
34
6
The
Triumph
over
Sensationalism
T H E T R A D I T I O N A L I S T S . A n o t h e r reaction against sensationalism, b u t w i t h a m a r k e d o r i e n t a t i o n t o w a r d social, p o l i t i c a l a n d historical problems, appeared i n a group o f C a t h o l i c thinkers whose ties w i t h R o m e were s t r o n g ; this g r o u p founded the ultramontanist movement, w h i c h recognized the Papacy a n d l e g i t i m a c y as the bases o f social order. These m e n represented a t r a d i t i o n a l i s t position w h i c h mistrusted reason a n d f o u n d the f u n d a m e n t a l t r u t h s i n " belief, " of w h i c h society is the g u a r d i a n ; i n politics they opposed the s p i r i t a n d doctrines o f the F r e n c h R e v o l u t i o n . T h e most i m p o r t a n t thinkers o f this circle were C o m t e Joseph de M a i s t r e ( i 753-1821) o f Savoy, w h o was Sardinia's ambassador to Russia (Du Pape ; Soirées de Saint-Pétersbourg), a n d Louis de B o n a l d (1754-1840), w h o a t t e m p t e d to systematize t r a d i t i o n a l i s m (Législationprimitive; Essai analytique sur les lois naturelles de Vordre social). Félicité R o b e r t de L a m e n n a i s — w h o finally left the C h u r c h — J e a n Baptiste H e n r i L a c o r d a i r e a n d the C o m t e de M o n t a l e m b e r t (Charles Forbes) were p a r t i a l l y connected w i t h this g r o u p , b u t their o u t l o o k was m o r e l i b e r a l . T h e R e v o l u t i o n , w h i c h p r o d u c e d this t r a d i t i o n a l i s t reaction, aroused at the same t i m e a m o v e m e n t t h a t was social i n character ; this was led b y several F r e n c h theorists whose social doctrines were U t o p i a n imaginings, b u t n o t w i t h o u t p e n e t r a t i n g ideas on the p r o b l e m o f society. O u t s t a n d i n g here were S a i n t - S i m o n (Claude H e n r i de R o u v r o y ) , François M a r i e Charles F o u r i e r a n d Pierre Joseph P r o u d h o n , w h o at one a n d the same t i m e s t i m u l a t e d socialistic p o l i t i c a l currents a n d the f o u n d i n g of the social sciences. A l l these elements are u t i l i z e d i n v a r y i n g degree b y positivism, the most i m p o r t a n t aspect of nineteenth-century philosophy. B A L M E S . T h e C a t a l a n priest J a i m e L u c i a n o Balmes, w h o was b o r n at V i c h i n 1810 a n d d i e d i n 1848, represents, together w i t h Sanz del R i o , Spain's m a j o r c o n t r i b u t i o n to nineteenth-century p h i l o s o p h y ; his t h o u g h t has c e r t a i n affinities w i t h t h a t o f the above-mentioned F r e n c h theorists. H i s short life was filled w i t h a n intensive a c t i v i t y as p o l i t i c i a n , j o u r n a l i s t a n d philosopher. H i s most i m p o r t a n t works are El criterio—a p o p u l a r logic o f c o m m o n s e n s e — E l protestantismo comparado con el catolicismo—a rejoinder t o François Guizot's Histoire de la civilisation
en Europe—Filosofía
elemental
and
Filosofíafundamental.
Balmes, w h o became f a m i l i a r w i t h Scholasticism t h r o u g h his t r a i n i n g for the priesthood, was able t o renew i t i n a p e r i o d o f great decadence, b r i n g i n g to i t ideas f r o m the Scottish school, o n the one h a n d , a n d f r o m the systems o f Descartes a n d L e i b n i z , o n the other. Even w i t h i n the l i m i t a t i o n s imposed u p o n his w o r k b y the historical circumstances i n w h i c h he l i v e d a n d b y his early death, his w r i t i n g s
347
Spiritualism
still signified a serious a n d valuable a t t e m p t to revive philosophical studies i n Spain, a n d a true reawakening m i g h t have been expected as a result. Balmes' v i e w o f contemporary philosophy, especially G e r m a n idealism, is superficial and falls far short o f the m a r k ; b u t he brings m a n y other questions into sharp focus w i t h good sense a n d frequently w i t h perspicacity. Outside the strict field of philosophy a n d very close to the F r e n c h traditionalists is the w o r k o f J u a n Donoso Cortés (1809-1853), Spain's ambassador to France. I n Paris he came into contact w i t h the Catholic thinkers, w h o esteemed h i m h i g h l y . His major w o r k is the Ensayo
sobre el catolicismo,
el liberalismoy
el
socialismo.
Comtess
Positivism
L I F E A N D W O R K S . Auguste Comte was b o r n i n 1798 a n d d i e d i n 1857. A l t h o u g h he came f r o m a f a m i l y t h a t was Catholic, m o n a r c h i s t a n d conservative, he was q u i c k to a d o p t a n o u t l o o k t h a t was inspired b y the French R e v o l u t i o n . H e collaborated w i t h Saint-Simon ( w i t h w h o m he later b r o k e ) , a n d f a m i l i a r i z e d h i m s e l f w i t h social problems. H e was a student a t the École Polytechnique o f Paris, a n d there acquired a solid f o u n d a t i o n i n mathematics a n d science. L a t e r he was a t u t o r at the É c o l e , u n t i l enmities there caused h i m to lose t h e position. W h i l e still q u i t e y o u n g , he published a series o f extremely interesting Opuscules o n society, a n d t h e n began t h e great w o r k i n six t h i c k volumes w h i c h he called Cours de philosophie positive. H e next w r o t e a short general b o o k , the Discours chisme positiviste,
sur l'esprit
a n d his second basic w o r k ,
positif,
Système de politique
the
Catépositive,
ou Traité de sociologie, instituant la religion de l'Humanité, i n four volumes. T h e Cours was published between 1830 a n d 1842, a n d the Système between 1851 a n d 1854. Comte's life was h a r d a n d u n h a p p y . H e was u n f o r t u n a t e i n his p r i v a t e life a n d , i n spite o f his unquestionably b r i l l i a n t n a t u r e a n d industry, he never achieved the least economic security. I n his last years he was s u p p o r t e d b y his friends a n d followers, especially those f r o m France a n d E n g l a n d . Auguste C o m t e h a d marks o f m e n t a l imbalance w h i c h sometimes became very m u c h accentuated. A t the e n d o f his life C o m t e fell deeply i n love w i t h C l o t i l d e de V a u x , a n d her death s h o r t l y a f t e r w a r d was a loss t h a t helped o v e r w h e l m him. 348
History
i.
349
HISTORY
T H E L A W O F T H E T H R E E STATES. A c c o r d i n g to Comte, knowledge passes t h r o u g h three distinct theoretic states, i n the i n d i v i d u a l as w e l l as i n the h u m a n species. T h e law of the three states, the basic p r o p o s i t i o n of positive philosophy, is at once a t h e o r y o f knowledge a n d a p h i losophy o f history. These three states are called theological, m e t a physical a n d positive. T h e theological or fictitious state is p r o v i s i o n a l and preparatory. I n i t the m i n d seeks the causes and origins of things, t h a t w h i c h is deepest, most distant a n d inaccessible. There are three d i s t i n c t phases i n this state: fetishism, i n w h i c h objects are personified a n d a t t r i b u t e d magic or divine power; polytheism, i n w h i c h personification is w i t h d r a w n f r o m m a t e r i a l things a n d transferred to a series o f divinities, each o f w h i c h represents a g r o u p o f powers: the bodies o f water, the rivers, the forests, a n d so o n ; a n d , finally, monotheism, the superior phase, i n w h i c h all these d i v i n e powers are united a n d concentrated i n one, called G o d . As we can see, the designation theological for this state is not a p p r o priate ; i t w o u l d be preferable to say religious or perhaps mythical. T h i s state, i n w h i c h the imagination predominates, corresponds, Comte says, to infancy i n H u m a n i t y . I t is also the p r i m a r y c o n d i t i o n of the m i n d , t h a t i n t o w h i c h the m i n d falls again a n d again i n a l l epochs, a n d only a slow e v o l u t i o n can make the h u m a n spirit p a r t w i t h one idea in order to pass o n to another. T h e role o f the theological state is historically indispensable. T h e metaphysical or abstract state is essentially critical a n d transit i o n a l . I t is a n i n t e r m e d i a t e stage between the theological a n d positive states. I n i t absolute knowledge is still sought. Metaphysics tries to explain the n a t u r e o f beings, their essence, their causes. T o do this, however, i t resorts, n o t to supernatural agents, b u t to abstract entities, whence its n a m e ontology. T h e ideas of o r i g i n , cause, substance, essence denote s o m e t h i n g distinct f r o m the things, a l t h o u g h inherent i n t h e m , closer to t h e m : the m i n d , w h i c h was s t r i v i n g after the remote, step b y step approaches the things. I n the previous state the powers were summed u p i n the concept of God, b u t here Mature is the great general entity w h i c h takes the place of G o d ; b u t this u n i t y is weaker, i n t e l lectually as w e l l as socially, and the character of the metaphysical state is, above a l l , c r i t i c a l a n d negative, p r e p a r a t o r y for the step to the positive state: a k i n d o f crisis o f p u b e r t y o f the h u m a n spirit before i t reaches the age of m a n h o o d . T h e positive or real state is the definitive one. I n i t i m a g i n a t i o n is subordinated to observation. T h e h u m a n m i n d relies on the things.
Comte
s
Positivism
Positivism seeks o n l y facts a n d their laws. N o t causes o r origins o f essences or substances—all this is inaccessible. Positivism relies o n the positive, o n t h a t w h i c h is set forth or given : i t is the p h i l o s o p h y o f the datum. T h e m i n d , i n a l o n g regression, finally comes to rest face to face w i t h the things. I t renounces w h a t i t is v a i n to t r y to k n o w , a n d seeks o n l y the laws o f phenomena. R E L A T I V I S M . T h e positive spirit is relative. T h e study of p h e n o m e n a is never absolute, b u t relative to our o r g a n i z a t i o n a n d o u r s i t u a t i o n . T h e loss or g a i n o f a sense, Comte says, w o u l d completely change o u r w o r l d and our knowledge o f i t . O u r ideas are phenomena, n o t o n l y i n d i v i d u a l p h e n o m e n a b u t also social a n d collective, a n d they depend o n the conditions o f our i n d i v i d u a l a n d social existence, a n d therefore on history. K n o w l e d g e must incessantly come nearer a n d nearer to the ideal l i m i t fixed b y o u r necessities. A n d t h e goal o f knowledge is r a t i o n a l f o r e s i g h t : voir pour prévoir, prévoir pour pourvoir
(see i n o r d e r t o
foresee, foresee i n o r d e r to provide) is one o f Comte's lemmas.
2.
SOCIETY
T H E SOCIAL C H A R A C T E R OF T H E POSITIVE SPIRIT. C o m t e affirms t h a t
ideas govern the w o r l d ; there is a c o r r e l a t i o n between w h a t is i n t e l lectual a n d w h a t is social, a n d the latter depends o n the f o r m e r . T h e positive spirit m u s t find a n e w social o r d e r t o replace t h e one demolished b y c r i t i c a l metaphysics, a n d must t r i u m p h over the crisis o f the West. C o m t e formulates a n acute t h e o r y concerning s p i r i t u a l and t e m p o r a l power. T h e basis for positive knowledge is the existence of a sufficient social a u t h o r i t y . A n d this reinforces t h e historical character of positivism ; Comte says t h a t the system w h i c h explains the past w i l l be master o f the future. I n this w a y , b y historical c o n t i n u i t y a n d social e q u i l i b r i u m , Comte's p o l i t i c a l l e m m a can be realized : ordre et progrès; order a n d progress. A n d t h e i m p e r a t i v e o f C o m t e a n m o r a l i t y — w h i c h is a n essentially social m o r a l i t y — i s to l i v e for one's fellow m a n : vivre pour autrui. SOCIOLOGY. C o m t e is the founder of the science o f society, w h i c h he first called social physics and then sociology. C o m t e tries to raise the study o f collective H u m a n i t y to the positive state, t h a t is, to convert i t i n t o a positive science. T h i s sociology is, above a l l , a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f historical reality. I n society there governs, also, a n d p r i n c i p a l l y , the l a w o f the three states, a n d there are the same n u m b e r o f stages. I n one, w h i c h lasts u n t i l the t w e l f t h century, the military dominates. Comte values h i g h l y the o r g a n i z a t i o n a l role t h a t falls to the Catholic C h u r c h ; i n the metaphysical epoch social influence falls to the lawmakers; i t is the era
Science
o f the i r r u p t i o n o f the m i d d l e classes, the passage f r o m m i l i t a r y society to economic society; i t is a period of t r a n s i t i o n , c r i t i c a l and dissolvent, revolutionary ; Protestantism contributes to this dissolution. F i n a l l y , corresponding to the positive state is the industrial era, governed b y economic interests; i n i t social order must be re-established, a n d i t must be founded o n intellectual and social power. T h e great protagonist o f history is H u m a n i t y , and Comte's sociology ends by almost deifying i t and b e c o m i n g a
religion.
T H E R E L I G I O N O F H U M A N I T Y . I n his last years Comte a r r i v e d at ideas w h i c h , t h o u g h eccentric, emerge f r o m the deepest recesses o f his t h o u g h t : for example, the idea o f the " r e l i g i o n o f H u m a n i t y . " H u m a n i t y is i n its t o t a l i t y the Grand-Être, the goal o f our personal lives; therefore, m o r a l i t y is altruism, l i v i n g for others, for H u m a n i t y . A n d this Great Being must be accorded a cult, first o f a l l p r i v a t e worship, i n w h i c h m a n feels at one w i t h his ancestors and descendants, but also p u b l i c w o r s h i p . Comte came to i m a g i n e the organization o f a complete c h u r c h , w i t h " s a c r a m e n t s , " priests, a calendar w i t h feast days devoted to the great figures o f H u m a n i t y , and so o n . T h e o n l y t h i n g missing i n this c h u r c h is G o d , a n d n a t u r a l l y i t is for this reason t h a t i t has no religious meaning. W i t h this strange idea, w h i c h obviously was strongly tinged w i t h madness, Comte expresses very clearly the role he assigns to spiritual power i n the organization o f social life; he seeks his m o d e l i n the s p i r i t u a l power par excellence, the Catholic C h u r c h , the hierarchy a n d c u l t o f w h i c h are the i n s p i r a t i o n for Comte's " r e l i g i o n . " A n d thus the positivist philosopher comes to summarize his t h o u g h t i n a final l e m m a : L'Amour pour principe, l'Ordre pour base, et le Progrès pour but (Love as a p r i n c i p l e , O r d e r as a basis, a n d Progress as a g o a l ) . N o w we see the f u l l significance of the complete title o f Comte's sociology: politics, sociology and the r e l i g i o n o f H u m a n i t y are inseparably l i n k e d together. 3.
SCIENCE
T H E CLASSIFICATION OF T H E SCIENCES. C o m t e formulated a classification o f the sciences w h i c h has since h a d great influence, a n d w h i c h is especially interesting because i t t h r o w s i n t o relief certain characteristics o f his t h o u g h t . T h e sciences stand i n a determined hierarchic order, as follows : mathematics-astronomy
physics-chemistry
biology-sociology
This h i e r a r c h y has a historical a n d d o g m a t i c , scientific a n d logical meaning, says C o m t e . I n the first place, i t is the order i n w h i c h the sciences were developed and, above a l l , the order i n w h i c h they
Corns/s
Positivism
attained their positive state. I n the second place, the sciences are arranged i n decreasing order of generality a n d increasing order o f complexity. I n the t h i r d place, they are a r r a n g e d according to t h e i r independence: each one has need o f those t h a t precede i t a n d is necessary to those t h a t follow i t . F i n a l l y , they are grouped i n three groups of two, w i t h special affinities between t h e m . T h e life sciences— biology a n d sociology—are the last to emerge f r o m the theologicalmetaphysical state. Sociology, especially, is the creation of Comte, w h o converts i t i n t o a true science. T h u s , n o t o n l y is the h i e r a r c h y o f sciences completed, b u t the most i m p o r t a n t discipline w i t h i n the Comtean scheme o f philosophy, defined b y its historical a n d social character, is o b t a i n e d . Certain strange omissions w i l l be observed i n Comte's classification. I t is i m m e d i a t e l y evident t h a t metaphysics is missing. Positivism considers metaphysics impossible, a l t h o u g h , as we have seen, i t indulges i n i t , since C o m t e elaborates a concrete theory of r e a l i t y ; also missing, n a t u r a l l y , is theology; this scarcely needs a n e x p l a n a t i o n . But i n a d d i t i o n , w e do not find psychology either; that discipline is treated p a r t l y u n d e r biology, p a r t l y u n d e r sociology; C o m t e considers introspection impossible, a n d o n l y believes possible experim e n t a l psychology, w h i c h enters into the sphere o f one or the other o f the t w o life sciences, depending on whether the i n d i v i d u a l or m a n i n his social dimension is being investigated. H i s t o r y a n d , i n general, the sciences of the spirit do not appear autonomously i n Comte's list, because he was taken w i t h the idea of u n i t y of m e t h o d , a n d insisted on always a p p l y i n g the m e t h o d o f the n a t u r a l sciences, despite his i m a g i n a t i v e vision of the role o f history. PHILOSOPHY. W h a t then is philosophy for the positivist? A p p a r e n t l y , i t is a reflection u p o n science. A f t e r the sciences are exhausted, there remains no independent object for philosophy b u t the sciences themselves; philosophy becomes theory of science. T h u s positive science acquires u n i t y and consciousness o f itself. B u t i t is clear t h a t philosophy disappears; and this is w h a t happens i n the positivist movement of the nineteenth century, w h i c h has very little to d o w i t h philosophy. But this does n o t occur i n Comte's o w n t h o u g h t . Aside f r o m w h a t he believes he is accomplishing, there is his a c t u a l accomplishment. A n d we have seen t h a t , i n the first place, he has given a philosophy o f history (the l a w o f the three states); i n the second place, he has g i v e n a metaphysical t h e o r y o f reality, conceived i n such o r i g i n a l a n d novel terms as t h a t o f social being, a historical a n d relative t h e o r y ; i n the t h i r d place, he has given a complete philosophical discipline, the
The
Significance
of
Positivism
353
science o f society—so complete t h a t sociology, i n the hands o f later sociologists, has never attained the d e p t h o f vision that i t reached w i t h its founder. T h i s , i n short, is the truest a n d most interesting aspect o f positivism, the aspect w h i c h , despite a l l appearances a n d even a l l positivists, makes i t really philosophy.
4.
T H E SIGNIFICANCE
OF
POSITIVISM
W h a t attracts most a t t e n t i o n i n C o m t e is the i m p o r t a n c e he attributes to h i m s e l f at the outset. H e is conscious o f a n enormous, definitive i m p o r t a n c e w h i c h he has for the w o r l d , a n d always begins his books w i t h a n air o f v i c t o r y , steeped i n the solemnity o f a n i n a u g u r a t i o n . W h y does Comte have such i m p o r t a n c e ? W h a t does he bear i n his hands w i t h such solemnity ? Observe h o w this first grave, almost h i e r a t i c a l gesture is m e n t a l l y i n t e r t w i n e d w i t h the u l t i m a t e ceremonies o f the religion o f H u m a n i t y . W e must seek the t h r e a d t h a t goes f r o m the one t h i n g to the other. Auguste C o m t e is sure that he is n o t speaking i n his o w n n a m e ; his voice is n o t his alone: i t is the concrete, i n d i v i d u a l i z e d voice o f h i s t o r y ; that is w h y i t resounds w i t h such majesty. Comte is, w i t h o u t a d o u b t , attuned to his own time. A n d that is the i m p o r t a n t fact. Being a t t u n e d to one's o w n t i m e means being at h o m e i n positive p h i l o s o p h y ; a n d positive p h i l o s o p h y is n o t h i n g less t h a n the definitive state o f the h u m a n m i n d . Being a t t u n e d to one's o w n t i m e therefore means h a v i n g already a r r i v e d a n d n o t being i n the m i d d l e o f one's j o u r n e y . T h i s positive science is a discipline o f modesty; a n d this is its v i r t u e . Positive k n o w l edge adheres h u m b l y to the things; i t comes to a h a l t before t h e m , w i t h o u t i n v o l v e m e n t , w i t h o u t leaping over t h e m to fling itself i n t o a deceptive p l a y o f ideas; i t no longer seeks causes, b u t o n l y laws. A n d , thanks to this austerity, i t attains those laws, a n d possesses t h e m w i t h precision a n d w i t h certainty. B u t i t so happens t h a t this situation is n o t p r i m a r y ; j u s t the c o n t r a r y : i t is the result o f the efforts o f m i l l e n n i a to restrain the m i n d , w h i c h was dashing o f f to the farthest distances, a n d force i t to l i m i t itself docilely to the things. These efforts make u p a l l o f history; C o m t e w i l l have to account for a l l o f i t i n order to understand positivism for w h a t i t is, f a i t h f u l l y , w i t h o u t falsifying i t , i n a positive way. A n d i t is n o t h i n g b u t a result. T h u s we see that the very i m p e r a t i v e of positivity also postulates a philosophy o f history; a n d this w o u l d be the first aspect o f his system: the l a w o f the three states. Positive p h i losophy is, ah initio, something historical. T i m e a n d again Comte returns, i n the most explicit m a n n e r , to the p r o b l e m o f history, a n d claims i t as the proper d o m a i n o f positive
Comte
s
Positivism
philosophy. Tout est relatif; voilà le seul principe absolu ( E v e r y t h i n g is r e l a t i v e ; t h a t is t h e o n l y absolute p r i n c i p l e ) — h e h a d w r i t t e n as early as 1817, w h e n he was still a boy. A n d i n t h a t r e l a t i v i s m he finds, nearly t h i r t y years later, the reason for the h i s t o r i c a l character o f positive philosophy, w h i c h can explain the entire past. T h i s is not a l u x u r y o f philosophy, s o m e t h i n g given to i t as a n a d j u n c t , b u t , as O r t e g a has seen and shown, t h e essential p o i n t i n his metaphysics. Perhaps C o m t e w o u l d not have t a k e n account of this, because he d i d not t h i n k he was engaging i n metaphysics ; b u t the central i m p o r t a n c e of this r e l a t i v i s m d i d not escape h i m . O n i t is founded positive philosophy's capacity for progress, a n d thus the possibility of c h a n g i n g a n d i m p r o v i n g n o t o n l y the condition o f m a n , b u t , above a l l , his nature. T h i s is a m o n g the weightiest things t h a t can be said, a n d , for t h a t v e r y reason, I w i s h to do no more t h a n m e n t i o n i t ; a sufficient c o m m e n t a r y w o u l d lead t o problems t h a t c a n n o t even be sketched here. B u t I do n o t w i s h t o conclude w i t h o u t q u o t i n g a few words o f Comte, l u c i d a n d m e a n i n g f u l today, w h i c h crystallize his t h o u g h t : Today
it can be affirmed—he
sufficiently of this proof
explained
w r i t e s — t h a t that
the past in its totality
alone, intellectual
leadership
will over
doctrine
inexorably
which
obtain,
in
shall
have
consequence
thefuture.
W e see then t h a t beneath his scientific n a t u r a l i s m we find i n C o m t e , as the essential p o i n t , a system of t h o u g h t o n h i s t o r i c a l principles. A n d this is w h a t gives his philosophy its greatest contemporaneity a n d fruitfulness. I t is completely crisscrossed b y the p r o b l e m w h i c h I have attempted to specify, i n w h i c h its profoundest u n i t y is made evident. A n d t h a t u n i t y is, precisely, the positive s p i r i t .
Philosophy of Positivist
i.
T H E FRENCH
Inspiration
THINKERS
Almost a l l nineteenth-century philosophy is essentially d o m i n a t e d by positivism a n d shows its influence i n one w a y o r another. T h e presence o f positivism is more v i t a l a n d constant i n France t h a n anywhere else. H e r e i t found a representative w h o c o u l d be called " o f f i c i a l " i n M a x i m i l i e n P a u l E m i l e Littré (1801-1881), w h o i n his exposition o f Comte's w o r k d i d n o t stress its most f r u i t f u l a n d o r i g i n a l aspects. H i p p o l y t e T a i n e (1828—1893) appears w i t h i n a n analogous philosophical m i l i e u ; T a i n e is t h e a u t h o r o f a w i t t y a n d superficial book o n c o n t e m p o r a r y French philosophy (Les philosophes classiques du XIX siècle en France), a long book called De l'intelligence a n d numerous studies i n h i s t o r y a n d art. Also i n this g r o u p is Ernest R e n a n (1823¬ 1892), a n O r i e n t a l i s t a n d specialist i n Semitic p h i l o l o g y a n d the history o f religions. O n e d i r e c t i o n o f French positivism was especially devoted t o sociology, f o l l o w i n g ( w i t h less insight) the p a t h entered u p o n b y C o m t e . A m o n g these sociologists are E m i l e D u r k h e i m ( 1858¬ 1917), whose p r i n c i p a l books are De la division du travail social ( T h e Division o f L a b o r i n Society) a n d Les règles de la méthode sociologique ( T h e Rules o f Sociological M e t h o d ) ; G a b r i e l T a r d e (1843-1904), author o f Les lois de l'imitation, La logique sociale a n d Les lois sociales; a n d L u c i e n L é v y - B r u h l (1857-1939), a dedicated specialist i n studies o f e t h n o g r a p h y a n d the sociology o f p r i m i t i v e peoples, whose m a j o r w o r k is La mentalité primitive. Close connection w i t h positivism is also shown b y t h e physician Claude B e r n a r d (1813-1878), a u t h o r o f Introduction à l'étude de la medecinae expérimentelle ( I n t r o d u c t i o n t o the e
355
Philosophy
of Positivist
Inspiration
S t u d y o f E x p e r i m e n t a l M e d i c i n e ) , w h o i n his later years became involved w i t h metaphysics. Even though, strictly speaking, they go b e y o n d positivism a n d p a r t i a l l y represent a reaction against i t , i t is necessary to m e n t i o n here a g r o u p of nineteenth-century French thinkers w h o were very i n f l u ential i n their day a n d some o f w h o m p r e p a r e d the way for the renewal o f philosophy achieved by Bergson. These m e n i n c l u d e : A l f r e d Fouillée (1838-1912), author o f L''évolutionisme des idées-forces; M a r i e Jean G u y a u (1854-1888), w h o h a d c e r t a i n affinities w i t h Nietzsche (La morale d'Épicure, L'irréligion de l'avenir, Esquisse d'une morale
sans obligation
ni sanction,
La morale
anglaise
contemporaine,
L'art
au
a n d whose m a n y ideas were penetrating, t h o u g h n o t systematic; A n t o i n e A u g u s t i n G o u r n o t (1801-1877), profound a n d original t h i n k e r n o t yet thoroughly studied ( Traité de l'enchaîne-
point
de vue sociologique)
a
ment
des idées fondamentales
fondements
dans
de nos connaissances
Matérialisme,
vitalisme,
les sciences
et dans
l'histoire;
et sur les caractères de la critique
rationalisme
; Considérations
sur
les
philosophique
Essai
;
sur la marche
des idées et
des événements dans les temps modernes) ; J e a n G a s p a r d Félix RavaissonM o l l i e n (1813-1900), a continuer o f s p i r i t u a l i s m a n d one o f the renewers o f Aristotelianism i n the nineteenth c e n t u r y (Essai sur la Métaphysique
d'Aristote,
Rapport
sur la philosophie
en France
au XIX
e
siècle,
; a n d Charles Bernard R e n o u v i e r ( 1815-1903), a neocriticist t h i n k e r o f great intellectual p r o d u c t i v i t y (Manuel de Testament
philosophie sophie
philosophique)
ancienne,
analytique
Manuel
de l'histoire,
2.
de philosophie
moderne,
Introduction
à la
philo-
Uchronie).
ENGLISH
PHILOSOPHY
U T I L I T A R I A N I S M . English positivism is especially concerned w i t h ethical problems, a n d also w i t h questions o f logic. U t i l i t a r i a n ethics, first developed b y J e r e m y B e n t h a m (1748-1832) a n d later most significantly by J o h n S t u a r t M i l l (1806-1873), finds that the goal o f o u r aspirations is pleasure, a n d that the good is t h a t w h i c h is useful a n d gives us pleasure. T h i s is n o t a n egoistic ethics, b u t is social i n character; w h a t i t seeks is the greatest happiness of the greatest number (Utilitarianism, On Liberty). T h e middle-class, capitalistic a n d i n d u s t r i a l era o f the mid-nineteenth c e n t u r y finds an extremely clear expression i n u t i l i t a r i a n ethics. M i l l also published an i m p o r t a n t w o r k o n l o g i c : A System
of Logic,
Ratiocinative
and
Inductive.
E V O L U T I O N I S M . Also related to positivism a n d u t i l i t a r i a n i s m are the English thinkers w h o develop the concept o f evolution, w h i c h was F r e n c h i n o r i g i n ( T u r g o t , Condorcet, L a m a r c k ) b u t was given its
The
Positivist
Era in
Germany
357
philosophic f o r m u l a t i o n b y Hegel. T h o u g h n o t himself a philosopher, the biologist Charles D a r w i n (1809—1882) was extremely i n f l u e n t i a l . His m a j o r w o r k , On the Origin of Species, was published i n 1859-60, b u t its ideas date f r o m the 1830's a n d the famous voyage a b o a r d the Beagle; this book contained a biological theory of e v o l u t i o n based on t h e p r i n c i p l e s o f the struggle for existence
a n d adaptation
to
environment,
w i t h the consequent natural selection o f the fittest. T h i s d o c t r i n e i n f l u enced every aspect o f nineteenth-century intellectual life a n d furnished M a r x w i t h a basis for his o w n d o c t r i n e . H e r b e r t Spencer (1820-1903), a n engineer w h o devoted h i m s e l f to philosophy, adopted the idea o f e v o l u t i o n i n a different f o r m ; he enjoyed a n e x t r a o r d i n a r y p o p u l a r i t y i n the second h a l f o f the century w h i c h was t h e n q u i c k l y lost. H i s extremely voluminous o u t p u t was largely published under the general title o f A System of Synthetic Philosophy. T h e various parts are First Principles (these are the u n k n o w a b l e a n d t h e k n o w a b l e ) , Principles ciples
and
of Sociology
Principles
of Biology,
Principles
of Psychology,
Prin-
H e also wrote, a m o n g other Man versus the State, a n expression
of Ethics.
works, The Study of Sociology a n d The of liberal political individualism.
A c c o r d i n g to Spencer, there takes place i n the universe a n unceasing r e d i s t r i b u t i o n o f m a t t e r a n d m o t i o n , w h i c h constitutes e v o l u t i o n w h e n the i n t e g r a t i o n o f m a t t e r a n d dissipation o f m o t i o n p r e v a i l , a n d dissolution w h e n the opposite occurs. T h i s transformation is accompanied b y a secondary one, t h a t o f the homogeneous i n t o the heterogeneous, a n d takes place t h r o u g h o u t the entire universe a n d a l l its domains, f r o m the nebulae to s p i r i t u a l a n d social life. T h e p r i n c i p a l cause o f e v o l u t i o n is the instability of the homogeneous; that which remains q u a n t i t a t i v e l y i n v a r i a b l e , as a substratum o f a l l the evolut i o n a r y processes, is a power w i t h o u t limits, w h i c h Spencer calls unknowable. T h i s doctrine, more interesting for its details (for instance, the frequently penetrating sociological observations) t h a n for its feeble metaphysics, d o m i n a t e d E u r o p e a n t h o u g h t for several decades a n d exerted a p r o f o u n d influence even o n Bergson. 3. T H E P O S I T I V I S T E R A I N G E R M A N Y A S noted earlier, G e r m a n positivism generally led to m a t e r i a l i s m a n d naturalism, w h i c h are devoid o f philosophic interest. F r i e d r i c h K a r l Christian L u d w i g Büchner, K a r l V o g t , J a c o b Moleschott, Ernst H e i n r i c h Haeckel a n d W i l h e l m O s t w a l d a r e , i n general, practitioners o f the n a t u r a l sciences, w i t h u n f o u n d e d philosophical pretensions, i m b u e d w i t h superficial atheism a n d m a t e r i a l i s m a n d , i n short, l a c k i n g i n true scientific spirit. MATERIALISM.
3J8
Philosophy
oj Positivist
Inspiration
A T T E M P T S T O S U P E R S E D E P O S I T I V I S M . O f greater interest are other, m o r e independent thinkers w h o b r i n g the p o p u l a r positivist views o f t h e i r day i n t o line w i t h the earlier G e r m a n philosophic t r a d i t i o n or a t t e m p t to replace those views. A m o n g these m e n are Gustav T h e o d o r Fechner (1801-1887), co-founder w i t h Ernst H e i n r i c h Weber o f psychophysics, a n d W i l h e l m W u n d t (1832-1920), a m a n of immense knowledge a n d i n d u s t r y a n d the most i m p o r t a n t w o r k e r i n experim e n t a l psychology a n d the so-called ethnopsychology (Völkerpsychologie). R u d o l f H e r m a n n Lotze (1817-1881), influenced b y L e i b n i z and the idealists, a n d D i l t h e y ' s predecessor i n the B e r l i n professorship, i n i t i a t e d a reaction against n a t u r a l i s m a n d w o r k e d o n the problems o f history a n d esthetics (Mikrokosmos, System der Philosophie). Friedrich A d o l f T r e n d e l e n b u r g (1802-1872), Dilthey's teacher, was, along w i t h Ravaisson, G r a t r y a n d Brentano, the m a n w h o r e i n t r o d u c e d A r i s t o telianism to his contemporaries (Elementa logices Aristotelicae, Logische Untersuchungen). Gustav Teichmüller (1832-1888), a professor at D o r p a t (Estonia) w h o was influential i n Russia, was a perspicacious and learned t h i n k e r w h o w r o t e i m p o r t a n t studies of Greek philosophy (Aristotelische
Forschungen,
Studien
zur Geschichte
der Begriffe,
Neue
Studien
a n d a n i m p o r t a n t b o o k o f metaphysics, i n w h i c h he makes a b r o a d use o f the concept o f " p e r s p e c t i v e " : Die zur
Geschichte
wirkliche
der Begriffe)
und die scheinbare
Welt:
Neue
Grundlegung
der Metaphysik
(The
R e a l a n d the A p p a r e n t W o r l d : N e w F o u n d a t i o n o f Metaphysics). T h i s author is the source o f the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f t r u t h i n the sense o f the Greek
aXqOeta.
P a r t i c u l a r l y i n f l u e n t i a l i n their day were c e r t a i n philosophers whose w o r k r a p i d l y lost its p o p u l a r i t y : E d u a r d v o n H a r t m a n n (1842-1906), w h o was simultaneously inspired by G e r m a n idealism a n d the biological sciences, a n d whose major w o r k is the Philosophie des Unbewussten (Philosophy of the Unconscious); H a n s V a i h i n g e r (1852¬ 1933) (Die Philosophie des Als Ob), close to p r a g m a t i s m , w h o f o r m u l a t e d a philosophy o f the "as i f " ( a n allusion to K a n t ' s regulative I d e a s ) ; and lastly the adherents o f the so-called Empiriokritizismus—-Richard Avenarius (1843-1896): Kritik der reinen Erfahrung ( C r i t i q u e o f Pure Experience) a n d Ernst M a c h (1838-1916): Analyse der Empfindungen (Analysis of Sensations). T h e titles of their works are clearly i n d i c a t i v e o f the content. N E O - K A N T I A N I S M . I n the second h a l f of the c e n t u r y G e r m a n y is the scene o f a philosophic m o v e m e n t w h i c h attempts to supersede positiv i s m , although i t is i n fact conditioned b y its spirit. These thinkers saw the salvation o f philosophy i n the r e t u r n to K a n t , a n d i n i t i a t e d a r e v i v a l of K a n t i a n i s m . W e have already seen, w h e n s t u d y i n g K a n t ,
The
Positivist
Era
in Germany
3J9
the v i e w p o i n t f r o m w h i c h the Neo-Kantians consider h i m . T h e first impulse i n this direction came f r o m the book b y O t t o L i e b m a n n (1840-1912) e n t i t l e d Kant und die Epigonen (1865), each chapter of w h i c h c o n c l u d e d : " T h e r e f o r e , i t is necessary to r e t u r n to K a n t . " A n o t h e r step i n the same d i r e c t i o n is m a r k e d b y F r i e d r i c h A l b e r t Lange (1828-1875), a u t h o r of a famous History of Materialism. B u t the chief representatives o f the N e o - K a n t i a n movement are the thinkers of the Marburg school: H e r m a n n C o h e n (1842-1918), the most i m p o r t a n t of a l l , w h o was the teacher o f the y o u n g O r t e g a (System der Philosophie: Logik der reinen Erkenntnis [System o f Philosophy: Logic o f Pure K n o w l e d g e ] , Ethik des reinen Willens [Ethics o f Pure W i l l ] , Ästhetik des reinen Gefühls [Esthetics o f Pure F e e l i n g ] ) ; Paul N a t o r p (1854-1924), w h o f o r m u l a t e d a N e o - K a n t i a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f Platonism and m a d e special studies of psychological a n d pedagogical problems (Piatos Ideenlehre, Kant und die Marburger Schule); and recently, Ernst Cassirer (1874-1945), a professor i n the U n i t e d States i n his last years, w h o studied the p r o b l e m of knowledge (Das Erkenntnisproblem in der Philosophie und Wissenschaft der neueren Zeit [ T h e P r o b l e m of K n o w l edge], Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff [Substance a n d F u n c t i o n ] , Philosophie der symbolischen Formen [Philosophy o f Symbolic F o r m s ] , Phänomenologie der Erkenntnis [Phenomenology o f K n o w l e d g e ] , Descartes, Leibniz' System). H e also wrote Philosophy of the Enlightenment and Philosophical
Anthropology.
A n o t h e r i m p o r t a n t N e o - K a n t i a n g r o u p is the so-called Baden school, whose most i m p o r t a n t members are W i l h e l m W i n d e l b a n d (1848¬ 1915), a great h i s t o r i a n o f philosophy (Einleitung in die Philosophie, Lehrbuch der Geschichte der Philosophie, Präludien) a n d H e i n r i c h R i c k e r t (1863-1936), devoted to studies o f m e t h o d o l o g y a n d epistemology (Die
Grenzen
der naturwissenschaftlichen
und Naturwissenschaft,
Philosophie
des
Begriffsbildung, Lebens).
Kulturwissenschaft
The Discovery
of Life
W e n o w begin to consider the thinkers o f the last t h i r d o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y . T h i s period, perhaps more clearly t h a n a n y other, reveals the m e a n i n g o f the history o f philosophy. I w i l l speak o f philosophers w h o were, i n general, somewhat m a r g i n a l to the central c u r r e n t o f t h e i r time. W e have seen d o w n w h a t f u t i l e paths the thinkers after C o m t e were led b y p o s i t i v i s m ; therefore, w e w i l l f i n d authentic philosophy only i n the thinkers w h o are at variance w i t h the tenor o f t h e i r age, i n those thinkers w h o go beyond the bounds o f the p r e v a i l i n g schools o f philosophy. T h i s is true to such a n extent t h a t these m e n either do n o t seem to be philosophers or else are misunderstood. H o w e v e r , the foregoing statement must be f o l l o w e d b y the observation t h a t such an i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the t h o u g h t o f the end o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y is possible o n l y i n the t w e n t i e t h c e n t u r y . S t r i c t l y speaking, this t h o u g h t came to be a u t h e n t i c a n d f r u i t f u l because i t served as a stimulus a n d precedent for present-day metaphysics; i t acquires value o n l y i n the l i g h t o f m o d e r n thought. W e m u s t collect elements w h i c h the last century w o u l d have considered most cont e m p t i b l e a n d w h i c h achieve f u l l a c t u a l i t y o n l y outside themselves, to w i t , i n the philosophy o f recent years. T h e philosophers I refer to were n o t , o f course, systematic thinkers. I n general, they h a d b r i l l i a n t i n t u i t i o n s , conjectures, visions; however, a l t h o u g h a l l this amounts to a great deal, i t does n o t , strictly speaking, constitute philosophy. N a t u r a l l y , philosophy needs concepts, b u t i t also requires a system. T h i s fragmentary philosophy achieves its r e a l i t y — H e g e l w o u l d say its truth—in a later phase o f philosophy, a n d i n t h a t 360
Kierkegaard
l a t e r stage i t constitutes a first step t o w a r d a n authentic metaphysics. i.
KIERKEGAARD
Soren K i e r k e g a a r d ( 1 8 1 3 - 1 8 5 5 ) was a D a n i s h t h i n k e r whose i n f l u ence o n philosophy, a l t h o u g h h a r d l y visible, has been real a n d lasting. H e l i v e d i n Copenhagen, t o r m e n t e d by his religious a n d philosophical problems a n d influenced, i n the negative sense o f complete opposition to i t , b y G e r m a n i d e a l i s m . A m o n g Kierkegaard's works we f i n d The Gospel
the
ofSuffering,
Concluding
Either/
Unscientific
Or (Enten-Eller), Postscript,
the Philosophical
Fragments
and
one o f his most i m p o r t a n t writings.
L i k e other thinkers o f his t i m e , K i e r k e g a a r d appeals t o C h r i s t i a n i t y — i n his case, t h r o u g h Protestant t h e o l o g y — i n o r d e r t o understand man's being. H e dwells i n p a r t i c u l a r o n the concept o f suffering, w h i c h he relates to o r i g i n a l sin a n d i n w h i c h m a n feels h i m s e l f to be alone. T h i s leads K i e r k e g a a r d to f o r m u l a t e an anthropology shaped by the idea o f existence; this idea is o f v e r y great interest a n d o f considerable p h i l o sophical p r o d u c t i v i t y , i n spite o f its unsystematic character a n d o f the dangerous i r r a t i o n a l i s m w h i c h has made itself felt i n certain of Kierkegaard's followers. K i e r k e g a a r d rejects t h e " e t e r n a l i z a t i o n " t h a t Hegelianism i n t r o d u c e d i n t o philosophy because t h a t abstract a n d sub specie aeternitatis t h o u g h t does n o t take i n t o account existence, t h a t is, the very mode of man's being—every man's, even t h a t o f the abstract t h i n k e r himself. M a n is something t h a t is concrete, t e m p o r a l , i n the process o f b e c o m i n g ; something w h i c h partakes o f this m o d e o f being t h a t we c a l l existence because he is a m i x t u r e of w h a t is t e m p o r a l a n d eternal; something t h a t is submerged i n suffering. M o t i o n , w h i c h sub specie aeternitatis t h o u g h t denies, is essential to existence. A c t i n g o n religious suppositions, K i e r k e g a a r d deals w i t h h u m a n r e a l i t y i n its strictly i n d i v i d u a l a n d personal f o r m , a n d n o t i n its abstract f o r m , as m a n i n general. H e speaks a b o u t my existence i n a l l its concrete a n d irreplacea b l e personal i d e n t i t y . H o w e v e r , this positive aspect o f his t h o u g h t is obscured by his i r r a t i o n a l i s m . K i e r k e g a a r d believes t h a t we cannot conceive of existence a n d m o t i o n , because w h e n w e t r y t o conceive of these things they become i m m o v a b l e , eternal a n d , therefore, abolished. B u t , since he w h o thinks, exists, existence a n d t h o u g h t are posited at the same t i m e , a n d existence is the serious topic for philosophy. K i e r k e g a a r d influenced U n a m u n o considerably, a n d Heidegger f o u n d m u c h o f value i n his t h o u g h t . T h u s the v i t a l core o f K i e r k e gaard's metaphysics appears i n systematic a n d m a t u r e f o r m i n the v e r y center of present-day philosophy.
36z
The
Discovery
2.
of
Life
NIETZSCHE
L I F E A N D W O R K S . F r i e d r i c h Nietzsche was b o r n i n 1844. H e studied classical p h i l o l o g y i n B o n n a n d L e i p z i g a n d i n 1869, w h e n he was twenty-five years o l d , was n a m e d professor o f t h a t discipline at Basel. I n 1879 he h a d to give u p his position because of i l l h e a l t h , a n d after t h a t he s u p p o r t e d himself i n d e p e n d e n t l y as a w r i t e r . H e w e n t insane i n 1889 a n d i n 1900, at the close o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y , d i e d c o m pletely estranged f r o m the w o r l d . Nietzsche is a n extremely c o m p l e x personality; he possessed great artistic t a l e n t a n d is one of the best of the m o d e r n G e r m a n w r i t e r s . H i s style, i n prose as w e l l as i n verse, is passionate, inspired a n d o f great l i t e r a r y beauty. H i s knowledge of a n d interest i n Greek c u l t u r e play a large role i n his philosophy. H o w e v e r , the central theme o f his t h o u g h t is m a n , h u m a n life, a n d he is completely preoccupied w i t h history a n d ethics. Schopenhauer a n d R i c h a r d W a g n e r influenced h i m greatly, and perhaps this accentuated his l i t e r a r y a n d artistic value a n d broadened his influence, w h i c h has been so extensive as to be d e t r i m e n t a l to his philosophy a n d even to preclude a fair e v a l u a t i o n of his w o r k . I n d u b i t a b l y , there is i n Nietzsche m u c h more t h a n w h a t the dilettantism w h i c h took possession of his w o r k and personality at the end of the last c e n t u r y and the b e g i n n i n g o f this c e n t u r y has been accustomed to show us. One of the tasks of present-day philosophy is to b r i n g to l i g h t the metaphysical content o f F r i e d r i c h Nietzsche's thought.
Nietzsche's p r i n c i p a l works are Die T r a g e d y ) , Unzeitgemdsse Betrachtungen Menschlich.es,
(Dawn),
Allzumenschliches
der Tragodie (The Birth of ( I n o p p o r t u n e Considerations),
Geburt
( H u m a n , A l l Too
Human),
Morgenrote
( T h u s Spake Z a r a t h u s t r a ) , Jenseits von Gut und Bose (Beyond G o o d a n d E v i l ) , Z Genealogie der Moral ( O n the Genealogy of M o r a l i t y ) , Der Wille zur Macht ( T h e W i l l to P o w e r ) . T h e last book was published after his death under a title w h i c h the a u t h o r d i d n o t give i t a n d i n a f o r m w h i c h dilutes its meaning. R e c e n t w o r k b y K a r l Schlechta has revealed h o w Nietzsche's works were m a n i p u l a t e d i n order to give t h e m a racist significance a n d to relate t h e m to the " t o t a l i t a r i a n i s m " of our century. Also
sprach
%arathustra
ur
THE
PRINCIPLE OF DIONYSUS A N D T H E PRINCIPLE OF A P O L L O .
An
i n t e r p r e t a t i o n w h i c h Nietzsche makes of Greek t h o u g h t comes to have great i m p o r t a n c e i n his philosophy. H e distinguishes t w o principles: the p r i n c i p l e o f A p o l l o a n d the p r i n c i p l e o f Dionysus. A p o l l o is the s y m b o l o f serenity, clarity, m o d e r a t i o n , r a t i o n a l i s m ; he is the Greek classical image. O n the other h a n d , Dionysus is the symbol of impulsive-
Nietzsche
363
ness, excess, u n c o n t r o l l a b i l i t y , the affirmation o f life, eroticism, a n d o r g y as a c u l m i n a t i o n o f the l o n g i n g to live, to say Yes! to life i n spite of a l l its sorrows. Schopenhauer's influence is t u r n e d inside o u t ; Nietzsche, instead o f n e g a t i n g the w i l l to live, places t h a t w i l l at the center o f his thought. T H E E T E R N A L R E T U R N . T O a certain extent Nietzsche derives f r o m the positivism of the age; he denies that metaphysics is possible; f u r t h e r m o r e , he assumes a loss o f f a i t h i n G o d a n d i n the i m m o r t a l i t y o f the soul. However, the life w h i c h he affirms a n d w h i c h forever wishes to live longer, w h i c h asks for an eternity o f happiness, returns t i m e a n d again. Nietzsche makes use o f a n idea t h a t derives f r o m H e r a c l i t u s i n his n o t i o n o f the " eternal r e t u r n " (ewige Wiederkunft) of the things. After a l l possible combinations o f the elements of the w o r l d have been realized, there is a n i n t e r v a l of a previously u n d e t e r m i n e d d u r a t i o n , a n d then the cycle begins again, a n d so o n , indefinitely. E v e r y t h i n g that happens i n the w o r l d repeats itself i n i d e n t i c a l fashion t i m e a n d again. E v e r y t h i n g returns eternally, i n c l u d i n g everything t h a t is e v i l , miserable a n d v i l e . B u t m e n can transform the w o r l d a n d themselves b y means o f a transmutation of all values (Umwertung alter Werte), a n d can progress t o w a r d becoming supermen. T h u s Nietzsche's a f f i r m a t i o n of life is not l i m i t e d to one's accepting a n d w i s h i n g for life o n l y once, b u t an i n f i n i t e n u m b e r o f times. THE S U P E R M A N . Nietzsche is opposed to a l l the equalitarian, h u m a n i t a r i a n and democratic trends o f his age. H e is a c h a m p i o n of m i g h t y personalities. T h e highest good is life itself, w h i c h culminates i n the will to power. M a n m u s t go beyond himself a n d become somet h i n g superior to m a n , j u s t as m a n is superior to the m o n k e y : this is the theory o f the superman. Nietzsche models his superman o n unscrupulous a n d i m m o r a l Renaissance personalities w h o nevertheless h a d g i g a n t i c capacities for life a n d w h o were strong, i m p u l s i v e a n d energetic. T h e concept o f the superman leads Nietzsche to a new idea o f morality. T H E M O R A L I T Y O F M A S T E R S A N D T H E M O R A L I T Y O F S L A V E S . Nietzsche is p a r t i c u l a r l y hostile to the K a n t i a n ethics o f d u t y , a n d also to u t i l i t a r i a n ethics a n d C h r i s t i a n m o r a l i t y as w e l l . H e values only the strong, healthy, impulsive life w h i c h has the w i l l to d o m i n a t e . T h i s represents good, whereas weakness, sickness a n d f a i l u r e are evil. Compassion is the greatest e v i l . T h u s Nietzsche distinguishes t w o types o f m o r a l i t y . T h e m o r a l i t y o f the masters is t h a t o f powerful i n d i v i d u a l s o f superior v i t a l i t y ; this m o r a l i t y applies o n l y to these superior beings a n d is based o n exigency and o n the a f f i r m a t i o n o f the v i t a l impulses. I n contrast, the m o r a l i t y of the slaves is t h a t o f weak a n d
The
Discovery
of
Life
miserable people, of degenerates; i t is governed b y lack o f confidence i n life a n d respect for compassion, h u m i l i t y , patience, a n d the like. N i e t z s c h e says that i t is a m o r a l i t y o f resentment, w h i c h opposes everyt h i n g t h a t is superior a n d w h i c h therefore affirms every f o r m o f e q u a l i t a r i a n i s m . Nietzsche a t t r i b u t e s this character o f resentment to C h r i s t i a n m o r a l i t y ; however, this is an o u t r i g h t error o n his p a r t , arising f r o m his lack o f u n d e r s t a n d i n g of the m e a n i n g o f C h r i s t i a n i t y . Scheler has p r o v e d the absolute distance between C h r i s t i a n i t y a n d every f o r m o f resentment (see M a x Scheler: Ressentiment). Because o f his h i g h regard for energy a n d p o w e r , Nietzsche figures a m o n g the thinkers w h o have most exalted t h e value o f w a r ; w a r seems to h i m to be a n o p p o r t u n i t y for the d e v e l o p m e n t of superior values, the spirit o f sacrifice, bravery, n o b i l i t y , a n d so o n . Nietzsche rejects t h e m i d d l e class nineteenth-century idea o f m a n as an industrious a n d useful b e i n g a n d affirms the idea o f the k n i g h t , the courageous a n d powerful m a n w h o vigorously accepts life. A l l these ideas have a p o i n t i n c o m m o n w i t h Christianity, a l t h o u g h Nietzsche was n o t a b l e to see i t . T h e most i m p o r t a n t elements o f Nietzsche's p h i l o s o p h y are his idea o f life a n d his awareness o f the existence o f v i t a l values, t h a t is, values w h i c h p e r t a i n specifically to human life. T h e expression vital values contains t w o o f the ideas w h i c h come to dominate later philosophy. Nietzsche is a source of'the philosophy of values a n d of'the philosophy oflife.
The Return
to Traditional
Metaphysics
A t the same t i m e t h a t the theme o f life appears i n the philosophy o f the n i n e t e e n t h century, a n d perhaps even a few years before this happens, the content o f p h i l o s o p h y changes and p h i l o s o p h y once again approaches the previous t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics w h i c h h a d been i n t e r r u p t e d — a t least so i t seemed—by positivism. T h i s is not j u s t a r e t u r n t o the most i m m e d i a t e f o r m o f t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysics, the G e r m a n idealist t r a d i t i o n , b u t r a t h e r a r e t u r n to the traditions o f r a t i o n a l i s m , Scholasticism a n d , i n p a r t i c u l a r , Greek philosophy. Because o f this, philosophy regains its f u l l d i g n i t y a n d the commencem e n t o f a new stage o f philosophical p r o d u c t i v i t y becomes possible. T h i s development occurs precisely at the b e g i n n i n g o f the present century. I t is n o t mere coincidence t h a t the thinkers o f this tendency were Catholics a n d , i n fact, for the most p a r t priests. T h e C h u r c h , for p r i m a r i l y theological reasons, has kept close to the great metaphysical systems. F o r a long t i m e — w e m a y say since Suarez—Scholasticism has been practically a dead t r a d i t i o n ; to whatever extent i t has concerned itself w i t h philosophic questions, i t has done so i n a " scholastic " spirit i n t h e n a r r o w sense o f the w o r d , as a mere exegesis o f medieval t h o u g h t a n d " r e f u t a t i o n o f m o d e r n e r r o r s . " T h u s i t has a l l too often o v e r l o o k e d the entire history o f m o d e r n philosophy as i f i t d i d not exist, as i f i t were n o t h i n g b u t a mere error or w h i m w h i c h had i n c o m p r e h e n s i b l y a p p r o p r i a t e d to itself the p o p u l a r i t y once enjoyed b y the o n l y true philosophy, t h a t o f the M i d d l e Ages, a n d more specifically T h o m i s m . T h i s conception is absolutely inadmissible, for i t J6j
¿66
The
Return
to
Traditional
Metaphysics
has been completely superseded as often as thinkers w i t h i n the Scholastic t r a d i t i o n have h a d some knowledge o f m o d e r n philosophy a n d o f medieval Scholasticism itself. T h e n i t has been seen t h a t the l i v i n g philosophical c o n t i n u a t i o n o f Scholasticism is to be f o u n d n o t so m u c h i n the presumptive Neo-Scholastics as i n m o d e r n philosophy. Descartes a n d L e i b n i z are descended f r o m St. A u g u s t i n e , St. A n s e l m , St. T h o m a s , Duns Scotus, O c c a m and E c k h a r t , as anyone even m o d e r a t e l y acquainted w i t h t h e m knows very w e l l ; as, for example, F a t h e r G r a t r y so very fully k n e w . T h u s , Catholic philosophers h a d n o t lost contact w i t h metaphysics. T h r o u g h o u t the nineteenth c e n t u r y , there is a series o f attempts to restore m a t u r i t y to p h i l o s o p h y ; this movement c u l m i n a t e s i n Bren¬ t a n o . A t t h a t m o m e n t the p h i l o s o p h y o f our age is set i n m o t i o n .
i.
T H E FIRST
ATTEMPTS
B O L Z A N O . T h e A u s t r i a n philosopher B e r n h a r d Bolzano ( i 7 8 1 — 1848) l i v e d i n the first h a l f o f the nineteenth c e n t u r y . H e was a C a t h o l i c priest, professor o f the philosophy o f r e l i g i o n at Prague f r o m 1805 to 1820, i n w h i c h year he was compelled to leave his post. I n 1837 he p u b l i s h e d his major w o r k , Wissenschqftslehre ( T h e o r y o f Science); as far as the " e l e m e n t a r y p a r t " o f logic is concerned, this b o o k "leaves far b e h i n d everything offered b y universal l i t e r a t u r e i n the w a y o f systematic essays o n l o g i c , " according to the o p i n i o n o f E d m u n d Husserl, w h o considered Bolzano " o n e of the greatest logicians o f all t i m e . " Bolzano's views were m u c h closer to those o f L e i b n i z t h a n to those o f the G e r m a n idealists w h o were his contemporaries; he b r o u g h t a m a t h e m a t i c a l spirit to the study o f logic and the p r o b l e m o f k n o w l edge. I n m a n y ways Bolzano a n t i c i p a t e d ideas w h i c h have proved to be o f i m p o r t a n c e for symbolic a n d m a t h e m a t i c a l l o g i c ; his theory a f f i r m i n g the character of being as independent o f the consciousness o f s p i r i t u a l ideal contents deeply influenced Husserl's phenomenology, w h i c h , i n one o f its decisive aspects, is a new c h a m p i o n i n g o f ideal objects. Bolzano also w r o t e the Paradoxien des Unendlichen (Paradoxes o f the I n f i n i t e ) . R O S M I N I A N D G I O B E R T I . T h e t w o I t a l i a n philosophers A n t o n i o R o s m i n i - S e r b a t i (1797-1855) a n d Vincenzo G i o b e r t i (1801-1852), s t a r t i n g o u t f r o m very s i m i l a r positions, also c o n t r i b u t e d to the reinstatement o f metaphysics i n the m i d - n i n e t e e n t h c e n t u r y . B o t h were Catholic priests w h o took a n active p a r t i n p u b l i c life a n d the p o l i t i c a l movement i n b e h a l f o f I t a l i a n u n i t y . R o s m i n i was Sardinia's ambassador to the Pope, G i o b e r t i its premier. R o s m i n i w r o t e Nuovo
The
First
Attempts
3°7
( N e w Essay o n the O r i g i n o f Ideas), Principii (Principles o f M o r a l Science), Teosojia (Theosophy) a n d the Saggio storico-critico sulle catégorie e la dialettica (Historical and C r i t i c a l Essay o n the Categories a n d Dialectic). Gioberti's p r i n c i p a l works are Introduzione alio studio dellafilosofia ( I n t r o d u c t i o n to the Study o f P h i l o s o p h y ) , Degli errori filosofici di Rosmini ( O n Rosmini's Philosophical E r r o r s ) , Protologia, Del buono ( O n the G o o d ) , Del bello ( O n the B e a u t i f u l ) a n d Teorica del sovrannaturale (Theory o f the S u p e r n a t u r a l ) . saggio
suW origine
delta scienza
delle idee
morale
R o s m i n i seeks the i n t u i t i o n o f a " f i r s t t r u t h " w h i c h is the standard for a l l other truths, a n i n t e l l i g i b l e f o r m whose u n i o n w i t h the intelligence there results the intelligence itself; this is b e i n g as such, the p r i m a r y object o f the intelligence. There is a very close connection between these views a n d those o f M a l e b r a n c h e a n d , consequently, the idea o f the vision o f the things i n G o d . Analogously, i n Gioberti's t h o u g h t being is a p r i o r i i n character; therefore, the h u m a n intellect possesses essentially a direct knowledge o f G o d , w i t h o u t w h i c h i t cannot k n o w a n y t h i n g . S o m e t h i n g divine appears directly to the m i n d i n the created t h i n g s ; i t is thus n o t necessary to prove the existence o f G o d . " T h e great concept o f the D e i t y , " G i o b e r t i says, " h a s h e l d u p to n o w a more o r less secondary place i n philosophic doctrines, even i n those w h i c h , i n appearance or i n r e a l i t y , are the most r e l i g i o u s . . . . T h e speculative sciences have u p to n o w m o r e or less p a r t a k e n o f a t h e i s m . " I n o p p o s i t i o n to this, G i o b e r t i ' s idealformula declares t h a t the ontological p r i n c i p l e (God) is the l o g i c a l a n d ontological p r i n c i p l e at the same t i m e . " A l l of existence depends u p o n the E n t i t y , a n d a l l knowledge depends u p o n the i n t u i t i o n o f H i m . . . . T h e concept o f the E n t i t y is present i n a l l our t h o u g h t . " One cannot begin philosophy w i t h m a n , b u t w i t h G o d Himself, w h o posits H i s o w n Self ; m a n can recognize H i s existence, b u t c a n n o t demonstrate i t , because the so-called proofs o f the existence o f G o d presuppose " a p r i o r a n d o r i g i n a l intuition. " These I t a l i a n thinkers do violence to reality w h e n they overlook the fact t h a t G o d does n o t manifest H i m s e l f directly, b u t is h i d d e n and dwells i n a n inaccessible light; therefore, our imperfect knowledge o f H i m is the true state o f the case, a n d an effort is needed to show His existence, w h i c h can be k n o w n intellectually o n l y b y means o f the created things, per ea quae facta sunt, as St. Paul says. " N o one has ever seen G o d . " T h e ontologist error was condemned b y the C h u r c h i n 1861 a n d 1887; i t was used to a certain extent b y the complex heterodox movement k n o w n as modernism, w h i c h was defined a n d c o n d e m n e d b y the C h u r c h i n the first years o f the present century.
3
68
The
Return
to Traditional
2.
Metaphysics
GRATRY
O f greater interest a n d scope is the philosophy o f F a t h e r G r a t r y . Auguste Joseph Alphonse G r a t r y was b o r n at L i l l e i n F r a n c e i n i805 a n d d i e d i n 1872. H e s t u d i e d at the École Polytechnique a n d was o r d a i n e d as a priest ; he was a professor at Strasbourg a n d Paris, a n d i n 1852 founded the C o n g r e g a t i o n o f the O r a t o r y o f the I m m a c u l a t e C o n c e p t i o n , a renewal o f the O r a t o r y ofJesus to w h i c h M a l e b r a n c h e belonged. F r o m 1863 o n he was professor o f m o r a l theology at the Sorbonne. Gratry's most i m p o r t a n t works are La connaissance de l'âme ( T h e K n o w l e d g e of the S o u l ) , Logique, La morale et la loi de l'histoire ( M o r a l i t y a n d the L a w o f H i s t o r y ) and especially La connaissance de Dieu ( T h e K n o w l e d g e o f G o d ) , t h e best philosophical b o o k a b o u t G o d w r i t t e n i n a century. F o r m a n y years G r a t r y has been very l i t t l e k n o w n a n d almost f o r g o t t e n , especially as a, philosopher. His w o r k , w h i c h is essentially metaphysical and i n w h i c h t h e theme of G o d is c e n t r a l , c o u l d n o t be u n d e r s t o o d , strictly speaking, w i t h i n the positivist e n v i r o n m e n t o f his d a y ; his very qualities have been the chief cause o f his obscurity. B u t for precisely this reason he is o f the greatest interest t o us t o d a y . G r a t r y is clearly aware t h a t the history o f philosophy has f o l l o w e d a single course, b e g i n n i n g i n Greece a n d c o m i n g d o w n to o u r o w n d a y ; thus, i n o r d e r to e x p o u n d his personal philosophy, he begins b y showing the i n t e r n a l evolution o f the problems of philosophy f r o m Plato to r a t i o n a l i s m . Secondly, he interprets metaphysics as t h e essential element o f philosophy, i n o p p o s i t i o n to the o p i n i o n c u r r e n t i n his t i m e , a n d takes a decisive step f o r w a r d along the p a t h o f r e s t o r i n g metaphysics. H e believes, above a l l , t h a t the p r o b l e m o f metaphysics is f o r m u l a t e d as the c o n t i n u a t i o n o f t w o great questions, w h i c h are the ones t h a t philosophy is c o m p e l l e d to cope w i t h t o d a y : t h a t of the person a n d t h a t of G o d . L a s t l y , i n his Logic he expounds, as the p r i n c i p a l procedure o f reason, a p r o f o u n d theory o f i n d u c t i o n or dialectic w h i c h is very closely related to the p h e n o m e n o l o g i c a l doctrines o f i n t u i t i o n a n d the k n o w l e d g e of essences. These are the central themes o f Gratry's t h o u g h t . I f there is a knowledge o f G o d , i t is based o n a n essential aspect o f m a n , j u s t as man's knowledge o f the things is based o n his contact w i t h t h e m , w i t h their reality. T h e knowledge of G o d , like a l l knowledge, is s o m e t h i n g derived f r o m a n o t h e r p r i m a r y ontological aspect, w h i c h is t h e basis for its possibility. T h e p r o b l e m of G o d involves m a n ; since m a n , essentially, is endowed w i t h a body a n d exists i n a w o r l d , the
Gratry
369
ontology o f m a n takes us back i n t u r n to the ontology o f the w o r l d i n w h i c h m a n finds himself. T h u s , a l l o f metaphysics is s u m m e d u p i n the problem of God. M a n , according to G r a t r y , has three faculties: the p r i m a r y faculty o f sense a n d two derived ones, intelligence a n d w i l l . Sense is the deepl y i n g p a r t o f the person. T h i s sense is threefold: external sense, by means o f w h i c h I sense the r e a l i t y o f m y body a n d o f the w o r l d ; i n t e r n a l sense, b y w h i c h I sense myself and my fellow men; a n d divine sense, b y w h i c h I find G o d i n the depth o f m y soul, w h i c h is the image o f H i m . T h i s divine sense defines man's p r i m a r y relationship w i t h God, w h i c h is prior to all knowledge and vision; i t is a fundamental relationship because the h u m a n e n t i t y has its basis and its r o o t i n G o d . T h e soul finds i n its o w n depths a contact w i t h the D e i t y , a n d therein resides its force,
which
causes it to be.
G o d is the root o f m a n , w h o depends upon H i m . G o d makes m a n live a n d sustains h i m . Therefore, H e is the basis o f h u m a n l i f e ; m a n exists a n d lives u p o n his root, supporting himself o n G o d . T h i s is the necessary presupposition o f a l l knowledge o f the D e i t y , a n d i t is f r o m this viewp o i n t t h a t G r a t r y interprets atheism. T h e atheist is a m a n w h o is d e v o i d o f the divine sense; thus, he is insensate (foolish), de-ment-ed. T h e causes o f this estrangement f r o m G o d are sensuality a n d p r i d e ; t h r o u g h sensuality, m a n makes the things the center o f his existence a n d turns away f r o m G o d , w h i l e pride makes m a n consider himself as his o w n basis. T h e n the d i v i n e sense is extinguished a n d the heart is d a r k e n e d , at the same t i m e t h a t the i m a g i n a t i o n becomes v a i n , as St. P a u l says. Because the soul is r o o t e d i n G o d , i t is able to be u p r o o t e d ; i t becomes empty, r e m a i n i n g completely w i t h o u t substance a n d consistency. T h u s the p o i n t o f o r i g i n o f the knowledge of G o d is the d i v i n e sense, the mysterious a n d obscure contact w i t h G o d i n the d e p t h o f the person, w h i c h is not knowledge b u t only a p r i o r c o n d i t i o n for the possibility o f knowledge. W h e n m a n conquers his sensuality a n d pride, he recognizes his insufficiency a n d can raise himself t o G o d through similarity a n d , especially, t h r o u g h contrast. G r a t r y distinguishes between t w o procedures o f reason: one based on i d e n t i t y , w h i c h is the syllogism or deduction, a n d the other based o n the p r i n c i p l e o f transcendence, w h i c h is i n d u c t i o n or dialectic. T h i s is the intellectual path b y w h i c h one reaches G o d . T h e result of i n d u c t i o n is n o t contained i n the s t a r t i n g p o i n t , b u t goes b e y o n d i t ; the present d a t u m refers us to another one, w h i c h is not i n c l u d e d i n the o r i g i n a l p o i n t ; i n order to raise ourselves to the new p o i n t we need a n inventive impulse (elan), w h i c h not everyone possesses. T h e things induce us to raise ourselves to G o d ;
jyo
The Return
to Traditional
Metaphysics
this is t h e f u n d a m e n t a l a n d p r i m a r y m e a n i n g o f i n d u c t i o n , w h i c h is a t o t a l m o v e m e n t o f the soul. F a t h e r G r a t r y i n t u i t e d t h a t , o n the one h a n d , the e x t e r n a l w o r l d is i n v o l v e d i n the deep-lying r e a l i t y o f m a n , a n d that, o n t h e other, m a n , w h o is n o t self-sufficient, remains basically insufficient even w h e n taken together w i t h the w o r l d , because his basis i n G o d is s t i l l l a c k i n g . W h e n he enters w i t h i n his o w n depths, m a n finds, together w i t h contingency, the s u p p o r t w h i c h makes h i m be a n d live, w h i c h sustains h i m ; this f o u n d a t i o n is not the world, w h i c h touches us only superficially, b u t G o d , o n w h o m o u r root rests. T h i s shows Gratry's great significance for present-day philosophy, since his metaphysics leads us t o the latest questions t h a t w e have posed a n d indicates a sure m e t h o d b y w h i c h w e m a y deal w i t h t h e m . * * A detailed study of Gratry's thought and his place in the history of philosophy will be found in my book La Filosofía del Padre Gratry [Ob ras, I V ] .
CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY
Brentano
i.
BRENTANO'S
POSITION I N T H E HISTORY
OF
PHILOSOPHY
L I F E A N D W O R K S . T h e A u s t r i a n thinker Franz Brentano is extremely i m p o r t a n t . H e was b o r n i n M a r i e n b e r g i n 1838 a n d d i e d i n Z u r i c h i n 1917. H e was a Catholic priest a n d a professor i n V i e n n a , b u t later he broke w i t h the C h u r c h — w i t h o u t abandoning his p r o f o u n d l y Catholic c o n v i c t i o n s — a n d gave u p his professorship. Brentano w r o t e b u t little, a n d the greater p a r t o f his w r i t i n g s was not published u n t i l after his death. Nevertheless, Brentano attracted unusually effective pupils, a n d his influence, t h o u g h q u i e t a n d inconspicuous, has been immense. Present-day philosophy begins w i t h h i m ; i f not its exclusive founder, he is still a major one. B r e n t a n o w r o t e short books, almost pamphlets, o f i n c o m p a r a b l e density a n d accuracy; and each one has b r o u g h t a b o u t the radical t r a n s f o r m a t i o n o f a philosophical discipline. Brentano a n d D i l t h e y together represent the h i g h p o i n t o f t h e i r epoch and constitute the most efficacious a n d direct antecedent o f present-day p h i l o s o p h y . I n m a n y respects, Brentano and D i l t h e y are d i a m e t r i c a l l y opposed; the former is concise, expressive, extremely clear, whereas the l a t t e r is diffuse a n d his t h o u g h t is unusually v a g u e ; Brentano adopts the n a t u r a l sciences as his model, whereas D i l t h e y changes e v e r y t h i n g i n t o history; D i l t h e y ' s most direct i n t e l l e c t u a l antecedents are f o u n d i n G e r m a n idealism, whereas Brentano condemns this t r a d i t i o n a n d , o n the c o n t r a r y , invokes that o f Descartes a n d L e i b n i z , o f St. T h o m a s a n d , above a l l , o f Aristotle. Nevertheless, D i l t h e y and B r e n t a n o essentially c o m p l e m e n t one another, a n d i t is n o t difficult to
37«
Brentano
372
see h o w the philosophy o f o u r t i m e derives f r o m t h e i r j o i n t influence. Brentano's most i m p o r t a n t works are Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkennt¬ nis ( O n the O r i g i n o f E t h i c a l K n o w l e d g e ) , a b r i e f p a m p h l e t w h i c h transformed ethics a n d led to the value theory; Die Lehre Jesu und ihre bleibende Bedeutung (Jesus' D o c t r i n e a n d Its Permanent Significance); his masterwork Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (Psychology f r o m the E m p i r i c a l S t a n d p o i n t ) , f r o m w h i c h d i r e c t l y proceeds phenom e n o l o g y a n d therefore present-day philosophy i n its most rigorous o r i e n t a t i o n ; studies o n A r i s t o t l e w h i c h completely renewed A r i s t o t e l i a n i s m ; several short w r i t i n g s o n philosophy a n d its history, p a r t i c u l a r l y those entitled Die vier Phasen der Philosophie ( T h e F o u r Phases o f Philosophy) a n d ttber die Z ^ fi der Philosophie ( O n the F u t u r e o f P h i l o s o p h y ) ; Kategorienlehre ( T h e o r y of the Categories); Wahrheit und Evidenz ( T r u t h a n d E v i d e n c e ) ; a n d , lastly, a n extensive posthumous s t u d y : Vom Dasein Gottes ( O n the Existence o f G o d ) . u
un
B R E N T A N O ' S P H I L O S O P H I C A L S I T U A T I O N . Every philosopher is fixed w i t h i n a philosophical t r a d i t i o n , a n d Brentano even m o r e e x p l i c i t l y t h a n most. I t is thus necessary to establish his s i t u a t i o n i n some detail. A c c o r d i n g to his b i r t h date, he should be a post-Hegelian, immersed i n a positivist atmosphere; however, as a Catholic priest he finds himself r o o t e d i n a Scholastic a n d therefore Aristotelian t r a d i t i o n . Brentano has a manifest congeniality w i t h Aristotle a n d St. T h o m a s — m o r e so w i t h Aristotle, j u s t as t h a t m e d i e v a l philosopher h a d w i t h the Greek; after T r e n d e l e n b u r g , B r e n t a n o renews Aristotelianism i n a n epoch i n w h i c h i t h a d been a b a n d o n e d ; one should n o t forget t h a t m o d e r n p h i l o s o p h y arose as a n a t t e m p t to displace Aristotle. T h i s A r i s t o t e l i a n element gives exceptional fecundity to Brentano's t h o u g h t ; whenever p h i l o s o p h y has established real contact w i t h Aristotle's t h o u g h t , i t has i m m e d i a t e l y become m o r e precise a n d serious. Brentano is a n example o f this, as was Scholasticism i n the t h i r t e e n t h c e n t u r y a n d , later, L e i b n i z , a n d , later still, H e g e l . M o r e o v e r , Aristotle's close presence is one reason for the i n d u b i t a b l e p r o f u n d i t y of present-day philosophy. B r e n t a n o condemns idealist philosophy f r o m K a n t to H e g e l ; i t seems to h i m to be a straying f r o m the t r u e p a t h . I t is, a c c o r d i n g to Brentano, p a r t l y — b u t only p a r t l y — t r u e . Brentano adopts the positivist a t t i t u d e o f his t i m e ; this a t t i t u d e was j u s t i f i e d to the extent t h a t i t asked m e n to concern themselves w i t h w h a t they encountered w i t h o u t engaging i n m e n t a l constructions; its serious error lies i n the fact t h a t i t d i d n o t concern itself w i t h w h a t i t encountered, b u t i n d u l g e d i n other, no less groundless constructions. T h u s Brentano returns to a p o i n t o f view i n o p p o s i t i o n to idealism; he calls his an " e m p i r i c a l v i e w p o i n t . " O b v i o u s l y , Brentano is a n y t h i n g b u t an empiricist; he c o u l d be con-
Psychology
373
sidered such i n the sense t h a t A r i s t o t l e was an empiricist, b u t n o t i n the sense t h a t Locke was. A r i s t o t l e frequently refers to d i r e c t v i s i o n w i t h o u t r a t i o n a l d e d u c t i o n ; this has been called e m p i r i c i s m , b u t i t has n o t h i n g t o do w i t h experience i n the m e a n i n g o f sensible experience; rather, A r i s t o t l e refers to the nous, the noetic vision, b y w h i c h p r i n c i ples are apprehended d i r e c t l y . W e w i l l soon demonstrate the meani n g o f Brentano's " e m p i r i c i s m , " w h i c h leads precisely to the total defeat o f sensationalist e m p i r i c i s m i n its final psychologistic forms. B r e n t a n o establishes a c o n n e c t i o n between the purest a n d most a u t h e n t i c root o f ancient p h i l o s o p h y a n d m o d e r n p h i l o s o p h y , and f r o m this position he transforms the philosophy o f his t i m e . H e begins w i t h his v i s i o n of t w o disciplines: psychology a n d ethics. L e t us now consider Brentano's c o n t r i b u t i o n to these disciplines. 2.
PSYCHOLOGY
I n Brentano's day, psychology consisted o f an a t t e m p t to change itself i n t o a n experimental, positive science; i t was a n associationist psychology related to English philosophy w h i c h a t t e m p t e d to explain e v e r y t h i n g b y means o f the associations o f ideas, a n d f u r t h e r m o r e to intervene i n the other disciplines—for example, i n logic, ethics, esthetics—in order to change t h e m i n t u r n i n t o psychology. Brentano's psychology has a completely new character. P H Y S I C A L A N D P S Y C H I C A L P H E N O M E N A . T h e first essential p r o b l e m t h a t arises is to differentiate clearly between physical a n d psychical p h e n o m e n a . T h e thinkers o f the M i d d l e A g e s — A v i c e n n a i n p a r t i c u l a r — k n e w o f a characteristic o f psychical phenomena t h a t was forgotten later o n ; this was w h a t they called intentional inexistence (the prefix on the second t e r m means in, n o t n e g a t i o n : existence in) or s i m p l y intentionality. B r e n t a n o accepts this characteristic and assigns i t a n i m p o r t a n c e a n d precision that i t d i d n o t have i n Scholasticism. Intentionality means reference to something t h a t is d i s t i n c t ; i n the case o f psychical acts, reference to a content, an object (this does not m e a n t h a t the object must be real). T h i n k i n g is always t h i n k i n g of something; feeling is feeling s o m e t h i n g ; w a n t i n g is w a n t i n g something; l o v i n g or h a t i n g is l o v i n g or h a t i n g something. T h u s , every psychical act is d i r e c t e d t o w a r d a n object; the object m a y n o t exist, as w h e n I t h i n k o f a centaur or o f the squared circle or the regular p e n t a h e d r o n ; however, b o t h the squared circle a n d the regular p e n t a h e d r o n exist as correlatives o f m y t h o u g h t , as objects indicated b y m y act o f i m a g i n i n g or t h i n k i n g . Brentano says t h a t acts w h i c h are not i n t e n t i o n a l are not psychical acts—for example, the sensation of green, or a stomachache. A c c o r d i n g to h i m , sensations are simple n o n - i n t e n t i o n a l
374
Brentano
elements o f the psychical ( i n t e n t i o n a l ) act t h a t is m y perception o f a green tree; a n d the psychical act is the feeling o f discomfort whose i n t e n t i o n a l object is the stomach-ache. T h i s idea of i n t e n t i o n a l i t y has far-reaching consequences. I n the first place, i t leads to the reappearance o f ideal objects a n d , a m o n g these, to w h a t Husserl w i l l c a l l meanings. I t also leads to the n o t i o n t h a t t h o u g h t does not exhaust itself, t h a t i t is essentially directed t o w a r d something distinct f r o m itself. F i n a l l y , i t gives rise to the belief t h a t m a n is i n t e n t i o n a l , ex-centric, a n d t h a t he points to s o m e t h i n g distinct f r o m himself. T h e idea o f m a n as a n entity t h a t is " open to the t h i n g s " is based o n this idea of Brentano's. B R E N T A N O ' S M E T H O D . W h a t is Brentano's m e t h o d , the m e t h o d t h a t he calls " e m p i r i c a l " ? T o a n E n g l i s h m a n , to a n associationist psychologist, empiricism w o u l d have meant observation of facts. The e m p i r i c i s t observes one fact, a n d another, a n d t h e n abstracts a n d generalizes the c o m m o n factors. Brentano's m e t h o d is a different k i n d o f empiricism. L e t us suppose that I wish to observe a p h e n o m enon : I take a single case a n d see w h a t the essential p a r t o f i t is, w h a t i t consists of, w h a t i t cannot exist w i t h o u t . I n this w a y I o b t a i n the essence o f the p h e n o m e n o n : then I a m able to say, for example, not t h a t psychical acts are generally i n t e n t i o n a l , b u t t h a t t h e y are essentially i n t e n t i o n a l . Brentano intuits the essence o f a p h e n o m e n o n . T h i s m e t h o d is refined and perfected b y Husserl a n d becomes phenomenology. C L A S S I F I C A T I O N OF P S Y C H I C A L P H E N O M E N A . After differentiating the psychical phenomena, B r e n t a n o must classify t h e m . Since i n t e n t i o n a l i t y is w h a t is essential i n t h e m , he classifies t h e m o n this basis, a c c o r d i n g to the various modes o f i n t e n t i o n a l reference. H e d i s t i n guishes three kinds o f acts:
{
representations (what have been called " assumptions") judgments emotions (or phenomena of interest, love or volition)
B r e n t a n o uses the w o r d representation very loosely: i t is a t h o u g h t , idea or image. T o B r e n t a n o , a representation is a n y t h i n g t h a t is present to the consciousness. H e restates a n ancient Scholastic p r i n c i p l e w h i c h we have already e n c o u n t e r e d — i n Spinoza, for e x a m p l e — a n d w h i c h is k n o w n b y the name o f Brentano's principle: " E v e r y psychical act is either a representation or is based o n a r e p r e s e n t a t i o n . " I f I a m h a p p y a b o u t something, m y happiness presupposes a representation o f the t h i n g w h i c h makes m e h a p p y ; or i f I desire something, o f the t h i n g w h i c h I desire, a n d so o n . Therefore, there is a first degree o f i n t e n t i o n a l i t y , w h i c h is simple reference to the object represented, a n d a
Ethics
second degree, i n w h i c h , while operating on the basis of a representation, I take a p o s i t i o n o n a second i n t e n t i o n a l act. Judgment consists o f accepting o r rejecting something as true. E m o t i o n , interest, w i l l o r love consists of one's mooing toward something, t h a t is, of one's a p p r e c i a t i n g or v a l u i n g i t , of one's esteeming it. T h i s also involves the t a k i n g of a position, a p p r o v a l or rejection, b u t o f a different nature. Brentano's ethics derives f r o m this, as does value p h i l o s o p h y later o n . P E R C E P T I O N . I n his Psychology, B r e n t a n o also formulates a t h e o r y of perception. H e finds t w o basic modes : internal perception (perception of psychical phenomena) a n d external perception (perception o f physical p h e n o m e n a ) . I n t e r n a l p e r c e p t i o n is direct, self-evident a n d i n f a l l i b l e (adequate) ; external p e r c e p t i o n , o n the contrary, is i n d i r e c t , not self-evident, a n d subject to e r r o r (inadequate). Therefore, internal perception is the sure criterion of c e r t a i n t y . T h i s idea has been a d o p t e d and corrected b y Husserl, w h o believes t h a t a l l external perceptions and also some i n t e r n a l (empirical) perceptions are inadequate, a n d t h a t o n l y phenomenological perceptions are adequate. I n short, i t is a question o f n o t m a k i n g positions o f existence ; the experiences s i m p l y must be described, w i t h o u t t a k i n g a position w i t h regard to the existence of a n y t h i n g external to t h e m , for example, of real objects.
3.
ETHICS
Brentano's ethics is o u t l i n e d i n Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis, w h i c h is the text o f a lecture he delivered i n V i e n n a i n 1889 e n t i t l e d " O f the N a t u r a l Sanction o f the J u s t a n d the M o r a l . " Brentano applies to ethics a viewpoint analogous to the one used i n his psychology ; he calls this v i e w p o i n t e m p i r i c a l i n the sense t h a t w e have seen. S A N C T I O N . Brentano begins b y i n q u i r i n g about the n a t u r a l sanction of the j u s t a n d the m o r a l . I f I say t h a t something is good or b a d , there must be some basis, some a u t h o r i t y o r sanction that can verify the goodness or badness of the t h i n g . B r e n t a n o rejects the solutions o f various earlier philosophers: h e d o n i s m , eudaemonism, K a n t i a n m o r a l i t y , a n d so f o r t h .
B r e n t a n o has one r u l i n g p o i n t o f view : he makes w h a t is true correspond to w h a t is good, a n d w h a t is logical correspond to w h a t is m o r a l . H e says t h a t the ethical i m p e r a t i v e is very similar to the logical i m p e r a t i v e . W h a t is true is accepted as t r u e i n a.judgment: w h a t is good is accepted as such i n an act of love. T r u t h is believed, affirmed: goodness is loved. Conversely, falsity is denied, a n d e v i l is hated. THE M O R A L C R I T E R I O N . W h a t tells m e whether a t h i n g is g o o d or
37^
Brentano
b a d ? T h e fact t h a t I love or hate i t ? N o . A n d i n logic t r u t h does n o t depend on whether I a f f i r m o r deny s o m e t h i n g ; I m a y be w r o n g . A t h i n g is not good because I love i t ; o n the c o n t r a r y , I love a t h i n g because i t is good. B u t I m a y be w r o n g : error cannot be restricted to the r e a l m o f j u d g m e n t ; a different k i n d o f error is possible i n v a l u a t i o n . Brentano has p r o v i s i o n a l l y transferred us to the sphere o f object i v i t y . T h a t w h i c h is good is the object; m y reference m a y be erroneous; m y a t t i t u d e w i t h respect to the things receives its sanction f r o m the things themselves, n o t f r o m me. S E L F - E V I D E N C E . I f i n d myself l o v i n g or h a t i n g something. I m a y be w r o n g . W h o can t e l l m e w h e t h e r the t h i n g is good or b a d ? Brentano resorts to the parallelism o f l o g i c : h o w does logic p r o v i d e m e w i t h a c r i t e r i o n to k n o w w h e t h e r I err o r not ? Brentano distinguishes between blind judgments a n d self-evidentjudgments,.1 deny m a n y things, a n d steadfastly affirm a n d believe i n others; b u t these j u d g m e n t s are m o r e o r less obscure, based o n f a i t h , a u t h o r i t y , custom, a n d the like. I can believe i n such j u d g m e n t s w i t h complete resoluteness, b u t they d o n o t c o n t a i n w i t h i n themselves the basis o f their o w n t r u t h ; either they are n o t true, or else t h e i r t r u t h is n o t a p a r t o f t h e m . Such j u d g m e n t s d o n o t contain w i t h i n themselves the justification o f t h e i r t r u t h ; Brentano calls these b l i n d j u d g m e n t s . I n contrast, there is another class o f j u d g m e n t s w h i c h Brentano calls judgments. T h e y c o n t a i n a k i n d o f l i g h t w h i c h makes i t evident that they are t r u e j u d g m e n t s . O n e does n o t o n l y believe a n d a f f i r m t h e m ; rather, one sees t h a t they are t r u e a n d completely u n d e r stands t h a t they cannot be otherwise. I believe t h a t 2 a n d 2 are 4, n o t because I have been t o l d so, b u t because I see t h a t i t is so a n d t h a t i t cannot be otherwise. T h u s , self-evident j u d g m e n t s are those t h a t c o n t a i n w i t h i n themselves the reason for their t r u t h o r falsity. self-evident
T H E J U S T L O V E . L e t us go back to the p r o b l e m o f ethics, w h i c h deals w i t h w h a t is good a n d w h a t is b a d . Brentano says t h a t m y l o v i n g o r h a t i n g a t h i n g does n o t i n itself prove that the t h i n g is good or b a d . M y love or hate must be just. L o v e can be j u s t o r unjust, adequate o r inadequate. O n the other h a n d , there can be a love t h a t has its o w n j u s t i f i c a t i o n w i t h i n itself. W h e n I love a t h i n g because i t is u n d o u b t e d l y good, t h e n m y love is ajust love. I f I love a t h i n g i m p u l s i v e l y , confusedly, m y love c a n be either j u s t or unjust. W h e n i t is perceived t h a t the t h i n g is good, a n d w h y i t is good, t h e n the justness o f the love becomes manifest. T h e adequate a t t i t u d e w h e n c o n f r o n t i n g a good t h i n g is to love i t , a n d w h e n c o n f r o n t i n g a b a d t h i n g , to hate i t . A n d w h e n a t h i n g is understood as either good or b a d , one loves o r hates i t by necessity. One's subsequent conduct is a n o t h e r m a t t e r . B r e n t a n o
The
Existence
of God
377
recalls the classical verse: Video melioraproboque, deteriorasequor. Therefore, ethics is founded objectively. A n d valuation, far f r o m being c o n t i n gent on subjective choice, must adjust to the goodness or badness of the things, j u s t as belief must adjust t o t h e i r t r u t h . Brentano's ethics has given b i r t h to value theory, w h i c h contains great i n t e r n a l difficulties, but w h i c h represents a major c o n t r i b u t i o n t o the objective a n d hierarchical arrangement of values a n d therefore to the f o u n d a t i o n o f ethics a n d the other estimative disciplines. 4.
T H EEXISTENCE OF G O D
Brentano's posthumous book Vom Dasein Gottes contains several lectures o n t h e existence o f G o d w h i c h were delivered i n W i i r z b u r g a n d i n V i e n n a between 1868 a n d 1891, a n d a b r i e f treatise d a t i n g f r o m 1915 e n t i t l e d Gedankengang beim Beweisfiir das Dasein Gottes ( O u t l i n e o f a Proof of the Existence of G o d ) . I n the earlier p e r i o d , Brentano rejects the ontological p r o o f a n d affirms four a posteriori proofs: the teleological proof, the p r o o f b y m o t i o n , the p r o o f b y contingency a n d t h e psychological p r o o f b y the nature o f the h u m a n soul. Brentano p r e fers the first t w o , p a r t i c u l a r l y the teleological proof, to w h i c h he gives undreamed-of scientific precision. H o w e v e r , i n the 1915 treatise he makes use o f the a r g u m e n t b y contingency, w h i c h is of a p u r e l y m e t a physical n a t u r e . Brentano first proves the necessity f o r t h e existence o f the e n t i t y , w h i c h cannot be absolutely c o n t i n g e n t ; once the existence of a necessary e n t i t y has been proved, he affirms t h a t n o t h i n g that comes w i t h i n o u r experience, neither physical nor psychical phenomena, is directly necessary; therefore, there must be a transcendent directly necessary entity. * B R E N T A N O ' S S I G N I F I C A N C E . T h e core o f Brentano's t h o u g h t is the idea ofself-evidence. T h i s is the m e a n i n g o f his " e m p i r i c i s m " : the selfevident v i s i o n o f the essence of the things. T h i s renewed concern w i t h essence represents a r e t u r n t o metaphysics p r o p e r ; i n Brentano, philosophy once again consists o f c o n q u e r i n g essences, strictly metaphysical knowledge, w h a t philosophy has always been w h e n i t has been a u t h e n t i c . O n the other h a n d , Brentano gives us the m a j o r elements o f present-day philosophy: t h e assimilation o f the entire philosophical t r a d i t i o n , i n t e n t i o n a l i t y , t h e i n t u i t i o n o f essences, the idea o f v a l u e . D i l t h e y w i l l give us, o n his p a r t , historicism. W i t h these elements i n h a n d , the philosophy o f o u r century gets under w a y .
* O n the problems associated with this proof, see my study " E l problema de Dios en la filosofía de nuestro tiempo" in San Anselmo y el insensato [Obras, I V ] .
The Idea of
I.
Life
DlLTHEY
L I F E A N D W O R K S . W i l h e l m D i l t h e y was b o r n i n 1833 a n d d i e d i n 1911. F r o m 1882 o n he was a professor at the U n i v e r s i t y o f B e r l i n , where he succeeded L o t z e . I n the last years o f his life he r e t i r e d f r o m the university a n d gathered together a s m a l l g r o u p o f pupils at his home. Dilthey's influence has been t r u l y enormous, b u t belated, i n conspicuous a n d u n u s u a l . D i l t h e y devoted himself especially to historical studies, p r i n c i p a l l y the history o f l i t e r a t u r e and o f the other sciences o f the s p i r i t ; he also was deeply concerned w i t h psychology. H i s intellectual b a c k g r o u n d was tremendous i n scope ; he was inspired directly by the G e r m a n idealists, p a r t i c u l a r l y Schleiermacher, b u t his development was also shaped b y the great rationalists, the m e d i e v a l philosophers ( i n c l u d i n g the Arabs) a n d the Greeks. D i l t h e y ' s Introduction to the Sciences of the Spirit reveals the vast philosophical a n d historical m a t e r i a l t h a t he commanded.
Seemingly, D i l t h e y ' s p r o d u c t i o n is l i t t l e m o r e t h a n this : psychology a n d history o f the s p i r i t . Every t i m e he t r i e d to formulate his p h i losophy i n response to specific p u b l i s h i n g requirements, he was o n l y able to supply inadequate sketches. Y e t i n D i l t h e y ' s w o r k there is the inconsistent a n d always poorly expressed i n t u i t i o n o f a new idea : the idea of life. O n e o f the two m a j o r roots o f present-day p h i losophy is f o u n d i n D i l t h e y (the other is i n B r e n t a n o ) , b u t D i l t h e y ' s philosophy can o n l y be understood i n this w a y , i n its t r u t h , from the viewpoint o f the n o w m a t u r e philosophy o f t o d a y . T h i s is the reason 37
8
Dilthey
379
for the essential vagueness o f Dilthey's t h o u g h t a n d style, a n d for the sparseness a n d inconspicuousness o f his influence. Dilthey's w o r k consists p r i m a r i l y o f sketches or notes, w h i c h were p a r t i a l l y published after his death. H i s m a j o r b o o k — a l m o s t his o n l y b o o k — i s the Einleitung in die Geisteswissenschaften ( I n t r o d u c t i o n to the Sciences of the S p i r i t ) , o f w h i c h he completed only the first v o l u m e . H e also w r o t e a series o f studies grouped u n d e r the general title o f
Weltanschauung und Analyse des Menschen seit Renaissance und Reformation ( V i e w o f the W o r l d a n d Analysis o f M a n since the Renaissance a n d the R e f o r m a t i o n ) ; another series e n t i t l e d Die geistige Welt: Einleitung in die Philosophie des Lebens ( T h e S p i r i t u a l W o r l d : I n t r o d u c t i o n to the Philosophy o f L i f e ) , i n w h i c h are to be f o u n d the Ideen ubereine beschrei¬ bende und zergliedernde Psychologie (Ideas o n a Descriptive and A n a l y t i c a l Psychology) and-Dai Wesen der Philosophie ( T h e N a t u r e of Philosophy); a m o n g the w r i t i n g s o f his final period is the Weltanschauungslehre ( T h e o r y of W o r l d V i e w s ) . H e also w r o t e a book called Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung (Experience a n d Poetry). D I L T H E Y ' S P O I N T O F V I E W . H i p p o l y t e T a i n e , Ernest R e n a n , W i l ¬ h e l m W u n d t , F r i e d r i c h A l b e r t Lange a n d H e r b e r t Spencer belong to the generation p r i o r to Dilthey's, a n d yet o u r impression is t h a t they were even f a r t h e r i n the past. T h e y represent that generation o f positivist thinkers w h i c h begins to feel uncomfortable a n d reacts against positivism. B u t strictly speaking, o n l y D i l t h e y achieves the break w i t h p o s i t i v i s m , a n d even he n o t completely. Auguste C o m t e ( b o r n i n 1798) was three generations earlier: D i l t h e y — w h o belonged to the same generation as Brentano, Nietzsche a n d W i l l i a m J a m e s — no longer undergoes Comte's direct influence, b u t o n l y the residualforce o f t h a t influence. T h e w o r k o f D i l t h e y a n d the Neo-Kantians is c o n d i tioned by their dependence u p o n positivism i n controversial matters.
F r o m Comte's philosophy D i l t h e y receives t w o very i m p o r t a n t ideas, w h i c h s t i m u l a t e his thought i n a n o r i g i n a l and different direction. O n e idea is t h a t all o f earlier philosophy was partial, t h a t i t d i d not embrace the whole o f reality as i t i s ; the other is t h a t metaphysics is impossible, a n d that only the positive sciences are a m a t t e r o f concern. D i l t h e y attempts to base philosophy " o n total, f u l l experience, w i t h o u t t r u n c a t i o n s : therefore, o n e n t i r e a n d complete r e a l i t y " ; o n the other h a n d , he attempts to supersede metaphysics as he u n d e r stands i t , t h a t is, as " absolutism o f the i n t e l l e c t " : this latter o u t l o o k is the t r i b u t e he pays to the age he lives i n . Strictly speaking, D i l t h e y created neither a system, nor a theory o f life, nor even a historical d o c t r i n e ; he d i d something less a n d somet h i n g m o r e : he came i n t o direct contact w i t h the reality o f life a n d ,
j8o
The
Idea
of
Life
thus, o f history. " A l l m e n , " I have w r i t t e n elsewhere,* apropos o f D i l t h e y , " live w i t h i n history, b u t m a n y m e n do not k n o w this. Others know t h a t t h e i r p e r i o d will be historical, b u t they do not live i t as such. D i l t h e y b r o u g h t us historicism, w h i c h is, of course, a doctrine, b u t first of all a mode of b e i n g : historical consciousness, w i t h the intellectualist a n d d o c t r i n a l nuances removed f r o m the t e r m 'consciousness.' T o d a y , fully immersed i n this historicism, we f i n d i t very difficult t o realize the o r i g i n a l i t y o f t h a t discovery. W e are conscious o f existing w i t h i n a determined p e r i o d of t i m e , w h i c h is destined to pass away l i k e a l l other periods, to be superseded b y another. W e are capable o f t r a n s p o r t i n g ourselves i n t o other ages, and we live, n a t u r a l l y , i n a w o r l d directly constituted b y t e m p o r a l i t y . W h e n we study a n y t h i n g whatever, we need to k n o w its date, how i t fits i n t o h i s t o r y ; otherwise we d o not understand i t . W e t h i n k of every t h i n g as b e i n g enclosed i n its historical surroundings; o u r v i e w of a city, for example, is not the direct v i e w o f w h a t the c i t y is at present; rather, the c i t y seems to us to be a n a c c u m u l a t i o n of strata o f time, a h i s t o r i c a l ' result,' i n w h i c h the past survives a n d the f u t u r e is i n t u r n betokened. F o r D i l t h e y , this is closely related to the skepticism produced b y the discrepancies a m o n g ideas a n d systems. T h e s p i r i t u a l attitude w i t h w h i c h we live excludes everyt h i n g definitive; we do not believe we are settling any problems once a n d for a l l ; r a t h e r , we believe we are s u p p l y i n g answers w h i c h are appropriate to o u r o w n era, b u t w h i c h are destined to be superseded or corrected i n the f u t u r e . T h e vision of history i n D i l t h e y i s ' a n immense field of r u i n s . ' I t should be recalled t h a t this was not always the case. T h e r e have been l o n g periods i n w h i c h m a n has regarded m a n y things as standing a p a r t f r o m time, as being e n d o w e d w i t h a certain timeless v a l i d i t y : this is the case w i t h a l l classical periods. B u t i n less peaceful and settled epochs, especially i n those w h i c h signified a break w i t h previous norms, the present was declared to be a new situation a n d , at the same t i m e , a valid situation, w i t h o u t f u r t h e r qualification. I n contrast to history, w i t h its storehouse of errors, the present seemed to be a rectification a n d e l i m i n a t i o n of error. T o d a y we feel the peculiar ephemerality o f the historical event, b u t at the same t i m e w e feel t h a t the m o m e n t i n w h i c h we live is i n c l u d e d i n t h a t history. I n order to understand any person's name we must a d d to i t the t w o l i m i t i n g dates of his life, a n d w h e n t h i n k i n g about ourselves we anticipate the still uncertain second date, w h i c h is represented b y a question m a r k . Never so m u c h as n o w has m a n lived his life as the true reality of counted days. A n d t h a t is history. . . . I n our age i t is a c q u i r i n g basic a n d o r i g i n a l
* Biografta de la Filosqfia, V I , 37 [Obras, I I ] .
Dilthey
characteristics h i t h e r t o u n k n o w n . . . because o u r age is discovering t h a t w h a t changes is man himself. N o t o n l y is m a n w i t h i n history, n o t o n l y does he have a history, b u t he is h i s t o r y ; h i s t o r i c i t y affects the very being o f m a n . " T h i s is D i l t h e y ' s p o i n t o f v i e w . H U M A N L I F E . D i l t h e y discovers life i n its historical dimension. O f a l l the different ways i n w h i c h the nineteenth century came to t o u c h u p o n that r e a l i t y w h i c h is life, D i l t h e y ' s has been the most f r u i t f u l . L i f e is historical i n its very substance; h i s t o r y is life itself, f r o m the v i e w p o i n t of the t o t a l i t y of m a n k i n d . T h i s v i t a l r e a l i t y is not a " w o r l d " o f things and persons; i t is a complex (Zusammenhang, the w o r d D i l t h e y constantly repeats) o f v i t a l relationships. E a c h " t h i n g " is no m o r e t h a n a n ingredient o f o u r life, and acquires its m e a n i n g w i t h i n o u r life. " [ A person's] f r i e n d is a force w h i c h exalts his o w n existence; each m e m b e r of his f a m i l y has a determined place i n his life, he understands everything i n his e n v i r o n m e n t as life a n d s p i r i t w h i c h have become objectivized there. T h e bench i n f r o n t o f his door, his house a n d garden have t h e i r essence and their m e a n i n g i n this objectivity. T h u s life creates its o w n w o r l d t h r o u g h the eyes o f each i n d i v i d u a l " ( T h e o r y of World
Views).
T h e w o r l d is always a correlate of the self, a n d the self does n o t exist w i t h o u t the other t e r m , the world. N o w , this life appears as a r i d d l e w h i c h needs t o be understood; death, especially, evokes this need, because it is the incomprehensible. B u t life can o n l y be understoodfrom its own viewpoint; knowledge cannot look b e h i n d the scenes of life. F o r this reason, i n contrast t o causal explanation, the m e t h o d of the n a t u r a l sciences, D i l t h e y makes descriptive understanding the m e t h o d o f the sciences of the s p i r i t , o f the knowledge o f life. Since understanding o f the life of others, especially i n the past, requires an explanation, Dilthey's m e t h o d is hermeneutics. Hence the " d e s c r i p t i v e a n d a n a l y t i c a l " psychology w h i c h he calls for, i n o p p o s i t i o n to the explicative psychology of the e x p e r i m e n t a l psychologists, w h o treat h u m a n life as nature. T h e structure o f h u m a n life is a u n i t a r y t o t a l i t y , w h i c h is d e t e r m i n e d b y the selfhood of the person. Every psychical state is a process, b u t life itself is n o t ; r a t h e r , i t is a lasting c o n t i n u i t y w i t h i n w h i c h occur the processes w h i c h pass by, D i l t h e y says, " i n the same w a y as a fastm o v i n g traveler sees objects disappear b e h i n d h i m w h i c h a m o m e n t before were i n f r o n t o f h i m and alongside h i m , w h i l e the t o t a l i t y o f the landscape is always preserved." T h a t is, the p r i m a r y r e a l i t y is the u n i t y of life, within w h i c h occur t h e ' ' t h i n g s , " o n the one h a n d , a n d , o n the other, the p s y c h i c a l ' ' processes.'' T h i s basic interconnection w h i c h is life is characterized byfinality.
The
Idea
of
Life
H u m a n life is a n o r i g i n a l a n d transcendent u n i t y : i t is n o t a composite o f elements; rather, starting o u t f r o m its u n i t a r y r e a l i t y , the psychical functions are differentiated, b u t r e m a i n u n i t e d w i t h life i n their i n t e r c o n n e c t i o n . D i l t h e y says t h a t this fact, w h i c h is expressed i n its highest degree as the u n i t y o f consciousness a n d the u n i t y o f the person, completely distinguishes psychical life f r o m the e n t i r e corporeal w o r l d . Therefore, D i l t h e y rejects a l l forms o f psychical f r a g m e n t a t i o n . Seen i n another way, this u n i t y occurs w i t h i n a m i l i e u . T h e u n i t y of life is engaged i n m u t u a l reaction w i t h the external w o r l d . Life consists i n the action of the v i t a l u n i t y u p o n s t i m u l i , m o d i f y i n g t h e m or a d a p t i n g t h e m to its conditions b y means o f v o l u n t a r y activity. L a s t l y , transition f r o m one set o f members to another w i t h i n psychical life does n o t take place b y simple causality i n t h e sense o f external n a t u r e ; ideas or representations do n o t c o n t a i n a reason sufficient to m a k e t h e m become processes, nor do processes have sufficient reason for their t r a n s f o r m a t i o n i n t o v o l i t i o n a l processes. D i l t h e y says t h a t one could imagine a n e n t i t y w h i c h w o u l d be a mere subject o f representations, and w h i c h i n the midst of the t u m u l t o f a battle w o u l d be a n indifferent a n d volitionless spectator o f its o w n destruction; o r one could imagine t h a t this same entity m i g h t f o l l o w the struggle r a g i n g about i t w i t h feelings o f fear and a l a r m , b u t t h a t nevertheless n o defensive movements w o u l d proceed f r o m those feelings. T h e connection that occurs between the elements o f psychical life is o f a p e c u l i a r nature a n d o f a superior t y p e ; i t proceeds f r o m t h a t p r i m a r y t o t a l i t y w h i c h is h u m a n life itself. Dilthey's analysis of h u m a n life, inadequate b u t e x t r a o r d i n a r i l y perceptive, is the p o i n t of departure for present-day metaphysics, a n d i t is constantly necessary to refer back to i t . P H I L O S O P H Y . " ' W h a t is p h i l o s o p h y ? ' is a question w h i c h cannot be answered i n accordance w i t h each man's personal taste; r a t h e r , the function o f philosophy must be e m p i r i c a l l y discovered i n history. I t is clear t h a t this h i s t o r y must be understood f r o m the v i e w p o i n t o f the spiritual v i t a l i t y f r o m w h i c h we ourselves proceed, and i n w h i c h we live p h i l o s o p h y . " These are Dilthey's t w o g u i d i n g ideas: the essence o f philosophy can be discovered only i n the historical reality o f w h a t i t actually has been, a n d history can be understood only f r o m the viewp o i n t of the life i n w h i c h i t is located. Therefore, D i l t h e y must make a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f a l l o f history i n order to determine the b e i n g o f philosophy. T h e t w o chief traits t h a t are c o m m o n to all philosophy are universality a n d autonomy, or the c l a i m to be universally v a l i d : a l l other traits are p e c u l i a r to i n d i v i d u a l philosophies. D i l t h e y corrects the idea o f p r o d u c t i v e t h o u g h t w h i c h the G e r m a n
Dilthey
3S3
idealists found so appealing. Philosophy, D i l t h e y says, analyzes, b u t does n o t produce; i t creates n o t h i n g ; i t can o n l y show that w h i c h exists. T h a t is, he renews i n a truer a n d m o r e f u n d a m e n t a l f o r m the d e m a n d of the positivists to h o l d fast to the things, a n d not to replace t h e m w i t h m e n t a l constructions; this a t t i t u d e w i l l be shared b y phenomenology. Philosophy is the science o f the r e a l ; t h a t is, o f all the r e a l , w i t h o u t truncations. B u t D i l t h e y is v e r y far removed f r o m a position of intellectual absolutism. T h e intelligence is not something isolated and standing a p a r t ; rather, i t is a vital function a n d has m e a n i n g only w i t h i n the t o t a l i t y w h i c h is h u m a n l i f e ; knowledge o f life must be " d e r i v e d . " B u t i n the second place, knowledge does n o t exhaust the r e a l : " I n the f i n a l analysis r e a l i t y itself cannot be explained logically, b u t o n l y understood. I n a l l r e a l i t y w h i c h occurs to us as such there is something ineffable, u n k n o w a b l e . " T h a t w h i c h is supplied to us, he adds, is irrational. T h e basis o f systematic philosophy for D i l t h e y is autognosis, consciousness of one's self (Selbstbesinnung). F r o m autognosis one proceeds to hermeneutics, t h a t is, knowledge o f the life o f others, the compreh e n d i n g i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f other lives, a n d thus o f history. Lastly, one goes f r o m that p o i n t to the knowledge o f nature. Philosophy proceeds f r o m w h a t is nearest—ourselves—to w h a t is farthest away. Even t h o u g h absolute systems are not possible—each system contains its o w n p a r t i a l t r u t h w h i c h , at least i n p r i n c i p l e , does not exclude the equally p a r t i a l t r u t h o f the other systems—man conceives them a n d they remain as a constituent fact o f h u m a n consciousness. Every m a n has a Weltanschauung, a n idea or view o f the w o r l d , w h i c h is u l t i m a t e l y r o o t e d not i n the intellect, b u t i n life itself. These w o r l d views, w h i c h philosophy at first studies historically, can be reduced to types i n order t h a t we may k n o w the possible ways o f i m a g i n i n g the universe; thus, O r t e g a (Guillermo Dilthey y la idea de la vida) summarizes the four themes of Dilthey's philosophy i n this w a y : ( 1 ) history o f the evolution o f philosophy as a propaedeutic; ( 2 ) theory o f knowledge; (3) classific a t i o n of the sciences; (4) theory o f w o r l d views. D i l t h e y calls for a
Reason; this is w h a t his Introclaims to be. H e hopes to achieve for " the other h a l f o f the globus intellectualis" w h a t K a n t d i d for the k n o w l edge o f nature. T h i s is Dilthey's g r a n d i d e a : i n opposition to the i r r a t i o n a l i s m reached i n the nineteenth c e n t u r y b y those w h o are aware of the failure o f " p u r e reason" w h e n they wish to conceive o f life a n d history, D i l t h e y champions a new, broader f o r m of reason w h i c h does not exclude the historical element. B u t strictly speaking, he duction
to the Sciences
Critique
of Historical
of the Spirit
The
Idea
of
Life
tries o n l y to apply reason to h i s t o r y ; t h a t is, reason itself. Therefore, he ends b y considering the w o r l d views as being beyond h i s t o r y , a n d to t h a t extent he cannot account, t h a t is, give a reason, for t h e m . T h e t e r m historical reason i n D i l they does n o t — c a n n o t — h a v e the scope w h i c h we shall see i t a t t a i n i n the philosophy of O r t e g a . THE M E A N I N G O F D I L T H E Y ' S P H I L O S O P H Y . W e have seen t h a t i n D i l t h e y ' s t h o u g h t t w o disciplines are indissolubly l i n k e d : psychology and history. O n the one h a n d , there is the analysis of what is human, especially b y means of autognosis: philosophy as a science of the spirit. O n the other h a n d , this h u m a n r e a l i t y is history, i t is human life; this analysis is philosophy of life a n d t h e r e f o r e — t o the extent t o w h i c h this life is t h a t of others a n d i n the p a s t — h i s t o r i c a l i n t e r p r e t a t i o n , hermeneutics. I t s m o d e of knowledge is n o t causal explanation b u t understanding (Verständnis), and its t h e o r y constitutes a t r u e c r i t i q u e o f historical reason. W e n o w have several of the ingredients o f present-day p h i l o s o p h y ; but the g r o u p must still be c o m p l e t e d . I n the first place, there must be a new i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of vital time, supplied b y H e n r i Bergson; i n the second place, after European p h i l o s o p h y has once more re-entered its t r a d i t i o n o f metaphysical a n d systematic t h o u g h t , the r e n e w a l — d u e to B r e n t a n o — o f the idea of intentionality w i l l stimulate the r i p e n i n g i n E d m u n d Husserl's philosophy o f a new m e t h o d : phenomenology. We shall t h e n have a l l the elements t h a t constitute the philosophy w h i c h is being p r a c t i c e d today: i n G e r m a n y , existential philosophy, especially t h a t of M a r t i n Heidegger; i n Spain, Ortega's metaphysics of vital reason, w h i c h is, moreover, quite different i n meaning a n d i n its most p r o f o u n d tendencies; a n d the doctrines w h i c h are derived f r o m one or the other or f r o m b o t h .
2.
SIMMEL
L I F E A N D W O R K S . Georg S i m m e l , w h o was b o r n i n 1858 a n d d i e d i n 1918, was almost exactly c o n t e m p o r a r y w i t h Bergson a n d Husserl. H e was a professor at the universities o f Strasbourg a n d B e r l i n a n d concerned h i m s e l f especially w i t h topics related to sociology a n d history. I n spite of some essential faults, Simmel's Soziologie is one o f the most p e n e t r a t i n g attempts to give a firm basis to this discipline. S i m m e l — one o f the most i m p o r t a n t figures i n philosophy i n the early years o f this c e n t u r y — a t t e m p t e d i n his w r i t i n g s to come as close as possible to a direct contact w i t h objects a n d p r o b l e m s ; this gives his w o r k s t h e i r p r i n c i p a l source of attraction a n d , at the same t i m e , their fruitfulness.
His most i m p o r t a n t writings are
Kant
(a series of lectures),
Schopen-
Simmel hauer
und Nietzsche,
Probleme
Philosophic
der Geschichtsphilosophie
des Geldes
(The
(Philosophy o f M o n e y ) ,
Die
Problems o f the Philosophy o f
H i s t o r y ) , Grundprobleme der Philosophic ( F u n d a m e n t a l Problems o f Philosophy) and Lebensanschauung ( V i e w o f L i f e ) ; t h e n there are his i m p o r t a n t Sociology a n d a great m a n y perspicacious essays on Feminine Culture,
Philosophy
of Coquetry,
Philosophy
of Fashion,
and
so
on.
T h e most p r o f o u n d aspect o f Simmel's t h o u g h t is his conception of life, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the f o r m i n w h i c h i t is e x p o u n d e d i n the first chapter o f his Lebensanschauung. Simmel says t h a t man's position i n the w o r l d is defined, because at every m o m e n t m a n finds t h a t he is between t w o l i m i t s . Always, everywhere, we have l i m i t s , a n d therefore w e also are l i m i t s . T h e r e is always a greater and a lesser, a closer to a n d f a r t h e r t h a n our here a n d now a n d thus; our life appears to be defined b y t w o values w h i c h f r e q u e n t l y conflict w i t h one a n o t h e r : richness a n d d e t e r m i n a t i o n . L I F E AS T R A N S C E N D E N C E .
B u t the interesting p o i n t is t h a t , a l t h o u g h the general l i m i t is necessary to life, any specific, i n d i v i d u a l l i m i t m a y be transcended and exceeded. O u r actions are s i m i l a r to those of the chess p l a y e r ; the chess player needs to k n o w w i t h a certain p r o b a b i l i t y the consequences of a m o v e , b u t the game w o u l d be impossible i f this prescience were to be extended indefinitely. T h e l i m i t s to h u m a n life can be displaced; thus S i m m e l says paradoxically, " i n a l l senses we are l i m i t e d , and i n no sense are we l i m i t e d . " E v e r y v i t a l action implies b o t h a l i m i t a t i o n and the o v e r c o m i n g o f a l i m i t . T h e spirit exceeds itself, transcends itself, a n d thus appears to be t h a t w h i c h is absolutely alive. I n this sense, i t is possible to say that m a n is something that o u g h t to be surpassed; m a n is a l i m i t e d entity t h a t does n o t have any limits. T I M E . S i m m e l begins w i t h a reflection on t i m e i n o r d e r to achieve a c o n c e p t i o n of life. The
present
is a n unextended moment;
i t is not time any
m o r e t h a n a p o i n t is space. T h e present is n o t h i n g b u t the c o m i n g together o f the past a n d the f u t u r e , w h i c h are themselves, of course, t e m p o r a l magnitudes, t h a t is, t i m e . However, the past no longer exists, and the f u t u r e does not yet exist; reality occurs o n l y i n the present, and therefore reality is i n n o sense t e m p o r a l . " T i m e does not exist i n r e a l i t y , a n d reality is n o t t i m e . " B u t i n spite of e v e r y t h i n g , when life is lived subjectively, i t is felt to be real i n a temporal extension. English and Spanish usage do n o t understand by " p r e s e n t " a mere p o i n t , b u t r a t h e r a p o r t i o n of the past together w i t h a p o r t i o n of the future, w i t h l i m i t s t h a t vary depending o n whether we are speaking of the personal, p o l i t i c a l or historical present. L i f e appears to refer to the future. This statement can be understood i n a r a t h e r t r i v i a l sense: m a n always proposes a f u t u r e end for himself;
3
86
The
Idea
of
Life
however, this end is a n i m m o v a b l e p o i n t a n d is separated f r o m the present, a n d w h a t is most characteristic o f the present w i l l ' s v i t a l p e n e t r a t i o n (Hineinleben) i n t o the f u t u r e is that life''s present consists of its transcending the present. T h e r e is no real threshold between the present a n d the f u t u r e . T h e future is n o t a l a n d t h a t we have never t r o d d e n u p o n , separated f r o m the present b y a b o u n d a r y ; r a t h e r , we live i n a frontier region that belongs to the future as m u c h as to the present. " L i f e is really b o t h past a n d f u t u r e . " Simmel adds, " O n l y for life is t i m e r e a l . " " T i m e is the f o r m o f consciousness o f t h a t w h i c h constitutes life itself i n its i m m e d i a t e concreteness, a n d w h i c h cannot be enunciated, b u t only l i v e d ; i t is life stripped of its c o n t e n t s . " THE E S S E N C E O F L I F E . Present life transcends t h a t w h i c h is n o t its presentness, b u t i n such a w a y t h a t this transcending nevertheless constitutes its presentness. T h i s is the essence of life. Life is o u r name for a mode of existence the r e a l i t y of w h i c h is n o t restricted to the present m o m e n t , i n w h i c h the past a n d the future are n o t relegated to i r r e a l i t y ; rather, life's peculiar c o n t i n u i t y is really m a i n t a i n e d beyond this separation; t h a t is, the past really exists b y e x t e n d i n g i n t o the present, a n d the present really exists b y expanding i n t o the future.
N o w t h e n , life occurs o n l y i n individuals; and this creates a serious p r o b l e m : life is at the same t i m e u n l i m i t e d c o n t i n u i t y a n d a n ego d e t e r m i n e d b y its limits. Life's transcendence is i m m a n e n t i n i t ; life's p r i m a r y phenomenon is t h a t i t can exceed itself; i n Simmel's phrase, this constitutes " w h a t is absolute i n our r e l a t i v i t y . " Therefore, the p r i n c i p a l a n t i n o m y is the one t h a t exists between f o r m a n d c o n t i n u i t y ; f o r m is i n d i v i d u a l i t y , a n d life is everywhere individual. S i m m e l relates his conception o f life to Schopenhauer's doctrine o f the w i l l to live a n d Nietzsche's d o c t r i n e of the w i l l to p o w e r ; however, he observes t h a t w h a t is decisive is the agreement between the t w o moments. T h e r e are t w o definitions of life w h i c h r e c i p r o c a l l y complem e n t each o t h e r : life is more life a n d i t is more than life. T h i s w o r d more is no accidental a d d i t i o n . L i f e is a m o t i o n w h i c h is always p u l l i n g things t o w a r d i t , a t t r a c t i n g things i n order to change t h e m i n t o life. L i f e can exist o n l y because i t is more life. D e a t h , w h i c h according to S i m m e l resides i n life beforehand, is also a n aspect of life's transcending itself. Procreation a n d death b o t h transcend life; one u p w a r d a n d the other d o w n w a r d . L i f e requires f o r m , a n d at the same t i m e i t requires something more than form. B u t life, especially i n its creative aspect, also transcends its o w n contents. I t is n o t only more life; i t is more than life. Life is o n l y a subject's constant transcending of w h a t is foreign to i t or the p r o d u c t i o n of w h a t is foreign to i t . T h i s does n o t subjectivize this foreign b e i n g ; rather, i t
Bergson
retains its independence, its " b e i n g more t h a n life " ; t h e absoluteness o f the other, o f the more, is the f o r m u l a a n d c o n d i t i o n o f life. Life's u n i t y exists i n the f o r m o f a dualism. T h u s , i n a final clever p a r a d o x Simmel can say t h a t life finds its essence a n d its realization i n being more life a n d more than life; that is, t h a t life's positive element is as such already its comparative element. These ideas f r o m Simmel's m a t u r i t y (his Lebensanschauung dates from the year o f his death, 1918) signify a b r i l l i a n t step o n t h e r o a d to the comprehension o f the r e a l i t y o f h u m a n life.
3.
BERGSON
L I F E A N D W O R K S . W i t h Bergson w e leave the n i n e t e e n t h century a n d enter the t w e n t i e t h . Bergson's roots a n d the first phase o f his i n t e l l e c t u a l development are i n the past century; b u t his life as w e l l as the u l t i m a t e significance o f his philosophy already b e l o n g to o u r epoch or, m o r e p r o p e r l y speaking, are a typical m o m e n t o f t r a n s i t i o n , like the rest o f the philosophy o f t h a t t i m e : one more step o n the r o a d to o v e r c o m i n g positivism i n o r d e r to r e t u r n once more to metaphysics.
H e n r i Bergson was b o r n i n Paris i n 1859 a n d d i e d early i n J a n u a r y i n 1941. H e was a professor o f philosophy i n the Lycées o f Angers and C l e r m o n t - F e r r a n d , i n the u n i v e r s i t y i n the latter c i t y , i n t h e Collège R o l l i n a n d i n the L y c é e H e n r i I V o f Paris; also i n t h e École N o r m a l e Supérieure. After 1919, he was professor i n the Collège de France, the highest F r e n c h i n s t i t u t i o n o f l e a r n i n g . D u r i n g his last years, o l d age forced h i m to w i t h d r a w f r o m p u b l i c life. H i s most i m p o r t a n t works are his doctoral thesis, Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience, Matière et mémoire, Le rire, Durée et simultanéité, L'évolution créatrice; t w o collections o f essays a n d lectures: L'énergie spirituelle a n d La pensée et le mouvant ( w h i c h contains his Introduction à la métaphysique), a n d his last book, Les deux sources de la morale et de la religion, i n w h i c h his increasing rapprochement w i t h C a t h o l i c i s m was first made public. S P A C E A N D T I M E . Space a n d t i m e are usually t h o u g h t to be comp a r a b l e a n d parallel t e r m s — K a n t understood t h e m as such. Bergson reacts energetically against this idea, a n d says t h a t these terms are opposites. Space is a n aggregate o f points, f r o m a n y one o f w h i c h we can pass t o a n y other; t i m e , o n the other h a n d , is irreversible, i t has a direction, a n d every m o m e n t o f t i m e is unsubstitutable, irreplaceable, a t r u e creation w h i c h cannot be repeated and to w h i c h w e cannot r e t u r n . B u t Bergson's time is n o t the t i m e o f the clock, spatialized t i m e , w h i c h can be measured a n d w h i c h is represented b y a l e n g t h , b u t living time
3
88
The
Idea
of
Life
as i t presents itself i n its i m m e d i a t e reality to the consciousness: i t is w h a t is called real duration, dure'e réelle. Space a n d t i m e are t o each other as m a t t e r to m e m o r y , as the b o d y to the soul; they correspond to t w o basically different a n d even, i n a certain sense, opposite i n t e l l e c t u a l modes of m a n : t h o u g h t a n d i n t u i t i o n . I N T E L L E C T A N D I N T U I T I O N . Conceptual t h o u g h t , w h i c h i n a n a r r o w sense is called intellect, is the m e t h o d of scientific k n o w l e d g e ; i t moves a m o n g the things a n d tends t o w a r d spatialization. I n general, science seeks measurement; this process is accomplished either d i r e c t l y t h r o u g h the comparison o f l e n g t h (the meter a n d the r o a d b e i n g measured) or b y means o f a n a t t e m p t to reduce o t h e r magnitudes to l e n g t h or to another f o r m of space, for example, t o a n angle, w h i c h can i n t u r n be reduced to l e n g t h (the clock, the m a n o m e t e r , the d y n a m o m e t e r a n d the t h e r m o m e t e r measure various magnitudes w h i c h are i n themselves non-spatial b y c o m p a r i n g t h e m w i t h the displacem e n t o f a needle or the expansion i n length o f a c o l u m n o f m e r c u r y ) . T h o u g h t , w h i c h is directed t o w a r d science—or t o w a r d p r a c t i c a l life, t h e m a n i p u l a t i o n o f things—proceeds by means o f logic, observation a n d concepts. T h o u g h t tends t o discover r i g i d concepts, w h i c h the i n tellect manages easily. I t tends to solidify everything. W h a t is m o r e , t h o u g h t searches for similarities, for things t h a t various i n d i v i d u a l s h a v e i n c o m m o n ; t h o u g h t generalizes. I n t e l l e c t is the sphere o f t h a t w h i c h is i n e r t , at rest, a n d therefore discontinuous; i t is the sphere o f matter. These conditions are different f r o m those r e q u i r e d for the apprehension o f l i v i n g reality. Specifically, t h o u g h t does n o t a p p r e h e n d l i v i n g t i m e , duration, the t i m e t h a t I must w a i t for sugar t o dissolve i n a glass of water. Real m o t i o n , such as i t is seen f r o m w i t h i n w h e n I m o v e m y a r m , is perceived b y the intellect as a series o f disconnected states of rest, w h i c h are not m o t i o n . M o v i n g one's a r m is a single, continuous, living m o t i o n . T h o u g h t schematizes i t , fixes i t i n a concept, stops i t ; t o be precise, i t robs i t of its f l u i d i t y . O n l y intuition is capable of appreh e n d i n g real duration, m o t i o n i n its true i m m e d i a c y — i n short, life. I n t u i t i o n can capture m o b i l i t y , i t can comprehend the v e r y process o f m o t i o n a n d l i v i n g t i m e before these things become p e t r i f i e d i n t o concepts. I n t e l l e c t has a p p l i c a t i o n to matter a n d therefore t o science, whereas i n t u i t i o n adapts itself t o life. Bergson relates this faculty t o instinct, t h a t marvelous non-conceptual a d a p t a t i o n t o v i t a l problems w h i c h animals enjoy. Bergson says t h a t science a n d philosophy, w h i c h are conceived f r o m a s p a t i a l p o i n t of view, have h a r d l y k n o w n i n t u i t i o n ; they have always o p e r a t e d w i t h the categories of conceptual t h o u g h t , which is of no use in
Blondel
3*9
life and real time. Therefore, m a n finds i t v e r y d i f f i c u l t to conceive o f these realities ; he lacks the appropriate instruments a n d , w h a t is m o r e , the h a b i t o f m a k i n g use of them. H e n r i Bergson's p h i losophy approaches the reality o f life w i t h an attitude t h a t differs f r o m the usual one ; his attitude is based o n m o b i l i t y itself, o n processes that are n o t yet realized and c o m p l e t e d , t h a t are i n the very act o f being realized. I n t u i t i o n tries to c a p t u r e life f r o m w i t h i n ; i t does n o t first k i l l life, i n o r d e r to reduce i t to a spatialized, conceptual scheme. apprehending
" T h e r e a l i t y of life is d y n a m i c ; it is a v i t a l i m p u l s e or T h i s impulse determines a n evolution i n t i m e ; a n d this e v o l u t i o n is creative, because r e a l i t y is a l i v i n g c o n t i n u i t y . I t is not composed o f given elements, a n d o n l y after reality has been consumm a t e d c a n t h o u g h t t r y to compose i t w i t h i m m o v a b l e a n d given elements, as i f one could recompose m o t i o n f r o m a series o f states of repose. T h i s puts Bergson i n contact w i t h the philosophy of life, w h i c h finds i n h i m one of its clearest a n d most fecund precursors. H o w e v e r , one must make i t clear t h a t Bergson understands life i n a biological sense r a t h e r t h a n i n a biographical or historical sense, a n d t h a t therefore he does n o t touch u p o n the most essential peculiarity o f human life. Bergson's t h o u g h t must be c o m p l e t e d along these lines i f i t is to achieve f u l l efficacy. O n the other h a n d , i t w i l l also be necessary to overcome the irrationalism t h a t menaces every f o r m of i n t u i t i o n . Philosophy is strict knowledge a n d , therefore, concept a n d reason. Reason w i l l have to conceive o f this n e w object, life, i n a l l its fluidity and m o b i l i t y ; i t w i l l be different f r o m scientific and m a t h e m a t i c a l reason, but i t m u s t always be reason. O r t e g a has seen this fully a n d clearly, and therefore he is careful always to speak of'vital reason. "ELAN VITAL.
élan vital.
4.
BLONDEL
M a u r i c e Blondel (1861-1949) is, after Bergson, the most o r i g i n a l a n d interesting figure i n c o n t e m p o r a r y French philosophy. A p u p i l o f O l l é - L a p r u n e , about w h o m he w r o t e a w o r k , Blondel represents a n aspect w i t h i n Catholic t h o u g h t t h a t has been called " p r a g m a t i s m " — i n a very different sense f r o m E n g l i s h a n d A m e r i c a n p r a g m a t i s m — o r " a c t i v i s m " or, better yet, philosophy of action. His p r i n c i p a l w o r k is a book t h a t is now already q u i t e o l d , since i t dates f r o m 1893: his d o c t o r a l thesis entitled L'Action. Essai d'une critique de la vie et d'une science de la pratique. After m a n y years d u r i n g w h i c h his a c t i v i t y as a w r i t e r was restricted to collaborations i n philosophical j o u r n a l s , Blondel published not very l o n g ago three extremely l o n g works : La pensée, L'Être et les êtres a n d a complete revision, i n t w o volumes, of his
39°
The
Idea
of
Life
old thesis VAction, as w e l l as several studies o n apologetics a n d on the C h r i s t i a n spirit i n its relationships w i t h philosophy. BlondePs p o i n t of d e p a r t u r e is the question w h e t h e r h u m a n life has m e a n i n g a n d m a n has a destiny. I act w i t h o u t k n o w i n g w h a t action is, w i t h o u t h a v i n g wished to l i v e , w i t h o u t k n o w i n g w h o I a m or i f I a m . A n d according to w h a t w e are t o l d , I a m n o t able at any cost to conquer nothingness; r a t h e r , I a m condemned to life, d e a t h a n d eternity w i t h o u t h a v i n g k n o w n o r wished for this. N o w t h e n , this p r o b l e m , w h i c h is inevitable, is i n e v i t a b l y solved b y m a n , for good or i l l , t h r o u g h his actions. A c t i o n is man's t r u e , effective answer to the p r o b l e m of l i f e ; therefore, action is necessarily man's first concern. A c t i o n is the most general a n d most constant fact of m y life: Blondel says t h a t action is more t h a n a f a c t — i t is a necessity, since even suicide is a n act. W e can p e r f o r m a n a c t i o n only b y closing o f f a l l other ways a n d d e p r i v i n g ourselves of everything we could have otherwise k n o w n or obtained. Every decision cuts off an infinite n u m b e r o f possible actions. A n d we cannot desist a n d suspend a c t i o n , n o r can we delay. I f we do not act, something acts i n us or outside us, a n d almost always against us. Blondel says t h a t peace is defeat; a c t i o n does n o t tolerate a n y postponement other t h a n death. Therefore I c a n n o t be guided b y m y ideas, because complete analysis is not possible to a finite i n t e l l i gence, a n d practical life does n o t tolerate delays: I cannot defer a c t i o n u n t i l I o b t a i n evidence, a n d a l l evidence is p a r t i a l . F u r t h e r m o r e , m y decisions usually go b e y o n d m y thoughts, a n d m y actions usually go b e y o n d m y intentions. Therefore, we must construct a science of a c t i o n ; i t must be i n t e g r a l because every f o r m o f t h i n k i n g a n d l i v i n g deliberately implies a complete solution to the p r o b l e m o f existence. B l o n d e l , w h o of course refers to the religious p r o b l e m , is opposed to i n t e l l e c t u a l i s m a n d fideism, n o t i n the name of feeling, b u t i n t h a t o f a c t i o n . H i s c r i t i c i s m of Scholasticism derives f r o m this. Entities are, above a l l , w h a t they do. Philosophy must " p r e v e n t t h o u g h t f r o m i d o l i z i n g itself, show the insufficiency a n d n a t u r a l s u b o r d i n a t i o n o f speculation, i l l u m i n e the exigencies and paths of a c t i o n , prepare a n d j u s t i f y the ways of f a i t h . " W e cannot discuss here the details o f this philosophy, the p r o f o u n d a n d difficult aspects of BlondePs t h o u g h t ; i t is sufficient to indicate the v i e w p o i n t f r o m w h i c h B l o n d e l considers the p r o b l e m of life.
5.
UNAMUNO
L I F E A N D W O R K S . M i g u e l de U n a m u n o , w h o was b o r n i n Bilbao i n 1864 a n d died i n Salamanca i n 1936, is one o f the most i m p o r t a n t
Unamuno
Spanish thinkers. H e cannot be considered a philosopher i n the strict sense, a n d yet he is o f extreme interest i n the history o f p h i l o s o p h y . H i s w o r k a n d very personality constitute a philosophic p r o b l e m i n themselves. H e w r o t e copiously i n m a n y different genres: poetry, novels a n d stories, plays, ideological essays. F r o m the v i e w p o i n t o f philosophy, his most i m p o r t a n t works are his seven volumes o f Ensayos (Essays); La vida de Don Quijote y Sancho ( T h e Life o f D o n Q u i x o t e a n d Sancho); Del sentimiento trágico de la vida ( T h e T r a g i c Sense o f L i f e ) , his most n o t e w o r t h y book; La agonía del cristianismo ( T h e A g o n y o f C h r i s t i a n i t y ) ; a n d especially some o f his novels and stories: Paz en la
guerra, Niebla, Abel Sánchez, La tía Tula, San Manuel Bueno, mártir a n d his poetical n a r r a t i v e Teresa. H i s P R O B L E M . U n a m u n o , w h o h a d a keen sense o f the problems o f philosophy, concentrated his w h o l e i n t e l l e c t u a l and l i t e r a r y a c t i v i t y on w h a t he called " t h e one a n d o n l y q u e s t i o n " : the personal immortality o f the i n d i v i d u a l m a n , w h o lives a n d dies and does n o t w i s h to die completely. A t a m o m e n t o f history w h e n the generally accepted sciences d i d n o t even touch u p o n this question, U n a m u n o , i n exasperat i o n , m a d e i t the center o f his w h o l e life. H i s religious f a i t h , weak a n d r i d d l e d w i t h doubts ( " i n the throes o f d e a t h , " to use his expression) d i d n o t satisfy h i m . H e thus felt o b l i g e d to pose the p r o b l e m o f i m m o r t a l i t y , w h i c h , o f course, leads to the p r o b l e m o f death a n d n a t u r a l l y refers back to the problems o f life a n d the. person. B u t instead o f w r i t i n g philosophical studies, as m i g h t have been expected, U n a m u n o composed essays w i t h l i t t l e scientific content, poems a n d especially stories. W h a t is the reason for this unusual l i t e r a r y p r o d u c tion? H i s M E T H O D . F o r historical reasons, because he belonged to a p a r t i c u l a r generation, U n a m u n o was i m b u e d w i t h the irrationalism w h i c h I h a v e already m e n t i o n e d repeatedly. L i k e K i e r k e g a a r d , like W i l l i a m James, like Bergson, he believed t h a t reason does n o t h e l p us to k n o w l i f e ; t h a t w h e n t r y i n g to apprehend life i n fixed a n d r i g i d concepts, reason robs i t o f its fluidity w i t h i n t i m e and kills i t . O f course, these t h i n k e r s were speaking o f p u r e reason, the reason o f physics a n d mathematics. T h i s conviction caused U n a m u n o to look a w a y f r o m reason a n d t u r n t o w a r d the imagination, w h i c h he called " t h e most substantial f a c u l t y . " Since i t was no longer possible to grasp the reality o f life b y means o f reason, he t r i e d to do i t w i t h the i m a g i n a t i o n , living life a n d anticipating the experience o f death i n narratives. R e a l i z i n g t h a t h u m a n life is a h a p p e n i n g w i t h i n t i m e , something t o l d or n a r r a t e d — i n short, h i s t o r y — U n a m u n o used the s t o r y — a n o r i g i n a l f o r m o f story w h i c h m i g h t be called existential or, better yet, personal—
392
The
Idea
of
Life
as his m e t h o d o f knowledge. T h i s k i n d o f story constitutes a very f r u i t f u l attempt t o a p p r e h e n d h u m a n reality d i r e c t l y ; i t is, t o be sure, a n inadequate a t t e m p t , b u t one that c o u l d serve as the basis for a precise metaphysics, w h i c h is not to be f o u n d i n U n a m u n o . Despite his diffuseness a n d his failure t o achieve p h i l o s o p h i c a l fullness, U n a m u n o was a b r i l l i a n t prophet w h o a n t i c i p a t e d m a n y i m p o r t a n t discoveries concerning that reality w h i c h is h u m a n life ; a n d his findings, i n c o m p l e t e as they are, frequently go b e y o n d a l l p h i l o sophical investigations u p to the present. U n a m u n o is a t r u e precursor o f the metaphysics o f existence or life, a precursor w i t h a personality o f his o w n . This justifies his inclusion i n the history o f philosophy, a n inclusion w h i c h was d e t e r m i n e d i n the final analysis b y the fruitfulness o f his prophecies, w h i c h cannot be studied i n d e t a i l here. * * See my book Miguel de Unamuno (1943) for a complete study of the philosophical problem posed by Unamuno and his contribution to contemporary philosophy (English translation, Harvard University Press, in press). See also La Escuela de Madrid [Obras, V ] .
English^Language
Philosophy
A s i n almost every era, English philosophy presents i n o u r day characteristics t h a t are relatively different f r o m those of C o n t i n e n t a l philosophy; nevertheless, this does n o t preclude parallel developments a n d a l o n g series o f reciprocal influences. Moreover, i n the last years o f the n i n e t e e n t h century a new factor enters the scene: the U n i t e d States. Closely related to the B r i t i s h t r a d i t i o n b u t strongly influenced b y the Germans a n d , to a lesser extent, by the French, the philosophical speculation w h i c h begins i n A m e r i c a is conditioned b y the distinctive social structure of the c o u n t r y a n d its different perspective on the problems o f philosophy. I n o u r century, A m e r i c a n t h o u g h t has i n t u r n influenced British t h o u g h t ; m a n y thinkers o f b o t h nations have been active, have taught a n d have l i v e d o n b o t h sides o f the A t l a n t i c ; thus, a f o r m o f English-language philosophy has been created w h i c h has various nuances b u t w h i c h presents a c o m m o n configuration. I n the last few decades, this philosophy has begun to influence t h a t o f the European C o n t i n e n t , a n d i t is therefore necessary to take i n t o account, i f only very concisely, its general m e a n i n g a n d its major phases, since i t has become t o d a y a decisive component o f Western philosophy. i.
PRAGMATISM
T h e first i m p o r t a n t a n d o r i g i n a l s p r o u t i n g o f A m e r i c a n t h o u g h t was p r a g m a t i s m . Previously the " transcendentalists"—among t h e m R a l p h W a l d o Emerson ( i 803-1882) a n d H e n r y D a v i d T h o r e a u ( 1 8 1 7 - 1 8 6 2 ) — h a d i n i t i a t e d a reaction against m a t e r i a l i s m a n d the 393
English-Language
394
Philosophy
prevalence o f positivist t h i n k i n g ; this was i n N e w E n g l a n d , i n the area o f Boston a n d C a m b r i d g e , the site of H a r v a r d U n i v e r s i t y a n d the first center o f i n t e l l e c t u a l life i n A m e r i c a . B u t A m e r i c a reaches its first philosophical m a t u r i t y o n l y w i t h the pragmatists. T h e t e r m " p r a g matism " is especially l i n k e d w i t h the n a m e o f W i l l i a m J a m e s ; he was the first to use this designation i n w r i t i n g , i n 1898; b u t he h a d adopted the t e r m f r o m Peirce, w h o originated the d o c t r i n e a n d h a d already expounded i t t w e n t y years earlier. T h e r e has been a great deal o f discussion o n the relationship between Peirce a n d James. F o r g o t t e n for m a n y years, Peirce has recently aroused l i v e l y interest; h e has been esteemed m u c h m o r e h i g h l y t h a n James, w h o h a d enjoyed enormous prestige a n d was t h e n subjected to severe c r i t i c i s m . T h e r e has been discussion o f the connection between the t w o interpretations o f p r a g m a t i s m ; i t has even been said t h a t " the philosophical m o v e m e n t k n o w n as p r a g m a t i s m is i n large p a r t the result o f James's h a v i n g misunderstood P e i r c e . " T h i s is, w i t h o u t d o u b t , a n exaggeration w h i c h is due to the belated " d i s c o v e r y " o f Peirce a n d the reaction against the exclusive l i n k i n g o f p r a g m a t i s m w i t h James a n d his i m m e d i a t e followers. T h i s is n o t the place to review the numerous ramifications o f the p r o b l e m ; i t w i l l be sufficient to indicate the o r i g i n a l f o r m i n w h i c h the doctrine appears i n the w o r k o f b o t h m e n a n d i n the subsequent tradition. P E I R C E . Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914), a c o n t e m p o r a r y o f D i l t h e y , Brentano a n d Nietzsche, was b o r n i n C a m b r i d g e , Massachusetts ; he t a u g h t sporadically at H a r v a r d a n d Johns H o p k i n s for several years, a n d p u b l i s h e d very l i t t l e — o n l y articles a n d reviews o f p h i l o sophical books, w h i c h since his death have been collected i n t o volumes: i n 1923 there appeared the v o l u m e Chance, Love and Logic, edited b y M o r r i s R . C o h e n ; f r o m 1931 o n , the eight volumes o f The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, edited b y Charles H a r t s h o r n e , Paul Weiss a n d A r t h u r W . Burks; a n d finally, another anthology volume,
The
Philosophy
of
Peirce
(or,
The
Philosophical
Writings
of
edited b y Justus Buchler. O n e o f the most i n f l u e n t i a l o f Peirce's w r i t i n g s was the article " H o w to M a k e O u r Ideas C l e a r , " published i n J a n u a r y , 1878; i t is the o r i g i n a l a n d basic t e x t o f p r a g matism. Peirce was able to complete o n l y one book, The Grand Logic, w h i c h was published as a posthumous w o r k a m o n g his collected papers.
Peirce),
Peirce's first readings i n philosophy were F r i e d r i c h Schiller's Letters Education of Man, R i c h a r d Whately's Logic, a n d the Critique of Pure Reason, w h i c h he learned almost b y h e a r t ; he also underwent the influence o f Scotus a n d o f his o w n education i n m a t h e on the Esthetic
Pragmatism
395
matics. Peirce's a t t i t u d e is p r i m a r i l y theoretic: for h i m philosophy belongs as a " s u b c l a s s " u n d e r the science o f discovery, w h i c h i n t u r n is a b r a n c h o f theoretic science. T h e f u n c t i o n o f philosophy is to e x p l a i n and show the u n i t y i n the diversity o f the universe; philosophy has a twofold p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e : logic, the r e l a t i o n o f signs w i t h their objects, and phenomenology, the r a w experience o f the objective real w o r l d . These t w o disciplines converge i n three basic metaphysical categories w h i c h are i n t e r r e l a t e d i n a very complex fashion; these m a y be called q u a l i t y , r e l a t i o n a n d m e d i a t i o n . Peirce's t h o u g h t , w h i c h is q u i t e fragmentary a n d n o t very systematic, touched u p o n numerous problems of the t h e o r y o f knowledge, logic a n d metaphysics; b u t , above a l l , he proposed to establish a method, a n d t h a t is precisely w h a t p r a g m a t i s m is. I t is " a m e t h o d o f ascertaining the m e a n i n g o f h a r d words a n d o f abstract concepts," or else " a m e t h o d o f ascertaining the m e a n i n g s . . . o f . . . intellectual concepts, t h a t is to say, o f those u p o n the structure o f w h i c h , arguments concerning objective fact m a y h i n g e . " M o r e specifically, Peirce proposed to clarify the t r a d i t i o n a l metaphysical questions and, where possible, to eliminate t h e m as meaningless. This shows that Peirce's p r a g m a t i s m is, above a l l , a logical discipline, as opposed to the t r a d i t i o n a l view o f p r a g m a t i s m derived f r o m a p a r t i a l a n d inexact i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the f o r m w h i c h i t a c q u i r e d i n the w o r k o f James. But i t should be noted t h a t the " l o g i c a l " side is not foreign to James, nor the " p r a c t i c a l " side to Peirce. F o r the latter, the function o f t h o u g h t is to produce habits o f a c t i o n ; b y this p a t h he arrives, laboriously a n d i n f r e q u e n t l y obscure a n d infelicitous formulations, at the idea of p r a g m a t i s m . T h e first expression o f p r a g m a t i s m ( i n " H o w to M a k e O u r Ideas C l e a r " ) is this: " Consider w h a t effects, t h a t m i g h t conceivably have p r a c t i c a l bearings, we conceive the object o f o u r conception to have. T h e n , our conception o f these effects is the whole o f o u r conception o f the o b j e c t . " A second f o r m u l a , somewhat l i g h t e r a n d clearer, runs: " I n order to ascertain the m e a n i n g o f a n i n t e l l e c t u a l conception one should consider w h a t p r a c t i c a l consequences m i g h t conceivably result b y necessity f r o m the t r u t h of that conception; a n d the sum o f these consequences w i l l constitute the entire m e a n i n g o f the c o n c e p t i o n . " L a s t l y , a t h i r d thesis gives greater precision to the m e a n i n g o f pragm a t i s m i n Peirce: " P r a g m a t i s m is the p r i n c i p l e t h a t every theoretical j u d g m e n t expressible i n a sentence i n the i n d i c a t i v e m o o d is a confused f o r m o f thought whose o n l y meaning, i f i t has any, lies i n its tendency to enforce a corresponding practical m a x i m expressible as a c o n d i t i o n a l sentence h a v i n g its apodosis i n the i m p e r a t i v e m o o d . "
English-Language
396
Philosophy
I n the face o f the increasing use o f the t e r m " p r a g m a t i s m " i n a sense different f r o m that w h i c h he wished to give i t , Peirce renounced the use o f i t a n d coined the n a m e " p r a g m a t i c i s m " for his o w n p h i losophy ; this name he j u d g e d " u g l y enough to be safe f r o m k i d n a p p e r s . " Peirce's w o r k , still n o t published i n its entirety a n d o n l y p a r t i a l l y k n o w n a n d studied, appears today to be very f r u i t f u l a n d valuable. J A M E S . W i l l i a m James (1842-1910), w h o was o f the same generat i o n as Peirce, was b o r n i n N e w Y o r k . A professor at H a r v a r d f r o m 1872 o n , a physician, a psychologist a n d a philosopher, h e is the most o u t s t a n d i n g figure i n A m e r i c a n philosophy. James, w h o was a n extremely v i v i d a n d s t i m u l a t i n g w r i t e r a n d lecturer, f u l l o f ideas, c o n t r i b u t e d m o r e t h a n anyone else to the a c c l i m a t i z a t i o n o f p h i l o sophical t h o u g h t i n the U n i t e d States. H i s first o r i e n t a t i o n was t o w a r d psychology, a discipline i n w h i c h he was one o f the most f r u i t f u l classic researchers; his t w o books o n psychology are b o t h masterpieces, unsurpassed i n certain respects; m a n y parts o f t h e m are s t i l l v a l i d a n d fertile. H i s a t t e n t i o n was then centered o n m o r a l a n d religious themes a n d , finally, o n metaphysics. H i s m a j o r works are The Principles of Psychology, i n t w o volumes, a n d a m o r e concise and c o m p a c t treatise, A
Textbook
Experience; A Pluralistic and
Essays
of Psychology; Pragmatism:
The
Will
A New
Universe;
The Meaning
in Radical
Empiricism.
to Believe;
Name
for
of Truth;
The
Some
Old
Varieties Ways
Some Problems
of of of
Religious Thinking; Philosophy;
James's philosophy is one o f the attempts undertaken a t the close o f the n i n e t e e n t h century to conceive o f a n d understand h u m a n life. H i s psychology represents a p e n e t r a t i n g comprehension o f the r e a l i t y o f psychical life i n its dynamic aspect: the image of the stream of consciousness is a revealing one. B u t this interest i n life assumes the f o r m — h a b i t u a l i n his d a y — o f anti-intellectualism a n d , further, o f i r r a t i o n a l i s m ; f r o m K i e r k e g a a r d t h r o u g h O s w a l d Spengler a n d U n a m u n o , a n d i n c l u d i n g Nietzsche a n d Bergson, this was the risk r u n b y a l l analogous movements. W i t h this a t t i t u d e James takes u p t h e theme o f p r a g m a t i s m . As he understands i t , there can be no difference t h a t makes no difference; we m i g h t say t h a t no difference can be indifferent. " T h e w h o l e f u n c t i o n o f p h i l o s o p h y , " he says, " ought to be to find o u t w h a t definite difference i t w i l l make to y o u a n d me, at definite instants o f o u r life, i f this w o r l d - f o r m u l a or t h a t w o r l d - f o r m u l a be the true o n e . " T h i s p r a g m a t i s m , i n James's o p i n i o n , is not new: its antecedents are f o u n d i n Socrates and A r i s t o t l e , Locke and Berkeley; i t is the e m p i r i c a l a t t i t u d e , b u t i n a m o r e basic a n d less objectionable f o r m ; i t means the abandonment o f abstraction a n d insufficiency, o f v e r b a l
Pragmatism
397
solutions, b a d a p r i o r i reasoning, r i g i d principles, closed systems a n d presumptive absolutes a n d origins, a n d a r e t u r n to concreteness a n d adequacy, facts, action a n d power. I n contrast to the conception of metaphysics as a n enigma t h a t is solved b y means o f a w o r d or a p r i n c i p l e , James asks for the cash value o f every w o r d ; this is not so m u c h a solution as a p r o g r a m for further w o r k a n d especially a n i n d i c a t i o n o f how existing realities m a y be changed. " T h e o r i e s thus become instruments, n o t answers to enigmas, i n w h i c h we can rest." P r a g m a t i s m thus understood has no dogmas or doctrines; i t is a m e t h o d t h a t is compatible w i t h various doctrines; i t is " the a t t i t u d e o f l o o k i n g a w a y f r o m first things, principles, 'categories,' supposed necessities; a n d o f l o o k i n g towards last things, fruits, consequences, facts." T h i s leads to a n idea o f t r u t h . James renounces the idea o f a h a r m o n y between t h o u g h t a n d the things, since one c o u l d make a j u d g m e n t about this only b y means o f t h o u g h t a n d the things are accessible only w i t h i n t h o u g h t . Ideas, w h i c h are p a r t o f o u r experience, are t r u e to the extent t h a t they help us to enter i n t o satisfactory relationships w i t h other parts o f o u r experience. T r u t h is w h a t " w o r k s , " w h a t " t u r n s out a l l r i g h t , " w h a t " i t w o u l d be better to b e l i e v e , " i n other words, w h a t " we ought to believe." T h e formulations o f this conception o f t r u t h are relatively vague a n d u n c e r t a i n i n James a n d his followers; the f r u i t f u l seed enclosed i n this idea is obscured b y the i r r a t i o n a l i s m that threatens i t , by the tendency o f these p h i losophers t o w a r d a n a r r o w u t i l i t a r i a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f this " t u r n i n g o u t a l l r i g h t " or being successful, a tendency w h i c h cuts o f f a n entire decisive g r o u p of vital acts, such as those o f strict i n t e l l e c t i o n ; therefore, p r a g m a t i s m signifies a d e g r a d a t i o n o f the idea o f t r u t h , even f r o m its o w n p o i n t o f v i e w — t h a t is, f r o m w h a t its p o i n t o f v i e w w o u l d be i f one were to take i t perfectly seriously. T H E C O N T I N U E R S O F P R A G M A T I S M . T h e most i m p o r t a n t later pragmatists are J o h n Dewey, F e r d i n a n d C a n n i n g Scott Schiller a n d R a l p h B a r t o n Perry ( i 8 7 6 - 1 9 5 7 ) . J o h n Dewey (1859-1952), w h o was b o r n i n the same year as Husserl a n d Bergson, was for m a n y years a professor i n C o l u m b i a U n i v e r s i t y ; t h r o u g h o u t his l o n g lifetime he was one o f the most i n f l u e n t i a l m e n i n the intellectual life o f the U n i t e d States, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the field o f education. His most i m p o r t a n t books are
How
We
Reconstruction The
Democracy
in Philosophy,
and Education,
Experience
Essays
and Mature,
in Experimental A Common
Faith,
of Inquiry, Problems of Man. Dewey used the w o r d t o designate his personal version o f p r a g m a t i s m .
Theory
mentalism
Think,
Logic, Logic: instru-
F. C. S. Schiller (1864-1937) was b o r n i n A l t o n a (near H a m b u r g ) ,
398
English-Language
Philosophy
G e r m a n y . H e was a professor i n C o r n e l l a n d O x f o r d a n d later i n C a l i f o r n i a . His p r i n c i p a l books are Humanism a n d Studies in Humanism. Schiller is also associated w i t h James's philosophy; he considered his o w n t h o u g h t , humanism, t o be a w i d e r f o r m o f p r a g m a t i s m , one t h a t encompassed a l l philosophical disciplines. L i k e the earlier p r a g m a tists, Schiller m a i n t a i n e d t h a t t r u t h depends o n p r a c t i c a l consequences; since a l l i n t e l l e c t u a l life has as a n u l t i m a t e goal the i n d i v i d u a l h u m a n e n t i t y , a l l knowledge is s u b o r d i n a t e to h u m a n n a t u r e a n d its f u n d a m e n t a l necessities. H u m a n i s m , Schiller says, " i s m e r e l y the perception t h a t t h e philosophical p r o b l e m concerns h u m a n beings s t r i v i n g t o comprehend a w o r l d o f h u m a n experience b y the resources o f h u m a n m i n d s . " Schiller believes t h a t we actually t r a n s f o r m t h e realities b y means o f o u r cognitive efforts a n d t h a t our desires a n d ideas are therefore real forces i n the c o n f i g u r a t i o n o f the w o r l d .
2.
PERSONALISM
A second d o m i n a n t t r e n d i n t h e Anglo-Saxon t h o u g h t o f o u r t i m e is t h e movement k n o w n as personalism. O n e must note t h a t this t e r m is used i n a n a r r o w sense to designate a coherent g r o u p or school, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n the U n i t e d States, a n d i n a w i d e r sense t o designate m a n y different groups w h i c h are u n i t e d b y a c o m m o n tendency a n d a s p i r i t u a l affinity; I use the t e r m here i n the w i d e r sense. Personalism's most general feature is its insistence o n the r e a l i t y a n d value o f the person a n d its a t t e m p t t o i n t e r p r e t reality f r o m this p o i n t o f v i e w . Closely related to p r a g m a t i s m w i t h respect to the p r o b l e m o f logic, opposed to mechanism a n d behaviorism w i t h respect to psychology, a n d also hostile to a naturalistic i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f r e a l i t y , personalism affirms h u m a n freedom a n d the personal basis o f r e a l i t y , t h a t is, the existence o f a personal G o d . A few idealist thinkers, such as Josiah R o y c e ( i 8 5 5 - 1 9 1 6 ) , are closely related to personalism. Royce, w h o was b o r n i n California a n d t a u g h t i n H a r v a r d , w r o t e The Spirit of
Modern Philosophy, Studies in Good and Evil, The World and the Individual, The Conception of Immortality, The Philosophy of Loyalty. H i s w o r k has been i n f l u e n t i a l i n E u r o p e , p a r t l y t h r o u g h the interest o f G a b r i e l M a r c e l , w h o wrote a book a b o u t h i m . F. C. S. Schiller's h u m a n i s m is also closely related to personalism. T h e classic f o r m o f A m e r i c a n personalism is represented b y a g r o u p o f thinkers centered i n N e w E n g l a n d : Borden Parker B o w n e (1847— 1910), a professor i n Boston U n i v e r s i t y (Metaphysics, Philosophy of Theism, Theory of Thought and Knowledge, Personalism); M a r y W h i t o n
Recent
Trends
399
Calkins (1863-1930) of Wellesley College (An Introduction to Psychology, The Persistent Problems of Philosophy, The Good Man and the Good); E d g a r Sheffield B r i g h t m a n (1884-1952), Bowne's successor i n Boston U n i v e r sity (The Problem of God, A Philosophy of Religion, An Introduction to Philosophy). W i l l i a m Ernest H o c k i n g (b. 1873) of H a r v a r d is also connected w i t h this g r o u p ; his p r i n c i p a l w o r k is The Meaning of God in Human Experience.
3.
RECENT
TRENDS
S A N T A Y A N A . Jorge R u i z de Santayana—George Santayana, as he signed his w o r k — w a s b o r n i n M a d r i d i n 1863, grew u p i n A v i l a , was educated i n Boston, taught i n H a r v a r d , a n d died i n R o m e i n 1952. Santayana w r o t e b r i l l i a n t l y i n English a n d was a novelist a n d essayist; he was n o t p a r t i c u l a r l y systematic, a n d has at times been called a realist or n a t u r a l i s t — r a t h e r vague d e n o m i n a t i o n s — a n d also a materialist. H e left a copious a n d v a r i e d b o d y o f w o r k , p a r t l y autob i o g r a p h i c a l , t h a t perhaps culminates i n his idea o f animal faith as a m e t h o d o f a p p r o a c h i n g reality. H i s most i m p o r t a n t books are The Sense of Beauty ; The Life of Reason (five v o l u m e s ) ; Scepticism and Animal Faith; The Realms of Being (comprised o f four parts: The Realm of Essence, The Realm of Matter, The Realm of Truth, The Realm of Spirit); his a u t o b i o g r a p h y consisting ofPersons and Places, The Middle Span, a n d My Host the World; the novel The Last Puritan; and finally, Dominations and Powers. A L E X A N D E R . Samuel Alexander (1859-1938) was b o r n i n Sydney, Australia. H e was a professor i n O x f o r d a n d Manchester, a n d his t h o u g h t , w h i c h has also been i n t e r p r e t e d b o t h as n a t u r a l i s m a n d as realism, represents one o f the grandest metaphysical constructions i n c o n t e m p o r a r y English philosophy. H i s major w o r k is Space, Time and Deity. W H I T E H E A D . A l f r e d N o r t h W h i t e h e a d (1861-1947), the most i m p o r t a n t o f the contemporary English philosophers, t a u g h t i n E n g l a n d ( p r i n c i p a l l y mathematics) a n d after 1924 i n the U n i t e d States ( H a r v a r d a n d Wellesley), where he specialized i n philosophy. His m a t h e m a t i c a l a n d logical w o r k is o f enormous i m p o r t a n c e , especially his Principia Mathematica ( w r i t t e n i n c o l l a b o r a t i o n w i t h B e r t r a n d Russell). H i s deep interest i n problems o f education is evident i n a series o f works t h a t spans most of his life (The Aims of Education); the p r o b l e m of t h o u g h t a n d its forms is another p r i n c i p a l theme i n his w o r k (The Function of Reason, Adventures of Ideas, Modes of Thought); his m a j o r w o r k is a book o f metaphysics presented as " a n
400
English-Language
Philosophy
essay i n cosmology," Process and Reality (1929). W h i t e h e a d ' s influence is d o m i n a n t today, perhaps even more so i n the U n i t e d States t h a n i n England. R U S S E L L . B e r t r a n d Russell (b. 1872), w h o has t a u g h t i n C a m b r i d g e , was associated w i t h W h i t e h e a d on the great w o r k Principia Mathematica a n d , like W h i t e h e a d , is the author o f some extremely i m p o r t a n t contributions to t h e theory of mathematics a n d s y m b o l i c l o g i c : The Principles of Mathematics, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. H e is also the a u t h o r o f a book o n L e i b n i z , Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibnitz; o f A History of Western Philosophy; o f t w o books entitled The Analysis of Mind a n d The Analysis of Matter; o f a general treatise, An Outline of Philosophy; o f a book on the theory o f knowledge, Human Knowledge, a n d o f numerous essays and books o n e d u c a t i o n , sociology a n d politics. H e has received the N o b e l Prize i n L i t e r a t u r e (as d i d R u d o l f C h r i s t o p h E u c k e n a n d H e n r i Bergson before h i m ) . M O R E R E C E N T M O V E M E N T S . I n E n g l a n d a n d t h e U n i t e d States, these are the decisive t h i n k e r s ; however, they d o n o t represent the o n l y trends, a n d the influence o f C o n t i n e n t a l E u r o p e a n philosophy is steadily increasing, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n A m e r i c a . T h e E n g l i s h m a n R o b i n George C o l l i n g w o o d (1889-1943) already belonged to a cosmopolitan Western t r a d i t i o n t h a t was p a r t i c u l a r l y influenced b y I t a l i a n i d e a l i s m ; this is evident i n his t w o posthumous books The Idea of Nature a n d The Idea of History. T h e same is true to a lesser degree o f George E d w a r d M o o r e (1873-1958), a u t h o r o f Principia Ethica, Ethics, a n d Philosophical Studies, w h o devoted a considerable p a r t o f his w o r k to the analysis o f w h i c h w e w i l l speak later; a n d o f C h a r l i e D u n b a r B r o a d (b. 1887), w h o w r o t e The Mind and Its Place in Nature, Five Types of Ethical Theory, Ethics and the History of Philosophy. B o t h M o o r e a n d Broad were professors i n C a m b r i d g e .
A n energetic presentation o f European t h o u g h t is also f o u n d i n such A m e r i c a n thinkers as George Boas (b. 1891) a n d especially A r t h u r O . Lovejoy (1873-1962), whose most i m p o r t a n t book is The Great Chain of Being: A Study in the History of an Idea, as w e l l as Charles W . H e n d e l , w h o studied Rousseau a n d the English philosophers, a n d B r a n d Blanshard (The Nature of Thought, and so o n ) , b o t h o f Yale, a n d P h i l i p E. W h e e l w r i g h t (The Burning Fountain, Heraclitus, Metaphor and Reality). However, the t r e n d w h i c h has the most followers i n E n g l a n d today is the one w h i c h we c a n call, rather imprecisely, " linguistic analysis," i n w h i c h almost a l l present-day British thinkers p a r t i c i p a t e , a l t h o u g h to very different extents. T h e origins o f this m o v e m e n t are p a r t l y English a n d p a r t l y E u r o p e a n , d e r i v i n g especially f r o m the V i e n n a
Recent
Trends
401
Circle ( M o r i t z Schlick, Hans Reichenbach, O t t o N e u r a t h a n d R u d o l f C a r n a p , who for m a n y years was a professor i n the U n i t e d States). T h e p r i n c i p a l influence was u n d o u b t e d l y L u d w i g W i t t g e n s t e i n (1889-1951), a n A u s t r i a n b y b i r t h , b u t for m a n y years a professor i n Cambridge. H i s famous Tractatus logico-philosophicus was first p u b lished i n 1921, a n d the f o l l o w i n g year i t was republished i n the o r i g i n a l G e r m a n , together w i t h a n English translation and a n i n t r o d u c t i o n by B e r t r a n d Russell. Later, W i t t g e n s t e i n changed his viewpoints considerably i n various articles w h i c h were collected after his death i n Philosophische Untersuchungen (Philosophical Investigations) a n d other volumes. A m o n g the most interesting contemporary B r i t i s h philosophers are G i l b e r t Ryle (The Concept of AieW), J o h n O . W i s d o m
(Other Minds, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis), C. K . Odgen a n d I . A . Richards (The Meaning of Meaning), J o h n L . A u s t i n (1911-1960; Sense and Sensibilia, Philosophical Papers) a n d A l f r e d Jules A y e r (Lan-
guage, Truth and Logic; The Problem of Knowledge). I n spite o f t h e i r great differences, these philosophical groups have some features i n c o m m o n . I n A u s t r i a as w e l l as i n E n g l a n d a n d the U n i t e d States, the V i e n n a Circle c u l t i v a t e d symbolic or m a t h e m a t i c a l logic, i n the same m a n n e r as d i d the Polish logicians o f the so-called W a r s a w C i r c l e ; this t r e n d , a field t h a t is l i m i t e d b u t o f considerable interest, is perhaps the most valuable one. T h e w o r k o f Lukasiewicz, A l f r e d T a r s k i , C a r n a p , K u r t Godel a n d W i t t g e n s t e i n himself is l i n k e d w i t h that o f the A m e r i c a n logicians Clarence I r v i n g Lewis (Mind and '.he World Order), A l o n z o C h u r c h , Susanne K . Langer (the a u t h o r o f :he interesting book Philosophy in a New Key), W i l l a r d v. O . Q u i n e
(Mathematical Logic, Methods of Logic, From a Logical Point of View), Charles W . M o r r i s (Signs, Language and Behavior), and so f o r t h . H o w ever, aside f r o m this, a n d b y i g n o r i n g subtle differences, the positions w h i c h these groups take can be s u m m a r i l y characterized i n the f o l l o w i n g w a y : their general tendency is anti-metaphysical—some consider metaphysics impossible, others t h i n k that i t is meaningless, t h a t its statements are tautologies or p u r e l y " e m o t i v e " or w i t h o u t verifiable m e a n i n g ; they are " e m p i r i c i s t s " i n a new sense o f the w o r d — t h e s e movements are sometimes called " l o g i c a l e m p i r i c i s m " o r " l o g i c a l p o s i t i v i s m " or " n e o p o s i t i v i s m , " a n d sometimes " s c i e n t i f i c a l i s m " o r " p h y s i c a l i s m , " a n d they t e n d t o w a r d the m a t h e m a t i z a t i o n o f t h o u g h t . I n E n g l a n d there has been a d o m i n a n t belief t h a t the m a j o r i t y o f philosophical problems, i n c l u d i n g philosophical statements, are meaningless a n d due merely to imperfections o f language, w h i c h makes i t obligatory to undertake a clarification o f the questions b y means o f " linguistic analysis." N a t u r a l l y , philosophy has
402
English-Language
Philosophy
undertaken such clarification at a l l times, b u t present-day English thought, p a r t i c u l a r l y i n O x f o r d , claims t h a t philosophy is confined to such c l a r i f i c a t i o n . M a n y o f these thinkers believe that any scientific statement can always be reduced to a physical statement, t h a t is, one that says t h a t such-and-such a n event happened i n such-and-such a place at such-and-such a t i m e ; i n other w o r d s , to a pure statement o f fact. T h i s a t t i t u d e leads to behaviorism o r the description o f conduct, a n d i n sociology to a social behaviorism. These positions rest o n a rather a r b i t r a r y idea o f metaphysics t h a t is identified w i t h certain very special forms o f i t or, rather, w i t h the conception o f i t t h a t these thinkers i n v e n t ; o n the other h a n d , m a n y o f their affirmations are a n y t h i n g b u t e m p i r i c a l , a n d cannot be j u s t i f i e d o n the basis o f their o w n suppositions. I n general, the analysis o f " s t a t e m e n t s " ignores the factor t h a t makes t h e m philosophical statements, a n d this type o f t h o u g h t tends to raise objections r a t h e r t h a n practice philosophy. A p a r t f r o m this, m a n y o f these efforts are interesting c o n t r i b u t i o n s to the c l a r i f i c a t i o n o f certain questions. T h e increase i n relations between E u r o p e a n d the U n i t e d States i n the last t w e n t y years has been enormous, a n d is steadily being accelerated. Phenomenology; Heidegger's w o r k ; secondarily, t h a t o f the existentialists ; Ortega's w o r k t h r o u g h numerous translations ; the presence o f E t i e n n e Gilson a n d Jacques M a r i t a i n — a l l these c o n t r i b u t e to re-establishing the complexity o f p h i l o s o p h y i n the U n i t e d States a n d o v e r c o m i n g the onesidedness o f the English influence t h a t h e l d sway for several decades. O n the other h a n d , A m e r i c a n t h o u g h t is becoming m o r e a n d m o r e w e l l k n o w n i n E u r o p e . I t is to be h o p e d t h a t the c o m m u n i c a t i o n between the t w o sections o f Western philosophy, w h i c h was b r o k e n at the t i m e o f the Renaissance a n d w h i c h since t h e n has been evident o n l y i n a few discontinuous instances, w i l l be i n creased. O n l y i n this w a y can we g a i n f u l l possession o f the Western philosophical t r a d i t i o n .
Husserl s 3
Phenomeno
H U S S E R L A N D H I S S C H O O L . E d m u n d Husserl was b o r n i n 185g—in the same year as B e r g s o n — a n d died i n 1938. H e is Brentano's most i m p o r t a n t a n d o r i g i n a l p u p i l . Husserl was a professor i n Göttingen a n d later i n F r e i b u r g . H e devoted himself to the study o f mathematics a n d , r a t h e r late i n life, t o philosophy. I n 1900 he published the first e d i t i o n o f his Logische Untersuchungen ( L o g i c a l Investigations), w h i c h renewed and transformed philosophy; i n 1913 there appeared the first v o l u m e — t h e o n l y one published d u r i n g his l i f e t i m e — o f his Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie undphänomenologischen Philosophie) (Ideas for a P u r e Phenomenology a n d Phenomenological P h i l o s o p h y ) . His p r i n c i p a l works also i n c l u d e Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft (Philosophy as S t r i c t K n o w l e d g e , 1911), Formale und transzendentale Logik ( F o r m a l a n d Transcendental L o g i c , 1929) a n d Méditations cartésiennes (1931). H i s p u p i l Heidegger p u b l i s h e d the Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren £eitbewusstseins (Lectures for the Phenomenology o f the I n t e r n a l Consciousness o f T i m e ) . After his death, several essays a n d the b o o k entitled Erfahrung und Urteil (Experience a n d J u d g m e n t , 1939) w e r e published. M u c h o f Husserl's w o r k is still u n p u b l i s h e d or i n the process o f being p u b l i s h e d , a n d this precludes a n exposition of his last doctrines, p a r t i c u l a r l y w i t h respect to the genealogy o f logic. T h e Husserl Archives i n t h e U n i v e r s i t y o f L o u v a i n c o n t a i n almost 45,000 pages—mostly i n s h o r t h a n d — o f unpublished materials. T h e f o l l o w i n g w o r k s have recently been published : the o r i g i n a l text o f the Cartesianische Meditationen; Die Idee der Phänomenologie o f 1907; a new enlarged e d i t i o n o f the first book o f the Ideen and the second a n d t h i r d books o f 4°3
Husserl's
Phenomenology
t h a t w o r k ; the i m p o r t a n t b o o k Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie ( T h e Crisis o f the E u r o p e a n Sciences a n d Transcendental Phenomenology); t w o volumes o f the Erste Philosophie (First Philosophy), a n d most recently, v o l u m e I X o f the Husserliana series: Phänomenologische Psychologie (Phenomenological Psychology). Husserl derives essentially f r o m B r e n t a n o ; therefore, his p h i l o sophical t r a d i t i o n is the same as Brentano's: Catholic, S c h o l a s t i c — i n short, Greek. W e must also note the influence o f Bolzano, o f the E n g l i s h p h i l o s o p h e r s — H u m e i n p a r t i c u l a r — a n d most m a r k e d l y , of L e i b n i z ; a n d also, of course, the influence of K a n t i a n i s m . Husserl is also related to Brentano's other pupils, especially to A n t o n M a r t y a n d Alexius M e i n o n g . T h e phenomenological school, famous for its h i g h standards o f scholarship, precision and fecundity, has arisen a r o u n d the figure of Husserl; its j o u r n a l , the. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung (Yearbook for Philosophy a n d Phenom e n o l o g i c a l I n v e s t i g a t i o n ) , was first published i n 1913. T h e phenomenologists include the most i m p o r t a n t philosophers o f G e r m a n y , n o t a b l y M a x Scheler a n d Heidegger, w h o represent a n o r i g i n a l position w i t h i n phenomenology.
1.
IDEAL
OBJECTS
P S Y C H O L O G I S M . Phenomenology makes its appearance j u s t as the t w e n t i e t h century commences. As we have said, Husserl's Logical Investigations was published i n 1900; i n this w o r k Husserl says he is dealing w i t h "descriptive p s y c h o l o g y " ; the t e r m phenomenology does not yet appear. T h i s book represents a decisive step i n the restoration o f a u t h e n t i c philosophy. I n order to understand phenomenology, one must locate oneself i n the h i s t o r i c a l framework i n w h i c h i t appears. I n 1900 there was no ruling philosophy. T h e idealist t r a d i t i o n had been lost ever since the years i n w h i c h positivism h e l d s w a y ; philosophical anarchy p r e v a i l e d . T h e r e were o n l y certain trends t h a t opposed metaphysics, w h i c h they considered something to be s h u n n e d ; English-style associationist psychology was d o m i n a n t . T h i s psychology had i n f i l t r a t e d the p h i l o sophical doctrines, c o n t a m i n a t i n g t h e m w i t h psychologism. Psychologism is the a t t i t u d e b y w h i c h a philosophical discipline is reduced to psychology. F o r example, the psychologists understand logic to be a normative discipline of the psychical acts o f t h i n k i n g . L o g i c w o u l d thus consists o f rules o n how to t h i n k w e l l .
Husserl opposes this psychologism a n d devotes the first v o l u m e o f
Ideal
Objects
his Investigations to c o m b a t i n g a n d overcoming it. I f he h a d n o t b r o k e n w i t h psychologism, he w o u l d n o t have been able to create a p h i losophy. A m i n u t e l y detailed controversy was necessary, the fine points o f w h i c h need n o t concern us, since psychologism is no longer a problem. H e r e as w e l l as elsewhere, Husserl's m e t h o d consists o f m a k i n g descriptions. Husserl agrees t h a t logic deals w i t h ideas, concepts, j u d g m e n t s , a n d the like, b u t he does n o t agree t h a t i t is concerned w i t h things of a psychological n a t u r e ; r a t h e r , he says that logic always deals w i t h ideal objects. Husserl takes a single case a n d observes its m e a n i n g : for example, the p r i n c i p l e of c o n t r a d i c t i o n . A c c o r d i n g to the psychologists, this p r i n c i p l e meant t h a t m a n c o u l d not conceive t h a t A is A a n d n o t - A . Husserl rejects this view a n d says that the m e a n i n g o f the p r i n c i p l e is t h a t i f A is A , i t cannot be n o t - A . T h e p r i n c i p l e of contrad i c t i o n does n o t refer to the possibility o f man's conceiving somet h i n g , b u t to the t r u t h o f the concept, to the behavior o f objects. T h e p r i n c i p l e o f c o n t r a d i c t i o n , a n d likewise a l l the other principles of logic, have objective v a l i d i t y . O n one h a n d , psychologism can be skepticism; o n the other h a n d , i t tends t o w a r d relativism. Skepticism denies that t r u t h can be k n o w n ; r e l a t i v i s m allows t h a t a n y t h i n g can be true, b u t t h a t t r u t h is relative: there is a r e l a t i v i s m o f i n d i v i d u a l s a n d a relativism o f the species; t r u t h — t h e v a l i d i t y o f the p r i n c i p l e s — w o u l d be l i m i t e d to the h u m a n species, w h i c h cannot conceive t h a t A is A and n o t - A . Husserl refutes r e l a t i v i s m , n o t only the r e l a t i v i s m o f individuals, b u t also t h a t of the species; he says t h a t i f the angels understand A, being a n d truth to mean the same things we understand t h e m to mean, they must say t h a t A cannot be A a n d n o t - A at the same t i m e . I t is a question o f a n a p r i o r i a n d absolute v a l i d i t y t h a t is independent of the psychological conditions o f t h o u g h t . Therefore Husserl calls for, i n contraposition to psychologistic logic, a. pure logic of ideal objects, that is, of the principles of logic, o f the pure logical laws a n d meanings. P H E N O M E N O L O G Y . Phenomenology is a science of i d e a l objects. I t is therefore a n a p r i o r i science; f u r t h e r m o r e , i t is a universal science,
because i t is a science o f the essences
of experiences.
An
experience
is any psychical act; i f phenomenology involves the study o f all experiences, i t must also involve the study of the objects of the experiences, because the experiences are intentional, a n d reference to an object is essential to t h e m . Therefore, phenomenology, w h i c h comprises the study o f experiences a n d their i n t e n t i o n a l objects, is a p r i o r i a n d universal. (Erlebnis)
I D E A L BEING.
I d e a l objects are distinguished f r o m real objects b y a n
4o6
Husserl's
Phenomenology
essential characteristic. I d e a l b e i n g is non-temporal, whereas real being is subject to t i m e , is hie et nunc, here and n o w . T h e desk as w h i c h I a m w r i t i n g is here i n the r o o m a n d , above a l l , at this m o m e n t ; b u t the n u m b e r three, the circle a n d the principle o f c o n t r a d i c t i o n have a v a l i d i t y apart f r o m t i m e . Therefore, ideal objects are species; they do not have the p r i n c i p l e of i n d i v i d u a t i o n w h i c h is the here a n d now. I n Greek, idea is t h a t w h i c h is seen; this is also t r u e oí species i n L a t i n . I d e a l objects are thus species or, using another t e r m , essences. P R O B L E M S O F I D E A L B E I N G . F o r Husserl, ideal objects are eternal, or r a t h e r non-temporal. B u t i t m i g h t be asked w h e r e they are located. Husserl finds this question meaningless. T h e r e are three possible hypostases, a l l of w h i c h he rejects:
(1) T h e psychological hypostasis, w h i c h w o u l d consist i n locating ideal objects i n the m i n d ; t h e i r existence w o u l d be m e n t a l , they w o u l d exist in my
thought.
(2) T h e metaphysical hypostasis—which is t h a t o f Platonism, for e x a m p l e — i n w h i c h the ideas are entities located i n a n i m m a t e r i a l place. (3) T h e A u g u s t i n i a n or theological hypostasis, i n w h i c h the ideas are located i n the m i n d of G o d , w h o is eternally t h i n k i n g t h e m . Husserl, sharing the fear o f metaphysics w h i c h was the inheritance of his era, avoids a l l semblance of i t and says t h a t i d e a l objects merely have validity. This p o i n t p r o v o k e d a controversy over t r u t h between Husserl and Heidegger. Husserl's opinion was t h a t N e w t o n ' s f o r m u l a , for example, w o u l d be t r u e even i f no one h a d conceived i t . Heidegger said t h a t this is meaningless, t h a t the t r u t h o f the f o r m u l a w o u l d not exist i f there had been no existence to conceive i t . I f there h a d been no m i n d — e i t h e r h u m a n or n o n - h u m a n — t o conceive i t , there w o u l d be heavenly bodies, there w o u l d be m o t i o n , i f y o u w i s h , b u t there w o u l d be no truth of Newton's f o r m u l a , nor any other t r u t h . T r u t h needs someone to conceive i t , to discover i t (alétheia), w h e t h e r m a n , angel or God.
2.
MEANINGS
W O R D , M E A N I N G A N D O B J E C T . W e have seen t h a t phenomenology deals w i t h meanings. L e t us see h o w this is to be understood. L e t us t h i n k o f a w o r d , table, for example. W e have a n u m b e r o f things here. First of all, a physical, acoustical p h e n o m e n o n , the sound of the w o r d ; b u t this alone is n o t a w o r d . A physical phenomenon m a y be a sign: for example, a r e d c l o t h is a sign of danger. B u t this does not suffice, either; to be a sign does not exhaust the being o f a w o r d ,
The
Analytic
and the Synthetic
407
because expressions m a y have t w o functions, one communicative, which w o u l d encompass the sign-function, a n d another w h i c h is the " solitary life o f the s o u l . " I do n o t make signs to myself i n order to understand what I am thinking. T h a t w h i c h makes a w o r d be a w o r d is meaning (as early as Aristotle a w o r d was defined as &phone semantike). W h a t is m e a n i n g ? Is it located w i t h i n the w o r d ? O b v i o u s l y not. Different words m a y have a single m e a n i n g (words i n different languages, for example). I t w o u l d then seem t h a t meaning is the object; b u t this is n o t so, because at times the object does not exist, a n d cannot be the m e a n i n g — f o r example, w h e n I say " a squared c i r c l e . " Meanings are ideal objects. I t is meaning t h a t refers to the object; i t intervenes between the w o r d a n d the object. Meanings consist o f references to i n t e n t i o n a l objects, not necessarily real objects or necessarily ideal, b u t objects w h i c h m a y be non-existent—for example, i f I speak of " a regular p e n t a h e d r o n . " T h i s object does not exist; i t is n e i t h e r real nor i d e a l , b u t impossible, a n d yet the expression has a m e a n i n g w h i c h refers to a n i n t e n t i o n a l object. N o w , whether the object exists or n o t is another question w h i c h is n o t of interest here. I N T E N T I O N A N D I M P L E T I O N . I f I hear or read a n expression, I understand i t ; b u t there are t w o very different ways of understanding. O n e is simple understanding o f the expression; the other is an i n t u i t i v e representation o f meanings. Husserl calls the mere understanding o f a m e a n i n g symbolic thought or significative intention. T h e i n t u i t i v e representation of meanings he calls intuitive thought or significative impletion (or "filling"). I n the first case there is a mention, a mere allusion; i n the second, an intuition: this is a n i n t u i t i o n o f essences. Phenomenology, w h i c h is a descriptive science, describes essences, never objects.
Therefore, i n o r d e r to express a n y t h i n g , a m e a n i n g is needed; a m e a n i n g is superimposed u p o n the p h e n o m e n o n o f the expression, and w h e n this m e a n i n g is filled With content b y means of i n t u i t i o n , we have the apprehension of the essence.
3.
T H E ANALYTIC AND T H E SYNTHETIC
W H O L E A N D P A R T . Husserl's t h i r d investigation is a study o f the w h o l e and its p a r t s ; this study is extremely i m p o r t a n t for the comprehension of phenomenology. T h e w o r d whole suggests something composed of parts. Conversely, part suggests a component of a whole. Husserl distinguishes between independent parts ( w h i c h m a y exist b y themselves, like the leg o f a table) a n d non-independent parts ( w h i c h c a n n o t exist i n isolation, like the color or the extension o f the t a b l e ) .
Husserl's
Phenomenology
Husserl calls the independent parts pieces a n d the n o n - i n d e p e n d e n t parts moments: extension, color, f o r m , a n d so o n . W i t h i n moments, t w o types m a y b e distinguished: ( i ) color, for example, w h i c h is located in the t a b l e ; a n d (2) the s i m i l a r i t y between this table a n d another one, a s i m i l a r i t y w h i c h is n o t l o c a t e d in t h e table. C o l o r is a trait of a t h i n g , s i m i l a r i t y is a relationship. I M P L I C A T I O N A N D " C O - P L I C A T I O N . " Here we r u n i n t o the p r o b l e m of w h a t i t is t h a t unites the parts. C o r p o r e a l i t y does n o t occur alone, but occurs together w i t h color, extension, and the like. Husserl speaks of two basic types of unions: (1) W e say: a l l bodies are extended. Corporeality a n d extension go together. Body implies extension; to i m p l y something means to i n c l u d e i t ; the t h i n g i m p l i e d is a t r a i t o f t h a t w h i c h implies i t . A m o n g the traits oí body is t h a t of being extended; b e i n g a d i a m o n d i m p l i e s b e i n g a stone. T h i s is w h a t K a n t calls a n analytic judgment, a n d is today generally called implication. (2) O r t e g a gave the n a m e o f " co-plication " (complicación) to t h a t relationship b y w h i c h one p a r t is united to another b u t is n o t contained w i t h i n i t . Color, for example, " c o - p l i c a t e s " extension; a n unextended color cannot exist. Husserl calls this same r e l a t i o n s h i p "founding" (Fundierung). F o u n d i n g m a y be reversible or irreversible. T r a i t A a n d t r a i t B m a y require each other's presence m u t u a l l y , o r else A m a y r e q u i r e B, b u t n o t conversely. T h e t r a i t color " c o - p l i c a t e s " the t r a i t extension, b u t n o t the other w a y a r o u n d ; o n the other h a n d , there is no r i g h t w i t h o u t a left, a n d vice versa. " C o - p l i c a t i o n " can t h u s be either unilateral or bilateral. A N A L Y T I C A N D S Y N T H E T I C J U D G M E N T S . Husserl speaks o f a n a l y t i c and synthetic j u d g m e n t s w i t h m u c h greater precision t h a n K a n t . A n a l y t i c j u d g m e n t s are those i n w h i c h the predicate is i m p l i e d i n the subject. Synthetic j u d g m e n t s are those i n w h i c h the p r e d i c a t e is n o t i m p l i e d i n , b u t added to, the subject. I t is obvious t h a t a n a l y t i c j u d g m e n t s are a p r i o r i . B u t K a n t speaks o f a p r i o r i s y n t h e t i c j u d g ments. Husserl finds t h a t such j u d g m e n t s are those i n w h i c h the subject " c o - p l i c a t e s " the p r e d i c a t e ; i n such j u d g m e n t s there is a " f o u n d i n g " relationship between the subject and the p r e d i c a t e .
4.
CONSCIOUSNESS
P h e n o m e n o l o g y is a descriptive
science
of the essences of pure
consciousness.
W h a t is consciousness ? Husserl distinguishes three w a y s o f u n d e r standing this t e r m : (1) As the
aggregate
of all
experiences:
the u n i t y of the consciousness.
Consciousness
(2)
T h e w a y the t e r m is understood w h e n one speaks o f being of a t h i n g , taking it into account. I f I see a t h i n g , seeing i t is a n act of m y consciousness (in the first sense); b u t i f I realize t h a t I see i t , I a m conscious (in the second sense) of h a v i n g seen i t . (3) Consciousness understood as a n intentional experience. T h i s is the p r i m a r y sense of the t e r m . conscious
I N T E N T I O N A L E X P E R I E N C E . T h i s is a psychical act w h i c h consists o f m o r e t h a n b e i n g a n a c t : i t refers to a n object. W h e t h e r o r n o t t h e object exists, as a n intentional object i t is something distinct f r o m t h e psychical act. A specific i n t e n t i o n a l experience has t w o groups o f elements: intentional essence a n d non-intentional contents (sensations, feelings, a n d so o n ) ; these contents i n d i v i d u a l i z e t h e experiences—for example, t h e perception o f a r o o m f r o m different viewpoints. T h a t w h i c h does n o t differ is t h e intentional essence, w h i c h is composed o f t w o elements: quality (the characteristic of the act w h i c h makes the experience be the experience of this object a n d in this manner) a n d matter. I f I say " t h e v i c t o r of J e n a " a n d " the vanquished a t W a t e r l o o , " I have t w o representations o f a single i n t e n t i o n a l object ( N a p o l e o n ) ; b u t the matter is different, since i n one case I a p p r e h e n d N a p o l e o n as the v i c t o r a n d i n the other as the vanquished. L e t us s u m u p this explanation d i a g r a m matically:
intentional essence Intentional experience
. .. , non-intentional contents
("quality (^matter fsensations . < reelings [_ drives
intentional object J
Husserl distinguishes between t h e sensory matter, o r vXrj, a n d the i n t e n t i o n a l f o r m , or / x o p ^ r j , a n d between the i n t e n t i o n a l act, or nôesis, and the objective content to w h i c h the act refers, or nôema. P H E N O M E N O L O G I C A L R E D U C T I O N . W e have reached the basic aspect of phenomenology, w h a t is called phenomenological hroxq (abstent i o n ) . T h i s consists i n t a k i n g a n experience a n d " b r a c k e t i n g " i t (Einklammerung)
or " disconnecting " i t
(Ausschaltung).
T h e r o o t o f this is to be f o u n d i n Husserl's idealism. I d e a l i s m h a d reduced i n d u b i t a b l e reality to processes o f consciousness. Brentano had said t h a t i n t e r n a l perception is self-evident, adequate a n d i n f a l lible. Husserl follows Brentano's lead, b u t makes a change. W e have a perception ; for Husserl, w h a t is i n d u b i t a b l e is the perception as such ; the perception of a table consists i n m y apprehending i t as existing, as
/ilo
Husserl's
Phenomenology
real. I t is this, the belief t h a t accompanies i t , t h a t differentiates percept i o n f r o m other experiences—for example, f r o m a mere representat i o n . B u t i n order n o t to leave the r e a l m o f the i n d u b i t a b l e , instead o f saying: " I a m seeing this table, w h i c h exists," I o u g h t to say: " I have a n experience, a n d one of its characteristics is m y belief i n the existence of the t a b l e " ; b u t the belief always figures as a characteristic o f the experience. Husserl calls this process o f b r a c k e t i n g phenomenological reduction
or
epokhe.
These experiences are, after a l l , m i n e . A n d w h a t a m I ? Phenomenological r e d u c t i o n must also extend to m y ego, a n d the phenomenologist must also " s u b m i t " to epokhe as a psychophysical subject, as an existential p o s i t i o n ; a l l t h a t remains is the pure ego, w h i c h is n o t a historical subject i n the here a n d now, b u t the focus o f the experience " r a y s . " T h i s is pure or phenomenologically reduced consciousness. T h u s , we now have the experiences of pure consciousness. But this is n o t enough. W e must take a f u r t h e r step. T h e phenomenologist carries o u t phenomenological r e d u c t i o n , a n d once he is left w i t h experiences he must raise himself to essences (eidetic reduction) . E S S E N C E S . I t is impossible to describe a n y object whatsoever because i t has a n i n f i n i t e n u m b e r o f traits. B u t b y means o f eidetic r e d u c t i o n one m a y m a k e the transition f r o m experiences to their essences. W h a t are the essences ? Husserl gives a rigorous d e f i n i t i o n : The
aggregate
essence of the
of all
the traits joined
together
by founding
constitutes
the
experience.
Let us t h i n k of a t r i a n g l e ; I take one t r a i t , its b e i n g e q u i l a t e r a l ; this t r a i t is j o i n e d b y " c o - p l i c a t i o n , " or " f o u n d i n g , " to its being equiangular, a n d i n this w a y to m a n y other t r a i t s ; a l l of t h e m together constitute the essence of the equilateral t r i a n g l e . Husserl distinguishes between definite a n d indefinite m a n i f o l d s ; i n the former, w h e n c e r t a i n of their elements have been d e t e r m i n e d , the rest can be rigorously deduced. T h i s is w h a t occurs w i t h m a t h e m a t i c a l essences: i f I d e t e r m i n e the traits " p o l y g o n w i t h three sides," the entire essence of the t r i a n g l e can be rigorously deduced f r o m this. O n e cannot reach the essence of the other k i n d o f m a n i f o l d so s i m p l y or so completely. 5.
P H E N O M E N O L O G Y AS A M E T H O D A N D AS A N I D E A L I S T
THESIS
THE C O M P L E T E D E F I N I T I O N . I f we gather together the characteristics o f phenomenology w h i c h we have been discovering, we find t h a t i t is a descriptive eidetic science of the essences of experiences of pure
Phénoménologie
al
Philosophy
411
T h e m e a n i n g o f this abstruse definition is already transp a r e n t to us. W e now see w h y phenomenology is a n a priori and universal science. I t is a p r i o r i i n its fullest sense, because i t describes o n l y essences (that is, ideal a n d n o t e m p i r i c a l objects) o f the experiences o f a consciousness w h i c h is itself not e m p i r i c a l but pure a n d thus also a p r i o r i . Phenomenology is universal because i t is concerned w i t h a l l experiences, a n d since experiences refer to their objects, intentional objects are encompassed w i t h i n phenomenological considerations; t h a t is, all that exists for the phenomenologist is i n c l u d e d . consciousness.
T H E M E T H O D . T h i s m e t h o d , w h i c h we have explained, leads us to the knowledge o f essences, w h i c h is t r a d i t i o n a l l y the goal o f p h i losophy. I t is a self-evident knowledge w h i c h is based o n intuition; this, however, is not a sensible b u t an eidetic i n t u i t i o n , t h a t is, a n i n t u i t i o n o f essences (eidos). F r o m the i n t u i t i o n o f a single case I raise myself to the i n t u i t i o n o f its essence b y means o f phenomenological r e d u c t i o n . T h e example w h i c h serves as m y basis m a y be a n act o f perception or s i m p l y a n act o f i m a g i n a t i o n ; the q u a l i t y o f the act is o f no i m p o r t a n c e to the eidetic i n t u i t i o n .
T h i s phenomenological m e t h o d is the method of present-day philosophy. As a m e t h o d , phenomenology is a b r i l l i a n t discovery w h i c h opens a free p a t h to philosophy. I t is the p o i n t o f departure f r o m w h i c h one necessarily sets out. B u t i t is n o t j u s t a m e t h o d : there is a falsity at the v e r y core o f phenomenology, a n d this is its metaphysical significance. P H E N O M E N O L O G I C A L I D E A L I S M . Husserl wishes to a v o i d metaphysics at a l l costs; this a t t e m p t is futile, because philosophy is metaphysics. A n d , i n fact, Husserl is i n d u l g i n g i n metaphysics w h e n he affirms that p u r e consciousness is the f u n d a m e n t a l reality. Husserl is a n idealist; i n his w o r k idealism attains its most acute a n d refined f o r m . B u t this position is untenable; idealism, i n this, its final a n d most perfect phase, shows its i n t e r n a l c o n t r a d i c t i o n . I f we t h i n k phenomenology t h r o u g h p r o f o u n d l y , we w i l l leave its d o m a i n . This is w h a t the metaphysics o f the last few years has done. W h e n phenomenology is f u l l y achieved, i t carries us beyond Husserl's t h o u g h t to other forms i n w h i c h the o r i g i n a l eidetic a n d descriptive science becomes t r u e philosophy i n its fullest a n d most precise f o r m : metaphysics.
6.
PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY
P H I L O S O P H Y AS A P R E C I S E S C I E N C E . W i t h regard to the content o f philosophy, Husserl renews the o l d d e m a n d o f Socrates a n d Plato, o f Descartes a n d K a n t , for the establishment o f philosophy as a strict and definitive science. O n c e a g a i n , there is a refusal to a t t r i b u t e u l t i m a t e
Husserl's
Phenomenology
r e a l i t y to existing p h i l o s o p h y : i t is n o t , Husserl says, t h a t p h i l o s o p h y is a n imperfect science, b u t t h a t i t is n o t yet a science. T h e t w o chief obstacles t h a t it encounters i n its historical surroundings are naturalism — a result o f the discovery o f n a t u r e — w h i c h starts o u t f r o m thetic suppositions, f r o m existential " p o s i t i o n s , " a n d historicism—a result of the discovery of h i s t o r y — w h i c h leads to a skeptical a t t i t u d e o f a relativist f o r m . By f o l l o w i n g these, philosophy becomes Weltan¬ schauungsphilosophie, philosophy of w o r l d views, whereas Husserl calls for philosophy as a strict science. T h e p o i n t of departure, n a t u r a l l y , must be i n t e n t i o n a l i t y . A l l consciousness is " consciousness o f , " a n d the study of consciousness, as w e have already seen, includes the study o f its meanings a n d its i n t e n t i o n a l objects. W h e n every existential position is e l i m i n a t e d b y means o f cnoyf¡, we get a phenomenology o f consciousness. I n the psychical r e a l m , understood i n this sense, there is no d i s t i n c t i o n between phenomenon a n d b e i n g ; this gives phenomenology a c e r t a i n "absoluteness," w h i c h , o f course, excludes a l l positions or theses. Phenomenological i n t u i t i o n leads to the c o n t e m p l a t i o n o f essences; essences are something absolutely given, b u t as essential being (Wesenssein), never as existence (Dasein). " O n l y a really f u n d a m e n t a l a n d systematic p h e n o m e n o l o g y , " Husserl says, " c a n give us comprehension o f the p s y c h i c a l . " T h e r e fore, psychology is very closely related to philosophy; this is the kernel of t r u t h t h a t was latent i n the erroneous psychologist p o s i t i o n : the tendency t o w a r d a phenomenological establishment of philosophy. I D E A O F T H E W O R L D A N D S C I E N C E . T h e great philosophies o f the past h a d a double concern: w i t h science a n d w i t h the concept o f the w o r l d . B u t this situation has changed since the f o u n d a t i o n of a " t i m e less universitas of precise sciences"; n o w , Husserl says, there is a sharp d i s t i n c t i o n between the concept of the w o r l d a n d science. T h e " i d e a " of the f o r m e r is different for each e r a ; the idea o f the latter is timeless ( " s u p r a t e m p o r a l " ) , a n d is n o t l i m i t e d b y any relationship w i t h the spirit of t i m e . O u r life goals are of two classes: some are for t i m e , others for e t e r n i t y ; science is concerned w i t h absolute, n o n - t e m p o r a l values. O n e cannot abandon eternity i n favor o f t i m e . O n l y science can d e f i n i t i v e l y overcome the necessity w h i c h arises f r o m science. C o n cepts o f the w o r l d m a y differ a m o n g themselves; o n l y science can decide, a n d its decision, Husserl says, bears the seal o f e t e r n i t y . T h i s science is one value a m o n g others w h i c h are equally j u s t i f i e d ; i t is i m p e r s o n a l , a n d its q u a l i t y o u g h t to be the clarity w h i c h belongs to theory, n o t the profundity p r o p e r to w i s d o m . O u r t i m e , Husserl says, bears the promise o f a great era, b u t i t is plagued b y negative skepti-
Phenomenological
Philosophy
413
cism wearing the mask o f positivism; i t is necessary to overcome this w i t h a true positivism, w h i c h w i l l h o l d fast o n l y to realities, w h i c h w i l l take its departure n o t f r o m philosophies b u t f r o m the things a n d problems, and w i l l thus be a science o f true principles, o f origins, o f the pi^iofiara TTUVTUIV. T h i s is the f u n c t i o n t h a t can be performed only b y the phenomenological apprehension o f essences. T R A N S C E N D E N T A L P H I L O S O P H Y . T O the extent t h a t phenomenology is philosophy a n d n o t merely a m e t h o d , i t can be defined as a new k i n d o f transcendental philosophy; i t could almost be considered a k i n d o f neo-Cartesianism, a Cartesianism t h a t has been rendered more fundam e n t a l and t h a t avoids the deviations w i t h w h i c h Descartes m a r r e d his o w n discoveries. I n effect, Husserl represents the subtlest a n d most refined f o r m o f t h a t idealism w h i c h begins w i t h Descartes.
Husserl demands the self-evidence i n w h i c h the things " themselves " are present. H o w e v e r , there is also a perfect k i n d of self-evidence, apodictic self-evidence, w h i c h confers absolute undoubtedness o n the order o f that possessed b y principles. T h e self-evidence o f the w o r l d is not apodictic; o n the other h a n d , the ego cogito is the u l t i m a t e a n d apodictically certain d o m a i n o n w h i c h a l l f u n d a m e n t a l philosophy m u s t be based. Husserl's r e t u r n to Descartes' v i e w p o i n t , to the p r i n ciple o f the cogito, stems f r o m this; however, u n l i k e Descartes, Husserl must not confuse the ego, the p u r e subject o f cogitationes, w i t h a n independent substantia cogitans, t h a t is, a h u m a n mens sive animus. Psychical life is conceived in the world; the phenomenological epokhe eliminates the existential value o f the w o r l d , brackets i t , a n d thus focuses its a t t e n t i o n o n the phenomenologically reduced transcendental ego. P U R E S C I E N C E O F T H E E G O . T h e epokhe isolates a " new a n d i n f i n i t e " sphere o f existence t h a t is accessible t h r o u g h a new f o r m o f experience, transcendental experience. Husserl states—and this is very i m p o r t a n t — t h a t to every k i n d o f real experience there corresponds something t h a t is purely fictitious, a quasi experience (Erfahrung alsob). A n absolutely subjective science thus is originated, a n d begins provisionally as a p u r e science of the ego; this leads to a transcendental solipsism w i t h w h i c h phenomenology w i l l later have to concern itself. Thanks to this peculiar transcendental experience, the ego can explicate itself indefinitely and systematically. However, this requires further explanation.
T h e basic difference between Descartes' position a n d Husserl's is the idea o f intentionality. O n e cannot be content w i t h the simple ego cogito, according to w h i c h the ego becomes a res separated f r o m a l l other reality, as Descartes believed. Since to t h i n k is always to t h i n k o f something, the precise f o r m u l a is: ego cogito cogitatum. Phenomenology
4H
Husserl's
Phenomenology
does n o t forget the w o r l d : the w o r l d remains as the cogitatum. The consciousness o f the universe is always present (mitbewusst); i t is the u n i t y o f consciousness. T h e ego o f phenomenological m e d i t a t i o n can be a spectator o f itself, a n d this " i t s e l f " comprises all o b j e c t i v i t y t h a t exists for i t such as i t exists for i t . T h e r e v e l a t i o n of the ego t h r o u g h phenomenological analysis thus comprises a l l i n t e n t i o n a l objects correlative to the acts, f r o m w h i c h every existential p o s i t i o n has, o f course, been e l i m i n a t e d . These objects exist a n d are w h a t they are o n l y as objects of a real or possible consciousness; a n d , for its p a r t , the transcendental ego (or, psychologically speaking, the soul) is w h a t i t is o n l y i n r e l a t i o n to the i n t e n t i o n a l objects. T h e ego apprehends itself as i d e n t i c a l to itself. A n d the basic f o r m of the synthesis of experienced ( " l i v e d " ) acts (each one of w h i c h has a n experienced d u r a t i o n ) is the i m m a n e n t consciousness o f t i m e . I t is a characteristic o f i n t e n t i o n a l i t y t h a t every state o f consciousness has a n i n t e n t i o n a l " h o r i z o n , " w h i c h refers t o potentialities of consciousness i n a continuous protension. T h i s h o r i z o n defines a " h a l o " of possibilities t h a t could be realized i f one were t o t u r n one's perception i n another direction. Therefore, indeterminateness is a n essential characteristic o f the cogitatum; i t is never d e f i n i t i v e l y g i v e n ; rather, particularities r e m a i n i n a state of irresolution. H o w e v e r , this ego is n o t an uncharged p o l e ; b y v i r t u e o f the laws o f w h a t Husserl calls transcendental genesis (a very i m p o r t a n t concept w h i c h was developed i n Husserl's last w r i t i n g s ) the ego acquires a new, permanent p r o p e r t y w i t h every new k i n d of act. I f I make u p m y m i n d , I a m already a n ego t h a t has made u p its m i n d i n a c e r t a i n w a y : the act passes, the decision remains. G o r r e l a t i v e l y , I t r a n s f o r m myself w h e n I abjure m y decisions a n d actions. T h i s involves the c o n s t i t u t i o n of a self, a p e r m a n e n t person, t h a t retains a " s t y l e , " a personal character. T h e self constitutes itself for itself i n the u n i t y o f a history. T h e objects a n d categories t h a t exist for the self are constituted b y v i r t u e o f the laws o f the genesis. Therefore, eidetic phenomenology, w h i c h for Husserl is a " f i r s t p h i l o s o p h y , " has t w o phases: the first, static, w i t h descriptions and systemizations analogous t o those o f n a t u r a l h i s t o r y ; the second, genetic. T h i s genesis occurs i n t w o f o r m s : active, i n w h i c h the self participates i n a creative w a y (practical reason), a n d passive, the p r i n c i p l e of w h i c h is association. I n a l l these constitutions a c t i o n is i r r a t i o n a l , b u t Husserl observes t h a t " the action itself, w i t h its irrationality, is a structural concept in the system of the concrete 'a priori.'" M O N A D O L O G I C A L I N T E R S U B J E C T I V I T Y . Husserl distinguishes between the self as a mere self-identical pole a n d s u b s t r a t u m o f the
Phénoménologie
al
Philosophy
a n d the ego i n its concrete fullness, w h i c h he designates b y the L e i b n i z i a n t e r m monad. T h e m o n a d i c ego contains the w h o l e o f conscious life, b o t h real a n d p o t e n t i a l , and its phenomenological explication coincides w i t h phenomenology i n general. H o w e v e r , this solipsism is corrected b y the fact t h a t i n me, a transcendental ego, other egos, a n d thus a n " o b j e c t i v e w o r l d " c o m m o n to everyone, are transcendentally constituted. Such a w o r l d appears, a n d i n i t occurs a philosophy c o m m o n to " a l l of u s , " one w h i c h we m e d i t a t e i n c o m m o n , habitus,
a
Philosophiaperennis.
T h e ego comprises m y very b e i n g as a m o n a d a n d the sphere formed by i n t e n t i o n a l i t y ; i n this sphere there is constituted later a n ego, as i t were, reflected i n m y o w n ego, i n m y m o n a d — t h a t is, a sort of alter ego, w h i c h is a n analogue, b u t at the same t i m e other. Consequently, i t is a question of the constitution of the other as extraneous w i t h i n the sphere of m y o w n i n t e n t i o n a l i t y . T h r o u g h its c o m m o n i n t e n t i o n a l i t y , this c o m m u n i t y of monads constitutes a single w o r l d t h a t is the same for all, and this presupposes a " h a r m o n y ' ' of the monads. S P A C E A N D T I M E . M y b o d y , w h i c h is d i r e c t l y present at every m o m e n t , establishes a n interrelationship i n m y sphere: i t is given to me i n the m o d e o f " h e r e , " oihie. E v e r y other b o d y — i n c l u d i n g m y n e i g h b o r ' s — i s i n the m o d e o f there, illic. Possible changes i n m y o r i e n t a t i o n cause there to be constituted a spatial n a t u r e , w h i c h is i n i n t e n t i o n a l relationship w i t h m y body. A n y t h i n g t h a t is present, at hand, can become here, a n d I can perceive " t h e same things "from there (Mine). T h e other seems to m e t o possess the phenomena t h a t I w o u l d have i f I were there, b u t his b o d y is given to h i m i n the f o r m o f an absolute
here.
M y experiences do n o t e n d u r e ; nevertheless, they acquire for me a value o f b e i n g , o f t e m p o r a l existence, because t h r o u g h re-presentations I r e t u r n to the o r i g i n a l t h a t is no m o r e ; these representations are unified i n a synthesis accompanied by the self-evident consciousness o f the same thing. I n the case o f the ideal objects, Husserl explains their n o n t e m p o r a l i t y as an omnitemporality, correlative to the possibility o f being p r o d u c e d a n d r e p r o d u c e d at any m o m e n t o f t i m e . A n d the coexistence of m y self and the other, of my i n t e n t i o n a l life a n d t h a t of the other, of m y realities a n d those o f the other, presupposes the creation of a commonform
of
time.
T h e r e c a n be, then, b u t one c o m m u n i t y o f monads, c o m p r i s i n g all the coexisting monads: a single objective w o r l d , or n a t u r e . A n d this w o r l d must exist i f I have w i t h i n m e structures t h a t i m p l y the coexistence of other monads. THE P R O B L E M S O F P H E N O M E N O L O G I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y . Husserl points
Husserl's
Phenomenology
o u t t w o stages i n phenomenological investigations: a " transcendental esthetic," i n a fuller sense t h a n the K a n t i a n , t h a t refers to a noematic a p r i o r i o f sensible i n t u i t i o n , a n d a theory o f experience of the other {Einfühlung). T h e u l t i m a t e o r i g i n of all a p r i o r i sciences is i n a p r i o r i a n d transcendental phenomenology. Husserl says t h a t transcendental phenomenology, systematically and completely developed, is a n authentic, concrete, universal ontology, w h i c h he also calls concrete logic of being. W i t h i n this there w o u l d be, first of a l l , a solipsist science o f the ego, a n d then a n intersubjective phenomenology. As we have already seen, Husserl, w h o was shaped by the presuppositions o f his age, eliminates metaphysics; however, this e l i m i n a t i o n is b u t p a r t l y successful. Phenomenology eliminates o n l y ingenuous metaphysics, t h a t is, metaphysics t h a t deals w i t h the '' absurd things i n themselves," a n d n o t metaphysics i n general. I n the i n t e r i o r o f the m o n a d i c sphere, a n d as an ideal possibility, there reappear for Husserl the problems o f contingent r e a l i t y , d e a t h , destiny, the " m e a n i n g " o f history, a n d so o n . T h e central problems o f philosophy occur w i t h i n the h o r i z o n o f the reduced consciousness. T h u s there is constituted a system o f phenomenological disciplines, the base o f w h i c h is not the simple a x i o m ego cogito, b u t a consciousness o f oneself, complete, i n t e g r a l a n d universal, first m o n a d i c a n d t h e n i n t e r m o n a d i c . I t is first necessary t o lose the w o r l d t h r o u g h the eTroxq i n o r d e r to recover i t later i n this act of being conscious. T h i s is the f i n a l m e a n i n g t h a t Husserl gives to phenomenology, w h i c h renews the o l d D e l p h i c precept yvwdi creavTov ( K n o w thyself) a n d at the same time St. Augustine's statement: Noliforas ire, in te redi, in inferiore nomine habitat Veritas ( D o not go outside, r e t u r n w i t h i n yourself; t r u t h dwells i n the inner man). T h e philosophy o f E d m u n d Husserl is one o f the three or four great intellectual achievements o f o u r time. Nevertheless, the fecundity a n d scope of this philosophy are still b u t little k n o w n ; this is p a r t l y due to accidental reasons, i n c l u d i n g the not inconsiderable one t h a t the greater part of Husserl's w o r k is still unpublished. T h i s m a t e r i a l has, however, been saved f r o m t h e misfortunes o f the t e r r i b l e decade t h a t followed Husserl's death a n d is preserved at the U n i v e r s i t y o f L o u v a i n . I n his last published works Husserl begins to deal w i t h new a n d very serious problems, w h i c h lead h i m to question the v e r y idea of phenomenology and w h i c h m o t i v a t e his final development, k n o w n today o n l y i n a fragmentary w a y . I t is to be hoped t h a t i n the next years there w i l l appear a series o f volumes w h i c h w i l l give us a new image o f Husserl a n d of the roads b e y o n d phenomenology sensu stricto t o w a r d
Phenomenological
Philosophy
w h i c h the p h i l o s o p h i c a l t h o u g h t o f o u r t i m e must d i r e c t itself, u n d e r Husserl's i n d i s p u t a b l e — b u t m o r e o r less r e m o t e — l e a d e r s h i p . * * For a further discussion, see Ortega, Apuntes sobre el pensamiento: su teurgiay su demiurgia (Obras Completas, V , pp. 517-19 and 540-42). See also my Introducción a la Filosofía (Reason and Life), Sections "Phenomenology" (in Chapter I V ) , " T h e concept as a function of meaning" (in Chapter V ) and " T h e problem of logic" (in Chapter V I I ) [Obras, I I ] .
Value
Theory
I t is useful to distinguish value theory (Werttheorie) f r o m the " p h i losophy o f v a l u e " (Wertphilosophie) w h i c h derives f r o m R u d o l f H e r m a n n Lotze a n d is represented p r i n c i p a l l y b y W i l h e l m W i n d e l b a n d and Heinrich Rickert. T h e science o f j u d g m e n t or values begins a p p r o x i m a t e l y at the t u r n o f the century. I t s direct sources are to be f o u n d i n Brentano's ethics a n d i n phenomenology, w h i c h also derives f r o m Brentano. Brentano's i m m e d i a t e p u p i l s — A l e x i u s M e i n o n g a n d C h r i s t i a n v o n Ehrenfels, i n p a r t i c u l a r — w e r e the first to concern themselves philosophically w i t h the p r o b l e m o f value. L a t e r , value theory was magnificently developed b y t w o great G e r m a n thinkers: M a x Scheler a n d N i c o l a i H a r t m a n n . W e must study the characteristics o f values before investigating briefly the philosophies o f Scheler a n d H a r t m a n n .
i.
T H E P R O B L E M OF V A L U E
T H E P O I N T O F D E P A R T U R E . I n Brentano, " j u s t love" was t h a t selfevident love w h i c h contains w i t h i n itself the reason for its justness. I t was the love o f a n object t h a t shows self-evidently t h a t the a p p r o p r i a t e a t t i t u d e w i t h reference to i t is to love i t . W h e n a n object makes us recognize its a u t h e n t i c q u a l i t y o f r e q u i r i n g to be loved, i t becomes the object of just love. W e are only a step away f r o m value t h e o r y : I prefer a t h i n g because I see t h a t the t h i n g has value, t h a t i t is to be valued. T h u s , values are something t h a t the things possess a n d t h a t exercise a strange power over us; they are not l i m i t e d to being at h a n d , to being 41 &
The Problem
oj
Value
419
a p p r e h e n d e d ; rather, values oblige us to esteem t h e m , to value t h e m . I m a y perhaps see something t h a t is good a n d n o t seek i t , yet I cannot h e l p b u t esteem i t . To see something as good is already to esteem i t . T h i s modest, s m a l l a n d i n t i m a t e act o f esteeming t h e m is the o n l y t h i n g t h a t values oblige us to do. T h u s v a l u e is something t h a t the things have w h i c h makes us esteem t h e m . B u t this is n o t enough. W e m u s t raise a second p r o b l e m . W e have seen t h a t there is something w h i c h merits a n d at the same t i m e requires t h e name o f v a l u e ; b u t w e do not yet k n o w a n y t h i n g about this strange r e a l i t y . T h e basic question is: W h a t are values? T h e answers g i v e n to this question have frequently been w r o n g ; value has been confused w i t h other things, a n d its true n a t u r e has r e m a i n e d visible o n l y t h r o u g h the inconsistencies of those erroneous viewpoints. T H E O B J E C T I V I T Y OF V A L U E . I t has been t h o u g h t ( M e i n o n g ) t h a t a t h i n g is o f value w h e n i t pleases us a n d , conversely, t h a t w h e n a t h i n g pleases us, i t is o f value. T h i s w o u l d mean t h a t value is subjective, based o n the pleasure w h i c h a t h i n g produces i n me. B u t i t so happens t h a t things please us because they are good—or seem good to us, because we f i n d goodness i n t h e m . T h e cause o f o u r happiness is goodness apprehended. T o be d e l i g h t e d is t o be delighted w i t h something, a n d i t is n o t o u r d e l i g h t t h a t gives v a l u e ; rather, i t is the other w a y a r o u n d : value provokes o u r d e l i g h t . O n the other h a n d , i f M e i n o n g ' s theory were true, o n l y objects t h a t existed w o u l d be o f value, since they are the o n l y objects t h a t can please us; i t turns o u t , h o w e v e r — a s Ehrenfels s a w — t h a t we value most t h a t w h i c h does n o t exist: perfect justice, complete knowledge, the h e a l t h we l a c k — i n short, ideals. T h i s obliges Ehrenfels t o correct M e i n o n g ' s t h e o r y : the things w h i c h have value are n o t the things w h i c h please us, b u t the things w h i c h we f i n d desirable. V a l u e is s i m p l y the p r o j e c t i o n o f o u r desire. I n this case as i n the f o r m e r , value is subjective; i t is something t h a t belongs not to the object, b u t to the psychical states o f the subject. H o w e v e r , b o t h o f these theories are i n c o r r e c t . I n the first place, there are certain p r o f o u n d l y unpleasant things w h i c h we feel have v a l u e : to care for a person w h o is sick w i t h the plague, to be w o u n d e d o r d i e for a noble or w o r t h y cause, a n d so on. A person m a y have a m o r e fervent desire to eat t h a n to possess a w o r k o f a r t , or to be r i c h t h a n to live a j u s t life, a n d at the same t i m e value a w o r k o f a r t or righteousness m u c h m o r e t h a n food or money. O u r v a l u a t i o n of a t h i n g is i n d e p e n d e n t of our delight a n d desire. I t is not i n t h e least subjective; i t is objective a n d is based o n the r e a l i t y o f the things. T h e w o r d s " p l e a s u r a b l e " a n d " d e s i r a b l e " have a m e a n i n g other
4-2.0
Value
Theory
t h a n t h a t w h i c h pleases a n d t h a t w h i c h is desired, a m e a n i n g w h i c h is o f m o r e interest here: t h a t w h i c h deserves to be desired. T h i s desert or m e r i t is something t h a t the things possess, a d i g n i t y w h i c h they have i n themselves, something independent of m y v a l u a t i o n . T o value a t h i n g is n o t to give value, b u t t o recognize the value w h i c h the t h i n g possesses. V A L U E S A N D GOODS. H o w e v e r , we must n o w m a k e a d i s t i n c t i o n between value a n d the t h i n g w h i c h is valued. T h e things have various types a n d degrees o f value. V a l u e is a quality o f the things, n o t the things themselves. A p a i n t i n g , a landscape a n d a w o m a n have beauty, b u t beauty is not any o f these things. T h i n g s t h a t are v a l u e d are called goods. T h u s , goods are t h e bearers of values, a n d values are realized or e m b o d i e d i n the goods. U N R E A L I T Y OF V A L U E . W e say t h a t values are qualities. T h e r e are real qualities, such as color, f o r m , size, m a t e r i a l , a n d so o n , b u t value is not a real q u a l i t y . I n a p a i n t i n g I f i n d canvas, paints a n d the depicted forms, a l l of w h i c h are elements o f the p a i n t i n g ; the p a i n t i n g also possesses beauty, b u t this is a different type of possession; beauty is a n u n r e a l q u a l i t y ; i t is n o t a t h i n g , nor an element o f a t h i n g . Besides value, there are other qualities w i t h this characteristic: alikeness, for example. T h e alikeness between t w o coins is n o t h i n g t h e coins really possess, so l i t t l e so t h a t a single c o i n cannot possess alikeness. Alikeness cannot be perceived b y the senses; rather, i t is observed b y means of a comparison w h i c h the m i n d performs; alikeness is seen b y means o f the intellect. A n d yet alikeness is perfectly objective, since I cannot say t h a t a table a n d a b o o k are a l i k e ; alikeness is a r e l a t i o n s h i p between things, w h i c h is apprehended or recognized b y the i n t e l l e c t . T h e case o f value is s i m i l a r : the m i n d apprehends value as s o m e t h i n g objective w h i c h impresses itself u p o n the m i n d , b u t something perfectly u n r e a l ; value is n o t perceived b y means o f the senses, nor is i t comprehended; i t is esteemed. T o apprehend v a l u e is, precisely, to esteem i t . CHARACTERISTICS OF V A L U E . Values present c e r t a i n characteristics w h i c h clarify even f u r t h e r their o b j e c t i v e — t h e i r i d e a l l y o b j e c t i v e — sense. I n the first place, they have polarity, t h a t is, they are necessarily positive or negative, i n contrast to real things, w h i c h have t h e characteristic o f being positive (or, i n the extreme case, the characteristic o f privation). G o o d is the opposite o f b a d , b e a u t i f u l o f u g l y , a n d so o n . T h a t is, the value " beauty " possesses a positive or negative " c h a r g e , " as do a l l the others. I n the second place, there is a hierarchy o f values: there are higher a n d lower ones; elegance is inferior to beauty, beauty t o goodness, goodness, i n t u r n , to holiness. T h e r e is thus a n objective h i e r a r c h y o f precisely graded values.
The Problem
of
Value
421
I n the t h i r d place, values possess matter, t h a t is, a u n i q u e a n d i n d i v i d u a l content. Values do not merely exist; they appear w i t h i r r e d u c i b l e contents, w h i c h one must perceive d i r e c t l y : elegance a n d holiness are t w o values w i t h different matter, a n d i t w o u l d be futile to a t t e m p t t o reduce one to the other. T h e reaction o f the m a n w h o perceives values is different according to t h e i r m a t t e r : the a p p r o p r i a t e r e a c t i o n to holiness is reverence; to goodness, respect; to beauty,pleasure, a n d so on. Therefore, i t is possible to classify values w i t h regard to their m a t t e r a n d i n accordance w i t h t h e i r h i e r a r c h y ; i n every case this classific a t i o n w i l l f o l l o w the double, p o l a r f o r m o f positive a n d negative. T h u s , there are values o f utility (capable/incapable, a b und a nt / scarce); of life (healthy/ill, strong/weak, o u t s t a n d i n g / c o m m o n ) ; o f mind (true/false, self-evident/probable); o f morality (good/bad, just/ u n j u s t ) ; of esthetics (beautiful/ugly, elegant/inelegant); o f religion (sacred/profane), a n d so f o r t h . P E R C E P T I O N O F A N D BLINDNESS T O V A L U E .
Values m a y or m a y
not
be perceived; every era possesses a sensitivity to certain values a n d loses i t or lacks i t w i t h r e g a r d to others; certain m e n are b l i n d to a p a r t i c u l a r v a l u e — f o r example, to the esthetic value or to the religious value. Values—objective realities—are discovered, j u s t as continents a n d islands are discovered; b u t at times the sight o f t h e m is clouded over a n d m a n ceases t o feel t h e i r strange force. H e ceases t o esteem t h e m , because he does n o t perceive t h e m (see O r t e g a y Gasset: cQue son los valores?
i n Complete
Works,
VI).
B E I N G A N D V A L U E . T h e value theory has insisted, perhaps excessively, o n distinguishing value f r o m being. I t is said t h a t a value does not exist, b u t t h a t something has value; t h a t a value is n o t a n ens, b u t a valens. T h i s , however, is dubious, because the question, " W h a t are values ? " is m e a n i n g f u l , a n d we cannot a v o i d the p r o b l e m of being w i t h the subterfuge o f " h a v i n g v a l u e . " A careful d i s t i n c t i o n is m a d e between the good a n d its value, b u t one should n o t forget t h a t Greek metaphysics always said t h a t being, the good a n d the one accompany one another a n d are expressed i n similar ways. T h e y are, as we have seen, the transcendentals. T h e good of a t h i n g is t h a t w h i c h the t h i n g is. Being, the good a n d the one are n o t things, b u t transcendentals, somet h i n g t h a t imbues a n d envelops a l l things a n d makes t h e m be, a n d makes t h e m be one a n d good. T h u s , i t is possible to contemplate the serious p r o b l e m o f the relationship between b e i n g a n d value, w h i c h c a n n o t be considered as t o t a l l y e l i m i n a t e d . Perhaps this ontological defect has prevented value theory f r o m a c q u i r i n g greater p r o f u n d i t y a n d i m p o r t a n c e . A few years ago, i t
Value
Theory
looked as i f value philosophy were going to be the i m p o r t a n t p h i losophy o f o u r time. T o d a y i t is clear t h a t this is not t h e case. V a l u e theory is n o w seen to be a closed chapter, one w h i c h lacks a n u l t i m a t e basis. T h e philosophy of our t i m e has t u r n e d its back o n v a l u e theory a n d has chosen a more f r u i t f u l course b y resolutely e n t e r i n g u p o n the p a t h o f metaphysics. 2.
SCHELER
L I F E A N D WORKS. M a x Scheler was b o r n i n 1874 a n d d i e d i n 1928. H e was a professor at the U n i v e r s i t y o f Cologne, a n d is one o f the most i m p o r t a n t thinkers o f our age. H i s intellectual roots are i n the w o r k o f R u d o l f C h r i s t o p h Eucken, whose p u p i l he was, a n d i n t h a t o f Bergson, b u t most o f a l l i n Husserl's phenomenology, w h i c h he adapts i n a personal w a y . Scheler entered the C a t h o l i c C h u r c h a n d i n one phase o f his life was a true apologist for C a t h o l i c i s m ; nevertheless, i n his last years he strayed f r o m o r t h o d o x y i n the d i r e c t i o n o f p a n t h e i s m . Scheler is a w r i t e r o f extreme fecundity. H i s masterpiece is the Ethics, the complete title o f w h i c h is DerFormalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik ( F o r m a l i s m i n Ethics a n d the M a t e r i a l Ethics o f V a l u e ) ; i n i t he criticizes K a n t ' s formalistic ethics a n d establishes the bases for a n ethics o f values, w i t h content. H e also w r o t e Wesen und Formen der Sympathie ( T h e N a t u r e o f S y m p a t h y ) , a revision o f a n earlier w o r k ; Das Ressentiment im Aufbau der Moralen (Resentment i n the Structure o f M o r a l i t i e s ) ; Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos ( M a n ' s Place i n the Cosmos); Die Wissensformen und die Gesellschaft ( T h e Forms o f K n o w l e d g e a n d Society); a n d the great w o r k o f his C a t h o l i c phase: Vom Ewigen im Menschen ( O n the E t e r n a l i n M a n ) . Scheier's o u t p u t was very large, a n d p a r t o f i t is n o t yet published. H i s studies i n philosophical anthropology are especially interesting. H i s book Vom Ewigen im Menschen contains t w o o f his best essays: " R e u e u n d W i e d e r g e b u r t " (Repentance a n d R e b i r t h ) a n d " V o m Wesen der Philosophic " ( O n the N a t u r e o f Philosophy). SCHELER'S PHILOSOPHY. W e cannot enter i n t o a detailed exposition o f Scheier's t h o u g h t . For one t h i n g , i t is too complex a n d copious, a n d w o u l d lead us too far beyond the l i m i t s o f this survey: Scheier's systematic t h o u g h t cannot easily be reduced to a n essential nucleus f r o m w h i c h his m a n y v a r i e d ideas c a n be shown to emanate. F o r another t h i n g , we are still too close to h i m to make h i m a subject o f the history of philosophy i n the strict sense. W e can choose either t o e x p o u n d a n d i n t e r p r e t the content o f his philosophy, or else merely t o place h i m i n his setting. I shall confine myself completely to the second course o f action.
Hartmann Scheler is a phenomenologist. F r o m its very i n c e p t i o n , phenomenology has been a n i n t u i t i v e knowledge o f essences. Scheler sets o u t to w i n mastery over essences, especially i n the areas o f m a n a n d h u m a n life a n d i n the area o f value. Scheler's c l a r i t y a n d fruitfulness i n this knowledge o f essences are r e m a r k a b l e . B u t knowledge o f essences is n o t enough. K a n t h a d already observed t h a t i n t u i t i o n w i t h o u t a concept is n o t science, a n d even t h o u g h phenomenological i n t u i t i o n is eidetic rather t h a n sensible, philosophy cannot r e m a i n content w i t h b e i n g a descriptive science, n o t even w h e n i t is describing essences; i t must be a system a n d its basis must be metaphysics. T h i s is Scheler's great f a i l i n g . H i s t h o u g h t , acute a n d clear as i t is, is n o t strictly metaphysical. M o r e o v e r , as a consequence o f this, his philosophy is deficient i n systematic u n i t y . H i s b r i l l i a n t insights i l l u m i n a t e various regions o f reality, b u t he lacks t h a t all-inclusive coherence w h i c h philosophic knowledge requires. Philosophic t r u t h must appear i n the f o r m o f a system i n w h i c h each t r u t h is sustained b y a l l the others. T h i s system is missing i n Scheler. T h i s makes his t h o u g h t essentially provisional. H i s p h i l o s o p h y is like a hothouse where b r i l l i a n t ideas sprout i n confusion, b u t these ideas lack roots f r o m w h i c h they can g r o w a n d acquire m a t u r e significance. A f t e r using phenomenology as a knowledge o f essences, one must place i t i n the service o f a systematic metaphysics. Scheler d i d n o t do this, b u t he prepared the w a y for present-day metaphysics. H e concentrated his a t t e n t i o n o n the themes o f m a n a n d h u m a n l i f e : his philosophy was oriented t o w a r d a philosophical anthropology w h i c h he was unable t o b r i n g t o m a t u r i t y . W h e n this tendency a c q u i r e d a systematic basis a n d became a precise metaphysics, i t l e d t o existential analytics.
3.
HARTMANN
N i c o l a i H a r t m a n n (1882-1950), a professor at B e r l i n a n d later at G o t t i n g e n , also represents a phenomenological o r i e n t a t i o n w h i c h is related to Scheler's i n its concern w i t h the problems o f value. After Scheler's great w o r k o n ethics (1913), H a r t m a n n published i n 1926 his Ethics, a n i m p o r t a n t systemization o f the ethics o f values. B u t i n a d d i t i o n , H a r t m a n n was intensely occupied w i t h the problems o f knowledge a n d ontology. Therefore we observe i n his p h i l o s o p h y its clear i n t e n t i o n to be systematic a n d to become metaphysics. H i s most i m p o r t a n t works besides the above-mentioned Ethics are Platos Logik des Seins (Plato's L o g i c o f Being), Grundziige einer Meta¬ physik der Erkenntnis ( F u n d a m e n t a l Characteristics o f a Metaphysics of
Value
Theory
K n o w l e d g e ) , Das Problem des geistigen Seins ( T h e P r o b l e m o f S p i r i t u a l Being), Die Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus ( T h e Philosophy o f German Idealism), Z Grundlegung der Ontologie ( T o w a r d a Basis for O n t o l o g y ) , Möglichkeit und Wirklichkeit (Possibility a n d R e a l i t y ) , a n d Der Aufbau der realen Welt (The Structure o f the R e a l W o r l d ) . I n 1942 he published " N e u e Wege der O n t o l o g i e " ( N e w Paths i n O n t o l o g y ) , w h i c h appeared i n a collection o f papers e n t i t l e d Systematische Philosophie, w h i c h H a r t m a n n himself edited. H i s last works to appear were Philosophie der Natur (Philosophy o f N a t u r e ) , i n 1950, a n d t w o volumes o f short essays, Kleinere Schriften. ur
Heidegger s Existential
Philoso-
L I F E A N D WORKS. M a r t i n Heidegger, w h o was b o r n i n 1889, is a professor at the U n i v e r s i t y o f F r e i b u r g i m Breisgau, where he succeeded Husserl after h a v i n g been a professor at M a r b u r g . H e is the most i m p o r t a n t G e r m a n philosopher o f the present d a y ; i n order to find a figure o f comparable stature one w o u l d have to go back to the great classic thinkers o f G e r m a n philosophy. Heidegger derives d i r e c t l y f r o m phenomenology, a n d his t h o u g h t is closely related to t h a t o f Husserl a n d Scheler; b u t o n the other h a n d , he has ties w i t h the most precise t r a d i t i o n o f metaphysics and especially w i t h Aristotle. H i s d o c t o r a l thesis was a study o f Duns Scotus. H e has w r i t t e n a n entire book o n the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of K a n t as a metaphysician. I n his works one observes the constant presence o f the great philosophers o f the past: the pre-Socratics, Plato, St. Augustine, Descartes, Hegel, K i e r k e g a a r d , D i l t h e y a n d Bergson, as w e l l as those m e n t i o n e d above. Heidegger's t h o u g h t has great p r o f u n d i t y a n d o r i g i n a l i t y . I t also contains great difficulties. Heidegger has created a philosophical t e r m i n o l o g y t h a t is q u i t e h a r d to understand, b u t even harder to translate. I n his a t t e m p t to express new ideas a n d to disclose h i t h e r t o neglected realities, Heidegger does not eschew a r a d i c a l reformation of the v o c a b u l a r y o f philosophy, i n order to lead us to a clearer i n t u i t i o n o f w h a t he wants us to see. F o r another t h i n g , Heidegger's philosophy is essentially incomplete. O n l y the first h a l f o f his m a j o r book has been p u b l i s h e d ; p u b l i c a t i o n o f this was followed b y a l o n g and a l most t o t a l silence, b y shorter w r i t i n g s , q u i t e different i n character a n d o r i e n t a t i o n , a n d b y the decision n o t to p u b l i s h the second 42J
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
v o l u m e . T h i s increases the difficulties o f a n exposition o f his t h o u g h t , w h i c h , strictly speaking, cannot today be c a r r i e d o u t w i t h precision a n d w i t h o u t i n d u l g i n g i n conjecture. I shall therefore have to l i m i t myself to i n d i c a t i n g Heidegger's p o i n t o f view a n d to observing a few m a j o r aspects o f his metaphysics w h i c h w i l l a i d i n the comprehension o f his meaning a n d i n the understanding o f his works. These works are n o t very extensive. Besides a dissertation o n Die Lehre vom Urteil im Psychologismus ( T h e T h e o r y o f J u d g m e n t i n Psychologism), the above-mentioned thesis, Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus (Duns Scotus' T h e o r y o f Categories a n d M e a n i n g ) a n d a lecture o n " D e r Z e i t b e g r i f f i n der Geschichtswissenschaft" ( T h e Concept of T i m e i n the Science o f H i s t o r y ) , his m a j o r w o r k is the first a n d o n l y volume of Sein und Zeit (Being a n d T i m e ) , published i n 1927. I n 1929 he published his second book, Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik ( K a n t a n d the P r o b l e m o f Metaphysics), a v e r y personal i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the K a n t i a n i s m o f the Critique of Pure Reason, understood as a basis for metaphysics. L a t e r i n the same year he p u b l i s h e d t w o pamphlets, b r i e f b u t f u l l o f content: Was ist Metaphysik? ( W h a t is Metaphysics ?) a n d Vom Wesen des Grundes ( O n the N a t u r e o f Cause). These were followed i n 1933 b y a speech: " D i e Selbstbehauptung der deutschen U n i v e r s i t ä t " ( T h e Self-Affirmation o f the G e r m a n U n i v e r sity) a n d finally, other essays: " H ö l d e r l i n u n d das Wesen der D i c h t u n g " (Hölderlin a n d the N a t u r e of P o e t r y ) — l a t e r i n c l u d e d i n the v o l u m e Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung (Elucidations o f Hölderlin's P o e t r y ) — a n d " V o m Wesen der W a h r h e i t " ( O n the N a t u r e o f T r u t h ) . I n 1947 he published a short book, Piatons Lehre von der Wahrheit. Mit einem Brief über den "Humanismus" (Plato's T h e o r y o f T r u t h , w i t h a L e t t e r o n " H u m a n i s m " ) , i n w h i c h he opposes c e r t a i n interpretations o f his philosophy, distinguishing his o w n t h o u g h t f r o m Jean-Paul Sartre's " e x i s t e n t i a l i s m . " I n 1950 there appeared a v o l u m e t i t l e d Holzwege (Forest Paths), made u p o f six studies w r i t t e n at different times: " D e r U r s p r u n g des Kunstwerkes " ( T h e O r i g i n o f the W o r k o f A r t ) , " D i e Z e i t des W e l t b i l d e s " ( T h e T i m e o f the W o r l d I m a g e ) , " H e g e l s Begriff der E r f a h r u n g " (Hegel's Concept of E x p e r i ence) , " Nietzsches W o r t ' G o t t ist t o t " ' (Nietzsche's S a y i n g , ' G o d Is D e a d ' ) , " W o z u D i c h t e r ? " ( W h a t Is the Purpose o f the Poet?) a n d " D e r Spruch des A n a x i m a n d e r " (Anaximander's M a x i m ) . I n 1953 he published the book Einführung in die Metaphysik ( I n t r o d u c t i o n to Metaphysics) a n d , later, various pamphlets a n d articles: " G e o r g T r a k l " ; " D e r F e l d w e g " ( T h e Path i n the Fields); " . . . Dichterisch w o h n e t der M e n s c h . . . " ( M a n Lives b y P o e t r y ) ; " Aus der E r f a h r u n g des D e n k e n s " ( F r o m the Experience of T h o u g h t ) ; " Z u r Seinsfrage"
The
Problem
of
Being
( T h e Question o f B e i n g ) ; " W a s ist das—die P h i l o s o p h i e ? " ( W h a t Is This T h i n g Philosophy?); and " H e b e l — d e r Hausfreund" (Hebel, the " F r i e n d o f the F a m i l y " ) ; the recent volumes o f essays Was heisst Denken? ( W h a t Is M e a n t by T h i n k i n g ? ) ; Vorträge und Aufsätze (Lectures and Essays), w h i c h includes, a m o n g other essays, " D i e Frage nach der T e c h n i k " ( T h e Question o f T e c h n o l o g y ) ; " Ü b e r w i n d u n g der M e t a p h y s i k " (Metaphysics Superseded); " L o g o s , M o i r a , A l e t h e i a " ; a n d , finally, Der Satz vom Grund ( T h e Principle o f Cause), i n 1957, a n d a l o n g , t w o - v o l u m e w o r k , Nietzsche, i n 1961.
1.
T H E P R O B L E M OF B E I N G
B E I N G A N D T I M E . T h e p r o b l e m t h a t Heidegger deals w i t h i n his investigation e n t i t l e d Sein und Zeit is the meaning of being (die Frage nach dem Sinn von Sein). H e is concerned w i t h n o t entities, b u t w i t h being. B e i n g a n d n o t h i n g else is the subject of his i n q u i r y . A n d his i n i t i a l goal is the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of time as the possible horizon for a l l intellection o f b e i n g i n general. W e must n o t forget, as others have too frequently forgotten, t h a t Heidegger p a r t i c u l a r l y insists t h a t the f u n d a m e n t a l p r o b l e m is the m e a n i n g o f being. E v e r y t h i n g else anticipates this question a n d is i n s t r u m e n t a l i n solving i t . B E I N G A N D E N T I T Y . Heidegger begins b y considering the p r o b l e m o f b e i n g as i t has been dealt w i t h i n earlier metaphysics. Ever since A r i s t o t l e , being has been understood to be transcendental, " that w h i c h is most universal o f a l l " (Metaphysics, Book I I I , 4 ) ; its universality was understood to be n o t t h a t o f the genus, as Plato believed, b u t a u n i v e r sality based o n the u n i t y of analogy. H o w e v e r , Heidegger says t h a t this concept of b e i n g is n o t the clearest; o n the c o n t r a r y , i t is the most obscure. Being (Sein) is n o t the same as e n t i t y (Seiendes). Being cannot be defined; b u t this i n itself raises the question o f its meaning. " B e i n g " is the most understandable a n d self-evident o f all concepts. Everyone understands such statements as " t h e sky is b l u e , " " I am h a p p y . " H o w e v e r , the fact t h a t we understand the everyday use o f " b e i n g " whereas its m e a n i n g a n d relationship to the e n t i t y is obscure to us, indicates t h a t being is an enigma. T h i s is w h y we are obliged to raise the question o f the m e a n i n g o f being. E v e r y ontology, Heidegger says (Sein und Ze^); b l i n d i f i t does n o t first sufficiently explain the m e a n i n g o f being a n d t h e n embrace this e x p l a n a t i o n as its f u n d a m e n t a l theme. l s
D A S E I N A N D B E I N G . I n a s m u c h as science is a n a c t i v i t y carried o n b y m a n , i t has the m o d e of being of this e n t i t y , m a n . Heidegger calls this e n t i t y Dasein. H o w e v e r , he observes t h a t science is not the o n l y mode
4z&
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
of b e i n g of Dasein, nor even the most immediate. Dasein is understood i n its b e i n g ; the understanding of being is a d e t e r m i n a t i o n of the b e i n g of Dasein. I t can therefore be said t h a t Dasein is o n t o l o g i c a l . T h e b e i n g o f Dasein is Existenz, existence. Heidegger uses the t e r m existential to describe e v e r y t h i n g relative to the structure o f existence. T h e ontological analytic o f the e n t i t y Dasein necessitates a p r i o r consideration o f existentiality, t h a t is, the mode o f being o f the e n t i t y t h a t exists. W e already see i n this the idea of being, a n d t h e analytic o f Dasein presupposes the p r i o r question o f the meaning of being in general. D A S E I N A N D W O R L D . H o w e v e r , i n the r e a l m o f the sciences, Dasein deals w i t h entities t h a t are n o t necessarily themselves Dasein. A n essential element o f Dasein, t h e n , is being in a world. T h u s , the understanding o f the being of Dasein presupposes, i n a n equally primary way, the u n d e r s t a n d i n g of the " w o r l d " a n d of the being of the e n t i t y t h a t is f o u n d w i t h i n the w o r l d . Consequently, the ontologies o f the entities t h a t are n o t themselves Dasein are based on the ontic structure o f Dasein. T h i s is w h y we must look for the fundamental ontology, the o n l y one t h a t can give rise to a l l the others, i n the existential analytic of Dasein (existenziale Analytik des Daseins). Dasein has a p r i o r i t y over a l l other entities. I t has, i n t h e first place, a n ontic p r i o r i t y : this e n t i t y is d e t e r m i n e d i n its b e i n g b y existence. Secondly, i t has a n ontological p r i o r i t y : because of its d e t e r m i n a t i o n as existence, Dasein is i n itself " ontological." A n d t h i r d l y , since Dasein is able to comprehend being w h i c h is n o t Dasein, i t has a n ontic-ontological p r i o r i t y : i t is the c o n d i t i o n for the possibility o f a l l ontologies. Therefore, there is no specific mode o f b e i n g t h a t Dasein does n o t comprehend. T H E A N A L Y T I C OF D A S E I N . T h e analytic o f Dasein is n o t o n l y i n c o m p l e t e ; i t is also provisional. I t merely reveals the b e i n g of this entity, w i t h o u t i n t e r p r e t i n g its m e a n i n g . Its mission is s i m p l y to prepare a n opening i n the necessary h o r i z o n for the p r i m a r y i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f being. N o w , the m e a n i n g o f the being o f Dasein is temporality. T h i s furnishes us w i t h the ground for the u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f the m e a n i n g o f being. I t is from the standpoint of time t h a t Dasein comprehends a n d interprets being. T i m e is the h o r i z o n for the u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f being. Therefore, philosophy's first mission is a primary explanation of time as the horizon for the understanding of being from the standpoint of temporality, as the being ofDasein. H E I D E G G E R ' S M E T H O D . T h e m e t h o d used i n connection w i t h the f u n d a m e n t a l question concerning being is phenomenological. T o Heidegger, phenomenology does n o t involve his subscribing to any " p o i n t o f v i e w " or " d i r e c t i o n , " for phenomenology is a concept of
The
Analysis
of
Dasein
method. Phenomenology does n o t describe the " w h a t " o f the object o f philosophical investigation, b u t the " h o w " o f this i n q u i r y . Heidegger understands phenomenology as a n i m p e r a t i v e to go to the things themselves, t o dispense w i t h a l l i m a g i n a r y constructions, chance discoveries a n d a p p a r e n t questions. The
w o r d " p h e n o m e n o l o g y " comes f r o m t w o Greek words, (phaindmenon) a n d Aoyo? (logos). T h e first w o r d derives f r o m phainesthai, the m i d d l e voice o f phaino, w h i c h means " to place i n the l i g h t , " i n c l a r i t y , a n d w h i c h comes f r o m the same r o o t as a>s (phos), l i g h t . Phenomenon means " t h a t w h i c h is s h o w n , " t h a t w h i c h is placed i n the l i g h t ; therefore, i t is n o t the same as appearance. Logos means a saying, a making manifest (8-qXovv); A r i s t o t l e explained i t as apophainesthai, i n w h i c h we again encounter the root o f " p h e n o m e n o n . " A n d this s h o w i n g or m a k i n g manifest is a discovering, a m a k i n g patent, a p l a c i n g i n t r u t h or ak-qdeia (aletheia). Falsity is, i n t u r n , a covering up. T h i s is the m e a n i n g o f p h e n o m e n o l o g y : a mode of access to the theme o f ontology. Ontology is possible only as phenomenology. aivoiievov
T h e m e a n i n g o f the phenomenological description o f Dasein is interpretation. Therefore, phenomenology is hermeneutics. P H I L O S O P H Y . O n t o l o g y a n d phenomenology are n o t t w o p h i l o sophical disciplines a m o n g others. T h e y are t w o descriptions w h i c h characterize philosophy b y its object a n d its method. Philosophy is universal phenomenological ontology, a n d i t begins w i t h the hermeneutics of Dasein. T h e e l a b o r a t i o n o f the problems o f being comprises t w o topics, a n d therefore the investigation is d i v i d e d i n t o t w o sections, of w h i c h o n l y a p a r t o f the first has been published. T h e o u t l i n e is as follows: First p a r t : T h e analysis o f the t e m p o r a l i t y o f Dasein a n d the e x p l a n a t i o n o f t i m e as the transcendental h o r i z o n o f the p r o b l e m o f being. Second p a r t : T h e f o u n d a t i o n for a phenomenological destruction o f the h i s t o r y o f ontology, g u i d e d b y the p r o b l e m o f t e m p o r a l i t y . T h i s is the m e a n i n g o f Heidegger's p h i l o s o p h y ; i t is, i n the f i n a l analysis, the ancient question concerning being, w h i c h has still not been answered adequately. 2.
T H E A N A L Y S I S OF D A S E I N
T H E ESSENCE O F D A S E I N . T h e e n t i t y whose analysis Heidegger undertakes is every one o f us. T h e being of this e n t i t y is always my own (je meines). T h e essence o f this e n t i t y (its quid, its was) must be understood f r o m the s t a n d p o i n t o f its b e i n g or existence; however, i t is
43°
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
necessary to i n t e r p r e t this existence i n a m e a n i n g peculiar to this e n t i t y t h a t is us, a n d n o t i n the usual sense o f t h a t w h i c h is present (Vorhandensein). T h u s , Heidegger can say: The "essence" of Dasein consists in its existence (Das " Wesen" des Daseins liegt in seiner Existenz). Dasein always implies the personal p r o n o u n : " I a m , " " y o u a r e . " Dasein is essentially its o w n possibility; therefore i t c a n " choose itself," " w i n itself," or "lose i t s e l f . " T h u s , i t has t w o modes o f b e i n g : authenticity and unauthenticity. W h e n the characteristics o f being refer to Dasein, they are called existentials, and w h e n they refer to other modes of b e i n g they are called categories. So the e n t i t y is a who (existence) or a what ( b e i n g present i n the fullest sense). Heidegger observes t h a t the a n a l y t i c o f Dasein is different f r o m a l l forms of anthropology, psychology a n d biology, a n d also p r i o r to t h e m . T h u s , i t is n o t simply t h a t Heidegger's philosophy is basically an i n q u i r y i n t o the m e a n i n g of being a n d n o t a b o u t m a n ; for previous inquiries i n t o the being of Dasein cannot be understood as anthropology either. " B E I N G - I N - T H E - W O R L D . " T h e determinations o f the being o f Dasein have to be seen a n d understood on the basis o f w h a t is called " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d " ; this is a unitary phenomenon, a n d therefore i t s h o u l d n o t be understood as a complex of the terms i n this expression. I n this expression, " i n " is n o t a spatial concept; r a t h e r , spatiality is something that is derived f r o m the p r i m a r y m e a n i n g o f " i n " a n d is based o n " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d , " the basic mode of the b e i n g of Dasein. N o r is knowledge p r i m a r y , for i t is a mode o f being o f " being-in-thew o r l d . " K n o w i n g the things is one o f the possible modes o f dealing w i t h t h e m ; however, a l l modes presuppose the p r i o r a n d f u n d a m e n t a l s i t u a t i o n o f Dasein, constitutive o f i t , w h i c h is to be, as a m a t t e r o f course, i n something t h a t is k n o w n chiefly as world. T H E W O R L D . " B e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d " (In-der-Welt-sein) c a n be f u l l y understood o n l y b y v i r t u e of a phenomenological consideration of the world. T o begin w i t h , the w o r l d is n o t the things (houses, trees, m e n , m o u n t a i n s , stars) w h i c h exist w i t h i n the w o r l d , a n d w h i c h are " w o r l d l y " (innerweltlich). N o r is the w o r l d nature, a n e n t i t y w h i c h is f o u n d i n the w o r l d a n d w h i c h can be described i n various forms a n d at various levels. N o t even the ontological i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the being o f these entities refers to the p h e n o m e n o n " w o r l d , " w h i c h is already presupposedin these modes of access to objective being. O n t o l o g i c a l l y , world is a characteristic o f Dasein itself. Heidegger mentions four different ways i n w h i c h the concept world is used: ( 1 ) W o r l d as the sum t o t a l of the e n t i t y that can exist w i t h i n the w o r l d . (2) W o r l d as a n ontological t e r m : the being o f the e n t i t y o f w h i c h we
The
Analysis
of
Dasein
are speaking; i t sometimes designates a region e m b r a c i n g a m u l t i p l i c i t y o f entities, as w h e n one speaks o f the w o r l d o f the m a t h e m a t i c i a n . (3) W o r l d as t h a t " i n w h i c h there lives " a factitious Dasein as such. (4) W o r l d as the ontologico-existential d e n o m i n a t i o n o f worldliness. M a n finds himself i n a w o r l d t h a t is n o t p r i m a r i l y present (vorhanden), b u t at hand (zuhanden). T h i s is the basis for the things' role as utensils (Z S )i subject w h i c h Heidegger has analyzed i n d e p t h . T a k i n g this as his p o i n t o f departure, he has analyzed worldliness a n d i n t e r p r e t e d the Cartesian ontology o f the w o r l d as res externa, i n o r d e r u l t i m a t e l y to study the spatiality o f existence. However, we cannot go i n t o the details of this m a t t e r here. eu
e
a
C O E X I S T E N C E . By v i r t u e o f the constitutive nature o f Dasein, there c a n be no mere subject w i t h o u t a w o r l d ; n o r can there be one ego isolated f r o m the others. T h e others coexist i n " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d . " T h e w o r l d o f Dasein is a common world (Mitwelt): to be in means to be with others, a n d this i n h e r e n t l y " w o r l d l y " being is coexistence. T h e " w h o " o f this coexistence is n o t this one or t h a t one; i t is n o t anyone i n p a r t i c u l a r , n o r is i t everyone together: i t is the impersonal, the " they " (das Man). A n existential characteristic o f the " t h e y " is t h a t i t is a n average t e r m (Durchschnittlichkeit). T h e " t h e y " fulfills Dasein i n its everyday life. " T h e ' t h e y ' is a n existential a n d i t belongs to the positive c o n s t i t u t i o n o f Dasein as a p r i m a r y p h e n o m e n o n . " A n d a u t h e n t i c being itself is a n existential m o d i f i c a t i o n of the " t h e y . " E V E R Y D A Y L I F E . O n one h a n d , Dasein is characterized b y facticity; o n the other h a n d , i t is also characterized b y openness (Erschlossenheit), the q u a l i t y o f b e i n g essentially open t o the things. However, Heidegger distinguishes t w o different modes o f " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d . " W e have, o n the one h a n d , everydayness (Alltäglichkeit), w h i c h is t r i v i a l , unauthentic existence. T h e subject o f this t r i v i a l existence is the Man, the " o n e , " the i m p e r s o n a l " t h e y . " Existence becomes t r i v i a l — i n a n unquestionable a n d necessary m a n n e r — i n the " t h e y , " i n the " a n y o n e , " a n d is a decadence orfall (Verfallen). T h e Man sees itself as fallen a n d lost i n the w o r l d . T h e constitutive mode of existence is to find oneself i n a state o f thrownness (Geworfenheit). A U T H E N T I C EXISTENCE. H o w e v e r , Dasein can overcome this everyd a y t r i v i a l i t y a n d come i n t o its o w n ; t h e n i t becomes eigentliche Existenz or authentic existence. T h e m o d e i n w h i c h this is f o u n d is anguish (Angst)—a concept o f w h i c h K i e r k e g a a r d h a d already m a d e use. T h i s anguish is n o t due to this or t h a t cause; rather, i t is caused b y nothing; he w h o is i n anguish is i n anguish over nothing. T h u s , i t is nothingness t h a t reveals itself to us i n anguish. A n d Dasein is seen t o be
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
characterized as Sorge, care, i n its p r i m a r y m e a n i n g o f concern or preoccupation. Heidegger interprets a L a t i n fable b y H y g i n u s , according to w h i c h Care made m a n a n d , i n accordance w i t h a n e d i c t o f S a t u r n ( t i m e ) , has charge of h i m w h i l e he lives. T R U T H . T h e question o f the m e a n i n g o f being is possible o n l y i f there is a n understanding o f being. ( T h i s pertains to the m o d e o f being o f the e n t i t y we call Dasein.) Being comes to mean reality. T h i s concept raises the question of the existence o f the external w o r l d , a question t h a t has been decisive i n the disputes between realism a n d i d e a l i s m ; b u t Heidegger observes t h a t the question o f whether t h e r e is a w o r l d a n d w h e t h e r its existence can be p r o v e d is meaningless, as i t is a question t h a t establishes Dasein as " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d . " Heidegger distinguishes between world as the where o f being-in (In-Sein) and "world" as a " w o r l d l y " e n t i t y . T h e n the w o r l d is essentially open (erschlossen) w i t h the being o f Dasein; a n d the " w o r l d " has also already been discovered w i t h the openness o f the w o r l d . T h i s result coincides w i t h the thesis o f realism: the e x t e r n a l w o r l d really exists. However, Heidegger makes a distinction between his thesis a n d realism; he does n o t believe, as does realism, t h a t r e a l i t y needs to be p r o v e d or can be p r o v e d . A n d w h e n idealism affirms t h a t b e i n g a n d r e a l i t y are only " i n the consciousness," i t affirms t h a t being cannot be explained b y the e n t i t y : r e a l i t y is possible o n l y i n the u n d e r s t a n d i n g o f being (Seinsverstdndnis); i n other w o r d s , for a l l entities, b e i n g is " t h a t w h i c h is t r a n s c e n d e n t a l " ; b u t i f idealism consists o f r e d u c i n g every e n t i t y to a subject or consciousness t h a t is i n d e t e r m i n a t e i n its being, t h e n i t is j u s t as ingenuous as realism. T h e forerunners o f present-day philosophy ( M a i n e de B i r a n , D i l t h e y ) defined reality as resistance. H o w e v e r , Heidegger examines this p r o b l e m i n an even more f u n d a m e n t a l way. T h e experience o f resistance, discovery b y means o f the effort o f that w h i c h resists, is ontologically possible only b y v i r t u e o f the world's openness. Resistance characterizes the being o f the " w o r l d l y " e n t i t y ; b u t i t is based i n a p r i o r w a y o n " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d , " w h i c h is open to the things. "Consciousness o f r e a l i t y " is itself a m o d e o f " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d . " I f we wished to take the cogito sum as the p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e o f the existential analytic, we w o u l d have to i n t e r p r e t the first a f f i r m a t i o n , sum, to m e a n : / am in the world. H o w e v e r , w h e n Descartes affirms the present r e a l i t y o f the cogitationes, he also affirms a n ego as a res cogitans without a world. T h u s , instead o f understanding m a n as a reality shut u p i n his o w n consciousness, the existential analytic sees h i m as a n e n t i t y w h i c h is essentially open to the things a n d w h i c h is defined b y its " being-in-the-
The
Analysis
of
Dasein
433
w o r l d " ; therefore, as a n e n t i t y w h i c h consists of transcending itself. T h e w a y was prepared for this conclusion earlier b y the discovery o f i n t e n t i o n a l i t y as a characteristic o f psychical acts, a characteristic t h a t n a t u r a l l y affects man's very being. M a n transcends himself, points to the things, is open to t h e m . As we have seen, this places the p r o b l e m o f the reality o f the external w o r l d i n a r a d i c a l l y new perspective; the external w o r l d no longer appears as something " a d d e d " to m a n , b u t as something t h a t is given along w i t h m a n . T h i s is the basis for truth. Heidegger reintroduces the ancient, t r a d i t i o n a l d e f i n i t i o n o f t r u t h as adaequatio intellectus et rei ( m a k i n g the m i n d equal to the t h i n g ) i n order to prove its inadequacy. T r u t h is p r i m a r i l y the discovery o f being i n itself (a\r/8eia). A n d this discovery is possible o n l y i f based o n " b e i n g - i n - t h e - w o r l d . " T h i s phenomenon, w h i c h is a f u n d a m e n t a l a n d constitutive dimension o f Dasein, is the ontological basis for t r u t h , w h i c h is therefore seen to be based o n the very structure o f Dasein. I n his essay " V o m Wesen der W a h r h e i t " (1943), Heidegger locates the essence o f t r u t h i n freedom; freedom is seen as a " l e t t i n g be " (Seinlassen) o f the e n t i t y ; m a n does n o t " possess " freedom as a p r o p e r t y ; r a t h e r , freedom, the " e x i s t e n c e " m a n discovers, possesses m a n ; a n d Heidegger relates this to the historicity o f m a n , the o n l y historical e n t i t y . '' There is'' truth only in sofar as and while there is Dasein, Heidegger says. T h e e n t i t y is dis-covered a n d open o n l y w h e n a n d w h i l e there is Dasein. Newton's laws, the p r i n c i p l e o f c o n t r a d i c t i o n , a n y t r u t h w h a t ever : a l l these are true o n l y w h i l e there is Dasein. Before a n d afterward there is neither t r u t h nor falsity. Before N e w t o n , his laws were neither true nor false; this does n o t m e a n t h a t the e n t i t y w h i c h these laws discovered d i d n o t exist previously, b u t t h a t the laws t u r n e d out to be true t h r o u g h the agency o f N e w t o n ; b y means o f these laws the e n t i t y discovered became accessible to Dasein, and this is precisely w h a t t r u t h is. Therefore, the existence o f " eternal truths " c o u l d be demonstrated o n l y i f i t were p r o v e d t h a t there has been a n d w i l l be Dasein t h r o u g h o u t eternity. T h u s , every t r u t h is relative to the being o f Dasein; this, n a t u r a l l y , does n o t indicate either psychologism or subjectivism. B u t o n the other h a n d , t r u t h coincides w i t h being. " T h e r e i s " being—rather t h a n a n entity—when there is truth. A n d there is t r u t h only w h i l e there is Dasein. Being a n d t r u t h , Heidegger concludes, " are " equally p r i m a r y . D E A T H . I n Heidegger's philosophy the p r o b l e m o f death appears as an i m p o r t a n t theme. Dasein is always incomplete, because its conclusion implies at the same t i m e a ceasing to be. I t is possible, i n a
434
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
certain sense, to experience the death o f one's neighbor. I n such a case, the sum o f w h a t the neighbor attains i n d e a t h is a no longer existing, i n the sense o f " n o longer being i n the w o r l d . " D e a t h produces the corpse; the end of the e n t i t y qua Dasein is the beginning of this e n t i t y qua present t h i n g . B u t i n spite of everything, the corpse is something m o r e t h a n an i n a n i m a t e t h i n g , a n d can be understood o n l y f r o m the viewp o i n t of life. D e a t h is something peculiar to each a n d every m a n : " N o one can take some one else's death away f r o m h i m , " Heidegger says. D e a t h is a n essential characteristic o f D a s e i n ; b u t i t is n o t a n event w i t h i n the w o r l d . D e a t h for the Dasein is always a " n o t y e t . " I t is a m a t t e r o f " c o m i n g to one's e n d , " a n d this is w h a t Heidegger calls literally being-towards-deaih (Sein-zum-Tode). T h i s being-towards-death is a constituent p a r t o f Dasein; a n d dying, f r o m the p o i n t o f v i e w o f its ontological possibility, is based on Sorge, care. D e a t h is the most authentic possibility o f existence. B u t the " t h e y , " the Man, i n its t r i v i a l everyday existence, tries to hide this fact f r o m itself as m u c h as possible; they say: death w i l l surely come b u t , for the t i m e being, n o t yet. W i t h this "but," Heidegger says, the " they " denies t h e c e r t a i n t y o f death. I n this w a y , the " t h e y " covers u p the peculiar feature o f the certainty of d e a t h : t h a t i t is possible at any m o m e n t . As soon as a m a n is b o r n , he is o l d enough to d i e ; conversely, n o one is so o l d t h a t he does not still have a n open f u t u r e . D e a t h is the most proper possibility of Dasein. I n authentic existence, the illusions of the Man are overcome, a n d Dasein isfree for d e a t h . T h e state of mind w h i c h permits this acceptance o f death as the most proper h u m a n possibility is anguish. T h e r e is not o n l y a being-towards-death, b u t also a freedom for death (Freiheit zum Tode). T h i s doctrine of Heidegger's bristles w i t h question marks a n d i n t e r n a l difficulties, w h i c h cannot even be a l l u d e d to here. T E M P O R A L I T Y . W e have seen Dasein characterized as Sorge. W h a t , n o w , is the m e a n i n g of this Sorge, this care ? A n g u i s h i n the face o f death is always a not yet; concern is characterized b y a n awaiting (erwarten); thus, i t is p r i m a r i l y a m a t t e r o f something i n the future. A n d the resoluteness (Entschlossenheit) of Dasein is always i n apresent. Lastly, i n Geworfenheit, " t h r o w n n e s s , " the past, especially, functions as such. Temporality (Zeitlichkeit) manifests itself as the sense of a u t h e n t i c care, and the p r i m a r y p h e n o m e n o n o f o r i g i n a l a n d authentic t e m p o r a l i t y is the future. Heidegger subjects t e m p o r a l i t y a n d historicity (the latter based o n the f o r m e r ) to a p r o f o u n d a n d far-reaching analysis. H e finds t h a t Dasein is essentially l i n k e d w i t h t i m e , a n d this explains the connection between the t w o central terms o f Heidegger's ontology t h a t furnish the t i t l e o f his m a j o r w o r k : being a n d time.
"Existentialism"
435
T h i s b r i e f o u t l i n e is n o t i n t e n d e d as a n adequate exposition o f Heidegger's philosophy, w h i c h , at any rate, is perhaps n o t yet possible today. T h i s philosopher's w o r k is n o t yet concluded, a n d f u r t h e r m o r e , its i n t e r p r e t a t i o n is p r o b l e m a t i c a l a n d controversial. I t has been nearly forty years since the first v o l u m e o f Being and Time was p u b lished, a n d the works published b y Heidegger since t h e n do not represent a b o d y o f d o c t r i n e — a t least i n m a t u r e f o r m — c o m p a r a b l e to the systematic d o c t r i n e i n t h a t book. T h u s , a question arises over the m e a n i n g of Heidegger's philosophy. I n his most recent works he has skillfully criticized the too hasty interpretations o f his thought. W h a t is o f interest here is to show the sense a n d the position o f this metaphysics t h a t is so exceptionally p r o f o u n d , r i c h a n d s t i m u l a t i n g , b u t also b r i m m i n g over w i t h philosophical problems a n d risks, w h i c h are a p p a r e n t today i n the w o r k o f those thinkers w h o w i t h greater or lesser j u s t i f i c a t i o n c l a i m Heidegger as their teacher a n d inspirer. I have also t r i e d to offer assistance to those w h o wish to undertake the very necessary, t h o u g h difficult, task of reading Heidegger's b r i l l i a n t w o r k ; he is read less frequently a n d less carefully t h a n m a y be i m a g i n e d . Therefore, I deemed i t preferable to l i m i t myself p r i n c i p a l l y to the incomplete torso o f Being and Time, instead o f s t u d y i n g i n detail his later w r i t i n g s , w h i c h w o u l d require a n enormously painstaking exposition before any c l a r i t y could be a t t a i n e d .
3.
"EXISTENTIALISM"
I n the last few decades, a n d especially since the end o f the Second W o r l d W a r , a h i g h l y complex philosophical movement has been greatly developed; this movement, w h i c h derives its major ideas f r o m the philosophy o f life, is generally referred to u n d e r the blanket name o f " e x i s t e n t i a l i s m , " a rather ambiguous a n d inexact d e n o m i n a t i o n . Some o f its representatives are about the same age as H e i d e g g e r — f o r instance, Jaspers, M a r c e l and W a h l , w h o belong to the same generat i o n as other, differently oriented thinkers, such as Ortega, H a r t m a n n , Lavelle, L e Senne, M a r i t a i n a n d Gilson. Jaspers, M a r c e l and W a h l began their philosophy independently o f Heidegger, b u t have undergone his influence; other thinkers have c o n t i n u e d his philosophy, developed i t , a n d often denatured i t . A l l these tendencies, very diss i m i l a r i n value a n d fruitfulness, d i v e r g i n g f r o m one another considera b l y a n d v a r y i n g greatly i n significance, nevertheless have certain features i n c o m m o n . A t one p o i n t they seemed to d o m i n a t e the p h i l o sophic scene, at least i n C o n t i n e n t a l E u r o p e a n d L a t i n A m e r i c a , b u t t h e i r influence a n d prestige have slackened i n the last few years.
436
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
T h e expression " e x i s t e n t i a l i s m " is the one most w i d e l y used, a n d yet m a n y o f these philosophers w o u l d reject i t as a n a m e for t h e i r doctrines. I n order to establish a n a p p r o x i m a t i v e classification, i t w o u l d be possible to distinguish between existential philosophy (Heidegger), philosophy of existence (Jaspers, M a r c e l ) a n d existentialism (a t e r m w h i c h w o u l d have to be reserved for Sartre a n d his followers). A l l these forms o f t h o u g h t have been inspired, m o r e or less remotely, b y K i e r k e g a a r d , whose shadow hovers over t h e m . K i e r k e g a a r d i n d i c a t e d his aversion to abstract or sub specie aeterni t h o u g h t a n d called a t t e n t i o n to existence: " A b s t r a c t t h o u g h t is sub specie aeterni, i t makes a n abstraction o f the p a r t i c u l a r , o f the t e m p o r a l , o f t h e process o f existence, of the anguish o f m a n , w h o is situated i n existence b y a c o m b i n a t i o n o f the t e m p o r a l a n d the e t e r n a l . " " A l l l o g i c a l t h o u g h t is g i v e n i n abstract a n d sub specie aeterni language. T o t h i n k o f existence i n this w a y means m a k i n g a n abstraction of the d i f f i c u l t y one finds i n t h i n k i n g the eternal w i t h i n becoming, w h i c h is w h a t we are obliged to d o , since whoever thinks is himself located w i t h i n b e c o m i n g . Conseq u e n t l y , t h i n k i n g abstractly is easier t h a n existing (like t h a t w h i c h is called a s u b j e c t ) . " " G o d does n o t t h i n k , H e creates; G o d does n o t exist, H e is eternal. M a n thinks a n d exists, a n d existence separates t h o u g h t f r o m being, keeps t h e m successively distant f r o m each o t h e r . ' ' " Subjectivity is t r u t h ; subjectivity is r e a l i t y . " These ideas o f K i e r k e g a a r d are the g e r m o f a great p a r t o f the existential doctrines, most d i r e c t l y those o f Jaspers a n d W a h l . These forms o f t h o u g h t have aroused lively interest. T h e deeper reason for this, l y i n g beneath any passing fads, is to be f o u n d i n the fact t h a t these philosophies are abreast of the times; they have stated the true problems o f o u r age, whatever the t r u t h o f their solutions m a y be; they have responded to the desire for concreteness characteristic o f a l l present-day t h o u g h t ; a n d above a l l , they have concentrated on the study o f t h a t reality w h i c h is, u n d e r one name or another, h u m a n life. I shall a t t e m p t to characterize briefly the most i m p o r t a n t thinkers o f this g r o u p . JASPERS. K a r l Jaspers, b o r n i n O l d e n b u r g i n 1 8 8 3 , a professor at H e i d e l b e r g a n d t h e n at Basel, was o r i g i n a l l y concerned w i t h the sciences; he came to philosophy f r o m psychiatry. H i s w r i t i n g s are numerous a n d some are enormously l e n g t h y ; the most i m p o r t a n t are Allgemeine Psychopathologie (General Psychopathology), Psychologic der Weltanschauungen (Psychology o f W o r l d V i e w s ) , Die geistige Situation der Zeit (translated as Man in the Modern Age), Philosophic ( 1 9 3 2 , three v o l u m e s : Philosophische Weltorientierung [Philosophical W o r l d O r i e n t a t i o n ] , Existenzerhellung [ E l u c i d a t i o n o f Existence], Metaphysik), Vernunft
"Existentialism"
437
und Existenz (Reason a n d Existence), Nietzsche, Descartes und die Philosophie, Existenzphilosophie, Der philosophische Glaube (translated as The Perennial Scope of Philosophy), Einführung in die Philosophie (translated as Way to Wisdom), Vom Ursprung und Z™1 der Geschichte ( T h e O r i g i n a n d Goal of H i s t o r y ) , Rechenschaft und Ausblick ( A c c o u n t i n g a n d Prospects), Vernunft und Widervernunft in unserer Zeit (Reason a n d Anti-Reason i n O u r T i m e ) , Von der Wahrheit ( O n T r u t h ; the first v o l u m e , extremely long, o f a Philosophische Logik) a n d Die grossen Philosophen ( T h e Great Philosophers). Jaspers has been constantly concerned w i t h ethics a n d has studied i n detail Germany's responsibility i n the Second W o r l d W a r , the defense of freedom a n d the historic problems o f o u r t i m e . F r o m the psychology o f Weltanschauungen, o r ' ' w o r l d views,'' Jaspers progressed to a philosophy o f existence (Existenzphilosophie); his p h i losophy has been characterized b y G a b r i e l M a r c e l as " a n orography o f the i n n e r l i f e . " I t is based o n the v i e w p o i n t of w h a t Jaspers calls mögliche Existenz, or possible existence; t h a t is, the incomplete. T h e question o f being involves a n d affects the m a n w h o asks i t ; the quest for being is always unachieved, b u t essential (an echo o f K a n t ' s concept of metaphysics as a Naturanlage, or n a t u r a l predisposition; K a n t ' s influence o n Jaspers is decisive). F o r Jaspers, existence is t h a t w h i c h is never an object; i t must come to grips w i t h itself a n d w i t h its o w n transcendence. Jaspers is especially interested i n " b o r d e r l i n e " or " u l t i m a t e " situations (Grenzsituationen), w h i c h cannot be m o d i f i e d , w h i c h belong to Existenz b u t signify the transition to transcendence— the historic d e t e r m i n a t i o n o f existence, death, suffering, struggle, g u i l t . A m a j o r concept i n Jaspers' t h o u g h t is w h a t he calls das Umgreifende ( t h a t w h i c h embraces or involves, " t h e c o m p r e h e n s i v e " ) ; i t is the being w h i c h is not merely subject n o r merely object: either the being i n itself w h i c h surrounds us ( w o r l d a n d transcendence) or the being we ourselves are (existence, consciousness, s p i r i t ) . W h a t we k n o w is in the w o r l d , i t never is the w o r l d ; transcendence i n its t u r n never comes to be the w o r l d , b u t " s p e a k s " t h r o u g h the being i n the w o r l d . I f the w o r l d is everything, there is no transcendence; i f there is transcendence, i t is perhaps indicated b y w o r l d l y being. B U B E R . M a r t i n Buber ( b o r n i n V i e n n a i n 1878, d i e d i n Jerusalem i n 1965) was a Jewish t h i n k e r w h o h a d close ties w i t h this existentialist t h o u g h t ; his p a r t i c u l a r interest was i n religious themes and Jewish mysticism. H e placed special emphasis o n subject-object and subject-subject relationships, a n d p a r t i c u l a r l y o n the I-Thou relationship. Buber made a great c o n t r i b u t i o n to the theme o f man's i n v o l v e m e n t w i t h his fellows. H i s most i m p o r t a n t works are: Ich und Du ( I a n d T h o u ) , Die chassidischen Bücher ( T h e Hasidic Books),
438
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
^wiesprache: ein Traktat vom dialogischen Leben ( D i a l o g u e : a Treatise on D i a l o g i c a l L i f e ) , " W a s ist der M e n s c h ? " ( W h a t Is M a n ? ) and Der Mensch und sein Gebild ( M a n a n d H i s I m a g e ) . M A R C E L . T h e first representative o f these doctrines i n France was G a b r i e l M a r c e l ( b o r n i n 1889). M a r c e l , w h o converted to Catholicism i n 1929, is a philosopher and p l a y w r i g h t ; he considers his d r a m a t i c works to be an essential p a r t o f his philosophical investigations. His most i m p o r t a n t books are Journal métaphysique, Être et avoir (Being and H a v i n g ) , Du refus à l'invocation, Homo viator a n d especially, Le mystère de l'être ( T h e M y s t e r y o f Being) ; a m o n g his works for the theater are Le seuil invisible ( T h e I n v i s i b l e T h r e s h o l d ) , Le quatuor en fa dièse ( Q u a r t e t i n F Sharp), Un homme de Dieu ( A M a n o f G o d ) , Le monde cassé ( T h e Broken W o r l d ) , Le dard ( T h e D a r t ) , Le fanal ( T h e L a n t e r n ) , La soif ( T h i r s t ) , Le signe de la croix ( T h e Sign of the Cross) a n d L'émissaire. M a r c e l is not very systematic; his circuitous t h o u g h t attempts to adhere to reality, f o l l o w i n g its meanderings a n d m a i n t a i n i n g the greatest possible a u t h e n t i c i t y , as w e l l as great fidelity to the things. T h e beauty o f his intellect, his veracity a n d his lack o f f r i v o l i t y are w e l l k n o w n . A religious m a n w h o is d o m i n a t e d b y respect for r e a l i t y , he makes a w o r t h y a n d p r o f o u n d use o f his i n t e l l e c t u a l gifts. H e first used the t e r m " e x i s t e n c e " i n 1914, a n d his t h o u g h t has been called " C h r i s t i a n e x i s t e n t i a l i s m , " b u t he rejects this name. " T h e r e is a plane, " M a r c e l writes, " o n w h i c h n o t o n l y is the w o r l d meaningless, b u t on w h i c h i t is even a c o n t r a d i c t i o n to pose the question o f whether i t has any m e a n i n g ; this is the plane o f direct existence ; i t is o f necessity the plane o f the fortuitous, i t is the order o f chance. " A decisive d i s t i n c t i o n for M a r c e l is the one he makes between problem a n d mystery. F o r h i m , a p r o b l e m is something one comes across, w h i c h blocks one's p a t h ; i t is there i n its e n t i r e t y i n f r o n t o f me. A mystery, o n the other h a n d , is something i n w h i c h I find myself engaged or i n v o l v e d (engagé) ; its essence consists i n not being entirely i n front of me, as i f i n t h a t region the difference between " i n m e " a n d " f a c i n g m e " were to lose its meaning. M a r c e l believes that the p r o b lems o f philosophy are not p r o p e r l y problems, b u t rather mysteries i n this sense. M a r c e l uses the concepts o f project, vocation, creation and transcendence. T o create means to create at a level above one's self; to transcend does n o t m e a n to transcend experience, because b e y o n d experience there is n o t h i n g , b u t to have experience o f the transcendent. T h e r e exists for M a r c e l an existential fulcrum, a s t a n d p o i n t or v i e w p o i n t , w h i c h is t h a t o f m a n . T h e p r o b l e m o f the body is stated as the c o n d i t i o n o f " being incarnate " ; this means appearing as this body, w i t h o u t i d e n t i f i c a t i o n or distinction. T h e b o d y is a manifestation o f
"Existentialism"
439
the nexus w h i c h unites me w i t h the w o r l d , a n d I can say, " I a m m y b o d y . " T h e existential is concerned w i t h b e i n g incarnate, the fact o f b e i n g i n the w o r l d ; a n d this is a chez soi ; feeling is n o t a passive act, b u t a p a r t i c i p a t i o n . M a r c e l has reflected deeply o n the h u m a n situation, o n sacrifice a n d suicide, o n p a t e r n i t y a n d its r e l a t i o n to the b o d i l y care o f the c h i l d — h e n c e the possibility o f adoptive p a t e r n i t y — a n d finally o n " c r e a t i v e f i d e l i t y . " M a r c e l proposes a " c o n c r e t e p h i l o s o p h y " d e t e r m i n e d b y the " b i t e o f reality, " the themes o f w h i c h are death, suicide, b e t r a y a l . T h e belief i n the " t h o u " is a n essential p a r t o f this philosophy ; being is the site o f fidelity, w h i c h signifies a n enormous compromise a n d hope as a n infinite c r e d i t ; these ideas, along w i t h f a i t h i n personal i m m o r t a l i t y , are closely l i n k e d w i t h love, a n d are a d m i r a b l y expressed i n a line spoken b y one o f Marcel's characters : Toi quej'aime, tu ne mourras pas ( Y o u w h o m I love, y o u shall n o t die). Also o f Marcel's generation are J e a n W a h l ( b o r n 1888), a professor at the Sorbonne a n d a u t h o r of Étude sur le Parme'nide de Platon, Vers le concret, Études kierkegaardiennes, Petite histoire de "L'existentialisme" (A Short H i s t o r y o f Existentialism) a n d Traité de métaphysique; Louis Lavelle (1883-1951), whose relations w i t h existentialism are m u c h m o r e remote : a u t h o r o f De l'Être, Traité des valeurs, La dialectique de l'éternel présent, a n d so o n ; a n d R e n é L e Senne (1883-1954), whose p r i n c i p a l books are Introduction à la philosophie, Le mensonge et le caractère, Obstacle et valeur, Traité de morale générale a n d Traité de caractérologie. T h e f o l l o w i n g generation, also closer to b o t h personalism a n d spiritualism t h a n t o existential t h o u g h t , is represented b y E m m a n u e l M o u n i e r (1905-1950), founder o f the magazine Esprit a n d a u t h o r o f books o n politics a n d o f the Traité du caractère, Introduction aux existentialismes (Existential Philosophies ; a n I n t r o d u c t i o n ) a n d Lepersonnalisme. S A R T R E . T h e best-known figure i n F r e n c h philosophy i n the years f o l l o w i n g the Second W o r l d W a r is the representative o f " e x i s t e n t i a l i s m " i n the strict sense, Jean-Paul Sartre ( b o r n 1905). A lycée p r o fessor, novelist, p l a y w r i g h t , p o l i t i c a l w r i t e r a n d director o f Les temps modernes, he studied for some time i n G e r m a n y , where he was strongly influenced b y Husserl's phenomenology a n d b y Heidegger, f r o m b o t h o f w h o m a great p a r t o f his ideas are derived. Nevertheless, Heidegger has p o i n t e d o u t the great distance between h i m s e l f a n d Sartre ; i n the last few years, Sartre has come increasingly closer to M a r x i s m . H i s w o r k is q u i t e extensive; his p r i n c i p a l philosophical w r i t i n g s are L'imagination, Esquisse d'une théorie des émotions ( T h e Emotions, O u t l i n e o f a T h e o r y ) , L'imaginaire a n d L'être et le néant (Being a n d Nothingness ; his m a j o r w o r k , 1943); after a l o n g silence, he published i n i 9 6 0 a n o t h e r very l o n g book, Critique de la raison dialectique ; one should also
Heidegger's
Existential
Philosophy
i n c l u d e his essays " Situations, " " Baudelaire, " " L'existentialisme est u n h u m a n i s m e " (Existentialism and H u m a n i s m ) , Saint-Genêt, comédien et martyr, a n d so o n . I n a d d i t i o n , there are h i s " e x i s t e n t i a l i s t " novels La nausée (Nausea; 1938), L'âge de raison ( T h e A g e of Reason), Le sursis ( T h e Reprieve) a n d La mort dans l'âme (translated as Iron in the Soul a n d as Troubled Sleep) ; his stories " L e m u r " ( T h e W a l l ) , " L e s j e u x sont f a i t s " ( T h e Chips A r e D o w n ) a n d " L ' e n g r e n a g e " ( I n the M e s h ) ; his plays Huis-clos ( N o E x i t ) , Les mouches ( T h e Flies), Morts sans sépulture (translated as Men Without Shadows), La putain respectueuse ( T h e Respectful P r o s t i t u t e ) , Les mains sales (translated as The Red Gloves), Le diable et le bon Dieu ( T h e D e v i l a n d t h e G o o d L o r d ) , Nekrassov a n d Les séquestrés d'Altona ( T h e C o n d e m n e d o f A l t o n a ) ; a n d a n a u t o b i o g r a p h i c a l book, Les mots ( T h e W o r d s ) . Sartre began w i t h a phenomenological psychology a n d m o v e d o n to o n t o l o g y rather b e l a t e d l y ; the subtitle o f L'être et le néant is "Essai d'ontologie p h é n o m é n o l o g i q u e . " I t is a book o f 722 t i g h t l y w r i t t e n pages, difficult to r e a d ; i t uses t r a d i t i o n a l t e r m i n o l o g y , w h i c h is generally employed w i t h transferred meanings; there are m i n u t e analyses, phenomenological descriptions, passages o f great l i t e r a r y t a l e n t a n d others where the prose is abstruse a n d f o r b i d d i n g . T h e p r i m a r y meaning o f " e x i s t e n t i a l i s m " is the p r i o r i t y o f existence over essence; this is equivalent to i n v e r t i n g the t r a d i t i o n a l terms w h i l e accepting the o l d o u t l i n e o f t r a d i t i o n a l ontology ; i n a c e r t a i n sense, one m i g h t say t h a t Sartre's philosophy is t r a d i t i o n a l Scholastic or phenomenological ontology à rebours, b u t w i t h o u t transcending the basic concepts a n d statements o f problems. Therefore, the concepts he uses constantly are being, nothingness, i n itself a n d for itself, for itself a n d for the other, a n d so f o r t h . T h e being o f m a n is i n t e r p r e t e d as pour-soi, or consciousness, a n d here he is completely i n line w i t h Husserl. "Consciousness," Sartre writes, " i s a b e i n g for w h i c h i t is essentially a question o f its b e i n g i n so far as this b e i n g implies a being other t h a n itself. " " Consciousness is a being for w h i c h i t is essentially a consciousness o f the nothingness o f its b e i n g . " Sartre states the p r o b l e m i n terms o f consciousness; i n this he is m u c h closer to Husserl t h a n to Heidegger. As for the rest, m a n y of his ideas were f o r m u l a t e d b y those t w o philosophers or b y O r t e g a : project, choice (choix), " being condemned to be free " ( O r t e g a t a u g h t decades earlier t h a t " m a n is necessarily free, " free for a n y t h i n g except for ceasing to be free, b u t at the same t i m e he saw clearly t h a t even i f m a n always chooses, n o t e v e r y t h i n g i n his life is a n object o f choice, neither his surroundings n o r his vocation or o r i g i n a l p r o j e c t ) . Sartre professes w h a t he calls " a consequent a t h e i s m , " w h i c h he
"Existentialism"
441
bases o n extremely feeble a n d q u i t e unjustifiable reasons; for h i m , man's basic state o f m i n d w h e n c o n f r o n t i n g r e a l i t y is the r e a l i z a t i o n t h a t everything is " too m u c h " (de trop)—consequently nausea. M a n is a passion t o f o u n d being a n d constitute the In-itself, the Ens causa sui— t h a t is, G o d . " B u t the idea o f G o d , " Sartre concludes, " i s selfc o n t r a d i c t o r y , a n d we lose ourselves i n v a i n ; m a n is a n ineffective passion." I n the Critique de la raison dialectique, Sartre says t h a t a s t r u c t u r a l a n d historical a n t h r o p o l o g y " t r o u v e sa place à l'intérieur de l a philosophie marxiste parce que j e considère le marxisme c o m m e l'indépassable philosophie de n o t r e temps et parce que j e tiens l'idéologie de l'existence et sa méthode ' compréhensive ' p o u r une enclave dans le marxisme lui-même q u i l'engendre et l a refuse t o u t à l a f o i s . " F o r Sartre, M a r x i s m is the unavoidable philosophy o f our t i m e , a n d the reason for this is t h a t M a r x i s m has h a r d l y begun to develop a n d m a n has n o t yet been able to overcome the circumstances w h i c h engendered i t : " l o i n d'être épuisé, le marxisme est t o u t j e u n e encore, presque en enfance: c'est à peine s'il a c o m m e n c é de se développer. I l reste donc l a philosophie de notre temps: i l est indépassable parce que les circonstances q u i l ' o n t engendré ne sont pas encore dépassées. " I have q u o t e d this passage f r o m Sartre's w o r k because i t exemplifies his h a b i t u a l manner o f reasoning. I n recent years, he has been the object o f m u c h criticism, a n d his prestige and influence have declined considerably. Sartre's influence o n Simone de Beauvoir, the novelist a n d a u t h o r o f philosophical studies, has been enormous ; a n d o r i g i n a l l y the great w r i t e r A l b e r t Camus ( i 9 1 3 - 1 9 6 0 ) was close to Sartre i n his t h i n k i n g ; however, Camus later broke completely w i t h M a r x i s m . M a u r i c e M e r l e a u - P o n t y ( 1908-1961 ) , w h o was greatly influenced by the contemporary G e r m a n philosophers, especially the phenomenologists, is the a u t h o r o f La structure du comportement, Phénoménologie de la perception, Les aventures de la dialectique, Signes. Echoes a n d imitations o f these trends have been h e a r d i n almost every c o u n t r y o f E u r o p e a n d i n L a t i n A m e r i c a , b u t i n the last few years they have begun to diminish.
Ortega and His Philosophy of Vital Reason
i.
ORTEGA'S
PERSONALITY
L I F E . José O r t e g a y Gasset, Spain's most i m p o r t a n t philosopher, was b o r n i n M a d r i d o n M a y 9, 1883, a n d died i n the same c i t y o n October 18, 1955. F r o m 1898 to 1902 he studied for his bachelor's degree i n the F a c u l t y o f Philosophy a n d Letters at the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d , a n d took his doctorate i n 1904 w i t h a thesis on Los terrores del ano mil—Critica de una leyenda ( T h e T e r r o r s o f the Year 1 0 0 0 — C r i t i q u e o f a L e g e n d ) . I n 1905 he went to G e r m a n y a n d studied at t h e U n i v e r sities of L e i p z i g , B e r l i n a n d M a r b u r g ; at M a r b u r g , w h i c h was p h i l o sophically the most i m p o r t a n t university i n G e r m a n y at t h a t t i m e , he was a p u p i l o f the great n e o - K a n t i a n H e r m a n n Cohen. I n 1910 Ortega became professor o f metaphysics i n the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d , where he t a u g h t u n t i l 1936. Ortega began his a c t i v i t y as a w r i t e r i n 1902. H i s collaborations i n newspapers a n d magazines, his books, lectures a n d p u b l i s h i n g efforts decisively influenced Spanish life, a n d i n the last few decades his influence has become increasingly evident outside Spain. I n 1923 he founded the Revis ta de Occidente (published u n t i l 1936), w h i c h , together w i t h its book p u b l i s h i n g p r o g r a m , the Biblioteca (still i n o p e r a t i o n ) , has kept Spanish-speaking readers f u l l y i n f o r m e d o n a l l i n t e l l e c t u a l matters. B y means of translations a n d editions Ortega i n c o r p o r a t e d i n t o Spanish t h o u g h t the most i m p o r t a n t parts o f E u r o p e a n — 441
Ortega's
Personality
443
p a r t i c u l a r l y G e r m a n — l e a r n i n g a n d a repertory of classical works ; his achievement makes i t possible for scholarship i n S p a i n to be the equal of t h a t f o u n d i n any other c o u n t r y today. A consequence o f this effort a n d especially o f Ortega's o w n philosophical endeavors has been the flourishing of a philosophical school i n the f u l l sense of the t e r m ; i t is k n o w n as the School of Madrid, a n d its members i n c l u d e , a m o n g others, M a n u e l G a r c i a M o r e n t e , Fernando V e l a , X a v i e r Z u b i r i , José Gaos, Luis Recaséns Siches, M a r í a Z a m b r a n o , A n t o n i o R o d r í g u e z Huéscar, M a n u e l G r a n e l l , José Ferrater M o r a , José A . M a r a valí, L u i s Diez del C o r r a l , Alfonso G . Valdecasas, Salvador Lissarrague, P a u l i n o G a r a g o r r i , Pedro L a i n E n t r a l g o , José L u i s A r a n g u r e n a n d the a u t h o r of this book. F r o m 1936 o n O r t e g a l i v e d i n France, H o l l a n d , A r g e n t i n a , P o r t u g a l a n d G e r m a n y , w i t h sojourns i n Spain b e g i n n i n g i n 1945. These were years i n w h i c h his t h o u g h t m a t u r e d a n d i n w h i c h he w r o t e his most i m p o r t a n t works. I t was also d u r i n g these years that his w r i t i n g s came to be k n o w n outside S p a i n — w r i t i n g s w h i c h n o w can be read i n a n y of a dozen languages. Ortega always dedicated himself to a m e d i t a t i o n o n Spain, a n d a l l his w o r k is c o n d i t i o n e d b y his Spanishness ; Spanish t h o u g h t as such is an influential force i n the w o r l d today because o f his efforts. I n 1948 he founded i n M a d r i d , w i t h Julián M a r i a s , the I n s t i t u t o de H u m a n i d a d e s , where he t a u g h t a n d took p a r t i n seminars o n various topics. I N T E L L E C T U A L STYLE. Ortega was a great w r i t e r . H e occupies a secure place a m o n g the half-dozen most a d m i r a b l e Spanish prose writers o f the c e n t u r y , a n d t r u t h f u l l y none is superior to h i m . H i s l i t e r a r y gifts p e r m i t t e d h i m to effect a t r a n s f o r m a t i o n i n the language and style of w r i t i n g , the stamp of w h i c h is visible i n a great m a n y of our c o n t e m p o r a r y authors. O r t e g a created a t e r m i n o l o g y a n d a p h i l o sophical style i n Spanish where previously they d i d not exist; his t e c h n i q u e — t h e opposite o f Heidegger's, for example—consists i n rejecting neologisms i n general a n d i n restoring to the deeply felt, c o m m o n l y used expressions o f the language, a n d even to the idioms, their most authentic a n d o r i g i n a l significance, w h i c h is often b r i m m i n g w i t h philosophical m e a n i n g or else capable of t a k i n g o n such m e a n i n g . A t his hands the m e t a p h o r attains, i n a d d i t i o n to beauty, a strictly metaphysical value. H e used to say, " I n philosophy, c l a r i t y is c o u r t e s y , " a n d i n his writings as i n his i n c o m p a r a b l e lectures he achieved m a x i m u m transparency for his t h o u g h t . O r t e g a carries t o a n extreme the effort to make himself i n t e l l i g i b l e , t o the p o i n t t h a t he q u i t e f r e q u e n t l y leads the reader to t h i n k t h a t because one has understood h i m w i t h o u t effort, one does not have to exert oneself to under-
444
Ortega
and His
Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
stand h i m fully. I n some o f his last writings O r t e g a a r r i v e d at a t o t a l l y o r i g i n a l w a y o f expression, i n w h i c h fidelity to the spirit o f the language is u n i t e d w i t h absolutely new stylistic procedures, a n d w h i c h corresponds to the f o r m o f reason o f w h i c h his p h i l o s o p h i c a l m e t h o d consists; this is w h a t I have called the statement of vital reason. * A t the same t i m e , O r t e g a achieved a renewal o f c e r t a i n l i t e r a r y forms. T h e w r i t i n g o f his works i n view o f the circumstances i n Spain obliged h i m for m a n y years to publish his t h o u g h t i n articles i n newspapers or i n essay f o r m ; he offered j u s t t h a t a m o u n t o f philosophy t h a t his readers c o u l d effectively absorb at any m o m e n t . " I t was necessary to seduce readers t o w a r d philosophical problems w i t h l y r i c a l m e t h o d s , " he once said. T h u s , Ortega w r o t e articles a n d essays o f a special nature, w h i c h constitute some of the most i m p o r t a n t works o f the t w e n t i e t h century. Ortega's interest was n o t l i m i t e d to strictly p h i l o s o p h i c a l problems; r a t h e r , he carried his philosophical p o i n t o f view to a l l themes o f life: l i t e r a t u r e , a r t , politics, history, sociology—all h u m a n themes have been dealt w i t h b y h i m . A n d w i t h respect to a n enormous n u m b e r o f questions, one often finds i n a page or t w o b y O r t e g a the i l l u m i n a t i o n one has sought i n v a i n i n heavy tomes. However, a l l his w r i t i n g s , even those t h a t seem furthest removed f r o m philosophy, are l i n k e d to a philosophical purpose, a n d they can be understood f u l l y o n l y i n the l i g h t o f his system. T h i s is because Ortega concerned h i m s e l f above a l l w i t h philosophy; a n d so today, centuries after Suárez, Spain again reckons w i t h an authentic, o r i g i n a l a n d strict metaphysician. By means of his intellectual w o r k a n d influence, O r t e g a m a d e philosophy i n Spain possible a n d a c t u a l . W O R K S . Ortega's l i t e r a r y p r o d u c t i o n was copious. H i s Complete Works, collected i n six volumes, comprise w r i t i n g s published f r o m 1902 to 1943; his later works make u p three a d d i t i o n a l volumes. H i s most i m p o r t a n t works are Meditaciones del Quijote ( M e d i t a t i o n s o n Q u i x o t e ) , 1914; El Espectador ( T h e Spectator) (eight volumes), 1916¬ 1934; España invertebrada ( I n v e r t e b r a t e S p a i n ) , 1921; El tema de nuestro tiempo ( T h e T h e m e o f O u r T i m e ) , 1923; Las Atldntidas ( T h e A t l a n tises), 1924; La deshumanización del arte e ideas sobre la novela ( T h e D e h u m a n i z a t i o n o f A r t a n d Ideas o n the N o v e l ) , 1925; Kant, 1924¬ 1929; La rebelión de las masas ( T h e Revolt o f the Masses), 1930; Misión de la Universidad (Mission of the U n i v e r s i t y ) , 1930; Guillermo Diltheyy la * I have given a detailed analysis of this aspect of Ortega's work in my study " V i d a y razón en la filosofía de Ortega" in La Escuela de Madrid; Estudios de filosofía española, Buenos Aires, 1959 [Obras, V ] . See also my Introducción a la Filosofía [Obras, I I ] .
Ortega's
Personality
445
idea de la vida ( W i l h e l m D i l t h e y a n d the I d e a o f L i f e ) , 1933; En torno a Galileo (translated i n t o English as Man and Crisis), 1933; Historia como sistema ( H i s t o r y as a System), 1935; Ensimismamiento y alteración (Selfabsorption a n d Change), 1939; Meditación de la técnica ( M e d i t a t i o n o n T e c h n i q u e ) , 1939; Ideas y creencias (Ideas a n d Beliefs), 1940; Apuntes sobre el pensamiento: su teurgia y su demiurgia (Notes o n T h o u g h t : Its T h e u r g y a n d Its D e m i u r g y ) , 1941; Estudios sobre el amor (Studies o n L o v e ) , 1941; Eel Imperio romano ( O n the R o m a n E m p i r e ) , 1941; a n d prefaces to three books: Historia de la Filosofía (History o f Philosophy) b y E m i l e Bréhier, 1942; Veinte Años de caza mayor ( T w e n t y Years of Big-game H u n t i n g ) b y the C o u n t o f Yebes, 1942; a n d Aventuras del Capitán Alonso de Contreras, 1943. H i s later works i n c l u d e Papeles sobre Veldzquezy Goya (Papers on Velazquez a n d G o y a ) , 1950; a preface to El collar de la Paloma ( k n o w n i n English as The Ring of the Dove) b y I b n H a z m , 1952; Stücke aus einer "Geburt der Philosophie" (Pieces f r o m a " B i r t h o f P h i l o s o p h y " ) , 1953; Europäische Kultur und europäische Völker ( E u r o p e a n C u l t u r e a n d E u r o p e a n People), 1954; Velázquez, 1954. T h e p u b l i c a t i o n of his posthumous w r i t i n g s began i n 1957 w i t h his book o n sociology, El hombre y la gente ( M a n a n d People); ¿ Qué es filosofía? ( W h a t Is Philosophy ?), lectures for a class given i n 1929; the extremely i m p o r t a n t a n d very l o n g book La idea de principio en Leibniz y la evolución de la teoría deductiva ( L e i b n i z ' Concept o f Principle a n d the E v o l u t i o n o f the Deductive T h e o r y ) — p r o b a b l y the most i m p o r t a n t o f a l l his w o r k s ; Idea del teatro ( I d e a o f the T h e a t e r ) ; the Meditación del pueblo joven ( M e d i t a t i o n o n a Y o u n g People); also, a "Preface for G e r m a n s " w r i t t e n a n d published i n G e r m a n i n 1934; his first course at the I n s t i t u t o de H u m a n i d a d e s , Una interpretación de la Historia universal, Meditación de Europa, Origen y Epílogo de la Filosofía ( O r i g i n a n d Epilogue o f P h i l o s o p h y ) ; Vives-Goethe, Pasado y porvenir para el hombre actual (Past a n d F u t u r e for the M a n o f T o d a y ) and Unas lecciones de Metafísica. Ortega's university lectures are o f enormous i m p o r t a n c e , especially those o f 1929 to 1936 a n d the later ones at the I n s t i t u t o de H u m a n i dades, w h i c h are indispensable for a precise knowledge o f his thought. Several have o n l y recently been published. These lectures reveal the systematic connection a n d i n t e g r a l metaphysical scope o f his other published works. I n these courses he dealt, above a l l , w i t h the theme o f idealism a n d its c r i t i q u e , the structure of historical a n d social life a n d the metaphysics o f v i t a l reason, the first version o f Ortega's p h i l o sophical system, o f w h i c h a complete exposition has never been p u b lished. U n t i l Ortega's posthumous w r i t i n g s have been completely e x a m i n e d , i t w i l l be impossible t o w r i t e an adequate book o n his
Ortega
and His Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
philosophy; this fact conditions the present exposition w h i c h , i n spite of m y knowledge of the course lectures a n d o f p a r t o f Ortega's u n published w o r k , is o f a fragmentary a n d provisional n a t u r e a n d is meant o n l y to facilitate the a p p r o a c h to Ortega's w o r k itself. *
2. T H E GENESIS O F O R T E G A ' S
PHILOSOPHY
The Critique of Idealism R E A L I S M A N D IDEALISM. Ortega's early f o r m a t i o n was n e o - K a n t i a n ; his years i n M a r b u r g gave h i m a detailed knowledge of K a n t , a strict intellectual discipline, a n i n t e r n a l vision o f a n u l t i m a t e f o r m o f " S c h o l a s t i c i s m , " a n d an i m m e r s i o n i n the idealist a t t i t u d e . H o w e v e r , as is evident i n his first w r i t i n g s , he q u i c k l y reacted i n a personal w a y ; a short t i m e later O r t e g a a r r i v e d at positions o f his o w n w h i c h , as we shall see, were determined b y the conquest o f a l l subjectivism a n d i d e a l i s m — w i t h o u t falling back o n the o l d realist thesis: t h e pressing need for a system a n d the absolute predominance o f metaphysics. These ideas, w h i c h passed t h r o u g h a n u n i n t e r r u p t e d process o f development, led h i m to his system oí metaphysics according to vital reason, a n d secondarily represent a decisive c r i t i q u e o f idealism. Realism is a n a t t i t u d e rather t h a n a thesis. T h i s attitude presupposes t h a t true r e a l i t y consists of the things; real being means b e i n g for itself, independent o f me. However, this apparently quite obvious position w h i c h d o m i n a t e d philosophical t h o u g h t for twenty-two centuries is not beyond c r i t i c i s m . F r o m Descartes to Husserl philosophy m a i n tained a n e w thesis w h i c h corrected a n d amended the realist thesis: this is w h a t is called idealism. Descartes discovers t h a t the things are not for sure; t h a t I m a y be w r o n g : t h a t there exist such things as dreams a n d hallucinations, i n w h i c h I accept as true realities things w h i c h are not true realities. T h e only t h i n g t h a t is certain a n d beyond d o u b t is the ego. O n t h e other h a n d , I k n o w n o t h i n g of the w o r l d of the things except i n so f a r as I a m present to t h e m , i n so far as I am a witness of t h e m . I k n o w o f the r o o m because I a m i n i t ; i f I leave i t , does i t continue to exist? I n t h e final * Many specific problems are developed in detail in my above-mentioned study La Escuela de Madrid and in Ortega y tres antípodas (1950); for the first stage of his intellectual development in particular, see my commentary to the Meditaciones del Quijote (Biblioteca de Cultura Básica de la Universidad de Puerto Rico, 1957; 2nd ed., 1966). Although it is not strictly an exposition of Ortega's philosophy, I also refer the reader to my Introducción a la Filosofía (Reason and Life), which is directly based on this philosophy; in this work I make systematic use of the method of vital reason. I n addition, a study in depth of this philosophy is to be found in my book Ortega, of which V o l . I, Circunstancia y vocación, was published in i960.
The
Genesis
of Ortega's
Philosophy
447
analysis, I cannot k n o w t h a t i t does. I k n o w o n l y t h a t i t exists w h i l e I a m i n i t , w h i l e i t is with me. Therefore, the things b y themselves, independent o f m e , are foreign a n d u n k n o w n to m e ; I do not k n o w a n y t h i n g a b o u t t h e m , n o t even that they exist. Consequently, the things are for me or in me, they are ideas of mine. T h e table a n d w a l l are things that I perceive. T h e f u n d a m e n t a l a n d p r i m a r y reality is the ego; the things possess a derived a n d dependent being, based o n that of the ego. T h e ego is the f u n d a m e n t a l substance. Descartes says t h a t I can exist w i t h o u t the w o r l d , w i t h o u t the things. T h i s is the idealist thesis, w h i c h c u l m i n a t e d i n its most perfect f o r m i n Husserl's idealism of p u r e consciousness, w h i c h has already been discussed. O r t e g a scrupulously opposes this thesis. T H E E G O A N D T H E THINGS. Idealism is perfectly r i g h t i n a f f i r m i n g t h a t I can k n o w the things o n l y i n so far as I a m present to t h e m . T h e t h i n g s — a t least to the extent t h a t I k n o w t h e m a n d t h a t i t is meaningful to speak o f their r e a l i t y — c a n n o t be independent o f me. However, idealism is w r o n g i n a f f i r m i n g the independence o f the subject. I cannot speak o f the things w i t h o u t m e ; b u t neither can I speak o f an ego without the things. I a m never alone; I a m always w i t h the things, d o i n g something w i t h t h e m ; I cannot be separated f r o m the things, a n d i f they need me, I i n t u r n need t h e m i n order to exist. I n an equally o r i g i n a l a n d p r i m a r y w a y I find myself w i t h m y ego a n d w i t h the things. T h e t r u e p r i m a r y r e a l i t y — t h efundamental reality—is that of the ego w i t h the things. / am myself
and my circumstance,
or
surroundings
(circunstancia), O r t e g a w r o t e as early as 1914, i n his first book. A n d at least i n p r i n c i p l e this is n o t a m a t t e r o f t w o separable elements—the ego a n d t h e t h i n g s — w h i c h are f o u n d together b y chance; rather, the f u n d a m e n t a l r e a l i t y is this i n t e r p l a y or " business " (quehacer) of the ego w i t h the things, w h i c h we call life. By using the things, m a n lives. T h i s action is t h e r e a l i t y i n w h i c h we o r i g i n a l l y find ourselves; n o w i t is not a thing—either m a t e r i a l or spiritual, because the Cartesian ego is also a res, even t h o u g h cogitans—but an a c t i v i t y , something t h a t we cannot p r o p e r l y say is, b u t t h a t is done. The fundamental is made up of what we do and what happens world,
to direct oneself toward
reality is our life. And
life
to us. To live is to deal with the
it, to act in it, to concern oneself with it. T h e r e -
fore, there is no p r i o r i t y o f the things, as the realists believed, nor does the ego have a p r i o r i t y over the things, as the idealists thought. T h e p r i m a r y a n d f u n d a m e n t a l reality, of w h i c h the ego a n d the things are but abstract moments, is the d y n a m i c " b u s i n e s s " w h i c h we call our life.
CONSCIOUSNESS. N O W we must examine the c u l m i n a t i n g m o m e n t o f idealism, idealism i n its most refined f o r m : Husserl's phenomenology.
Ortega
and His
Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
T h i s is not a subjective i d e a l i s m ; he speaks n o t o f the ideas o r experiences of an e m p i r i c a l ego, b u t o f the experiences o f p u r e consciousness. I n the effort to a v o i d metaphysics, w h i l e at the same t i m e i n d u l g i n g i n i t , Husserl closes himself u p i n the consciousness. Nevertheless, i t so happens that t h o u g h t — w h a t we c a l l consciousness—consists i n positing something. T o t h i n k is to posit something as true, as existent. N o w , phenomenology says t h a t this act o f positing is followed b y a second act w h i c h consists i n p r a c t i c i n g epokhe, i n i n v a l i d a t i n g the first a n d b r a c k e t i n g i t . However, this is neither so clear nor so simple as i t appears. I do not have consciousness o f a n act w h i l e I a m experiencing i t . I have before m e o n l y w h a t is seen or w h a t is thought; I a m n o t i n contact w i t h seeing or thinking, w i t h w h a t is called consciousness. W h a t is i n v o l v e d is: I with the thing. I a m able to say t h a t I have consciousness w h e n I realize t h a t I saw a t h i n g a m o m e n t ago b u t no longer see i t . W h e n I have consciousness o f m y experiences, I a m n o t l i v i n g t h e m , b u t m a k i n g t h e m objects o f reflection. I a m p r a c t i c i n g " a b s t e n t i o n " u p o n a n object t h a t is the memory o f m y previous vision. I a m n o w experiencing another a c t : the bracketing o f m y previous act. N o r a m I p r a c t i c i n g ' ' a b s t e n t i o n ' ' i n this second act; r a t h e r , I a m experiencing i t ; I have no consciousness o f the second act w h i l e experiencing i t , either; i n i t , too, I a m positing. T h u s I can p e r f o r m phenomenological reduct i o n o n l y u p o n memories o f acts, not u p o n the experienced or lived acts. Pure consciousness, w i t h all its reduced experiences, far f r o m being reality, is merely the result of a m e n t a l o p e r a t i o n t h a t I p e r f o r m ; t h a t is, i t is j u s t the opposite of r e a l i t y : i t is a n i n t e l l e c t u a l construction, a hypothesis. Therefore, phenomenological r e d u c t i o n is impossible. Act implies actuality, the present t i m e , being n o w ; i t is p u r e presentness. Time is interposed between the act a n d its phenomenological r e d u c t i o n — t i m e , w h i c h is precisely the f o r m o f h u m a n life. Therefore, I d o n o t come i n t o contact w i t h the p u r e ego, n o r w i t h consciousness, nor w i t h reduced experiences; a l l this is the result o f m y m e n t a l m a n i p u l a t i o n o f m y previous acts: precisely the opposite o f w h a t is meant b y reality. I t is o f the essence o f acts t h a t they are experienced s i m p l y a n d t h a t one can reflect u p o n t h e m o n l y f r o m the vantage p o i n t o f another a c t ; t h a t is, w h e n they are no longer present a n d being experienced, b u t are only i n the m e m o r y . Phenomenology bears w i t h i n itself a basically false i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f p r i m a r y reality. T h e t r u t h is t h a t I experience acts a n d t h a t these acts are intentional: I see something, I t h i n k something, I w a n t something; i n short, I have contact w i t h something. A n d I have contact w i t h i t i n a real a n d effective w a y , w i t h o u t any " a b s t e n t i o n " : in life. W h e n we t h i n k pheno-
The
Genesis
of Ortega's
Philosophy
449
m e n o l o g y t h r o u g h to its basis, we discover its u l t i m a t e erroneous r o o t a n d w e are left outside i t , beyond i t : we find ourselves n o t i n the consciousness, because, strictly speaking, there is none, b u t i n the f u n d a m e n t a l reality t h a t is life. T h i s is Ortega's c r i t i q u e o f idealism. H e adopts whatever was j u s t i f i e d i n the idealist thesis, the a f f i r m a t i o n o f the necessity o f the ego as a n ingredient o f reality, b u t he corrects the excessiveness o f idealism, the a f f i r m a t i o n t h a t this ego is the p r i m a r y reality. Neither the things alone n o r the ego alone is the p r i m a r y reality, b u t their i n t e r p l a y , the '' business " o f the ego w i t h the t h i n g s : i n other words, life.
The Stages in the Discovery I t is o f interest to consider very briefly the phases t h r o u g h w h i c h Ortega's t h o u g h t passed before he a t t a i n e d the m a t u r e f o r m o f his p h i l o s o p h y ; this w i l l shed l i g h t o n the m e a n i n g o f the formulas i n w h i c h the m a j o r theses o f his metaphysics are expressed. I A N D M Y CIRCUMSTANCE. Ortega's personal v i e w p o i n t first appeared i n a n essay published i n 1910 e n t i t l e d " A d á n en el P a r a í s o " ( A d a m i n Paradise; Complete Works, I , 469-498). I n the first place, he there employs the t e r m " l i f e " s t r i c t l y , i n the sense o f h u m a n life, b i o g r a p h i c a l l i f e ; i n the second place, he stresses man's e n v i r o n m e n t , e v e r y t h i n g t h a t surrounds h i m , n o t o n l y directly, b u t also r e m o t e l y ; n o t o n l y physically, b u t also historically a n d spiritually. M a n , O r t e g a says, is the p r o b l e m o f life, a n d O r t e g a understands life as something concrete, incomparable, u n i q u e : " L i f e is i n d i v i d u a l i t y . " H e defines i t w i t h greater precision as coexistence: " L i f e is a n exchange o f substances; therefore, a living together, coexisting" (p. 488). H e adds: " A d a m i n Paradise. W h o is A d a m ? A n y b o d y a n d n o b o d y i n p a r t i c u l a r : life. Where is Paradise ? Is i t a n o r t h e r n or southern l a n d scape? I t does n o t m a t t e r : i t is the u b i q u i t o u s stage for the immense tragedy o f l i v i n g " (p. 489). A d a m i n Paradise signifies: myself i n the w o r l d ; a n d this w o r l d , understood p r o p e r l y , is not a t h i n g o r a collection o f things, b u t a stage, because life is a tragedy or d r a m a , something w h i c h m a n performs, something w h i c h happens to h i m along w i t h the things. I n the Meditaciones del Quijote ( M e d i t a t i o n s o n Q u i x o t e ; 1914) there appears i n the f o r m o f a concept the idea t h a t h a d been expressed as a m e t a p h o r i n the title " A d a m i n P a r a d i s e " : / am myself and my circumstance. T h e reality r o u n d a b o u t m e " f o r m s the other h a l f o f m y person." A n d " t h e reabsorption o f his circumstance is man's concrete destiny." Starting w i t h this p o i n t o f view, O r t e g a makes an
450
Ortega
and His Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f w h a t a forest is, a v o i d i n g the realist as w e l l as the idealist presupposition; t h a t is, he sets i n m o t i o n t h e comprehension o f a r e a l i t y from the viewpoint of life. T h i s doctrine culminates i n a theo r y t h a t sees t r u t h as patency o r u n v e i l i n g — a l e t h e i a — c i v i l i z a t i o n as security, a n d l i g h t or c l a r i t y as t h e root o f man's c o n s t i t u t i o n (Complete Works, I , 322-358). PERSPECTIVISM. I n the same w o r k there also appears t h e idea t h a t perspective is a constituent i n g r e d i e n t o f r e a l i t y : " T h e definitive b e i n g o f the w o r l d is neither m a t t e r n o r soul, n o r a n y d e t e r m i n e d t h i n g ; i t is a perspective" ( p . 3 2 1 ) . T h i s doctrine is f o u n d already established as a doctrine ( a n d even endowed w i t h t h e n a m e perspectivism, w h i c h Ortega came t o prefer after t r y i n g other, less intellectualist names) i n a paper o f 1916, " V e r d a d y perspectiva'' ( T r u t h a n d Perspective; i n El Espectador, I ; Complete Works, I I , 15—20). " T h e i n d i v i d u a l p o i n t o f view seems to m e to be the only p o i n t o f view f r o m w h i c h we can see the w o r l d i n its t r u t h . " " Reality, precisely because i t is r e a l i t y a n d is f o u n d outside o u r i n d i v i d u a l m i n d s , c a n reach o u r m i n d s o n l y b y m u l t i p l y i n g itself i n t o a thousand faces o r facets." '' R e a l i t y can be looked at o n l y f r o m the vantage p o i n t w h i c h each a n d every m a n occupies, b y fate, i n the universe. Reality a n d t h e vantage p o i n t are correlates, a n d j u s t as r e a l i t y cannot be i n v e n t e d , so t h e vantage p o i n t cannot be f e i g n e d . " " Every m a n has a mission o f t r u t h . W h e r e m y eye is, there is no o t h e r ; t h a t p a r t o f r e a l i t y w h i c h m y eye sees is seen b y no other. T h e r e is n o substitute for a n y o f us, we are a l l necessary." I n 1923 he adds, i n a n even more precise a n d strict f o r m u l a t i o n : " Perspective is one of the components of reality. F a r f r o m being a d e f o r m a t i o n o f reality, i t is its o r g a n i z a t i o n . A r e a l i t y w h i c h w o u l d always t u r n o u t to be the same n o m a t t e r w h a t p o i n t i t was viewed f r o m is a n absurd c o n c e p t . " " T h i s w a y o f t h i n k i n g leads t o a fundam e n t a l r e f o r m a t i o n o f philosophy a n d , w h a t is m o r e i m p o r t a n t , a r e f o r m a t i o n o f o u r cosmic sensation." "Every life is a viewpoint on the universe." (El tema de nuestro tiempo [ T h e T h e m e of O u r T i m e ] ; Complete Works, I I I , 199-200). R E A S O N A N D L I F E . R e t u r n i n g again to Meditaciones del Quijote (the year 1914 is a decisive one for Ortega's t h o u g h t ) we f i n d i n t h a t book the beginnings o f a t h i r d theme, w h i c h is i n t i m a t e l y connected w i t h the t w o preceding ones a n d w h i c h w i l l affect b o t h o f t h e m w h e n i t reaches its m a t u r e f o r m u l a t i o n : the theme o f the r e l a t i o n s h i p between reason a n d life. " Reason cannot, need n o t aspire to replace life. T h i s very opposition between reason a n d life, w h i c h is used so m u c h today b y those w h o do n o t wish to w o r k , is already suspect. As i f reason were not a v i t a l a n d spontaneous f u n c t i o n o f the same type as sight o r
Vital
Reason
t o u c h ! " " W h e n we dethrone reason, let us be careful to p u t i t i n its proper p l a c e " (Complete Works, I , 353-354). T h i s idea reappears i n a m u c h m o r e precise a n d rigorous f o r m i n El tema de nuestro tiempo, where i t has become a doctrine o f vital reason: "Reason is only a form and function of life." "Pure reason must yield its domination to vital reason" (Complete Works, I I I , 178). L a t e r o n he says: "Pure reason must be replaced by a vital reason, in which pure reason can be localized and can acquire fluidity and the power of transformation." Philosophy needs to set aside its U t o p i a n nature, "preventing that which is a supple and expandable horizon from being ankylosed into a world." " W e l l , t h e n : the r e d u c t i o n or conversion of the w o r l d i n t o a h o r i z o n does not i n the least r o b i t of r e a l i t y ; i t merely relates i t to the l i v i n g subject, whose w o r l d i t is, a n d endows i t w i t h a v i t a l d i m e n s i o n " ( p p . 201-202). A c c o r d i n g to O r t e g a , the theme o f o u r t i m e is the conversion o f pure reason i n t o v i t a l reason: f r o m t h a t p o i n t on, his philosophy is the systematic achievement o f t h a t task. 3.
VITAL
REASON
F U N D A M E N T A L R E A L I T Y . O r t e g a says t i m e a n d again t h a t the f u n d a m e n t a l reality is o u r life. B u t this expression must be understood strictly. Fundamental r e a l i t y does not mean the " s o l e " r e a l i t y or the " m o s t i m p o r t a n t " r e a l i t y ; i t merely means w h a t i t indicates: the reality w h i c h is thefoundation for a l l other realities, i n w h i c h they have their root. T h e reality o f the things or o f the ego occurs in life, as an aspect o f life. " H u m a n l i f e , " O r t e g a writes i n Historia como sistema ( H i s t o r y as a System; Complete Works, V I , 13), " i s a strange reality, concerning w h i c h the first t h i n g t h a t may be said is t h a t i t is the fundam e n t a l reality, i n the sense t h a t we must relate a l l other realities to i t , since the other realities, actual or presumptive, must appear i n life i n one w a y o r another.'' R e a l i t y as such—as I have w r i t t e n elsewhere * — r e a l i t y as reality, is constituted w i t h i n m y life; to be real means, precisely, to have a basis i n m y life, a n d every r e a l i t y must be related to m y life, a l t h o u g h that which is real m a y transcend m y life i n some way. I n other words, m y life is the presupposition of the v e r y idea a n d sense of reality, a n d reality is i n t e l l i g i b l e only f r o m the standpoint of m y life: this means that the t e r m real can be understood f u n d a m e n t a l l y , i n its u l t i m a t e sense, o n l y w i t h i n m y life. B u t one should n o t forget that w h e n we speak oí something real a n d derive its aspect o f ' ' r e a l i t y ' ' f r o m m y life, the question o f the relationship o f m y life w i t h this "somet h i n g " remains open; stated i n a different way, to say t h a t I a m an * Introducción a la Filosofía, V I I , 66. Cf. also X I , 86.
4J2
Ortega
and His
Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
ingredient o f r e a l i t y does not signify i n any w a y that I a m a p a r t or component o f the real things or entities; rather, i t means t h a t the effective n a t u r e o f t h e i r " r e a l i t y , " understood as the d i m e n s i o n or nature o f t h a t w h i c h is real, is based o n t h e i r " existence for m e , " t h e i r " being rooted i n m y l i f e . " Even i n the case where that which is real is p r i o r , superior a n d transcendent to m y life, independent o f i t a n d even — i n the case of G o d — t h e o r i g i n a n d basis o f m y life itself, its reality as such ( i f we w i s h to give some effective m e a n i n g to t h a t t e r m a n d n o t reduce i t to a n e m p t y name or a n a m b i g u i t y ) has its foundation i n the f u n d a m e n t a l r e a l i t y o f m y life, to w h i c h i t is " related " i n so far as i t is " encountered " i n i t . V I T A L REASON A N D H I S T O R I C A L R E A S O N . F o r centuries, ever since
the Greeks, reason has been understood as something w h i c h grasps the i m m u t a b l e , the " e t e r n a l " essence o f the things. Philosophers have sought to consider things sub specie aeternitatis, a p a r t f r o m t i m e . T h i s view o f reason culminates i n the m a t h e m a t i c a l reason o f the seventeenth-century rationalists, w h i c h produces the physical sciences, a n d i n K a n t ' s " p u r e r e a s o n . " B u t this m a t h e m a t i c a l reason, w h i c h is so useful i n investigating nature, t h a t is, those things w h i c h have a fixed being, a ready-made reality, does n o t w o r k so w e l l i n h u m a n affairs. T h e sciences o f h u m a n i t y — s o c i o l o g y , p o l i t i c a l science, h i s t o r y — appear strangely imperfect i n comparison w i t h the marvels o f the abstract n a t u r a l sciences a n d their corresponding applied sciences. M a t h e m a t i c a l reason is incapable o f conceiving the changing, temporal reality o f h u m a n life. W h e n dealing w i t h h u m a n life, we cannot t h i n k sub specie aeternitatis, b u t must t h i n k i n terms o f t i m e . T h i s self-evident fact, w h i c h to a greater or lesser extent has cont i n u e d to impress itself u p o n philosophical t h o u g h t since the nineteenth century, has been the source o f the waves o f i r r a t i o n a l i s m t h a t have i n u n d a t e d philosophy d u r i n g the last h u n d r e d years. O r t e g a , i n no w a y a " r a t i o n a l i s t , " is opposed to every f o r m o f i r r a t i o n a l i s m . H e has w r i t t e n : " F o r me, reason a n d theory are synonymous. . . . M y ideology does n o t oppose reason, since i t admits o f no other m o d e of theoretic knowledge b u t reason; i t opposes o n l y r a t i o n a l i s m " (jV¿ vitalismo ni racionalismo [ N e i t h e r V i t a l i s m N o r R a t i o n a l i s m ] ; Complete Works, I I I , 237). T h e most authentic a n d p r i m a r y i m p o r t o f reason is " a c c o u n t i n g for [ g i v i n g a reason for] s o m e t h i n g " ; now, the r a t i o n alist does n o t take i n t o account the i r r a t i o n a l i t y o f the materials w i t h w h i c h reason deals, a n d he believes t h a t things behave the w a y o u r ideas do. T h i s error essentially mutilates reason a n d reduces i t to something p a r t i a l a n d secondary. " A l l the definitions of reason t h a t made its essential aspect consist o f certain special ways o f using the
Vital Reason
4J3
intellect were n o t o n l y too n a r r o w ; they sterilized reason, a m p u t a t i n g or b l u n t i n g its decisive dimension. F o r me, reason, i n the true a n d precise sense, is every intellectual a c t i o n t h a t puts us i n contact w i t h reality, b y means o f w h i c h we meet w i t h the transcendent" (Historia como sistema; Complete Works, V I , 46). I n fact, O r t e g a observes that m a t h e m a t i c a l reason, p u r e reason, is o n l y a p a r t i c u l a r species or f o r m o f reason. T o understand m a t h e m a t i c a l reason as reason p u r e a n d simple is to take the p a r t for the w h o l e : a n error. Alongside m a t h e m a t i c a l , " e t e r n a l " reason, a n d above i t , is vital reason. T h i s reason is no less reason t h a n the other k i n d , j u s t the c o n t r a r y . As we have seen, O r t e g a is a n y t h i n g b u t a " v i t a l i s t " w i t h a leaning t o w a r d i r r a t i o n a l i s m . H e is speaking o f a strict reason t h a t is capable o f apprehending the t e m p o r a l reality o f life. V i t a l reason is ratio, logos, a precise concept. W h a t does i t actually consist of? V i t a l reason a n d l i v i n g are " o n e a n d the same t h i n g " ; life itself is v i t a l reason, because " t o live is to have no other remedy t h a n to reason i n the face o f one's inexorable c i r c u m s t a n c e " (En torno a Galileo; Complete Works, V , 67). W h a t does this mean? T o be alive is already to u n d e r s t a n d ; the p r i m a r y a n d f u n d a m e n t a l f o r m o f i n t e l lection is h u m a n v i t a l action. T o understand something means to relate i t to the t o t a l i t y o f m y life i n progress, t h a t is, m y life as i t is developing, as i t is living. I t is life itself w h i c h makes a t h i n g i n t e l l i g i b l e b y p l a c i n g i t i n its perspective, b y inserting i t i n its context a n d m a k i n g i t function i n t h a t context. Life is therefore the very organ of comprehension. T h u s , i t m a y be said t h a t reason is human life. A h u m a n reality becomes i n t e l l i g i b l e o n l y f r o m the v i e w p o i n t o f life, w h e n related to t h a t t o t a l i t y i n w h i c h i t is rooted. O n l y w h e n life itself functions as reason are we able to understand something h u m a n . Stated w i t h the utmost conciseness, this is w h a t is m e a n t b y vital reason. B u t the h o r i z o n o f h u m a n life is h i s t o r i c a l ; m a n is defined b y the historical level at w h i c h i t has been his l o t to l i v e ; w h a t m a n has been is a n essential component o f w h a t he is; he is w h a t he is today precisely because he was other things f o r m e r l y ; the r e a l m of h u m a n life includes history. Life w h i c h functions as ratio is historical i n its very substance, a n d history functions i n every act o f real intellection. V i t a l reason is b y its n a t u r e historical reason. * O r t e g a w r i t e s : " I t is a question o f finding the o r i g i n a l a n d autochthonous reason o f history i n history itself. Therefore the expression ' h i s t o r i c a l reason' must be understood w i t h f u l l rigor. N o t a n extra¬ * For an extended investigation of the problem of reason, see Chapter V of my Introduction a la Filosqfia, especially pp. 47-49, from which I have extracted the preceding formulations.
454
Ortega
and His
Philosophy
oj Vital
Reason
historical reason w h i c h appears to f u l f i l l itself i n history, b u t l i t e r a l l y , that which has happened to man,
constituting
substantive
reason, the r e v e l a t i o n
o f a reality w h i c h transcends man's theories a n d w h i c h is m a n himself at the b o t t o m of his theories." " H i s t o r i c a l reason accepts n o t h i n g as a mere fact, b u t fluidifies every fact i n t o the fieri f r o m w h i c h i t stems: i t sees h o w
the fact is m a d e " (Historia
como sistema;
Complete
Works,
VI,
49-50). I t is obvious t h a t this presupposes the elaboration o f a series o f m e n t a l categories a n d forms capable o f grasping historical a n d v i t a l r e a l i t y ; the m i n d ' s h a b i t of t h i n k i n g things, substances i n the " Eleatic " sense, as O r t e g a says, makes i t v e r y difficult to a r r i v e at a n adequate concept o f t h a t w h i c h is n o t a " t h i n g , " b u t a n activity, t e m p o r a l life. O r t e g a asks us to pass beyond the n o t i o n of substance a n d every f o r m o f Eleatic t h o u g h t , so t h a t we can conceive this r e a l i t y w h i c h makes itself. " I n order to speak o f being-man, we must f o r m u l a t e a n o n Eleatic concept of being, j u s t as we have f o r m u l a t e d a n o n - E u c l i d e a n geometry. T h e t i m e has come for the seed sown b y H e r a c l i t u s to produce its great h a r v e s t . " Since the v i t a l is always i n d i v i d u a l a n d u n i q u e , determined b y its surroundings, the concepts w h i c h appreh e n d life must be " occasional," such as " I , " " y o u , " " t h i s , " " t h a t , " " h e r e , " " n o w , " even ( a n d especially) " l i f e , " w h i c h is always " t h e life o f each a n d every m a n . " W e are dealing, t h a t is, w i t h concepts t h a t do n o t always signify the same thing; rather, t h e i r sense depends, w i t h f u l l r i g o r , o n their circumstance. T h u s , historical a n d v i t a l reason is narrative; b u t i t presupposes, i n its t u r n , a n analytics o r abstract theory of h u m a n life, universal a n d v a l i d for a l l life, w h i c h becomes filled i n each case w i t h circumstantial p a r t i c u l a r i t y . P H I L O S O P H Y . M a n does n o t consist p r i m a r i l y of knowing. K n o w i n g is one o f the things t h a t m a n does; m a n cannot be defined—as r a t i o n a l i s m defined h i m — b y his cognitive dimension. K n o w l e d g e occurs i n life a n d must be derived f r o m i t . O n e cannot call knowledge something n a t u r a l a n d make i t one's p o i n t o f d e p a r t u r e ; r a t h e r , one m u s t e x p l a i n for what reason a n d for what purpose m a n knows. T h e r e is n o t h i n g h u m a n i n m a n t h a t is natural; everything i n h i m must be d e r i v e d f r o m his life. T h i s life is something w h i c h w e must make. I t is thus a p r o b l e m , insecurity, a shipwreck, as O r t e g a calls i t i n a n expressive m e t a p h o r . I n this insecurity m a n seeks a c e r t a i n t y ; he needs to know, i n the p r i m a r y sense o f " to k n o w w h a t to h o l d fast t o . " Life is always supported b y a system of beliefs w i t h i n w h i c h we exist a n d w h i c h we m a y n o t even be aware of; w h e n these beliefs fail m a n , he must do something i n order to k n o w w h a t to h o l d fast t o , a n d this t h i n g t h a t m a n does, whatever it may
Human
Life
455
be, is called thought. T h e n m a n comes to have ideas a b o u t the things. N o w , not a l l t h o u g h t is knowledge i n the strict sense; knowledge consists o f ascertaining what the things are, a n d this presupposes the p r i o r belief t h a t the things have a being a n d t h a t this being is k n o w a b l e b y m a n . (See Apuntes sobre el pensamiento [Notes o n T h o u g h t ] — a b r i e f b u t decisive study w h i c h contains the g e r m o f a t r a n s f o r m a t i o n o f p h i losophy ; Complete Works, V , 513-542.) K n o w l e d g e is thus one o f the essential ways i n w h i c h m a n overcomes u n c e r t a i n t y ; b y means o f knowledge I come to possess not the things—these I already have before me, hence m y i n q u i r y — b u t the being o f the things. Being is something t h a t I make, b u t i t must be clearly understood that I make i t with the things; being is a n i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of reality, m y scheme o f h o l d i n g fast to the things. W h e n I receive k n o w l edge, i t is this being o f the t h i n g s — a n d not the things themselves— t h a t passes i n t o m y m i n d : the b e i n g o f the m o u n t a i n , n o t the m o u n t a i n itself. Therefore knowledge is a m a n i p u l a t i o n or, better yet, a " m e n t a l c o n s t r u c t i o n " (mentefactura) o f reality, w h i c h is deformed or transf o r m e d b y i t ; a n d this is n o t a deficiency on the p a r t o f knowledge, b u t its essence, a n d its interest consists precisely i n this. M a n never possesses complete knowledge, b u t neither does he ever completely lack knowledge. H i s state is one o f ignorance or insufficient t r u t h . M a n possesses m a n y certainties, b u t they lack a n u l t i m a t e basis a n d some are i n c o n t r a d i c t i o n to others. M a n needs a basic certainty, a highest a u t h o r i t y that can reconcile a l l antagonisms; this certainty is philosophy. Thus philosophy is the basic t r u t h , the one t h a t does not presuppose other authorities or t r u t h s ; i t must t h e n be the highest a u t h o r i t y for a l l the other p a r t i c u l a r truths. A n d therefore i t must also be a n autonomous and universal certainty. T h i s is w h a t makes i t different f r o m the sciences, w h i c h are p a r t i a l truths a n d dependent o n p r i o r suppositions. B u t i n a d d i t i o n , philosophy is its own proof; i t is responsible a n d is made by man, a n d this distinguishes i t f r o m r e l i g i o n , w h i c h is based o n revelation a n d therefore comes f r o m G o d , a n d f r o m poetry or the experience o f life, w h i c h are " i r r e s p o n s i b l e " a n d d o n o t constitute p r o o f o f themselves, even t h o u g h they are universal. T h u s , philosophy is a task or "business" t h a t m a n , w h o is lost, carries o n i n order to a t t a i n a basic certainty t h a t can i n f o r m h i m w h a t to h o l d fast to i n life. T h i s explains for w h a t reason a n d for w h a t purpose m a n philosophizes.
4.
HUMAN
LIFE
T H E " I " A N D T H E W O R L D . T h e fundamental r e a l i t y — t h a t which I find all a r o u n d me a n d distinct f r o m a l l forms o f i n t e r p r e t a t i o n or
4j6
Ortega
and His Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
t h e o r y — i s my life. A n d life is w h a t we d o a n d w h a t happens to us. I n other words, I find myself w i t h the things, i n a d e t e r m i n e d c i r c u m stance or surroundings, h a v i n g to do something w i t h t h e things i n order to live. T h u s I find myself i n the m i d s t of life, w h i c h is p r i o r to the things a n d to m e ; m y life is given to me, not as s o m e t h i n g already made, b u t as something to be done (quehacer). Ortega says t h a t life, i n effect, affords m u c h to be done. T h e most condensed statement o f Ortega's p h i l o s o p h y is the sentence f r o m the Meditaciones del Quijote t h a t I quoted earlier : / am myself and my circumstance (or surroundings). T h e things are i n t e r preted as circum-stantia, as t h a t w h i c h surrounds the " I , " a n d therefore the things refer to the " I . " Therefore this involves a world w h i c h is not the s u m t o t a l o f the things, b u t the horizon o f t o t a l i t y over the things a n d separate f r o m t h e m ; the things are in the world, j ust as I a m ; but this w o r l d is m y w o r l d , t h a t is, m y circumstance. T o live is to be i n the w o r l d , to act i n i t , to be d o i n g s o m e t h i n g w i t h the things. T h u s m y circumstance consists o f the other-than-I, everyt h i n g t h a t I encounter, including my body and psyche. I can be dissatisfied w i t h m y b o d y a n d also w i t h m y disposition, intelligence o r m e m o r y ; therefore, these things are received; I find myself w i t h t h e m j u s t as I find myself facing the w a l l ; these realities are the ones t h a t are closest to me, b u t they are n o t I . M y circumstance, w h i c h on t h e one h a n d includes even m y b o d y a n d psyche, o n the other h a n d also comprises all of society, t h a t is, a l l other m e n , social customs, the e n t i r e r e p e r t o r y of beliefs, ideas a n d opinions t h a t I find i n m y t i m e ; thus i t is also m y historical circumstance. A n d since I do n o t possess reality b y itself, a n d since I make m y life essentially with m y circumstance, I cannot be separated f r o m m y circumstance a n d i t a n d I together m a k e m y l i f e whole. T h i s is w h y Ortega says : I a m myself a n d m y circumstance, and i f I d o n o t save i t , I do n o t save myself. T h i s p r o f o u n d analysis leads to a series o f i m p o r t a n t questions, questions dealing w i t h the who t h a t is anyone, the " / " t h a t makes its life w i t h its circumstance or w o r l d — i n short, w i t h the m a j o r question of the person. T H E V I T A L PROJECT. Since life is n o t something t h a t is ready-made, but something t h a t m a n must make for himself, m a n must determine beforehand what he is going to be. O r t e g a says t h a t life is a poetic task, because m a n must i n v e n t w h a t he is g o i n g to be. I a m a v i t a l p r o g r a m , a project or o u t l i n e t h a t I i n t e n d to c a r r y o u t a n d t h a t I h a v e h a d to conceive i n v i e w o f m y circumstance. I find myself faced w i t h a repertory or k e y b o a r d of possibilities a n d obligations, a n d I can live o n l y b y choosing a m o n g t h e m . T h e possibilities are finite, b u t there are
Human
Life
451
always several o f t h e m , a n d they seem t o be m a n y w h e n I project m y scheme or v i t a l p r o g r a m u p o n the p u r e facilities a n d difficulties t h a t go to make u p m y circumstance. Therefore m a n cannot live w i t h o u t a v i t a l project, be i t o r i g i n a l or u n o r i g i n a l , w o r t h y or u n w o r t h y ; for good or i l l , m a n m u s t be the novelist o f his o w n life, he must imagine o r invent the character he intends to be; consequently h u m a n life is, above all,pre-tension. " H u m a n l i f e , " O r t e g a writes, " i s n o t a n e n t i t y t h a t changes accidentally; o n the c o n t r a r y , its 'substance' is precisely change, w h i c h means t h a t i t cannot be t h o u g h t o f Eleatically as substance. Since life is a ' d r a m a ' t h a t happens a n d the 'subject' to w h o m i t happens is n o t a ' t h i n g ' apart and p r i o r to the d r a m a , b u t a f u n c t i o n o f i t , t h e n t h e ' substance' is its plot. A n d i f this varies, i t means t h a t the v a r i a t i o n is ' s u b s t a n t i a l . ' . . . T h e most disparate forms o f being h a p pen to m a n . T o the despair o f the intellectualists, being is i n m a n mere happening a n d happening to him.... M a n ' goes o n b e i n g ' a n d ' u n b e i n g ' — l i v i n g . M a n continues to accumulate b e i n g — t h e past: he goes o n m a k i n g a b e i n g for himself t h r o u g h his dialectical series o f experiments. . . . M a n is w h a t has happened to h i m , w h a t he has done. . . . This p i l g r i m o f being, this substantial e m i g r a n t , is m a n . . . . I n short, man has no nature; he has instead . . . history. O r , w h a t amounts to the same t h i n g : w h a t n a t u r e is to the things, h i s t o r y — a s res gestae—is to m a n . " (Historia como sistema; Complete Works, V I , 35-41). B u t elsewhere: " T h e b e i n g o f m a n is n a t u r a l a n d e x t r a n a t u r a l at the same time, a species o f ontological c e n t a u r " (Complete Works, V , 3 3 4 ) ; a n d also: " H u m a n r e a l i t y has an inexorable structure, w h i c h is neither more n o r less t h a n cosmic matter " (Complete Works, V I , 242). E T H I C S . N o t every activity is a d o i n g . C e r t a i n activities—for example, psychical activities—are p u r e mechanisms. Strictly speaki n g , they are n o t things I do, b u t things t h a t are done or produced i n m e : I refer to such activities as i m a g i n i n g , r e m e m b e r i n g , t h i n k i n g ; at most, w h a t I do is to begin to t h i n k or i m a g i n e , i n i t i a t e t h a t a c t i v i t y , for whose result I cannot answer. I can begin to solve a p r o b l e m or w r i t e a sonnet, b u t i t is n o t i n m y hands to find the answer or the a p p r o p r i a t e rhymes a n d metaphors. Doing is an a c t i v i t y w h i c h / perform,/or some reason a n d for some purpose, and therefore something for w h i c h I a m responsible. W e l l , t h e n , m y life is a task to be done, something I must do myself; I have at every m o m e n t to decide w h a t I a m going to do-—and therefore b e — a t the next m o m e n t ; I must choose a m o n g the possibilities t h a t I encounter, a n d no one can relieve m e o f this choice a n d decision. T h e p r o b l e m oifreedom is thus stated i n a n e n t i r e l y new w a y i n Ortega's
4j8
Ortega
and H i s Philosophy
of Vital
Reason
philosophy. F r e e d o m consists i n t h a t c o m p u l s o r y choice a m o n g possibilities. " T o be free means to lack constitutive i d e n t i t y , t o n o t be ascribed to a d e t e r m i n e d being, to be able t o be other t h a n w h a t one was a n d to n o t be able t o establish oneself once a n d f o r a l l i n a n y determined b e i n g . " M a n is thus constitutively a n d necessarily free, b u t this does n o t m e a n t h a t he is completely a n d forever free. Inasm u c h as his life is n o t ready-made, b u t something he has t o make for himself, m a n cannot cease to be free; m a n is necessarily free: he does n o t have the freedom to renounce his freedom. Since I have t o decide w h a t I a m going t o do at every m o m e n t , I need to justify myself to myself for d o i n g one t h i n g a n d n o t a n o t h e r ; life is responsibility, i n its u l t i m a t e substance, i t is moral. L i k e a l l h u m a n r e a l i t y , life admits o f degrees of being. T h e things are w h a t they are: a stone is a stone a n d a horse is a horse; i t is meaningless t o say t h a t a horse is more or less o f a horse; b u t i n contrast, i t makes perfect sense to say t h a t a w o m a n is quite a woman, or t h a t a m a n is either quite a m a n or not much of a m a n . Since the being of life is n o t already a n d i m m e d i ately given, i t can be realized fully or insufficiently; i t c a n be falsified. W h e n one's life is m a d e f r o m one's o w n s t a n d p o i n t , w h e n a m a n is t r u e to the voice w h i c h calls h i m to be a d e t e r m i n e d t h i n g , a n d w h i c h is therefore k n o w n as his vocation, his life is authentic; w h e n m a n abandons himself to w h a t is t r i t e a n d h a n d e d d o w n , w h e n he is u n f a i t h f u l to his i n t i m a t e a n d o r i g i n a l v o c a t i o n , he falsifies his life a n d changes i t i n t o unauthentic life. M o r a l i t y consists i n a u t h e n t i c i t y , i n b r i n g i n g life to its m a x i m u m r e a l i t y ; to live is to live more. M o r a l i t y consists i n each man's r e a l i z i n g his o w n u n i q u e a n d unsubstitutable destiny.
5. THE
HISTORICAL A N D SOCIAL L I F E
H I S T O R I C I T Y OF H U M A N L I F E . M a n
finds h i m s e l f l i v i n g i n a
p a r t i c u l a r p e r i o d o f t i m e : at a specific h i s t o r i c a l level. H i s life is composed of a peculiar substance, " h i s t i m e . " Whereas a tiger is always the " first t i g e r , " the one w h o is being a tiger for t h e first t i m e , m a n is the inheritor of a past, o f a series of past h u m a n experiences t h a t c o n d i t i o n his being a n d his possibilities. M a n has been c e r t a i n concrete things, a n d therefore he c a n no longer be t h e m a n d must be other determ i n e d things. I n d i v i d u a l life is thus already h i s t o r i c a l ; h i s t o r i c i t y is a n essential p a r t o f the life o f every one of us. Therefore, " i n order to understand a n y t h i n g h u m a n , be i t personal or collective, i t is necessary to relate its history. T h i s m a n , this n a t i o n does such a n d such a t h i n g a n d is as he or i t is because previously he or i t d i d this other t h i n g
Historical
and Social
Life
459
a n d was this other way. Life o n l y becomes somewhat t r a n s p a r e n t , " O r t e g a says,'' w h e n viewed t h r o u g h historical reason The individual h u m a n being does n o t i n a u g u r a t e h u m a n i t y . H e i m m e d i a t e l y encounters i n his surroundings other m e n a n d the society w h i c h they comprise. Hence his h u m a n i t y , t h a t w h i c h begins t o develop i n h i m , takes its p o i n t of departure f r o m another t h a t has previously developed a n d reached its c u l m i n a t i o n ; i n short, t o his h u m a n i t y there is added a n already forged mode of being m a n , something that he does not have to i n v e n t ; he need only r o o t himself i n i t a n d use i t as a starting p o i n t for his i n d i v i d u a l d e v e l o p m e n t . " (Historia como sistema; Complete Works, V I , 4 0 - 4 3 ) . T H E GENERATIONS. H i s t o r y has a precise structure, t h a t o f the generations. Every m a n finds a w o r l d t h a t is determined b y a repertory o f beliefs, ideas, usages a n d problems. Such a f o r m o f life possesses a c e r t a i n stability, i t lasts for a certain p e r i o d of time. O r t e g a says t h a t i t lasts fifteen years.'' A generation is a zone o f fifteen years d u r i n g w h i c h a c e r t a i n f o r m of life was prevalent. T h u s the generation represents the concrete u n i t o f authentic historical chronology; or, expressed differe n t l y , history advances a n d proceeds b y generations. W e c a n n o w u n d e r s t a n d the true nature o f the affinity between m e n o f a single generation. T h i s affinity derives n o t so m u c h f r o m t h e m as f r o m t h e i r r e a l i z i n g t h a t they are obliged to live i n a w o r l d t h a t has a d e t e r m i n e d a n d u n i q u e f o r m . " (Complete Works, V I , 371). Generations are determined b y a central date a n d constitute a " z o n e o f d a t e s " o f fifteen years—seven years before a n d seven years after the decisive year. T h u s a generation is c o m m o n to a l l w h o were b o r n w i t h i n this zone o f dates. O r t e g a makes a d i s t i n c t i o n between contemporaries—those w h o are l i v i n g at the same t i m e — a n d coevals— those w h o are o f the same age, t h a t is, w h o belong t o the same generation. T h e decisive generations are those i n w h i c h historical v a r i a t i o n is m u c h greater t h a n u s u a l ; they govern the over-all struct u r e o f historical epochs. I n Ortega's h a n d , the method oj the generations becomes a tool o f exemplary precision i n understanding historical reality. * M A N A N D PEOPLE. O n e of the things we find i n the r e a l m o f o u r life is society, social acts—customs, l a w , the State. These social acts are subscribed t o only b y m e n ; n o t h i n g t h a t deserves to be called social is to be f o u n d among the other creatures, a n d the so-called " a n i m a l societies " are something v e r y different. Society is thus a fact o f h u m a n life. H o w e v e r , this raises a serious p r o b l e m , because h u m a n life is * See J . M a r í a s , El método histórico de las generaciones (1949) and the chapter entitled " D i n á m i c a de las generaciones" in La estructura social (1955).
460
Ortega and His Philosophy of Vital Reason
always my life, each man's life, t h e life of every one of us. I t is life o n a n i n d i v i d u a l a n d personal basis, i n w h i c h the " / " finds itself i n surroundings or a w o r l d , w i t h o u t the security o f existing i n t h e i m m e d i a t e i n s t a n t a n d h a v i n g always to be d o i n g something i n o r d e r to assure its existence. T h u s , to be precise, w h a t is h u m a n is w h a t I do myself, w h a t is personal, w h a t has m e a n i n g for m e , a n d therefore w h a t I u n d e r stand. Therefore, h u m a n a c t i o n presupposes a responsible subject, a n d life is, i n its essence, solitariness. O n the other h a n d , w h a t is social does n o t arise f r o m m y solitude, b u t f r o m m y living jointly w i t h other men. T h u s , society is not life i n its p r i m a r y sense. B y w h o m are the social acts performed? A m a n shakes hands because i t is w h a t one does; a p o l i c e m a n stops traffic because he is ordered to. W h o is the subject i n t h e social acts ? E v e r y b o d y a n d n o b o d y i n p a r t i c u l a r ; collective h u m a n i t y , society; i n short, people. Therefore, social actions are h u m a n a n d not something else; h o w ever, they do n o t originate w i t h t h e i n d i v i d u a l ; they are n o t desired b y the i n d i v i d u a l a n d frequently t h e y are n o t even understood b y h i m . T o cite a t r i v i a l b u t i m m e d i a t e example, one does n o t k n o w w h y one m a n greets another b y shaking hands. T H E I N T E R I N D I V I D U A L A N D T H E SOCIAL. However, a c e r t a i n confusion has always prevented sociologists f r o m seeing t h e i r problems clearly. T h e y have t r a d i t i o n a l l y contrasted w h a t is i n d i v i d u a l w i t h w h a t is social or collective: o n t h e one h a n d , the i n d i v i d u a l m a n ; o n the other, t w o or more m e n l i v i n g j o i n t l y , w h i c h sociologists have i n t e r p r e t e d as collective h u m a n i t y o r society. Ortega establishes a n essential distinction w h i c h opens the w a y to a new sociology. T h e r e are t w o v e r y different ways i n w h i c h m e n live j o i n t l y . O n e o f these is the interindividual way, a relationship between t w o or m o r e i n d i v i d u a l s as such: love, friendship, a n d so o n , are i n t e r i n d i v i d u a l acts; they are instances o f the coexistence o f i n d i v i d u a l s as i n d i v i d u a l s . W h a t is i n t e r i n d i v i d u a l does not leave the r e a l m o f i n d i v i d u a l life, life sensu stricto. I n contrast, the other w a y is p r o p e r l y social; i t is i m p e r s o n a l a n d neither spontaneous nor responsible. Shaking hands, the policeman's stopping traffic, the postman's relationship w i t h the addressee o f a letter—these are not o r i g i n a l a n d v o l u n t a r y acts of i n d i v i d u a l s as such w h i c h i n d i v i d u a l s desire a n d understand. M a n merely performs social acts i n a mechanical fashion. CUSTOMS. A custom is w h a t we t h i n k , say or do because i t is w h a t one thinks, says o r does. Social acts are p r i n c i p a l l y customs. Customs do not o r d i n a r i l y originate w i t h i n d i v i d u a l s , b u t are imposed b y society, b y people. I f we d o not observe t h e m , society makes reprisals against us (social disapproval o f the m a n w h o does n o t greet others p r o p e r l y ,
Historical
and Social
Life
461
j u r i d i c a l or governmental pressure o n the m a n w h o crosses the street illegally). Customs are irrational a n d impersonal. T h e y are "social or collective l i f e , " a very strange f o r m o f life t h a t lacks some o f life's essential characteristics, something halfway between n a t u r e a n d m a n , a n " almost n a t u r e . " T h e r e is no such t h i n g as a collective soul." Society, collectivity, is the great soulless entity, for i t is h u m a n i t y t h a t has been n a t u r a l i z e d , mechanized, almost m i n e r a l i z e d . " Therefore i t is m e a n i n g f u l to call i t the social " w o r l d . " ( R e m e m b e r the p r o b l e m t h a t the " o b j e c t i v e s p i r i t " posed for Hegel.) Ortega says t h a t these customs p e r m i t us to foresee the conduct o f i n d i v i d u a l s w h o m we d o n o t k n o w , allow us almost to coexist w i t h strangers. F u r t h e r m o r e , they give us the i n h e r i t a n c e o f the past a n d b r i n g us abreast o f the t i m e s ; this explains h o w there can be progress and h i s t o r y : because there is society. F i n a l l y , customs, w h i l e rendering m a n y aspects o f life inflexible a n d automatic, give m a n openness for w h a t is most personal a n d a l l o w h i m " to create w h a t is new, r a t i o n a l and more p e r f e c t . " S O C I E T Y A N D DISSOCIATION. However, one must take note o f a n extremely i m p o r t a n t p o i n t : i f m e n are sociable, they are also u n sociable. T h a t is to say, society is never characterized b y s t a b i l i t y ; i t exists as a n effort to overcome dissociation a n d u n s o c i a b i l i t y ; i t is always p r o b l e m a t i c a l . Hence the f r i g h t e n i n g p a r t o f its character, its ties t o a u t h o r i t y , politics a n d the State, w h i c h " i n the f i n a l analysis are always v i o l e n c e — i n the best o f times, to a lesser degree; d u r i n g social crises, to a n a w f u l d e g r e e . " O n e m u s t c o m p r e h e n d collective life as w e l l as i n d i v i d u a l life because w h a t is collective happens to m a n i n his i n d i v i d u a l life. A f t e r s t u d y i n g h u m a n life i n its o r i g i n a l i t y , b y means o f the philosophy o f v i t a l reason one can a p p r o a c h the t w o m a j o r themes o f collective " life " : society a n d history. T h i s b r i e f sketch o f Ortega's philosophy, w h i c h cannot begin to i n c l u d e his final statements o n the most i m p o r t a n t themes, is i n t e n d e d merely to demonstrate his extreme o r i g i n a l i t y a n d i m p o r t a n c e a n d to show the d i r e c t i o n o f his t h o u g h t . W e f i n d t h a t his philosophy is completely rooted i n the p r o b l e m o f o u r t i m e . Step b y step, i n a m e a n i n g f u l progression, philosophy has led us to the discovery o f the r e a l i t y t h a t is h u m a n life. T h e destiny o f the age was to arrive at this p o i n t . As early as 1923 O r t e g a called the task o f r e d u c i n g p u r e reason to v i t a l reason the theme of our time. H e d i d n o t f a i l to respond to the inexorable summons o f this theme. H i s last works show the m a t u r i t y o f his t h o u g h t , the f i n a l positions he reached. Man and People signifies the
4-6z
Ortega and His Philosophy of Vital Reason
authentic f o u n d a t i o n o f sociology, understood as a theory o f social life a n d therefore rooted i n the theory o f i n d i v i d u a l h u m a n life, t h a t is, i n metaphysics. Ortega's 1929 course, ¿Qué es filosofía? ( W h a t Is Philosophy ?), is his first exposition o f the essential features o f his philosophic system. H i s book La idea de principio de Leibniz y la evolución de la teoría deductiva ( L e i b n i z ' Concept of P r i n c i p l e a n d the E v o l u t i o n o f the Deductive T h e o r y ) exhibits a capacity p r a c t i c a l l y u n k n o w n u p to n o w for p e n e t r a t i n g to the very r o o t o f the m e a n i n g o f Western t h o u g h t as i t is revealed i n its history : the Greeks—especially P l a t o , Aristotle, E u c l i d , the Skeptics a n d the Stoics; the Scholastics; the moderns—philosophers, mathematicians a n d physicists; a n d the contemporary " existentialists. " Ortega's c r i t i q u e shows " the level o f o u r r a d i c a l i s m " a n d the deeper m e a n i n g o f the philosophy o f v i t a l reason. A detailed exposition of these w o r k s — p r o b a b l y Ortega's most i m p o r t a n t — w i l l have to take i n t o account other w r i t i n g s t h a t are still u n p u b l i s h e d ; together, they comprise the last phase o f his t h o u g h t . (For more details o n this, see m y book Ortega, o f w h i c h the first v o l u m e has been published.)
6.
T H E SCHOOL OF
MADRID
Ortega's strictly philosophical influence has been so p r o f o u n d t h a t there is no f o r m o f t h o u g h t i n the Spanish-speaking w o r l d at the present t h a t does n o t owe some essential p a r t to h i m ; b u t this influence was exerted m o r e d i r e c t l y a n d positively u p o n his personal pupils, especially those w h o developed their t h o u g h t i n close p r o x i m i t y to h i m at the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d or those w h o were n o t i n his i m m e d i a t e surroundings b u t w h o received certain principles a n d methods o f t h o u g h t f r o m h i m . A t the b e g i n n i n g o f this chapter I m e n t i o n e d the names o f some o f the thinkers w h o comprise the so-called School o f M a d r i d ; we shall n o w examine briefly the w o r k o f four o f t h e m w h o have made c o n t r i b u t i o n s o f p a r t i c u l a r i m p o r t a n c e to the philosophy o f o u r t i m e . L i k e other members o f the g r o u p , t h e i r personalities have developed i n q u i t e different a n d independent forms, a n d this, too, corresponds to the d e m a n d for c i r c u m s t a n t i a l i t y a n d a u t h e n t i c i t y t h a t characterizes every nuance o f Ortega's t h o u g h t . M O R E N T E . M a n u e l Garcia M o r e n t e (1886-1942) was b o r n at A r j o n i l l a , near J a é n . H e studied at G r a n a d a a n d later at Bayonne a n d Paris, where he was a p u p i l o f Étienne Émile M a r i e B o u t r o u x a n d was influenced by Frédéric R a u h a n d especially Bergson, w h o was t h e n b e g i n n i n g to d o m i n a t e French t h o u g h t . A f t e r receiving his degree i n philosophy at Paris, M o r e n t e completed his studies i n G e r m a n y
The
School
of
Madrid
463
(Berlin, M u n i c h a n d M a r b u r g ) u n d e r Cohen, N a t o r p a n d Cassirer, the three most i m p o r t a n t n e o - K a n t i a n philosophers. F r o m 1912 o n he held the chair i n ethics a t the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d , where f r o m 1931 to 1936 he was dean o f the F a c u l t y o f Philosophy a n d Letters. O r d a i n e d as a priest i n 1940, he r e t u r n e d to his professorship and died i n M a d r i d t w o years later. M o r e n t e was a n extremely c u l t u r e d m a n a n d a n a d m i r a b l e teacher a n d translator. I n t h e course o f his life his t h o u g h t followed several paths. H e was attracted to the K a n t i a n i s m o f his G e r m a n teachers, a n d w r o t e a n a d m i r a b l e exposition o f i t i n his book La filosofía de Kant, w h i c h used the G e r m a n philosopher as a p o i n t of departure i n the past for a speculation concerning the present. L a t e r he became interested i n Bergson, w h o m he made the subject o f a short book, La filosofía de Henri Bergson. A p u p i l a n d friend o f O r t e g a , he attained t h e most m a t u r e phase o f his t h o u g h t i n his personal exposition o f Ortega's philosophy, w i t h extremely interesting contributions o f his o w n , such as the studies o n progress a n d p r i v a t e life i n c l u d e d i n his book Ensayos (Essays). H i s most i m p o r t a n t w o r k , w h i c h combines his v i e w o f the history o f philosophy w i t h his personal o r i e n t a t i o n , is the published version o f a course he gave at the U n i v e r s i t y o f T u c u m á n , A r g e n t i n a , Lecciones preliminares de Filosofía. * A f t e r the C i v i l W a r a n d the s p i r i t u a l crisis t h a t led to his o r d i n a t i o n as a priest, M o r e n t e published several works w h i c h are collected i n the v o l u m e Idea de la Hispanidad, as w e l l as some studies o f St. Thomas w h i c h , w h i l e n o t fully m a t u r e , give a n i n d i c a t i o n o f w h a t the final phase o f his t h o u g h t m i g h t have been. B u t this phase was i n t e r r u p t e d suddenly b y his death. Z U B I R I . X a v i e r Z u b i r i was b o r n i n San Sebastián i n 1898. H e studied philosophy a n d theology at M a d r i d , L o u v a i n a n d R o m e , t a k i n g his degree i n philosophy at M a d r i d w i t h a thesis e n t i t l e d Ensayo de una teoría fenomenológica del juicio (Essay o f a Phenomenological T h e o r y o f J u d g m e n t ) a n d his degree i n theology at R o m e . H e also pursued scientific a n d philosophic studies i n Germany. I n 1926 he became professor o f the history o f philosophy at the U n i v e r s i t y o f M a d r i d . H e was a w a y f r o m Spain f r o m early 1936 u n t i l the b e g i n n i n g o f t h e Second W o r l d W a r ; he was a professor at the U n i v e r s i t y o f Barcelona f r o m 1940 to 1942. Since t h e n he has lived i n M a d r i d , n o t engaged i n official i n s t r u c t i o n , b u t g i v i n g a series o f very i n f l u e n t i a l p r i v a t e courses or short series o f lectures since 1945. Z u b i r i ' s specifically philosophical development shows the influence * A new, considerably abridged and revised edition of this work was published posthumously in Spain under the title Fundamentos de Filosofía; the second portion of this work was written by Juan Z a r a g ü e t a .
4.64
Ortega and His Philosophy of Vital Reason
o f his three p r i n c i p a l teachers : J u a n Z a r a g ü e t a , O r t e g a a n d H e i degger. H i s theological studies a n d Zaragiieta's leanings gave Z u b i r i a p r o f o u n d f a m i l i a r i t y w i t h Scholasticism, the m a r k o f w h i c h is clearly visible i n his t h o u g h t . O r t e g a was a decisive factor i n his m a t u r e development a n d o r i e n t a t i o n ; Z u b i r i has w r i t t e n : " W e were m o r e t h a n pupils, we were his h a n d i w o r k , i n the sense t h a t he m a d e us t h i n k , o r a t least made us t h i n k o f things t h a t we h a d n o t t h o u g h t o f before a n d i n a f o r m we were n o t used t o . . . . A n d we were his h a n d i w o r k , we w h o were p r e p a r i n g to be w h i l e he was i n the process o f f o r m a t i o n . W e received f r o m h i m t h e n something that no one w i l l be able to receive again : the i n t e l l e c t u a l i r r a d i a t i o n f r o m a t h i n k e r i n the process o f development. " Lastly, Z u b i r i studied w i t h Heidegger a t F r e i b u r g f r o m 1929 to 1931, shortly after the p u b l i c a t i o n oí Sein und Zfitiy °\. the i m p r i n t o f this i n s t r u c t i o n has s i m i l a r l y enriched his t h o u g h t . T o this should be added Z u b i r i ' s very b r o a d a n d p r o f o u n d scientific k n o w l edge, r a n g i n g f r o m mathematics to neurology, to w h i c h h e has given e x t r a o r d i n a r y a t t e n t i o n a l l his life, a n d his studies o f classical a n d O r i e n t a l languages, p r i m a r i l y as aids i n the study o f t h e history o f religions. aTi
Z u b i r i ' s w r i t t e n œuvre has been slow i n c o m i n g a n d discontinuous, a n d its v o l u m e is still small. H i s philosophic essays—with t h e exception o f " S o b r e el p r o b l e m a de l a filosofía" a n d " O r t e g a , maestro de filosofía"—were collected i n 1944 i n the v o l u m e Naturaleza, Historia, Dios ( N a t u r e , H i s t o r y , G o d ) . H e published n o t h i n g else u n t i l 1962, w h e n his l o n g study Sobre la esencia ( O n Essence) appeared. I n 1963 he p u b l i s h e d a n edited version o f a short lecture course, Cinco lecciones de filosofía. Z u b i r i ' s historical studies comprise a large p a r t o f his w o r k a n d have e x t r a o r d i n a r y perspicacity a n d d e p t h . T h e y are composed i n a h i g h l y personal m a n n e r , as an a t t e m p t to seek the roots o f his o w n p h i l o s o p h y ; they thus have a r e l a t i o n to the present s i t u a t i o n o f t h o u g h t w h i c h gives t h e m a strictly philosophical character. T h i s is a w e l l - k n o w n q u a l i t y o f the first essays i n Naturaleza, Historia, Dios—"Nuestra situación i n t e l e c t u a l , " " ¿ Q u é es saber ?" a n d " Ciencia y r e a l i d a d " — w h i c h are a n i n t r o d u c t i o n to the consideration o f the past—as w e l l as the essays " E l acontecer h u m a n o : Grecia y la pervivencia del pasado filosófico" ( H u m a n Events: Greece a n d the S u r v i v a l o f Philosophy's Past), " L a idea de filosofía en Aristóteles," " S ó c r a t e s y la sabiduría g r i e g a " (Socrates a n d Greek W i s d o m ) , a n d " H e g e l y el p r o b l e m a metafísico. " A perspective d e r i v e d m u c h more f r o m theology, t h o u g h accompanied b y the u n m i s t a k a b l e presence o f c u r r e n t p h i l o s o p h y , is evident i n the essay " E l ser s o b r e n a t u r a l : Dios y la deificación en la
The
School
of
Madrid
4.65
teología p a u l i n a " ( S u p e r n a t u r a l B e i n g : G o d a n d D e i f i c a t i o n i n Pauline T h e o l o g y ) , perhaps the most i l l u m i n a t i n g a n d p r o f o u n d o f Z u b i r i ' s w r i t i n g s . His last book studies the idea o f p h i l o s o p h y t h r o u g h the works o f a discontinuous series o f thinkers: A r i s t o t l e , K a n t , C o m t e , Bergson, Husserl, D i l t h e y a n d Heidegger. H e has studied the p h i l o sophical significance o f c o n t e m p o r a r y physics i n the essay " L a idea de l a naturaleza: la nueva f í s i c a " ( T h e Idea o f N a t u r e : T h e N e w Physics). T h e most commented o n a n d i n f l u e n t i a l o f Z u b i r i ' s essays is " E n t o r n o a l p r o b l e m a de Dios " ( C o n c e r n i n g the P r o b l e m o f G o d ; 1935), w h i c h seeks the h u m a n d i m e n s i o n f r o m the standpoint o f w h i c h this p r o b l e m must be posed. M a n is implanted i n existence o r i m p l a n t e d i n b e i n g ; he is supported a tergo b y something t h a t makes us be. T h i s leads t o the idea o f b i n d i n g (religación): we are obliged to exist because we are previously bound to t h a t w h i c h makes us exist. Existence is n o t merely thrown; i t is also bound to its r o o t . M a n ' s openness to the things shows t h a t there are things; his being b o u n d reveals t h a t there is something b i n d i n g h i m a n d t h a t i t is the f u n d a m e n t a l root o f existence. Z u b i r i calls this deidad ( d e i t y ) ; the b i n d i n g w h i c h he speaks o f poses the i n t e l l e c t u a l p r o b l e m o f G o d as f u n d a m e n t a l or f o u n d i n g b e i n g . F r o m this arise the problems o f r e l i g i o n or irreligión, even i n c l u d i n g atheism, w h i c h appear posed i n this dimension o f b i n d i n g . T h e ideas i n the book Sobre la esencia were developed over a long p e r i o d o f t i m e i n university courses i n w h i c h Z u b i r i treated various problems o f metaphysics. I t is a n extremely t i g h t l y w r i t t e n and technical book t h a t investigates i n great detail a n d d e p t h a central question o f philosophy. Z u b i r i ' s purpose is to r e t u r n to " r e a l i t y i n itself a n d to ask w h a t is its s t r u c t u r a l element t h a t we c a l l essence." H e uses the concept o f structure i n a thematic way, basing his argum e n t o n the philosophy o f A r i s t o t l e . Moreover, he criticizes Aristotle's t h e o r y o f substance, a n d this c r i t i q u e leads to the concept o f substantivity, i n the discussion o f w h i c h Z u b i r i has frequent recourse to Scholastic t h o u g h t patterns a n d makes constant use o f the intellectual a p p r o a c h o f science, physics a n d even more, biology. A considerable p a r t o f the interest o f this w o r k is related to the possibilities i t offers of u n d e r s t a n d i n g biological r e a l i t y a n d especially the r e a l i t y o f species. A c c o r d i n g to Z u b i r i , essence is a n element o f a real t h i n g , a n d this element is a p r i m a r y u n i t o f its t r a i t s ; o n the other h a n d , this u n i t is not e x t e r n a l , b u t intrinsic to the t h i n g itself, a n d a p r i n c i p l e o n w h i c h all the other traits of the t h i n g are based, whether or n o t they are necessary ; essence thus understood, he concludes, is the truth o f a t h i n g that is w i t h i n i t , the t r u t h o f r e a l i t y . I n l o n g analyses he establishes the
466
Ortega and His Philosophy of Vital Reason
d o m a i n o f the " essentiable, " " essentiated " r e a l i t y a n d the very essence o f the real. T h i s complex a n d difficult book culminates i n the exposition o f the idea o f transcendental order, i n w h i c h Z u b i r i c r i t i cizes other conceptions of transcendentality and expounds his o w n . T h r o u g h o u t the book he uses concepts t h a t he h a d developed i n his courses, such as t h a t o f "sentient intelligence, " w h i c h makes m a n a n " a n i m a l o f realities, " defined b y this peculiar " h a b i t . " Despite the technicality o f his style, his constant use o f neologisms and his frequent references to the sciences, Z u b i r i ' s courses a n d w r i t i n g s are f u l l o f an unmistakable intellectual passion a n d a d r a m a t i c q u a l i t y d e r i v e d f r o m the efforts o f a n exceptionally p r o f o u n d p h i losophy to clear a p a t h for itself a m o n g its i n t u i t i o n s a n d u n f o l d t h e m dialectically i n order to a t t a i n formulas of its o w n . T h e v o l u m e Sobre la esencia is the first o f an announced series o f " Philosophic S t u d i e s " ; i n these studies Z u b i r i ' s enormous knowledge a n d p r o f o u n d t h o u g h t w i l l surely be w e l l expressed. G A O S . José Gaos was b o r n at G i j o n i n 1900. H e was a professor at the universities o f Zaragoza a n d M a d r i d , a n d rector o f the latter university f r o m 1936 to 1939; since t h a t t i m e he has l i v e d a n d t a u g h t i n M e x i c o . H i s teachers were O r t e g a , M o r e n t e a n d Z u b i r i , w i t h w h o m he w o r k e d closely i n the M a d r i d F a c u l t y o f Philosophy a n d Letters i n the years i m m e d i a t e l y preceding the C i v i l W a r . H e has devoted a great deal of effort to the t r a n s l a t i o n o f philosophic works, especially those o f Husserl a n d Heidegger. H e has w r i t t e n numerous studies o n Spanish and L a t i n A m e r i c a n t h o u g h t , o n p r o b l e m s i n the teaching of philosophy, a n d o n philosophy i n the strict sense. H i s most i m p o r t a n t books are Pensamiento de lengua española (Spanish-language Philosophy), Filosofía de la filosofía e historia de la filosofía, Dos exclusivas del hombre : la manoy el tiempo ( T w o T h i n g s Peculiar to M a n : T h e H a n d and T i m e ) , Confesiones profesionales, Sobre Ortega y Gasset, Filosofía contemporánea, Discurso defilosofía, Orígenes de lafilosofíay de su historia a n d De lafilosofía. Gaos has always been a n a d m i r a b l e teacher ; his gift, like M o r e n t e ' s , of i n s t r u c t i n g a n d c o m m u n i c a t i n g his t h o u g h t , his c l a r i t y o f o r a l expression, his intellectual curiosity, his precision, his w i d e knowledge and his sense o f h u m o r are qualities w h i c h have made h i m , i n Spain as i n M e x i c o , a m a n w h o has done m u c h to awaken a n d i n s p i r e p h i l o sophical vocations, and his influence has been very great. H i s gifts as a w r i t e r , perhaps because o f the great b u l k o f the translations he has completed, are below the level of his b r i l l i a n t a n d attractive o r a l style ; therefore, these qualities are especially to be f o u n d i n those books w h i c h are f a i t h f u l versions o f his lectures, such as Dos exclusivas del
The School of Madrid
467
hombre, i n w h i c h one can discover completely u n t r a m m e l e d the o r i g i n a l i t y , freshness a n d i n s p i r a t i o n o f Gaos's t h o u g h t . C o m b i n e d w i t h his vast a n d precise c o m m a n d o f the t o t a l i t y o f the philosophic t h o u g h t o f the past, Gaos has received a threefold i n f l u ence that lends h i m special forcefulness : t h a t o f O r t e g a , w h o shaped the very r o o t o f Gaos's t h o u g h t , as he d i d t h a t o f a l l the thinkers w h o experienced his direct influence; that o f Husserl, whose works he studied w i t h exceptional perceptiveness a n d i n s i g h t ; a n d t h a t o f Heidegger, perhaps the most apparent influence i n the last few years. Gaos, w h o at times declares t h a t he is n o t h i n g m o r e t h a n a professor o f p h i l o s o p h y — o n l y w h e n one is t r u l y a " p r o f e s s o r " is i t possible to develop oneself p h i l o s o p h i c a l l y — a n d w h o makes n o a t t e m p t to conceal a certain l e a n i n g t o w a r d skepticism, represents a n irreplaceable element i n the nascent Spanish philosophy o f the present day. F E R R A T E R . José (Josep) Ferrater M o r a belongs to the School o f M a d r i d o n l y i n d i r e c t l y . H e was b o r n i n Barcelona i n 1912, a n d was a personal p u p i l o f the master professors o f t h a t city's university, especially J o a q u i n X i r a u . H e emigrated i n 1939 a n d has l i v e d i n Cuba, Chile a n d finally i n the U n i t e d States, w h e r e he is a professor at B r y n M a w r . B u t his philosophic relations to the School o f M a d r i d are very close : X i r a u was a p u p i l o f Ortega ; Ferrater, referring to Ortega i n 1935, spoke o f the " f i l i a l attitude o f one w h o has absorbed f r o m h i m , more t h a n ideas, style; more t h a n thoughts, ways of t h o u g h t . " M o r e n t e a n d Z u b i r i have also exerted considerable influence o n Ferrater, a n d one should n o t forget the influence o f U n a m u n o a n d Eugenio (Eugeni) d ' O r s u p o n h i m . Ferrater's w r i t i n g s are very copious. M o s t i m p o r t a n t is his Diccionario de Filosofía, w h i c h he has enlarged a n d perfected i n successive editions u n t i l i t has become a splendid storehouse o f philosophical i n f o r m a t i o n , abreast o f the times, balanced a n d precise ; i t is a personal a n d strictly philosophic presentation o f the r e a l i t y o f past a n d present philosophy. O t h e r books b y Ferrater are Cuatro visiones de la historia universal (Four V i e w s o f U n i v e r s a l H i s t o r y ) , Unamuno: bosquejo de una filosofía (translated as Unamuno : a Philosophy of Tragedy), Ortegay Gasset : etapas de una filosofía ( O r t e g a y Gasset: a n O u t l i n e o f H i s Philosophy), Variaciones sobre el espíritu (Variations o n S p i r i t ) , Cuestiones disputadas, La filosofía en el mundo de hoy (Philosophy T o d a y ) , Lógica matemática ( i n collaboration w i t h H u g u e s L e b l a n c ) , El hombre en la encrucijada ( M a n at the Crossroads), a n d El ser y la muerte (Being a n d D e a t h ) . T h e lastnamed book is the one Ferrater considers most representative o f his t h o u g h t ; i n accordance w i t h a characteristic practice o f this a u t h o r , w h o likes to go b a c k over his o w n w r i t i n g s a n d revise t h e m , i t is a new
466
Ortega and his Philosophy oj Vital Reason
version o f his earlier book El sentido de la muerte ( T h e Sense o f D e a t h ) ; its subtitle i s ' ' Bosquejo de una filosofía integracionista " (Sketch o f a n Integrationist P h i l o s o p h y ) . By " i n t e g r a t i o n i s m " Ferrater understands " a type o f philosophy whose purpose is to construct a bridge over the g u l f t h a t a l l too often yawns between t h a t t h o u g h t w h i c h takes as its axis h u m a n existence or realities described b y analogy to i t a n d t h a t t h o u g h t w h i c h takes N a t u r e as its a x i s . " H e does n o t w a n t a mere " l e v e l i n g " o f the doctrines, nor an eclectic selection o f elements f r o m t h e m , n o r a " c o m p r o m i s e " between t h e i r extreme v i e w p o i n t s ; w h a t he wants is a bridge over w h i c h one can pass i n either d i r e c t i o n , w h i l e the respective u n t e n a b i l i t y o f each p o s i t i o n is preserved. Ferrater, w h o keeps close w a t c h on everything b e i n g done i n philosophy today, i n E u r o p e , i n the Anglo-Saxon w o r l d a n d even i n the Soviet w o r l d , presents this aggregate i n a r e l a t i v e l y flat, unforeshortened perspective t h a t is n o t p r i m a r i l y his o w n personal one. Outside the area of philosophy, a n analogous a t t i t u d e m a y be observed i n his interesting book Tres mundos: Cataluña, España, Europa (Three W o r l d s : Catalonia, Spain, E u r o p e ) , w r i t t e n w i t h the t r a n q u i l l i t y , keenness a n d intelligent i r o n y t h a t characterize a l l o f his i n t e l l e c t u a l w o r k . W e have followed the entire history o f W e s t e r n p h i l o s o p h y c e n t u r y b y century a n d stage b y stage, f r o m Greece to O r t e g a and the p h i l o sophical g r o u p o r i g i n a t e d b y h i m . G o d has a l l o w e d us to close this history, as is j u s t , w i t h Spanish names. As we reach this p o i n t , p h i losophy shows us the u n d e r l y i n g u n i t y o f its m e a n i n g , despite a l l its differences. A t the end we find the entire past present i n ourselves. T h i s is w h a t gives the history o f philosophy its seriousness; i n i t w e feel, in the present, the w e i g h t o f the entire past. B u t this e n d i n g is n o t a conclusion. T h e history o f philosophy comes to a close i n the present, b u t the present, w h i c h is laden w i t h the entire past, bears the f u t u r e w i t h i n itself; the mission o f the present consists o f setting the f u t u r e i n m o t i o n . Perhaps i n the t i m e to come Spain w i l l no longer be outside this movement, for i n O r t e g a Spain has made p h i l o s o p h y its o w n .
Bi
N O T E TO T H E PRESENT E D I T I O N N o title has been added to or deleted from the Apéndice Bibliográfico as printed i n the twenty-second Spanish edition. T h i s bibliography thus remains, according to the author's wishes, a record of the works he found most useful i n writing a n d revising his book. T h e translators have added authors' first names and places of publication wherever possible. T h e y have added references to all E n g l i s h translations of works that came to their attention, at the same time deleting references to Spanish translations wherever it was possible to supply the original title or a n English translation of a work. I.
DICTIONARIES AND GENERAL PHILOSOPHY
HISTORIES
OF
Eisler, Rudolf, Wörterbuch der philosophischen Begriffe und Ausdrücke, Berlin, 1 8 9 9 . Philosophen-Lexikon, Berlin, 1 9 1 2 . B a l d w i n , J a m e s M a r k (ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, new ed. ( 1 9 2 5 , 3 v o l . i n 4 ) reprinted N e w Y o r k , 1 9 4 0 - 4 9 . L a l a n d e , A n d r é , Vocabulaire technique et critique de la philosophie, 4 t h ed. ( 2 vol.), Paris, 1 9 3 2 . Schmidt-Streller, Philosophisches Wörterbuch. R u n e s , Dagobert D a v i d (ed.), TheDictionaryofPhilosophj>,TSiewYork, 1942. F e r r a t e r M o r a , J o s é , Diccionario deFilosqfia, 5 t h ed., Buenos Aires, 1 9 6 5 . Z a r a g ü e t a [Bengoechea],Juan, Vocabulario filosófico, M a d r i d , 1 9 5 5 . E r d m a n n , J o h a n n E d u a r d , Grundriss der Geschichte der Philosophie, 3 r d ed. ( 2 v o l . ) , Berlin, 1 8 7 8 . W i n d e l b a n d , W i l h e l m , Lehrbuch der Geschichte der Philosophie, n t h ed., T ü b i n g e n , 1 9 2 4 ; rev. by H e i n z Heimsoeth, 1 9 3 5 . W u n d t , W . , Oldenberg, H . , et al., Allgemeine Geschichte der Philosophie ( T e i l I , A b t . V of Die Kultur der Gegenwart), Berlin, 1 9 0 9 . 469
Bibliography Baeumler, A . and S c h r ö t e r , M . (edd.), Die Grunddisziplinen ( A b t . I oí Handbuch der Philosophie), M u n i c h , 1 9 3 4 . J a n e t - S é a i l l e s , Histoire de la philosophie, Paris, 1 8 8 7 . Messer, August, Geschichte der Philosophie ( 3 vol.), L e i p z i g , 1 9 1 2 - 1 6 . V o r l ä n d e r , K a r l , Geschichte der Philosophie, 9 t h ed. ( 2 v o l . ) , H a m b u r g , c. 1949-55-
B r é h i e r , É m i l e , Histoire de la philosophie ( 2 vol. in 7 ) , Paris, 1 9 2 6 - 3 2 . E n g . trans, by Joseph T h o m a s , History of Philosophy, Vol. 1 : The Hellenic Age, Chicago, 1 9 6 3 . Russell, Bertrand, A History of Western Philosophy, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 5 9 . Copleston, Frederick, A History
of Philosophy
( 5 vol. p u b l i s h e d ) , L o n d o n ,
I946-59R i v a u d , Albert, Histoire de la philosophie ( 4 vol. ), Paris, 1 9 4 8 - 6 2 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n (ed.), La filosofía en sus textos (anthology), 2 n d ed. ( 3 v o l . ) , Barcelona, i 9 6 0 . II.
ON T H E ESSENCE OF PHILOSOPHY
Bergson, H e n r i , Introduction à la métaphysique. E n g . trans, b y T . E . H u l m e , An Introduction to Metaphysics, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 1 2 . Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Das Wesen der Philosophie, Berlin, 1 9 0 7 . E n g . trans, by Stephen A . E m e r y a n d W i l l i a m T . E m e r y , The Essence of Philosophy, Chapel Hill, 1954. Husserl, E d m u n d , "Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos, 1 9 1 1 . Scheler, M a x , " V o m Wesen der Philosophie," in Vom Ewigen im Menschen, 1921.
Heidegger, M a r t i n , Was ist Metaphysik?, 3 r d printing, Bonn, 1 9 3 1 . O r t e g a y Gasset, J o s é , Prólogo a una Historia de la Filosofía (in V o l . V I of Obras Completas), M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , " S o b r e el problema de l a filosofía," Revista de Occidente, Nos. ii5andn8,
1935.
M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Introducción a la Filosofía, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . E n g . trans, by K e n n e t h S. R e i d a n d E d w a r d Sarmiento, Reason and Life, L o n d o n & New H a v e n , 1 9 5 6 . Biografía de la Filosofía, Buenos Aires, 1 9 5 4 . Idea de la Metafísica, Buenos Aires, 1 9 5 4 . III.
GREEK
PHILOSOPHY
Sources Diels, H e r m a n n (ed. & trans.), Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 6 t h e d . ( 3 vol.), Berlin, 1 9 5 1 - 5 2 . Ritter-Preller,Historiaphilosophiaegraecae ( 1 8 3 8 ) , 1 0 t h ed., H a m b u r g , 1 9 1 4 . A r n i m , H a n s Friedrich August v o n , Stoicorum veterum fragmenta ( 4 vol.), Leipzig, 1 9 0 3 - 2 4 . Nestle, W i l h e l m , (sel., ed. & trans.), Die Vorsokratiker, J e n a , 1 9 0 8 . Die Sokratiker. Die Nachsokratiker.
Bibliography Capelle, W i l h e l m , D i e Vorsokratiker, 1 9 5 3 . F r e e m a n , K a t h l e e n , ThePre-Socratic Philosophers, 2 n d ed., Oxford, 1 9 4 9 . Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers ( E n g . trans, of the fragments in D i e l s ) , Cambridge, Mass., 1 9 4 8 . V o g e l , C . J . de (ed.), Greek Philosophy ( 3 v o l . ) , L e i d e n , 1 9 5 9 - 6 3 . General
Works
Zeller, E d u a r d , Die Philosophie der Griechen ( 3 vol. i n 6 ) , L e i p z i g , 1 8 7 9 - 9 2 . G o m p e r z , Theodor, Griechische Denker ( 3 vol.), L e i p z i g , 1 9 0 3 - 9 . E n g . trans. by L a u r i e Magnus a n d G . G . Berry, Greek Thinkers ( 4 v o l . ) , L o n d o n , 1914-31.
J o ë l , K a r l , Geschichte der antiken Philosophie, T ü b i n g e n , 1 g 2 1 . H ö n i g s w a l d , R i c h a r d , Die Philosophie des Altertums, 1 9 1 7 . Cassirer, E r n s t and Hoffman, E . , Geschichte der antiken Philosophie, 1 9 2 5 . M e y e r , H . , Geschichte der alten Philosophie, 1 9 2 5 . Stenzel, J u l i u s , " M e t a p h y s i k des A l t e r t u m s , " i n A . Baeumler and M . S c h r ö t e r (edd.), Die Grunddisziplinen (Abt. I of Handbuch der Philosophie), Munich, 1934. H o w a l d , E r n s t , Ethik des Altertums, M u n i c h , 1 9 3 4 . J a e g e r , W e r n e r W i l h e l m , Paideia, 3 r d ed. ( 3 vol.), Berlin, 1 9 5 4 - 5 5 . E n g . trans, of 2 n d G e r m a n ed. b y G i l b e r t Highet, Paideia, 2 n d ed. ( 3 vol.), New York, i 9 6 0 . Stace, W a l t e r Terence, A Critical History of Greek Philosophy, L o n d o n , 1 g 2 0 . Burnet, J o h n , Early Greek Philosophy ( 1 8 g 2 ) , 4 t h ed., L o n d o n , 1 9 3 0 . Greek Philosophy, I : Thaïes to Plato, L o n d o n , 1 9 1 4 . R o b i n , L é o n , La pensée grecque, new ed., Paris, 1 9 4 8 . E n g . trans, by M . R . Dobie, Greek Thought and the Origins of the Scientific Spirit, L o n d o n and N e w York, 1928. T a n n e r y , P a u l , Pour l'histoire de la science hellène, Paris, 1 8 8 7 . S c h u h l , Pierre M a x i m e , Essai sur laformation de la pensée grecque, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1949-
W e r n e r , C , La philosophie grecque, Paris, 1 9 3 8 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Biografía de laFilosofia, Buenos Aires, 1 9 5 4 .
Monographs T H E PRE-SOCRATICS G i g o n , O l o f Alfred, Der Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie, Basel, 1 9 4 5 . Diels, H e r m a n n (ed. & trans.), Herakleitos von Ephesos, 2 n d ed., Berlin, 1 9 0 9 . Weerts,~Emü,HeraklitundHerakliteer, Berlin, 1 9 2 6 . R e i n h a r d t , K a r l , Parmenides und die Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie, 1 9 1 6 . R i e z l e r , K u r t , Parmenides, Frankfurt a m M a i n , 1 9 3 4 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , Naiuraleza, Historia, Dios, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 , pp. 2 1 6 - 2 5 5 . Bignone, Ettore, Empedocle, 1 9 1 6 . Jaeger, W e r n e r W i l h e l m : E n g . trans, by E d w a r d S. Robinson, The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers, Oxford, 1 9 4 7 . Wheelwright, Philip E l l i s , Heraclitus, Princeton, 1 9 5 9 .
Bibliography T H E SOPHISTS A N D SOCRATES G o m p e r z , H e i n r i c h , Sophistik und Rhetorik, L e i p z i g , 1912. M e u n i e r , M a r i o , La légende de Socrate, 1926. K u h n , H e l m u t , Sokrates, Berlin, 1 9 3 4 ; reprinted M u n i c h , 1 9 5 9 . D a w s o n , M i l e s Menander, Ethics of Socrates, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 2 4 . C a r r i l l , H . F . , Socrates, or The Emancipation of Mankind, 1 9 2 7 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , " S ó c r a t e s y l a s a b i d u r í a griega, " in Naturaleza,
Historia,
Dios,
Madrid, 1944. T o v a r , Antonio, Vida de Sócrates, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . G i g o n , O l o f Alfred, Sokrates, Bern, 1947. PLATO Grote, George, Plato ( 4 vol.), L o n d o n , 1 8 8 8 . R i t t e r , Constantin, Platon, 1 9 1 0 - 2 3 . Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U l r i c h v o n , Platon ( 2 vol.), Berlin, 1 9 1 9 ; Platon, sein Leben und seine Werke, ed. after author's 3 r d ed. b y B r u n o Snell, Berlin, 1 9 4 8 . Pater, W a l t e r , Plato andPlatonism,
London, 1912.
Natorp, P a u l G e r h a r d , Piatos Ideenlehre, L e i p z i g , 1903. L a n d s b e r g , P a u l L u d w i g ; Span, trans., La Academia platónica, M a d r i d , 1 9 2 6 . R o b i n , L é o n , Platon, Paris, 1 9 3 8 . M o r e a u , J o s e p h , La construction de l'idéalisme platonicien, Paris, 1 9 3 8 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " I n t r o d u c c i ó n a P l a t ó n , " i n Fedro (Span. e d . of Plato's Phaedrus), Buenos Aires, 1 9 4 8 . ARISTOTLE Brentano, F r a n z Clemens, Aristoteles und seine Weltanschauung, 1 9 1 1 . T a y l o r , Alfred E d w a r d , Aristotle, reprinted N e w Y o r k , 1955. H a m e l i n , O c t a v e , Le système d'Aristote, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 3 1 . Siebeck, H e r m a n n , Aristoteles, Stuttgart, 1 8 9 9 . Ross, Sir W i l l i a m D a v i d , Aristotle, 5 t h ed., L o n d o n , 1 9 5 6 . Jaeger, W e r n e r W i l h e l m , Aristoteles, 2 n d ed., Berlin, 1 9 5 5 . E n g . trans, by R i c h a r d Robinson, Aristotle, O x f o r d , 1 9 3 4 . B r ö c k e r , W a l t e r , Aristoteles, 2 n d ed., Frankfurt a m M a i n , 1 9 5 7 . R o b i n , L é o n , Aristote, Paris, 1 9 4 4 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Introduction to S p a n . ed. of Aristotle's Politics, M a d r i d , 1950. I n t r o d u c t i o n to S p a n . ed. of Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics, Madrid, 1960. A l l a n , D o n a l d J a m e s , The Philosophy of Aristotle, L o n d o n and N e w Y o r k , 1 9 5 7 . M o r e a u , J o s e p h , Aristote et son école, Paris, 1 9 6 2 . T H E I D E A L OF T H E WISE M A N G u y a u , TSÍa.rie]ea.n,Lamoraled'Épicure, Bignone, E t t o r e , Epicuro, 1 9 2 0 .
1878.
Barth, P a u l , DieStoa, 6 t h ed., Stuttgart, 1 9 4 6 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " I n t r o d u c c i ó n a l a filosofía
estoica," i n Sobre la
(Span. ed. of Seneca's De vitabeatd), M a d r i d , 1 9 4 3 . " M a r c o Aurelio o l a e x a g e r a c i ó n , " in San Anselmo y el Madrid, 1944.
felicidad insensato,
Bibliography
473
NEOPLATONISM
Simon, J u l e s , Histoire de l'êcoled'Alexandrie ( 2 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 8 4 5 . Vacherot, É t i e n n e , Histoire critique de l'école d'Alexandrie ( 3 vol.), Paris, 1846-51.
Whittaker, T h o m a s , TheNeo-Platonists, 2 n d ed., C a m b r i d g e ( E n g . ) , 1 9 1 8 . Inge, W i l l i a m R a l p h , The Philosophy of Plotinus, 3 r d ed., L o n d o n a n d N e w York, 1929. H e i n e m a n n , F . , Plotin, 1 9 2 1 . B r é h i e r , É m i l e , La philosophie de Plotin, Paris, 1 9 2 8 . E n g . trans, by J o s e p h T h o m a s , The Philosophy of Plotinus, C h i c a g o , 1 9 5 8 . Mehlis, Georg, Plotin, Stuttgart, 1 9 2 4 . IV.
CHRISTIANITY Sources
Migne, J a c q u e s P a u l (ed.), Patrologiae cursus completus. Séries Latina (P. L.) (221 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 8 4 4 - 6 4 ; Supplementum i n progress since 1 9 5 8 , P a r i s ; Indexes, R o t t e r d a m , 1 9 5 2 . Series Graeca (P. G.) (161 vol.) , Paris, 1 8 5 7 - 8 0 ; Indexes ( 2 vol. i n 3 ) , Paris, 1 9 2 8 - 3 6 . R o u ë t de J o u r n e l , M a r i e Joseph (comp.), Enchiridion Patristicum, 1 4 t h ed., Barcelona, 1 9 4 6 . General
Works
L a b r i o l l e , Pierre C h a m p a g n e de, Histoire de la littérature latine chrétienne, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 2 4 . E n g . trans, by H e r b e r t W i l s o n , History and Literature of Christianity from TertulliantoBoethius,NewYoT]t, 1925. La réaction païenne, Paris, 1 9 3 4 . Batiffol, Pierre, Anciennes littératures chrétiennes. La littérature grecque, Paris, 1 8 9 7 . Bardenhewer, O t t o , Geschichte der altkirchlichen Litteratur, V o l . I , F r e i b u r g i m Breisgau, 1 9 5 2 . H a r n a c k , A d o l f v o n , Geschichte der altchristlichen
Litteratur
( 2 vol.), L e i p z i g ,
1893-1904.
Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte ( 3 v o l . ) , F r e i b u r g i m Breisgau, 1 8 8 8 - 9 0 . E n g . trans, of 3 r d G e r . ed. by N e i l B u c h a n a n , History of Dogma, reprinted ( 7 vol. i n 4 ) , N e w Y o r k , 1 9 6 1 . Tixeront,Joseph, Histoire des dogmes ( 3 vol.), Paris, 1 9 0 5 - 1 2 . Puech, A i m é , Les apologistes grecs dur" siècle de notre ère, 1 9 1 2 . C o r b i è r e , Le christianisme et lafin de la philosophie antique, 1 9 2 1 . F a y e , E u g è n e de, Introduction à l'histoire dugnosticisme, Paris, 1 9 0 3 . Gnostiquesetgnosticisme,Fa.ris, 1913. N e w m a n , H . , Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine, 1845. MacGeffert, A.C., A History of Christian Thought, 1 9 3 2 - 3 3 . M a r i n Sola, J . , La evolución homogénea del dogma católico, 1 9 2 3 . A m o r R u i b a l , A . , Los problemas fundamentales de lafilosofíay del dogma ( 1 o v o l . ) . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , " E l ser sobrenatural: Dios y l a d e i f i c a c i ó n en l a t e o l o g í a p a u l i n a , " i n Naturaleza,
Historia, Dios, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 . Monographs
Prat, Origène, Paris, 1 9 0 7 .
Bibliography
474
F a y e , E u g è n e de, Origine, sa vie, sonœuvre, sapensée ( 3 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 9 2 3 - 2 9 . Esquisse de la pensée d'Origine, 1 9 2 5 . E n g . trans, by F r e d R o t h w e l l , OrigenandHis Work, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 2 9 . C a d i o u , Introduction au système d'Origène, 1 9 3 2 . K a r r e r , Otto, Augustinus. Das religiöse Leben, 1 9 2 3 . P o r t a l i é , E u g è n e , " Saint Augustin, " in Dictionnaire de Théologie Catholique ( 1 5 vol. in 2 7 ) , Paris, 1 9 0 9 - 5 0 , col. 2 2 6 8 - 2 4 7 4 . E n g . trans, of article by R a l p h J . B a s t í a n , A Guide to the Thought of Saint Augustine, C h i c a g o , i 9 6 0 . Gilson, É t i e n n e H e n r i , Introduction à l'étude de Saint Augustin, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 4 3 . E n g . trans, by L . E . M . L y n c h , The Christian Philosophy of Saint Augustine, New Y o r k , 1 9 6 0 . Troeltsch, E r n s t D . , Augustin,
die christliche Antike und das Mittelalter,
Munich,
I9I5-
E i b l , H a n s , Augustin unddiePatristik, Munich, 1923. Schmaus, Die psychologische Trinitätslehre des hl. Augustinus, 1 9 2 7 . M a u s b a c h , J . Die Ethik des hl. Augustinus (2 vol.), 1 9 0 g . P r z y w a r a , E r i c h (ed.), Die Gestalt als Gefüge, L e i p z i g , i g 3 4 . E n g . trans., An Augustine Synthesis, arranged by Erich Przywara, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 4 5 . Gui tton, J e a n , Le temps et l'éternité chez Plolin et Saint Augustin, Paris, 1 9 3 3 . Wolfson, H a r r y A u s t r y n , The Philosophy oftheChurchFathers, Vol.I, C a m b r i d g e , Mass., 1 9 5 6 . Philo : Foundations of Religious Philosophy in Judaism, Christianity, and Islam ( 2 vol.), C a m b r i d g e , Mass., 1 9 4 7 .
V.
MEDIEVAL General
PHILOSOPHY Works
H u i z i n g a , J o h a n ; E n g . trans., The Waning of the Middle Ages ( 1 9 2 4 ) , reprinted New Y o r k , i g 5 4 . T a y l o r , H e n r y Osborn, The Mediaeval Mind, 4 t h ed. ( 2 vol., i g 3 8 ) , reprinted Cambridge, Mass. G r a b m a n n , M a r t i n , Die Geschichte der scholastischen Methode ( 2 vol., 1 9 0 9 - 1 1 ) , reprinted G r a z , 1 9 5 7 . Mittelalterliches Geistesleben ( 3 vol.), M u n i c h , 1 9 2 6 - 5 6 . Filosofía medieval (Span, trans., 1 9 2 8 ) . Historiade la teología católica (Span, trans., 1 9 2 8 ) . Wulf, M a u r i c e de, Histoire de la philosophie médiévale, 6 t h ed. ( 2 v o l . ) , L o u v a i n , 1 9 3 4 - 3 6 . E n g . trans, of 6 t h F r e n c h ed. by E r n e s t C . Messenger, History of Mediaeval Philosophy, 3 r d e d . ( 2 vol.), L o n d o n , 1 9 3 5 - 3 8 . Gilson, É t i e n n e H e n r i , Laphilosophie aumoyenâge, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 5 2 . L'esprit de la philosophie médiévale, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 4 4 . E n g . trans, by A . C . H . Downes, The Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 3 6 . HistoryqfChristianPhilosophyintheMiddleAgeSjNewYork, 1955. Dempf, Alois, " Die E t h i k des Mittelalters, " in A . Baeumler and M . S c h r ö t e r (edd.), Mensch und Charakter (Abt. I I I of Handbuch der Philosophie), Munich, 1931.
Bibliography
475
Dempf, Alois,' ' Metaphysik des Mittelalters, " in A . Baeumler a n d M . S c h r ö t e r (edd.), Die Grunddisziplinen
(Abt. I of Handbuch der Philosophie),
Munich,
1934"
M ü n k , Salomon, Mélanges de philosophiejuive et arabe, Paris, 1 8 5 9 . C a r r a de V a u x , Bernard, La doctrine d'Islam ( 2 vol.), Paris, 1 9 0 9 . H o r t e n , M a x Joseph Heinrich, Die Philosophie des Islam in ihren Beziehungen zu den philosophischen Weltanschauungen des westlichen Orients, M u n i c h , 1 9 2 4 . N e u m a r k , D a v i d , Geschichte der jüdischen Philosophie des Mittelalters ( 2 vol. in 3 ) , Berlin, 1 9 0 7 - 2 8 . AnhangzumerstenBand, Berlin, 1 9 1 3 . C r u z H e r n á n d e z , Miguel, Filosofía hispano-musulmana. Monographs P r a , M a r i o dal, Scoto Eriugena ei il neoplatonismo médiévale, 1 9 4 1 . Dornet de Vorges, E d m o n d Charles E u g è n e , Saint Anselme, Paris, 1 go 1 . K o y r é , Alexandre, L'idée de Dieu dans la philosophie de Saint Anselme, Paris, 1 9 2 3 . Barth, K a r l , Anselms Beweis der Existenz Gottes, 1 9 3 1 . M.arias,Julian,SanAnselmoyelinsensato, Madrid, ig44O t t a v i a n o , Carmelo, " R i c c a r d o di S. V i t t o r e , " Reale Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei. Atti. Classe discienzemorali, storicheefilologiche, Ser. 6 , V o l . 4 , Fase. 5 , 1 9 3 3 » PP-
4II-54I-
C a r r a de V a u x , Bernard, Avicenne, Paris, 1 9 0 0 . C r u z H e r n á n d e z , Miguel, La metafísica de Avicena, M a d r i d , 1 g 4 g . R e n a n , Ernest, Averroèset l'Averroisme ( 1 8 5 2 ) , Paris, c. 1 9 1 2 . S a l i b ä , J a m ï l (Saliba, D j é m i l ) (ed. & trans.), Étude sur la métaphysique d'Avicenne, Paris, 1 9 2 6 . H o r t e n , M a x Joseph H e i n r i c h , Die Metaphysik des Averroes, H a l l e an der Saale, 1912.
A s í n Palacios, Miguel, El Islam cristianizado, M a d r i d , 1 9 3 1 . Huellas del Islam, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 . O r t e g a y Gasset, J o s é , " A b e n j a l d ú n nos revela el secreto," i n El Espectador, V I I I , Madrid, 1937. I b n K h a l d û n , The Muqaddimah. An Introduction to History, trans, and intr. by F r a n z Rosenthal ( 3 vol.), N e w Y o r k , 1 9 5 8 . Gaos, J o s é , Lafilosofía de Maimónides, 2 n d ed., Mexico, 1 9 4 0 . G i l s o n , É t i e n n e H e n r i , La philosophie de Saint Bonaventure, Paris, 1 9 2 4 . E n g . trans, by D o m I l l t y d T r e t h o w a n and F . J . Sheed, The Philosophy of Saint Bonaventure^onàon, 1938. Baumgartner, Matthias, Santo Tomas ( S p a n , trans., M a d r i d , 1 g 2 5 ) . G r a b m a n n , M a r t i n , Thomas von Aquin. E n g . trans, by V i r g i l M i c h e l , Thomas Aquinas; His Personality and Thought, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 2 8 . Sertillanges, Antonin Gilbert, Saint Thomasd'Aquin ( 2 vol.), Paris, 1 9 1 0 . M a r i t a i n , Jacques, Le docteur angélique, Paris, 1 9 3 0 . E n g . trans, by J . F . S c a n l a n , The Angelic Doctor, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 3 1 . Gilson, É t i e n n e H e n r i , Le thomisme, 5 t h ed., Paris, 1 9 4 4 . E n g . trans, of 3 r d F r e n c h ed. by E d w a r d Bullough, The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, 2 n d ed., St. Louis, i g 3 9 . Another E n g . trans, by L . K . Shook, The ChristianPhilosophyofSt. ThomasAquinas,New York, 1 9 5 6 . M e y e r , H . , Thomas von Aquin, 1 9 3 8 .
Bibliography M a n s e r , G a l l u s M..,Laesencia del tomismo (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 ) . A g u i r r e , A . , Rogerio Bacon, Barcelona, 1 9 3 5 . C a r r e r a s y A r t a u , T o m á s and J o a q u í n , Historia de lafilosofía española: Filosofía cristiana de los siglos XIIIal XV, M a d r i d , 1 9 3 9 . L a n d r y , Bernard, DunsScot, 1 9 2 2 . G i l s o n , É t i e n n e H e n r i , Jean Duns Scot, Paris, 1 9 5 2 . L o n g p r é , Laphilosophie du b. Duns Scot, 1 9 2 4 . Heidegger, M a r t i n , Die Kategorien- und Bedeutungslehre des Duns Scotus, Tübingen, 1916. H a r r i s , C h a r l e s R e g i n a l d Schiller, Duns Scotus ( 2 vol.), Oxford, 1 9 2 7 . A b b a g n a n o , Nicola, Guglielmo di Ockam, 1 9 3 1 . M o o d y , E r n e s t Addison, The Logic ofWilliam of Ockham^ewY ork., 1 9 3 5 . K a r r e r , O t t o (ed.), Meister Eckehart; das System seiner religiösen Lehre und Lebenswahrheit, M u n i c h , 1 9 2 3 . Seeberg, E r i c h , Meister Eckhart, T ü b i n g e n , 1 9 3 4 . M u l l e r - T h y m , B . J . , University ojBeing in M. Eckhart, 1 9 3 9 . VI.
MODERN
PHILOSOPHY
1 . GENERAL WORKS Erdmann, Johann
Eduard,
Versuch
Geschichte der neuern Philosophie
einer wissenschaftlichen
Darstellung
der
( 6 v o l . ) , R i g a and D o r p a t a n d L e i p z i g ,
1834-53-
Fischer, K u n o , Geschichte der neuern Philosophie, 4 t h ed. ( 1 0 v o l . ) , 1 8 9 7 - 1 9 0 4 ; 5 t h ed. ( 2 vol.), Heidelberg, 1 9 0 9 - 1 2 . E n g . trans, of section o n Descartes (from 3 r d G e r . ed.), History ojModern Philosophy, N e w Y o r k , 1 8 8 7 . W i n d e l b a n d , W i l h e l m , Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, 7 - 8 t h ed. ( 2 v o l . ) , Leipzig, 1922. Falckenberg, R i c h a r d F r i e d r i c h O t t o , Geschichte der neueren Philosophie, 8 t h ed., 1 9 2 7 . E n g . trans, of 2 n d G e r . ed. b y A . C . Armstrong, J r . , History of Modern Philosophyfrom Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time, 3 r d ed. reprinted Calcutta, 1953. Heimsoeth, H e i n z , La metafísica moderna (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1 9 3 2 ) . L i t t , T h e o d o r , La ética moderna (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1 9 3 3 ) . L e c k y , W i l l i a m E d w a r d Hartpole, History of the Rise and Influence of the Spirit of Rationalismin Europe,rev. ed. ( 2 v o l . ) , N e w Y o r k , 1 8 8 4 . Cassirer, E r n s t , Das Erkenntnisproblem ( 4 v o l . ) , 1 9 0 6 - 5 7 ; V o l . I — I I I , B e r l i n ; V o l . I V , Stuttgart. E n g . trans, by W i l l i a m H . Woglom a n d C h a r l e s W . H e n d e l , TheProblemofKnowledge,Ne'wJia.ven, 1950. 2 . T H E RENAISSANCE General
Works
Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Weltanschauung und Analyse des Menschen seit Renaissance und Reformation (GesammelteSchriften), V o l . I I , L e i p z i g . B u r c k h a r d t , J a k o b , Die Cultur der Renaissance in Italien, 3 r d ed. ( 2 vol.), L e i p z i g , 1 8 7 7 - 7 8 . E n g . trans, by S. G . C . Middlemore, The Civilization of the Renaissance in Italy, numerous reprints, of w h i c h the currently most economical is N e w Y o r k ( 2 v o l . ) , 1 9 5 8 .
Bibliography Heimsoeth, H e i n z , Die sechs grossen Themen der abendländischen Metaphysik,
477
3rd
ed., Stuttgart, c. 1 9 5 4 . Charbonnel, J . R . , La pensée italienne au XVI siècle et le courant libertin, 1 9 1 7 . Cassirer, E r n s t , Individuum und Kosmos in der Philosophie der Renaissance, L e i p z i g , e
1927.
Monographs HUMANISM Allen, Percy Stafford, The Age of Erasmus, Oxford, 1 9 1 4 . M a n n , Margaret, Érasme et les débuts de la Réforme française, 1517-1536,
Paris,
1934-
H u i z i n g a , J o h a n : E n g . trans, by F . H o p m a n , Erasmus, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 2 4 . Bataillon, M a r c e l , Érasme et l'Espagne, Paris, 1 9 3 7 . Bonilla y S a n M a r t í n , Adolfo, Luis Vivesy la filosofía del Renacimiento ( 3 vol.), Madrid, 1929. M a r a ñ ó n , Gregorio, Luis Vives, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 2 . Ortega y Gasset, J o s é , Vives, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 2 . Estelrich,Joan, Vives, Paris, 1 9 4 2 . NICHOLAS OF CUSA Vansteenberghe, E d m o n d , Le Cardinal Nicolas de Cues, Paris, 1 9 2 0 . R o t t a , Paolo, " I l C a r d i n a l e N i c o l ô di C u s a , " Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore, Milano. Pubb. Ser.prima: Scienzefilosofiche, V o l . 1 2 , 1 9 2 8 , pp. i - x v i , 1-448.
Hommes, Die philosophischen Grundlehren des Nicolaus von Cues, 1 9 2 6 . M o r i n , " N i c o l a s de C u e s , " i n Dictionnaire de philosophie et de théologie scolastique. G a n d i l l a c , M a u r i c e Patronnier de, La philosophie de Nicolas de Cuse, 1 9 4 1 . GIORDANO BRUNO Berti, Domenico, Giordano Bruno, sua vita e sue dottrine, 1880. Spampanato, V i n c e n z o , Vita di Giordano Bruno ( 2 v o l . ) , Messina, 1 9 2 1 . Gentile, G i o v a n n i , Giordano Bruno e il pensiero del Rinascimento, 2 n d ed., Florence, 1 9 2 5 . H ö n i g s w a l d , R i c h a r d , Giordano Bruno (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1 9 2 5 ) . M O D E R N PHYSICS Prantl, Carl, Galilei und Kepler als Logiker, 1 8 7 5 . G r a t r y , Auguste J o s e p h Alphonse, Logique, 1 8 5 5 . E n g . trans, by H e l e n a n d M i l t o n Singer, Logic, L a Salle, 111., 1 9 4 4 . Snow, A d o l p h J u d a h , Matter and Gravity in Newton's Physical Philosophy, London, 1926. Ortega y Gasset, J o s é , " L a ' F i l o s o f í a de l a H i s t o r i a ' de Hegel y l a historiologia, " i n V o l . I V oí O bras Completas, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , " L a n u e v a f í s i c a , " va. Natur ateza, Historia, Dios, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " F í s i c a y m e t a f í s i c a en Newton, " i n San Anselmo y el insensato, Madrid, 1944.
Bibliography SPANISH SCHOLASTICISM Solana, M a r c i a l , Historia de la Filosofía española, siglo XVI
(3 vol.), Madrid,
1940-41.
Getino, L u i s G . Alonso, El Miro. Fr. Francisco de Vitoriay el renacimiento teológico del siglo XVI, 3 r d ed., 1 9 3 0 . Mahieu,FrançoisSuarez ( 2 vol.), 1 9 2 1 . Scorraille, R . de, François Suarez ( 2 vol.) , 1 9 1 1 . R e c a s é n s Siches, L u i s , Lafilosofía del derecho de Francisco Suarez, 1 9 2 7 . Conze, R . E . , Der Begriffder Metaphysik beiFranz Suarez, 1 9 2 9 . Fichter, Joseph H e n r y , Man of Spain, Francis Suarez, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 4 0 . Z a r a g ü e t a [Bengoechea], J u a n , La filosofía de Suarez y el pensamiento actual, Madrid, 1 9 4 1 . G ó m e z Arboleya, E n r i q u e , Francisco Suárez,S.I., G r a n a d a , 1 9 4 6 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " S u á r e z en la perpectiva de l a r a z ó n h i s t ó r i c a , " i n Ensayos de teoría, Barcelona, 1 9 5 4 .
3 . SEVENTEENTH-CENTURY IDEALISM DESCARTES Bordas-Demoulin,Jean Baptiste, Le Cartésianisme ( 2 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 8 4 3 . Chevalier, Jacques, Descartes, Paris, 1 9 2 1 . Gilson, É t i e n n e H e n r i , Études sur le rôle de la pensée médiévale dans la formation du système cartésien, Paris, 1 9 3 0 . K o y r é , Alexandre, Descartes und die Scholastik, 1 9 2 3 . Essai sur l'idée de Dieu et les preuves de son existence chez Descartes, Paris, 1922.
H a m e l i n , O c t a v e , Le système de Descartes, Paris, 1 9 1 1 . Gouhier, H e n r i Gaston, Essais sur Descartes, Paris, 1 9 3 7 . Les premières pensées de Descartes, Paris, 1 9 5 8 . Études sur Descartes, pub. by Revue de métaphysique et de morale, Paris, 1 9 3 7 . Jaspers, K a r l , Descartes unddie Philosophie, 3 r d e d . , Berlin, 1 9 5 6 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , ' ' L o s dos cartesianismos, " in Ensayos de teoría, Barcelona, 1 9 5 4 . A l q u i é , F e r d i n a n d , La découverte métaphysique de l'homme chez Descartes, Paris, 195°.
Rodis-Lewis, G e n e v i è v e , La morale de Descartes, Paris, 1 9 5 7 . CARTESIANISM I N FRANCE Delbos, V i c t o r , Étude de la philosophie de Malebranche, C h â t i l l o n s/Seine and Paris, 1 9 2 4 . Gouhier, H e n r i Gaston, La philosophie de Malebranche et son expérience religieuse, Paris, 1 9 2 6 . Stieler, Georg, Nikolaus Malebranche, Stuttgart, 1 9 2 5 . Boutroux, É m i l e , Pascal, Paris, 1 9 0 0 . Strowski, Fortunat J o s e p h , Pascal et son temps ( 3 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 9 0 7 - 8 . Chevalier, Jacques, Pascal, Paris, 1 9 2 2 . E n g . trans. by L i l i a n A . C l a r e , Pascal, New Y o r k , 1 9 3 0 . J o v y , Ernest, Études pascaliennes, 1 9 2 7 - 2 8 . Busson, H e n r i , La pensée religieusefrançaise deCharron à Pascal, Paris, 1 9 3 3 .
Bibliography G u a r d i n i , R o m a n o , Christliches
Bewusstsein.
479 Versuche über Pascal,
¡rd
ed.,
Munich, 1956. SPINOZA C o u c h o u d , P a u l - L o u i s , Benoît de Spinoza, Paris, 1 9 0 2 . Delbos, V i c t o r , Le spinozisme, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 2 6 . G u n n , J o h n Alexander, BenedictSpinoza, Melbourne, 1 9 2 5 . Baensch, O . , et dl. (edd.), Baruch de Spinoza: Sämtliche philosophische Werke, 3 r d rev. ed. ( 6 vol. i n 2 ) , Leipzig, 1 9 0 7 . Societas Spinozana, Septimana Spinozana, T h e H a g u e , 1 9 3 3 . S é r o u y a , H e n r i , Spinoza, sa vie et sa philosophie, Paris, 1 9 3 3 . Dujovne, L e ó n , Spinoza; su vida, su época, su obra, su influencia ( 4 v o l . ) , Buenos Aires, 1 9 4 1 - 4 5 . LEIBNIZ Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Leibniz und sein Zeitalter ( V o l . I I I oí Gesammelte Schriften), L e i p z i g a n d Berlin, 1 9 2 7 . Russell, Bertrand, A Critica! Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz, with an Appendix ofLeading Passages, 2 n d ed., C a m b r i d g e , 1 9 3 7 . Couturat, L o u i s , La logique de Leibniz, d'après des documents inédits, H i l d e s h e i m , 1901.
Cassirer, E r n s t , Leibniz' System in seinen wissenschaftlichen Grundlagen, 2 n d ed., Hildesheim, 1962. Baruzi, J . , Leibniz et l'organisation religieuse de la terre, Paris, 1 9 0 7 . Heimsoeth, H e i n z , Die Methode der Erkenntnis bei Descartes und Leibniz ( 2 v o l . ) , Giessen, 1 9 1 2 - 1 4 . Leibniz's Weltanschauung, 1 9 1 7 . S c h m a l e n b a c h , H e r m á n , Leibniz, 1 9 2 1 . K i n k e l , W a l t e r , Leibniz. Stammler, G e r h a r d , Leibniz, M u n i c h , 1 9 3 0 . C a r r , H e r b e r t W i l d o n , Leibniz, Boston, 1 9 2 9 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , annotated Span. ed. of L e i b n i z ' Discours de métaphysique, 1 9 4 2 . M o r e a u , J o s e p h , L'universLeibnizien, Paris, 1 9 5 6 . O r t e g a y Gasset, J o s é , La idea de principio deductiva, Buenos Aires, 1 9 5 8 .
en Leibniz y la evolución de la teoría
4 . EMPIRICISM BRITISH PHILOSOPHY Sorley, W i l l i a m R i t c h i e , A History of English Philosophy, 2 n d ed., C a m b r i d g e (Eng.), 1 9 3 7 . R é m u s a t , C h a r l e s de, Bacon, sa vie, son temps, sa philosophie, et son influence jusqu'à nos jours, 3 r d ed., Paris, 1 8 7 7 . Wolff, Emil,Baconundseine Quellen ( 2 v o l . ) , 1 9 1 0 - 1 3 . Spedding, J a m e s , Account of the Life and Times of Francis Bacon ( 2 v o l . ) , 1 8 7 9 . Brochard, V i c t o r , " L a philosophie de Bacon, " i n Études de philosophie ancienne et de philosophie moderne, Paris, 1 9 1 2 .
Bibliography L e v i , Adolfo, Ilpensiero diF. Bacone, 1 9 2 5 . H ö n i g s w a l d , R i c h a r d , Hobbes und die Staatsphilosophie, M u n i c h , 1 9 2 4 . M e i n e c k e , F r i e d r i c h , Die Idee der Staatsräson in der neueren Geschichte, M u n i c h , 1924.
T ö n n i e s , F e r d i n a n d , Thomas Hobbes ; Leben und Lehre, Stuttgart, 1 9 2 5 . Brandt, Frithiof, Thomas Hobbes' Mechanical Conception of Nature. E n g . trans, by V a u g h n M a x w e l l a n d A n n i e I . Fausboll, Copenhagen, 1 9 2 8 . Laird, John, Hoiéej, London, 1934. P o l i n , R a y m o n d , Politique et philosophie chez Thomas Hobbes, Paris, 1 9 5 3 . H a z a r d , P a u l , La crise de la conscience européenne (1680-1J15), Paris, 1 9 3 5 . E n g . trans, by J . L e w i s M a y , The European Mind, 1680-1715, L o n d o n , 1 9 5 3 . A l e x a n d e r , Samuel, Locke, 1 9 0 8 . A a r o n , R i c h a r d I t h a m a r , John Locke, 2 n d ed., Oxford, 1 9 5 5 . O ' C o n n o r , D a n i e l J o h n , John Locke, L o n d o n , 1 9 5 2 . R e p r i n t e d N e w Y o r k , 1966.
P e t z ä l l , Â k e , Ethics and Epistemology in John Locke's "Essay Concerning Understanding," G ö t e b o r g , 1 9 3 7 . F r a s e r , Alexander C a m p b e l l , Berkeley, E d i n b u r g h and L o n d o n , 1 8 8 1 . M i l l , J o h n Stuart, Berkeley's Life and Writings, 1 8 7 1 . Cassirer, E r n s t , Berkeley's System, 1914.
Human
L u c e , A r t h u r Aston, Berkeley and Malebranche; a Study in the Origins of Berkeley's Thought, Oxford, 1 9 3 4 . H e d e n i u s , Ingemar, Sensationalism and Theology in Berkeley's Philosophy. E n g . trans, by G e r d a Wingqvist, U p p s a l a , 1 9 3 6 . W i l d , J o h n D a n i e l , George Berkeley; a Study of His Life and Philosophy, C a m bridge ( E n g . ) , 1 9 3 6 . W a r n o c k , G . J . , Berkeley, M e l b o u r n e a n d Baltimore, 1 9 5 3 . M e i n o n g , Alexius, HumeStudien ( 2 v o l . ) , V i e n n a , 1 8 7 7 - 8 2 . M e t z , Rudolf, David Hume ; Leben und Philosophie, Stuttgart, 1 9 2 9 . L a i n g , Bertram Mitchell, David Hume, L o n d o n , 1 9 3 2 . L a i r d , J o h n , Hume's Philosophy of Human Nature, L o n d o n , 1 9 3 2 . H e d e n i u s , Ingemar, Studies in Hume's Ethics, U p p s a l a , 1 9 3 7 . M a u n d , Constance, A Critical Examination of Hume's Epistemology, with Reference to Its Bearing on Modern Problems, L o n d o n , 1 9 3 6 . J o n e s , O l i n M c K e n d r e e , Empiricism and Intuitionism in Reid's Common Sense Philosophy, Princeton, 1 9 2 7 .
T H E ENLIGHTENMENT Cassirer, E r n s t , Die Philosophie der Aufklärung, T ü b i n g e n , 1 9 3 2 . E n g . trans, b y F r i t z C . A . K o e l l n and J a m e s P. Pettegrove, The Philosophy of the Enlightenment, Princeton, 1 9 5 1 . H a z a r d , P a u l , La pensée européenne au XVIII siècle, de Montesquieu à Lessing ( 3 vol. i n 2 ) , Paris, 1 9 4 6 . E n g . trans, by J . L e w i s M a y , European Thought in the i8thCentury,from Montesquieu to Lessing, L o n d o n , 1 9 5 4 . ème
Brunetière,Ferdma.iid, Études sur le XVIII siècle,Faxis, 1 9 1 1 . M o r n e t , D a n i e l , Les origines intellectuelles de la Révolution Française Paris, 1 9 3 3 . e
(1715-1J8J),
Bibliography Desnoiresterres, Gustave [ L e Brisoys], Voltaire et la société au XVIII siècle ( 8 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 8 6 7 - 7 6 . L a n s o n , Gustave, Voltaire, 2 n d ed., Paris, 1 9 1 0 . Aldington, R i c h a r d , Voltaire, L o n d o n , 1 9 2 5 . T o r r e y , N o r m a n L e w i s , Voltaire and the English Deists, N e w H a v e n , 1 9 3 0 . Barckausen, H e n r i Auguste, Montesquieu, ses idées et ses œuvres d'après les papiers de la Brède, Paris, 1 9 0 7 . Hoffding, H a r a l d , Jean Jacques Rousseau and His Philosophy. E n g . trans, of 2 n d D a n i s h ed. by W i l l i a m R i c h a r d s and L e o E . S a i d l a , N e w H a v e n and London, 1930. W r i g h t , Ernest H u n t e r , The Meaning ofRousseau,i.ondon, 1929. Gér'm, J . J . Rousseau, 1 9 3 0 . e
H e n d e l , Charles W i l l i a m , Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, Moralist
( 2 vol.), L o n d o n ,
1934-
H e l i g o n , E . , Condillac, 1 9 3 7 . M ü l l e r , M . , Essai sur la philosophie deJean d'Alembert, 1 9 2 6 . Delvaille, Jules, Essai sur l'histoire de l'idée de progrès, jusqu'à la fin du XVIII siècle, Paris, 1 9 1 0 . Bury, J o h n Bagnell, The Idea of Progress; an Inquiry into Its Origin and Growth, London, 1920. Reprinted New York, 1955. S é e , H e n r i E u g è n e , Les idées politiques enFrance au XVIII siècle, Paris, 1 9 2 0 . Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Friedrich der Grosse und die deutsche Aufklärung. Das achtzehnte Jahrhundert und die geschichtliche Welt ( V o l . I I I of Gesammelte Schriften), L e i p z i g a n d Berlin, 1 9 2 7 . Croce, Benedetto, La filosofía di Giambattista Vico ( V o l . 2 oîSaggifilosqfici), 2 n d ed., Bari, 1 9 2 2 . E n g . trans, by R . G . Collingwood. The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico, L o n d o n , 1 9 1 3 . Peters, R i c h a r d , Der Aufbau der Weltgeschichte bei Giambattista Vico, Stuttgart, e
e
!929-
Giusso, Lorenzo, Lafilosofía di Giambattista Vico e l'età barocca, 1 9 4 3 . H e r r , R i c h a r d , The Eighteenth-Century Revolution in Spain, Princeton, 1 9 5 8 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Los Españoles, M a d r i d , 1 9 6 2 . T H E FORMATION OF T H E M O D E R N EPOCH H a z a r d , P a u l , La crise de la conscience européenne (1680-1713), Paris, 1 9 3 5 . E n g . trans, b y j . L e w i s M a y , The European Mind, 1680-17 iß, L o n d o n , 1 9 5 3 . Sombart, Werner, Luxus und Kapitalismus, M u n i c h , 1 9 1 3 . E n g . trans., Luxury andCapitalism,Nev/York, 1938. Krieg und Kapitalismus, M u n i c h , 1 9 1 3 . T a w n e y , R i c h a r d H e n r y , Religion and the Rise of Capitalism; a Historical Study, New York, 1926. D u n n i n g , W i l l i a m A r c h i b a l d , A History of Political Theories from Luther to Montesquieu,NeviYork, 1905. Weber, M a x , Die protestantische Ethik und der Geist der Kapitalismus, T ü b i n g e n , 1 9 2 0 . E n g . trans, by T a l c o t t Parsons, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, L o n d o n , 1 9 3 0 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " L a p é r d i d a de D i o s , " i n V o l . ÏW oí Obras Completas, M a d r i d , 1944.
48z
Bibliography
5. GERMAN IDEALISM KANT C o h e n , H e r m a n n , Kants Theorie der Erfahrung, Berlin, 18 7 1 . Ruyssen, T h é o d o r e , Kant, Paris, 1 9 0 0 . Cassirer, E r n s t , Kants Leben und Lehre, 1 9 1 8 . G a r c i a Morente, M a n u e l , Lafilosofia de Kant, M a d r i d , 1 9 1 7 . W u n d t , M a x , Kant als Metaphysiker, 1 9 2 4 . Ortega y Gasset, J o s é , Kant, iys4~igs4; reflexiones de centenario, M a d r i d , 1 9 2 g . Menzer, P a u l , Kants Lehre von der Entwicklung in Natur und Geschichte, Berlin, ign. K ü l p e , O s w a l d , Immanuel Kant;
Darstellung
und Würdigung, 5 Ü 1 ed., L e i p z i g ,
1921.
Heidegger, M a r t i n , Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, Frankfurt a m M a i n , i g 3 4 . E n g . trans, by J a m e s S. C h u r c h i l l , Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, Bloomington, i g 6 2 . FICHTE Lask, E m i l , Fichtes Idealismus und die Geschichte, T ü b i n g e n , 1 9 0 2 . L é o n , X a v i e r , " L a philosophie de Fichte et l a conscience contemporaine, " i n Revue de métaphysique et de morale, Paris, 1 9 0 2 . Fichteetson temps ( 2 vol. in 3 ) , Paris, 1 9 2 2 - 2 7 . Medicus, F r i t z , Fichte, 1 9 1 1 . Einleitung zuFichtes Werke, 1 9 1 1 . H a r t m a n n , N i c o l a i , Die Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus,
2 n d ed., Berlin,
i960.
Heimsoeth, H e i n z , F i c h t e , M u n i c h , 1 9 2 3 . G u é r o u l t , M a r t i a l , L'évolution et la structure de la doctrine de la science chez Fichte, Paris, 1 9 3 0 . SCHELLING Fischer, K u n o , Schelling, 1 9 0 2 . Bréhier, É m i l e , Schelling, Paris, 1 9 1 2 . Knittermeyer, H i n r i c h , Schelling und die romantische Schule, M u n i c h , 1 g 2 g . HEGEL Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Die Jugendgeschichte Hegels und andere Abhandlungen zur Geschichte des deutschen Idealismus ( V o l . YV oî Gesammelte Schriften), L e i p z i g . K r o n e r , R i c h a r d , Von Kant bis Hegel ( 2 v o l . ) , T ü b i n g e n , i g 2 i - 2 4 . Falkenheim, H u g o , Hegel, 1 g 1 1 . Moog, W i l l y , Hegel unddiehegelsche Schule, M u n i c h , 1 g 3 0 . Croce, Benedetto, Saggio sullo Hegel ( V o l . 3 of Saggißlosqfici), Bari, 1 9 1 3 . E n g . trans, by Douglas Ainslie, What Is Living and What Is Dead of the Philosophy of Hegel, L o n d o n , 1 9 1 5 . Gentile, G i o v a n n i , La riforma della dialettica hegeliana, 3 r d ed., F l o r e n c e , i g 5 4 Teoria generale dello spirito come atto puro, 6 t h rev. ed., F l o r e n c e , 1 9 4 4 . E n g . trans, of 3 r d ed. by H . W i l d o n C a r r , The Theory of Mind as Pure Act, London, 1 9 2 2 . C u n n i n g h a m , Gustavus Watts, Thought and Reality in Hegel's System, N e w York, i g 10.
Bibliography
483
Ortega y Gasset, J o s é , " H e g e l y A m é r i c a , " i n V o l . I I of Obras Completas, Madrid, 1947. " L a ' F i l o s o f í a de l a H i s t o r i a ' d e H e g e l y l a h i s t o r i o l o g í a , " i n V o l . I V of ObrasCompletas, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , " H e g e l y el problema m e t a f í s i c o , " in Naturaleza, Historia, Dios, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 . Glockner, H e r m a n n , Hegel ( 2 vol.), Stuttgart, 1 9 2 9 - 4 0 . H a r t m a n n , N i c o l a i , Die Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus, I I , 2 n d ed., Berlin, i960.
S t e i n b ü c h e l , T h e o d o r , Das Grundproblem derhegelschen Philosophie, 1 9 3 3 .
T H E T H O U G H T OF T H E ROMANTIG A G E Dilthey, W i l h e l m , Das Leben Schleiermachers, 1 8 7 0 . Das Erlebnis und die Dichtung: Lessing, Goethe, Novalis, Hölderlin, 131h ed., Stuttgart, 1 9 5 7 . Mulert, H e r m a n n , Schleiermacher und die Gegenwart, Frankfurt a m M a i n , 1 9 3 4 . Simmel, Georg, Schopenhauer undNietzsche. Ein Vortragszyklus, Leipzig, 1 9 0 7 . Ruyssen, T h é o d o r e , Schopenhauer, 1 9 1 1 . Haase, H e i n r i c h , Schopenhauer, M u n i c h , 1 9 2 6 . Jobit, Pierre, Les éducateurs de VEspagne contemporaine. I : Les Krausistes,
Paris,
1936.
L ó p e z - M o r i l l a s , J u a n , El krausismo español, M e x i c o , 1 9 5 6 . C a c h o V i u , V i c e n t e , La Institución Libre de Enseñanza, M a d r i d , 1 9 6 2 .
6 . NINETEENTH-CENTURY PHILOSOPHY T H E T R I U M P H OVER SENSATIONALISM Nicolas, A . , Études sur Maine de Biran, 1 8 5 8 . C o u a i l h a c , M a r i u s , Maine de Biran, Paris, 1 9 0 5 . Michelet, J u l e s , Maine de Biran, Paris, 1 9 0 6 . Tisserand, Pierre, L'anthropologie de Maine de Biran, Paris, 1 9 0 9 . L a V a l l e t t e M o n b r u n , A m a b l e de, Maine de Biran (1766-1824) ; essai de biographie historique et psychologique, Paris, 1 9 1 4 . Delbos, V i c t o r , " M a i n e de Biran, " inFigures et doctrines de philosophes, 2 n d é d . , Paris, 1 9 2 6 . Gouhier, H e n r i G a s t o n , Introduction to Œuvres choisies de Maine de Biran, 1 9 4 2 . Journal (of M a i n e de Biran), edited b y G o u h i e r ( 3 vol.), N e u c h â t e l , 1
954-57-
M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " E l hombre y Dios en l a filosofía de M a i n e de Biran, " i n V o l . IV oí O bras Completas, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 .
COMTE'S POSITIVISM L i t t r é , E m i l e , Auguste Comte et la philosophie positive, Paris, 1 8 6 3 . M i l l , J o h n Stuart, Auguste Comte and Positivism, 4 t h é d . , L o n d o n , 1 8 9 1 . L é v y - B r u h l , L u c i e n , La philosophie d'Auguste Comte, 1 9 0 0 . E n g . trans, F r e d e r i c H a r r i s o n , ThePhilosophyqfAugusteComte,NewYork, 1903.
by
Bibliography
4&4
Gantecor, G . , Le positivisme,
i904.
Marcuse, Alexander, Die Geschichtsphilosophie Auguste Comtes, Stuttgart, 1 9 3 2 . Gouhier, H e n r i Gaston, La jeunesse d'Auguste Comte et la formation du positivisme ( 3 vol.), Paris, 1 9 3 3 - 4 1 . La vie d'Auguste Comte, Paris, 1 9 3 1 .
PHILOSOPHY OF POSITIVIST INSPIRATION T a i n e , Hippolyte A d o l p h e , Les philosophes français du XIX siècle, Paris, 1 8 5 7 . Ravaisson-Mollien, F é l i x , La philosophie enFrance au XIX siècle, P a r i s , 1 8 6 8 . F e r r a z , L . , Histoire de la philosophie enFrance au XIX siècle ( 3 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 8 8 0 ¬ e
e
e
89.
Benrubi, Isaak, Les sources et les courants de la philosophie contemporaine en France ( 2 vol.), Paris, 1 9 3 3 . E n g . trans. by Ernest B. D i c k e r , Contemporary Thought of France, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 2 6 . G u y a u , M a r i e J e a n , La morale anglaise contemporaine: morale de l'utilité et de l'évolution, 3 r d e d . , Paris, 1 8 9 5 . M u i r h e a d , J . H . (ed.), Contemporary British Philosophy, L o n d o n , 1 9 2 4 . Saenger, Samuel, John Stuart Mili, Britton, K a r l , John Stuart Mill,
Sein Leben und Lebenswerk,
Stuttgart, 1 9 0 1 .
L o n d o n and Baltimore, 1 9 5 3 .
T H E DISCOVERY OF L I F E L o w r i e , Walter, Kierkegaard, L o n d o n , 1 9 3 8 . Hoffding, H a r a l d , Seren Kierkegaardsomfilosof Copenhagen, 1 9 1 9 . L ö w i t h , K a r l , Kierkegaard und Nietzsche, H a l l e a n der Saale, 1 9 3 3 . Bertram, E r n s t , Nietzsche; Versuch einer Mythologie, 3 r d ed., B e r l i n , 1 9 1 9 . P f ä n d e r , A.,Nietzsche, 1 9 1 1 (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1 9 2 5 ) . Vetter, August, Nietzsche, M u n i c h , 1 9 2 6 . Jaspers, K a r l , Nietzsche; ed., Berlin, 1 9 4 7 .
Einführung in das Verständnis seines Philosophierens,
Schlechta, K a r l , Der Fall r
Nietzsche;
Aufsätze
3rd
und Vorträge, 2 n d e d . , M u n i c h ,
959-
T H E RETURN TO T R A D I T I O N A L METAPHYSICS P e r r a u d , C a r d i n a l , Le Père Gratry, sa vie et ses œuvres, Paris, 1 9 0 0 . B r a u n , L . L . , Gratrys Theorie von der religiösen Erkenntnis, 1 9 1 4 . Scheller, E . J . , Grundlagen der Erkenntnislehre bei Gratry, 1 9 2 9 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " L a filosofía del Padre Gratry, " i n V o l . I V o f O b r a s Completas, Madrid, 1944. "La
restauración
de l a m e t a f í s i c a
en el p r o b l e m a
de Dios y l a
persona, " i n V o l . I V o f O bras Completas, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 .
7 . CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY BRENTANO K r a u s , Oskar, Brentanos Stellung zur Phänomenologie und Gegenstandstheorie, Rogge, E . , Das Kausalproblem beiFranz Brentano, 1 9 3 5 . C r u z H e r n á n d e z , M i g u e l , Francisco Brentano, S a l a m a n c a , 1 9 5 3 .
1924.
Bibliography
48J
T H E I D E A OF L I F E M i s c h , Georg, Lebensphilosophie und Phänomenologie; eine Auseinandersetzung der dilthey'sehen Richtung mit Heidegger und Husserl, 2 n d ed., L e i p z i g , 1 9 3 1 . V o r b e r i c h t to V o l . V of Diltheys Gesammelte Schriften, L e i p z i g , 1 9 2 3 . Degener, Alfons, Dilthey und das Problem der Metaphysik,
Bonn a n d Cologne,
1933-
O r t e g a y Gasset, J o s é , Guillermo Dilthey y la idea de la vida, M a d r i d , 1 9 3 4 . H ö f e r , J . , Vom Leben zur Wahrheit. Katholische Besinnung an der Lebensanschauung Wilhelm Diltheys, 1 9 3 6 . Bollnow, Otto Friedrich, Dilthey ; eine Einführung in seine Philosophie, 2 n d ed., Stuttgart, 1 9 5 5 . L a i n E n t r a l g o , Pedro, Dilthey y el método de la historia, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 2 . P u c c i a r e l l i , F . , La esencia de lafilosofía, Buenos Aires, 1 9 4 4 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , " I n t r o d u c c i ó n a la filosofía de l a v i d a , " i n the annotated S p a n , trans, of Dilthey's Weltanschauungslehre, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 4 . Hodges, H e r b e r t Arthur, Wilhelm Dilthey, an Introduction, L o n d o n , 1 9 4 4 . D í a z de C e r i o R u i z , F r a n c o , Wilhelm Dilthey y el problema del mundo histórico, Barcelona, 1 9 5 9 . G a r c í a Morente, M a n u e l , Lafilosofía de Henri Bergson, M a d r i d , 1 9 1 7 . Z a r a g ü e t a [Bengoechea], J u a n , La intuición en la filosofía de Henri Bergson, Madrid, 1941. Hoffding, H a r a l d , Henri Bergson's filosofi; karakteristik og kritik, Copenhagen, 1914.
C h e v a l i e r , Jacques, Bergson, Paris, 1 9 2 6 . E n g . trans, by L i l i a n A . C l a r e , Henri Bergson, N e w Y o r k and L o n d o n , 1 9 2 8 . L e R o y , É d o u a r d , Une philosophie nouvelle; Henri Bergson, Paris, 1 9 1 2 . E n g . trans, by V . Benson, The New Philosophy of Henri Bergiorc, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 1 3 . M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Miguel de Unamuno, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 3 . La Escuela de Madrid; estudios defilosofía española, Buenos Aires, 1 9 5 9 . O r o m í , M i g u e l , El pensamiento filosófico de Miguel de Unamuno, filosofía existencial de la inmortalidad, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 3 . F e r r a t e r M o r a , J o s é , Unamuno; bosquejo de una filosofía, 2 n d ed., Buenos Aires,1 9 5 7 . E n g . trans, by P h i l i p Silver, Unamuno, a Philosophy of Tragedy, Berkeley, 1 9 6 2 . L a n d s b e r g , P a u l L u d w i g , "Reflexiones sobre U n a m u n o , " i n Cruz y Raya, No. 3 1 , Madrid, 1935. Serrano Poncela, Segundo, El pensamiento de Unamuno, Mexico, 1 9 5 3 . C a l v e t t i , C a r l a , La fenomenología della credenza in Miguel de Unamuno, 1 9 5 5 . M e y e r , F r a n ç o i s , L'ontologie de Miguel de Unamuno, Paris, 1 9 5 5 . ENGLISH-LANGUAGE PHILOSOPHY Schneider, Herbert W a l l a c e , A History of American Philosophy, 2 n d ed., N e w York, 1963. M o o r e , Addison Webster, Pragmatism audits Critics, Chicago, 1 9 1 0 . P r a t t , J a m e s Bissett, What Is Pragmatism?, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 0 9 . P e r r y , R a l p h Barton, Present Philosophical Tendencies; a Critical Survey of Naturalism, Idealism, Pragmatism, and Realism; Together with a Synopsis of the Philosophy of William J ames, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 1 2 .
486
Bibliography
L e r o u x , E m m a n u e l , Le pragmatisme américain et anglais; étude historique et critique, suivie d'une bibliographie méthodique,Va.û%, 1 9 2 3 . H o o k , Sidney, The Metaphysics of Pragmatism, Chicago and L o n d o n , 1 9 2 7 . G a l l i e , W . B., Peirce and Pragmatism, Harmondsworth, 1 9 5 2 . R e p r i n t e d N e w York, 1966. Boutroux, É m i l e , Williamjames. E n g . trans, ofended, by A . a n d B. Henderson, New York, 1912. K n i g h t , Margaret, William James, Baltimore, 1 9 5 0 . R u n e s , Dagobert D a v i d (ed.), Twentieth Century Philosophy ; Living Schools of TAougAi, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 4 3 . F ä r b e r , M a r v i n (ed), L'activité philosophique contemporaine en France et aux ÉtatsUnis ( 2 v o l . ) , Paris, 1 9 5 0 . E n g . trans., Philosophie Thought in France and the United States ; Essays Representing Major Trends in Contemporary French and American Philosophy, Buffalo, 1 9 5 0 . S c h i l p p , P a u l A r t h u r (ed.), The Philosophy of John Dewey, E v a n s t o n a n d Chicago, 1939. ThePhilosophy of George Santay ana, Evanston and C h i c a g o , 1 9 4 0 . The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead, Evanston a n d C h i c a g o , 1 9 4 1 . ThePhilosophy of Bertrand Russell, E v a n s t o n and Chicago, 1 9 4 4 . HUSSERL C e l m s , Teodors, El idealismo fenomenológico de Husserl (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1928).
G a o s , J o s é , La crítica delpsicologismo en Husserl, Zaragoza, 1 9 3 3 . Z u b i r i , X a v i e r , Ensayo de una ideafenomenológica del juicio, M a d r i d , 1 9 2 7 . L é v i n a s , E m m a n u e l , La théorie de l'intuition dans la phénoménologie de Husserl, Paris, 1 9 3 0 . X i r a u , J o a q u í n , Lafilosofía de Husserl. Una introducción a lafenomenología, Buenos Aires, 1 9 4 0 . F ä r b e r , M a r v i n , The Foundation of Phenomenology ; Edmund Husserl and the Quest for a Rigorous Science of Philosophy, C a m b r i d g e , Mass., 1 9 4 3 . Spiegelberg, H . , ThePhenomenologicalMovement, Tha Hague, i 9 6 0 . R o t h , Alois, Edmund Husserls ethische Untersuchungen, dargestellt anhand seiner Vorlesungsmanuskripte, T h e H a g u e , 1 9 6 0 . V A L U E THEORY O r t e g a y Gasset, José,¿ Quéson los valores?, M a d r i d , 1 9 2 3 . " M a x S c h e l e r ; u n embriagado de esencias ( 1 8 7 4 - 1 9 2 8 ) , " i n V o l . I V of ObrasCompletas, M a d r i d , 1 9 4 7 . G u r w i t s c h , Las tendencias actuales de la filosofía alemana (Span, trans., M a d r i d , 1935)-
Hessen, J o h a n n e s , Wertphilosophie, 1 9 3 7 . L a v e l l e , L o u i s , Traitédesvaleurs,Faris, 1951. HEIDEGGER Jaspers, K a r l , Existenzphilosophie, 2nd ed., Berlin, 1 9 5 6 . Vernunft und Existenz : fünf Vorlesungen, Bremen, 1 9 4 9 . E n g . trans, b y W i l l i a m E a r l e , Reason and Existence : Five Lectures, N e w Y o r k , 1 9 5 5 .
Bibliography
481
H e y s e , H . , Idee und Existenz, 1935. Bollnow, Otto F r i e d r i c h , Existenzphilosophie, 4th ed., Stuttgart, 1955. D e l p , A . , Existencia trágica; notas sobre la filosofía de Martin Heidegger. Span. trans. b y j . Iturrioz, M a d r i d , 1942. W a g n e r de R e y n a , Alberto, La ontologia fundamental de Heidegger. Waelhens, Alphonse de, La philosophie de Martin Heidegger, 3rd ed., L o u v a i n , 1948. G a r c í a B a c c a , J . D . , Nueve grandesfilósofoscontemporáneosy
sustemas, 1947.
Gaos, J o s é , Introduction to S p a n . ed. of Heidegger's Sein und Zeit, Mexico, I95IO R T E G A Y GASSET G a r c í a Morente, M a n u e l , Ensayos, M a d r i d , 1945. Barja, C é s a r , " Ortega y Gasset, " i n Literatura española : librosy autores contemporáneos, M a d r i d , 1935. Curtius, E r n s t Robert, " O r t e g a y Gasset, " i n Kritische Essays zur europäischen Literatur, Berne, 1950. Loeser, Norbert, Ortegay Gasset en de philosophie van he t leven, 194g. M a r í a s , J u l i á n , La Escuela de Madrid; estudios defilosofía española, Buenos Aires, 1959¬ Ortegay tres antípodas, Buenos Aires, 1950. Commentary to Ortega's Meditaciones del Quijote,
2nd ed., M a d r i d ,
1957Ferrater M o r a , J o s é , La filosofía de Ortegay Gasset, Buenos Aires, 1958. E n g . trans., Ortegay Gasset ; an Outline ofHisPhilosophy, N e w H ä v e n , 1963. G a r a g o r r i , Paulino, Ortega, unareformadelafilosofía, M a d r i d , 1958. Gaos, J o s é , Sobre Ortegay Gasset, Mexico, 1957. La Torre (University of Puerto R i c o ) , Homenajea Ortegay Gasset, 1956. S a l m e r ó n , F . , Las mocedades de Ortegay Gasset, M e x i c o , 1959. Niedermayer, F r a n z , Ortegay Gasset, 1959. Borel, J e a n P a u l , Raison et vie chez Ortegay Gasset, C h a u x - d e - F o n d s , 195g. G a l e n , G r ä f i n Brigitta v o n , Die Kultur- und Gesellschaftsethik José Ortega y Gassets, Heidelberg, 195g. C e p l e c h a , Christian, O . S . B . , The Historical Thought of José Ortegay Gasset, Washington, ig58. W a l g r a v e , J . H . , De wijsbegeerte van Ortegay Gasset, 1 g5g. M a r í a s , J u l i á n , Ortega. I : Circunstanciay vocación, M a d r i d , 1960. D í a z de C e r i o R u i z , F r a n c o , José Ortegay Gasset y la conquista de la conciencia histórica. Mocedad : igo2-jgi§, Barcelona, 1961. G a r c í a Astrada, A r t u r o , El pensamiento de Ortegay Gasset, Buenos Aires, 1961. L a r r a í n A c u ñ a , H e r n á n , La génesis delpensamiento de Ortega, Buenos Aires, 1962. Gaete, A r t u r o , El sistema maduro de Ortega, Buenos A i r e s , 1962. H i e r r o S.-Pescador, J o s é , El derecho en Ortega, M a d r i d , 1965. R o d r í g u e z H u á s c a r , A n t o n i o , Con Ortegay otros escritos, M a d r i d , 1965. Soler G r i m a , Francisco, Hacia Ortega, I , Santiago de C h i l e , 1965.
Index Terms appearing in Greek characters i n the text are here transliterated and alphabetized according to English order. Abelard, Peter, 148-149 absolute, the, 320, 321, 324, 327-329 absolute knowledge, 319-320, 325, 327, 349 _ absolutism, 252, 273, 281 Academicians, 115, 118 Academy, see Platonic Academy action, 310-311, 345, 385, 389-390 active intellect, 154, 157 activism, see action actuality, 68-69, 71, 78, 135, 156, 448 Adelard of Bath (^Ethelard of Bath), 148 Adeodatus, 114, 115 adikia, 14 Aenesidemus, 96 ^Ethelard of Bath, see Adelard of Bath agäpe, 57, 58 agathön, 74, 80 Agrippa von Nettesheim, 190, 195 Ahrens, Heinrich, 335 Ailly, Pierre d', 183 aisthesis, 23, 79, 288 akousmatikoi, 16 Alaric, 119 Albert of Boilstädt or Cologne, see Albertus Magnus, St. Albert of Saxony, 183 Albertus Magnus, St. (Albert of Boilstädt or Cologne), 134, 158, 160, 164-166, 167, 181 Albigenses, 147, 151-152, 160
A l c a l á de Henares, 193, 205 alchemy, 195, 236 Alcmaeon of Crotón, 18 Alcuin, 127 Alembert, Jean L e Rond d', 263 alétheia, 21, 28, 68, 75, 80, 320, 328, 358, 406, 429, 433, 450 alethés, 68 Alexander, Samuel, 3gg Alexander of Aphrodisias, 74 Alexander the Great, 2, 60, 84, 85, 94 Alexander of Hales, 160, 161 Alexandria, i n Alfarabi, 154 Al-Gazel, 154 alienation, 4, 138-139, 180, 181, 192 Alkindi, 154 Allah, 153 alloiosis, 12 Alltäglichkeit, 431 Amalric of Bena, 152 Ambrose, St., i n , 114, 115 Amiel, Henri Frédéric, 336 Ammonius Saccas, 99 Amyntas I I , 60 analogy, 53, 66, 74, 78, 149, 220, 427 analysis, see judgment, analytic and synthetic anamnesis, 48, 79 Anaxagoras, 31-32, 36, 46, 60 Anaximander, 14-15 Anaximenes, 15 489
490
Index
Andrés, Juan, 270 andría, 54 Andronicus of Rhodes, 62 dneu symplokês, 76 Angelus Silesius (Johannes Schemer), 195 Angst (anguish), 431, 434, 436 Anselm, St., 116, 130, 134, 137, 143¬ 146, 161, 171, 179, 217, 293 Anselm of Laon, 148 anthropological controversy, 111 anthropology, 305, 325, 361, 422, 423, 430 anthropomorphism, 19 Antioch, m Antisthenes, 89 Antoninus, Marcus Aurelius, 91, 93, 94 apathla, 93 dpeiron, 14, 72 apodeixis, 76 apokatástasis pánton, 109 Apollo, 362-363 Apologists, 108, n o , 167, 177 apophainesthai, 429 apóphansis, 76 apóphasis, 76 aporta, 44, 71 aporiai of Zeno, 25 apperception, 240, 242-243 Aquinas, St. Thomas, 2, 116, 129, 132, !34> 135. : 3 8 , 145. '40, 147, 154. 158-159, 160, 162, 164, 165, 166¬ 174, 178, 179 ; see also Thomism Arabic philosophy, 143, 147, 151, 152, 1 53~155, !56> l5&, l 6 = . l 6 5 , 172» '74, 378 Aranguren, J o s é Luis, 443 Arcesilaus, 96 Archytas of Tarentum, 18 areti, 40 Arianism, 111 Aristippus of Cyrene, 89, 90 aristocracy, 36, 84-85, 269 Aristophanes, 41 Aristotelian tradition, 99, 111, 126, 143, 147, 150, 152, 153, 154, 156, 157¬ 159, 160, 162, 163-174, 178, 183, 184, 191, 192, 193, 207, 238, 356, 358, 372, 4 2 5 Aristotle, 2, 3, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17, 20, 24, 26, 27, 32, 36, 37, 38, 39, 41, 43, 52, 53, 57, 58,59-85,87,88,100, 129, 134, 163, 170, 203, 220, 240, 249, 3 ° 2 , 310, 323, 373, 407, 465
arkhê, 13, 14, 65, 323, 324 Arnaldo de Vilanova, see Vilanova, Arnaldo de Arnauld, Angélique, 228 Arnauld, Antoine, 212, 228, 278 Arnobius, n o Arteaga, Esteban de, 270 aseity, 170 Asin Palacios, Miguel, 154 Aspasia, 31 asphdleia, 85 association of ideas, 255, 259, 373 ataraxia, 93 Athanasius, St., 111 atheism, 252, 264, 338, 369, 440-441 Athens, 31-32, 35, 38, 40, 42, 60, 82, 90, 94, 107 Atlantis, 43 dtomoi, 33 atoms, 31-32, 239, 255 Aufklärung, 267-268, 331 Augsburg Confession, 275 Augustine, St., 2, 53, 57-58, m , 112, I X 3 - I S I , 137,
144.
l 6 l
>
l
8
2
, 324,
327
Augustinian tradition, 143, 150, 159, 160,161,164,172, 173, 174,182, 226, 227-228, 406, 416 Austin, John L . , 401 autarchta, 61, 89, 92; see also selfsufficiency authority (sanction), 141, 175, 209, 256, 275 autognosis, 383, 384 Autrecourt, Nicolas d', 182, 183 atixesis, 12 Avempace (Ibn Bajja), 155 Avenarius, Richard, 358 Averroës (Ibn Rushd), 79, 152, 153, 155, ' 5 ° , 157, !79 Averroism, 162, 172, 174, 182, 183, 201 Avicebron (Ibn Gabirol), 156 Avicenna (Ibn Sina), 154, 155, 373 awe, 3-4, 88, 169 Ayer, Alfred Jules, 401 Baader, Franz von, 330 Bacon, Francis, 174, 190, 204, 248¬ 250, 258 Bacon, Roger, 141, 160, 165, 174-175, 177, 247, 249 Baden school, 359 Baghdad, 154 Balmes, Jaime Luciano, 260, 335, 346¬ 347
Index
Bâflez, Domingo, 206, 238 barbarians, 112, 119, 125-126, 127, 142 Barbaro, Ermolao, 192 Basil the Great, St., i n Baumgarten, Alexander, 267 Baumker, Clemens, 174 Baur, Christian, 333 Bayle, Pierre, 262-263 Beauvoir, Simone de, 441 becoming, 27, 315, 321, 322, 328 Bede, St., 127 behaviorism, 398, 402 being, 10, 17, 39, 46, 51, 66-69, 7*. 99, 152, 203, 209, 219-220, 235, 286, 301-305, 320-324, 421-422, 427¬ 442, 455, 457, 458; see also Entity, metaphysics, nothingness Bembo, Pietro, 277 Benedictines, 142, 160, 270 Bentham, Jeremy, 253, 356 Bergson, Henri, 300, 356, 357, 384, 387-389, 391, 396, 422, 462 Berkeley, George, 256-857, 258, 284, 286 Berlin, 237, 267, 307, 316 Bernard, Claude, 355 Bernard of Chartres, 147 Bernard of Clairvaux, St., 151, 161 Bernard of Tours, 152 Bessarion, Cardinal, 192 Biel, Gabriel, 184 biology, 29 bios theoretikâs, 16 Blanshard, Brand, 400 Bloch, Ernst, 338 Blondel, Maurice, 389-390 Boas, George, 400 Boethius, 126 B ö h m e , Jakob, 195 Bologna, 160 Bolzano, Bernhard, 366, 404 Bonald, Louis de, 344, 346 Bonaventure, St. (John of Fidanza), I 3 7 - i 3 8 , 145) »60-163, 164, »77 Bopp, Franz, 331 Bossuet, Jacques Bénigne, 115, 229, 237, 262, 278, 327, 331 Boston, 394 Boutroux, Étienne Émile Marie, 462 Bowne, Borden Parker, 398 Boyle, Robert, 203, 254 Brentano, Franz, 145, 167, 300, 310,
358, 371-377, 378, 384, 403, 4 ° 4 , 409, 418
4SI Brentano's principle, 374-375 Brightman, Edgar Sheffield, 399 British Isles, 127, 140-141, 143, 160, 174, 194, 209, 247-260, 263, 267, 278, 35&-357, 393, 398, 4 ° ° , 4 ° 2 Broad, Charlie Dunbar, 400 Bruno, Giordano, 196, 200-201, 232 Brunswick, Duke of, 236 Buber, Martin, 437-438 Büchner, Friedrich K a r l Christian, 357 Buddhism, 114, 322, 339 Budé (Budaeus), Guillaume, 277 BufTon, Georges, 330 Buridan, Jean, 183 Cabbala, 156, 232 Cajetan, Cardinal, 184 Calkins, Mary Whiton, 399 Calvinism, 193, 266, 277 Cambridge, 159-160 Campanella, Tommaso, 189, 193 Camus, Albert, 441 Cano, Melchor, 206, 238 Capella, Martianus, 126 Cappadocia, 111 caritas, see charity Carnap, Rudolf, 401 Carneades, 96 Carolingian Renaissance, 127, 140, 142 Carranza de Miranda, Bartolomé de, 206 Cartesianism, 192, 224-230, 232, 24g, 250, 261, 262-263, 413, 431; see also Descartes Carthage, 114 Cassiodorus, 127 Cassirer, Ernst, 359, 463 categorical imperative, see imperatives categories, 67-68, 70, 76, 287, 290¬ 292, 4 3 ° Cathari, 147, 151-152 catharsis, 80 Catherine the Great, 264 Catholic dogma, 206, 245; see also Christian dogma Cathrein, Victor, 174 causality (cause and effect), 259, 292, 293-294 causes, 72, 136, 169, 171, 203-204, 257 cave, myth of the, 48-51,56, 249 charity (caritas), 57, 58, 93, 116, 119, 137, 229 Charlemagne, 127, 140 Charles I I I , 270
49¿
Index
Charles I V , 270 Charles the Bald, 140 Charron, Pierre, 193 Chartres, 147-148, 174 Christian brotherhood, 93 Christian doctrine, influence of, 100, 137, l53> !54 Christian doctrine, influences upon, 53, 54, 55, 57, 98, 99- I O O > I o 8 , '47, 157 Christian dogma, 107, 108, m , 115, 129, 152, 167, 168-169, 178, 274¬ 276; see also Catholic dogma, Protestantism Christina, Queen of Sweden, 212 Christological controversy, 111 Chrypffs, Nicholas, see Nicholas of Cusa Chrysippus, 91 Cicero, 91, 97, 108, 114, 115, 120, 192 Cistercian Order, 151 citizen, Greek idea of, 35, 36, 37, 55-56, 83-85 city-state, 54-56, 83-85, 94 Clarke, Samuel, 253-254, 278 Clauberg, Johann, 267 Cleanthes of Assos, 90 Clement I V , Pope, 175 Clement of Alexandria, 108, m coexistence, 431, 449 cogito, cogitatio, 117, 121, 214, 215, 222, 232, 234, 255, 302, 413-414, 4 l 6 > 432, 447 Cohen, Hermann, 299, 359, 442, 463 Coimbra, 205 Collingwood, Robin George, 400 Columbus, Christopher, 183 communication between substances, 218, 233 communication of Ideas, 52, 53 Comte, Auguste, 269-270, 342, 348¬ 354, 355, 379 concept, doctrine of, 311, 320, 328, 329 Condillac, A b b é Étienne Bonnot de, 263-264, 330, 343 Condorcet, Antoine-Nicolas de, 264, 35° Congregation of the Oratory, see Oratory, Congregation of the consciousness, 408-411, 414, 440, 447¬ 449 Cooper, Anthony Ashley, see Shaftesbury Copernicus, Nicholas, 201, 202 . co-plication, 408, 410
Cordova, 154 corsi (cycles), 269 cosmology, 29 cosmopolitanism, 89, 90, 93-94 Council of Lyons, Second, 166 Council of Nicaea, First, n o Council of Trent, 194, 197, 205, 206, 238, 280 Council of Vienna, 172 Counter-Reformation, 113, 184, 194, 197, 206, 275, 278, 280 Courçon, Robert de, 152, 158 Cournot, Antoine Augustin, 356 Cousin, Victor, 345 Creation, the, 100, 106, m , 117, 129, 130, 131-133, 136, 139, 147, Ï5°> 162, 168, 169, 171, 315, 323 creationism, 118 Crockaert, Peter, 184 Cruz Hernández, Miguel, 157 Cudworth, Ralph, 253-254 Cumberland, Richard, 253 Cusanus, Nicolaus, see Nicholas of Cusa Cynics, 40, 82, 87, 89, 90, 92 Cynosarges, 89 Cyprian, St., n o Cyrenaics, 40, 87, 89-90, 94 daimónion, 38 Dante Alighieri, 155, 192 Darwin, Charles, 336, 357 Dasein, 427-435 David of Dinant, 152 death, 381, 386, 391, 433~434 definition, 39, 45 D e g é r a n d o , Joseph Marie, 344 deism, 141, 148, 252-254, 262, 278 Deity, see God deloûn, 429 Demiurge, 54 democracy, 35, 36, 84-85, 266 Democritus, 33-34, 95 Denys the Carthusian, 183, 190 Descartes, R e n é , 2, 117, 121, 145, 160, I 97, 200, 203, 208, 210-223, 232, 234, 238, 239, 240, 241, 244, 2 5 ° , 273, 274, 277, 278, 279, 283, 285, 286, 293, 302, 310, 346, 366, 411, 446; see also Cartesianism Destutt de Tracy, Count Antoine Louis Claude, 264, 344 determinism, 92, 234, 251, 282 Dewey, John, 3 9 Í Diadochi, 85
Index
dialectic, 24, 43, 288, 320-323, 337 didnoia, 82 diaphonia ton doxon, 96 Diderot, Denis, 263 Diez del Corral, Luis, 443 dikaiosyne, 55 dilectio, 57, 144 Dilthey, Wilhelm, 3, 265, 300, 358, 371, 378-384, 432 Diogenes of Sinope, 89 Dion, 42 Dionysius, 42 Dionysius the Areopagite, see PseudoDionysius Dionysus, 16, 54, 362-363 divine law, see law divine will, see will of God dogmatism, 246, 286, 293, 305 Dominic, St. (Domingo de G u z m ä n ) , 151, 160, 206 Dominicans, 151, 159, 160, 164, 166, 173, 181, 200, 206 Donoso Cortes, Juan, 347 double truth, doctrine of, 155, 174, 179, 183, 201 doxa, 22, 23, 37, 50, 96 dualism, 147, 151, 240, 387 Duns Scotus, John, 135-136, 138, 145, 160, 163, 178-179, 2 ° 7 , 245, 247 Dürkheim, Emile, 355 dynamis, 68 dynamism, 221, 238-239, 311 Dyroff, A . , 174 Eastern Church, 121, 276 Eckhart, Meister, 137, 150, 160, 181¬ 182, 195, 197, 199, 277 eclecticism, 97, 108, 344, 345 Ecphantus, 18 ecstasy, 99, 162 Edict of Nantes, 277 education, 55-56, 266 ego, 117, 121, 215, 217-219, 222-223, 258-259, 286, 294, 295, 301, 302, 304, 308-312, 314, 339, 345, 410, 413-415, 447-449 Ehrenfels, Christian von, 418, 419 eidetic reduction, 410-411 eidola, 34, g5 eidos, 32, 46, 57, 70, 411 etnai, 302 Einstein, Albert, 202 Eleatic school, 19-25, 37, 38, 77, 168, 454, 457
493 elements, 30, 31, 92 Elizabeth, Princess Palatine, 212, 213 emanation, 99, too, 109, 111, 141, 152 Emerson. R a l p h Waldo, 393 Empedocles, 29-31, 32 empeiria, 63 empiricism, 141, 159, 204, 209, 244, 247-283, 372-374, 377 encyclopedias, 126, 127, 158, 263 Encyclopedists, 258, 263, 265, 266, 280-281 ene'rgeia, 65, 68, 69 Engels, Friedrich, 336, 337 England, see British Isles English revolution, second, 252, 254, 256 Enlightenment, 141, 248, 253, 254, 258, 261-271, 272, 276, 331; see also Aufklärung ens (ab alio, a se, etc.), 131, 132, 137, 170, 179, 209, 242, 302-303, 421 entelechy, 6g, 78 entelékheia, 68 Entity, 20-28, 30, 32, 33, 37, 38, 44, 47, 48, 52, 53, 63-67, 70, 71, 73-74, 78, 82, 132, 138, 141, 150, 168, 170, 171, 293 Entschlossenheit, 434 eón, see ón epagogé, 76 Epictetus, gi Epicureanism, 2, 40, 90, 94-96, 115 Epicurus, 88, 94~95 epistéme, 63, 64 epistemology, see knowledge epokhé, 96, 409-410, 412, 413, 416, 448 Erasmus of Rotterdam, 194-195, 277 ernstes, 57 érgon, 65 Erigena, J o h n Scotus, 140-142, 394 éros, 48, 57 Erschlossenheit, 431, 432 essence, 17, 39, 40, 45, 74, 77, 328, 374, 377, 4 ° 7 , 4 ° 9 , 4 I O " 4 1 1 , 4 1 2 , 4 ' 3 , 423 estheticism, 254 esthetics, 80, 267-268, 288 Estienne, Henri (Stephanus), 193 eternal return, g2, 363 eternity of the world, 155, 162, 174, 183 ethics, 39-40, 54-56, 80-82, 86, 93, iog, 118, i19, 168, 172-173, 234¬ 235, 255-256, 287, 293-296, 309, 310, 326, 335,340,375-377, 457-45 8
494
Index
Eucharist, 129, 168 Eucken, Rudolf Christoph, 422 Euclid, 17, 101 eudaimonia, 35, 80, 89 Eugene of Savoy, Prince, 237 Europe, development of, 126, 140-141, 143,' 146 Euthydemus, 37 evil, 109, 175, 244-246, 280 evolution, biological, 314, 315, 357 evolutionism, 356-357 existentialism, 343, 384, 423, 428, 435¬ 441 existentials, 430 experience, 175, 260, 288, 289, 290, 292, 3 ° 4 , 373, 4 ° 5 , 4°9> 4'3 extension and thought, 221, 232, 233, 238, 239, 241, 286 Eyck, van, Hubert (Huybrecht) and Jan, 190 fact, 243, 344 faith, 116, 130, 137, 138, 144-146, 162 Faraday, Michael, 330 Fates, 93 Fathers of the Church, see Patristic thought Fechner, Gustav Theodor, 358 Feijoo, Benito J e r ó n i m o , 270 Fénelon, François de Salignac de la Mothe-, 229-230 Ferdinand I I of Aragon (the Catholic), 191, 273 Ferdinand V I , 270 Ferdinand V I I , 270 Ferrater Mora, J o s é (Josep), 443, 467¬ 468 fetishism, 349 feudalism, 279 Feuerbach, Ludwig Andreas, 336 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 299, 307-312, 3i3>3i4 Ficino, Marsilio, 192 Filmer, Sir Robert, 252, 256 Florence, 191, 192 Fonseca, Petrus de, 206 Fontenelle, Bernard le Bovier de, 224, 282 Forbes, Charles, see Montalembert, Comte de form, 70-72, 135, 172, 386 Fouillée, Alfred, 356 Foulques, Guy, 175 founding, see co-plication
Fourier, François Marie Charles, 346 France, 140, 141, 143, 147, 151, 183, 189, 193-194. 211, 224-230, 237, 250, 260, 262-267, 275, 277, 279, 355-356 Francis of Assisi, St., 160, 190 Franciscans, 135, 159, 160, 161, 163, 173, 174. 175, '77, '78, 180, 181, 190 Franck, Sebastian, 195 Francke, August Hermann, 268 Frederick I I (the Great), 264, 267 Frederick V , 211 freedom, 18, 252, 308, 314, 315, 316, 327. 328, 433, 457-458; see also free will, determinism freedom of religious interpretation, 274-275 free will, 84, 92, 119, 234-235, 245¬ 246, 251, 255-256, 293-294, 296, 306 Freiheit zum Tode, 434 French Revolution, 222, 262, 267, 270, 276, 279, 280-281, 346 Friars Minor, see Franciscans Fröbes, J . , 174 Fronde, the, 279 Fulbert of Chartres, 147 Fulda, 127 Galileo Galilei, 136, 160, 202, 203, 204, 250» 277, 278 Gallican Church, 277-278 Galvani, Luigi, 330 Gaos, J o s é , 443, 466-467 G a r c í a Morente, Manuel, see Morente, Manuel Garcia Garagorri, Paulino, 443 Gassendi, Pierre, 203, 212 Gaunilo, 144, 145 Gautier of Mortagne, see Walter of Mortagne generationism, 118 Genesis, 105, 137, 164 génesis, 12 genus and species, 53, 57, 70, 73, 133, 134. '35, '42, '47, 148, 170, '72, 406, 427 Gerard of Cremona, 158 Gerbert of Aurillac (Pope Sylvester I I ) , 142-143 Germanic invasions, tribes, see barbarians German school of history, 331, 332 Germany, 141, 183, 195, 267-268, 283, 284-340, 357-359
Index
Gerson, Jean, 183, 190 Geulincx, Arnold, 225 Geworfenheit, 431, 434 gignesthai, 322 Gilbert de la Porrée (Gilbert Porre¬ tanus), 147 Gilson, Étienne, 174, 183, 402 Gioberti, Vincenzo, 226, 366-367 gnosis, 109, n i Gnosticism, 109-110, n i , 114 gnôthi seautôn, 39, 416 God, ancient ideas of, 53, 64, 65, 66, 69, 71, 72-73, 83, 92, 93, 99, 100, 168 God, Christian and subsequent ideas of, 106, 116-117, 119, 121, 131, 132, 133, 135, ! 3 7 , !38, 139, i 4 I - I 4 2 , : 5 2 , 157-158, 161, 163-164, 169¬ 170, 172-173, 180, 181, 197-199, 201,
209,
2I6-22I,
226,
229,
232¬
234, 235, 241-242, 245-246, 257, a l 3 ° 3 , 323, 332, 369, 465; *° ontological argument God, existence of, 144, 150, 168, 169, 170, 216-218, 227, 234, 292, 377; see also ontological argument God, loss of, 180, 181, 246, 280, 281¬ 283 Gôdel, K u r t , 401 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 211,331 Gomez Pereira, ig4 Good, the, 52-53, 54, 57, 74, 80-81, 99, 421 Gorgias, 37-38 grace, 161, 178, 192, 280 Graciân, Baltasar, 339 Granell, Manuel, 443 Gratry, Father, 145, 358, 368-370 great year, 92 Gregory of Nazianzus, St., m Gregory of Nyssa, St., i n Gregory I X , Pope, 158 Gregory X , Pope, 166 Grosseteste, Robert, 158, 174 Grotius, Hugo, 206, 208, 278 Guizot, François, 275, 346 Gundisalvus, Dominicus (Gundissalinus), 158, 176 Guyau, Marie Jean, 356 Guyon, Jeanne Marie, 229 gymnasia, 49 Haeckel, Ernst Heinrich, 357 Halevy, Judah, 156 Halle, 267
49J
Hanover, 236, 237 happiness, 81, 89, 92 Hardenberg, Friedrich von, see Novalis harmony, pre-established, 240-241 Hartmann, Eduard von, 358 Hartmann, Nicolai, 418, 423-424 Hazard, Paul, 262, 282 Hebrew philosophy, see Jewish philosophy hedoné, 80 Hegel, Georg, 115, 145, 198, 199, 229, 275, 296, 299, 305, 313, 314, 315, 3 ' ° , 317-329, 332, 336, 337, 357, 372, 461 Heidegger, Martin, 48, 298, 300, 384, 402, 403, 404, 406, 425-436, 439, 464, 467 heimarme'ne, g2 Heine, Heinrich, 331 Héloïse, 148 Helvétius, Claude-Adrien, 264 hén, 26 Hendel, Charles W . , 400 henizein, 20 Henry V I I I , 194 Heraclitus, 27-29, 32, 92, 322, 363, 454 Herbart, Johann Friedrich, 334-335 Herbert of Cherbury, Edward, 253 Hercules, 268 Herder, Johann Gottfried von, 268, 331, 333 heresy, 107, 109-110, m , 112, 113, 147, 151-152 hermeneutics, 381, 383, 384, 429 Hertling, Georg von, 174 H e r v â s y Panduro, Lorenzo, 270 Hesiod, 12, 83 he'xis, 65 Hippasus of Metapontum, 17 Hippias, 37 historical Pyrrhonism, 213 historicism, 377, 380-384, 412 history, 5-6, 80, 92, 121, 126, 180, 189, 265, 268-270, 272-273, 283, 326¬ 327, 331-332, 349-350, 453-454, 458-461 history of philosophy, 4—5, 175, 185, 3i8, 329, 382 Hobbes, Thomas, 189, 212, 232, 250¬ 252, 253, 256 Hocking, William Ernest, 399 Hohenheim, Theophrastus von, see Paracelsus, Philippus Aureolus Holbach, Paul-Henri, 263, 264
496
Index
Hölderlin, Friedrich, 313, 317, 331 Holkot, Robert, 182 Holland, see Netherlands Holy Roman Empire, 180, 189 Homer, 268 homoiomereiai, 31-32, 46 Hugh of St. Victor, 149-150 humanism, 184, 190, 191, 192-195, 200, 277, 398 Humboldt, Alexander, 331 Humboldt, Wilhelm, 331 Hume, David, 255, 258-259, 284, 286, 404 Husserl, Edmund, 3, 48, 300, 366, 374, 375, 384, 4 3 - 4 i 7 , 422, 425> 439, 440, 447-448, 467 Hutcheson, Francis, 278 Huygens, Christian, 203 Hyginus, 432 hyle, 70, 409 hylomorphic, 70 hylozoism, 14 hypokeimenon, 69 0
Iamblichus, 100-101 Ibn Bajja, see Avempace Ibn Gabirol, see Avicebron Ibn Khaldun, 157 Ibn Rushd, see Averroës Ibn Sina, see Avicenna I b n Tufail, 155 Ibn Zaddik, 156 idia, 46, 57 ideal being and objects, 404-406, 407 idealism, 121, 200, 208, 210-246, 247, 257, 259, 268, 283, 284-340, 342, 365, 372, 3 8 3, 404, 4 ° 9 , 4 I O - 4 " , 413, 432, 446-449 ideas, 255, 257, 258, 259, 286, 302 Ideas, doctrine of, 39, 43-48, 4g, 50, 5!-53, 54, 57, 7 ° , 7 1 , 79, 89, 99, 117, ! 3 6 , '37, '47, 181, 198, 240, 293, 297, 324, 328 identity, 314, 315, 322, 323, 324, 325 ideologists, 343 idéologues, 264 idols, 249 Ignatius of Loyola, St., 206 Immaculate Conception, 178, 245 immanence, 152, 286 immortality, 18, 35, 54, 79, 155, 168, 172,183,235,391 imperatives (categorical, logical, moral), 40, 293-294, 295, 308, 375
impletion, 407 implication, 408 independence, see self-sufficiency In-der-Welt-sein, 430 individuation, 134-135, 136, 167, 172, 208, 406 inductive method, 39, 204-205, 248¬ 250 infinite, the, 198, 199-200, 201, 220 innatism, 243-244, 255 inner man, 116, 117, 121, 161 Innocent I I I , Pope, 159 Inquisition, 160, 200, 202, 225, 275 instinct, 388 instrumentalism, 397 integrationism, 468 intellectual life, 276-279, 281 intentionality, 154, 310, 373-374, 377, 384, 405, 407, 409, 413-415, 433, 448 interiority, 121, 325 intuition, 289-290, 311-312, 315, 322, 367, 377, 388-389, 407, 411, 423 Ionia, 11,13 Ireland, see British Isles Irenaeus, St., i i o - i n irenic negotiations, 229 irrationalism, 389, 391, 396, 397, 452 Isabella I (the Catholic), 273 Isidore of Seville, St., 126, 127 Italic school, 15 Italy, 126, 141, 174, 192-193, 273 Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich, 330, 333 James I , 207 James I I , 254 James, William, 391, 394, 395, 396-397 Jansen, Cornells (Jansenius), 227-228 Jansenists, 227-228, 238 Jansenius, see Jansen, Cornells J â s c h e , Gottlob Benjamin, 285 Jaspers, K a r l , 435, 436-437 Jean of Jandun, 183 Jena, 307, 313 Jesuits, 197, 206, 207, 211, 212, 228, 270 Jewish philosophy, 147, 152, 153, 155¬ 157, 158, 165, 232, 437 Joachim of Flora, 152 Jobit, Pierre, 336 Johannes Hispanus, 158 John of the Cross, St., 194 John of Fidanza, see Bonaventure, St. John of Salisbury, 147, 148
Index
John. X X I , Pope, see Petrus Hispanus John X X I I , Pope, 180 Jouffroy, Théodore, 345 John, St., 57, 75, 107, 137, 138, 227 Jovellanos, Gaspar Melchor de, 271 Judaeo-Christian thought, 100, 153 judgment, analytic and synthetic, 204, 205, 243, 288-292, 293, 376, 407-408 Julian the Apostate, 1 o 1 justice, 54-55, 5 ° Justinian, 42, 97 Justin Martyr, St., 110 kalbs k'agathos, 35 Kant, Immanuel, 3, 145, 203, 243, 255, 259, 267, 283, 284-306, 307, 308-311, 325, 329, 358, 383, 387, 408,411,423,437 Kantianism, see neo-Kantianism katà symbebekôs, 67 katà symplokén, 76 katdphasis, 76 katK auto, 67 kathêkon, 93 katôrthoma, 93 Kempis, Thomas à, see Thomas à Kempis kenôn, 78 Kepler, Johann, 202 khrémata, 37 khronos, 78 Kierkegaard, Soren, 300, 361, 391, 3g6, 43!, 436 Kilwardby, Robert, 173 kinesis, 12, 64 knowledge, 1-3, 33-34, 39, 40, 45, 47¬ 48, 5 1 , 56-58, 62-63, 65, 72, 76-77, 87, 88, 91, 116, 136, 139, 161-162, 168-169, ' 7 ° , 173, 175, 198, 200, 203-204, 235, 255, 259, 286-296, 300-302, 312, 319-320, 350, 454-455 koinai énnoiai, 91 koinonia, 52, 53, 82 kôme, 83 Koran, 154, 155 kosmopolites, 89 Krause, K a r l , 330, 335, 336 Krebs, Nicholas, see Nicholas of Cusa Lacordaire, Jean Baptiste Henri, 346 Lactantius, 110 L a i n Entralgo, Pedro, 443 Lamarck, Jean Baptiste Pierre, 330,356 Lamennais, Félicité Robert de, 346 L a Mettrie, Julien de, 264
497
Lange, Friedrich Albert, 379 Langer, Suzanne K . , 401 language, 83 Laromiguière, Pierre, 344 Lassalle, Ferdinand, 336, 337 Latin Averroism, see Averroism Lavelle, Louis, 439 law, 92, 118-119, 138, 173, 251, 256, 265, 269, 278 Leclerc, Jean, 267 légein, 75 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 145, 160, 177, '79, '97, 9 9 , 200, 201, 203, 208, 221, 229, 236-246, 254, 257, 267, 277, 278, 283, 289, 309, 334, 346, 366, 372, 404, 415, 462 Leo X I I I , Pope, 173 Leonhardi, Hermann K a r l , 335 Le Senne, R e n é , 439 Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, 268 Leucippus, 33 Lévy-Bruhl, Lucien, 355 Lewis, Clarence Irving, 401 Liebmann, Otto, 359 linguistic analysis, 400, 401 Lissarrague, Salvador, 443 Littré, Maximilien Paul Émile, 355 Llull, R a m ó n , see Lullus, Raimundus Locke, John, 237, 244, 252, 254-256, 284, 373 logic, 61, 74-77, 244, 249, 320-323, 405 logical positivism, 401 logos, 10, 30, 74, 75-76, 83, 136, 137, 138, 178, 320, 429, 453 logos apophantikós, 76 logos spermatikós, 92 Lombard, Peter, see Peter Lombard López-Morillas, Juan, 336 Lotze, Rudolf Hermann, 358, 418 Louis X I , 191 love, 30, 48, 56-58, 116, 119, 179, 235, J
376-377, 4 i 8 Lovejoy, Arthur O . , 400 Lucretius, 29, 95 Ludwig of Bavaria, Emperor, 180 Lukács, Gyôrgy, 338 Lukasiewicz, Jan, 401 Lullus (Lull, Lully), Raimundus (Raymond), 176-177, 201, 244 Luther, Martin, 118, 182, 184, 195,274 Lyceum, 60, 61, 87 Macedonia, 60, 85 Mach, Ernst, 358
498
Index
Machiavelli, Niccolô, 193, 273 Madrid; School of Madrid, 443, 462¬ 468 maieutiké, 38 Maimonides, Moses (Moses ben M a i m ó n ) , 156-157, 232 Maine de Biran, 344-345, 432 Maistre, Comte Joseph de, 344, 346 Malebranche, Nicolas de, 221, 224¬ 227, 233, 241, 257, 367, 368 Manes, 114 mania, 17 Manichaeism, i n , 114 Maravall, J o s é A . , 443 Marburg school, 359 Marcel, Gabriel, 398, 435, 436, 437, 438-439 Marcus Aurelius, see Antoninus, Marcus Aurelius Maréchal, Father, 174 M a r í a s , J u l i á n , 443 Maritain, Jacques, 174, 402, 435 Martin, Peter, 166 Martinez, Martin, 270 Marty, Anton, 404 Marx, K a r l , 336, 337-338 Marxism, 338, 439, 441 materialism, 33, 92, 99, 152, 263-264, 337. 338, 357 mathematics, 13, 17-19, 101, 136, 139, 159, 160, 161, 175, 181, 190, 198, 202, 203, 221, 236, 244, 250, 290; see also physics, natural sciences mathematikoi, 16 matter, 70-72, 135, 147, 154, 155, 172, 179. 257, 264, 292, 388, 409, 421 Matthew of Aquasparta, 162 Maurice of Nassau, 211 Maurice of Spain (Mauritius Hispanus), •52 Maurus, Rabanus, 127 Mausbach, J , , 120 Maximilian of Bavaria, 211 Mazarin, Jules, 279 Mazdaism, 114 meanings, 374, 406-407 Medici, Cosimo de', 192 Medina Sidonia, Duke of, 279 Meinong, Alexius, 404, 418, 419 Melanchthon, Philip, 195 Melissus, 19, 25 Mendelssohn, Moses, 333 Menéndez y Pelayo, Marcelino, 260 Mercier, Cardinal, 174
Merinero, Juan de, 184 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 441 mesóles, 82 metaphysical optimism, 244—245 metaphysics, 62, 64-74, 86, 98, 116, 129, 131, 133, 139, 142, 145, 170¬ 172, 179. '82, 192, 196, 199-200, 205, 207-209, 210, 215, 223, 232¬ 234, 238-242, 257, 267, 283, 286¬ 298, 300, 305-306, 308-311, 315, 344-345, 352, 365-370, 377. 4 ° 6 , 411, 416, 423; see also being, Entity metaxy, 56, 57 metempsychosis, see transmigration méthexis, 52, 71 métron, 82 Miletus (Milesian school), 11-15, 17 Mill, John Stuart, 253, 356 modes of being, 67-69, 70, 72, 74, 168, 323. 428, 430, 432 Mohammed, 153 Moleschott, Jacob, 357 Molina, Luis de (Molinism), 206, 238, 245 Molinos, Miguel de, 229 Mommsen, Theodor, 331 monads, theory of, 200, 201, 239-243, 245, 334, 4 I 4 " 4 I 6 monarchy, 84-85, 173, 193, 252, 256, 265, 269, 273, 279, 281 monis, 239 Monica, St., 113, 114, 115 monism, 152, 241 monotheism, 19, 32, 151, 349 Montaigne, Michel de, 176, 193 Montalembert, Comte de, 346 Montesquieu, Baron (Charles de Secondat), 263, 264, 265 Moore, George Edward, 400 Mora, J o s é Ferrater, see Ferrater Mora, José morality, 294-296, 305-306, 326, 363¬ 364 Morcillo, Sebastián Fox, 194 More, Thomas, 194, 277 Morente, Manuel Garcia, 443, 462¬ 463, 466 morphé, 46, 70, 409 Morris, Charles W . , 401 Moses ben M a i m ó n , see Maimonides, Moses Moslem philosophy, see Arabic philosophy
Index
motion, io, 12-13, 22, 23, 24-25, 26¬ 33, 47, 64, 69, 70, 71-72, 77, 78, I 0 5 , 131, 136, 142, 155, 171, 203-204, 239, 240, 323, 361, 388, 389 Mounier, Emmanuel, 439 movement of being, 320, 321, 322 multiplicity, 10, 12, 13, 22, 25, 26, 29, 30-31, 7 1 , 99, 240 mysticism, 100, 121, 141, 147, 149, 150, 151, 161-162, 181-182, 183-184, 189-190, 195, 197, 274 Natorp, Paul, 299, 359, 463 natural law, see law natural morality and religion, see deism natural sciences, 141, 160, 165, 174, 175, 181, 183, 193, 195, 201-205, 222, 278, 314-315, 330, 35 r -353, 388, 412-413; see also physics, mathematics naturalism, 250, 252, 265, 266, 278, 281, 412 nature, 10, 12, 64, 66, 70, 72, 77-78, 84, 89, 92, 136, 139, 141-142, 161, 178, 190, 192, 201-205, 233, 234, 240, 277-278, 280, 283, 293-294, 314-315, 323-324, 383 neikos, 30 neo-Kantianism, 299—300, 311, 339, 358-359, 379, 4 ° 4 , 446, 463 Neoplatonism, 53, 87, 98-101, 108, 109, i n , 132, 141, 147, 152, 153, 154, 156; see also Platonic tradition neo-Pythagoreanism, 16, 17 neo-Thomism, see Thomism Nero, 91 Nestorianism, i n Netherlands, 183, 194-195, 212, 278 Neurath, Otto, 401 Newton, Isaac, 160, 203, 205, 236, 284 Nicholas of Gusa (Nicolaus Cusanus, Nicholas Krebs), 182, 190, 195, 196, 197-200, 201 Nicole, Pierre, 228 Nicomachus (father of Aristotle), 60 Nicomachus (son of Aristotle), 60, 80 Niebuhr, Barthold Georg, 331 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 92, 300, 362-364, 386, 396 nihility, see nothingness nirvana, 340 nöema, 409 no'esis, 65, 73, 409 ndesis noeseos, 83
499 nominalism, 132, 133, 134, ^ - H S , 138, 139, H 3 , !59, 161, 178, 180, 182, 183, 190, 196, 201, 250, 257, 259 nômos, 23, 82, 93 nothingness, 105-106, i n , 117, 131, 137, 147. l 8 i , 315, 321-323, 328, 390, 431 nous, 20-23, 28, 31, 32, 36, 48, 50, 63, 77, 79, 82, 99, 373 nous poietiko's, 79 Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg), 313, 331 6
Occam, see William of Occam Occamism, 182-183, 184, 203, 232, 249 occasionalism, 225-227, 241 Odon of Tournai, 143 Ogden, G. K . , 401 oikia, 83 Olivi, Petrus Johannis (Pierre Olieu), 163 O l l é - L a p r u n e , Léon, 389 omnipotence, 138 ön (eon), 20-24, 26, 28, 33, 37, 47, 64, 67, 74, 302, 320; see also Entity One, the, 53, 74, 82, 99, 312 onoma, 76 ontological argument, 145-146, 162, 171, 179, 217, 221, 242, 283, 293, 304-305, 329, 367; see also God, existence of ontology, 20, 21, 23-24, 50, 66, 86, 130, 132, 220, 240, 260, 323, 416, 428, 429; see also being, Entity, metaphysics opinion, see doxa optimism, 280, 281 Oratory, Congregation of the, 224, 225, 368 Oresmus, Nicholas, 183 ôrganon, 249 Origen, 111 original sin, n o , 118, 134, 143, 266, 280 Orphic mysteries, 16, 17, 54 Ors, Eugenio (Eugeni) d', 467 Ortega y Gasset, José, 2, 3, 9, 40, 52, 120, 204, 211, 215, 223, 256, 265, 274, 277, 281, 290, 297, 298, 300, 302, 309, 321, 327, 335, 359, 383, 384, 389, 402, 408, 417, 421, 440, 442-462, 463, 464, 466, 467, 468
Index
Ostwald, Wilhelm, 357 ousia, 64, 69, 70, 240, 324 Oxford, 159, 173, 174, 250
Philolaus of Crotón, 18 philosophia, 17, 65 philosophy of action, see action philosophy of caution, 213 paganism, 107, 108, 112, 120 philosophy of history, 115, 116, 119, paideia, 37 327 Painted Portico, go philosophy of life, 378-392, 435 pân, 323 philosophy, meaning of, 1-6, 56-58, Panaetius of Rhodes, 91 169, 175 panentheism, 335 philosophy, origin of, 3-4, 9-13, 169 panspermia, 31 Philostratus, 36 pantheism, 99, 100, 142, 147, 152, 181, phoné, 83 195, '99, 201, 2 3 3 , 3>5> 316, 322¬ phoné semantiké, 76, 407 323, 422 phorá, 12, 33 Paracelsus, Philippus Aureolus (Theophós, 429 phrastus von Hohenheim), 195 phrónesis, 54, 55 Paris, 136, 147, 149, 152, 158, 159, 160, phthisis, 12 164, 166, 173, 175, 205, 277, 347, phthorá, 12 Parmenides, 19-25, 26-33, 37, 38, 44, physics, 12, 24, 72, 77-78, 92, 136, 139, 45, 48, 5 ° , 52, 7', 168, 210, 286, 322 159, 160, 161, 168, 175, 183, 196, participation, see mêthexis 201-205, 239, 284; see also natural Pascal, Blaise, 228-229 sciences, mathematics Patricius, 113 physiológoi, 12 Patristic thought, 100, 107-112, 118, physis, 12, 14, 28, 33, 35, 70, 77, 78, 127, 128, 12g, 143, 144, 167, 228 92, 192, 323, 324 Paul, St., 57, 107, 324, 367, 36g Pico della M i r á n d o l a , 192 Peckham, John, 163, 173 Pietism, 268, 284, 330 Peirce, Charles Sanders, 394-396 Piquer, Andrés, 270 Pelagianism, i n pístis, I I I perception, 242-243, 255, 257, 258¬ Planck, Max, 202 259, 375, 4 ° 9 - 4 ! ° > 421; see also Plato, 20, 26, 32, 36, 37, 38, 40-41, 42¬ sensory perception 58, 7 1 , 73, 88, 89, gg, 101, 108, i n , Perez y Lopez, Antonio Xavier, 270 116, 1 g 1, 240, 24g, 2g7, 323-324,411 Pericles, 31 Platonic Academy, 17, 42, 60, 87, g i , Peripatetics, 60 g7; see also Academicians Perry, Ralph Barton, 397 Platonic Academy of Florence, see personalism; 398-399, 439 Florence perspective, 32, 46 Platonic tradition, 147, 159, 160, 164, perspectivism, 450 '72, 173, 174, 192, 193, 257, 406; Peter of Ibernia, 166 see also Neoplatonism Peter Lombard, 128, 151, 161 Plotinus, 98-100, 115 Petrarch, 190, 192 pluralism, 239 Petrus Hispanus (Pope John X X I ) , 176 Plutarch, 97 phainômenon, 42g pneúma, 324 phantasia kataleptiké, 91 poiesis, 61, 65, 81 phenomenological reduction, see epokhé polis, 55, 83, 84, 94 phenomenology, 244, 300, 343, 372, politeia, 55, 85 polites, 35 374, 383, 384, 402, 4 ° 3 - 4 I 7 , 423, politics and society, 35, 36, 37, 43, 54¬ 425, 428-429, 447-448 56, 82-85, 119, 173, 189, 193, 251¬ philia, 30, 57, 58 252, 256, 265, 266-267, 272-274, Philip I I , 273 Philip I V , 27g 276-281, 326, 337-338, 350-351, Philip of Macedonia, 60 459-461 Philo of Alexandria, 97, 10g, 111 Polygnotus, 90
Index
polytheism, 349 Pomponazzi, Pietro, 192 Porphyry, 98, 100, 115, 126 Porretanus, Gilbert, see Gilbert de la Porrée Port-Royal, 228, 238, 345 Portugal, 193, 205, 206 Posidonius, 91 positivism, 300, 340, 342-343, 346, 348¬ 359, 365, 372, 379, 383, 413 potentiality, 10, 68-69, 7 1 , 78, 156 practical reason, 293-296, 305, 306, 308 prdgmata, 23 pragmaticism, 397 pragmatism, 248, 389, 393-398 praxis, 61, 65, 82, 138, 287, 296 Preachers, Order of, see Dominicans pre-Socratics, 11-34, 84 pre-tension, 457 prime mover, 72-73, 78, 155, 168 Proclus, 101 Prodicus, 37 Protagoras, 31, 37 prête ousia, 134, 302 Protestantism, 118, 184, 195, 209, 274¬ 276, 280 Proudhon, Pierre Joseph, 336, 346 providence, 92, 157 Pseudo-Dionysius (Dionysius the Areopagite), 101, 141 pseûdos, 68 psychologism, 404-405, 412, 433 psychology, 54, 235, 255, 325, 373~375, 381 psykhé, 78 ptöseis toû éntos, 67 pure reason, 287, 288 pyr tekhnikon, 92 Pyrrho, 96 Pythagoras, 15-16 Pythagoreanism, 16-17, 54 quadrivium, 126, 127, 150, 166 quietism, 229 Quine, Willard van O . , 401 Raimundo, 158 Raimundo de Sabunde (Sabiuda, Raymond Sebond), 176 R a m é e , Pierre de la (Petrus Ramus), 193, 277 Ranke, Leopold von, 331 ratio, 118, 198, 453
JO I rationalism, 189, 222-223, 231, 237— 238, 240, 242, 246, 247, 250, 261, 268, 273-274, 277, 280, 281, 284, 285-286, 304, 365, 452 R a u h , Frédéric, 462 Ravaisson-Mollien, Jean Gaspard Félix, 356, 358 real duration, see time realism, 133-134, 142, 143, 147, 148, 172, 222, 286, 304, 334, 432, 446-447 reality, 48-51, 133, 135, 218, 222-223, 310-311, 342, 432, 447, 448, 450-452 real predicate, 23, 293, 303, 304 reason, 12, 47, 50, 92, 136-139, 141, 144-146, 162, 169, 175, 189, 215, 219-220, 222-223, 226, 228-229, 235, 243, 259, 263, 281, 287-296, 383-384, 38g, 391 ; see also practical reason, pure reason, vital reason R e c a s é n s Siches, Luis, 443 Reformation, 113, 182, 190, 193, 195, 197, 267, 274-276, 277, 280, 281 regalism, 279 Reginald of Piperno, 166 Reichenbach, Hans, 401 Reid, Thomas, 259-260, 345 reincarnation, see transmigration Reinhardt, K a r l , 20 relativism, 350, 354, 405 Renaissance, 91-92, 148, 161, 174, 179, 181, 183, 184, 189-209, 238, 249, 273, 280, 281 Renaissance man, 139, 192, 195, 277 Renan, Ernest, 355, 379 Renouvier, Charles Bernard, 356 Reuchlin, Johann, 195 revelation, 117, 132, 138, 141, 162, 168-169, 171 rhéma, 76 Ricardus de Mediavilla (Richard of Middleton), 163, 173 Richard of St. Victor, 150 Richards, I . A., 401 Rickert, Heinrich, 359, 418 R ö d e r , K a r l David August, 335 Rodriguez Huéscar, Antonio, 443 Roland of Cremona, 160 R o m a n Empire, 94, 112, 119, 125, 327 Romanticism, 141, 330, 331 Rome, 91, 143, 191, 205 roots, the four, see elements Roscellinus of Compiègne, 134, 143, 148, 149 Rosmini-Serbati, Antonio, 226,366-367
JOZ
Index
Ross, W . D., 60 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 363, 264, 265¬ 267, 268, 278, 279, 280 Rouvroy, Claude Henri de, see SaintSimon Royce, Josiah, 398 Royer-Collard, Pierre Paul, 260, 345 Russell, Bertrand, 399, 400, 401 Ruysbroeck, J a n van, 190 Ryle, Gilbert, 401 Sabiuda, see Raimundo de Sabunde Saint-Simon (Claude Henri de Rouvroy), 346, 348 Salamanca, 205, 206 S a l m e r ó n , Alfonso, 206 S á n c h e z , Francisco, 193 sanction, see authority Sanseverino, Gaetano, 174 Santayana, George, 39g Sanz del Río, J u l i á n , 335-336 S à o T o m é , J o ä o de, 206-207 Sarmiento, Martín, 270 Sartre, Jean-Paul, 426, 436, 439-441 Savigny, Friedrich K a r l von, 331 Scheeben, Mathias Josef, 333 Scheler, Max, 364, 404, 418, 422-423, 425 Schelling, Friedrich, 201, 299, 313— 3*6> 317, 322 Schiller, Ferdinand Canning Scott, 397-398 Schiller, Friedrich, 331, 394 Schlechta, K a r l , 362 Schlegel, August Wilhelm, 313, 331 Schlegel, Caroline, 313 Schlegel, Friedrich, 313, 331 Schleiermacher, Friedrich Daniel, 316, 328, 330, 332-333, 378 Schlick, Moritz, 401 Scholasticism, 53, 79, 100, 116, 121, 125-130, 131, 132, 133, 141, 142, *43, '44. 146, 147, 149. i5i> '53: I 5 4 » '57; '58, i59> 160, 161, 163¬ 174» I 7 7 - Ï 7 8 , 182, 184, 190, 191, '94. 196-197, '98, 204, 205-209, 227, 232, 238, 249, 270, 276-277, 3 ° 5 , 338, 346, 365-366, 372, 373, 374, 3 9 ° , 404, 464 schools, medieval, 127, 140, 142, 146¬ 147 Schopenhauer, Arthur, 330, 338-340, 362, 363, 386 science, see natural sciences
scientific method, 202, 204-205 scientific traditionalism, 175 Scotism, 163, 184, 232 Scotland, see British Isles Scottish School, 259—260, 345, 346 Scotus, John Duns, see Duns Scotus, John Scotus Erigena, John, see Erigena, John Scotus Sebond, Raymond, see Raimundo de Sabunde Secondât, Charles de, see Montesquieu, Baron self, 257, 258, 381, 383, 414 self-evidence, 215—216, 222, 229, 260, 375, 376-377, 4 ° 9 , 4 ' 3 self-existence, see aseity self-identity, see identity self-sufficiency (or independence), 61, 89, 92, 96, 220, 222, 240, 302-303, 328; see also autarchia Seneca, 80, 91, 108 sensationalism, 34, 91, 141, 247, 248, 258-259, 261, 263-264, 341-347, 373 sensory perception, 21, 30, 32, 33—34, 79, 9 i , 95, 1 5 ° , 198, 264, 292, 293; see also perception Shaftesbury, first earl of, 254 Shaftesbury, third earl of (Anthony Ashley Cooper), 254, 278 Shakespeare, William, 248 sharing, see méthexis Siger of Brabant, 174, 183 Simmel, Georg, 384—387 sin, 144, 246; see also original sin skepticism, g6-g7, 213, 248, 255, 25g, 405 skholé, 16 Snellius (Willebrord Snell), 203 socialism, 336-338 society, see politics and society Society of Jesus, see Jesuits sociology, 350-353, 355 Socrates, 37, 38-41, 43, 45, 46, 87, 8g, 340, 411 Socratic tradition, 40-41, 87, 88-90 sophia, 17, 36, 55, 57, 63, 65, 66, 76 Sophists, 31, 35-38, 43, 82, 87 sophon, 28-29 sophds, 17, 34, 86 sophrosyne, 54 Soto, Domingo de, 206 soul, 47-48, 54, 55, 57, 78-80, 91, 99,
Index
iog, n o , 116-118, 119, 142, 143, 162, 168, 170, 172, 181, 234, 242¬ 243, 251, 259, 325 space, 33, 289-290, 387-388, 415 Spain, 126, 142, 153, i54-i55> : 5 8 , 173, 176-177, 184, 193-194, 196¬ 197, 202, 205-209, 238, 260, 270¬ 27 1 , 273, 278, 279, 347, 442-443, 468 species, see genus and species Spencer, Herbert, 357, 379 Spener, Philipp Jakob, 268 Spengler, Oswald, 396 Speusippus, 60 Spinola, Cristobal Rojas de, 237, 278 Spinoza, Baruch de, 58, 157, 200, 221, 231-235, 238, 240, 277, 278, 374 spirit, 280, 314-315, 324-329 spiritualism, 257, 344, 345-347, 439 State, the, see politics and society Stendhal (Marie Henri Beyle), 279 Stephanus, see Estienne, Henri Stewart, Dugald, 259-260, 345 Stoa, 88, 90-91 stoä poiktte, go Stoicism, 2, 40, 84, 87, 88, 90-94, 95, 96, i n , 115, 191-192, 232, 235 Strauss, David, 333, 336 Sturm und Drang, 268, 330 S u ä r e z , Francisco, 197, 205, 206, 207— 209, 232, 238, 365, 444 subjectivism, 223, 325, 433, 436, 446 substance, 64, 65-66, 67, 68, 69-71, 92, 134, 168, 201, 203, 218-220, 226, 232, 233-234, 240, 258, 302, 454, 457, 465 substantial form, 172, 173 Sufism, 154 superman, 363 Suso, Heinrich, 190, 195 Sweden, 212 Sydenham, Thomas, 254 syllogismds, 76 syllogistic method, 24g Sylvester I I , Pope, see Gerbert of Aurillac symbols, 136, 13g, 181, 203 syncretism (Arabic), 153-155 sjinolon, 70 synthesis, see judgment, analytic and synthetic tabula rasa, 79, 255 Tacitus, 108
Taine, Hippolyte, 355, 379 Talmud, 232 Taparelli, Luigi, 174 Tarde, Gabriel, 355 Tarski, Alfred, 401 Tartaretus, Peter, 184 Tathandlung, 311 Tauler, Johannes, 190, 195 Teichmüller, Gustav, 358 tekhne, 57, 63, 92 tekhnites, 63 Telesio, Bernardino, 193 Ulos, 69, 73, 323 Tempier, Etienne, 173, 175 Teresa, St., 194 terminism; terms, 136, 143, 149 Tertullian, 108, n o , 119 tetractys, 18 Thales of Miletus, 13-14, 329 theism, 252, 315, 412 theodicy, 237, 244-246, 329 Theodoric (Ostrogothic king), 126, 127 Theodoric of Chartres, see Thierry of Chartres theogony, 12, 14 Theologia deutsch, 184, 195 theology, 53, 64, 65, 78, 92, 93, 99, 116, 129-130, 133, 138, 168—169, 171, 178, 180, 189-190, 206-209, 213-214, 227-230, 246, 332-333 theophany, 142, 19g Theophrastus, 27 theoretic life, 1, 2, 16, 31, 35, 65, 81, 87 theoria, 10, 61, 65, 73, 287, 296 theos, 65, 66, 73, 178, 323 theosis, 142 Thierry (Theodoric) of Chartres, 147 Thirty Years' War, 277 "thisness" (haecceitas), 136, 17g Thomas k Kempis, 190 Thomas, St., see Aquinas, St. Thomas Thomism, 163, 167, 168, 169, 170, 172, 173-174, 178, 184, 205, 207, 208, 227, 365; see also Neo-Thomism Thoreau, Henry David, 393 thought, 303-304, 311, 319, 322, 328, 388-389 thought and extension, see extension and thought Tiberghien, Guillaume, 335 Tieck, Ludwig, 313, 331 time, 14, 78, 28g-2go, 384, 385-386, 387-389, 4 ° 6 , 412, 414, 415, 427, 428, 42g, 434-435, 448
Index
Timon, 96 Toledo, 158, 176 Tongiorgi, S., 174 topos, 33, 78 topos hyperourdnios, 47 Torricelli, Evangelista, 203 Tournai, 143 traducianism, 110, 118 tragedy, 80 transcendency, 225, 259, 385-386 transcendental philosophy, 285-288, 292-293, 3 ° i - 3 ° 6 , 3 " , 4 i 3 - 4 5 , 466 transcendentalism, 393-394 transcendentals, 53, 73-74,82, 170, 421 transmigration (metempsychosis), 18, I
35, 99 transubstantiation, 129 Trendelenburg, Adolf, 358, 372 Trinitarian controversy, 111 Trinity, 117, 134, 149, 153, 161, 168 trivium, 126, 127, 150, 166 truth, 4, 5-6, 21, 39, 68, 75-76, 87, 88, 96, 137, 144, 169, 175, 177, 181, 198, 213, 215-216, 218, 243, 320, 321, 323, 326, 383, 397, 405, 432-433 T ü b i n g e n , 333 Turgot, Anne Robert Jacques, 263, 264, 356
virtue, 40, 54, 55, 82, 93 vital action, see action vital reason, 223, 300, 343, 384, 389, 442-462 vital time, see time vital values, see value theory Vitoria, Francisco de, 184, 206 Vives, Luis, 191, 194, 277 Vogt, K a r l , 257 void, 22, 33, 78, 100, 105 Volta, Alessandro, 330 Voltaire, François Arouet de, 262, 263, 264-265, 268, 281 voluntarism, 138, 178, 179, 180 vox (term), see terminism
Wadding, Luke, 184 Wagner, Richard, 362 Wahl, Jean, 435, 436, 439 Walter (Gautier) of Mortagne, 148 Warsaw Circle, 401 Weber, Ernst Heinrich, 358 Weber, Georg, 335 Weigel, Valentin, 195 Weltanschauung, 383, 412, 437 Whately, Richard, 394 Wheelwright, Philip E . , 400 Whitehead, Alfred North, 399-400 will, 119, 179, 235, 266, 295, 339-340; Ultramontanist movement, 346 see also free will Unamuno, Miguel de, 361, 390-392, will of God, i n , 117, 138, 171 William of Champeaux, 134, 148, 149 396, 4 7 William of Conches, 148 United States, 393-402 William de la Mare, 173 universals, 70, 133-136, 147-148, 149, William of Moerbeke, 158, 167 168, 171-172, 179, 180, 208, 250 William of Occam (Ockham), 135, universities, 147, 159—160 136, 138, 159, 160, 178, 179-181, U r b a n V , Pope, 158 utilitarianism, 356 182, 247, 277, 283; see also Occamism William of Orange, 256 William of Tocco, 166 Vaihinger, Hans, 358 Winckelmann, Johann Joachim, 267¬ Valdecasas, Alfonso G . , 443 268 V a l d é s , J u a n de, 193 Windelband, Wilhelm, 359, 418 V a l l a , Lorenzo, 191 Wisdom, John O . , 401 Vallès, Francisco, 194 value theory, 335, 364, 372, 375, 377, Witt, John de, 231 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 401 418-424 Wolff, Christian, 237, 267, 292 V a u x , Clotilde de, 348 world soul, 54, 99, 201 Vela, Fernando, 443 Wulf, Maurice de, 151 Venerable Bede, see Bede. St. Wundt, Wilhelm, 358, 379 Vico, Giambattista, 268-270, 327 Victorines, 149-152, 161 Vienna Circle, 401 Xenophanes, 19-20 Vilanova, Arnaldo, de, 176 Xenophon, 38, 40 Vinci, Leonardo da, 193 X i r a u , Joaquin, 467 6
Index Zambrano, Maria, 443 Z a r a g ü e t a , Juan, 464 Zaratas, Zarathustra, see Zoroaster zên, 83, 92 Zeno of Citium, 90 Zeno of Elea, 19, 24-25, 26
zoon politikon, 83 Zoroaster, 16, 114, 268 Zubiri, Xavier, 4, 20, 39, 57, 65, 72, 76, 106, 132, 137, 138-139, 181, 182, 204, 207, 318, 328, 329, 443, 463-466 Zwingli, Huldreich (Ulrich), 195