The Place of Law
The Amherst Series in Law, Jurisprudence, and Social Thought
Each work included in The Amherst Serie...
18 downloads
816 Views
18MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
The Place of Law
The Amherst Series in Law, Jurisprudence, and Social Thought
Each work included in The Amherst Series in Law, Jurisprudence,
and Social Thought explores a theme crucial to an understanding of
law as it confronts the changing social and intellectual currents of the
twenty-first century.
Works edited by Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns
The Fate of Law
Law's Violence
Law in Everyday Life
The Rhetoric of Law
Identities, Politics, and Rights
Legal Rights: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives
Justice and Injustice in Law and Legal Theory
Law in the Domains of Culture
Cultural Pluralism, Identity Politics, and the Law
History, Memory, and the Law
Human Rights: Concepts, Contests, Contingencies
Works edited by Austin Sarat, Lawerence Douglas,
and Martha Merrill Umphrey
Lives in the Law
Law's Madness
The Place of Law
The Place of Law
EDITED BY
Austin Sarat,
Lawrence Douglas,
AND
Martha Merrill Umphrey
The University of Michigan Press
Ann Arbor
First paperback edition 2006
Copyright © by the University of Michigan 2003
All rights reserved
Published in the United States of America by
The University of Michigan Press
Manufactured in the United States of America
O Printed on acid-free paper
2009 2008 2007 2006
5 4 3 2
No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system,
or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical,
or otherwise, without the written permission of the publisher.
A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
The place of law / edited by Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha
Merrill Umphrey.
p. cm.-
(Amherst series in law, jurisprudence, and social
thought)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-472-11350-X (cloth : alk. paper)
1. Law-Methodology. 2. Exterritoriality 3. Jurisdiction
4. International and municipal law. I. Sarat, Austin. II. Douglas,
Lawrence. III. Umphrey, Martha Merrill. IV. Series.
K212 .P58 2003
340'.1-dc21
First paperback edition 2006 Copyright ©by the University of Michigan 2003 All rights reserved Published in the United States of America by The University of Michigan Press Manufactured in the United States of America @ Printed on acid-free paper
2003011961
ISBN 0-472-03158-9 (pbk. : alk. paper)
ISBNI3 978-0-472-11350-7 (cloth :alk. paper)
2009
2008
2007
2006
5
4
3
2
ISBNI3 978-o-472-o3158-o (pbk.: alk. paper)
ISBNI3 978-o-472-o0220o8-3 (electronic)
No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, or otherwise, without the written permission of the publisher.
A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The place of law I edited by Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Umphrey. p. em. - (Amherst series in law, jurisprudence, and social thought) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN o-472-11350-x (cloth: alk. paper) 1. Law-Methodology. 2. Exterritoriality 3· Jurisdiction 4· International and municipal law. I. Sarat, Austin. II. Douglas, Lawrence. III. Umphrey, Martha Merrill. IV. Series. K212.P58 2003 340'.1-dc21 ISBN
o-472-03158-9 (pbk.: alk. paper)
ISBNI3 978-o-472-11350-7 (cloth: alk. paper) ISBNI3 978-o-472-03I58-o (pbk.: alk. paper) ISBNI3 978-o-472-02208-3 (electronic)
To my son Benjamin (A.S.)
To KRM and TJUM (M. U.)
For NEP (L.D.)
Acknowledgments
We are grateful to our colleague David Delaney for his help in shaping
the ideas that inform this book. We thank our students in Amherst Col-
lege's Department of Law, Jurisprudence and Social Thought for their
interest in the issues addressed in this book. We would like to express
our appreciation for generous financial support provided by the Col-
lege's Charles Hamilton Houston Forum on Law and Social Change and
to the Dean of the Faculty, Lisa Raskin, for her interest and support.
Contents
Where (or What) Is the Place of Law? An Introduction
Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Umphrey 1
Time against Territoriality: National Laws and
Literary Translations
Wai Chee Dimock
21
The Empty Place: Legal Formalities and the Cultural State
Annelise Riles
43
The Architecture of Authority: The Place of Law in
the Space of Science
Susan S. Silbey and Patricia Ewick
75
Digital Networks, State Authority, and Politics
Saskia Sassen
1o9
The Place of Cyberlaw
Lawrence Lessig
131
Against Cyberspace
Richard Ford
147
Contributors
181
Index
183
Where (or What) Is the Place of
Law? An Introduction
Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and
Martha Merrill Umphrey
The association of law and place is as old as law itself. It is difficult to
think of law without adding the name of a place-be it a powerful
nation-state, or a small municipality.' That law reflects the customs,
values, and ideas associated with particular places is hardly news.2
Identifying the place of law in any social order has long since become
standard practice in legal studies. And yet the meaning of the concept
of "the place of law" remains far from self-evident.
For some, place connotes a landscape, carved up or marked in vari-
ous ways, a "given" of the physical universe.3 This conception links law
and geography by treating place as a precondition of social life.4 For
other scholars, the place of law directs inquiry to the contribution of
law to social life, to the functions of law and law's role in society.5 Still
others describe place as the product of human labor, social processes,
and political contest.6 These scholars recognize that law plays a large
role in the production of a territorialized understanding of place. Law
can be, and is, used to create particular kinds of places, differentiating,
for example, individual property from public land;7 and law invests
place with value or meaning, such that individual property becomes
private.8
Place sometimes is used metaphorically, as a way of organizing our
conceptions of the world. As a metaphor it contends with other ways of
organizing understandings of, or relations to, legal authority, other
ways of marking social relations, other metaphors through which legal
power operates.9 Approached this way, we can inquire about the rela-
2
THE PLACE OF LAW
tive utility of the deployment of metaphors of place for the organiza-
tion of law or the design of legal regulation.'o
These different conceptualizations connect the place of law with the
"various social projects and social practices through which geographi-
cal forms and spatial relations are changed."" Although natural law
theorists may ask us to imagine law as a set of abstract ideals, floating
timelessly beyond the boundaries of cities, states, and nations, few
would deny, as a descriptive matter, that positive law derives its par-
ticular form, content, and social administration from its rootedness in a
geographically defined space.
First and foremost, then, the concept of the "place of law" has a hor-
izontal component: law spreads itself over a specific territory. Thought
of in this way, the place of law is a matter of jurisdiction. Jurisdiction
marks the domain within which one set of legal authorities can be said
to exercise legitimate authority. At the same time, jurisdiction delin-
eates the boundaries beyond which some other law holds sway.12 In
our domestic context, jurisdiction often refers to that rarified and
abstract space in which state interests collide with federal power. More
generally, however, questions of jurisdiction lead us to consider the
very sources and limits of legal authority, and to consider the law's
role in the construction of the classical political form of Western
modernity: the sovereign nation-state. In this regard, law connects
place to power as part of the apparatus through which areas and peo-
ple are governed. Place is important to sovereignty's projects of pro-
ducing social order and ruling a people.13
The study of jurisdiction inevitably invites inquiry into the nature of
legal boundaries, about what is inside and outside of law.14 From the
perspective of state law, boundaries must be clear; the where of law's
authority must never be left ambiguous. But the very act of drawing
sharp boundaries involves an imagination of an outside, a place from
which law is constitutively absent. Law is a set of social institutions and
practices constructed on the basis of imaginings of a place beyond law's
boundaries. Law thus authorizes itself as a lesser or necessary evil and
as a response to our inability to live in a place without law, the Hobbe-
sian state of nature.'5
Hobbes's famous picture of life without law captures a fundamental
dilemma of the human condition: whether people should live freely but
insecurely, or should relinquish their freedom in the name of a greater
security.16 For Hobbes the answer was clear. Power (and so freedom)
WHERE (OR WHAT) Is THE PLACE OF LAW?
3
must be transferred to a single entity (or person) if peace and security
were to be realized. The sovereign must lay claim to rule over a specific
location, a place over which its authority would be complete.
Hobbes's conclusion, however, also asks us to think of the place of
law vertically. In this regard, our responsibility as legal subjects is to
know our place vis-a-vis the law. We must humbly accept the law's
authority as supreme if we are to enjoy its ordering effects. Like Joseph
K.'s vision of the Castle in Kafka's novel, the law occupies a space on
high; as law-abiding citizens, we must approach the law with reverence
and our gaze must be directed upward. Consider the argument of the
Supreme Court in Walker v. Birmingham, a case that asked whether civil
rights protesters could lawfully ignore a court order prohibiting their
march. Although the Supreme Court recognized that the lower court's
injunction was based on an arguably unconstitutional local ordinance,
the majority insisted that the petitioners had no right to ignore the
injunction until the question of constitutionality had been resolved by a
legal authority. Offering a classic statement of what we have called
both the vertical and horizontal understandings, Justice Stewart wrote,
"No man can be a judge in his own case, however exalted his station,
however righteous his motives . . . Respect for judicial process is a
small price to pay for the civilizing hand of law."'7 By reasserting the
law's authority, the Court reminds us of our place before the law by
conjuring the state of nature that lurks beyond law's boundary."8 We
are reminded that the peace and security achieved by law's power are
ever vulnerable; that lies the abyss just beyond the place of law.19
Numerous other cases, from the mundane to the bizarre, deal with
other complications arising from law's relationship to place, both hori-
zontally and vertically conceived. Can, for example, law's authority
extend beyond the place of its origin? Do citizens leave the reach of that
authority when they cross law's geographical boundary? To what
extent does the reality-or even fantasy-of such a space beyond law
trouble law's legitimacy? A classic illustration of this problem is found
in Queen v. Dudley and Stephens-a case that is a parable about the vio-
lence of a lawless place and the utter necessity of sovereign power.20
The case began with the sinking of an English yacht in 1884. As the ship
went down, the defendants, Dudley and Stephens, along with one
other sailor and a young boy, escaped in an open lifeboat. After drifting
for more than twenty days, during which they exhausted their food
and water, Dudley and Stephens killed the weakened and defenseless
4
THE PLACE OF LAW
young boy and "fed upon... [his] body and blood."21 Eventually the
three survivors, found "in the lowest state of prostration," were res-
cued; and, contrary to the long-followed custom of the sea, Dudley and
Stephens were charged with murder.22
At trial, Lord Coleridge acknowledged that the situation in the
lifeboat was one of "necessity," and he painted the actions of Dudley
and Stephens in starkly Hobbesian terms.23 Their actions were, in
Coleridge's view, guided by the belief that "in order to save your own
life you may lawfully take away the life of another, when that other is
neither attempting nor threatening yours, nor is guilty of any illegal act
whatever towards you or anyone else."24 The question as he saw it was
whether that belief, the equivalent of the right of self-preservation that
Hobbes tells us governs behavior in the state of nature, should be rec-
ognized by law, whether the lifeboat was, under such extreme condi-
tions, a place beyond the legitimate reach of positive law.
Though custom had for centuries sanctioned similar lifeboat killings
in cases of dire necessity, for Coleridge this question was not particu-
larly difficult.25 While he recognized that the defendants found them-
selves in a situation where it was almost impossible to "keep ... judg-
ment straight and ... conduct pure,"26 he contended that it is precisely
in such situations where law must stand guard against the frailties that
constitute our very humanness. Law must refuse to acknowledge and
justify actions according to nature's dictates or recognize those dictates
as its own. Coleridge flatly asserted that the idea of an unqualified right
of self-preservation is "immoral"; morality requires that we distance
ourselves from, rather than give in to, the impulses of the state of
nature. "It is not correct," he wrote, "to say that there is any absolute or
unqualified necessity to preserve one's life."27
Recognizing such a principle would mean, Coleridge argued, that
the "weakest, the youngest, the most unresisting" would be most vul-
nerable and most likely victimized. Portraying life without a common
power in Hobbesian terms as violent and exploitative, Coleridge
warned that an incorrect decision in this case, a decision legitimating
such violence and exploitation, "would be of fatal consequence."28 By
conjuring the prospect of a widespread outbreak of lawless violence,
Coleridge justified treating the actions of Dudley and Stephens as
"willful murder."
Coleridge's opinion suggests that the place of law is the place of sov-
WHERE (OR WHAT) Is THE PLACE OF LAW?
5
ereignty and sovereign power.29 Indeed for Coleridge there can be no
moral place outside the sphere of law's authority, at least for the "civi-
lized" English on land or sea.30 But just as the formation of the sover-
eign nation-state played a crucial role in the emergence of a territorial
and jurisdictional understanding of law (and vice versa), the rapid and
often radical transformation of this political form is one of the defining
characteristics of our era. Under pressures variously labeled transna-
tionalism and globalization, state forms throughout the world are
undergoing transformation, adding new functions, shedding old ones,
refining institutional processes, developing new alliances within and
beyond national borders-and, in so doing, changing the relationship
between law and place.
Territory, jurisdiction, boundary: each of these ways of describing
the place of law is called into question by contemporary processes of
globalization that create new territories, rearrange jurisdictions, and
blur boundaries. In the abstract, globalization refers to the increasing
interconnectedness of social relations; in reality, it asks us to imagine
obscure localities shaped by events across the globe, and vice versa.31 In
the domain of culture, globalization entails the penetration of even the
most closed societies by common symbolic forms.32
The driving force behind this diffusion of culture and the hallmark
of globalization is the worldwide spread of corporate capitalism and
neoliberal values.33 As such, globalization can be seen as a vast project
in political economy, a restructuring of the global order to maximize its
compatibility with the values and interests of multinational corporate
enterprise, and as a crucial reorienting of dominant political ideologies.
At the level of jurisdiction, the global economic system has been
institutionalized in the World Bank, the International Monetary Fund,
the World Trade Organization, and the North American Free Trade
Agreement, to name only a few. These arrangements seek to impose the
discipline of the market on economies that have been, it is claimed, cor-
rupted by crony capitalism, welfare state social policy, and other
autarchic tendencies. Accordingly, the mission of these institutional
messengers of globalized capitalism is to dismantle barriers to the free
flow of populations, commerce, information, and especially capital
all in the service of economic growth and industrial development.
Globalization opens up state processes to far-reaching forces and
leads to reconfigurations of state power. As these global forces impinge
6
THE PLACE OF LAW
on the state, the place of law is altered. New challenges and opportuni-
ties emerge, new locations of legal authority develop. The process of dis-
aggregating and reconfiguring state power leads directly to the question
of what roles territory, jurisdiction, and boundaries play in defining the
place of law. Whether at the level of supranational institutions or
reformed domestic ones, globalization alters competition and contesta-
tion over norms, over the content of legal regulations and standards.34
Clearly the globalized political economy is exerting a transformative
impact on the place of law. Complementing globalization in this trans-
formation are newly emergent international and supranational human
rights regimes. "The past few decades," Richard Wilson notes, "have
witnessed the inexorable rise of the application of international human
rights law as well as the extension of a wider public discourse on
human rights, to the point where human rights could be seen as one of
the most globalized political values of our times."35Appeals to human
rights and an emerging body of international law have, then, the poten-
tial to transform power relations within states and open up new possi-
bilities for forces seeking social change.36 And as the creation of the
International Criminal Court suggests these changes may radically
redefine traditional concepts of sovereignty and the jurisdictional lim-
its of legal authority.
Though questions of jurisdiction and sovereign authority present
the most concrete way of analyzing what we mean by the "place" of
law, there is yet another way of conceptualizing "place" that shifts
from the geopolitical to the sociological. Taking this perspective, so-
ciolegal scholars have asked about the role law plays in social life. How
important is it in the lives of citizens?
Two general ways of thinking about the place of law in social life
have emerged in the literature. The first, instrumentalism, posits a rela-
tively sharp distinction between various kinds of legal standards, on
the one hand, and various kinds of nonlegal human activities, on the
other. It then explores the effects of the former on the latter.37 Instru-
mentalism conceives of law as a tool for sustaining or changing aspects
of social life, but not as a major force in shaping society. Instrumental-
ism denies that law is already an integral part of that which it regulates.
Perhaps the key to the instrumentalist understanding is the belief
that there is a fairly firm division between the legal and the social. As
Robert Gordon has observed, writers in this tradition
WHERE (OR WHAT) Is THE PLACE OF LAW?
7
divide the world into two spheres, one social and one legal. Soci-
ety is the primary realm of social experience. It is "real life":
What's immediately and truly important to people ... goes on
there.... "Law" or "the legal system," on the other hand, is a
distinctly secondary body of phenomena. It is a specialized
realm of state and professional activity that is called into being
by the primary social world in order to serve that world's needs.
Law is auxiliary-an excrescence on social life, even if some-
times a useful excrescence.38
Law, then, is pictured as a residual category whose role in the everyday
is episodic, artificial, and often disruptive.39
The second perspective, the constitutive, contends that social life
inevitably is run through with law.40 In bold outline, the constitutive
view suggests that law occupies an important place in society, shaping
it from inside out, providing the principal categories in terms of which
social relations are made to seem largely natural, normal, cohesive, and
coherent. We are not, as instrumentalists suggest, merely pushed and
pulled by laws that impinge on us from the "outside." Rather, we
internalize law's "meanings" and its representations of us, so much so
that our own purposes and understandings can no longer be extricated
from them.41
So conceived, it is understandable that law's place might be either
relatively invisible (as part of the frame in terms of which actions are
formulated) or seemingly necessary and natural (as part of what it
means to be an agent or actor at all). Thus, in thinking about the place
of law, those who adopt the constitutive perspective tend to see the
links between law and society at the level of networks of legal practices,
on the one hand, and clusters of beliefs, on the other. While these links
tend to be relatively diffuse, they are nonetheless incompatible with
portraits of legal systems as "struggling to retain what seems like a ten-
uous grasp on the social order,"42 as having little place in the organiza-
tion of society.43
The essays collected in The Place of Law speak to these different under-
standings of place. They treat place as a geographical fact, calling our
attention to the way distinctive localized cultures are expressed in legal
norms. They analyze the social processes through which the place of
8
THE PLACE OF LAW
law is created and maintained, exploring new places or spaces within
which legal authority might be deployed. Finally, they consider the
way globalization works. Taken together, they help us see the way law
both defines territory and attempts to keep things in place. They high-
light the spatiality of law and the normative contests that spring from
the legal regulation of space. They draw our attention to the fact that
law lives most vividly far beyond its most majestic embodiments, in the
common, the quotidian, the ordinary. They challenge scholars to attend
to the difficult task of charting where (or what) the place of law really is
in any society and in any historical period.
The first two essays in this collection examine the place of law in
repressive political conditions. Both are interested in the intersections
between law as a technology for the governance of particular geogra-
phies and other systems of meaning and control, including literature
and culture. The first examines what happens when the place of law is
penetrated by "literary culture"; the second, what happens at the inter-
section of culture and legal formality.
Wai Chee Dimock begins our inquiry by trying to identify the place
of law in the former Soviet Union, a place in which the rule of law was
allegedly absent. Dimock's essay takes issue with this view, examin-
ing law as a technology of governance, not as something standing
apart from the lives of ordinary citizens living under totalitarianism.
She focuses on law's horizontal axis, that is, its location on a geo-
graphical map. Her essay points to the importance of knowing about
the borders and boundaries of law and whether the jurisdiction and
scope of law are coextensive with the geographic boundaries of
nation-states.
Dimock describes the place of Soviet law in the life of one individual,
Osip Mandelstam. Mandelstam, "probably the greatest Russian poet of
the twentieth century," was arrested twice as a result of his allegedly
subversive poetry, including most especially his "Stalin Epigram."
Dimock insists that the prosecution of Mandelstam occurred within,
not beyond, the boundaries of law. It was, she says, an act clearly
authorized by the Soviet Criminal Code, a code designed to serve the
needs of the state apparatus.
This identification of law and the state came at considerable cost. So
intertwined were law and the state under the Soviets that their law had
neither jurisdiction nor moral force beyond the territorial scope of the
state. Law is generally a powerful expression of the nation as a single,
WHERE (OR WHAT) Is THE PLACE OF LAW?
9
integral, rule-governed and rule-abiding unit that unifies and homoge-
nizes the territorial. Law not only regulates conduct, but, following
what we have called the constitutive view, it seeks to establish the tem-
poral and spatial horizon of its citizens. Yet in this effort law, as it did
in Stalinist Russia, often fails.
Here Dimock uses Mandelstam's profound attachment to Dante as
an example of the power of "literary culture" to overlay the place of
law. Literary culture establishes a different temporality by reaching a
community of readers beyond national boundaries and is activated
when authors write and when readers in different places read their
words. This linguistic migration, Dimock suggests, is one of the most
important challenges to law's jurisdiction. It punches holes in the bor-
ders of the nation, opening them up to alien influences of incalculable
magnitude.
Dimock contends that Mandelstam's love of, and immersion in,
Dante, put him, in one sense, beyond the jurisdiction of Soviet law.
"Space and time," she says, "have no absolute jurisdiction when it
comes to the bonds between texts and readers." Translation of litera-
ture from one language to another is, even under totalitarianism, "the
basis for a limited freedom." Political repression "forces the mind to
think globally." Thus, paradoxically, even as law is used to insure the
territorial jurisdiction of the repressive state, it creates the conditions
under which it is increasingly unable to govern the place of its origin.
Literary culture provides a terrain for engagement in a normative
struggle against the efforts of states to keep things in place. It provides
a vehicle of escape, putting the subjects of such repression in touch
with the values, ideas, and linguistic possibilities of other places and
times.
This preoccupation with boundaries and their disruption is also cen-
tral to the essay by Annelise Riles. Like Dimock, Riles begins with a
problem in legal theory, here the geographic and cultural preconditions
of "legal formalism." Calling attention to the significance of formalism
in debates about jurisprudence, Riles argues that the formalism of the
twentieth century was a compromised, altered version of its earlier iter-
ation. While it was absent from totalitarian states like those described
by Dimock, even the confrontation with totalitarianism could not res-
cue the strictest versions of formalism. No longer insisting on the pos-
sibility that judicial interpretation could be governed solely by the lan-
guage of legal texts, the new formalism of the late twentieth century
10
THE PLACE OF LAW
combined pragmatism with a faith in the salutary effect of solid rules
and stable legal categories.
Riles traces the debate about the instrumental and expressive effects
of law, a debate central to contemporary thinking about formalism, to
what she calls "the cultural state." The cultural state, as she describes it,
is "organized according to theories of culture and cultural difference
and devoted.., to the preservation and elaboration of this difference."
But the cultural state is also "a discursive state . . . in which the hege-
mony of culture.., is nearly absolute." Formalism, in its strictest sense,
is offered up as a response to anxieties about culture and cultural dif-
ference. In this account formalism seeks to place law outside of, or
above, cultural difference. The role of law is, in the view of formalists,
to provide vehicles and devices for regulating, if not resolving, cultural
conflicts.
Riles turns to colonial and postcolonial Fiji, and to its use of a land
titles registration system, to illustrate this conception of formalism.
Because, like Dimock, Riles is interested in the place of law under con-
ditions of repression, she examines what happened to people in Fiji
who were defined as outside culture because they were "half-castes" or
"part-Europeans." For these people, unlike Mandelstam, there was no
possibility of escape from a territorialized version of law, no access to a
literary culture that might have provided an alternative normative
horizon.
For the Fijians any escape from the most extreme conditions of
repression could be found solely in their attachment to land. Their abil-
ity to hold onto land, in turn, was made possible by a very particular
kind of formalism, namely the Fijian land title registration system. This
system created for the half-castes "a set of actual places shielded from
the reach of the cultural state." The law governing place was for the
half-castes a place of protection, a place in which "antihegemonic pos-
sibilities for living" could be carved out and maintained. Examining the
"empty place" that is the domain of legal formalities, Riles contends
that it made possible "particular sociality" for "refugees of the cultural
state, the people without culture."
The next two essays move away from the nation-state in order to
chart the place of law in the constitution of political and social life. They
alter the focus, shifting away from the impact of law on individuals and
groups to analyze its place in institutions and political arrangements.
Thus Patricia Ewick and Susan Silbey inquire about the place of law in
WHERE (OR WHAT) IS THE PLACE OF LAW?
11
modern scientific practice. The laboratory, they argue, "has been trans-
formed over the centuries from a private place of gentlemanly inquiry
to an open and accessible public arena, the forms of regulation govern-
ing the processes of production and certifying the knowledge pro-
duced therein have also shifted." Over time, law has come to have a
much more important role in regulating scientific practices. Legal reg-
ulation has, however, been largely indirect, oriented to controlling the
design and operation of space, namely the laboratory. Law, Ewick and
Silbey suggest, works through the very institutions it allegedly trans-
forms. By regulating space, state law helps to produce a particular kind
of scientist and a particular kind of science.
Ewick and Silbey present a brief history of scientific laboratories to
show how law encouraged, and helped make possible, their transfor-
mation from a private into a public domain, from a personal space into
a democratized, standardized, and anonymous space. Here they chart
the way law invests places with meanings while focusing its regulatory
activity on "the constitution of space." Space itself has become "the
object of governance, and individuals are incidentally (and episodi-
cally) controlled and constructed as subjects only as they occupy or pass
through these governed spaces."
For Ewick and Silbey, inquiry about the social significance of law,
inquiry designed to determine what the place of law is in regard to sci-
ence, should be directed to understanding where the place of law is.
Borrowing from Nikolas Rose, they designate the regulation of the
spaces in which science is done "governing from a distance." Legal reg-
ulation operates through rules about environmental protection and
workplace safety, through the rules governing intellectual property
and the creation of trusts and endowments. But law also encourages
self-regulation, identifying problem areas while leaving it to scientists
to develop standards of practice to address them, creating what look
like places of autonomy beyond its boundaries at the same time it colo-
nizes those places. In this sense, law has both "certified areas of scien-
tific autonomy" and has "been constitutively present.., in the expan-
sion and organization of modern science." Ewick and Silbey's work
suggests that law has a place both outside and inside science. "Scien-
tific authority," they contend, "is in part constituted by law's deference
to science's claims to discover truths that exist prior to and indepen-
dent of human institutions."
The essay by Saskia Sassen moves from the localized context of the
12
THE PLACE OF LAW
scientific laboratory to the global dimensions of the digital revolution.
Sassen is interested in one particular mode or mechanism of the emerg-
ing global order, what she calls "digitization" and its impact on "the
regulatory capacities of states." She notes that the development of the
Internet has important implications for "current framings for state
authority and democratic participation." Digitization creates a new
geography of power. In Sassen's view, it represents both a reposition-
ing of the state in a broader field of power and a reconfiguring of the
work of states.
The Internet's democratic potential cannot resist the incursion of
new modalities of control, control exercised less by public than by pri-
vate actors. Thus the digital revolution creates new challenges to, and
new opportunities for, regulatory activity. New normative regimes,
what she calls "privatized and technologically based rule enforce-
ment," alter the shape, as well as the place, of law. Digitization repre-
sents less a loss of power for the nation-state than a relocation of state
power and the power of state law.
While Sassen urges us not to underestimate the potential of the
Internet to be a site of democratic politics, she notes that its impact on
the jurisdiction of state law and its power to neutralize sovereignty
come from the existence of the private digital networks of international
finance. Because capital can be moved within and beyond national bor-
ders with a single keystroke, international finance capital can exercise
enormous power in state legal orders. These actors and institutions pri-
vatize what was once public and denationalize formerly national policy
agendas. In so doing, they reposition and reorient law; they infuse it
with new norms. Global financial markets, she argues, compete with
state law not only as domains of power, but in establishing a logic that
seems proper and appropriate for new problems of governance.
Yet globalization, as Sassen sees it, does not just happen to states;
globalization works in and through them. While the Internet con-
tributes to countergeographies of globalization, making possible cross-
border political activism, digital space, whether private or public, is
partly embedded in actual social structures and power dynamics. In
this sense the place of law in the digital world is, and will continue to
be, both within and beyond the state.
The remaining two essays in this book, though less focused on glob-
alization, continue Sassen's inquiry into the place of law in cyberspace,
its place in regulating the Internet, and the utility of metaphors of place
WHERE (OR WHAT) IS THE PLACE OF LAW?
13
and space in helping us think about the world that computers have
helped bring into being. Lawrence Lessig's essay shares the instrumen-
talist conception of law that animates Sassen's work; for Lessig, as for
Sassen, law provides one form of regulation among many. Thus he con-
trasts law's regulatory role in cyberspace to the role of social norms, the
market, and what he calls the "architecture" of the world as we find it.
Today many people argue that cyberspace is a place beyond law's
boundaries, a state of nature where freedom exists without danger.
Those who advocate cyber-libertarianism suggest that cyberspace pro-
vides authentic, unconstrained human freedom that is "unregulable."
It is that place where individuals are inherently free from the control of
real place sovereigns.
Lessig takes issue with this view, seeing in cyberspace not a place of
freedom, but instead a place that has the potential to be the most fully,
and extensively regulated space that we have ever known. Noting that
behavior in cyberspace, like behavior elsewhere, is regulated by law,
norms, markets, and architecture, Lessig argues that the most signifi-
cant of these regulatory constraints is what he calls "code," the soft-
ware and hardware that set the terms on which cyberspace operates.
Like other architectural forms, it is not optional. Code is a rival sover-
eign, competing with the regulatory power of geographically located
sovereigns. Lessig describes the complex intersections of law, norms,
markets, and architecture as they occur in the contemporary regulation
of cyberspace, taking as his example the effort to regulate pornography
on the Internet. He contrasts what he calls "real space" and cyberspace,
saying that the latter is indeed less regulable in the sense that there is
less that governments can do to govern behavior there. The source of
this difference, he argues, seems to be architectural. Its architecture ren-
ders it ostensibly unregulable.
Or so it would seem. Architecture stands in the way of the regulation
of cyberspace only if one assumes, as many commentators do, that it
can have one and only one possible architecture. This is the error of nat-
uralism as applied to cyberspace. It is a serious error because it under-
estimates the permeability of the architecture and the significance of
legal decisions about it.
By insisting that manufacturers of encryption assure that any
encryption system have built into it a key recovery ability or insisting
on the use of certifying IDs, law can ensure that the architecture of
cyberspace makes behavior in cyberspace more regulable. In the face of
14
THE PLACE OF LAW
these possibilities it is important, Lessig notes, that we not assume that
freedom in cyberspace is a given. Instead, like freedom in other places,
it must be fought for and maintained with diligence and with no assur-
ance of its survival. We must participate in an intense normative strug-
gle if we are not going to move from an architecture of freedom to one
of control, an architecture every bit as draconian in its reach as the total-
itarian structure that ensnared Osip Mandelstam in Stalin's Soviet
Union.
Yet perhaps understanding cyberspace as a place or in spatial terms
may have its own perverse consequences, its own implications for the
role law can and does play in regulating communications.44 Spatial
metaphors may undermine our capacity to engage in the kind of nor-
mative struggle that Lessig seeks to encourage. Richard Ford concludes
this book by providing a careful examination of the implications of
using place as a metaphor in the context of the Internet. Ford, like
Sassen and Lessig, sees in much of the current discourse surrounding
the Internet the dream of an autonomous (and free) space. He too
thinks that this is something of an illusion. Looking more closely, Ford
argues, reveals "the dependency of cyberspace on the terra firma of
political sovereigns."
Treating the Internet as a place, a territory, underlies the illusion of
autonomy that surrounds it. While Ford acknowledges that spatial
metaphors provide an attractive way of organizing thinking about the
Internet, he insists that they are not the only, or indeed even the best,
way of doing so. "The decision to think of the Internet in spatial terms
... will not help us to understand the Internet so much as it will affect the
way we understand the Internet." Ford worries that spatial metaphors
allow scholars to ignore the technical and normative complexity of the
domain we label cyberspace. He worries, in particular, that they con-
strain and distort thinking about the place of law in cyberspace.
To illustrate the pervasiveness of metaphors of place and space and
their impact in discussions about the Internet, Ford examines the
Supreme Court's adjudication of the Communications Decency Act
and arguments about the impact of the Internet on our thinking about
race. With respect to the former, the government's defense of the CDA
relied explicitly on the idea of place, treating the Internet as "analogous
to a territorial jurisdiction-a cyber city-and thought of restrictions on
Internet obscenity as analogous to local zoning law." On the Court, Jus-
tice O'Connor in particular seemed attracted to this way of thinking,
WHERE (OR WHAT) IS THE PLACE OF LAW?
15
suggesting that a zoning of cyberspace would pass constitutional
muster, though such zoning was not yet possible given the limits of
available technology.
Turning to race, Ford criticizes arguments that the Internet will pro-
mote new consciousness about race. Because it is possible to "speak"
over the Internet without a prejudged racial identity being assigned to
the speaking subject, some scholars seem to favor a form of racial
authentication in order to insure that race is not elided. This argument
is based on the fact that such scholars think about the Internet as a
place. As in any other place, it seems appropriate that people bring
their physical selves with them. However, if we see the Internet as a
medium of communication rather than as a place, we can more readily
identify the dangers of a demand for compulsory racial identification.
Thinking about the Internet as if it were a place or a space "encour-
ages us to import our biases, mythologies, misperceptions, and unre-
flective habitual practices around land and territory into a new
domain." Rather than imagining a preexisting space, whether in phys-
ical or cyber landscapes, into which law may be allowed entrance, we
should remember that law helps to create place, to give it meaning. If
we do so, Ford contends, we may then be able to use the Internet, and
the challenges it poses, to help us develop new ways of thinking about
"real space." In cyberspace, as elsewhere, the definition of space is part
of a normative struggle, not a fact that can resolve it.
This normative struggle reminds us that the place of law-whether
defined as territory, jurisdiction, or sociological fact-is always a place
both of regulation and of contestation. Law's place is never a given in
social life. It is rather always contingent-sometimes strengthened by
other social forces, sometimes limited. As a result, whether in Stalinist
Russia or Fiji, in scientific laboratories or the new institutions of a
global political economy, in or beyond the Internet, charting the place
of law is at once enriching and challenging. The essays in this book sug-
gest that the place of law is as difficult to pin down as the outcomes of
normative struggles are to predict.
NOTES
1. As Richard Ford reminds us, this appearance is deceiving. Instead of
being inevitable, "territorial jurisdictions. . . are relatively new and intuitively
surprising technological developments.... We are now accustomed to territor-
s6
THE PLACE OF LAW
ial jurisdiction-so much so that it is hard to imagine that government could be
organized in any other way." Richard Ford, "Law's Territory (a History of
Jurisdiction)," Michigan Law Review 97 (1999): 843.
2. For an example of this kind of argument see Lawrence Friedman, The
Legal System: Social Science Perspectives (New York: Russell Sage Foundation,
1975).
3. Simon Schama provides an illuminating discussion of the way land-
scape is made into cultural tradition. See Landscape and Memory (New York:
Knopf, 1995). See also Barbara Bender, ed., Landscape: Politics and Perspectives
(Providence, R.I.: Berg, 1993).
4. "Space (and place in a richer understanding of this concept) is fre-
quently reduced to the status of a given." David Delaney, Richard Ford, and
Nicholas Blomley, "Preface: Where Is Law?" in The Legal Geographies Reader, ed.
Nicholas Blomley, David Delaney, and Richard Ford (Oxford: Blackwell, 200ool),
xvi.
5. See, for example, Bryant Garth and Austin Sarat, eds., How Does Law
Matter? (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1998).
6. "[P]lace seems to connote inertia, closure, and passivity.... However,
recent scholarship in geography would suggest that place can best be under-
stood in other ways. Rather than a passive stage on which the histories of social
life unfold, place, like space, is actively constructed through a constellation of
material and discursive practices. In historical terms, consequently, we should
think of places not as static entities but . . . as in a constant process of becom-
ing." Nicholas Blomley, "Landscapes of Property," Law and Society Review 32
(1998): 581. Also see Nicholas Blomley, Law, Space, and the Geographies of Power
(New York: Guilford Press, 1994); Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans.
D. Nicholson-Smith (Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1991); and Doreen Massey,
Space, Place, and Gender (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1994).
7. See C. B. McPherson, "The Meaning of Property," in Property: Main-
stream and Critical Positions, ed. C. B. McPherson (Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, 1978); and Margaret Radin, Reinterpreting Property (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1993).
8. A telling example of this is provided by Justice Scalia's opinion in a
recent case on the use of high-tech surveillance to identify the presence of mar-
ijuana in someone's home. See Kyllo v. United States, 121 S.Ct. 2038 (2001). Also
Carol Rose, Property as Persuasion (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1994).
9. For an interesting example of a metaphorical use see Boaventura De
Sousa Santos, "Law: A Map of Misreading. Toward a Postmodern Conception
of Law," Journal of Law and Society 14 (1987): 279.
10. See Neil Smith and Cindi Katz, "Grounding Metaphor: Toward a Spa-
tialized Politics," in Place and the Politics of Identity, ed. Michael Keith and Steve
Pile (New York: Routledge, 1993).
11. Delaney, Ford, and Blomley, "Preface: Where Is Law?" xvi.
12. Robert Cover, "Folktales of Justice: Tales of Jurisdiction," Capital Univer-
sity Law Review 14 (1985): 179.
WHERE (OR WHAT) IS THE PLACE OF LAW?
17
13. Cover asserts that most jurisdictional thinking is "largely apologetic,
state-serving." "Folktales of Justice," 185.
14. "Law," Delaney argues, "is scrupulous about patrolling its own borders.
It is, as I said, imperialistic." See David Delaney, "Beyond the Word: Law as a
Thing of This World," in Law and Geography, ed. Jane Holder and Carolyn Har-
rison (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), 70.
15. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. MacPherson (New York: Penguin,
1968). Hobbes described the state of nature as a condition of life in which men
might live "without a common Power to keep them in awe" (185). That condi-
tion is one, as every undergraduate knows, of violence, or the perpetual fear of
violence. Given rough equality of desire and power, men "endeavour to
destroy or subdue one another" and are, as a result, "in a condition which is
called Warre; and such a warre, as is of every man against every man" (184-85).
As Hobbes noted in one of the most famous passages in his work, life in the
state of nature is "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short" (186).
16. Duncan Kennedy argues that this dilemma poses a fundamental chal-
lenge for liberal political theory. See "The Structure of Blackstone's Commen-
taries," Buffalo Law Review 28 (1979): 211-13. See also Roberto Unger, Knowledge
and Politics (New York: Free Press, 1975). As Unger describes this dilemma,
The apparent guarantee of your safety will be the final cause of your
degradation. The self whose continuity your obedience insures is not
your own.... The others save you from being nothing, but they do not
allow you to become yourself.... The freedom to be unstable in your
desires and pursue the goals you choose, after you have rendered trib-
ute to Caesar, simply confronts you once again with the paradoxes of
the morality of desire from which you were trying to escape. (61)
17. Walker v. Birmingham, 388 U.S. 307, 320-21.
18. As Justice Frankfurter once suggested in explaining the necessity of law,
"no one, no matter how exalted his public office, or how righteous his private
motive, can be a judge in his own case. This is what courts are for.... If one man
can be allowed to determine for himself what is law, every man can. That
means first chaos, then tyranny." See United States v. United Mine Workers, 330
U.S. 258, 308-9, 312 (1947).
19. The threat of such lawless violence is also conjured in United States v.
Holmes, 26 Fed. Cas. 360 (C. E. D. pa. 1842), reprinted in Joseph Goldstein, Alan
Dershowitz, and Richard Schwartz, Criminal Law: Theory and Process (New
York: Free Press, 1974), 1023. Holmes, is a case whose tragic circumstances begin
with the sinking of a ship and the resulting murder trial of a sailor who
attempted to save his own life, as well as the lives of others, by throwing pas-
sengers overboard from an overcrowded, leaking lifeboat.
20. Queen v. Dudley and Stephens, LR 14 QBD 273 (1884), reprinted in John
Bonsignore, Ethan Katsh, Peter D'Errico, Ronald Pipkin, and Stephen Arons,
Before the Law (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1974), 25. For a complete history of
18
THE PLACE OF LAW
the case, see A. W. B. Simpson, Cannibalism and the Common Law: The Story of the
Tragic Last Voyage of the Mignonette and the Strange Legal Proceedings to Which It
Gave Rise (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984).
21. Bonsignore et al., Before the Law, 26.
22. Ibid. See Simpson, Cannibalism, chap. 5, for a history of the English mar-
itime customs governing such situations.
23. Bonsignore et al., Before the Law, 25.
24. Ibid., 27.
25. Indeed the authorities in London decided to prosecute Dudley and
Stephens with the thought of producing a leading case on the issue; as Simpson
demonstrates, conviction was essentially foreordained.
26. Bonsignore et al., Before the Law, 27.
27. Ibid., 30.
28. Ibid.
29. On the connection of law and sovereignty see John Austin, The Province
of Jurisprudence Determined, ed. Wilfred Rumble (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1995). For a provocative reworking of the idea of sovereignty see
Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel
Heller-Roazen (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998).
30. See Nikolas Rose, Powers of Freedom: Refraining Political Thought (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). For specific examples of the way
power is exercised through the governance of space see Davina Cooper, Gov-
erning Out of Order: Space, Law, and the Politics of Belonging (London: Rivers
Oram Press, 1998); and Marianna Valverde, Diseases of the Will: Alcohol and the
Dilemmas of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
31. Anthony Giddens, The Consequences of Modernity (Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 1990), 64.
32. See Arjun Appadurai, Modernity at Large: Cultural Dimensions of Global-
ization (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996). As Susan Sibley
puts it:
[R]ap music from American urban ghettos is played in the shops in
Paris and on the streets in Budapest, portable telephones manufactured
in Finland adorn the hips of stock brokers and manual laborers from
Santiago to Sidney, from Cancun to Cape Town, and television stations
around the globe fill their schedules with the likes of Melrose Place while
the office workers from Moscow to Buenos Aires munch on Big Macs
and fries.
Susan Silbey, "'Let Them Eat Cake': Globalization, Postmodern Colonial-
ism, and the Possibilities of Justice," Law and Society Review 31 (1997): 212.
33. Christopher, Chase-Dunn, Globalization: Structures of the World Economy
(Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991).
34. Pheng Cheah, "Posit(ion)ing Human Rights in the Current Global Con-
jecture," Public Culture 9 (1997): 8.
35. See Richard Wilson, "Human Rights, Culture, and Context: An Intro-
WHERE (OR WHAT) IS THE PLACE OF LAW?
19
duction," in Human Rights, Culture, and Context, ed. Richard Wilson (London:
Pluto Press, 1996), 1.
36. This possibility is discussed by Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns,
"The Unsettled Status of Human Rights: An Introduction," in Human Rights:
Concepts, Contests, Contingencies, ed. Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns (Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 200ool), 5-6.
37. David Trubek, "Where the Action Is: Critical Legal Studies and Empiri-
cism," Stanford Law Review 36 (1984): 575.
38. See Robert Gordon, "Critical Legal Histories," Stanford Law Review 36
(1984): 60.
39. David Engel and Eric Steele, "Civil Cases and Society: Process and
Order in the Civil Justice System," American Bar Association Research Journal
(1979): 295.
40. See Gordon, "Critical Legal Histories." Also see Christine Harrington
and Barbara Yngvesson, "Interpretive Sociolegal Research," Law and Social
Inquiry 15 (1990): 141. We should emphasize at the outset that there are con-
siderable differences among those we have lumped together as taking the
constitutive view. For example, Barbara Yngvesson's study "Making Law at
the Doorway: The Clerk, the Court, and the Construction of Community in
a New England Town," Law and Society Review 22 (1988): 409, draws atten-
tion to the power of legal officials in shaping the (social) meanings of "good
neighbor," or "dutiful parent"; but this effect of law on social meaning
seems quite different from what, say, Gabel and Feinman have in mind
when they contend that contract law encodes an invasive ideology, an ideal-
ized (and generally unarticulated and unexamined) way of thinking about
conflicts and agreements that tends to legitimate (as natural and necessary)
various oppressive socioeconomic realities. See Peter Gabel and Jay M. Fein-
man, "Contract Law as Ideology," in The Politics of Law: A Progressive Cri-
tique, ed. David Kairys (New York: Pantheon, 1982). In the first case, the
law's effect on social meaning is relatively transparent and explicit; in the
other, social meaning is engendered systemically and is, as a result, less eas-
ily detected.
41. Trubek, "Where the Actions Is," 589-604. From the constitutive perspec-
tive, law enters social practices and is, indeed, "imbricated" in them, by shap-
ing consciousness, by making law's concepts and commands seem, if not invis-
ible, then perfectly natural and benign. As Trubek writes:
[S]ocial order depends in a nontrivial way on a society's shared "world
view." Those world views are basic notions about human and social
relations that give meaning to the lives of society's members. Ideals
about the law-what it is, what it does, why it exists-are part of the
world view of any complex society.... Law, like other aspects of belief
systems, helps to define the role of an individual in society and the rela-
tions with others that make sense. At the same time that law is a system
of belief, it is also a basis of organization, a part of the structure in
which action is embedded
20
THE PLACE OF LAW
Gordon points out that "lawmaking and law-interpreting institutions have
been among the primary sources of the pictures of order and disorder, virtue
and vice, reasonableness and craziness, realism and visionary naivete and
some of the most commonplace aspects of social reality that ordinary people
carry around with them and use in ordering their lives." See "Critical Legal
Histories," o109. See also W. V. O. Quine and Joseph Ullian, The Web of Belief
(New York: Random House, 1970).
42. Susan Silbey, "Law and the Order of Our Life Together: A Sociological
Interpretation of the Relationship between Law and Society," in Law and the
Order of Our Life Together, ed. Richard Neuhaus (Grand Rapids, Mich.: William
Eerdmans, 1990), 20.
43. Thus, returning to Queen v. Dudley and Stephens with this different sense
of "place" in mind, we might imagine an instrumentalist analysis of the case
that focused upon the conflict between long-standing social practices that sanc-
tioned cannibalism in some limited conditions on the open sea, and external
authorities who impose a different regulative principle upon seafaring culture
for purposes of their own. A constitutive approach, on the other hand, might
emphasize the "legal" standing of custom as an integral part of theories of the
English common law and the ways in which a national conception of the doc-
trine of necessity signals the emergence of an alternative, rather than wholly
external, locus of legal authority. Under the latter approach in particular, geo-
graphical and sociological understandings of "place" are linked insofar as the
case implicates a tension between customary and national definitions of law
and the role both play in ordering the social world.
44. "Liberal legal discourse is an embarrassingly rich source of spatial
tropes and metaphors.... The metaphors do work and this work is crucial to
how law itself works." Delaney, "Beyond the Word," 69.
Time against Territoriality: National
Laws and Literary Translations
Wai Chee Dimock
How territorial is the jurisdiction of law? Is it mapped by one set of spa-
tial coordinates? Does it have borders, and where do those borders fall?
Do they coincide with the borders of a sovereign nation? Are both of
these placeable phenomena, describable in geographical terms? If so, is
the jurisdiction of law predicated on, and perhaps even parasitic on, the
jurisdiction of a territorial entity? And what about the jurisdiction of lit-
erature? Is it predicated in the same way on that entity?
I want to address these questions by looking at the conduct of law
and literature in one particular setting, the former Soviet Union. The
operative scopes of these two enterprises are worth comparing, not
only in light of their greater or lesser coincidence with that regime, but
also in light of the possibly nonterritorial ontology on the part of at least
one of them. I want to argue, specifically, that while law is spatially
predicated, most often operating within the limits set by geopolitics, lit-
erature is much less so. That, in turn, suggests that the jurisdiction of
these two must be theorized in two ways: not only in terms of the brute
fact of national borders, but also in terms of something working in defi-
ance of that brute fact. What might this be? What are the grounds for a
form of governance different from territorial sovereignty? In what fol-
lows, I explore time-the time of literary culture, an extended and con-
tinuously evolving duration-as one candidate. Here is a tribunal that
pits the transmission of words against the location of law. And, to the
extent that any large-scale transmission requires translation, requires
the crossing of borders national, linguistic, and chronological, the
cumulative time of literature must act sooner or later as an extraterrito-
21
22
THE PLACE OF LAW
rial force. A duration long in its making and dispersed in its unfolding,
the polyglot, polychronic time of literature cuts across the placeability
of law within the nation-state.
The Place of Law
It is useful, however, to begin with that placeability of law, and with the
nation-state that underwrites it. The former Soviet Union here stands as
a striking example. Of course, for some, this example might not count
at all. In theory-liberal theory as well as Marxist theory-the Soviet
Union was not supposed to have been ruled by law. Here was a nation
constituted by revolutionary justice, not by the judicial apparatus of a
bourgeois state. In practice, however, as Harold Berman and Robert
Conquest have shown, the Soviet Union did have an extensive body of
law, not only common law but more specifically civil law. Formal cod-
ification began in earnest in the early 1920os:
In 1922 and 1923 there appeared a Judiciary Act, a Civil Code,
Code of Civil Procedure, Criminal Code, Code of Criminal Pro-
cedure, Land Code, and a new Labor Code.... These codes gave
Soviet Russia a legal system which on paper and in its main out-
lines is similar to that of the countries of continental Europe,
including prerevolutionary Russia, differing from that of Eng-
land and the United States in technique but alike in many of its
basic principles.
The Judiciary Act established a hierarchy of courts and a sys-
tem of trials and appeals familiar, with variations, to all Western
countries. Its most unusual feature (possibly borrowed in part
from the German practice in commercial cases) was the provi-
sion for trial by a three-judge court, with two of the judges,
called people's assessors, chosen from the general population for
ten-day periods. The Civil Code dealt in traditional terms with
such matters as legal capacity, persons, corporations, legal trans-
actions, statute of limitations, property, mortgages, landlord and
tenant, contracts and torts, unjust enrichment, inheritance....
No American lawyer would be shocked by the provision that
"by the contract of sale one party (the seller) undertakes to trans-
fer property to the ownership of another party (the buyer), while
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
23
the buyer undertakes to accept the property and to pay the price
agreed upon."'
Law did exist in the Soviet Union, and well within the parameters of
law in the West. In its provenance Soviet law was international and het-
erogeneous. In its operative scope, however, it was inflexibly bound by
the borders of the nation, and nothing better illustrates this than the
brute fact of geography that made Soviet criminal law absolute in its
power but limited in the extent of its exercise. This body of law was
peculiar to the nation in which it was housed. Its "doctrine of analogy"
was uniquely charged to criminalize acts not otherwise prohibited;2
that unique charge made it frame-dependent, limited to one particular
locale. The "Soviet" in the Soviet Criminal Code and the Soviet Crimi-
nal Procedure Code both licensed and circumscribed. It was key to
what these laws were: instruments of repression all powerful within
one nation, but not extendable anywhere else, with no power abroad. I
want to look at these geographical limits of law in the context of one
particular individual, the poet Osip Mandelstam, someone fated to live
and die within those geographical limits, but permeated all the same by
an alternate jurisdiction.
Mandelstam, probably the greatest Russian poet of the twentieth
century, was a poet who had serious run-ins with that adjective, "Rus-
sian." The law of the land was never much to his taste, and never much
on his side. In 1934, he brought upon himself what Nadezhda Mandel-
stam, his wife (and soon to be his widow), would call his "rendezvous
with the State."3 This rendezvous came at the heels of a poem recited to
a small circle of friends. Usually called the "Stalin Epigram," it includes
details such as "the ten thick worms his fingers," and the "huge laugh-
ing cockroaches on his top lips." The poem ends with these lines:
He forges decrees in a line like horseshoes,
One for the groin, one the forehead, temple, eye.
He rolls the executions on his tongue like berries.
He wishes he could hug them like big friends from home.4
The Stalin Epigram was never written down. It was heard by no more
than five or six people. Nonetheless, the incident was reported to the
authorities, and Mandelstam was arrested in due course. In fact, he was
24
THE PLACE OF LAW
arrested twice. On the night of May 13, 1934, he was taken by the secret
police to their headquarters in the Lubianka Prison, interrogated, and
later sentenced to three years of exile. He had a reprieve in 1937. Then,
on May 2, 1938, he was arrested a second time. This time he was sen-
tenced to a labor camp in Eastern Siberia, and he died on his way there,
probably on December 27, 1938.5
Mandelstam's arrest, both times, was strictly within the provisions
of Soviet law. The second arrest in 1938 was authorized by the People's
Commissariat of Internal Affairs, or NKVD. The arrest took place
before guilt was established, but this was not a procedural irregularity.
Pretrial arrests were perfectly legal according to Article 104 of the
Soviet Criminal Procedure Code, which stated:
In all cases of detention of a suspect (Art. 100 of the Criminal
Procedure Code), the agencies of inquiry shall, within 24 hours,
send notification, with an indication of the bases of detention, to
the investigator in whose district the agency of inquiry is located
or to the nearest People's Judge.
Within 48 hours, counting from the moment of receipt of noti-
fication from the agency of inquiry of notification about a deten-
tion that has occurred, the investigator or the People's Judge
must confirm the detention or revoke it. Agencies of inquiry
shall change the measure of restraint upon receipt of a corre-
sponding notification from the agencies to which notification
was sent.6
The NKVD, in short, had the legal power to detain a suspect on its own
authority. After the arrest had taken place, the case would then go to a
sentencing agency, which had 48 hours to confirm or revoke this action.
In Mandelstam's case, this sentencing agency was something called the
Special Board. This was actually an administrative-rather than judi-
cial-body, but it was authorized to make legal decisions, because a
resolution of November 5, 1934 (SZ SSSR, 1935, No. 11, item 84) gave it
the explicit power to impose sentences upon "persons recognized as
especially dangerous," without any need to name a specific crime com-
mitted.7 Mandelstam was sentenced on those grounds. The Special
Board reached the verdict that he was guilty of "counterrevolutionary
activity," which meant five years in a correctional labor camp.8 The ver-
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
25
dict was read out to Mandelstam, and his signature was part of the trial
records to show that he was a witness to his sentencing.9
I want to highlight the Soviet Criminal Procedure Code and the com-
pliance with that code in Mandelstam's arrest and trial, in order to
make two related arguments. First, simply to repeat the obvious, the
judicial apparatus was very much in place in the Soviet Union. We
might think of it as a kind of legalized lawlessness, as Richard Pipes
does,'o but the fact remains that it was there, solidly there. There was
due process for Mandelstam; his pretrial arrest was procedurally in
order; there was an arrest warrant, a record of his detention and trans-
fer; the sentencing was done by an authorized agency and in compli-
ance with a specific resolution.
There was no violation of the Soviet Criminal Procedure Code in the
conduct of the NKVD and the Special Board. This brings me to my sec-
ond point. These two agencies were law-abiding, and they could afford
to be, because within the Soviet Union there was of course a very com-
fortable fit between the formal codes of law and the agencies charged
with their enforcement. Both were cut from the same cloth; both were
the handiwork of the same nation-state. But to say that is also to say
there was no gap, no spatial separation, between the adjudicative vehi-
cle and what it adjudicated. The Criminal Procedure Code was not
"above" the rest of the Soviet regime. On the contrary, it was continu-
ous with that regime, a handmaiden to the latter and bound by its
terms of servitude. Its codification took place inside territorial borders;
that territorial genesis gave it its operative scope. It had teeth only
because the power of the state was there to back it up. By the same
token, because this legal might was so much the might of the state, it
must come to an end at just that point where the Soviet Union did.
Jurisdiction and sovereignty were here coincidental.
Soviet law was no doubt an extreme case in being so territorially
predicated. This extreme case, however, does say something about the
general rule. Even outside the Soviet Union, the demarcating lines
among different bodies of law are by and large the demarcating lines of
geopolitics." As Bruce Ackerman points out, "The typical American
judge would not think of learning from an opinion by the German or
French Constitutional Court. Nor would the typical scholar."'2
National laws are both consolidated and bounded by their spatial
nonextendability. Even in those rare cases (such as extradition) where
26
THE PLACE OF LAW
the nonextendability of foreign law is briefly suspended, the newswor-
thiness of those events suggests that they are anomalies.13 Such rare
instances aside, legal jurisdiction and national sovereignty are one.
This explains why adjectives that designate territorial entities-French,
German, Israeli, Iranian-can serve as adequate designations for differ-
ent bodies of law.
Jurisdiction without Sovereignty
And yet a sea change is afoot. In this era of globalization, "world con-
stitutionalism" is no longer a wishful or exotic-sounding term even
among U.S. constitutional scholars.14 Among international lawyers,
this is more obviously the case. The classic "Westphalian" model
with its operative landscape defined by territoriality, recognizing only
sovereign states as legitimate players-is increasingly seen as out-
moded, ill-equipped for the emerging legal order of the twenty-first
century.15 Concepts such as NGOs (nongovernmental organizations),
"nonstate actors," and "transnational adjudication" have entered the
lexicon as never before.'6 What is at stake, once again, is the nature,
scope, and action-bearing entities of this new legal order. Law's operat-
ing theater, its coincidence or noncoincidence with territorial regimes,
the demarcation of its normative fields and the naming of participatory
players: all of these are up for grabs. And, as far as the two growth areas
of international law are concerned-the protection of the environment
and the protection of human rights-global governance is more than
just a dream.'7 It is an actualized fact, here to stay.
It is in this context, in face of this sharp challenge to the territoriality,
sovereignty, and primacy of the nation-state, that I want to invoke the
cumulative time of literature as a robust and well-tested instance of
global governance, a NGO avant la lettre. My claim is that literary cul-
ture is planetary in scope: planetary both in its temporal extension and
in its global reach. Its jurisdiction cuts across the static lines of the
geopolitical map, even as it cuts across the segmented planes of
national chronology. This view of literature not only suggests an alter-
native to the territorial paradigm of law, it also brings into focus a pow-
erful challenge to what Benedict Anderson sees the temporal precondi-
tion of the nation-state, what he calls a regime of "simultaneity."
In Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nation-
alism, Anderson argues that "the genesis of nationalism" is predicated
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
27
on "an idea of homogeneous, empty time, in which simultaneity is, as
it were, transverse, cross-time, marked not by prefiguring and fulfil-
ment, but by temporal coincidence, and measured by clock and calen-
dar."'8 National time for Anderson is synchronized time: synchronized
by mechanical devices, and synchronized, as well, by "the novel and
the newspaper" (30). These purveyors of simultaneity unite the nation
under an official "now," binding all its citizens to the same temporal
plane. Such an account of national time does work well with the Soviet
Union, a nation founded on a chronological script and eager to clock
itself according to that script: as the designated successor to capitalism,
the final act on the world stage.19 The very legitimacy of this nation
rested on the timetable it claimed for itself.
But, as we know, that timetable could not actually clock the lives of all
Soviet citizens. What was there to undermine its regime? What alternate
time frames messed up its chronological rigor? Obviously, there are
multiple candidates here. In what follows I concentrate on just one, a
temporal formation I call "literary culture." What I have in mind is a
large-scale phenomenon, an extended and continuously compounded
duration, made up not just of a handful of people who write but, above
all, of an entire population who reads, a population spread across coun-
tries and centuries. This large-scale duration is activated whenever
words are lifted from the page, whenever they are taken up by readers
"alien" to the author in space and time. This alienating process is crucial,
because it is only when words are taken out of their original contexts that
literary culture can become planetary, can become a cumulative and
extraterritorial force. Going back thousands of years and going forward
even more indeterminately, literary culture holds out to its readers
stretches of time so far flung, so deeply recessed and so wildly unpre-
dictable that they can never gel with the synchronic plane of national
chronology. Reading creates time warps. It disturbs the official now.
Such, indeed, was the effect of reading on Osip Mandelstam. I focus
on him, then, not only as a poet but above all as a reader, spurred on by
long-lasting words to become a kind of temporal noncitizen, out of step
with the official chronology of the Soviet Union and surviving beyond
it perhaps for just that reason. It is worth noting, then, that, amidst the
nation-based legality of his arrest, there was one small, irregular detail,
a hint of an alternate jurisdiction. That arrest did not come as a surprise;
Mandelstam had the luxury of preparing for it. Those preparations
were recorded by Nadezhda:
28
THE PLACE OF LAW
M. obtained an edition of the Divine Comedy in small format and
always had it with him in his pocket, just in case he was arrested
not at home but in the street. You could be arrested anywhere
sometimes they came for you at your place of work, and some-
times you were lured out to another place on a false pretext and
no one ever heard of you again.... When M. went to Samatikha
(the place where he was arrested the second time), he left his
pocket Dante in Moscow and took another, rather more bulky
edition. I do not know whether he managed to keep it until he
reached the transit camp [at Vtoraya Rechka] near Vladivostok,
where he died. I somehow doubt it: in the camps under Yezhov
and Stalin, nobody could give any thought to books.20
In a moment of extreme political terror, Mandelstam-Russian and
Jewish-saw fit to immerse himself in a medieval Christian poem. The
immersion did not save him. He died, as mentioned, on his way to a
labor camp. Still, in spite of this biological triumph of the Criminal
Code, it was not a trivial fact that a medieval poem was still around,
after hundreds of years, to be read by a Soviet citizen. That fact gave
Mandelstam a different reference point, a jurisdiction not reducible to
the arm of the Soviet government.21
Conflicting Time Frames
Mandelstam's love of Dante-the physical presence of the poetry
inside his pocket-makes it clear that literary culture is above all an
extended temporal formation, at odds with territorial sovereignty and
numerical chronology. Authors centuries and thousands of miles apart
can turn out to be inseparable. Their adjacency stems from a linguistic
bond, and has little to do with the metrical structure articulated by
numbers, whether these numbers take the form of latitudes and longi-
tudes or whether they take the form of dates. The remoteness or prox-
imity of linguistic events is not something that lends itself to uniform
calibrations. It cannot be expressed as a numerical constant: as one hun-
dred years or one thousand miles. No mileage can tell us how far one
author is from another; no dates can tell us who is close to whom.
This nonnumerical structure of space and time might be described
by borrowing a concept from Einstein: "relativity of simultaneity."22
Einstein uses this to challenge the notion of a universal present, a
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
29
"now" everywhere enforced, a temporal plane that synchronizes the
entire globe, putting it under a unified chronology. There is no such
synchronized plane, Einstein says, because space and time are not
absolute givens but operational effects, deriving their particular
lengths and widths from the relative motion of the frames in which
measurements are being taken. What is simultaneous in one frame
might not be simultaneous in another; what registers as "now" in one
might not so register elsewhere.
Of course, for Einstein, relativity of simultaneity is a strictly mathe-
matical concept: it is a description of the geometry of space-time. I have
argued elsewhere that this concept can also be understood nonmathe-
matically, that it can be transposed to describe the temporal effects
engendered by reading.23 Transposed in this way, relativity of simul-
taneity highlights the existence of conflicting time frames in any popu-
lation of readers. The apparent unity of the numerical date gives way to
a plurality of experiential "nows." These nows are not discretely or uni-
formly slotted; they do not all line up on the same synchronic plane.
They owe their shapes to the irregular compass of words: their differ-
ent antecedents, different extensions of meaning. Nows are different
because reading habits are, because the strength of linguistic bonds can
have a drastic effect on the distance between any two users of words.
Two thousand years and two thousand miles can sometimes register as
near simultaneity; ten years and ten miles can sometimes pose an
impassable gulf. Thanks to this elasticity, the time frame experienced
by any reader is singly individuated, unlike anyone else's. It has its
own sequence, its own coevals. Its relational fabric is separately cut,
stretching and bulging in odd places. It is not synchronized with the
numerical "now" on any standard calendar.
Understood in this sense-as the temporal disunity engendered by
reading-relativity of simultaneity suggests that the literary contin-
uum is anarchic: impossible to regulate, impossible to police. Where lit-
erary bonds are intensified by particular circumstances-as happens
with Mandelstam and Dante-space and time can undergo the most
astonishing contraction, can turn a standardized metrical unit into a
virtual zero, bringing supposedly remote objects into direct contact.
Space and time, in short, have no absolute jurisdiction when it comes to
the bond between texts and readers. Not a sovereign grid, they are
molded instead by the actions and passions of words. They can behave
like "a kind of fan,"24 as Mandelstam says. The fan can be folded up,
30
THE PLACE OF LAW
putting Italy in the immediate vicinity of Russia, and making strange
bedfellows out of the fourteenth and the twentieth centuries.
Alien Life-Forms
This folded fan denationalized Dante and Mandelstam both: making
each Italian and not Italian, Russian and not Russian. In Mandelstam's
case, denationalization began with his attempt to learn Italian to read
Dante. He was joined by Anna Akhmatova. The two poets would com-
pare notes, testing each other's memory, savoring every word from that
alien tongue that had ceased to be alien. "Poetry itself is one enormous
quotation," Akhmatova would later note.25 Mandelstam might have
said the same. One would taunt the other: "Do you remember this line?"
"Did you notice that wonderful bit?" Then they would settle down to
read "aloud together, pointing out the passages they liked best, sharing
their finds with each other."26 Spending so much time among these
barely domesticated words-so much time away from his supposedly
native tongue-Mandelstam ended up being a caricature of a national
poet. He was, of course, not Italian. But then, neither was he completely
Russian. Instead, we might think of him, as he says, as a "translator by
calling, by birth," a "foreign emissary from a non-existent phonetic
kingdom."27 Translation was the actual job he had, what he did for a liv-
ing, when his official status as a pariah barred him from all other jobs.
But he also lived off it in a deeper sense, as Clarence Brown suggests,
consigning himself to it as to "a sort of intellectual Siberia."28
This intellectual Siberia is not exactly a Soviet address. Its terrain,
like its provenance, cannot be exclusively localized within one nation.
To be sure, the intellectual Siberia has something to do with the territo-
rial Siberia, but this territorial alignment might not be the primary one,
certainly not the only one. Two frames of reference, at least, are
involved here, one playing upon the other and relativizing the other.
For the very presence of a foreign tongue-the very meaningfulness of
that tongue-already suggests a counterpoint to the entity called the
nation, showing up its limits, its failure to dictate an exact match
between the linguistic and the territorial. Every intellectual Siberia is an
affront to the sovereignty of the state. It points to dimensions of space
and time not fully nationalized because not fully rationalized, space
and time not conforming to an official number, not integrated by a uni-
fied metric. Translation not only turns a foreign language into Russian,
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
31
it also puts tremendous pressure on the native tongue:29 alienates it,
puts it into perspective, throws it into a linguistic continuum more tur-
bulent and more alive than the inert lines of a geopolitical map.
This linguistic continuum is the basis for a limited freedom. It is the
freedom of an alien life-form: a form of extension and duration not
matching those of the nation, and perhaps not coming to an end with
the latter's demise. This alien life-form sustains every author and every
translator, as Mandelstam makes clear in "To the German Language":
Destroying myself, contradicting myself,
like the moth flying into the midnight flame,
suddenly all that binds me to our language
tempts me to leave it....
An alien language will be my swaddling clothes.
Long before I dared to be born
I was a letter of the alphabet, a verse like a vine,
I was the book that you all see in dreams.30
Under political repression, the only life a poet can have is nonbiologi-
cal. Wislawa Szymborska, writing in Poland in 1970, made the same
point:
When in danger the sea-cucumber divides itself in two ...
We know how to divide ourselves, how true, we too.
But only into a body and an interrupted whisper.
Into body and poetry.31
The latter alone has a chance for rebirth in a different tongue. Of course,
that chance depends on events altogether accidental: the luck of foreign
translators adopting the poems, the luck of foreign readers picking
them up. Haphazard as this might seem, many of Mandelstam's poems
were indeed translated, wrapped in swaddling clothes made in Eng-
land, France, and the United States, long before they were published in
the Soviet Union.
There is an ontological mismatch between literary culture and terri-
torial sovereignty, between the deep time of a linguistic continuum and
the finite borders of geopolitics. The swaddling clothes of foreign lan-
guages highlight that fact. They highlight what happens to official bor-
32
THE PLACE OF LAW
ders and official timetables when texts are born again and again, into
different countries, different centuries. Nonbiological reproduction cre-
ates a life-form that the nation-state cannot destroy. It turns a seem-
ingly bounded text into something far more random, scattered by cir-
cumstances across the length and width of the globe. The very life of
literature depends on such randomizations. Rather than being stuck in
one national context-and saying predictable things within that con-
text-a literary text becomes a new semantic template, a new form of
the legible, each time it crosses a national border. Global transit makes
for the unexpected extension, triangulation, and transformation of its
meaning. This fact alone challenges the power of the territorial as a
determining force in literature. The space-time coordinates of any
given text are not only fluid when they first come into being, poorly
captured by the map of geopolitics, they are also subsequently and
unforeseeably revisable, induced by their temporal and spatial dis-
placements to play new tricks with the static borders of the nation.
With every new translation they punch a hole in those borders, an
incline that rolls outward:
The earth is at its roundest on Red Square
And its unchained curve is hard,
On Red Square the earth is at its roundest
And its curve, rolling all the way down to the rice fields,
Is unexpectedly expansive
While there are still any slaves on the earth.32
Territorial sovereignty, its incontestable might in one locale, forces the
mind to think globally. The earth on Red Square is roundest because,
for anyone who does not wish to be chained to that spot, this bit of
earth must be taken as a curve, an arc of a larger circumference. That
circumference, rather than being a slavish copy of its origins, is an off-
center set of vibrations, chaotic and tangential. It expands with the
more or less random accretion of signifying moments, emerging at var-
ious temporal and spatial removes.
Ruptured Chronology
Nor is this only a twentieth-century phenomenon. Indeed, the same
alien life-form, the same nonbiological duration that permeates Man-
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
33
delstam he attributes also to Dante. "Having combined the uncombin-
able, Dante altered the structure of time." What results is a "synchro-
nism of events, names and traditions severed by centuries."33 Dante is
not a slave of chronology either. He too creates adjacencies on grounds
other than numerical dates. Mandelstam pays tribute to this heresy in
this portrait:
What is Dantean erudition?
Aristotle, like a double-winged butterfly, is edged
with the Arabian border of Averroes.
Averrois, che il gran comento feo
(Inferno, IV, 144)
Here the Arab Averroes accompanies the Greek Aristotle.
They are both components of the same drawing. They can both
find room on the membrane of a single wing.
The conclusion of Canto IV of the Inferno is truly an orgy of
quotations. I find here a pure and unalloyed demonstration of
Dante's keyboard of references.
A keyboard stroll around the entire horizon of Antiquity.
Some Chopin polonaise in which an armed Caesar with a
gryphon's eyes dances alongside Democritus, who had just fin-
ished splitting matter into atoms.34
According to Mandelstam, the Divine Comedy is a fan that has folded
away the fifteen hundred years separating Aristotle from Averroes,
the twelfth-century Arab philosopher. These two are paired up, both
of them contemporaries of Dante's in the fourteenth century. The fan
also folds in Chopin, not exactly around when Dante was alive but
eventually to be born, the supposed Frenchness of whose music Man-
delstam traces instead to Florentine origins. And he does not stop
there. For good measure he also throws in Democritus, invoked by
Dante in Inferno IV.136,35 and catapulted now from the fifth century
B.C. to the fourteenth, and onward to the twentieth and beyond.
This might seem a bizarre description of a medieval poem, but what
Mandelstam is trying to highlight here is a giddy voluminousness
peculiar to Dante, innocent of anything that might be called chronolog-
ical decorum. Balloonlike, Dante's metaphors yoke together terms so
disparate, so perilously strung out, as to leave the poem hanging by a
34
THE PLACE OF LAW
hair across vast temporal and spatial distances. Something of that gid-
diness can be seen in these lines from Paradiso XII:
As two concentric arcs of equal hue,
are seen as they bend through the misty clouds
when Juno tells her handmaid to appear
the outer from the inner one an echo,
like to the longing voice of her whom love
consumed as morning sun consumes the dew
and reassure the people here below
that by the covenant God made with Noah,
they have no need to fear another Flood
even so those sempiternal roses wreathed
twin garlands round us as the outer one
was lovingly responding to the inner.
(XII.lo-21)36
Dante seems to see nothing wrong mixing Greek mythology with bibli-
cal allusions, mentioning Juno and her handmaid, Iris, goddess of the
rainbow, in the same breath as Noah and the Flood. Also in the same
breath he mentions Echo, consumed by her love for Narcissus "as
morning sun consumes the dew," until nothing is left of her but her
"longing voice." Jupiter's heavens and Jehovah's heavens seem to have
merged into one. The same rainbow brightens the horizon of both. And
nimble figures of speech hop from one to the other: Echo is both the
name of a nymph and the name for the mutuality of the blessed revolv-
ing in their concentric circles. Thanks to Dante, centuries of readers
have swallowed such temporal heresies with barely a gulp.37
For Mandelstam, such temporal heresies are the largest gifts poetry
has to offer, to reader and writer alike. This is not the familiar claim
about the "timelessness" of literature. Mandelstam's point is much
more interesting than that. To him, the "anachronism"38 of the Divine
Comedy comes about not because the poem is timeless but because it is
timeful. It is full of time, densely populated, home to each of the cen-
turies bearing signs of human life. This is a home not numbered by a
metric, not sequenced by a chronological axis. A continuum, it grants
adjacency to any two points in space and time. And since it goes for-
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
35
ward as well as backward, it stretches the life of every finite point to a
potential infinity. This is why Aristotle and Averroes are both here;
why latecomers such as Chopin can be included; and why Democritus,
exponent of an ancient "atomic theory" in the fifth century B.C., can be
said to have lived out his extended life through the extended life of the
poem, surviving with the help of the Divine Comedy to "split matter into
atoms" in the twentieth century.39
An "anachronistic" poem, as Mandelstam uses the term, is one that
makes the world both cumulative and nonsequential. It gathers
together all coordinates, all points in the life of the planet, paying no
attention to their supposed remoteness or proximity. In this way, the
human species articulates itself across space and time, its signature
coterminous with its habitat. As a form of duration and extension, lit-
erature is thus a heresy, an insult and an affront, to the finiteness that is
the norm of biological organisms and territorial jurisdictions. This
heresy allows human beings to have a collective life, not identical to the
life span of a perishable individual or a perishable nation. Against the
robust continuum of the Divine Comedy, either of these life-spans might
look like "less than a wink of the eyelash."40
Mandelstam, who learned about Einstein during his stay in
Kharkov,4' might have referred to this continuum as the "relativity of
simultaneity." He did, in fact, begin one of his essays, "On the Nature
of the Word," with an explicit tribute to Einstein: "Due to the quantita-
tive change in the content of events occurring over a given time inter-
val, the concept of a unit of time has begun to falter, and it is no accident
that contemporary mathematical science has advanced the principle of
relativity."42 For anyone living under Stalin, this relativity of simul-
taneity is not an esoteric idea. It is a living fact, a political fact, the only
recourse against the absolute tyranny of an absolute synchronic plane.
A long past and a long future are signs of hope. And hopelessness, con-
versely, is to be caught in a time slot eternal in its territoriality. This is
the condition of hell. But hell, Mandelstam also insists, is a temporal
effect, the effect of a present that has everything under its thumb. That
thumb shrinks in size the moment we can bring to bear upon it a dif-
ferent time frame, different verb tenses. This, for Mandelstam, is the
central meaning of Dante. Above all it is the meaning of Canto X of the
Inferno, a canto driven by the contrary "forms of verb tenses: the per-
fective and imperfective past, the subjunctive past, even the present
and the future are all categorically and authoritatively presented."43
36
THE PLACE OF LAW
This jumble of tenses is occasioned by Dante's and Virgil's visit to the
sixth circle of hell, the circle of the heretics. Among these, none is more
heretical than Farinata, a Ghibelline who is proud and, of course, unre-
generate, who, hearing the Florentine tongue from Dante's lips, simply
cannot hold his own tongue.
Nonterritorial Time
Dante, already frightened, now draws closer to Virgil. It is at this point
that the present tense enters the scene, in a little cry of annoyance. Vir-
gil has no patience with such slinking and shrinking on Dante's part.
And he is not too ceremonious about it. "Volgiti: che fai?" "Turn
around: What are you doing?" Most readers would simply read this as
an offhand rebuke. Mandelstam turns it into a capsule summary of hell,
hell as a verb tense:
The horror of the present tense is given here, some kind of terror
praesentis. Here the unalloyed present is taken as a sign intro-
duced to ward off evil. The present tense, completely isolated
from both the future and the past, is conjugated like pure fear,
like danger.44
The horror of the present tense is perhaps more vivid to Mandelstam
than to Dante. Still, even for the latter, hell is hell precisely because its
time is sealed, because its torments take the form of an iron necessity, a
here and now from which all doors are closed. What is striking about
Farinata, though, is that for him the doors are not closed, at least not the
door to the past. That remains open, and the traffic through it is con-
stant and uninterrupted. Farinata's love for Florence is as lively as ever;
its familiar accents stir him even in hell. Indeed, it soon becomes clear
that if Farinata is "in" hell, it is only in the weakest possible sense. No
full containment comes with that preposition. His heart and mind are
elsewhere, still caught up in the past, a Florentine past in which he
takes great pride and which, for him, remains the eternal reference
point. It is from that reference point that he asks Dante: "Chi fuor li
maggior tui?" "Who were your ancestors?" Here of all places, ancestry
is still the first thing to find out. The question is rude, crude, effortlessly
insulting, because Farinata, great nobleman that he was, still has the
right to exact that bit of information and in just that tone of voice. When
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
37
told, he lifts his eyebrows a little, half in recognition and half in disdain.
And he persists in both veins: "Bitter enemies of mine they were / and
of my ancestors and of my party; / I had to scatter them not once but
twice."45 Even in hell, what matters the most to Farinata is the memory
of that scattering, the grim satisfaction of it, not once but twice. That
memory is untouched by hell, and forever untouchable. Because Fari-
nata is his memory: a memory prior to hell and external to hell, and
enfolding him forever in that priority and externality.
To Mandelstam, the powerful "past tense" of "Chi fuor li maggior
tui" explodes "like a mighty tuba."46 Hell does not exactly crumble
with that sound, but it is no longer what it purports to be. Its eternal
present has been punctured, shown to be not sovereign, not absolute,
not even governed by the same verb tense. It cannot banish the echoes
of an alien tongue, and it cannot erase the memories of an earthly city,
both of which make a mockery of its less than unified "now." Indeed,
hell does not even have the power to inflict the worst suffering on its
inmates. When told by Dante that the Ghibellines have been defeated
and sent into exile but, unlike the Guelfs, have not "learned the art" of
returning, Farinata counters with this lament: "if they have badly
learned that art, it is worse torment to me than this bed."47 Just as he
loves Florence the best, so he is pained the most by what he sees as its
misfortunes. Nothing in hell can compete with that. Farinata will never
be anything other than what he was: a Florentine, a Ghibelline, some-
one who lived by the sword and revered only the sword. No length of
sojourn in hell would make him a well-behaved inmate.
Surprisingly, the power of the past tense is not even unique to Fari-
nata, so haughty, so magnificent, and so obviously a heretic. Canto X is
not the sole habitat of one individual. Another Florentine is there. This
turns out to be Cavalcante, father of Dante's best friend, Guido. Listen-
ing for some time to the exchange between Dante and his neighbor, he
can finally stand it no longer. Suddenly raising himself up, he looks
around eagerly to see if anyone is with Dante. Not finding anyone, he
cries out:
"Where is my son? Why is he not with you?"
"I do not come alone," I said to him,
"that one waiting over there guides me through here,
the one, perhaps your Guido held in scorn."...
Instantly, he sprang to his full height and cried,
38
THE PLACE OF LAW
"What did you say? He held? Is he not living?
The Day's sweet light no longer strikes his eyes?"
And when he heard the silence of my delay
responding to his question, he collapsed
into his tomb, not to be seen again.
(Inferno, X.58-63, 67-72)48
Like Farinata, Cavalcante is Florentine, but almost the exact opposite of
his compatriot. Farinata's firm and weighty words, the stately balance
of his syntax, give way to Cavalcante's "irregular and plaintive ...
questions."49 The civic and military glories of Florence are now set
aside, leaving a single tie, an affective tie, in the foreground. Cavalcante
loves his son, believes in his genius, and wants him to be still alive, his
eyes bathed in the sweet light of Tuscany. He wants him to be Dante's
honored companion in this tour of hell. But Guido is nowhere in sight.
Not seeing him, and catching Dante's words-"ebbe a disdegno,"
"held in contempt"-he can only repeat that verb in dumb terror:
"Come dicesti? 'Egli ebbe?' non viv'elli ancora?" "What did you say? He
held? Is he not living?"
The word ebbe, a slip of a word, will travel across the centuries, com-
ing home to Mandelstam as the sound of the "fated past perfect."5° As
in the exchange with Farinata, the human drama here revolves around
a dramatized verb tense. The kinship between these two is all the more
significant for their obvious difference. For Farinata, the word fuor is
summoned with all due deliberation; for Cavalcante, the word ebbe falls
like a bolt from the sky. Still, the two are the same: same kind of tem-
poral heretics. In his single-minded devotion to his son, and in his dev-
astation at the (mistaken) news of Guido's death, Cavalcante turns out
not to be a slave to the "now" of hell, just as Farinata is not a slave. His
reference point, too, remains anterior and exterior. He too will never be
anything other than what he was: a weakling, too easily broken, too
easily given to despair, but prior to hell in just that way, not a full-time
resident of the sixth circle.
Farinata and Cavalcante, one larger than life, the other not at all,
together give voice to the heresy of an unofficial "now." This heresy
infiltrates and permeates even where it does not altogether liberate.
Bursting in upon the supposedly closed doors of hell, it clashes either
as a "mighty tuba" or as "an oboe or clarinet."5' Either way, it lets loose
the force of the unsynchronized, the relativity of simultaneity. This
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
39
force breaks up the territorial sovereignty of hell. It also breaks up
another kind of territorial sovereignty. The Soviet Union has never
been airtight; Mandelstam and Dante make it less so.
NOTES
1. Harold J. Berman, Justice in the U.S.S.R., rev. ed. (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1963), 34. Berman's account of Soviet law is substantiated by
Robert Conquest, Justice and the Legal System in the U.S.S.R. (New York: Praeger,
1968), 15.
2. Berman, Justice in the U.S.S.R., 35-36; Conquest, Justice and the Legal Sys-
tem, 74, 138-39.
3. Nadezhda Mandelstam, Hope against Hope, trans. Max Hayward (New
York: Athenaeum, 1970), 6.
4. Osip Mandelstam, Selected Poems, trans. Clarence Brown and W. S. Mer-
win (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), 70.
5. Mandelstam, Hope against Hope, 3-41, 360-97.
6. Peter B. Maggs, The Mandelstam and "Der Nister" Files: An Introduction to
Stalin-Era Prison and Labor Camp Records (Armonk, N.Y.: M. E. Sharpe, 1996), 13.
7. Ibid., 27.
8. Ibid., 28; Document M-3.
9. Ibid., 30-31; Document M-3.
10. Richard Pipes, Legalized Lawlessness: Soviet Revolutionary Justice (London:
Alliance, 1980).
11. For a helpful analysis of "law's space," the constitution of law as a fact
of political geography, see Paul W. Kahn, The Cultural Study of Law (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1999), 55-65.
12. Bruce Ackerman, "The Rise of World Constitutionalism," Virginia Law
Review 83 (1997): 772.
13. I am thinking, for instance, of the attempt to have Pinochet extradited
for trial in Chile.
14. See, for instance, Ackerman, "Rise of World Constitutionalism";
Laurence R. Helfer and Anne-Marie Slaughter, "Toward a Theory of Effective
Supranational Adjudication," Yale Law Journal 10o7 (1997): 273-391; Annelise
Riles, "Wigmore's Treasure Box: Comparative Law in the Era of Information,"
Harvard International Law Journal 40 (1999): 221-83; Mark Tushnet, "The Possi-
bilities of Comparative Constitutional Law," Yale Law Journal lo8 (1999):
1225-1309.
15. Stephen D. Krasner argues that "the Westphalian model has never been
an accurate description of many of the entities that have been called states." See
his "Compromising Westphalia," International Security 20 (1995-96): 115-51.
For normative proposals of nonterritorial paradigms, see John Gerard Ruggie,
"Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International Rela-
tions," International Organization 47 (1993): 139-74; Ruggie, Constituting the
40
THE PLACE OF LAW
World Polity: Essays on International Institutionalization (New York: Routledge,
1998); Christopher Harding and C. L. Lim, "The Significance of Westphalia: An
Archaeology of the International Legal Order," in Essays and Commentary on the
European and Conceptual Foundations of Modern International Law, ed. Christo-
pher Harding and C. L. Lim (Boston: Nijhoff, 1999), 1-23.
16. The literature here is vast. See, for instance, Virginia Haufler, "Crossing
the Boundary between Public and Private: International Regimes and Non-
state Actors," in Regime Theory and International Relations (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1993), chap. 5; Peter Spiro, "New Global Communities: Nongovernmen-
tal Organizations in International Decision-Making Institutions," Washington
Quarterly 18 (1994): 45-57; Bringing Transnational Relations Back In: Non-state
Actors, Domestic Structures, and International Institutions, ed. Thomas Risse-Kap-
pen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995); Global Law without a State,
ed. Gunther Teubner (Aldershot: Dartmouth Gower, 1997); Helfer and Slaugh-
ter, "Effective Supranational Adjudication"; Margaret Keck and Kathryn
Sikkink, Activists beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Relations
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1998).
17. See, for instance, Peter Haas, "Introduction: Epistemic Communities
and International Policy Coordination," International Organization 46 (1992):
1-35; Kathryn Sikkink, "Human Rights, Principled Issue-Networks, and Sover-
eignty in Latin America," International Organization 47 (1993) 411-41; Thomas
Princen and Matthias Finger, Environmental NGOs in World Politics (New York:
Routledge, 1994); Martha Finnemore, "Constructing Norms of Humanitarian
Intervention," in The Culture of National Security, ed. Peter Katzenstein (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 153-85; Ronnie D. Lipschutz, Global
Civil Society and Global Environmental Governance (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1996); Paul Wapner, Environmental Activism and World Civic
Politics (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996); Kal Raustiala,
"States, NGOs, and International Environmental Institutions," International
Studies Quarterly 41 (1997): 719-40; Richard Price, "Reversing the Gun Sights:
Transnational Civil Society Targets Land Mines," International Organization 52
(1998): 613-44.
18. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and
Spread of Nationalism (London: Verso, 1983), 30.
19. For an interesting discussion of time and the Soviet Union, see Stephen
E. Hanson, Time and Revolution: Marxism and the Design of Soviet Institutions
(Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1997).
20. Mandelstam, Hope against Hope, 228.
21. No doubt for this reason, the Divine Comedy was important not only to
Mandelstam but also to many other Soviet authors, including Anna Akhma-
tova, Joseph Brodsky, and Aleksandr Solzhenitsyn.
22. "Relativity of Simultaneity" is the title of chapter 9 of Einstein's Relativ-
ity: The Special and the General Theory, trans. Robert W. Larson, 15th ed. (New
York: Crown Trade Paperbacks, 1961), 29.
23. Wai Chee Dimock, "A Theory of Resonance," PMLA 113 (1997): 1060-71.
TIME AGAINST TERRITORIALITY
41
24. Osip Mandelstam, "On the Nature of the Word," in Complete Critical
Prose, trans. Jane Gary Harris and Constance Link (New York: Vintage, 1997),
73.
25. The line "No, mozhet byt', poeziia sama- / Odna velikolepnaia tsitata"
is from Akhmatova, "Ne povtoriai-dusha tvoia bogata." I quote from Nancy
Pollak, Mandelstam the Reader (Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press, 1995),
4.
26. Mandelstam, Hope against Hope, 223.
27. Mandelstam, "Nature of the Word," 79.
28. Clarence Brown, Mandelstam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1973), 90.
29. Walter Benjamin, "The Task of the Translator," in Illuminations, trans.
Harry Zohn (New York: Schocken, 1969), 69-82, esp. 73.
30. Mandelstam, no. 266, in Selected Poems, 65.
31. Wislawa Szymborska, "Autonomia/Autonomy," in Sounds, Feelings,
Thoughts: Seventy Poems by Wislawa Szymborska, trans. Magnus J. Krynski and
Robert A. Maguire (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981), 136-37.
32. Mandelstam, no. 306, in Osip Mandelstam: Selected Poems, trans. James
Greene (New York: Penguin, 1991), 68.
33. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," in Complete Critical Prose,
282.
34. Ibid., 255.
35. Inferno IV.136, "Democrito, che '1 mondo a caso pone" [Democritus, who
ascribes the world to chance], Sinclair's translation.
36. Dante, The Divine Comedy, vol. 3, Paradise, trans. Mark Musa (New York:
Penguin, 1986), 144-45.
37. Of course, it is Christian theology-Christian teleology-that enables
Dante to see the entire course of time on the same synchronic plane. In this
sense, Dante is not heretical at all.
38. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 282.
39. By "atoms" Democritus meant small invisible particles differing from
each other only in size, shape, and motion. The modern atomic theory is far
more elaborate, assigning to atoms an internal structure with neutrons, pro-
tons, and electrons.
40. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 254.
41. Nadezhda Mandelstam, Hope Abandoned, trans. Max Hayward (New
York: Athenaeum, 1973), 74; Brown, Mandelstam, 97.
42. Mandelstam, "Nature of the Word," 73.
43. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 256.
44. Ibid.
45. "Fieramente furo avversi / a me e a miei primi e a mia parte, / si che per
due fiate li dispersi." Inferno, X.46-48.
46. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 257. He has actually made a
slight error here, misquoting the line as "Chi fuo li maggior tui."
47. Inferno, X.77-78. Sinclair's translation, 137.
42
THE PLACE OF LAW
48. "'mio figlio ov' &? Perch& non & ei teco?' / E io a lui: 'Da me stesso non
vegno: / colui ch'attende li per qui mi mena, / forse cui Guido vostro ebbe a
disdegno.' . . . / Di subito drizzato grido: 'Come / dicesti: "Egli ebbe"? Non
viv'elli ancora? / non fiere li occhi suoi il dolce lome?' / Quando s'accorse d'al-
cuna dimora / ch'io facea dinanzi alla risposta, / supin ricadde e piu non parve
fora." I use Musa's translation, 16o.
49. Auerbach points out that Cavalcante's lines "might have been modeled
after Andromache's in Aeneid, 3:310, that is, after a woman's lamentations." See
Erich Auerbach, Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature (Gar-
den City, NY: Doubleday, 1953), 158.
50. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 257. "Ebbe a disdegno" are
three of the most puzzled-over words in the Divine Comedy. For a reading of
these words, see Charles S. Singleton, "Inferno X: Guido's Disdain," MLN 77
(1962): 49-65. Robert Durling sums up the ambiguity of the verb tense: "in
addition to its meaning as a past absolute (Guido habitually disdained), a passato
remoto (Guido at a specific time did indeed disdain), or as a passato prossimo
(Guido just now disdained), also its meaning as a perfect (Guido no longer dis-
dains)." See Durling, "Farinata and the Body of Christ," Stanford Italian Review
2 (1981): 24-25.
51. Mandelstam, "Conversation about Dante," 257.
The Empty Place: Legal Formalities
and the Cultural State
Annelise Riles
This essay concerns the uses of technical legal rules concerning prop-
erty ownership in creating what I call an empty place. From the point of
view of contemporary cultural theory, the notion of an empty place is a
contradiction in terms. In the early 1990s, anthropologists, literary the-
orists, cultural geographers, and like-minded legal scholars argued for
an understanding of space and place as constructed and constructive in
nature.' These scholars emphasized the role of conceptions of place
aesthetic, geographic, political-in the construction of personal, group,
and national identities.2 Ideological constructions of space and place
were shown to play important roles in, for example, regimes of racial
exclusion.3 Likewise, displacement was taken to have consequences for
a loss of personal or group identity.4 And yet the socially constitutive
character of space also suggested that place remained available as a
resource of resistance and empowerment.5
Of particular interest, from the point of view of the theme of this col-
lection, was the role of law in the construction of place and vice versa.6
David Campbell, for example, has described how what he terms a
"political anthropology" of group identities informed the cartographic
orientation of international lawyers working in Bosnia, and how as a
result the solutions to the conflict there inscribed and enshrined nation-
alist ideologies within the geography of legally defined boundaries.7
This understanding of the mutually constitutive nature of law and
space was also taken as a source of hope: If law was constitutive of spa-
tial arrangements and vice versa, and spatial arrangements in turn
inscribed important notions of identity and politics, it followed that as
43
44
THE PLACE OF LAW
a socially constituted practice, law must be available for groups to rein-
terpret as an instrument of social change. For example, Nicholas Blom-
ley has described how notions of landscape at work in conceptions of
property become available as a resource for disempowered groups in
conflict with developers over urban development.8
These scholars definitively demolished the notion that there could
ever be such a thing as "empty" space and emphasized the ideological
uses of the notion in the European colonial project, or global capital-
ism.9 Lefebvre describes the concept of abstract space as "the locus and
environment of Reason,"'0 characterized by a will to authoritarian
domination, an emptying out of the "natural," and a "flattening" of
"social and 'cultural' spheres":
This modern state promotes and imposes itself as the stable cen-
ter-definitively-of (national) societies and spaces. As both the
end and the meaning of history.., it flattens the social and "cul-
tural" spheres. It enforces a logic that puts an end to conflicts
and contradictions."
Against this ideological notion of the emptiness of space, these
scholars proposed the concept of "place": they sought to reimagine the
passive, neutral space that is the "raw material" of capitalist philo-
sophical tracts as a receptacle for meaningful objects, actions, agents, or
ideologies'2 and also to demonstrate how local communities opposed
the forces of global capitalism by deploying ideas of place. This work
demonstrated that spaces gained psychological and symbolic reso-
nancel3 by the way they are experiencedl4 and "eulogized" as they are
imbued through memory with imaginative qualities.'5
From this point of view, the purposefully "cartographic" orientation
of the laws I will describe, and my own insistence on the possibility of
an empty place in this essay, will seem naive and politically troubling
in the way they fail to appreciate that people always imbue spaces with
political meaning (to deny this fact seems to give renewed voice to an
old ideological position that had taken much hard work to decon-
struct).16 For now, I simply want to note that in this literature place is
imagined as the product, and hence the cultural property of persons by
virtue of their capacity for meaning-making. What is given primacy in
this response to the "cartographic" obsession with space that character-
THE EMPTY PLACE
45
izes the tradition of property as economic means, is persons and their
creative propensity for knowledge/ownership.
In this essay, instead, I want to suggest that the very possibility of a
debate about the expressive qualities of a legally constituted place is
dependent on a particular notion of government and social life that I
will call the cultural state. I intend the term in two senses: First, I refer to
government organized according to theories of culture and cultural dif-
ference and devoted in ostensibly benevolent ways to the preservation
and elaboration of this difference. Nearly all states are to some degree
cultural states today. But second, I refer to a phenomenon that tran-
scends and encapsulates the character of government. Our "cultural
state" is a discursive state or condition in which the hegemony of cul-
ture, and of the kinds of arguments, assumptions, and aspirations that
produced the culture concept, is nearly absolute.
I want to trace out the consequences of the culturalist foundations of
the state practices with respect to an admittedly exotic and unique case,
the legal and political treatment of mixed-race peoples in the colonial
and precolonial state of Fiji. What makes Fiji interesting as a case of colo-
nial governmentality is that it represents the apotheosis of the vision of
cultural government I have described. Fiji was ceded to the British
Crown in 1874, at the moment at which theories of "culture" in the mod-
ern sense were first appearing on the academic stage. Fiji's first governor,
Arthur Gordon, the son of a prime minister, was deeply influenced by
the anthropology he had learned at Cambridge, and his project in Fiji
was to be an experiment in cultural rule. His native policies bear the
strong imprint of the evolutionary theories of Sir Henry Maine champi-
oned.17 In Fiji, the cultural state extended to the form of governance itself:
Gordon presented himself to his native subjects as a high chief among
chiefs and even accepted sevusevu (presentation of kava root as an
expression of chiefly respect) according to what he took to be Fijian cus-
tom. Successive governors took the matter even further by writing schol-
arly articles for anthropological journals and engaging in learned argu-
ments about the extent to which Gordon's policies, as a scientific matter,
had gotten the "facts" of Fijian culture right. Generations of critiques of
colonialism in Fiji have largely continued this tradition, albeit to opposite
ends, by asking to what extent Gordon's policies were built upon "essen-
tialist" notions of Fijian culture-"invented traditions"-and what
effects these essentialisms have had on those subjected to colonial rule.'8
46
THE PLACE OF LAW
The Fiji case brings into relief the less benevolent side of culturalism
as it is deployed in academic and popular debate, as in governmental
action. I focus on what happens to those people defined as "without
culture"-here, the so-called half-castes, or part-Europeans, or today,
just simply, but officially, "Others"-descendants of sexual unions
between foreigners and the indigenous population, many of whom
today live on small plots of land obtained by their ancestors.19 Since the
colonial era, these people have been defined through a discourse of
"illegitimacy": they were, in the government's eyes, the products of
illegitimate marriages and hence could claim neither European nor
Fijian citizenship. They were also culturally illegitimate-to a colonial
government devoted to good anthropological theories of culture, half-
castes represented, quite literally, the bastardization of Fijian culture.
For many of these "others," land has physically defined their space
in the polity. In each generation, the plots acquired by ancestors have
been further divided, and land is rarely sold outside the clan.20 Even
within this legally and spatially circumscribed sphere, however, Part-
Europeans confront the legal effects of their illegitimacy. For example,
until recently, most half-castes could not count on the rules of inheri-
tance that provided for land to pass to one's heirs in the absence of a
will because as "illegitimates"-children born out of wedlock-those
heirs would not be recognized. My hope is that this example will enable
a conversation about some of the consequences of the hegemony of cul-
ture outlined above. The second part of the essay turns to the uses Part-
European's made of a particular kind of legal institution, the land title
registration system. I argue that in Fiji, legal formalities created a set of
actual places shielded from the reach of the cultural state and also a set
of antihegemonic possibilities for living in the shadow of the hegemony
of identity and cultural politics.
The Cultural State
The Republic of Fiji consists of a group of South Pacific islands first col-
onized by the British in 1874 and independent since 1976. From the
beginning of the colonial project, the British colonial government
sought to address two competing concerns: how to turn a profit from
the resources of the colony and how to preserve native culture. Unlike
earlier colonies such as New Zealand and Australia, which were
"depopulated" of their aboriginal peoples in order to make room for
THE EMPTY PLACE
47
economic development, from its inception as a colony, the colonial gov-
ernment in Fiji sought to preserve its "native population." By the time
of Fiji's colonization, the modern, educated colonial administrator was
expected to act out of respect and appreciation for the special needs of
peoples at particular stages of evolutionary development.
Fiji had no major natural resources and was geographically iso-
lated. Brief attempts to develop a cotton industry prior to cession in
1874 had collapsed with the end of the American Civil War. The gov-
ernment's solution was to develop a small sugar industry.21 This pro-
ject presented the government with a problem, however: plantations
would require labor. Both the practical experience of other colonies
with indentured labor and the evolutionary theories of the day sug-
gested that to use Fijians as labor would mean the destruction of the
"native way of life." The colonial government's dual commitments to
preserving native culture and making the colony profitable
demanded a turn to another source of labor. In order to avoid turning
Fijians into laborers, therefore, Gordon arranged for large numbers of
indentured laborers to be brought to Fiji from India as plantation
workers on the theory that these Indians were already culturally
degenerate from generations of less culturally enlightened coloniza-
tion.22 From the beginning, therefore, the colonial government's twin
preoccupations of culture and economy were located in the two prin-
cipal populations of the colony, the Fijians and the Indians, respec-
tively. What followed were a series of problems for the colonial gov-
ernment concerning how to deny that Indians had a "culture" so that
they could be treated as belonging to the sphere of free-market capi-
talism in which, unlike Fijians, they were free to alienate their labor as
commodity.23
The cultural state, as it is exemplified in the admittedly extreme case
in Fiji, therefore, is a state devoted to capitalist economic development
within a world economy. Within that framework, "culture" emerges as
a kind of exception, a circumscribed project of its own that can be
accommodated within the larger economic project, and through which
the economic project can be given positive valence by turning economic
profits to a positive end. Capitalism serves as the means, in other words,
and cultural preservation as the end, although the end can never be
allowed to swallow the means.
In Fiji, the accommodation of these two competing projects, and
their elaboration as a relationship of means to ends, was achieved pri-
48
THE PLACE OF LAW
marily through policy toward land. One of the first acts of the colonial
government was to prohibit the sale of land by "natives," and to return
much of the land held by foreigners at the time of cession to its native
owners. A Land Claims Commission was established immediately
after cession to investigate the validity of every "European title" and
ultimately disallowed more than half of all claims.24
The commission proceeded on the basis of an anthropological the-
ory, extrapolated from Lewis Henry Morgan's evolutionary scheme,
that land was communally owned by Fijians and inalienable.25 Euro-
peans who had paid Fijian chiefs for land had not properly acquired
title the commission held, since they had paid the chief individually
rather than dealing with the communal group and since, in any case,
Fijians did not have a concept of alienability to speak of. What is impor-
tant for our purposes is that this framing of the issue in turn set up the
necessity of balancing the cultural realities against the legal require-
ments of the deed of cession, which explicitly promised that existing
land titles would not be overturned.26
The Land Claims Commission subjected title claims to three very
open-ended, subjective, and context-bound determinations: The first
concerned whether the original vendors had the right to dispose of the
land. This first requirement in turn demanded that the commission
hold hearings in every locale and gather ethnographic evidence from
diverse members of each Fijian community as to who was the rightful
chief, what was the nature of the landowning group, and what were its
lands. The second requirement for title was that the purchaser had paid
a fair price for the land. This requirement allowed the LCC to deny vast
numbers of claims out of hand based on its own concept of fairness. To
these, the LCC added a third requirement: "the buyer, or his successor,
to have occupied the land, whether by living on it, or by establishing a
plantation, or both."27 This final requirement most explicitly addressed
questions of equity-the commission would compromise its theory of
culture and allow the claim only where equitable factors, such as effi-
cient uses of the land or long-standing occupation, seemed to demand
it.28 Where claims were rejected, claimants could appeal to the Execu-
tive Council, and the governor could award title on one final open-
ended basis, that of an "ex gratia" award. Where the Land Claims Com-
mission or the governor allowed a claim, a certificate of title was issued
to the landholder.
The indeterminacy of these criteria has been critiqued from all sides
THE EMPTY PLACE
49
for both the bias entailed in judgments about fair price or who had the
right to dispose of land, and the administrative nightmare this process set
into play. For the present purposes, I want to note how the cultural state
deploys a particular type of administrative process: It is a loose, hands-
on, managerial, pragmatic process emphasizing case-by-case discre-
tionary decision making. The state's own criteria of decision are under-
stood to be compromised from the start; indeed, they are set up so that
they cannot help but be compromised. In this case, the balancing of the
legal requirements of the deed of cession against the cultural truths of
Fijian land tenure proceeded according to a second set of more substan-
tive policy criteria. Here again, however, the state faces a conflict between
its twin concerns: on the one hand, the preservation of cultural essences,
and on the other hand, the demands of capital and economic develop-
ment. To merit title, for example, land had to be productively used. But
on the other hand, what the government regarded as the less palatable
sides of capitalism such as speculation in land were to be reigned in
under the LCC's criteria so that speculators who simply owned large
tracts of land for future sale would have their claims disallowed.
At the conclusion of the LCC's work, land policy was bifurcated into
two regimes and land into two kinds of spaces-a space of capitalist
land ownership and a regime of "native land" on which native peoples
were expected to dwell. Unlike "freehold land," which was owned
individually and could be bought or sold at will, native land was sur-
veyed and registered as communally owned by the mataqali, or clan,
and rendered inalienable. As the colonial government's director of
lands later put it, the government
adopted an attitude of complete laissez-faire to land in freehold
ownership and a policy of rigid protectionism towards land in
the ownership and occupation of the native Fijians. The former
was forced upon it by the circumstances of economic reality and
the latter it voluntarily adopted as a self-imposed obligation.29
Crucial to the governmentality of the cultural state was the delin-
eation of a limited sphere for law so that it would not intrude in the
sphere of culture. As Arthur Gordon wrote to his superiors in London,
One of the most important questions which I have had to con-
sider since my arrival here, is the degree and measure in which
50
THE PLACE OF LAW
native laws and customs should be preserved in force, and how
far English law should be at once generally introduced.... What
then is to be done?... Is the whole body of English Law to be
imposed on all the population of the Colony alike, on the hun-
dred thousand colored subjects of her Majesty equally with the
white residents?30
Of particular concern to Gordon was the mix of fact and law entailed in
the common-law system-and the ensuing discretion it vested in
judges to make judgments about matters of value of the kind Gordon
reserved to the administrators of the cultural state:
Is the English law to be nominally imposed but with a power
vested in the Courts of modifying it in each case, according to
circumstances or is there to be a distinct code of laws applicable
to natives alone?
No sane man could, I think, seriously maintain the first propo-
sition.... Not only would the imposition in all respects of English
Law be inequitable; but it would, I am convinced, be altogether
impracticable to enforce obedience to it, and any serious attempt
to do so would, I have not the smallest doubt, cause an insurrec-
tion the limits of which it would be difficult to define....
Now, if there is one thing about the unknown and much
dreaded law of the foreigners which the Fijians fear more than
another, it is the uncertainty of its operation, of which they have
already seen some striking instances, and nothing can be con-
ceived more calculated to increase that uncertainty to the highest
point, than a system of law to be administered, not as it stands
written, or as it would be applied in the case of whites, but with
such deviations as in each case the Court thinks just and expedi-
ent according to its own appreciation of native usages; and the
degree of respect with which it may be disposed to regard
them.31
Gordon explicitly tied his disdain for the common law to problems of
culture: the danger was that the law, by hemorrhaging authority from
the chiefs, "would degrade the chiefs and render them idle." His solu-
tion was a "recognized Native Code in addition to the General Law and
subsidiary to it."32
THE EMPTY PLACE
51
Gordon enclosed with his dispatch the comments of two important
figures in the formulation of native policy in Fiji-Walter Carew, the
commissioner of native affairs, and the Reverend Langham, of the
Methodist mission in Fiji. Both strongly supported the view that the
flexibilities of the common law were inappropriate to the native race.
But while both framed their arguments in terms of questions of proce-
dure and form, the examples they deployed revealed concern about a
particular problem-the regulation of adultery and other sanctioned
sexual practices. Carew pointed out that English law allowed only for
monetary damages for adultery, while the natives demanded out-and-
out punishment of adulterers:
A native's wife is his cook, his gardener, his horse and cart, his
water-carrier, his fish-provider, and the bearer of children to
him....
With reference to the necessity of punishment of fornication,
it should be understood that every native woman has an owner
... if another seduces her, the owner of the woman has been
robbed.... Before the introduction of white men's laws,
breaches of chastity were most rare. What is the case now, say
at Bau, where religion has had a footing for more than thirty
years? There chastity is almost unknown among the single
young women, girls of high family prostituting themselves on
their arrival in Levuka with common natives, half-castes, and
petty shopkeepers; the parents say, if a girl steps on a white
man's verandah, she is undone, yet are powerless at present to
prevent it.33
Langham, likewise, began by emphasizing the cultural specificity of
the form of the common law:
British laws as administered among English people are fre-
quently regarded as most incomprehensible and vexatious pro-
ceedings. But to a Fijian they would simply be intolerable. They
would be so difficult to understand, so expensive to set in
motion, so tedious in their operations, so uncertain in their
results, as they would also be oppressive and vexatious in their
restraints and impositions, as to force the conviction that they
are utterly unsuitable and impracticable.34
52
THE PLACE OF LAW
Yet his argument quickly turned from procedure to matters of sub-
stance:
[Fijian law should be maintained for] offenses against chastity,
adultery, seduction, fornication, etc., the punishment of which
should be certain, prompt, easy of execution, and in proportion
to the gravity of these offences. This is impossible if British law
only be applied in such cases.35
Gordon's antipathy toward the effects of English law in the colony
evidently took him so far as to doubt that any sphere should be carved
out for a European legal regime. As he wrote to Lord Carnarvon about
the ordinance establishing native magistrates and providing for the
adjudication of cases within the village by the chiefs,36
I do not myself see why, if [white] men choose to settle in so
wild, uncivilized and exceptional a district, they should not be
subject to an exceptional jurisdiction and I have only inserted the
clause in question [compelling attendance at white tribunals in
cases involving whites] in compliance with the urgent request of
the legal members of the board.37
It ultimately was settled that even where the English courts would have
jurisdiction, they could admit evidence of native custom "not repug-
nant to justice and morality, especially in regards to marriages, wills,
the title to land, the transfer of property inter vivos and the devolution
of intestacy," and the courts were "to deal with such cases in accor-
dance with natural equity and good conscience."38
In the view of administrators in Fiji, therefore, the common law was
inappropriate to the cultural state they sought to create. Their position
was a complicated one. On the one hand, they justified their rejection of
the common law in a need for clear, firm rules. In his dispatches, Gor-
don made many of the points today's legal formalists make concerning
the indeterminacy of judge-made law and the dangers of judicial dis-
cretion. Yet if Gordon articulated this formalist position to his superi-
ors, it was only to preserve a sphere of extreme antiformalism for him-
self. Having effectively eliminated the judge from the sphere of "native
law," Gordon was able to pursue his "native policy" unfettered. Here,
as for example in the adjudication of the boundary between native and
THE EMPTY PLACE
53
nonnative spheres, the cultural state turned to case-by-case, pragmatic
administration. It freely combined Fijian ritual and economic science
into an "on balance" adjudication of the equities of each particular case.
The cultural state, in other words, was both formalist and antiformalist
in turn, and its particular genre of governmentality depended upon the
careful orchestration of both at the level of rhetoric and practice.
The colonial government's antipathy toward the common law
would seem to vindicate the argument that the debate about rules ver-
sus standards is a debate about matters of substance39-about chastity,
adultery, seduction, fornication, in this case. I want only to highlight
the place of the culture concept in defining the nature of "substance"
here. Culture became the vehicle for the introduction of matters of sub-
stance into a debate about legal form. It is the ethnographic valence of
the discussion-the adoption by Gordon and his colleagues of the role
of explaining Fijian culture to their faraway superiors in London-that
justifies the explicit intrusion into the debate of questions such as the
state's attitude toward adultery. This problem of managing cultural
difference, likewise, makes of a Methodist missionary a kind of gov-
ernment official, a local expert in Fijian culture on whom the govern-
ment might call. It is the cultural difference of the natives, moreover,
that ultimately justifies one regime of governmentality over the other.
Culture can be made to serve an argument for either rules or for stan-
dards, here, and therefore it does not actually end the debate. Yet this
does not diminish its rhetorical power as a stopping point. It feels like
the end of the story, when introduced by Gordon as justification for for-
mal law.
Knowing the Half-Castes
At the time of cession, there were approximately four hundred so-
called half-castes-children of unions between foreigners and Fijians
and their descendents-in Fiji.40 The children of these first-generation
mixed marriages for the most part married other part-European chil-
dren, the sons and daughters of their fathers' partners, and have con-
tinued to do so in large numbers to this day.4' From the early years of
colonial administration, government officials took a contemptuous
view of people of mixed race. Half-castes were seen as mentally dull,
devious, untrustworthy, lazy, and lacking in all of the chiefly qualities
that administrators admired in the Fijian population.
54
THE PLACE OF LAW
One of the ostensible sources of government antipathy toward half-
castes was fear of outside intrusion into Fijian custom. Half-castes were
the products of Fijian contact with outsiders, and it was thought that
their interaction with Fijians only weakened the hold of custom.
Administrators displayed great anxiety about married Fijian women
running away from their husbands to live with part-European men, for
example, and even considered suggesting to the Rokos that Fijians use
physical force to take back their women in such cases.42
The government's assumption, that where half-castes came into con-
tact with Fijians the result would be the corruption of Fijian ways, often
found itself challenged by interactions that both Fijians and half-castes
described as vaka viti (according to Fijian custom). Where this occurred,
officials usually reacted with suspicion and incredulity. For example,
the Land Claims Commission routinely recommended the disallowance
of grants of land made by Fijians to half-castes where money was not
exchanged, on grounds that these were "merely vaka viti" transactions
and not bona fide purchases. Consider, for example, the case of Jimmy
Dyer, "half-caste, son of James S. Dyer," who gave evidence to the com-
mission concerning his father's land at Rewa. Dyer told the commission
that his father was given drawe (tribute of uncooked food) each year as
evidence of his status among Fijians. Commissioner Walter Carew
reported to the governor that this simply could not be true:
My entire impression is, that all that portion of this witness' evi-
dence is utterly unreliable. Dyer had lived many years with
these natives, and lived as a native himself, including polygamy.
He was their "white man"; their agent for the transaction of busi-
ness with foreigners; they allowed him, as one of themselves, to
plant where he pleased, and they fed him. And yet it is pre-
tended by this witness that the yams were given as "drawe" to
his father by the people of Toga.
I may here state that, to say that such or such a chief is
"draweti," or receives "drawe" is to place him in the foremost
rank of the highest class of chiefs in the country, such as the
Vunivalu of Bau, Tui Cakau, or Roko Tui Dreketi.
It is altogether beyond belief, and impossible, that a native
tribe would "draweta" a foreigner, and above all, a person of low
origin and standing amongst his own colour, as it must have
been patent, that to such a quick-witted and intelligent race, the
man Dyer was.43
THE EMPTY PLACE
55
For the government, illegitimacy-cultural, personal, legal-became
the defining parameter of the half-caste and also the question through
which most aspects of government interaction with half-castes were
framed. For example, when the children of American and German set-
tlers petitioned their governments for assistance with regard to the
rejection of their claims to land by the Land Claims Commission, the
governor, and following him, the British Government, held that
because under principles of private international law an illegitimate
child takes the nationality of his mother, these claimants could not
appeal to foreign governments unless they could prove that their par-
ents had had a Christian wedding:
As regards half-caste claimants I took the position with Mr. Scid-
more [the U.S. agent sent to Fiji to investigate the claims] at my
first interview that they were (with one exception known to me),
the offspring of polygamous marriages, or in other words the
offspring of native concubines taken, or bought, at pleasure; and
that until the contrary was shewn I must contend they followed
the nationality of the mother and were therefore British Subjects.
No attempt was made to show me that a valid marriage had
taken place in any one case.44
One of the problems the cultural state encountered, however, was
who should count as half-caste for the purposes of law and administra-
tion. In a case involving the prosecution of a half-caste for adultery
with a Fijian woman, for example, the crucial issue was the "legiti-
macy" of the half-caste man. If he was illegitimate (the child of parents
who did not have a Christian wedding), then he was a "native" and
could be prosecuted for adultery under native regulations. If he was
legitimate, however, he was exempt from those laws.45 In 1893, Chief
Justice H. S. Berkeley ruled that, following English common law, an
illegitimate child takes the citizenship of its mother. Therefore, Berke-
ley wrote, all "illegitimate offspring of aboriginal native women are
aboriginal natives within the meaning of the interpretation ordinance.
Let them be so treated till the question has been decided to the contrary
by a Court of Law after hearing argument."46 Given that very few half-
caste marriages met this legal test of legitimacy, this meant in effect that
most half-castes were prima facie to be considered Fijian. This formula-
tion quickly proved unsatisfactory from an administrative point of
view, as the question of whether half-castes could be tried in Native
56
THE PLACE OF LAW
Court or had to be tried in High Court always turned on whether a per-
son could prove that his parents or ancestors had been married in a
church and had properly registered their wedding. Following a series
of absurdly formalistic legal results and a protest from the head of
police, Berkeley three years later proposed the ultimate pragmatist and
culturalist test:
Prima facie the illegitimate child of a Fijian woman is a Fijian;
but the presumption may be rebutted. If the child is nursed and
brought up in a Fijian community it is a Fijian and subject to the
Native Regulations. If brought up apart from such community it
probably is not.... It is very difficult to lay down a general rule
on the subject. I think each case must be dealt with, as it arises,
on the facts.47
The case of the Fijian half-castes illustrates how the benign pastoral-
ism of the cultural state can in fact be a source of oppression. The par-
ticular idea of culture and cultural purity entertained by the colonial
government led it to treat those in the interstices of culture as danger-
ous and distrustful persons without entitlements. Further, this concep-
tion was difficult to challenge because the cultural state had implicitly
but finally assumed for itself the task of determining culture, of defin-
ing it, and of assigning persons to it.
One view of the harm perpetuated by the cultural state would focus
on the particular concept of culture it deploys. In this "antiessentialist"
view, what was wrong with Arthur Gordon's policies was that they
were founded on a simplistic notion of Fijian culture as a timeless,
bounded entity. Thinking of Fijianness as an essential identity, the
argument goes, led Gordon to imagine any kind of contact with others
as dangerous and degrading.48 This view might even celebrate cultural
hybridity, as exemplified by the half-caste in this case, as the perfor-
mance of a kind of antihegemonic cultural politics.49
I believe the case of Fiji demands a different view. As we have seen,
the concept of culture was borrowed from popular anthropological the-
ories of the day, but it spoke powerfully to the colonial government's
idea of itself as balancing means and ends, capitalist economic devel-
opment and welfare. The "essentialism" of culture was not happen-
stance; on the contrary, it made it possible spatially to arrange the dif-
fering interests of economy and welfare into a physical, bounded
THE EMPTY PLACE
57
spaces of Fijian culture and pure economy. It was the pragmatic vision
of government as a careful, well-intentioned but realistic balancing of
means and ends, in other words, that made the holistic and simplistic
culture concept so useful in the first place. Culture emerged from a
compromise between welfare and economy, between local conditions
and global markets. It also set in motion its own compromises: once the
colonial government had its theory of Fijian land tenure, as we saw, it
was bound to violate that theory in the name of reasonable economic
development. This pragmatic mode of government in turn required a
rejection of law in favor of policy, where the latter could be either rule-
like or standardlike but was undertaken in light of the totality of the
circumstances.
Management of this kind is fundamentally about knowing things,
and the Fiji case suggests clearly that fact-finding commissions, anthro-
pological theories, ritual meetings with chiefs, and a host of knowl-
edge-making practices were central to the administration of govern-
ment.50 Nothing was beyond the interest or sphere of relevance of the
colonial administrator. Gordon entreated his underlings to take notes
about everything they saw and did, and he encouraged the chiefs and
native officials to report to the government anything and everything
that might occur within their territory.5'
The pragmatism of the colonial government, in other words, was
also a particular regime of knowing with its own epistemological foun-
dations. From this point of view, the harm suffered by Fiji's half-castes
was not due to their neglect per se, but rather to the government's over-
attention to culture at large. It was the excess of knowledge, the insa-
tiable appetite for more factors and elements that might be incorpo-
rated into the pragmatic calculus, that fueled the theories of culture,
and the politics of the cultural state. The politics of the cultural state, in
other words, were inseparable from the smaller cultural state-the dis-
cursive state in which more knowledge was always better than less, in
which ideas about culture as integrated wholes suggested that ever
more factors could be integrated into the understanding.
The Empty Place
Unlike the regulation of native land, which sought to balance the pro-
tection of the native and his culture against the necessities of capital-
ism, the legal regime governing freehold land was aimed at encourag-
58
THE PLACE OF LAW
ing economic development through the efficient allocation of capital.52
If the early administrators saw Fijian culture as distinctive and hence
demanding tailor-made policy solutions, the administration of the
economy was a far more generic policy problem. The administration of
freehold land, therefore, was a matter of opting for the most advanced
and technical of land registration systems available in the empire.
Fiji borrowed the "Torrens system" of title registration from Aus-
tralia, where it was first implemented in 1857, and also imported much
of its case law.53 The goals of the Torrens system are purely instrumen-
tal: It aims to address the special problems associated with treating land
as a commodity-in the words, of Fiji's former lands commissioner, "it
seeks to make transactions in land as straightforward and uncompli-
cated.., as dealing in tins of sardines at a market stall."54 The crucial dis-
tinction between a plot of land and a can of sardines, for these purposes,
is that in the case of sardines, possession is a fairly reliable indicator of
ownership. In contrast, with land, possession is no guarantee that the
seller has good title. The system therefore contributes to the value of
land by making it easier to alienate land free of concerns about the valid-
ity of title since the register contains all relevant information about
adverse claims such as mortgages or encumbrances.55 Although consid-
erable expense is involved in establishing an Torrens system, once set
up, this system is deemed easier to administer, enables efficient taxation
of land, and gives the state a great deal of accurate information.56
The Torrens system represented a significant departure from the
regime of private investigation of title that had existed in England up to
that time, in which there was no centralized record of land owner-
ship,57 or the land-recording systems in use in much of the United
States, in which deeds were recorded and indexed under the names of
the transacting parties,58 in which, as Robert Torrens, the Torrens sys-
tem's architect once put it, "title by deed can never be demonstrated as
an ascertained face: it can only be presented as an inference more or less
deducible from the documentary evidence accessible at the time
being."59 The Torrens system turns away from people-as-owners in
favor of a focus on land itself. In this system, "land is initially placed on
the register as a unit of property, transactions are registered with refer-
ence to the land itself and not merely as instruments executed by the
owner, and registration of transactions becomes essential to their valid-
ity and serves as a warranty of title and a bar to adverse claims."60 Land
is imagined in two dimensions, with each unit physically and legally
separate from the next.61 The goal is
THE EMPTY PLACE
59
transference of primary attention from the mobile, mortal, mis-
takable persons temporarily possessing or claiming rights over
patches of the earth's surface, to the immovable, durable, pre-
cisely definable units of land affected and the adoption of these
as the basis of record instead.62
This system fixes a moment in time at which all begins-the moment
at which the first Crown title is issued. Unlike the American system,
which emphasizes the historicity of a chain of ownership, in the Tor-
rens system, the document at the registry is the thing. The registrar of
title examines instruments presented for registration and can refuse
any application that appears irregular.63 Thereafter, the state stands by
the document, and its validity can only be contested for fraud, adverse
possession, and a number of other very limited reasons.64 It is often
asserted that the Torrens system functions as a "'curtain' between the
present and the past"65 since historical searches of title records become
superfluous.66
This focus on land in turn asks of the state and its administrators a
very different kind of cognition. As Fiji's latter-day director of lands
described it, its focus was on the accurate spatialization of claims:
the system is based on the concept that every parcel of land must
be properly identified on the ground and accurately surveyed so
that the survey plan is a mirror reflection of the land itself. Every
plan has to be carefully recorded in a register of plans, and every
transaction involving the land should also be recorded in a land
register and referenced to the plan register.67
Indeed, this surveyor's account of the meticulous attention the gov-
ernment devoted to surveying freehold land in the early days of the
colony-the team of surveyors sent from London, the instruments, the
days of laborious work under difficult conditions-is particularly strik-
ing when juxtaposed against the government's lack of interest in the
half-castes who owned and lived upon many of these lands. In this spa-
tialization, the title presents a true, that is complete, nonmetaphorical
representation: commentators often describe title in the Torrens system
as a "mirror" of the land.68
The Torrens system is an instrumentalist, mechanical administration
of justice. The "European law" that would govern freehold land in Fiji
turned out to be a categorical rejection of the case-by-case administra-
60
THE PLACE OF LAW
tion of justice that Gordon so despised in the English common-law tra-
dition. The rules governing title transfer represented a categorical bar
to equity, as embodied in doctrines of constructive notice, for exam-
ple.69 In most Torrens system jurisdictions, the efficient functioning of
the system was taken to be dependent on the vigilance of the registrar
of title to assure that false or mistaken titles were not registered in the
first place.70 The very mechanical, rule-based nature of the system, in
other words, depended on a certain degree of context-specific adminis-
trative decision-making on the part of the registrar to ensure the sub-
stantive validity of the titles to be registered.7'
In Fiji, however, this pragmatic compromise was emphatically
rejected. In a 1904 case, the Land Claims Commission had granted
title to a piece of land on which an entire Part-European village was
located to an expatriate speculator under circumstances that sug-
gested something close to fraud. The Supreme Court of Fiji (in the
only case involving Part-European land to reach the court) hinted
strongly that something was amiss in the Land Claims Commission's
decision. Nevertheless, it insisted the decisions of the LCC could not
be reopened.72 Even where title was probably incorrectly issued, as
long as the form of the issue conformed to the prescribed formalities,
the registrar could not interfere.73 Likewise, in a case involving the
transfer of land by a trustee, an issue arose as to whether the trustee
was acting in his fiduciary capacity in alienating the land. The regis-
trar of titles had asked for either an order of the court or the consent
of the beneficiary to this effect before registering the transfer. The
court did not agree that this was necessary and held that "if the con-
veyance or other transfer is presented to the Registrar in proper form
and duly attested, the Registrar must accept and register the instru-
ment and the new title thereby created."74 The purposeful remote-
ness of these decisions from the facts and the equities of the cases at
hand is particularly remarkable when set against the extreme prag-
matism and deep desire for knowledge about factual specifics and
equities that, as we have seen, characterized the governmentality of
the cultural state. The Torrens system, in other words, epitomizes the
"other side" of the cultural state. It is an enabling device, something
that makes capitalism, on the one hand, and efficient government, on
the other, possible. It is about rule-bound efficiency, in its purest
form.
As good legal modernists, we are suspicious of claims that anything
THE EMPTY PLACE
6i
might be "merely a formality." We are doubtful of the state's claim to
mechanical neutrality-we do not believe in such a thing as a rule that
does not signify.75 In an era in which form follows function, we under-
stand how procedures and institutions create the very parameters of the
imaginable in the guise of efficiency of administration, or through the
implementation of political compromises such as the carving out of a
space for freehold or native land. Even if one were to accept the notion
of a contentless rule, moreover, we understand that it is often impossi-
ble to tell whether a particular rule is a contentless formality established
to aid the parties in private ordering, or a rule designed to deter state-
sanctioned conduct.76 The state may also be passing its own obligations
onto private actors through such devices by forcing them to bear the
cost of producing and maintaining accurate survey maps, for example.
The mainstream academic position therefore is that formalities such as
the Torrens system are better understood as sites of contested cultural or
political meanings. Gregory Alexander, for example, tells us that nine-
teenth-century American debates surrounding alterations to land trans-
fer procedures "metaphorically expressed [a] dual sense of regret for
loss of the past and optimism about the effects of present and future
change."77 What was at stake in these seemingly technical debates,
Alexander emphasizes, was not just technicalities but a deeper set of
ambivalences about the onslaught of the market and the sacrifice of sta-
bility and also the elimination of social hierarchy that would accompany
it. From this perspective, it might be possible to read into the adminis-
trative apparatus of land title registration a cultural politics.
What interests me, however, is how Alexander's point about the
conflicting values embodied in property would seem to have been
missed by the designers of Fiji's land titles registration system, who, as
we have seen, were so keenly sensitive to the point in a multitude of
other contexts. Legal scholars tell us again and again that land registra-
tion is just a means, not an end. As one leading commentator on land
registrations systems has put it,
Land is the source of all material wealth.... Land registration
must, however, be kept in perspective. It is a device which may
be essential to sound land administration but it is merely part of
the machinery of government. It is not some sort of magical spe-
cific which will automatically produce good land use and devel-
opment; nor is it a system of land holding; it is not even a kind of
62
THE PLACE OF LAW
land reform, though it may be a valuable administrative aid to
land reform. In short, land registration is only a means to an end.
It is not an end in itself. Much time, money, and effort can be
wasted if that elementary truth be forgotten.78
Unlike land, which is essential in every sense of the term, then, land
registration is just procedure, in this view. It is simply about surfaces,
not about meanings. In the remainder of this essay I want to hold back
the critiques I have just described for a moment in order to explore this
claim on its own terms.
Scholars traditionally analyze the Torrens system as two separate
stages-the stage of its establishment and the stage of its operation.79
The establishment of the system is without a doubt a mere extension of
the existing devices and policies of the cultural state. Yet once it is up
and running, the system is no longer managerial in this sense.80s The
dimension of the Torrens procedures that is salient is its "routinizing
value."8 Its modality is not bureaucracy, but machine. Although the
machine is the outcome of pragmatist politics, then, it itself is no longer
pragmatic. What intrigues me here is how something born out of the
very pragmatist, instrumentalist policies I have described in this essay
might escape them not by stepping outside their logic, but by taking the
ideal of instrumentality to its own ultimate conclusion. With the Tor-
rens system machine, the question of "simplification and guarantee of
title for what purpose?" becomes superfluous. The instrument becomes
an end in itself.
In Fiji, this transformation of the bureaucratic into the mechanical
took a concrete, organizational form: the moving of the land titles reg-
istration system into the Department of Lands and Surveys. In most
British colonies, questions of land tenure were considered to be closely
tied to matters of governance and vital to the fostering of the kind of
polity the colonial government sought to create. Land tenure therefore
remained within the jurisdiction of the governor or administrator.
"Survey, on the other hand, was regarded as the technical process
involved in the general topographical surveying and mapping of a
country, which had no social significance and was in no way concerned
with the recording of the proprietary units into which the country was
divided."82 In 1880, however, in response to practical difficulties
encountered with organizing the surveying and titling of land, the
administration of land tenure in freehold in Fiji was allocated to a new
THE EMPTY PLACE
63
Department of Lands and Surveys, wherein the commissioner of lands
would also serve as registrar of titles.83 This simple organizational
change subsumed land policy within the technical work of creating
surveys and hence replaced law with technoscience, the mathematics
of measurement of the earth's surface, as the register for defining prop-
erty. With the replacement of the lawyer and judge with the surveyor,
matters of land were devalued from questions of high political valence,
to be handled by people of high prestige, to questions of a merely tech-
nical nature to be handled by junior functionaries. Henceforth, what
was foregrounded was the mechanical nature of the system.
We are clearly quite far from the pragmatism of the cultural state,
then, and its benevolent replacement of legal rules with gentle case-by-
case administration. The critiques leveled at Governor Arthur Gor-
don's culturalist project-the questioning of the notion of culture that
guided his administration,84 or the inquiry into the way such Fou-
cauldian pastoralism constituted its subjects85-would begin to suggest
the ways in which the mundane, even trivial spaces devoid of purpose-
ful administration such as the Land Titles Office might offer a kind of
respite from the overdetermined significations of the cultural state.
My concern here is with the implications of this mechanical govern-
mentality for those who did not benefit from the state's culturalist pas-
toral care. Here, the Land Titles Office, with its regime of government
focused only on the spatial arrangement of titles, the "mirror" of the
land and the "curtain" between the present and the past, transformed
the "half-caste" into an entry in a title document, a placeholder for a
particular spatial unit.86 This ironically shielded Part-Europeans, who
largely lived on these small plots of land, from the reaches of the state's
cultural knowledge. Given the state's antipathy toward half-castes, it is
quite remarkable that the lands they received a century ago remain
largely in their possession today. Had the legal formalities surrounding
title to land been rendered more flexible, and hence contestable, the
state would have been called in to make further cultural judgments (is
it usual practice among half-castes for a man to leave his land to his
sons rather than to his wife?). Given the views of the colonial adminis-
tration as to the moral quality of half-castes and the degeneration of
culture they represented, it is not difficult to imagine the shape such
judgments would have taken.
Some of the best pieces of evidence for the significance of the empty
place this machine created for Part-Europeans are the wills they have
64
THE PLACE OF LAW
produced over the last century. As noted earlier, because of their status
as illegitimates, Part-Europeans could not count on the rules of intes-
tacy, and hence the writing of a will concerning the disposition of one's
land has become a universal practice for them. At death, these wills are
submitted for probate and then forwarded to the registrar of lands so
that the new owner of the land may be recorded in the registry. As we
have seen, the case law made it clear that the registrar was to inquire
only into matters of form; as long as the formal requirements were met,
the content of the documents was not within his jurisdiction. As a
result, Part-European wills have become rich sites for statements about
practices of family, ownership, and even philosophy and morality that
openly contradict the ambitions and values of the cultural state. Wills
often refer to the allocation of property as between multiple wives, for
example, despite the criminalization of polygamy in Fiji. Likewise,
wills often repeat that since the founding of the clan it has been a prin-
cipal tenet that land is never to be sold outside the family, in contra-
vention of the very idea of alienable land and ease of transfer that the
Torrens system aims to facilitate.
My point is that where Part-European sociality was cast as a matter
of ownership of freehold land, and where freehold land in turn was
cast as a matter of simple mechanical title transfer, this sociality
achieved a kind of invisibility that allowed it ironically to survive in the
very interstices of a set of government practices bent on its illegitimacy.
The land titles documents of the Torrens system enshrined a set of spa-
tial entities-pieces of land. These spatial entities were fictions and
were understood to be fictions by the architects of the system. But they
were also placeholders, symbols that blocked the cultural state from
inquiring further about what lay behind them. By taking on the form of
possessive individualism, in other words, Part-Europeans were able to
live in ways far outside the matrix of individuals and collectivities envi-
sioned by the cultural state.
For Fiji's half-castes, therefore, the possibilities entailed in the slip-
page of formalities as means into formalities as ends created the radical
possibility of an empty place inside the very matrix of the cultural state.
For Part-Europeans, land could not be merely a means to an end
because as people without culture in a cultural state they had no ends,
no place, no meaning to be represented. But they had means, and these
means-the legal formalities-could be taken literally so that they
transformed themselves into ends of their own. In so doing, they cor-
THE EMPTY PLACE
65
doned off an empty, mundane place where the state would not signify
and also failed to see any form of signification worthy of intrusion,
development or concern.
A Postcolonial Postscript
Upon independence, the land ordinance and its system of legal formal-
ities was replaced by a new Property Law Act87 that abolished many of
the formalities I have described. Henceforth, deeds required one wit-
ness but "no particular form of words." Likewise, seals, formal deliv-
ery, and so on would no longer be required (par. 4). Fiji also abolished
the formalities governing the form required of wills found in the Eng-
lish Wills Act of 1837 that had governed to that point.88 In the final days
of the colony a new ordinance governing inheritance in cases where
there was no will explicitly provided for illegitimate children to inherit
equally with legitimate children if the father had admitted paternity.89
The assumptions behind these reforms was a progressive, 1970S
worldview. They were built on the assumption that formalities have a
politics, and a meaning-that the state cannot help but signify. The hid-
den politics were taken to be repressive, restraining individuals'
desires and impairing their creativity by "channeling" their imagina-
tions into strictly regimented forms. The implication of this reform,
however, was to drag freehold land into the orbit of the cultural state,
as freehold land became just like any other dimension of social life
and hence open to cultural administration and cultural politics.
The effect as well as the cause was the overt politicization of land.
Where in the past the boundaries depicted in the title were of far lesser
interest than the divisions one could create within the boundaries, in
the postcoup era, Part-Europeans living on freehold land told of daily
cat-and-mouse games in which Fijians raided their lands or tore down
their fences and then ran back into the hills, leaving behind a message
about the contestability of the boundary line.
If the formalities had evaporated, so too had the land as genitor of
individuals. Those who had moved to the city now saw themselves as
individuals and members of groups, people who could accumulate
wealth and hence for whom productivity was a newfound problem. The
Whippys in Suva often expressed frustration with and estrangement
from their relatives in Kasavu, who, they said, were "wasting their
resources" and therefore were "much poorer than they should be."
66
THE PLACE OF LAW
In this new world of individual and group politics surrounding
land, it should be no surprise that title has become a means to an end
in precisely the sense imagined by modernist legal theorists. In par-
ticular, at the time of my fieldwork, land had become the subject of a
protracted legal dispute. In 1994, clan members living in Suva and
overseas brought individual suits to have themselves declared the
owners of the 2,110-acre portion still held in common by the heirs of
Samuel Whippy. Their goal was to lay claim to this one remaining
block of undivided land in order to sell the virgin timber it contained
to a foreign logging company. Although the flurry of court affidavits,
pleadings, and submissions of evidence included many of the same
certificates of title considered above, these documents now had
become instruments, means of signifying (ownership) defined in
terms beyond the documents, rather than arbiters of their own referen-
tial truth.
NOTES
Acknowledgments: This paper is based on ethnographic and archival research in
Suva and Kasavu, Fiji, conducted from September 1994 to April 1996. I owe my
deepest thanks to the Whippy family, and to the many other Part-European
families who so generously took time to teach me about questions of family and
land. I thank the Cornell Law School, where this paper was written, and the
American Bar Foundation for research support and Margaret Werry and Claire
Korenblit for their research assistance. Versions of this paper were presented as
the Keck Lecture, Amherst College, March 2001, at the Workshop on Law and
Colonialism in the Pacific held at the School for American Research, Santa Fe,
New Mexico, March 2001, the Wenner-Gren Foundation International Sympo-
sium on the New Property, April 2001, and the Northwestern Law School Prop-
erty Workshop, May 2001, and I thank each of these groups for many helpful
suggestions. For comments and assistance of many kinds, I thank Gregory
Alexander, Rick Brooks, Paul Kahn, Richard Ford, Tom Merrill, Hiro Miyazaki,
Kunal Parker, Austin Sarat, and Henry Smith. This essay draws at points on a
companion essay as well as on material presented to the Constitutional Review
Commission of Fiji. See Annelise Riles, "Part-Europeans and Fijians: Some
Problems in the Conceptualization of a Relationship," in Fiji in Transition, ed.
Brij V. Lal and Tomasi R. Vakatora (Suva: University of the South Pacific, 1997);
Annelise Riles, "Law as Object," in Legal Legacies, Current Crises: Fiji and Hawaii,
ed. Donald Brenneis and Sally Merry (Santa Fe: School of American Research
Press, 2003).
1. Akhil Gupta and James Ferguson, "Culture, Power, Place: Ethnography
at the End of an Era," in Culture Power Place: Explorations in Critical Anthropol-
THE EMPTY PLACE
67
ogy, ed. Akhil Gupta and James Ferguson (Durham: Duke University Press,
1997), 6; Donald S. Moore, "Subaltern Struggles and the Politics of Place:
Remapping Resistance in Zimbabwe's Eastern Highlands," Cultural Anthropol-
ogy 13, no. 3 (1998): 344-81; James Duncan and David Ley, eds., Place/Cul-
ture/Representation (New York: Routledge, 1993).
2. Ian Baucom, ed., Out of Place: Englishness, Empire, and the Locations of
Identity (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); Linda McDowell, Gender
Identity and Place: Understanding Feminist Geographies (Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press, 1999).
3. Peter Jackson and Jan Penrose, "Introduction: Placing 'Race' and
Nation," in Constructions of Race, Place, and Nation, ed. Peter Jackson and Jan
Penrose (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1994); Alistair Bonnett,
"Constructions of 'Race,' Place, and Discipline: Geographies of 'Racial' Identity
and Racism," Ethnic and Racial Studies 19, no. 4 (1996): 864-83; David Delaney,
ed., Race, Place, and the Law, 1836-1948 (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1998);
Kevin Durrheim and John Dixon, "The Role of Place and Metaphor in Racial
Exclusion: South Africa's Beaches as Sites of Shifting Racialization," Ethnic and
Racial Studies 24, no. 3 (2001): 433-50.
4. Angelika Bammer, ed., Displacements: Cultural Identities in Question
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994); Gillian Bottomley, From Another
Place: Migration and the Politics of Culture (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992).
5. Steve Pile, "Introduction: Opposition, Political Identities, and Spaces of
Resistance," and Donald Moore, "Remapping Resistance: 'Ground for Strug-
gle' and the Politics of Place," both in Geographies of Resistance, ed. Steve Pile
and Michael Keith (New York: Routledge, 1997); Jenny Robinson, "Spaces of
Democracy: Remapping the Apartheid City," Environment and Planning D: Soci-
ety and Space 16 (1998): 533-48.
6. Richard Ford, "The Boundaries of Race: Political Geography in Legal
Analysis," Don Mitchell, "The Annihilation of Space by Law: The Roots and
Implications of Anti-homeless Laws in the United States," and Gerald Frug, "A
Legal History of Cities," all in The Legal Geographies Reader: Law, Power, and
Space, ed. Nicholas Blomley, David Delaney, and Richard T. Ford (Oxford:
Blackwell, 200ool).
7. David Campbell, "Apartheid Cartography: The Political Anthropology
and Spatial Effects of International Diplomacy in Bosnia," Political Geography
18, no. 4 (1999): 395-435.
8. Nicholas Blomley, "Landscapes of Property," Law and Society Review 32,
no. 3 (1998): 567-612.
9. Carolyn L. Cartier, "The Dead, Place/Space, and Social Activism: Con-
structing the Nationscape in Historic Melaka," Environment and Planning D:
Society and Space 15 (1997): 555-86; David Sadler, "Culture, Place, and Space in
Contemporary Europe," European Urban and Regional Studies 6, no. 3 (1999):
195-96.
10. Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), 21.
11. Ibid., 23. The nostalgia at play here, and the simplicity of the accompa-
68
THE PLACE OF LAW
nying idea of rational abstraction that forms the other side of the dichotomy,
has lately come under a good deal of postmodern criticism. See, e.g., David
Harvey, "From Place to Space and Back Again: Reflections on the Condition of
Postmodernity," in Mapping the Futures: Local Cultures, Global Change, ed. Jon
Bird, Barry Curtis, Tim Putnam, George Robertson, and Lisa Tickner (New
York: Routledge, 1993).
12. See, e.g., E. C. Relph, Place and Placelessness (London: Pion, 1976); and
Irwin Altman and Ervin H. Zube, introduction to Public Places and Spaces, ed.
Irwin Altman and Ervin H. Zube (New York: Plenum Press, 1989).
13. See, e.g., Richard A. Etlin, "Space, Stone, and Spirit: The Meaning of
Place," in The Eight Technologies of Otherness, ed. Sue Golding (New York: Rout-
ledge, 1997); and Steven Feld and Keith H. Basso, introduction to Senses of Place,
ed. Steven Feld and Keith H. Basso (Santa Fe: School of American Research
Press, 1996).
14. See, e.g., Pierre Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice, trans. Richard
Nice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977).
15. Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space, trans. Maria Jolas (New York:
Orion Press, 1964), xxxi; cf. Kathleen Stewart, A Space on the Side of the Road: Cul-
tural Poetics in an "Other" America (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).
16. In framing land as an "empty place," I am working against the title of
James Weiner's artful study of Foi poetics. See James F. Weiner, The Empty
Place: Poetry, Space, and Being among the Foi of Papua New Guinea (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1991). If by poetics one intends a rigid and careful
attention to matters of form, then one might say that the empty place framed by
bureaucratic technicalities and legal formalities I will describe is as poetic as
that of Foi myth as elucidated by Weiner. However, to the extent that for
Weiner poetics must imply a notion of metaphor and hence of meaning, the
empty place I invoke is radically different. The analysis I present here would
suggest in fact that the metaphorical poetics of the kind Weiner describes-the
preoccupation with the alternative concealment and elucidation of meaning,
the creative deployment of memory in the service of making space into place-
is part of the same matrix of pragmatic ideas that alternatively rationalize for-
malities and tear them down again.
17. Peter France, The Charter of the Land: Custom and Colonization in Fiji
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969), 124.
18. Nicholas Thomas, Entangled Objects: Exchange, Material Culture, and Colo-
nialism in the Pacific (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991); and Martha
Kaplan, Neither Cargo nor Cult: Ritual Politics and the Colonial Imagination in Fiji
(Durham: Duke University Press, 1995).
19. Half-castes was the universal appellation for those who were neither full
Fijian, European, nor Indian until 1936, when the term was officially replaced
with "Persons of European and Native Descent" (File F114/1, National
Archives of Fiji) (after considering Anglo-Polynesians, Anglo-Fijians, Euro-Poly-
nesians, and later Euronesians). In the 1940s, this was again replaced by Part-
Europeans. In recent years, Part-Europeans have reappropriated the term half-
caste to ironic and enabling effects similar to the American gay community's
THE EMPTY PLACE
69
reappropriation of the term queer. In this essay, I use Part-European and half-
caste interchangeably.
20. Annelise Riles, "Division within the Boundaries," Journal of the Royal
Anthropological Institute, n.s. 4, no. 3 (1998): 409-24.
21. Bruce Knapman, Fiji's Economic History, 1874-1939: Studies of Capitalist
Colonial Development (Canberra: National Centre for Development Studies,
Research School of Pacific Studies, Australian National University, 1987).
22. John D. Kelly, A Politics of Virtue: Hinduism, Sexuality, and Countercolonial
Discourse in Fiji (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991).
23. John D. Kelly, "Fear of Culture: British Regulation of Indian Marriage in
Post-indenture Fiji," Ethnohistory 36, no. 4 (1989): 372-91.
24. Gerald R. Ward, "Land Use and Land Alienation in Fiji to 1885," Journal
of Pacific History 4 (1969): 3.
25. France, Charter of the Land, 118.
26. Peter France quotes Gordon's private letter to the permanent undersec-
retary at the Colonial Office:
I cannot too soon or too strongly impress upon you that the adoption of
the course you now seem inclined to follow would be fatal alike to the
settlers and the natives. Unless you find some means of overcoming the
scruples of the gentlemen of the long robe, and substantially adhering to
the original plan, the colony must go to pieces. (Charter of the Land, 115)
Clause 4 read,
That the absolute proprietorship of all lands not shown to be now alien-
ated so as to have become the bona fide property of Europeans or some
other foreigners or not now in the actual use or occupation of some
Chief or tribe or not actually required for the probable future support
and maintenance of some Chief or tribe shall be and is hereby declared
to be vested in Her said Majesty her heirs and successors.
27. Ward, "Land Use and Land Alienation," 12.
28. "[T]he commission proceeded with its adjudicatory functions on the
basis of equity and empiricism and not on dogma or theory." D. T. Lloyd,
"Land Policy in Fiji," University of Cambridge Department of Land Economy
Occasional Paper No. 14 (1982), 143.
29. Ibid., 130.
30. Despatch from Gordon to Earl of Carnarvon, March 6, 1876, enclosing
minutes on question of native law by W. C. Carew, commissioner to the Kai
Colos, and by Rev. F. Langham, head of the Wesleyan Mission.
31. Ibid.
32. Ibid.
33. Ibid.
34. Ibid.
35. Ibid.
70
THE PLACE OF LAW
36. Ordinance No. 16 of 1875, An Ordinance to Provide for the Judicial
Administration of Certain Districts of the Colony.
37. Gordon to Lord Carnarvon, November 20, 1875.
38. Dispatch from the secretary of state to the governor, March 22, 1875.
This was the standard treatment of customary law within the local courts
throughout the colonies. See M. B. Hooker, Legal Pluralism: An Introduction to
Colonial and Neoclassical Laws (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975).
39. Duncan Kennedy, "Legal Formality," Journal of Legal Studies 2 (1974):
351-
40. Ward, "Land Use and Land Alienation," 9.
41. A demographic study conducted in 1966 found that over 50 percent of
part-Europeans married other part-Europeans, while over 20 percent married
Europeans, and 25 percent married Fijians. See D. L. Kelly, "The Part-Europeans
of Fiji," M.S. Thesis, Dept. of Geography, University of Wellington, 1966, 5.
42. Colonial Secretary's Office (CSO) 274/1885; CSO 2883/1885; CSO
3389/1885, National Archives of Fiji. Rokos were Fijian officers who served as
heads of Fijian administrative provinces in the colonial government.
43. Land Claims Commission Report No. 400, Claim of Thomas P. K. Wil-
son for Lands in Rewa Province known as Toga Island, National Archives of
Fiji.
44. John B. Thurston, dispatch to Colonial Office re US Land Claims, Office
of Public Records, London (OPR), September 2, 1896.
45. CSO 2027/1902, Assault on Half Caste; Status of Half-Castes in Native
Courts, May 2, 1902, National Archives of Fiji.
46. Ruling of His Excellency the Administrator-the Hon. H.S. Berkeley-
Having Reference to the Status of a Portion of the Half Caste Population, May
13, 1893, CSO 1421/1893, National Archives of Fiji.
47. CSO 1032/1896, National Archives of Fiji.
48. Cf. Kaplan, Neither Cargo nor Cult; and Ann Stoler, "'Mixed Bloods' and
the Cultural Politics of European Identity in Colonial Southeast Asia," in The
Decolonization of Imagination: Culture, Knowledge, and Power, ed. Jan Nederveen
Pieterse and Bhikhu Parekh (London: Zed Books, 1995), 128-48.
49. Cf. Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity
(New York: Routledge, 1990).
50. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan
Sheridan (London: Penguin, 1991).
51. Nicholas Thomas, "Sanitation and Seeing: The Creation of State Power
in Early Colonial Fiji," Comparative Studies in Society and History 32: (1990):
149-70.
52. One of the colonial government's first acts was the introduction of its
Real Property Ordinance in 1876 (An Ordinance to Provide for the Transfer of
Land by Registration of Titles [No. 6 of 1876], March 1, 1877). The importance
the government attached to the workings of this ordinance is evidenced by its
almost continual revision over the decades that followed: amendments were
introduced in 1877, 1883, 1892, 1895, 1913, 1923, and 1924, and the entire ordi-
nance was ultimately redrafted in 1933 (An Ordinance to Amend the Law of
THE EMPTY PLACE
71
Property and the Law Relating to the Transfer of Land and to the Registration
of Title to Land [No. 14 of 1933], July 25, 1933). The purpose of the ordinance
was to provide for all the trappings of a modern capitalist land system where
freehold land was concerned: provisions were made for transfer (pars. 41-48),
inheritance (pars. 25-31, 82-92), lease (pars. 40-57), mortgage (pars. 58-75), and
ejectment (pars. 103-7). The 1933 ordinance took the demands of capitalist land
use even further by clarifying the process for acquiring land by adverse pos-
session (pars. 82-97), limiting abolishing the rights of widows to dower (par.
116), specifying the rules for land ownership by corporations (pars. 147-48),
and providing for subdivision and roads (pars. 170-76).
53. In re West (1890), Fiji Law Report 1:227-29 (following the practice of the
Colony of Victoria concerning the registration of underleases). Fiji's Real Prop-
erty Ordinance of 1876 was modeled on the South Australian Real Property Act
of 1858 (Lloyd, "Land Policy in Fiji," 153).
54. Lloyd, "Land Policy in Fiji," 154.
55. Eustace J. Harvey, Land Law and Registration of Title: A Comparison of the
Old and New Methods of Transferring Land (London: Longmans, Green, 1910),
187.
56. Lloyd, "Land Policy in Fiji," 154.
57. In 1875, the Land Transfer Act purported to establish a national registry
system for title in England. However, registration was largely voluntary and
the act gave such broad discretion to the registrar that the utility of the system
was largely undermined (Harvey, Land Law, 199-243).
58. The American system, in contrast, is a recording system rather than a
registration system; conveyances are recorded at a central registry, and the
ensuing records are admissible in court as evidence of ownership. They do not
in themselves constitute or conclusively prove ownership, however, as they do
in the Torrens system. See Rufford G. Patton and Carroll G. Patton, Patton on
Titles (St. Paul: West, 1957), 17.
59. Robert Torrens, The South Australian System of Conveyancing by Registra-
tion of Title, quoted in Bernard O. Binns, Cadastral Surveys and Records of Rights
in Land (Rome: Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations,
1953).
60. C. K. Meek, Land Law and Custom in the Colonies (London: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1949), 275.
61. Lloyd, "Land Policy in Fiji," 155.
62. Ernest Dowson and V. L. O. Sheppard, Land Registration, 2d ed., HMSO
Colonial Research Publications No. 13 (London, 1956), 19.
63. John L. McCormack, "Torrens and Recording: Land Title Assurance in
the Computer Age," William Mitchell Law Review 18 (1992): 101.
64. Caldwell v. Mongston (1908), Fiji Law Report 2:62-76 (even where Crown
grant may have been issued in error, court will not go "behind" the grant); Ram
Kali v. John Percy Bayly and Santa and the Registrar of Titles (1954), Fiji Law Report
4:139.
65. McCormack, "Torrens and Recording," 80.
66. Fiji's ordinance asserts,
72
THE PLACE OF LAW
The duplicate certificate of title issued by the Registrar upon a genuine
transfer shall be taken by all courts of law as conclusive evidence that
the person named therein as proprietor of the land is the absolute and
indefeasible owner thereof and the title of such proprietor shall not be
subject to challenge except on the ground of fraud or misrepresentation
... or on the ground of adverse possession.
67. D. T. Lloyd, "A Brief Historical Review of the Land Boundaries in Fiji,"
The Fiji Society: Transactions and Proceedings in Fiji Society 9 (1962): 3.
68. See Theodore B. F. Ruoff, An Englishman Looks at the Torrens System:
Being Some Provocative Essays on the Operation of the System after One Hundred
Years (Sydney: Law Book Company of Australia, 1957); and S. Rowton Simp-
son, Land Law and Registration (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976),
22.
69. James Edward Hogg, Registration of Title to Land throughout the Empire: A
Treatise on the Law Relating to Warranty of Title to Land by Registration and Trans-
actions with Registered Land in Australia, New Zealand, Canada, England, Ireland,
West Indies, Malaya, etc. (Toronto: Carswell, 1920), 97.
70. See, e.g., McCormack, "Torrens and Recording," 1o1-2; and Harvey,
Land Law, 194.
71. See Harvey, Land Law, 196-97.
72. Gaspard v. Colonial Sugar Refining Co. (1904), Fiji Law Report 3:58.
73. In contrast, judges in other British colonies confronted with such errors
treated them as constructive cases of fraud, and hence expanded the exception
to the conclusive presumption of the validity of title as registered in cases of
fraud to accommodate notions of equity. See Hogg, Registration of Title, 109,
129.
74. Re The Estate of H. Maughan (1929), Fiji Law Report 3:123; Re The Estate of
W. A. Scott (1929), Fiji Law Report 3:125.
75. The land regime is inherently political in this realist view; it does not just
record entitlements, it makes them. See Gregory S. Alexander, Commodity and
Propriety: Competing Visions of Property in American Legal Thought, 1776-1970
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997). The critique of twentieth-century
Progressive formalities, then, parallels the cultural studies project of rediscov-
ering in abstract "space" a notion of "dwelling" or "place": the one aims to
demonstrate the politics that lurk behind the seemingly objective formality,
while the other aims to recover culture.
76. Duncan Kennedy, "Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication,"
Harvard Law Review 89 (1976): 1692.
77. Alexander, Commodity and Propriety, loo.
78. Simpson, Land Law and Registration, 3.
79. See, e.g., Dowson and Sheppard, Land Registration, 73.
80. In this, the Torrens system might be described in Gunther Teubner's
terms as an autopoetic system. See Gunther Teubner, Law as an Autopoetic Sys-
tem (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).
THE EMPTY PLACE
73
81. Mann, "Formalities and Formalism," 1048.
82. Lloyd, "Land Policy in Fiji," 148.
83. Ibid., 147-49.
84. Thomas, Entangled Objects.
85. Kaplan, Neither Cargo nor Cult, 71.
86. As Bill Maurer has argued with respect to the property regime estab-
lished by the British in the British Virgin Islands, this system encouraged "peo-
ple to think and act as if individual attributes derived from descent are more
important in figuring identity than corporate group membership." Bill Maurer,
Recharting the Caribbean: Land, Law, and Citizenship in the British Virgin Islands
(Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1997), 172.
87. An Act to Consolidate and Amend the Law Relating to Property and for
Incidental and Other Purposes (No. 18 of 1971), April 15, 1971.
88. An Act to Consolidate and Amend the Law Relating to Wills (No. 1 of
1972), March 3, 1972, par. 6.
89. An Ordinance to Consolidate and Amend the Law Relating to Succes-
sion, Probate and Administration of Estates of Deceased Persons (No. 20 of
1970), July 2, 1970, par. 6 (3-4).
The Architecture of Authority: The
Place of Law in the Space of Science
Susan S. Silbey and Patricia Ewick
A doctor, a lawyer, and a scientist were having a discussion about
whether it is better to have a wife or a mistress. The lawyer claimed that
it is much better to have a mistress than a wife; if the relationship went
sour, there were fewer legal complications. The doctor said that was all
wrong. It is better to have a wife than a mistress, less threat of a heart
attack from the greater sexual passion with a mistress. The scientist
intervened saying they were both wrong. He wanted a wife and a mis-
tress. He could tell his mistress he was with his wife, tell his wife he was
with his mistress, then go to the lab and work without interruption.
This joke circulates among physical and biological scientists, dis-
playing with unmasked pride a different sort of pleasure than offered
by wives and mistresses: pleasure taken in a professional, albeit comic,
identity as a single-minded pursuer of abstract truths rather than sen-
sual desire, pushing back the frontiers of knowledge by working on a
noble and selfless quest. Of course the joke is sexist, but so too is mod-
ern science. Of course too, science is hardly selfless, and whether it is
noble is for others to say. Unfortunately for those misled by our intro-
duction, our focus is not about sex, wives, or mistresses, but about
space, science, and law.
Our subject is the significance of laboratory space as the habitat of
the research scientist and the place of law in those scientific spaces. Our
thesis is simple. As the laboratory has been transformed over the cen-
turies from a private place of gentlemanly inquiry to an open and acces-
sible public arena, the forms of regulation governing the processes of
production and certifying the knowledge produced therein have also
75
76
THE PLACE OF LAW
shifted. As the authority of science has grown, ironically, it has become
increasingly subject to legal constraint and regulation. The legal regu-
lation of science is, however, "from a distance." Rather than directly
controlling the behavior of scientists, science is more often regulated
through the design and monitoring of the spaces of science. What had
been governed primarily by conventions among gentlemen and the
prerogatives of class and aristocracy have been replaced by the tech-
niques of governmentality. Rather than the scientist inviting acquain-
tances to his' home and relying on conventional morality to secure
trustworthy witnesses to scientific experiments, the contemporary
research laboratory is a space governed by a network of laws, regula-
tions, and rules helping to produce a specific kind of subject: a particu-
lar kind of scientist and a particular kind of science. In the spatial regu-
lation of science, processes of social control are largely internalized,
sustaining science and the scientists' authority for autonomy and self-
governance.
Science's traditional remove from everyday life and intractability to
outside control have been challenged by modern transformations in
forms of governance and in the characterizations of science as danger-
ous. Powerfully shaping contemporary life, science is perceived to be
dangerous, both in terms of its potential to produce physical harm and
in its insistence upon an independent source of authority. Many legal
constraints focus on material and physical dangers, and our empirical
data will address the regulation of environmental, health, and safety
hazards in the spaces of scientific production. Nonetheless, we must
note that science is dangerous primarily because its norms and prac-
tices are indecipherable by other institutions. The law's pursuit of jus-
tice and its construction of truth, for example, do not correspond to,
and are often incommensurate with, science's pursuit of empirical real-
ity. This disconnect can be threatening when science offers empirical
answers that seem to undermine the law's truths. Scientific ways of
perceiving, ordering, and manipulating phenomena create the possibil-
ity that other (similarly authoritative) institutions will be unable to
apprehend, no less control, those phenomena. In this sense, science is
dangerous because, being indecipherable, it may incapacitate the law's,
or religion's, or the economy's routinized ways of operating and con-
struing the world. However, an important aspect of its indecipherabil-
ity, especially from the point of view of law and religion, is science's
claim to operate without normative commitments. Thus, by abdicating
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
77
responsibility for the social terrain attended by law and religion, it
turns out, science secures a measure of autonomy for its most serious
dangers.
We do not wish to suggest that the history and development of mod-
ern science has been a story of total immunity from the influences of
competing social institutions. Indeed, we will argue the opposite. The
law has been constitutively present, sometimes centrally so, in the
expansion and organization of modern science. But, in its efforts to pro-
mote (as well as contain) the development and consequences of science,
the law has, over the centuries, certified areas of scientific autonomy,
putting them beyond the law's reach. Just as the liberal state derives a
good part of its legitimacy from its purported separation from and pro-
tection of civil society (asserted to be prior to and independent of the
state that discursively and legally constructs that divide), so too, scien-
tific authority is in part constituted by law's deference to science's
claims to discover truths that exist prior to and independent of human
institutions. In other words, the law's deference to science's claim-to
have access to something that is independent of its own activities
helps construct scientific authority and legitimacy at the same time as it
instantiates and legitimates law's authority to regulate.
What the law regulates, constrains, and enables may be influenced, if
not determined, by science's methods and conclusions, but how that
regulation takes place, through what sorts of procedures and sanctions,
are the law's specific prerogative. Thus, we manage the dangers of radi-
ation through an elaborate system of continuous surveillance that can
lead to mandatory cessation of operation or personal exclusion from
work. On the other hand, we respond to the dangers of smoking by
requiring notices on cigarette packages, prohibiting advertising and
sale to minors, but taxing rather than prohibiting consumption for
adults. And, in most American states, we respond to the dangers of sex-
ually transmitted diseases not by providing or requiring surveillance or
mandated notices, nor by monitoring the sexual practices of infected
persons; we do, however, permit and certify marriages only after
screening for disease. In each of these instances, the dangers have been
identified through scientific research; the modes and forms of regula-
tion are legal inventions.
By collaborating with science's authority, deferring to its truths, and
its claims to have access to a world independent of itself, law enhances
its own capacity and authority, including the power to regulate the pro-
78
THE PLACE OF LAW
duction of science. Importantly, part of this collaboration between sci-
ence and law includes a recognition that the experimental method is
among the central features of scientific epistemology and authority.
Acknowledging that scientific facts are always revisable, the content of
legal regulation drawn from scientific knowledge is also always revis-
able. Thus, by incorporating and deferring to scientific epistemology
and methodology, law justifies the need to come back again, so to
speak, with new regulations. The revisable status of scientific truths
creates a platform for extending the quantity and thus the reach of law,
illustrating the degree to which regulation is characterized not by its
specific content, but its form.
The contemporary history of legal regulation of science is in many
ways a picture of the legal constitution of laboratories. From trusts,
endowments, intellectual property, as well as environmental protec-
tion and workplace safety, legal rules not only penetrate but suffuse
the spaces and production of science. In its engagement with science,
however, this regulatory culture is not often a Weberian model of
top-down command-and-control, mandating specific acts and pro-
hibiting others. Today, in a transformed regulatory environment, we
have bottom-up self-regulation where the law identifies the kinds of
spaces that demand regulation, spaces in which an organization must
define for itself and its members permissible types of action and
interaction. In this contemporary regime, scientists take on the mis-
sion of the law, align their interests with those of the law, and pro-
duce through this process "the content of the form." The form of reg-
ulation is itself experimental, intentionally revisable, and along the
way transportable. In the course of this experimental, engaged form
of self-regulation, the law extends its power and reach, perhaps to
places it might not otherwise be able to enter so easily or effectively.
This is the regime of modern regulation Foucault described as gov-
ernmentality.
We are suggesting that law and science collaborate in a mutual con-
stitution whereby each is transformed, and the authority of each is pre-
served and extended. The interaction between law and science ends up
recreating the world, not only materially but also culturally and
morally. Although science takes pride in its material accomplishments,
it often denies responsibility for the organization of social relations it
helps to constitute. The very capacity to shape the material world cre-
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
79
ates moral problems that science denies having the capacity or respon-
sibility to solve. Nonetheless, the experimental process supporting sci-
entific authority has become so much a part of the way Western soci-
eties think and act that human subjects and the conduct of human life
itself are regarded as experiments, to be observed and manipulated just
the same as physical matter.2
Our work shows, however, that the scientific life is not immune
from the consequences of the social technologies science has spurred.
Specifically, we see that as the law operates on the spaces and the
forms within which science takes place, it contributes to the produc-
tion of a distinctive content: a particular kind of science and a partic-
ular kind of scientist, the content of knowledge claims and the daily
practices of scientists. By helping to constitute more separated spaces
for science, environmental and safety regulations push the private
lives of scientists out of the labs. As scientists are forced to segment
their lab and nonlab activities, they become increasingly fragmented,
just like other modern social subjects. Ironically, however, as the sci-
entists conform to standardized practices, becoming more like every-
one else, their claims to extraordinary objectivity and authority
increase.
We will illustrate the mutual constitution of science and law through
the construction and regulation of laboratory spaces in three parts.
First, we refer to the standard history of laboratory construction in
which what was once a private and elite space has become public and
relatively democratic. Without repeating the familiar history of
Enlightenment liberalism, the invention of the liberal subject, and the
development of democratic cultures, we will suggest some ways in
which the development and standardization of scientific laboratories is
part of, and mimics, that political story in terms of science's invocation
of some of the central norms of liberal democracy.
In the next part of the paper, we illustrate these processes with
ethnographic data collected in a major research university. These data
show that scientific spaces are defined around the contradictory issues
of danger and democracy, or interdiction and access. In the final section
of the paper, we will examine the processes of regulation that have
emerged to define scientific practice. In particular, the constitution of
space has emerged as a principal modality of governance. The creation,
design, and surveillance of space has, we argue, become increasingly
80
THE PLACE OF LAW
important in a world of autonomous subjects. Since it does not directly
challenge the autonomy of liberal subjects, the control of space operates
obliquely, sidestepping issues of subject freedom even while the spaces
thus constituted define and shape subjectivity and practice.
Transforming Spaces of Science and Creating Liberal
Subjects of Law
Over the course of the past four centuries, science has faced a formida-
ble epistemological dilemma. From its inception, science's claims about
an objective, lawlike, natural world challenged religious truth.
Whereas religious truth is based on faith, scientific knowledge derives
its legitimacy from empirical observation. In other words, scientific
authority has always been based upon a claim that seeing is believing.
Yet very few people actually see a gas turn into liquid under pressure,
or directly see the molecular structure of ribonucleic acid. Thus,
although science is offered as a direct challenge to a system based on
faith and trust, there is, Steven Shapin says,3 an ineradicable problem of
trust at the heart of science. "Why ought one to give one's assent to
experimental knowledge claims?" Why believe what one has not seen
and often cannot see?
A solution to this problem required that science engage in a project
of self-presentation.4 Scientific practice had to discover ways of
demonstrating or representing its found truths to a public in order to
obtain the legitimacy and deference, and thus effectiveness, it sought.
The various solutions that have been adopted have all implicated a
particular power optics, involving a designation of who can see and
what can be seen. And at the centerpiece of this history is the labora-
tory. As Lynch has observed,5 "There can be no doubt about the moral
and epistemological significance of. . . the 'physical place' of the sci-
entific laboratory."6
Up until the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, the laboratory was
a "truth spot,"7 a place in which the empirical truths of science were
revealed to a select audience of gentlemen.8 The particular location,
configuration, ownership, and design of the laboratory was available
to that select audience-for inspection. The legitimacy of scientific
claims about the world were dependent upon the idiosyncrasies of
place and the particularistic relationship that existed between the sci-
entist and his audience. Knowledge and truth were thus inscribed onto
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
8i
the laboratory and the social ties that connected scientists, their labora-
tory spaces, and their public.
Over the last two centuries, laboratory architecture and culture have
changed.9 What was private and personal, identified with and occu-
pied by a specific, socially located individual, became, with the collab-
oration of public authorities, more accessible, in a sense democratized,
standardized, and relatively indistinguishable from other similar
spaces. Laboratories have developed into vast, prototypical, universal
products with interchangeable parts and equipment, unremarkable in
the ease with which they are reproduced and installed in very different
physical conditions and cultural locations. Their contents have been so
standardized that contemporary laboratories are designed and built
Lego style: a pattern module is composed of stock materials, then
arranged in various configurations, most often in rows and bays, to fit
a building's dimensions and each research group's desired social orga-
nization.o Some laboratories emphasize unfettered correspondence
from one group to another, creating open passages between the rows
and bays; others limit communication but nonetheless create some pas-
sages to insure safety exits. Some labs build in sets of shared, commu-
nal equipment in order to leave more space for individual work-
benches, while other labs replicate each instrument, machine, and
facility for every work group in order to avoid dealing with differential
work and housekeeping habits."
The transformation of the laboratory into an anonymous and stan-
dardized space imparts to the laboratory an epistemological authority
that differs radically from its premodern antecedent. The laboratory is
no longer the place where truth is lodged; it has been demoted to a
backstage. Where the credibility of science in the seventeenth century
rested on public demonstrations and access to private homes, the pub-
lic part of science is no longer a performance in the Royal Society or a
visit to a researcher's lab. It is a publication. The text becomes the new
public space, open and accessible to all, in and through which the
provenance of science is established. Rather than seeing the experi-
ment, we see the report of it. We defer to the report because of what
Shapin calls the "literary technology" of the scientific journal: peer
review and critique, "a highly stylized machine for manufacturing
credible knowledge."'2 In modern scientific practice, the validity of a
claim is made and evaluated through replication, claimed and certified
through writing, peer review, publication, and circulation. Truth tran-
82
THE PLACE OF LAW
scends its place of discovery. In short, because the laboratory has
become standardized in its construction and composition, it can disap-
pear as an epistemological marker; we can take it for granted because it
is constant and universal.
Today the laboratory remains a context for scientific discovery, but it
is not seen as integral to the scientific truths it yields. This alteration in
the role of the laboratory reveals a much broader transformation in the
role of science in society in general, and in the relationship between law
and science in particular. The changing spaces of science correspond to
similar changes in the social construction of knowledge and the know-
ing subject. Slowly over these last four centuries, science has been
democratized, contributing a particularly modern source of authority.
Today, education and training, not familial or political status, permit
access to scientific knowledge.13 In this regard, the development of sci-
ence followed a host of liberalizing tendencies of the modern world.
The development of professional laboratories corresponds with and
was part of the more general liberalization of social relations, politics,
and law that came with the Enlightenment. With this liberalization, the
scientist qua observer is dislodged from his or her berth in the aristo-
cratic and caste based social structures. His or her relationship to others
in social hierarchies no longer grants the capacity to personally certify
or endow credibility. In much the same way that scientific truth has
been gradually dislodged from its place within the laboratory and resit-
uated in abstract textual space, the scientist is dislodged from particu-
lar, limited geographic and social spaces. The knower and the known
are, thus, seen as transcending any particular social arrangements.
Similarly, just as the laboratory virtually disappears from contempo-
rary accounts of scientific discovery,14 scientists, as embodied, histori-
cal persons, also largely disappear.'5 Contemporary critics of positivist
science often find fault with this obliteration of the observer and the sci-
entific claims to abstract, objective knowledge.'6 What is sometimes
overlooked in these critiques, however, is that this epistemology of
objectivity was politically subversive when it appeared in the emerging
modern world. Rejecting the constraints of religion, tradition, or state,
positivist epistemology both drew from and contributed powerfully to
the construction of the modern liberal subject, a subject who is believed
to be endowed with capacities and rights that transcend and predate
any particular social arrangement.
Linking the emergence of modern science with the creation of the
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
83
free liberal subject, the sociologist of science Edgar Zilsel has argued
that the closed, stratified social structure of feudal Europe was anath-
ema to experimental method.'7 The complete separation of intellectual
and manual labor characteristic of feudalism precluded the experimen-
tal manipulations that lie at the heart of scientific discovery. Feminist
philosopher of science Sandra Harding likewise observes,
Science's new way of seeing the world developed from the per-
spective of the new kind of social labor of artisans and inventors
of modern technologies. In turn, the new learning produced by
experimental observation increased the economic and political
importance of this kind of activity and social person. Experimen-
tal method became first possible and subsequently important
because it approached the world as it could be grasped only
from the perspective of a violation, a gap, a free space, in the feu-
dal division of labor.'8
Of course, as science became democratized-in the sense of being
taken out of the restricted hierarchies of aristocracy, caste, and place
it also became increasingly professionalized. Although there were no
longer any explicit legal or political restrictions on who could become a
scientist, few could claim familiarity or facility with scientific tech-
niques or knowledge. By the beginning of the twenty-first century this
professionalization has become more pronounced: scientific knowl-
edge has become even more technical, and laypersons have become
even less equipped to comprehend it. Yet despite the inaccessibility of
scientific knowledge for most citizens, there exists a cultural under-
standing of scientific knowledge as belonging to a community that
extends beyond the profession of scientists. Broman has used Haber-
mas's concept of the public sphere to explain this seeming paradox:
even as scientific knowledge becomes more inaccessible to nonprofes-
sionals lacking the educational or technical training, it is still seen as the
common property of everyone. Scientists, according to Shapin, assume
the role of the priests of what "we know."
Thus, the history of scientific laboratories, a history that culminates
in the epistemological disappearance of lab and scientist, replicates the
development and refinement of the mutual constitution of law and sci-
ence. Despite the fact that science was crucially implicated and depen-
dent upon political developments of the Enlightenment, it is precisely
84
THE PLACE OF LAW
through these developments that scientific practice, and the knowledge
it produces, can present itself as lying beyond the social, a sphere of
authoritative knowledge protected by claims of objectivity, transcen-
dence, and universality. Without asserting any causality or direction of
influence, it is sufficient to note here the remarkable salience between
the Enlightenment conception of the iconographic liberal individual
and the idealized conception of normal science. Just like scientific
knowledge, liberalism's subject exists independently of and prior to the
political order, the embodiment and carrier of rights that, just like sci-
entific knowledge, are objective, transcendent, and universal.
As science has been increasingly understood to transcend the social
and historical contexts of its production, the authority of tradition, reli-
gion, and law to confine scientific practice have been undermined. As a
more open and meritocratic system of education supplanted the system
of aristocratic privilege, it became more difficult to regulate science
through the norms of status and gentlemen's culture. This experiential
duality, an awareness of the dangers being created here coupled with
deference to the processes that are creating and possibly mastering
those dangers,19 mimics legality's similarly ambiguous relationship to
laboratory science. The moral and epistemological authority of science,
coupled with its instrumental material successes, sustains an almost
unparalleled autonomy from legal regulation of the "substance" of sci-
ence. At the same time, the immediate and potential perils cannot be
ignored. Science is simultaneously something wonderfully productive
and beneficial, and a threat in need of surveillance and control. Science
is simultaneously beyond the laboratory, in the consequences of its
knowledge, and materially and concretely within the spaces where sci-
entists work.
Governing Science
A building is a dogma, a machine is an idea.
-Victor Hugo
As Durkheim wrote, "the truths of science are independent of any local
context."20 Claiming to deal in universal physical laws, science has his-
torically positioned itself beyond the reach of humanly created law. It is
precisely the fetishization of science as a universal abstraction, we sug-
gest, that opens the lab-the material space of science-as a focus of
legal regulation.
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
85
As science achieved its epistemological authority as objective and
universal, the laboratory became less personal and more standard. The
laboratory's standardization makes the features of any particular labo-
ratory invisible in the production of science,21 unremarkable to the
degree that descriptions of laboratories are conventionally omitted
from most publications and presentations of experimental results.22 Yet
the apparent disappearance of the laboratory in contemporary
accounts of science disguises its increased importance as a site and gen-
erator of truth. Rather than provenance secured by locating each step of
the discovery process in a place and with a person (as, for example, is
the case of the provenance for a work of art), the paradoxical prove-
nance for scientific facts is secured by making the production of science
placeless. The standardization of labs makes particularistic knowledge
of each laboratory meaningless. Indeed, the intention of standardiza-
tion is to eliminate the particular in determining the validity or reliabil-
ity of the knowledge produced. In this way, the invisibility of the place
"secures the placelessness"-the universality-of scientific facts.23
Ironically, it is this placelessness of scientific facts that has created an
opening for law to enter and shape the practice of science. In denying
any particular epistemological importance to the laboratory, science
thereby permits law to claim this space as a terrain upon which it oper-
ates. In other words, through the governance of laboratory space, law
plays a role in shaping contemporary science and contemporary scien-
tists. From the contracts and trusts that establish the institutions within
which science is accomplished, to the safety regime of the federal labo-
ratory standard (a complex array of Occupational Safety and Health
Administration regulations), law is as much a part of the edifice of sci-
ence as the steel and glass, ducts and ventilating shafts so characteristic
of modern laboratory buildings. As sociolegal scholars have discovered
in studying other social and institutional sites-including workplaces,
neighborhood playgrounds, schools, and hospitals, the law is "all over"
the laboratory.24 Yet here, as elsewhere, the ubiquity of law is typically
overlooked. And in the final analysis, it is the failure to see the law that
is all over that grants it much of its power to constitute social life.
To identify the place of law in the space of science, we have been
studying scientific laboratories in several universities. The institutions
we are studying are ranked among the top ten in every scientific disci-
pline; their science faculties are world renowned, including dozens of
members of the National Academy of Sciences and the American Acad-
emy of Sciences, as well as a handful of Nobel laureates. We make no
86
THE PLACE OF LAW
claims to be speaking about all or a random sampling of contemporary
science. We are looking at elite American science. Our ethnographic
practice involves regular observation, watching, listening, taking notes
on what we see and hear, asking questions, collecting documents, and
conducting formal interviews with principal investigators, graduate
students, postdoctoral fellows, and lab directors on three campuses.
When introducing our research to the scientists we have interviewed
thus far, we have been receiving a fairly standard reaction to our
announced purpose of studying the connection between law and sci-
ence. Most say that there will be little to talk about. According to Fred
Donner, the director of one of the biomedical laboratories, the law is
irrelevant to science. "Oh, there is no law here. You will be wasting
your time. Of course there are OSHA and EPA regulations, but other-
wise the law is not pertinent to what we do."
Despite these disclaimers, it is undeniable that university laborato-
ries are saturated with legality. They are, of course, legal creations.
Through trusts, bequests, incorporation, and property law, universi-
ties, as well as the laboratories within, are legally created entities. All
research grants and contracts specify legal relationships. Although all
research scientists working with grants and contracts are, according to
their statements, painfully aware of the legal aspects of the funding
relationships, the legal constitution of their roles as employee-scien-
tists, as supervisors of subordinate employees (students or techni-
cians), or as researchers themselves is less salient. In general, they
become aware of these legal relationships only when a taken-for-
granted prerogative of one of their roles, such as tenure, is challenged.
In addition, the results of scientific research are routinely converted
into legally protected property through publication, copyright, patent-
ing, and licensing. Indeed, over the centuries, as science has become an
ever more public enterprise, its products have become increasingly and
more rapidly privatized.25 Thus, scientific laboratories are legal cre-
ations in the sense that they would not exist without the contracts and
trusts that created them, defined their purposes, established their
boundaries, specified the statuses and obligations of the scientists, and
secured the ownership of the research results.
These traces of legality are acknowledged by scientists but routinely
dismissed as being external to the process of discovery itself. Although
they are sometimes contentious and bitter and even more often annoy-
ing, the stipulations of labor law or even property law tend to be for-
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
87
gotten when scientists enter the laboratory to conduct their research.
Nonetheless, legality operates less conspicuously and yet powerfully in
the practice of science. In fact, law is "all over" science even as it is all
over social life in general.
First, law is inscribed in what Lefebvre referred to as the spaces of
representation: the signs used by the planners, architects, scientists,
and other social engineers to align "what is lived and perceived"26 with
their abstraction of it. The spaces of representations are, in effect, space
apprehended and conceptualized.27 Laboratories are designed, built,
operated, and inspected imagining certain types of scientific subjects
and scientific practice. Those subjects and practices are shaped, in part,
by the design and construction of the material laboratory spaces. To the
degree that science is regarded as a public process, its spaces will be
accessible; to the degree that science is conceived of as a matter of
national security, it could be politically dangerous and access will be
restricted.28 Because science is routinely believed to be physically and
materially dangerous, the design and building of the laboratories is a
thoroughly regulated matter. Thus, through the architectural concep-
tion of the laboratory, law participates in the material constitution of
laboratory science.
In addition to the abstractions of space, the law is also present in the
images and symbols embodied in the physical space, communicating
distinctive meanings. This is not the abstracted conception of the labo-
ratory appearing in drawings or blueprints, but the laboratory space as
it is experienced, as the aesthetic rather than instrumental imagination
apprehends and appropriates it. This is the space of perception not con-
ception, according to Lefebvre.29 "Overlay[ing] physical space," it
makes symbolic use of spatial objects. Representational space refers to
the metaphors and allegorical dimensions of space that mobilize sensa-
tions and affect. "The symbolic level," however, "is where architecture
itself kicks in," and "where land use rises above the level of real estate
speculation" and the organization of concrete, steel, and glass is more
than just a shelter from the elements. Architectural critics offer
accounts of the symbolic messages of buildings; "while not quantifi-
able," these representational aspects of space are "as substantial as the
materials from which the buildings are made."30
Finally, Lefebvre claims that there is not only conceived space, and
perceived space, but there is also lived space, or what he calls spatial
practices. By spatial practices, Lefebvre means the ways in which the
88
THE PLACE OF LAW
organization of space enables or constrains the conduct of life. In this
dimension of social spatialization, we want to know how scientific
research is conducted in these spaces. Here, we continue the focus on
the perception of laboratories as dangerous spaces to ask how the legal
regulation of danger has transformed the practice of scientific research.
In particular, legal regulation of laboratories has led scientists to trans-
form the routines of scientific research to manage the inherent dangers.
Although success at managing the danger enhances belief in scientific
mastery, the safety regime may be transforming the meaning of being a
scientist at the very same time.
These three dimensions of space can be used to interpret the social
significance of any particular site. Within a specific site, they may either
contradict or reinforce one another. Collectively, they constitute social
spaces whose foundation, according to Lefebvre, is prohibition. Social
space erects
the gulf between [the members of a society], their bodies and
consciousnesses, and the difficulties of social intercourse; the dis-
location of their most immediate relationships, and even the dis-
location of their bodily integrity; and lastly, the never fully
achieved restoration of these relations in an "environment"
made up of a series of zones defined by interdictions and bans.31
In the modern state, prohibitions, interdictions, and bans are the
province of law, in liberal regimes more often justified by the necessity
of containing harm and danger than by promoting a substantial good.
In fact, one of the most salient features of space as it is constructed
within contemporary scientific labs is the anticipation and containment
of danger: The semiotic and aesthetic representations of science are
coded for danger and hazard. The science of spatial planning, reflected
in architectural plans designating the size and layout of labs, is an
attempt to manage the inherent danger of experimentation. Finally, sci-
entific practice is spatialized along the transits of danger and safety that
lead to a partitioning of both lives and space. In each of these construc-
tions of dangerous spaces, law announces the danger, instructs appro-
priate responses, and reorganizes relationships among scientists and
their science.
Alongside the expression of danger and the prohibitions it requires,
the spaces of science are also coded as public, collective, that is, demo-
cratic. Thus, the social space of science is a shifting boundary whose
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
89
legally established outline comes to define in various ways the practice
of science and the identity of scientists.
Public Access and Dangerous Space
The image of science as both accessible and yet dangerous is first
encountered upon entering the buildings that house laboratories.
Within these buildings the public-private boundary is constructed
architecturally, decoratively, and legally to symbolize simultaneously
its public stature and significant danger.
At the entrance to many contemporary laboratories, we see broad
inviting plazas, marble vestibules, and grand staircases welcoming vis-
itors and workers alike. These are extraordinarily well built places; they
look as if no expense has been spared in terms of the durability and
attractiveness of the materials, the vastness of the spaces, and the vol-
ume and density of the technical facilities and equipment.
The doors are often unlocked; guards do not police entry. The title
and ownership of the building is nonetheless prominently displayed on
or next to the doors. Whom to call in case of emergency is also noted.
Thus, it is clear that these buildings are private and belong to some
legally responsible agent. Nonetheless, the public is offered free access
to these spaces.
It is not exactly clear, however, what the public gains access to when
they enter. The lobbies, in fact, lead nowhere. And few people do in fact
enter off the street. Most of time these vast impressive spaces are con-
spicuously empty, or function principally as transits through which
personnel enter the space of science.
Among the marble floors and grand stairways of these lobbies, one
cannot miss the art. There are commissioned murals designed as part
the building itself, paintings purchased for this site or borrowed from
the university museum; there are sculptures standing at entrances and
in courtyards. But the art does not stop in the public spaces. Along the
private corridors, on tack boards interspersed among lab equipment,
amid the posters tacked on bulletin boards announcing new courses,
upcoming conferences, or warning of one or another significant dan-
ger, there are watercolors, lithographs, and posters of famous and not-
so-famous artists: a Renoir portrait here, a Lichtenstein abstract there,
and watercolors of sailboats on the river.
Ironically, what is conspicuously absent from these open spaces is
science. The boundary between public and private space, the space of
90
THE PLACE OF LAW
science, is marked explicitly-through signs stating that the public is
not allowed beyond this point. The exclusion is not expressed in terms
of personal character or eligibility. No passes are demanded, no screen-
ing devices or card readers operate. The invocation of danger is the
rationale for restricting public access, and that danger is expressed lit-
erally, loudly, and profusely, the warning labels appended almost
everywhere.
Along the corridors, amid the posters, sculptures, and paintings,
there is an almost endless parade of warnings: "Danger, Radioactive
Materials"; "Danger, do not open this door"; "Danger, never leave this
door open." Some signs describe what attire must be worn in these
spaces and what cannot be worn. "Do Not Enter Without Eye Protec-
tion." "Do not wear contaminated clothing outside of the lab." Or the
signs include instructions about what to do in case of contamination.
"BLi: This is a Level 1 Biohazard facility. In case of accident call . . ."
Other signs instruct how materials are to be disposed from this space.
Another sign reads "BL2: This is a Level 2 Biohazard facility. In this lab-
oratory,..." continuing on to explain the conditions for entering, leav-
ing, disposing of materials.
Yet the danger is also conveyed tacitly and implicitly by the archi-
tecture, fittings, and furnishings. There is a noticeable shift in materials
from the public to the private spaces, from marble and mahogany to
glass and steel. Beyond the public spaces, the perils are contained
behind steel doors with small viewing windows reminiscent of the
doors and passages in a contemporary prison. These are clearly sealed
spaces. The danger is also symbolized by the profusion of combination
locks on the doors, locks that can be opened when your hands hold
samples and equipment. The constant jeopardy is represented by the
row of safety showers installed along the corridors. The design of the
showers seems to have varied over the years. In one very recently ren-
ovated laboratory, their presence is both announced and camouflaged,
expressing the latent ambiguity one experiences in these spaces. There
is a simultaneous recognition of the persistent and pervasive danger of
what is going on here coupled with a sense of mastery that suggests
whatever the dangers are, they are under control.
Constructing Safe Spaces
Danger is not simply constructed by policing the public-private bound-
ary. It is constantly negotiated within the work spaces of the lab itself.
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
91
In the course of our research, we heard a story that illustrates how
space is legally partitioned to manage danger. At the university, new
laboratories were being created in older buildings undergoing total
renovation. The chemistry department would be given additional
space in the renovated area. The chair of the department worked
closely with the faculty who were to move into the new spaces, collect-
ing their wish lists for square footage and facilities.
Nine months into the planning meetings with the architects, draw-
ings began to appear. At that point the chair discovered that there were
25 percent fewer lab benches than had been agreed in the earlier meet-
ings. When he pressed for an explanation, the architects responded that
legal regulation stipulated greater distance between the benches than
the faculty had specified. Among the scientists affected, this change in
design was described as a crisis. By increasing the distance between the
lab benches and reducing their number, the architects had reduced the
possible size, and therefore productivity, of the research groups. When
the department chair presented the faculty's grievances to the archi-
tects, they responded that it was a matter of safety regulations and
insisted that they could not change the designs. A monograph had been
published by a professor at another university-as part of his research
product-that recommended good laboratory practices.32 When the
architects had conferred with the university's attorneys, they were told
that the existence of the book made it unwise to build the lab benches
closer than the distance specified there. Should there ever be an acci-
dent, the attorneys claimed, the book could be cited in expert testi-
mony, and the university might be held liable.
As Lefebvre suggested, the abstract conceptualized spaces of repre-
sentation, such as blueprints, have the capacity to modify and inter-
vene in space.33 In this case, an imagined legal constraint was figura-
tively and then concretely built into the laboratory, significantly
reducing the overall research capacity of these groups.
Governing Danger and Managing Self-Governance
The management of danger is not necessarily imposed from outside of
science. Increasingly, safety in the laboratory has become a major part
of the scientific persona. For one of our subjects, David Laslett,34 this
preoccupation with laboratory safety began with his appointment as
department safety officer. This role was traditional in chemistry depart-
ments but has now spread to every department that uses any chemicals
92
THE PLACE OF LAW
for any activity-from cleaning paint palettes, to disinfecting animal
cages, to synthesizing new molecules. Concerns with laboratory safety
took on new meaning when in 1990 OSHA enacted what is known as
the Lab Standard for the safe handling and disposal of chemicals in
research laboratories.
The Lab Standard was created because the existing OSHA rules
were designed for industrial sites and did not work well for research
laboratories. Industrial sites do the same things over and over again.
Because of this standardization and repetitiveness, the forms and
processes of industrial safety can, like the work, also be routinized. By
contrast, most scientific laboratories perform a vast array of different
activities, some of them infrequently. They also typically perform these
acts on a smaller scale, using smaller quantities of chemicals or other
potentially hazardous materials. Because of the variation in processes
and materials, it is difficult to anticipate the kinds of dangers that might
be involved. "There are lots of things," Laslett said, "for which hazards
are not known. They're new substances we've created as part of our
research. And so research lab people said that the laws that are being
applied to us really are not relevant." In other words, the dangers that
attach to research laboratories are to a significant degree unspecifiable
in advance. As a consequence, according to Laslett, the scientists have
taken on the role of regulating themselves. Laslett describes the
process.
We tried to change the culture of safety when I took over in 1990.
... I would say the prior situation was an adversarial relation-
ship between the safety police and researchers and faculty. Occa-
sionally some sort of proclamation would come through-like
you can't wear shorts if you work in the lab-that people would
treat derisively and ignore totally.... The chemists didn't have
much respect for [the safety inspectors who did come by or
make rules] because they weren't as smart in chemistry as we
are, and they came and were saying you're not using this prop-
erly. But they didn't know what the structure and properties of
the chemicals were. They would lose credibility in front of the
students. It was a really bad situation.
We had, in a sense, to reinvent our whole safety regime. So it
was an opportunity to do this differently. It's as if you're saying
we're throwing out our entire legal code and rewriting it.
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
93
The OSHA Lab Standard is an interesting performance-based
law, which means that it doesn't lay out in detail [that] under the
following conditions you must wear safety glasses, under the
following conditions you don't. Instead, what it comes down to
is it says you must appoint a person called the chemical hygiene
officer and you must write something called the Chemical
Hygiene Plan. And it doesn't specify what you put in there.
What it does say is that this has to be effective in protecting all
researchers from hazards. We're not telling you what a safe labo-
ratory is. You are going to make up rules that make a safe labo-
ratory. That's what the law, the federal law says.... They did
not lay out in excruciating detail one-size-fits-all safety rules. It
says, "We will allow you to... design your own safety plan. We
may inspect and determine if it is effectively protecting people,
and if it is, then it's satisfactory, but we are not going to micro-
manage things."
When the law went into effect, the first thing [we] had to do
was to decide, how are we going to comply with it? Are we
going to have a single safety chemical hygiene officer who
would be safety czar over the entire [university], or are we going
to make every PI [principal investigator], every professor, a
chemical hygiene officer....
So the most important decision we made was that safety
should begin at the grass roots.... If we didn't enlist the people
affected by these rules in the creation of new rules [it wouldn't
work].... The idea was that we would create a structure. The
creation of the new safety rules would be done cooperatively by
faculty, students, and administrators within each department.
And the enforcement of compliance-monitoring the compliance
and enforcing-would similarly involve not only faculty admin-
istrators and authority figures but those researchers, the people
who are affected by the rules. [This was] to overcome the adver-
sarial relationship that otherwise inevitably develops if you have
people outside of the community creating rules and monitoring
compliance and enforcing them.
As Laslett claimed was common, Fred Donner expressed just that
resentment toward the agency that monitors the care and protection of
the animals in the laboratory he directs. "Look," he said, "it's a big pain
94
THE PLACE OF LAW
because we want the mice healthy. People are going to want them
healthy because they can't do their experiments [otherwise]. But, in
addition, we have a bureaucracy that deals with making sure that we
do." Because scientists have a direct interest in securing the health and
safety of their experimental animals, Donner claimed, the spot inspec-
tions and detective work of the government agencies wasted time and
energy.
Laslett's account of the invention of the safety regime at his univer-
sity illustrates the self-regulation that is at the heart of regimes of gov-
ernmentality.
After a lot of debate we came up with a plan which would be
more or less equivalent [across the university]. Every depart-
ment would have its own chemical hygiene officer and plan. We
felt that it was unrealistic for each individual laboratory profes-
sor to have one.
It was also not a good strategy to establish one policy for the entire uni-
versity. In the past, that had not produced an effective safety system
because of the hostility between the researchers and the safety profes-
sionals.
The researchers felt that they had no stake in the creation of the
laws. And the laws, any rules, tend to interfere in some way with
research if only in terms of making it less convenient to do cer-
tain things. And the fact is that some of the benefits are not
immediately apparent-like, I'm not going to get cancer thirty
years from now. It is not necessarily easy for people to see the
long-term benefits of these short-term inconveniences. The
inconveniences being applied from on high, naturally people are
less cooperative.
He continued, "My agenda was that if we involved everybody at the
beginning making rules, they were more likely to appreciate why these
are important and necessary; they are more likely to cooperate." Of
course, their cooperation must be verified.
It is very important not just to have an initial training lecture and
to give people copies of these documents, it's also important that
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
95
we check that they're working in compliance with it. So what we
have, in our department, is a system of inspections. Every
research lab (that means every group) is inspected unan-
nounced-unannounced inspection twice a year... by a team
consisting of one faculty member and one graduate student from
the chemical hygiene and safety committee.
Not all scientists defer so conspicuously to the law's authority.
Sometimes they engage instrumentally with the regulatory regime.
And Laslett, despite the grassroots training and surveillance system he
has created, is unwilling to bow down passively before what he calls
"the regulatory czars" if it means large fines or public embarrassment
for his university. When the EPA inspectors found violations, despite
the efforts of the university, he participated in negotiations over several
years to mitigate the violations and reduce the fines and public expo-
sure.
At other times, some scientists express their reluctance to take the
regulatory regime seriously, and go along either willingly or strategi-
cally. Laslett described some of his colleagues' reactions this way.
Now, in the first time around, when it went into effect, there
were several laboratories, three I remember, that you might say
failed the inspection, where your problems were so egregious
that the letter [we sent] said, "In view of these serious violations,
we will be returning within a few weeks to inspect again, please
correct the problems," something like that. It's a fairly positive
letter.... In two or three cases the second inspection they [also]
failed. Fortunately, the department chair at that time was a non-
laboratory person, a theoretical person not as intimate with real,
wet chemicals; he was particularly paranoid and very support-
ive. So the third letter basically says that in the event that there
are still any problems with the third inspection, we will have no
alternative but to order your laboratory closed to further
research until these problems are corrected. And then there was
a kind of postscript that federal law requires that if you have any
funding from federal agencies, we have to notify them that work
is ordered halted here.
So Goody had a bit of a problem [in his lab]-I don't think it's
there anymore-but he had on his website, for a while, a quote
96
THE PLACE OF LAW
from that letter. My words in that letter were that if your group
had been here when the EPA did their inspection, you definitely
would have been the worst lab in the department. So he actually
had one of those scrolling things on the bottom of his web page
[reading] "Worst Lab in the Department"...
Then he was supplanted by Shoemaker. When Shoemaker
had a bad inspection, I said, "Oh man, Goody, I don't think
you're in the lead anymore." He created a running thing which
said, "We are no longer the worst lab. For the link to the worst
lab..." etc.
Gusterson discusses the function of this kind of humor among scien-
tists as a means of managing the emotional consequences of their work's
danger.35 Although Gusterson focuses on the work of weapons scien-
tists whose task is to create the most horrendous and potential dangers
for human bodies (as a part of an elaborate and possibly perverse secu-
rity system-mutual assured destruction), the transmission and acquisi-
tion of a culture of embodied danger is generally part of the training and
socialization of scientists.36 Jokes become one of the ways in which
members of a community reveal and deal with conflict and anxiety.37
Gusterson reports that almost all the jokes he heard in a course on
nuclear physics "had to do with the vulnerability of the human body
and the ignorant fears of non-scientists."38 The jokes are funny, Guster-
son argues, because they are about dangers that have been mastered,
such as radioactivity. Jokes about AIDS, he suggests, are not funny
because AIDS is a subject "before which we feel helpless."
The radiation jokes are funny, at least for physicists, because
although radiation is dangerous, physicists feel confident that
they understand radioactivity and know how to deal with it
though the jokes have an extra edge because they nag anxiously
at this confidence. The jokes play with the body's vulnerability
to radioactivity, teaching students to laugh both at the danger
and at those who, not understanding that heavy water is not
radioactive, for example, have an exaggerated fear of it.39
"These are jokes," Gusterson writes, "that make an elite commu-
nity." Professors Goody and Shoemaker can run banners on their web-
sites announcing the poor safety records of their laboratories because
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
97
they are confident that they have mastered the real and possibly serious
dangers of chemical reactions. Thus, what their web screen crawls
announce is the foolishness of those who have insisted on these legal
regulations, and perhaps of the department chair, who doesn't "get
wet" with chemicals in a real lab.
Discussion: Space, Power, and Transformations in
Social Control
The parallel development of the liberal subject and autonomous science
share a trajectory that has long been observed in Western societies, cul-
ture, and law: from status to contract, from gemeinschaft to
gesellschaft, from mechanical to organic solidarity, each of these for-
mulations marking a transition from the corporeal to the abstract.
Abstractions themselves, these familiar characterizations also mark
transformations in specific practices of social control that are of partic-
ular relevance to legality and especially the capacities of law to contain
the dangers of modern science. These historical movements signal,
first, a shift away from the direct regulation of subject persons, and, sec-
ond, a shift toward the regulation of spaces, with the result that all ter-
ritories, properties, sites, zones, buildings, parks, homes, movie the-
aters, and, of course, laboratories are imprinted with law. In this
modern system, the social control of science is achieved primarily
through regulation of the physical spaces where the danger resides. We
have illustrated how this regulatory regime operates in some contem-
porary laboratories. We would like to elaborate the shape and texture
of this transformation in the relationship between space, power, and
law more generally.
Foucault, who has been called a cartographer of power, conceptual-
ized modern transformations in social control as a movement from
bodies to minds and spaces. According to Deleuze,40 Foucault's entire
theory of power is spatial in nature. Although space is central to Fou-
cault's work, the role of space is not the same across the different modes
of power Foucault identified. He invoked two powerful, but distinc-
tive, spatial images to represent and contrast exclusionary and discipli-
nary modes of power. In the former case, he described the leper and his
separation into an excluded, disqualified mass. In the case of discipline,
he evoked the image of the city under siege by the plague, where the
enclosure and meticulous partitioning of space allowed for the distrib-
98
THE PLACE OF LAW
ution of individuals to be supervised and contained. Each of these
modalities of regulation relies on space to produce (in the case of the
expelled leper) the pure community leached of the unredeemable, and
(in the case of the ordered city) a regimented society where no one was
excluded from the regulatory machinery.
In his later essays, Foucault outlined what has since been construed
by his intellectual progeny as a third form of regulation, governmental-
ity.4' Space figures most centrally and complexly in this form of regula-
tion. If exclusion and discipline are animated by the dreams of purity
and order, this third mode of power seeks a different dream, that of
freedom, or, to be more precise, a subject who can be governed through
his or her freedom. The dream of a free, but governable, subject is
necessitated by the paradox of power to which we have already
alluded and that lies at the heart of a liberal regime: that is, govern-
ments create zones of privacy and autonomy to which they, by their
own authority, are denied access. Governmentality, as a mode of regu-
lation, is a response or accommodation to this paradox. Through an
array of discursive and material practices and technologies, liberal sub-
jects are increasingly, albeit imperfectly, governed through, rather than
against, their freedom.42
This trick is achieved in part by the retreat and fragmentation of cen-
tral governing power. We are, to use Rose's term, governed at a dis-
tance. This distance is both constitutional, in that regulation is achieved
through a variety of nonpolitical experts and authorities (including
medical experts, architects, human relations experts, and the media),
and spatial, in that these operations are located and practiced in dis-
persed sites. Rather than the central tower of the panopticon, with its
single shrouded watcher, governing from a distance implicates hun-
dreds upon hundreds of experts, teachers, physicians, counselors, fam-
ily planners, architects, and talk show hosts, to name but a few.
Ironically, the terminus of these distant and dispersed vectors of reg-
ulation and control, the point at which they all converge and reach their
fullest expression, is the individual subject. In order that governmen-
tality succeed as a mode of regulation, it must realize or produce sub-
jects who are actively engaged in the very same technologies of gover-
nance as the political, scientific, medical, and ethical experts. In this
sense, governmentality is both distant and, at the same time, very close.
Capturing this contradiction, Mariana Valverde has described the
result of this process as the despotism of the self.43
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
99
To achieve this outcome, those who govern must develop strategies
of aligning their goals and projects with those to be governed. Rose
calls this task of alignment one of "translation." The various mecha-
nisms of translation instrumentalize political authority as freedom.
One of the primary technologies of translation involves the con-
struction, surveillance, and regulation of space. To fully capture how
governmentality works in the liberal cultures of freedom, this form of
governing through space must be distinguished from the spatial prac-
tices of discipline. Disciplinary techniques involve the enclosure of
space and the containment of individuals within enclaves (such as pris-
ons, schools, barracks, rows of desks, and office cubicles). By ordering
space and distributing individuals across the grids, subjects become the
objects of surveillance and control. In the case of discipline, space is a
means to achieve the disciplining of bodies. By contrast, in the case of
governmentality, space itself is the object of governance, and individu-
als are incidentally (and episodically) controlled and constructed as
subjects only as they occupy or pass through these governed spaces.
A few examples may help at this point. Recent legal battles over the
rights and obligations of pregnant women to their fetuses (including
the very recent case of a woman imprisoned in Massachusetts for refus-
ing to submit to a court-ordered medical examination) exemplify the
processes through which governable subjects are constructed through
the regulation of space. Over the past few decades, fetuses have been
constructed as persons deserving of protection from such things as
maternal drinking, or in the case we just cited above, from the mother's
religious convictions regarding the rejection of modern medicine.
These recent cultural (and legal) interpretations of fetuses as subjects
who are separate from and vulnerable to the mother depend upon
other cultural constructions, in this case specifically of the womb.
Petchesky has argued, for instance, that with the development of fetal
imaging technologies such as ultrasound, the fetus has been repre-
sented as separate and autonomous from the mother who, in turn, has
become the empty space inhabited by the new subject.44 The famous
Life magazine cover showing the fetus floating in space without context
or connection presents a creature who is uncontained. It is through
such a spatial uncoupling of mother and fetus that the absent mother
"is increasingly put in the position of adversary to her own pregnancy,
either by having presented a 'hostile environment' to its development
or by actively refusing some medical intervention."45 The Life magazine
100
THE PLACE OF LAW
image of the unbounded space, absent the demarcation of the environ-
ment of the womb, created a representation of an individual person
deserving of protection, but at the same time dependent and incapable
of self-governance. Thus, through this spatial imagery, the mother
becomes the relay or the proxy for this newly constructed subject.
Constructing the fetus as an autonomous subject through the fabri-
cation of space is a particularly rich example insofar as it illustrates the
crucial role of inscription in the process of governance. According to
Latour it is primarily through inscription techniques such as maps,
charts, blueprints, and in this case photographs, that what he calls
"immutable mobiles" from dispersed and distant places (such as the
wombs of countless women) are accumulated, stabilized, made
durable, and thus available for inspection and regulation. These mech-
anisms are "little machines for producing conviction in others." Most
importantly, given the political objectives of governmentality, as our
own experiences are converted through these representational devices
and thus made available to our own inspections, surveillance, and
judgments, these little machines (inscription techniques) produce con-
victions within the very subjects represented.
It is not just conviction that is produced, however. By designing
space, giving it form, dimension, locating it in relation to other spaces,
opening or closing access to it, and so forth, space becomes a context
and resource for social action. According to Shields, "the possible,
likely and habitual routines of place are thus concretized in built envi-
ronments and sedimented in the landscape."46 The parking garage with
the speed bumps and tire-ripping grids promote driving at certain
speeds and directions without having to make direct person-to-person
appeals to drivers.
According to Valverde's history of the regulation of alcohol, the
policing of saloons provides another example of this spatial modality of
power.47 In the early twentieth-century zeal to eliminate the saloon (a
space thought to generate excess and immorality), efforts were made to
prohibit some spatial designs and mandate others. Local licensing
boards debated whether patrons should be able to stand at the bar, or
what particular arrangement of furniture would be most unsaloonlike.
Some argued that saloons should have large windows onto the street to
foster surveillance. Others argued against windows on the grounds
that the streetside viewers would be tempted or contaminated by the
sight. For the most part these efforts were thwarted by the fact that
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
101
there was no consensus over the essential or defining features of a
saloon. The significant point, however, is that these local regulations
more or less ignored the soul of the drinker. The governing impulse
was targeted upon the drinking establishment itself and only inciden-
tally on the drinkers who would inhabit it.
This analysis points to the opportunities, routines, and escape routes
offered by certain spaces to create or foreclose possibilities for sociabil-
ity and consumption (in the case of the saloon), or for being and con-
nection (in the case of the womb). And, as Shields notes, when behav-
iors engendered by particular environments become ritualized or
conventionalized, this produces roles and identities for the individuals
(or groups) inhabiting those spaces.48
In Western thought, dating from Bacon and Descartes, space has
been understood to be an empty void that contains objects. According
to this view, space exists (or can be known to exist) only where it con-
tains objects,49 although even then it is not reducible to them. More
recent theorists, such as Lefebvre, reject this definition of space as
empty, or as simply a container.50 Lefebvre claims that space is itself a
materially produced form, a concrete abstraction, similar to Marx's
notion of the commodity. Space is, in this formulation, a material real-
ization of its design and production. It is, according to Lefebvre, a con-
densation of the social relations of its production. Whereas the classical
view of space was that it was defined by its inhabitants, Lefebvre's
reconceptualization admits the opposite possibility: that spaces are
capable of defining their inhabitants. Social space endows and consti-
tutes subjectivity by presupposing certain kinds of inhabitants (how-
ever temporary or brief their habitation). In other words, space is con-
structed (by virtue of its siting, shape, size, dimensions, contours,
openings, and relationships with other spaces) with certain practices
and persons in mind.
Of course, the classical view of space as a void defined by its contents
is itself a particular historical construction, the product of precisely this
dialectic of spatialization. Up until the twentieth century, cities,
dwellings, and other places derived their meaning and form from a long
"history of habitation." These spaces bore the imprint of the lives and
routines of their inhabitants. And the perfect coincidence of space and
its inhabitants made it difficult to imagine one without the other.
It is precisely this history of habitation that is ruptured by the social
and geographic mobility of modernity. The circulation of persons
102
THE PLACE OF LAW
throughout social structures and of bodies through and across geo-
graphic distances, renders older forms of regulation, in particular those
encompassing modes of subjectivity and power such as discipline,
more difficult. Under such conditions, it becomes much more effective
to focus on the governance of space and allow the circulation of sub-
jects.
Thus, we would propose that at the heart of governmentality is the
production and control of space. Individuals who circulate through or
inhabit the spaces so constructed are created as subjects enabled or dis-
abled by the environment. Governmentality offers a solution to the dif-
ficulty of governing free subjects in the modern liberal state. Explicit
moral instruction or legal prohibitions aimed at individual behaviors
are partially supplanted by a form of regulation that operates from afar
and somewhat obliquely. It operates by fabricating spaces designed to
constitute certain types of subjects, allow for certain types of behaviors,
and acknowledge certain types of truth.
Conclusions
Concerns about safety and danger have shaped the spaces and thereby
altered the professional lives, consciousness, and passions of scientists.
Because functions must be spatially separated-no exposing of bodies
in the presence of laboratory chemicals, no putting on makeup, no
ingesting food or drink of any kind-laboratories occupy more physi-
cal space for the same functions than they did in the past. In newer lab-
oratory buildings, spaces are allocated for in-house canteens so that
researchers need not travel to eateries. OSHA regulations prohibiting
eating in the lab can be satisfied while the sense of work too consuming
to abandon for lunch can also be sustained. Depending on the local cul-
ture, lunch/reading rooms have been allocated one per building, or
one per floor or corridor, creating unexpected but productive opportu-
nities for exchanges among members of different labs. Or, as is the case
in one newly renovated laboratory, lunch/reading rooms have been
attached to each investigator's laboratory, restricting rather than
expanding the possibilities of serendipitous exchanges among labs.
When space is at a premium, as it is in all universities, this mode of
accommodating the legal ban on food in the lab means that some per-
sons and some functions get short-changed or are eliminated entirely.
In the building where lunchrooms were allocated one per investigator's
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
1o3
lab, emeritus professors were moved out of the building, limiting their
continued interactions with the graduate students and junior faculty,
cutting short their professional careers.
Fred Donner offered us additional insight on the ways in which the
life and practices of experimental scientists have been transformed
through these new forms of regulation.
It used to be that all the professors' offices were, for example,
ensconced in the laboratories themselves, and that was part of
the general ethos, which was eating, sleeping, drinking, and
making love in the laboratories. It was all allowed. Or if it wasn't
allowed, people did it anyway. I mean they lived their lives in
the lab. Now there's none of that.... Offices, as you can see, are
cauterized from the laboratories, and if I see somebody eating,
smoking, or doing anything in the labs, they get fined one hun-
dred dollars. It's tough.
If the seventeenth-century chemist Robert Boyle brought chemistry
into his father's, sister's, and his own living quarters, twentieth-century
scientists brought, as Donner reports, their entire lives and selves into
the lab. As our introductory joke implies, the life of a scientist is sup-
posed to be a life devoted almost entirely to science; nonprofessional
aspects of life are sublimated to science. Indeed, Donner confesses that
the laboratory life, or life in the laboratory, was part of why he became
a scientist. He says, "I liked the life; I was a lab rat. I enjoyed being in
the lab." However, because of legal mandates and rules concerning
health, safety, and environmental protection, the characteristic features
of modern science and scientists have been transformed, and that way
of being a scientist is no longer possible. What was a life enacted almost
entirely within the laboratory has now been fragmented through the
partitioning and legal regulation of laboratory space. Shapin concludes
that the house of experiment is now a place where no one resides.51
Exploring the laboratory as an object of governance and as a spatial
means to regulate the dangers of science within liberal democracy, this
paper makes two moves. First, it shifts the focus of governance from the
liberal individual (who is made vulnerable to surveillance and control
through freedom) to an institution (which is made both dangerous and
vulnerable through its claims of autonomy and universality). Second,
we conceptualize governmentality as an ensemble of spatial processes
104
THE PLACE OF LAW
that in many ways operate alongside the subject-individual or institu-
tion-who is then "free" to circulate within the regulated spaces.
We argue that precisely because the laboratory plays a crucial role in
the production and governance of science, it has become an important
locus for the legal regulation of science and the various material and
cultural dangers science poses. As laboratories are designed, sur-
veilled, and monitored by literally hundreds of discrete legal rules, sci-
entists themselves-as embodied historical subjects who eat, drink,
sleep, and make love-are increasingly dislodged from these spaces.
By helping to constitute more separated spaces for science, legal regu-
lations push the private lives of scientists out of the labs, stripping sci-
entific practice of some of its more personal and idiosyncratic aspects.
Law works here, as elsewhere, to standardize and homogenize differ-
ences. In this instance, however, it may contribute to, rather than
undermine, the authority of science and scientists, as personal and idio-
syncratic characteristics create vulnerabilities in science's claims to
impersonal, placeless universality.
Ironically, however, because scientists no longer understand the lab-
oratory as an "authenticating place" (that is, a unique place that
imparts truth through its specific location, design, or content), legal
regulation of space has been able to operate with a minimum of resis-
tance. In other words, it is the increasing invisibility of the laboratory in
the epistemology and moral authority of science that has enabled law
to govern science "at a distance." The project of governing science from
a distance has been enabled by the efforts of scientists themselves to
construct science as an abstraction, a practice that lies beyond the reach
of law. Thus, dislodging truth from the laboratory, or locating it only
incidentally therein (because any similarly appointed lab would do),
has opened within the "space of science" a "place for law."
NOTES
This paper was first prepared for presentation as a Keck Lecture at Amherst
College, Department of Law, Jurisprudence and Social Thought, November 6,
2000. We wish to thank Karina Coombs and Ayn Cavicchi for their extensive
help collecting materials on the history of laboratory construction and on the
contemporary legal regulation of laboratories. We are also indebted to col-
leagues who have been generous with their time and comments, helping us to
navigate new terrain and saving us from egregious errors. We are particularly
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
105
grateful to Jack Balkin, Susan Bandes, Paul Berman, Kristin Bumiller, David
Caudill, David Delaney, Joe Dumit, Michael Fischer, Brian Glenn, Douglas
Goodman, David Kaiser, Jim Kinsey, Jennifer Mnookin, Laura Beth Nielsen,
Jason Owen-Smith, Tanina Rostain, Austin Sarat, Joseph Swingle, Abha Sur,
Alison Young, and the members of the Amherst Seminar on Law and Popular
Culture, for their helpful critiques.
1. We note that science has remained a gendered occupation to a greater
degree and far longer than many other professions.
2. Egon Bittner, "Technique and the Conduct of Life," Social Problems 30
(1983): 249.
3. Steven Shapin, "The House of Experiment in Seventeenth-Century Eng-
land," Isis 79 (1988): 373.
4. Stephen Hilgartner, Science on Stage (Palo Alto: Stanford University
Press, 2000).
5. Michael Lynch, "Laboratory Space and the Technological Complex: An
Investigation of Topical Contextures," Science in Context 4 (1991): 51.
6. Inquiry into the epistemological and moral significance of space is
growing. See for example John Brigham's forthcoming study of courthouse
architecture.
7. Tom Gieryn and David Brian, "Authenticating Places," paper presented
to meetings of the American Sociological Association, 1999.
8. Shapin, "House of Experiment."
9. P. Gallison and E. Thompson, eds., The Architecture of Science (Cam-
bridge: MIT Press, 1999).
10. The standardization of modern laboratories should not be exaggerated
to suggest that there is no variation among individual labs or between different
fields of science. Our reference to Lego style is meant to highlight the fact of suf-
ficient standardization such that the pieces that are put into most labs can be
purchased from catalogs of mass-produced items. Some subjects, for example,
organic chemistry and many areas of bioscience, are much more standard than
others because the tools of these fields are fairly universal and interchangeable.
Physical chemistry and physics labs tend to be idiosyncratic-some might say
chaotic-in their layout rather than arranged in rows and bays. Here the con-
struction of the equipment is often a major part of the scientist's invention.
Thus standardization may affect parts of the building more than the contents,
but, as we have said, this varies by field. See note 14 below.
11. Tom Gieryn, "Biotechnology's Private Parts (and Some Public Ones),"
in Making Space for Science: Territorial Themes in Shaping of Knowledge, ed. Cros-
bie Smith and Jon Agar (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1998).
12. Shapin, "House of Experiment."
13. As we suggested briefly above, science continues to be a highly gen-
dered profession (Sonner and Holton 1995, Schiebinger 1999, Reports of the
Committees on the Status of Women Faculty, MIT 2002). It is even more strati-
fied by race. Stratification by social class, which had characterized science for
io6
THE PLACE OF LAW
centuries, is no longer strong. Thus, in making our historical comparison, we
can mention an increasing social accessibility in contrast to the material inac-
cessibility of the laboratory. The rationale and the consequence of this inacces-
sibility have changed, however, so that exclusion is also democratic, based on
danger and contamination rather than class and gentlemanly status.
14. The laboratory-in the sense of the pieces and parts that can be dislodged
from the building shell and walls and could be metaphorically shaken out-are
usually not described in publications unless the design is highly unusual. The
specific apparatus developed by an investigator is, however, often described in
some detail, especially if it is a new invention. In many instances, however, there
will be separate publications in a vehicle such as the Review of Scientific Instru-
ments that deal solely with the apparatus. In some areas of physical science,
especially where the techniques are part of the invention, it is rare not to have a
description of the apparatus and its use in making the measurements. "To be
sure, these descriptions are often insufficiently detailed for exact replication of a
measurement, but in fact it is often the case that others will copy an innovative
technique," Jimmy Lloyd explained to us, although scientists may have to
design the apparatus themselves. Thus, like the standardization of the labora-
tory space, representation of the apparatus in publications varies by field and
discipline. In general, it is not a central part of the publication unless the tech-
niques or instruments are new. See notes 22 and 23 below.
15. Of course the scientist does not disappear from science. In terms of pres-
tige, the naming of discoveries, functions, awarding of prizes, science pays
abundant homage to its great men [sic]. These honors (prizes, biographies,
immortality) accrue to, and as far as we can see are enjoyed by, embodied
human beings, the scientists. When we say that the scientist disappears, then,
we refer here to the fact that personal authority or biography is not relevant for
the authority of an observation and that the observation stands independent of
the person observing. Indeed, much of the practice of science works to strip it
of these human individual markers (Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar, Labora-
tory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts [Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1979];
Bruno Latour, Science in Action [Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1988]).
16. Dorothy Smith, The Experienced World as Problematic: A Feminist Method,
Sorokin Lecture No. 12 (Saskatoon: University of Saskatoon, 1981); Nancy
Hartsock, "Political Change: Two Perspectives on Power," in Building Feminist
Theory: Essays from Quest, ed. Charlotte Bunch (New York: Longman, 1974).
17. Edgar Zilsel, "The Sociological Roots of Science," American Journal of
Sociology 47 (1942): 544-62.
18. Sandra Harding, The Science Question in Feminism (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press, 1986); Pierre Bourdieu, "The Specificity of the Scientific Field
and the Social Conditions of the Progress of Reason," in The Science Studies
Reader, ed. Mario Biagioli (New York: Routledge, 1998).
19. Bittner, "Technique."
20. Emile Durkheim, Selected Writings, edited and translated by Anthony
Giddens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972), 88.
21. We do not suggest that laboratories are unimportant to the production
THE ARCHITECTURE OF AUTHORITY
107
of science. Quite the opposite: Laboratories are essential vehicles for the pro-
duction of science. We emphasize only that the laboratory is no longer synony-
mous, as it once was, with the science. Today, it is the place where science is
produced; it is not science.
22. An important exception illustrates the general point (see notes o10 and 14
above). In presentations of experimental results, chemists and physicists pre-
sent information and images on the laboratory design and apparatus of their
research only when it is part of their invention, a singular and particular aspect
of the experimental design. Most often, however, presentations and publica-
tions contain little or no reference to the technologies and physical circum-
stances of the experimental apparatus, rarely enough that would enable the
necessary replication. That detailed technical information must be secured
through personal communication. This development stands in marked contrast
to the early scientific publications of the Royal Society. Referencing Shapin's
work on the early laboratories and Royal Society proceedings ("The House of
Experiment"), Gieryn remarks how those early accounts in the Royal Society
publications "were prolix-packed full of every little detail about how an
experiment was done, often with expensive engravings of the apparatus,
enabling the informed reader to become a 'virtual witness' via a reading of the
fact text. But over time, the scientific paper became less explicit in narrating
every detail, and more laconic about how an experiment was conducted or
with what equipment-shorthand codes were devised, and many particulars
were assumed to be so obvious to peer readers that mention of them could be
safely dropped. In effect, the amount of technical knowledge needed to read a
scientific journal was enlarged significantly as actual descriptions of the bones
of experiments became ever more brief" (Tom Gieryn and David Brain,
"Authenticating Places," paper presented at the American Sociological Associ-
ation, 1999, 4).
23. Tom Gieryn, "Model Farms as Truth-Spots," paper presented to the
Society for Social Studies of Science, October 29, 1999.
24. Austin Sarat, "'. . . The Law Is All Over': Power, Resistance, and the
Legal Consciousness of the Welfare Poor," Yale Journal of Law and the Humani-
ties 2 (1990): 343.
25. Jason Owen Smith and Walter W. Powell, "To Patent or Not: Faculty
Decision and Institutional Success at Technology Transfer," Journal of Technol-
ogy Transfer 26, no. o10 (2002): 99-114; Walter Power and Jason Owen Smith,
"Universities and the Market for Intellectual Property in the Life Sciences,"
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 17, no. 2 (1998): 253-77.
26. Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), 38.
27. Ibid.
28. H. Gusterson, Nuclear Rites: A Weapons Laboratory at the End of the Cold
War (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1996).
29. Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 38.
30. Herbert Muschamp, "A Rare Opportunity for Real Architecture Where
It's Needed," New York Times, October 22, 2000, Arts and Leisure, 1, 38-39.
io8
THE PLACE OF LAW
31. Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 35.
32. Cf. S. J. Rosenlund, The Chemical Laboratory: Its Design and Operation: A
Practical Guide for Planners of Industrial, Medical, or Educational Facilities (Park
Ridge, N.J.: Noyes, 1987).
33. Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 42.
34. The names of all subjects are pseudonyms.
35. Gusterson, Nuclear Rites.
36. Emily Martin (1992) has made a similar argument concerning the cul-
tural understandings of bodily danger among American doctors in The Woman
in the Body: A Cultural Analysis of Reproduction (Boston: Beacon, 1992 [2d ed.]).
37. A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, "On Joking Relationships," in Structure and Func-
tion in Primitive Society (New York: Free Press, 1965).
38. Gusterson, Nuclear Rites, 115.
39. Ibid., 117.
40. G. Deleuze, "Un Nouveau Archiviste," Critique 274 (March 1970):
195-209 (quote appears on p. 209), quoted from Rob Shields, Places on the Mar-
gin: Alternative Geographies of Modernity (Routledge, 1991, 30).
41. Michel Foucault, "Governmentality," in The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmental Rationality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 31.
42. Nikolas Rose, Powers of Freedom: Refraining Political Thought (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1999).
43. Mariana Valverde, Diseases of the Will: Alcohol and the Dilemmas of Free-
dom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
44. Rosalind Pollack Petchesky, "Fetal Images: The Power of Visual Culture
in the Politics of Reproduction," Feminist Studies 13 (1987): 263.
45. Ibid., 287. See Eileen McDonagh (1996) for an elaboration of this con-
struction of pregnancy that turns the interpretation of an adversarial relation-
ship against its more common purpose to privilege the fetus. McDonagh
describes pregnancy as an assault, invasion, and habitation of a woman's body
by another person. Eileen McDonagh, "From Pro-Choice to Pro-Consent in the
Abortion Debate: Reframing Women's Reproductive Rights," in Studies in Law,
Politics, and Society, edited by Susan S. Silbey and Austin Sarat, vol. 14 (1994),
245-90; McDonagh, Breaking the Abortion Deadlock: From Choice to Consent (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
46. Rob Shields, Places on the Margin: Alternative Geographies of Modernity
(New York: Routledge, 1991).
47. Valverde, Diseases of the Will.
48. Shields, Places on the Margin.
49. F. K. Harre, introduction to The Natural Landscapes of Canada, ed. J. B.
Bird (Toronto: Wiley, 1972).
50. Lefebvre, The Production of Space.
51. Shapin, "House of Experiment."
Digital Networks, State
Authority, and Politics
Saskia Sassen
The proliferation of global computer-based networks and the digitiza-
tion of economic and political activities, thereby enabled to circulate in
these networks, raise questions about the effectiveness of current forms
of state authority and democratic accountability. In a context of multi-
ple institutional changes linked to globalization, digitization has
enabled the entry of subnational entities, such as the global city, and
supranational entities, such as global markets, into domains once
exclusive to national states. This rescaling process does not always cor-
respond to existing formalizations of state authority.
These developments, in fact, destabilize older formal hierarchies of
scale and enable the emergence of new ones, often not yet fully formal-
ized. Hierarchies of scale dating from the period that saw the ascen-
dance of the nation-state continue to operate; they are typically orga-
nized in terms of institutional size and territorial scope: from the
international down to the national, the regional, the urban, and the
local. But today's rescaling dynamics cut across institutional size and
across the institutional encasements of territory produced by the for-
mation of national states.' What impact do these developments have on
the regulatory capacities of states, and what is their potential for under-
mining state authority as constituted over the last two centuries? More
analytically, we might ask whether these developments signal new
types of imbrications between authority and place.
This essay examines these questions by focusing on how digitization
and the associated rescalings have strengthened older actors and
enabled novel actors and spaces to engage the competence, scope, and
o109
110
THE PLACE OF LAW
exclusivity of state authority. The particular cases considered are global
finance and cross-border activist politics, both of which are instances of
a transformative digitization. Both instances involve multiple causali-
ties and contingencies, and by focusing on digitization I do not mean to
posit a single causality. On the contrary, digitization is caught up with
other dynamics that shape its development and uses. In some circum-
stances it is completely derivative, a mere instrumentality of other
dynamics; in others, it is constitutive of new domains. One key
assumption here is that understanding the imbrications between digiti-
zation and politico-economic processes requires recognizing the
embeddedness of digital space. When focusing on the social order,
purely technological readings of the technical capacities entailed by
digitization are not adequate.
This essay develops through an examination of three dynamics. The
first is the relation between state authority and the Internet, a necessary
introduction to a subject weighed down by assumptions about the
Internet's capacity to override existing relations of law to place, notably
that firms, individuals, and NGOs can elude government control when
operating in cyberspace. The second is the relation between state
authority and the global capital market, which is not only largely elec-
tronic and de facto supranational but also enormously powerful. The
third is global politics based in local concerns and struggles, politics
that expand democratic participation beyond state boundaries. These
noncosmopolitan versions of global politics entail relations of law to
place that are in some respects opposite to those we find in global
finance. My effort here is to map a conceptual problematic rather than
to provide all the answers.
State Regulation and the Internet
The condition of the Internet as a decentralized network of networks
has contributed to strong notions about its built-in autonomy from
state power and its capacity to enhance democracy, strengthening both
market dynamics and access by civil society.2 At the core of the Internet
are so-called Internet exchanges, national backbone networks, regional
networks, and local networks. These networks are often privately
owned.3 While in principle many of the key features of the Internet do
have a capacity to enhance democracy, its technology permits signifi-
cant control of exchanges and limitations on access.
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
111
In many ways the Net escapes most conventional jurisdictions,4 but
this does not mean the absence of regulation. Much of the literature on
this issue operates at one of two very different levels. The first is a set of
notions rooted in an earlier emphasis on the Internet as a decentralized
space where no structures of authority can be instituted. The second is
technical, a rapidly growing literature stimulated by the increasing
importance of Internet addressing and the domain name system reg-
istry, with associated legal and political issues.
At least three factors constitute a de facto management of the Inter-
net. One is the governmental authority to set technical and operational
standards for both hardware and software. The second is the power of
large corporate interests to orient the Internet toward privatizing capa-
bilities. And the third is the central authority overseeing crucial fea-
tures having to do with addresses and numbers granting, and the
domain name system. These three conditions do not show that regula-
tion is ipso facto possible. They merely signal that a representation of
the Net as escaping all authority is inadequate.
Boyle among others has shown that the set of standards built into the
Internet undermines claims that the state cannot regulate it.5 Indeed,
the state's regulatory agenda is already partially contained in the
design of the technologies. Thus, the state can regulate, but not in this
case via sanctions. Boyle alerts us to the fact that privatized and tech-
nologically based rule enforcement would take policing away from the
scrutiny of public law, freeing states from some of the constitutional
and other constraints restricting their options. Even in states that oper-
ate under the rule of law, government agencies can abuse power, as
examples in the United States make clear.6
The second de facto "regulatory" condition is the power of private
corporate interests to shape the activity space of the Internet. It makes
clear that the question of democratic governance goes far deeper than
the types of bodies set up to govern. Beyond governance, the actors
shaping the development of the Internet diverge sharply, ranging from
the original group of computer scientists that developed the open and
decentralized features of the Internet to multinational corporations
concerned with the protection of intellectual property rights. Most
recently, there has been a strengthening of civic and political groups
concerned with the extent to which private corporate interests are
shaping Internet access and development.
These divergent interests are captured in the fact that the leading
112
THE PLACE OF LAW
efforts in software development since the mid-199os have been fire-
walled intranets for firms, firewalled tunnels for firm-to-firm transac-
tions, identity verification, protection of trademarks, and billing. The
rapid increase of such software does not necessarily strengthen the pub-
licness of the Net and risks orienting it toward commercial interests.
This is especially significant if less new software is aimed at strengthen-
ing the openness and decentralization of the Internet, as was the case in
the earlier phases. Since 1995-96 political and technical developments
have brought about an increase in controls.7 Prior to 1995 users could
more easily maintain their anonymity while online, better protecting
privacy. The architecture of the Internet inhibited "zoning"-any tech-
nique that facilitates discrimination in access to, or distribution of, some
good or service.8 With the drive to facilitate e-commerce, this has
changed: the architecture of the Internet now facilitates zoning.9 These
conditions inevitably play a role in Internet governance.
The third factor is increasingly formalized central authority govern-
ing key functions of the Internet.'0 Its nature is not necessarily akin to
regulatory authorities, but it is a gatekeeping system and increases
oversight capacities. These capacities demand considerable innovation
in our concepts of regulation." The Internet Corporation for Assigned
Names and Numbers (ICANN), established in the summer of 1998 and
assigned to oversee the Net's address system, represents a formaliza-
tion of the earlier authority.12 It started as a group of insiders with fairly
loose and ineffective bylaws. By early 1999 it had implemented conflict-
of-interest rules, opened up some board meetings, and worked toward
developing a mechanism to elect board members in an effort to increase
accountability.13 Setting up ICANN has by no means solved all Internet
governance problems.14
ICANN is the subject of growing debate within digital subcultures.
Many commentators believe ICANN is setting up an undemocratic reg-
ulatory apparatus, largely dominated by U.S. interests, notably large
corporations.15 What I want to emphasize here is that these trends sig-
nal the existence of Internet management. They also show us, perhaps
more importantly, the necessity for fair governance if public interest is
also to shape the Internet. Market forces alone will not ensure that the
Internet strengthens democratic institutions, despite the assurances of
many a commentator. As the Internet has become more international
and economically important, desire for a more organized and account-
able system has grown.
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
113
The debate about the Internet is divided on the question of whether
it can be governed at all.16 Simplifying an overlapping set of positions,
we can say that for some the Internet is an entity that can be subjected
to governance, while for others there is no such entity, only a decen-
tralized network of networks that at best can lend itself to coordination
of standards and rules.
Those who consider the Internet a single entity have focused on the
establishment of a system of property rights and other such protections
and the means for enforcing them. They have disagreed on how to
administer and enforce such a system. Some believe that it must be
attached to a multilateral organization, notably the International
Telecommunications Union (ITU) and the World Intellectual Property
Organization, because trademark laws are national, not global.'7 This
would ensure recognition from member governments. For others, gov-
ernance has to come from the institutions of the Internet itself. Gould,
for example, argues that there is no need for outside institutions; rather,
Internet practices could produce a sort of constitutional governance
pertaining exclusively to the Net.'8 A third type of proposal has been
developed by Mathiason and Kuhlman,19 who suggest an international
framework convention agreed upon by governments, akin to the
United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change.
On the other hand, those experts who say there is no such entity as
the Internet, only a decentralized network of networks, argue that there
is no need for external regulation or coordination, which would in any
case be ineffective. But they tend to agree with the proponents of gov-
ernance mentioned above on the need for a system of property rights.
Gillett and Kapor argue for diffused coordination mechanisms; the
authority of such coordination, they posit, could be more easily legiti-
mated in a distributed network environment like the Internet, and
increasingly so given a stakeholder community that is becoming
global.20 Mueller argues against an Internet regulatory agenda and
against the policing of trademark rights.21 He is critical of the very term
governance, as it is incompatible with what ought to be the purpose of
any framework, that of facilitating internetworking. He argues that too
much effort has focused on restricting the ability to internetwork.
In one of the most systematic examinations of these various per-
spectives, Pare argues that neither of these two types of approaches
offers much insight into the processes actually shaping the governance
trajectory of the Internet, particularly the addressing system.22 Nor,
114
THE PLACE OF LAW
argues Pare, can these approaches account for the structures of the
organizations currently managing the core functions of internetwork-
ing (both at the national and at the international level) or the likeli-
hood of their survival.23
One important issue is the role of the features of the technology in
shaping forms of governance or coordination.24 Post and Johnson argue
that transnational electronic networks create jurisdictions different
from those of territorially based states, and hence there is little purpose
in replicating regulatory forms of the latter for the Internet.25 These
authors maintain that various dimensions of internetworking, includ-
ing Internet addressing, could be governed by decentralized emergent
law that eventually could converge into common standards for mutual
coordination. For others emphasizing technological constraints, the
Internet has been a regulated environment given the standards built
into the hardware and software. Thus Reidenberg agrees that the Inter-
net undermines territorially based regulatory governance.26 But new
models and sources of rules continue to be created out of the technical
standards and their capacity to establish default boundary rules that
impose order in network environments.27 Technical standards can be
used as instruments of public policy, and in this regard Reidenberg
posits the emergence of a Lex Informatica.28 This is clearly reminiscent,
for those of us working on the global economy today, of the Lex Mer-
catoria, a concept now being revived in the context of economic global-
ization and privatization.29
But the Internet is only one portion of the vast new world of digital
space, and much of the power to destabilize state authority attributed
to the Internet actually comes from private dedicated digital networks,
such as those used in wholesale global finance. To this topic I turn now.
Distinguishing Private and Public-Access Digital Space
Many assertions about digital dynamics and potentials are actually
about processes happening in private digital space and have little to do
with the Internet.30 This is a serious confusion. Most wholesale finan-
cial activity and other significant digital economic activities take place
in private digital networks.31
Private digital networks make possible forms of power other than
the distributed power we associate with public digital networks. Finan-
cial markets illustrate this well. The three properties of electronic net-
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
115
works-decentralization, simultaneity, and interconnectivity-have
produced orders-of-magnitude increases in the global capital market.
In a narrow technical sense, this resembles the sharp increase in the
number of transactions individuals can make in a given amount of time
using the Internet, as compared with previous technologies. However,
given that digital networks dedicated to financial activities are embed-
ded in a specific social field-the financial sector-the result of these
technical features is increased concentration rather than increased dis-
tribution, as is the case in the Internet. At the same time, the limits of
the weight of that social field-in this case, the financial sector-are set
by the transformative impact of digitization on the field itself.
One of the key outcomes of digitization on finance has been the jump
in orders of magnitude of value transacted. There are basically three
ways in which digitization has contributed to this outcome. One is the
use of sophisticated software, a key feature of the global financial mar-
kets that has made possible enormous innovation. It has raised the level
of liquidity as well as increased the possibilities of liquefying forms of
wealth hitherto considered nonliquid.32 This can require enormously
complex instruments; computers facilitated the development of these
instruments and enabled their widespread use, because much of the
complexity could be contained in software.
Second, the features of digital networks can maximize the implica-
tions of global market integration by producing the possibility of simul-
taneous interconnected transactions. Since the late 198os, a growing
number of financial centers have become globally integrated as coun-
tries deregulated their economies. This nondigital condition raised the
impact of the digitization of markets and instruments. Third, because
finance involves transactions, not just flows of money, the technical
properties of digital networks assume added meaning. Elsewhere I have
examined organizational complexity as a key variable allowing firms to
maximize the benefits they derive from digital technology.33 In the case
of financial markets, we could make a parallel argument.
The combination of these conditions has contributed to the distinc-
tive position of the global capital market vis-a-vis other components of
economic globalization. Indicators are the monetary values involved
and, though more difficult to measure, the growing weight of financial
criteria in economic transactions, sometimes referred to as the finan-
cialization of the economy. Since 1980, the total stock of financial assets
has increased three times faster than the aggregate GDP of the twenty-
116
THE PLACE OF LAW
three highly developed countries that formed the Organisation for Eco-
nomic Cooperation and Development (OECD) for much of this period;
and the volume of trading in currencies, bonds, and equities has
increased about five times faster and now surpasses this aggregate
GDP by far.34 The latter stood at $30 trillion in 2000, while the world-
wide value of internationally traded derivatives reached over $65 tril-
lion, and $192 trillion by 2002 (BIS 2003). To put these figures in per-
spective, compare the value of other major components of the global
economy, such as cross-border trade (ca. $8 trillion in 2000) and foreign
direct investment stock ($6 trillion in 2000). Foreign exchange transac-
tions were ten times as large as world trade in 1983, but seventy times
larger in 1999, even though world trade has itself grown sharply over
this period.35
In brief, the deregulation of domestic financial markets, the global
integration of a growing number of these markets, along with comput-
ers and telecommunications, together have contributed to an explosive
growth in the value of financial transactions.36 The high degree of inter-
connectivity, in combination with instantaneous transmission, signals a
potential for further exponential growth.37 The increase in volumes per
se may be secondary to their deployment, for instance, to overwhelm
national central banks, as happened in 1994 in Mexico and the Thai cri-
sis in 1997. In such cases, the fact of volume itself becomes a significant
variable. Further, when globally integrated electronic markets enabled
investors to rapidly withdraw well over $ioo billion from a few coun-
tries in Southeast Asia in the 1997-98 crisis, and the foreign currency
markets had the orders of magnitude to alter exchange rates radically
for some of these currencies, then digitization emerges as a significant
variable that goes beyond its technical features.
What is the impact of this concentration of capital in markets that
allow rapid, high-volume circulation in and out of countries? Does the
global capital market now have the power to "discipline" national gov-
ernments, that is, to subject certain monetary and fiscal policies to
financial criteria, where before this was not the case? How does this
potential affect national economies and government policies more gen-
erally? Does it alter the functioning of democratic governments? Does
this kind of concentration of capital reshape the accountability relation
that has operated through electoral politics between governments and
their people? Does it affect national sovereignty? And, finally, do these
changes reposition states and the interstate system in the broader
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
117
world of cross-border relations? These are some of the questions raised
by the particular ways in which digitization interacts with other vari-
ables to produce the distinctive features of the global capital market
today. The responses in the scholarly literature vary, ranging from
those who find that in the end the national state still exercises ultimate
authority, to those who see an emergent power gaining at least partial
ascendance over national states.38
If the global capital market represents a concentration of power that
is capable of influencing national government economic policy, and by
extension other policies, norms are a key issue. Today global financial
markets have produced a logic that becomes integrated into national
public policy and sets the criteria for "proper" economic policy.39 The
operational logic of the capital market contains criteria for what leading
financial interests today consider sound financial policy. These criteria
have been constructed as norms for important aspects of national eco-
nomic policymaking, going far beyond the financial sector as such. This
dynamic has become evident in a number of countries as they become
integrated into global financial markets. For many countries, these
norms have been imposed from the outside. As has been said often,
some states are more sovereign than others.40 Among the familiar ele-
ments that have become norms of "sound economic policy" are the
autonomy of central banks, anti-inflation policies, exchange rate parity,
and the items usually referred to as "IMF conditionality."4'
Digitization of financial markets and instruments played a crucial
role in increasing cross-border integration and hence the raw power of
the global capital market. Yet this process was shaped by interests and
logics that typically had little to do with digitization per se. This makes
clear the embeddedness of digitized markets in complex institutional
settings. Moreover, while the raw power achieved by the capital mar-
kets through digitization also facilitated the institutionalizing of certain
finance-dominated economic criteria in national policy, digitization per
se could not have done so.
One crucial implication of this embeddedness of global finance is
that the supranational electronic market space that partly operates out-
side any government's exclusive jurisdiction is only one of the spaces
for digitized industry. The other type of space is marked by the thick
environments of actual financial centers, places where national laws
continue to operate, albeit often profoundly altered laws. The embed-
dedness of private economic electronic space entails the formation of
118
THE PLACE OF LAW
massive concentrations of infrastructure, not just worldwide dispersal,
and a complex interaction between digitization and conventional com-
munications infrastructure-one much more subject to direct state
authority. The notion of "global cities" captures this particular embed-
dedness of global finance in actual financial centers.42 In the case of pri-
vate digital spaces such as those described here for global finance, this
embeddedness carries significant implications for theory and for poli-
tics, specifically, for the conditions through which governments and
citizens can act on the new electronic world.
In brief, the private digital space of global finance intersects in at
least two specific ways with the world of state authority and law. The
first is through the introduction into national state policy of new types
of norms, reflective of the operational logic of the global capital market.
The second is through the partial embeddedness of even the most digi-
tized financial markets in actual financial centers, which partly returns
global finance to the world of national governments. Global digitized
finance makes legible some of the complex and novel imbrications
between law and place. It does not simply override national state
authority. Rather, the result is both the use of that authority for the
implementation of regulations and laws that respond to the interests of
global electronic financial markets, and the renewed weight of that
authority in the case of financial centers.43
A Politics of Places on Cross-Border Circuits
An imbrication of law and place perhaps opposite from that of global
finance is evident in another domain that has been transformed by dig-
itization, yet under radically different conditions. The key digital
medium is the public-access Internet, and the key actors are largely
resource-poor organizations and individuals. The Internet has enabled
a new type of cross-border politics that can bypass interstate politics.
The participation of small organizations and resource-poor individuals
signals the possibility of a sharp growth in cross-border politics by
actors other than states. This produces a specific kind of activism, one
centered in multiple localities yet connected digitally at scales larger
than the local, reaching a global scale in many instances.
Of particular interest here is the potential for localized initiatives to
become part of cross-border networks through the Internet. Previously
subject to specific national and local laws, actors can move to a global
scale where these laws are dissolved into the collective presence of dif-
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
119
ferent localities in the global network. What kind of law holds sway in
a network of multiple localities?
Current uses of digital media in this new cross-border political
activism suggest two broad types of digital activism: one consists of
place-centered activist groups who connect with other such groups
around the world. The available evidence shows that most often these
places are cities, though not exclusively.44 Activists can develop net-
works for circulating information (about environmental, housing,
political, and other matters) and for executing political work and
deploying strategies of engagement.
There are many examples of such cross-border political work. For
instance the Society for the Promotion of Area Resource Centres
(SPARC), started by and centered on women, began as an effort to
organize slum-dwellers in Bombay to get housing. Now it has a net-
work of such groups throughout Asia and in some cities in Latin Amer-
ica and Africa. By being part of such a global network, the place-based
activists have gained something vis-a-vis the local governments they
need to engage: it is not money or power per se, but perhaps something
akin to political clout that has been an enabling condition. This repre-
sents one of the key forms of critical politics that the Internet can make
possible: A politics of the local with a difference-these are localities
connected with each other across a region, a country, or the world.
Because the network is global does not mean that all activities happen
at the global level.45
The second type of digital politics is one that does most of its work
within the network and then may converge on an actual terrain for
activism-as was the case of demonstrations in Seattle against the
World Trade Organization, the first in a series organized by the
antiglobalization network in cities hosting meetings of the major mem-
bers and institutions of the supranational system, or the coordination of
demonstrations against the war on Iraq held in over six hundred cities
on February 15, 2003. The extent to which the work and the political
effort is centered on the transactions in the digital network varies.
Organizing against the Multilateral Agreement on Investment was
largely a digital event. But when these digital political actions hit the
ground, they can do so very effectively, especially in the concentrated
places that cities are. This digital activism differs from hacktivism,46 in
that it is partly embedded in nondigital environments that shape, give
meaning, and to some extent constitute the event. It also has to be dis-
tinguished from cyberwar.47
120
THE PLACE OF LAW
These forms of activism contribute in multiple microlevel ways to an
unbundling of the exclusive authority, including symbolic authority,
over territory and people we have long associated with the national
state. Among the more strategic instantiations of this unbundling is
probably the global city, which operates as a partly denationalized plat-
form for global capital and at the same time concentrates an enormous
mix of people from all over the world. The growing intensity of trans-
actions among these cities is creating a strategic cross-border geogra-
phy that partly bypasses national states.48 The new network technolo-
gies further strengthen these transactions, whether they are electronic
transfers of specialized services among firms or Internet-based com-
munications among the members of diasporas and globally dispersed
interest groups.
The large city of today, especially the global city, and digital space
are two sites where the new claims by nonformal (or not yet formal-
ized) political actors assume concrete forms and can lead to cross-bor-
der transactions. Particularly in the case of cities, the partial loss of
power at the national level makes possible new forms of power and
politics at the subnational level. The national as container of social
process and power is cracked.49 This cracked casing opens up possibil-
ities for a political geography that links subnational spaces and allows
nonformal political actors to engage in cross-border activities. The city
and digital space are far more concrete spaces for politics than that of
the nation. These spaces can accommodate nonformal political actors in
a way that is much more difficult at the national level.50 Nationally pol-
itics needs to run through existing formal systems: whether the elec-
toral political system or the judiciary (taking state agencies to court),
and on the international scale, it needs to run through the interstate sys-
tem. Nonformal political actors are rendered invisible in the space of
national politics and largely lack access to the interstate system.
The combination of the strengthened geographies of transactions
that connect major cities across the globe and access to the new network
technologies has made it possible for a growing variety of organiza-
tions to join efforts with other such organizations around the world.
This is perhaps most evident today with small groups organized on
behalf of environmental issues, human rights, first-nation peoples, or
(typically nationality-based) immigrants. They are often located in only
one city of a country and may not be national, in the sense of operating
nationwide. Yet today these organizations can interact with global net-
works of organizations with similar aims. These aims may be parallel
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
121
local struggles, as is often the case with human rights organizations or
the SPARC effort alluded to above, or they may concern a global scale,
such as efforts to protect the ozone layer.
We can think of this mix of conditions and resources as facilitating a
place-specific politics with global span. It is a type of political work
deeply embedded in people's actions and activities5' but made possible
partly by the existence of global digital linkages. Further, it is a form of
political and institution-building work centered in cities and networks
of cities and in nonformal political actors. We see here the potential
transformation of a whole range of "local" conditions or institutional
domains (such as the household, the community, the neighborhood,
the local school and health care entities) where, for instance, women
"confined" to domestic roles can remain the key actors. Formerly expe-
rienced as nonpolitical or domestic, these places are transformed into
"microenvironments with global span."
What I mean by this construct is that technical connectivity creates a
variety of links with other similar local entities in other neighborhoods
in the same city, in other cities, in neighborhoods and cities in other
countries.52 A partly deterritorialized community of practice can
emerge that creates horizontal communications, collaborations, soli-
darities, and supports that arise out of specific localized struggles. Peo-
ple can experience themselves as part of global nonstate networks in
their daily localized political work. They enact some features of "global
civil society" in the microspaces of daily life rather than on some puta-
tive global stage.
The new network technologies have amplified these possibilities
and have in good part given them the essential vehicle necessary for the
outcome. But technology by itself could not have produced the out-
come. The emergence of global digital networks as nodes in trans-
boundary politics is the result of a complex mix of institutional devel-
opments. Perhaps crucial among these are globalization and the
international human rights regime. These have helped create formal
and informal operational openings for nonstate actors to enter interna-
tional arenas that were once the exclusive domain of national states.
Various, often as yet very minor developments, signal that the state is
no longer the exclusive subject for international law or the only actor in
international relations. Other actors-from NGOs and first-nation peo-
ples to immigrants and refugees who become subjects of adjudication
in human rights decisions-are emerging as subjects of international
law and actors in international relations. That is to say, these nonstate
122
THE PLACE OF LAW
actors can gain visibility as individuals and as collectivities, emerging
from the invisibility of aggregate membership in a nation-state exclu-
sively represented by the sovereign.
One of the most radical forms assumed today by the transformations
in the linkages that connect people to territory is the loosening of iden-
tities from traditional sources, such as the nation or the village. This
unmooring in the process of identity formation now probably affects
only a minority of people but includes the types of groups that concern
me here. For these groups this condition can engender new notions of
community of membership and of entitlement. The mix of focused
activism and local/global networks creates conditions for the emer-
gence of at least partly transnational identities.53 From the perspective
of my concerns in this essay, we might think of the enabling of transna-
tional identities as a condition that can facilitate cross-border relations
that at least partly bypass the world of interstate relations.
The space constituted by the worldwide grid of global cities, marked
by sharp imbrications of digital and nondigital conditions, is a strategic
one for the formation of transnational identities and communities. It is
characterized by density and diversity of transactions and by institu-
tional thickness. It is a space with new economic and political poten-
tialities that are both place-centered, that is, embedded in particular
and strategic cities, and transterritorial, because sites that are not geo-
graphically proximate can be intensely connected. Capital transmi-
grates in this cross-border geography, but so do people, both the rich,
that is, the new transnational professional workforce, and poor, that is,
most migrant workers. It is also a space for the transmigration of cul-
tural forms, for the reterritorialization of "local" subcultures. There is a
good possibility of transnational identities emerging as a consequence
of the thickness itself of this cross-border space even in the absence of
political aspirations in that direction. While these developments do not
neutralize attachments to a country or national cause, they do shift this
attachment to include translocal communities of practice or member-
ship, for example the transnational professionals of global finance or
the activist organizations described here.
Conclusion
The interactions between regulation and digital space are complex and
multivalent. On the one hand, there are several ways in which formal
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
123
and de facto "regulatory" forces are partly shaping the Internet. These
forces include government-largely U.S. government-standards built
into the hardware and software and the protection of property rights,
and they include the interests of multinational corporations built into
what are today the major directions of technical developments in soft-
ware, hardware, infrastructure, and "governance."
On the other hand, digitization has strengthened specific capabilities
of nonstate actors, such as global financial markets and political orga-
nizations, which can now operate in domains once exclusive to national
states in the world of cross-border relations. These nonstate actors are
gaining influence, and their claims are gaining legitimacy. For instance,
it could be argued (and it is my argument) that private digital space,
with global finance its emblematic manifestation, has had a far sharper
impact on sovereignty than has the Internet. The globalization and the
digitization of financial markets have made them a powerful presence.
Indeed, the logic of the global capital markets is today not merely a con-
dition of raw power but one with normative potential, in that the oper-
ational logic of these markets has contributed criteria for the "proper "
(that is, neoliberal) governmental conduct on the economy. This new
power of the financial markets is partly a consequence of their greater
magnitude, in good part through digitization and global integration,
two conditions that are mutually reinforcing. The capacity of these
markets to affect existing meanings of sovereignty is considerable, in
my view greater, thus far, than that of the Internet. However, access to
low-cost connectivity via the Internet along with the specific features of
these digital networks is enabling a proliferation of grassroots politics
that may eventually redefine aspects of the public sphere and of citi-
zenship practices and identities. Even as it allows place-bound strug-
gles embedded in national specifics to become part of global networks,
the Internet in part denationalizes such political work.
Insofar as the operations of these two types of nonstate actors are
partly embedded in actual territories, they reenter the terrain of
national state authority. But both the partiality of this reentry and its
specific features mark a difference: the insertion of the global into what
has been constructed historically as national, and the insertion of the
national into what is being constructed as the global. In the case of
global finance, its operational logic is inserted into the public domain,
reemerging as criteria for the governing of national economies. In the
case of the new types of global activism, the national specificities of
124
THE PLACE OF LAW
place-based struggles around the world are inserted into global net-
works, while being partially erased and amalgamated through the
sheer multiplication of national differences.
One of the greatest challenges to law and governance is the lack of
accountability inherent in the capabilities now deployable by powerful
actors, be they private or governmental, in the pursuit of their interests.
Unaccountable actors hold power to shape key features of digital space.
In the case of private actors, this capacity raises the issue of who can
claim legitimacy for their interests. In the case of governments, it raises
the issue of ensuring public scrutiny of government actions.
NOTES
This essay is a revised text of the Keck Lecture delivered at Amherst College,
February 13, 2000. It is based on a larger project, to be published as Denational-
ization: Territory, Authority, and Rights in a Global Digital Age (Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press, 2004).
1. Peter J. Taylor, "World Cities and Territorial States under Conditions of
Contemporary Globalization," Political Geography 19, no. 5 (2000): 5-32; John
Gerard Ruggie, "Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in Inter-
national Relations," International Organization 47, no. 1 (1993): 139-74; Saskia
Sassen, Denationalization: Territory, Authority, and Rights in a Global Digital Age
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003); Saskia Sassen, "Territory and
Territoriality in the Global Economy," International Sociology 15, no. 2 (2000):
372-93.
2. What constitutes the Internet is continuously changing (World Informa-
tion Order, World-Information Files: The Politics of the Info Sphere [Vienna: Insti-
tute for New Culture Technologies; Berlin: Center for Civic Education, 2002]).
Some years ago it could still be described as a network of computer networks
using a common communication protocol (IP protocol). Today networks using
other communication protocols are also connected to other networks via gate-
ways. Further, the Internet is not only constituted by computers connected to
other computers: also connected are point-of-sale terminals, cameras, robots,
telescopes, cellular phones, television sets, and an assortment of other hard-
ware components.
3. On October 24, 1995, the U.S. Federal Networking Council defined the
term Internet as follows:
"Internet" refers to the global information system that (i) is logically
linked together by a globally unique address space based on the Inter-
net Protocol (IP) or its subsequent extensions/follow-ons; (ii) is able to
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
125
support communications using the Transmission Control
Protocol/Internet Protocol (TCP/IP) suite or its subsequent exten-
sions/follow-ons, and/or other IP-compatible protocols; and (iii) pro-
vides, uses, or makes accessible, either publicly or privately, high level
services layered on the communications and related infrastructures
described herein. (http://www.itrd.gov/fnc/Internet_res.html)
4. David G. Post, "Anarchy, State, and the Internet: An Essay on Law-Mak-
ing in Cyberspace," Journal of Online Law (1995).
5. James Boyle, Foucault in Cyberspace: Surveillance, Sovereignty, and Hard-
Wired Censors (Washington, DC: College of Law, American University, 1997).
6. The power of the U.S. government to engage in multiple forms of sur-
veillance, including surveillance of corporations in countries run by govern-
ments who are strong and long-term allies, was illustrated in the alleged use of
Echelon system to spy on European corporations (World Information Order,
World-Information Files, chap. 6).
7. Lawrence Lessig, Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace (New York: Basic
Books, 1999).
8. Lessig labels the architecture of the Internet "code," and he means by
this the software and hardware that constitutes it and determines how people
interact or exist in this space.
9. Elsewhere I have made a similar argument using the notion of the emer-
gence of cybersegmentations. See Saskia Sassen, "Digital Networks and
Power," in Spaces of Culture: City, Nation, World, ed. M. Featherstone and S. Lash
(London: Sage, 1999), 49-63.
10. This centrally managed function of the Internet involves the control and
assignment of the numbers that computers need to locate an address. It there-
fore can instruct all the top "root servers" of the Net-the computers that exe-
cute address inquiries-which will accept these instructions. This is, clearly, a
power of sorts. As is well known, the particular function of assigning addresses
is crucial and was for many years under the informal control of one scientist
who named this function the "Internet Assigned Numbers Authority." More
generally, the scientists who have tried to make the Net workable and have
reached agreements on a broad range of technical matters have long been an
informal central "authority." In most other cultural settings they would proba-
bly have become a formal, recognizable body-with, one might add, consider-
able power. There is an interesting sociology here.
11. There are also more specific issues that may affect the regulation of par-
ticular forms of digital activity through a focus on infrastructure. There are dif-
ferent types of infrastructure for different types of digital activities, for
instance, financial markets versus consumer wireless phones.
12. With the growth of business interest in the Internet, the de facto author-
ity of the early pioneers and their logic for assigning addresses began to be crit-
126
THE PLACE OF LAW
icized. To cite a familiar case, firms found that their names had already been
assigned to other parties and that there was little they could do; the idea of
brand names and rights to names was not part of the early Internet culture. See
Robert Latham, "Networks, Information, and the Rise of the Global Internet,"
in Digital Formations: Mapping a New Field of Enquiry, ed. R. Latham and S.
Sassen (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2004).
13. Since October 2000 the board of ICANN has been the final decision-
making authority on standards. But a complex web of organizations is involved
in the operation of the Internet. The Internet Society and its subsidiary organi-
zations-the Internet Architecture Board, the Internet Engineering Steering
Group, the Internet Engineering Task Force, and the Internet Research Task
Force-are responsible for the development of communications and opera-
tional standards and protocols that allow users to communicate with each other
over the Net. The Internet Societal Task Force is responsible for naming Inter-
net policy issues. The copyright on the protocols is held by the Internet Society.
Other organizations such as the WWW Consortium specialize in the develop-
ment of standards for certain services of the Net.
14. The U.S. government's "Framework for Global Electronic Commerce"
(1996), a blueprint for Internet governance, argues that because of the Internet's
global reach and evolving technology, regulation should be kept to a mini-
mum. It also suggests that in the few areas where rules are needed, such as pri-
vacy and taxation, policy should be made by quasi-governmental bodies such
as the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO) or the Organisation for
Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD). One of the issues with this
proposal is the absence of transparency. Related problems become evident in
one of the first big Net policy dilemmas: cybersquatting (private speculators
seizing valuable corporate brand names on the Internet and selling them back,
at an enormous price, to the firms carrying those names). Net addresses are
important for establishing an identity online. So companies want to establish a
rule that they are entitled to any domain names that use their trademarks. But
the Net is used for more than e-commerce, so consumer advocates say this rule
would unfairly restrict the rights of schools, museums, political parties, and
other noncommercial Net users. However, in deliberations that have taken
place at WIPO, it is largely the large firms who are participating, in meetings
that take place mostly behind doors. This privatizes the effort to design regula-
tions for the Net.
15. For summaries of the debates, see Nettime, Net Critique, compiled by
Geert Lovink and Pit Schultz (Berlin: Edition ID-Archiv, 1997); Geert Lovink,
Dark Fiber (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002).
16. The distinctions noted here partly follow Pare's classification and
research on the subject. Daniel J. Pare, Internet Governance in Transition: Just Who
Is the Master of this Domain? (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002),
chap. 3.
17. E.g., William A. Foster, "Registering the Domain Name System: An
Exercise in Global Decision Making," Kennedy School of Government, Har-
vard University, 1996.
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
127
18. Mark Gould, "Governance of the Internet. A UK Perspective" (1996).
19. John R. Mathiason and Charles C. Kuhlman, "International Public Reg-
ulation of the Internet: Who Will Give You Your Domain Name?" Paper pre-
sented at the Internet in a Post-Westphalian Order, University of Minnesota,
Minneapolis, 1996.
20. Sharon Eisner Gillett and Mitchell Kapor. "The Self-Governing Internet:
Coordination by Design" (1996)
21. Milton Mueller, "The 'Governance' Debacle: How the Ideal of Internet-
working Got Buried by Politics." Paper presented at INET 98, Geneva, Switzer-
land, 1998.
22. Pare, Internet Governance in Transition.
23. Pare, ibid., develops another approach to these questions of governance
and coordination. He argues that an emphasis on end results and on optimal
governance strategies, as is typical for the authors briefly discussed here, pro-
duces analytical blind spots. A crucial issue is the need to understand the
dynamic relationship that exists between the institutional forms delivering
technology and the network structures that emerge over time. See also Lessig,
Code and Other Laws.
24. Pare, Internet Governance in Transition, chap. 3.
25. Post, "Anarchy, State, and the Internet"; David R. Johnson and David G.
Post, "Law and Borders: The Rise of Law in Cyberspace," Stanford Law Review
48 (1996), at 1367.
26. Joel R. Reidenberg, "Lex Informatica: The Formulation of Information
Policy Rules Through Technology," Texas Law Review 76 (1998), at 553.
27. See also Lessig, Code and Other Laws.
28. Reidenberg, "Lex Information."
29. Yves Dezalay and Bryant Garth, Dealing in Virtue: International Commer-
cial Arbitration and the Construction of a Transnational Legal Order (Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1996); Rodney Bruce Hall and Thomas J. Biersteker,
eds., Private Authority and Global Governance (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 2002). This bundle of issues, as they pertain both to the Internet and
to the global economy, is discussed in Sassen, Denationalization.
30. New types of private networks also connected to the Internet; see note 2.
31. Retail investment and stock trading use the Internet. So does direct
online investment, which is mostly retail and represents a minor share of the
overall global financial market. Even if we factor in its expected tripling in
value over the next three or four years, it will not have the power that charac-
terizes the wholesale global financial market.
32. For instance, after the Mexico crisis and before the first signs of the
Asian crisis, the leading financial services firms negotiated innovative deals
that expanded volumes in the financial markets and incorporated new sources
of profit, ensuring liquidity even in a situation of at least partial crisis. Typically
these deals involved novel ways to sell debt and novel concepts of what is a
saleable debt.
128
THE PLACE OF LAW
33. Sassen, The Global City: New York, London, Tokyo, 2d ed. (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 200ool), 115-16.
34. Pam Woodall, "The World Economy: Who Is in the Driving Seat?" Econ-
omist 337, no. 7935: 5-18.
35. The foreign exchange market was the first to globalize, in the mid-197os.
Today it is the biggest and in many ways the only truly global market. It has
gone from a daily turnover rate of about $15 billion in the 197os, to $60 billion
in the early 198os, and an estimated $1.3 trillion in 1999. In contrast, that same
year the total foreign currency reserves of the rich industrial countries
amounted to about $1 trillion.
36. For extensive evidence on the issues discussed in this section refer to
Sassen, Global City, chaps. 3, 4, and 7. For a different perspective on issues of
global finance, see Geoffrey Garrett, "Global Markets and National Politics:
Collision Course or Virtuous Circle," International Organization 52, no. 4 (1998):
787-824; Barry Eichengreen and Albert Fishlow, Contending with Capital Flows
(New York: Council of Foreign Relations, 1996).
37. According to some estimates, we have reached only the midpoint of a
fifty-year process of fully integrating these markets. Given the growth dynam-
ics made possible by digitization, this signals that financial markets could
expand even further in relation to the size of other components such as direct
investment and trade.
38. E.g. Helleiner 1999; Leo Panitch, "Rethinking the Role of the State in an
Era of Globalization," in Globalization: Critical Reflections, ed. James Mittelman
(Boulder, Colo.: Lynne Rienner, 1996).
39. I try to capture this normative transformation in the notion of a priva-
tizing of certain capacities for making norms that in the recent history of states
under the rule of law were in the public domain. (I am not concerned here with,
e.g., the Catholic Church, which has long had what could be described as pri-
vate norm-making capacities, but is of course a private institution, or is meant
to be that.) Now what are actually elements of a private logic emerge as public
norms, even though they represent particular rather than public interests. This
is not a new occurrence in itself for national states under the rule of law; what
is perhaps different is the extent to which the interests involved are global. For
a fuller discussion see Sassen, "Territory and Territoriality."
40. A particular feature that matters for my current research on denational-
ization is the fact that many states, more precisely, specific agencies and depart-
ments within states, have participated in the formation and implementation of
these conditions and rules. The result is a reorientation in some components of
"state-work" away from the national and toward the global economy.
41. Since the Southeast Asian financial crisis the specifics of these standards
have been revised. For instance, exchange rate parity is now posited in less
strict terms. The crisis in Argentina that broke in December 200ool raised further
questions about aspects of IMF (International Monetary Fund) conditionality.
But neither crisis has eliminated the latter.
42. For instance, the growth of electronic trading and electronic network
alliances among major financial centers allows us to see the particular way in
which digitized markets are partly embedded in these vast concentrations of
DIGITAL NETWORKS, STATE AUTHORITY, AND POLITICS
129
material resources and human talents represented by financial centers. See
Sassen, Global City, chaps. 4, 5, and 7.
43. For a full development of these issues please see Sassen, Denationaliza-
tion.
44. It is not clear how much difference it would make if these organizations
were located in rural areas. A more fine-grained analysis suggests that it would
have some effect. For an analysis of the distinctiveness of digital (and other)
networks centered in rural communities see Linda Garcia, "The Architecture of
Global Networking Technologies," in Global Networks/Linked Cities, ed. Saskia
Sassen (New York: Routledge, 2002). In this section I develop an argument that
posits the distinctiveness of large urban environments for these organizations,
derived particularly from my concern to capture the imbrications of digital net-
works with nondigital conditions.
45. I see parallel features in the cases where use of the Internet has allowed
diasporas to be globally interconnected rather than confined to a one-to-one
relationship with the country or region of origin. See, e.g., Centre for Civil Soci-
ety and the Centre for the Study of Global Governance, London School of Eco-
nomics, Global Civil Society Yearbook 2002, ed. Marlies Glasius, Helmut Anheier,
and Mary Kaldor (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
46. E.g., Dorothy E. Denning, Information Warfare and Security (Harlow:
ACM Press, 1998).
47. James Der Derian, Virtuous War: Mapping the Military-Industrial-Media-
Entertainment Network (Boulder: Westview, 200ool).
48. E.g., Taylor, "World Cities."
49. E.g., Taylor, "World Cities."
50. The space of the city accommodates a broad range of political activi-
ties-squatting, demonstrations against police brutality, fighting for the rights
of immigrants and the homeless, the politics of culture and identity, gay and
lesbian and queer politics. Much of this becomes visible on the street. Much of
urban politics is concrete, enacted by people rather than dependent on massive
media technologies. Street-level politics make possible the formation of new
types of political subjects that do not have to go through the formal political
system.
It is in this sense that those who lack power, those who are disadvantaged,
outsiders, discriminated minorities, can gain presence in global cities, presence
vis-a-vis power and presence vis-a-vis each other. This signals the possibility of
a new type of politics centered in new types of political actors. It is not simply
a matter of having or not having power. These are new hybrid bases from
which to act.
51. See Austin Sarat and Thomas R. Kearns, eds., Identities, Politics, and
Rights (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1995).
52. It is important to emphasize that digital networks can also be used for
strengthening local communications and transactions inside a city (see, e.g.,
Geert Lovink and Patrice Riemens, "Digital City Amsterdam: Local Uses of
Global Networks," in Sassen, Global Networks/Linked Cities), especially in an age
where the notion of the local is often seen as losing ground to global dynamics
and actors.
130
THE PLACE OF LAW
53. A growing number of scholars concerned with identity and solidarity
posit the rise of transnational identities (Maria de los Angeles Torres, "Transna-
tional Political and Cultural Identities: Crossing Theoretical Borders," in Bor-
derless Borders, ed. Frank Bonilla, Edwin Melendez, Rebecca Morales, and Maria
de los Angeles Torres [Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1998], 169-82.
Torres 1998; Robin Cohen, "Diasporas and the Nation-State: From Victims to
Challengers," International Affairs 72 [1996]: 507-20; Linda S. Bosniak, "Univer-
sal Citizenship and the Problem of Alienage," Northwestern University Law
Review 94 [2ooo]: 963-82) and translocal loyalties (Arjun Appadurai, Modernity
at Large [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996]). This literature
provides us with a broader conceptual landscape within which we can place
the more specific types of organizations and practices that concern me here.
The Place of Cyberlaw
Lawrence Lessig
We find the world as it is, even if the world we find is one we made.
Our experience is one of discovery, and our reaction is to change that
which we discover. We notice, and then we respond with the tools at
hand. We take what we can to remake what we find, to better fit our
picture of how the world is, or should be. It is in this sense that we say
the world is real and yet constructed: however it seems, it has been
built; even if built, it feels found.
If any world is constructed, cyberspace is. Yet in cyberspace more
than anywhere, the constructed seems found. As people come to know
how cyberspace is, they forget that however it is found, it was made.
They act as if it couldn't be different. They naturalize cyberspace more
completely than any natural place, forgetting that of all the places we
know now, this place is the least natural.
This forgetting first manifested itself in the belief that cyberspace
could not be regulated. Those who first knew this space-indeed, many
who built this space-came to believe that of all the places that human
society knows, cyberspace would be beyond the control of govern-
ments.' But soon into the life of cyberspace, or into the life of cyber-
space affecting real space life, this view (and for some, this hope) dis-
appeared. It is now so obvious that governments can change what
cyberspace is that it would be hard to imagine how any different
thought could have prevailed.
In learning how governments change this place, we are learning
something important and general about regulation itself. In this brief
essay, I sketch this learning. I begin with a model of regulation in real
space, and then apply that model to cyberspace. In both contexts, this
analysis makes clear the law's place within the domain of regulation
131
132
THE PLACE OF LAW
how and where it functions, and how its functioning can depend upon
the character of space. This is an understanding of how regulation func-
tions that is remote from ordinary understandings of the law. But
understanding cyberspace will make this remote understanding much
more local.
The world we find is filled with constraints. Some of these constraints
are made. Some of these "made" constraints act to limit-and, hence,
regulate-the liberty that we otherwise would have. These constraints
are of different kinds; they operate upon us in different ways. Consider
four of these constraints, and how they function together.2
The first of these four constraints-for the lawyer, at least-is law.
We are not permitted to travel in a car at speeds above sixty-five miles
per hour; the law imposes this constraint, not the car. In most states, we
are not allowed to marry people of the same sex; the law imposes this
constraint, not the nature of love. The law's constraints are constructed
through the self-conscious acts of courts, legislatures, and constitu-
tional conventions. They are statements that bind: Rules imposed
through words, that institutions then carry into effect.
But laws are not the only rules that regulate. Social norms-the sec-
ond of four constraints discussed here-regulate as well. Regardless of
the law, I would be punished by my neighbors if I drove through a
school zone at sixty-five miles per hour. In most of America, the most
significant constraint on single-sex relationships has nothing to do with
courts or legislators. These rules are not crafted by the self-conscious
actions of legislatures or courts; they live in the expectations and judg-
ments of the members of a community. And unlike laws, these rules
operate only with the complicity of the members of a community. We
might blame the church for restrictions placed on the erotic, but it's not
quite- or perhaps not just-the church that would scorn the reckless
endangerment of children at school.
Rules thus characterize two kinds of constraints: Laws and social
norms. Such rules-based constraints differ from a third type of con-
straints-those of the market. The market sets the terms under which
resources get traded. Its constraint says what must be given for what,
subject to the rules (both law and norms) within which the market func-
tions. The market's constraint is thus distinct from the barrier imposed
by law (for example, a felony conviction that might make it impossible
to be admitted to the bar), or by norms (that for most of our history,
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
133
scorned women from the legal profession). But the nature of the barrier
that the market might impose is a function of law and norms. The law
permits a student to wait tables to pay for law school; it doesn't permit
her to sell sex as a way to raise tuition. Norms support this law: the
same constraint on cash for sex is supported by a thick set of norms; a
different, but equally thick, set of norms would make it hard for a male
student to earn money by painting nails in a beauty shop.
The constraints of the market are conceptually different from the
constraints of the law and norms. Laws and norms punish deviation ex
post- one through an institution, the other through a community. The
market demands compliance, in a formal sense, simultaneously. You
trade cash for Coke, or an obligation to pay for a car. The constraint is
realized immediately, and perpetually, for example, as the hungry
man is continually aware that with the passing of each moment, he
can't buy food.
These three constraints are distinct from a fourth that will be the
focus of the argument to follow. This is the constraint of place, or what I
will call architecture. By architecture I mean the complement of physical
constraints that set the terms on which we experience real space. That a
wall is opaque means I can't see what's going on in the other room.
That's a constraint imposed by architecture. That a building has no
access ramp means the wheelchaired cannot get in. That too is a con-
straint imposed by architecture. These constraints of architecture are
distinct again from law and norms and the market. Like the market, they
operate in real time. We don't live life like the Coyote in Road Runner,
racing off a cliff, only then to be reminded of the law of gravity. Con-
straints of architecture are both formally, and effectively, simultaneous.3
Unlike law, norms, and the market, however, the constraints of
architecture require no human agency to be real. I may be able to slip a
bottle of perfume into my pocket and walk out of the store undetected,
and thereby escape the constraints of the market (which demand that I
pay for the perfume I have taken), and the constraints of social norms
(which say perfume is not for me), and the constraints of the law (which
say I can't take it without paying). It is a feature of these human-built
constraints that they must at some point be imposed by an agent to be
effective. The constraints of architecture cannot be escaped simply by
failing to be noticed. I can overcome some of them-I can blast a hole in
a wall to see what's going on in the other room, or I might be able to
pick a lock to get inside. But overcoming a constraint is different from
134
THE PLACE OF LAW
the constraint's not being enforced. Constraints of architecture are not
conditional in the way constraints of law, norms, and the market are.4
These four constraints are therefore different. Yet at any time, they
operate together. They interact. Sometimes they support each other: the
norm against students selling sex supports the law against students
selling sex. Sometimes they undercut each other: that there is a price for
sex undermines the norms and rules against it being for sale. Thus, to
understand the effectiveness of any particular regulation, we must sur-
vey how the modalities operate together. And this survey requires a
certain practice. We must become aware of constraints that are often
invisible; we must practice drawing their constraint into focus.
This need is especially true for policymakers. Because constraints
work together, and sometimes crosswise, anyone promoting a policy
should strive to understand how these four modalities interact. And
depending upon the interaction of these modalities, the policymaker
might have to alter or modify these different constraints. These con-
straints-if properly surveyed-can become tools in the hand of the
regulator; they get deployed or modified to whatever end the regulator
might have.
This is a point lawyers, and governments, tend to forget, and hence
the point remains obscure. But the insight that I want to move to the
foreground is that the law is just one of these four possible constraints,
and often not the most significant or important. Yet it is, among the
four, the constraint most relevant to changing the other three.
Take smoking as a simple example. In the United States (fortu-
nately), we live in the culture of the smoking prohibitionists. There are
laws against the sale of cigarettes to minors, as well as laws that zone
where smokers can smoke.5 So too do norms constrain the smoker-in
some places more than others, for some people more than others. Cali-
fornia is different from Detroit; the young executive is different from
the disaffected undergraduate. So too does the market constrain smok-
ing: Cigarettes cost money; money is a constraint. So too with architec-
ture: Smoking is hard to hide. And so too do these four constraints
sometime function together: In this society, we line up smokers at the
entrance of buildings so that they can be shamed by others entering and
leaving work.
Again, these different constraints operate together, and the policy-
maker can manipulate these different constraints to change how they
operate together. The policymaker can change the law, so it prohibits
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
135
more, or prohibits differently. Or the policymaker can fund television
commercials to change norms surrounding smoking-adding to the
stigma associated with smoking, or stigmatizing the producers of ciga-
rettes to reduce the demand to smoke. Or the policymaker can use the
market to increase the constraint on smoking-taxing cigarettes, for
examples. (We of course tax cigarettes heavily, while simultaneously
subsidizing tobacco production.)6 Or the policymaker could use archi-
tecture to regulate the consumption of cigarettes-for example, by reg-
ulating the amount of nicotine in a cigarette to reduce the addictiveness
of the habit.
Modern regulation-modern law-is the choice among these differ-
ent modalities of constraint. Modern regulation is the pragmatic disci-
pline of selecting the tool, or mix of tools, that best brings about the
desired social end.
This same mix of modalities exists in cyberspace, though the signifi-
cance of each is different. In the pages that follow, I want to argue that
in cyberspace, architecture will become the most significant regulator.
My point is not that cyberspace is the first place where architecture
mattered. The history of governments is littered with examples of
architecture as a tool of social policy. David Hackett Fischer describes
the founders of New England meticulously laying out the towns they
would found so that the relationship of the buildings to each other, and
to the town square, would assure that behavior within the town would
be properly regulated.7 Jeremy Bentham famously described the design
of a prison so that all cells would be viewable from one central position,
so that prisoners would never know whether they were being watched,
but that they always could be watched, and so they would be properly
regulated by the uncertainty about whether they were being monitored
or not.8 Napoleon III had Paris rebuilt so that the boulevards would be
broad, making it hard for revolutionaries to blockade the city, so that
Parisians would be properly regulated.9 Robert Moses built highway
bridges along the roads to the beaches in Long Island so that buses
could not pass under the bridges, thereby assuring that only those with
cars (largely white people) would use certain public beaches, and that
those without cars (largely African Americans) would be driven to use
other beaches, so that social relations would be accordingly regulated.'o
In each of these cases, architecture was a tool for regulating behav-
ior. But in cyberspace, architecture will become even more significant.
136
THE PLACE OF LAW
Relatively small changes in the character of the space will have pro-
found effects on the nature of the constraints experienced there. Under-
standing these changes, and their source, is the first step to under-
standing the place of law in cyberspace.
The problem of privacy in cyberspace will make the point more con-
cretely.
The Net was exposed to public view with the emergence of the
World Wide Web-a set of protocols for writing hyperlinked docu-
ments, and facilitating their interlinking across a network. The public
didn't see these protocols-HTML and HTTP-but they were layered
onto a more basic set of protocols that constituted the Internet-the
protocols of TCP/IP, which establish the basic architecture of Internet
communication."
None of these early Internet protocols made the identity of the user a
fact that the system needed to know in order to function. Each machine
on the Net needs an address (called an IP address) to communicate with
other machines on the Net; but those IP addresses have no necessary
connection with a geographic location or a particular person. Every time
the user connects, in principle he could receive a different IP address.
The web thus doesn't know through the IP address alone who I am.
This early architecture thus had the effect of protecting individual
privacy. The user could surf the Web without there being any auto-
matic way to figure out who or where he was. This is not because the
Web revealed nothing about the user. When the user connects to a Web
server using a browser, lots of data is exchanged between the server
and the browser: which operating system is being used, which address
you just came from, which type of browser is being run.12 But while all
these bits of data are communicated to the server, nothing about the
identity of the user is, necessarily, divulged.
For those who liked the world where surfing was anonymous, this
architecture was ideal. But for those who wanted to know their cus-
tomers-or at least their customers' customs-this world was not ideal.
Given the original architecture of the Web, it was difficult to know who
a user was, or what he wanted, and hence difficult to know how to sell
him what he wanted.
Early in the Net's history, the first major provider of a browser
Netscape-took steps to service those who wanted the Net to be less
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
137
anonymous. Netscape released a new protocol for Web servers-the
cookie technology.13 With cookies, a server could deposit a bit of data
on a user's machine, and when the user came back to the server, the
server would know with whom it was dealing. This made it easy to
monitor and track users, at least those users who tolerated cookies. And
this in turn meant that the protections for privacy had been changed.
Privacy was lessened on the World Wide Web, and the key is to focus
on why. Not because laws were changed or because norms had
evolved. Privacy was lessened because a simple feature of the architec-
ture of the Web had been altered. Changing the architecture to enable
cookies meant that less privacy was automatically assured.
This change was effected not by governments, but by a commercial
browser vendor trying to satiate the appetites of those commercial
enterprises keen to mine data for commerce from the Internet. Today,
as there is increased concern about privacy, different companies are
responding differently. Microsoft, for example, has built into its
browser a technology that enables users to block cookie deposits origi-
nating from sites that fail to make their privacy policies available in
machine readable form. The effect of this change has been to increase
the transparency of sites that use cookies to advertise to customers.
This increases the protection of a certain kind of data for users. Just as
the Netscape-initiated change to cyberspace architecture-cookies-
affected users' privacy on the Net, here too it was a change in cyber-
space architecture-Microsoft's cookie-blocking technology-that sim-
ilarly (yet inversely) affected users' privacy on the Net.'4
There are scores of examples just like this: The architecture of cyber-
space was one way; because it was one way, it protected a certain set of
values. The architecture was then changed, and the original values in
turn were lost or reshuffled. In each of these examples, we might imag-
ine the law playing a role in that change-by assuring a place stays as
it was, or in some cases, inducing a place to become something differ-
ent. In either case, the role of the law would be to alter a particular
architecture to better protect values chosen by the law.
In general, however, the law has not yet played that role in cyber-
space-even with a value as important as privacy that is recognized
both within cyberspace and without. And this is particularly true with
respect to values that are less in the fore than privacy, yet-or perhaps
X38
THE PLACE OF LAW
because-they are so close to the architecture of the original space as to
be invisible outside it. Among these, there is one that will prove to be
the most significant to the character of innovation and creativity. This is
the value of "end-to-end."
The "end-to-end argument" by Jerome Saltzer, David Clark, and David
P. Reed, directs designers about how intelligence in a network is to be
ordered.15 An end-to-end network places intelligence in the network at
the ends, or edge, of the network. Keep the network simple, or, as
David Isenberg calls it, stupid.16 Stupid networks, smart applications.
This was the character of the original Internet.
The early architects of the Net adopted this principle because
though they were among the best and the brightest network designers
of their time-they knew that they didn't know how the network
would be used. They had no idea how the network would mature, and
so they designed it so that it could mature in any way users wanted.
The network was not optimized to any particular use because no par-
ticular use was assured.'7
A kind of humility (and good pragmatic sense) thus guided these
first network designers, and this humility had a consequence. The net-
work was simple. It specified a simple protocol for exchanging packets
of data. This simplicity meant that the network didn't have within it the
power to discriminate among applications or content. Because the net-
work could not discriminate, innovators knew that their application or
their content could be served across the Internet regardless of the
wishes of the network owner. The network was a neutral platform; it
invited all comers.
For a brief span of time, this is just what the network did.'8 Previ-
ously unimagined applications were built for the Net. New ways of
doing business, both in real space and in cyberspace, were born-as
were new ways of creating, new ways of sharing the fruits of that cre-
ativity with others, new ways of being artists, new ways of innovating.
This architecture, in turn, disabled certain structures of social and
commercial control. Laws were less effectively enforced as behavior
moved outside of traditional institutions. Control over content and dis-
tribution was less effectively achieved as channels of distribution could
no longer be controlled by content providers.
The law's attitude to this change has been curiously ambivalent.
Where the interests affected by this architectural principle have been
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
139
solely state-or governmental-interests, the law-usually the first
line of defense for the state in protecting its interests-has been slow
to respond. The Internet has made it hard to collect and control taxes;
the government has decided to wait before responding.19 The Internet
has made it extremely hard to keep kids from material deemed harm-
ful to minors; the Supreme Court has made it practically impossible
for the government to respond.20 Where it is the state that has lost
because of this loss of a power to discriminate, the response of the
state has been to wait and see. The governmental attitude seems to be
along the lines of: Let the place mature a bit, let's see how it shakes
out before we launch regulation to alter it in a way that preserves
state values.
But where the interests affected by this architectural principle have
been private, a similar ambivalence has not been the practice. Instead,
the urgent response of both private and state actors has been to move
quickly to change the design of cyberspace to better protect or further
the affected interests.
Cable companies, for example, are building the next generation of
the Internet to be fundamentally different from the Net of the past. The
difference pertains to the value afforded the end-to-end argument.
Contrary to the end-to-end principle, cable companies are architecting
this new Internet to return control to the network owner.21 On the
Internet served by cable, content and applications can be discrimi-
nated among. Some content will flow quickly; other content will flow
slowly; some applications will be permitted; other applications will
not. This new network is being built to return control to the network
owner, and this change will affect fundamentally what innovation is
allowed.22
The same is true with the interests affecting the control of content in
our culture-that cultural institution referred to by a place, Hollywood.
As to content, too, the Net was initially a threat to the existing order: A
handful of companies controlled 80 percent of media in the world; five
companies control 90 percent of distributed music.23 These companies
recognized that the Net was a threat to their way of doing business.
They have responded with lawsuit after lawsuit aimed at stopping any
manner of distributing content that they can't control.24 Their efforts
have largely been a success. As Michael Robertson, former CEO of
mp3.com, told me, "I think the realities are that this litigation is as
much about straddling the competition as anything else."25
140
THE PLACE OF LAW
What they've done very successfully is dried up the capital mar-
kets for any digital music company.... [W]e went public a little
over a year ago-when you [could] raise 400 million dollars
from going public. Today, if you took a digital music company
business plan, you couldn't get a buck and a half from a venture
capital company.26
If we think about the Internet as divided into three layers-at the
bottom, a physical layer of wires and computers; in the middle, a code
layer setting the network protocols that make the Internet run; at the
top, a content layer that feeds the stuff that gets served by these proto-
cols across the wires and computers that constitute the Internet-then
the changes that I am describing are changes in the code (middle) layer,
induced by changes in the physical (bottom) and content (top) layers.
In the case of Hollywood, they are changes induced by pressure at the
content layer. In the case of cable, they are changed induced by pres-
sure at the physical layer. In both cases, the pressure induces changes to
the architecture that defines the Internet. The Net is moving from an
architecture that couldn't discriminate-that served content and appli-
cations as individuals wanted-to an architecture that discriminates
that serves content and applications as the influential commercial enti-
ties may control. In both cases, these changes transform the Internet
into something very different from what it was in its end-to-end mani-
festation, with the consequence that the Internet these changes create
increasingly protects traditional interests.27
The aim of both the network owners and the content owners is to use
their power to alter the basic architecture of the Net, so that that archi-
tecture-in particular, end-to-end-does not undermine their power. It
is the old protecting themselves against the new. It is the new being
forced to relinquish the potential that the Internet promised, in the face
of pressure from the old.
This is nothing new. In The Prince, Machiavelli described the same
pattern:
Innovation makes enemies of all those who prospered under the
old regime, and only lukewarm support is forthcoming from
those who would prosper under the new. Their support is indif-
ferent partly from fear and partly because they are generally
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
141
incredulous, never really trusting new things unless they have
tested them by experience.28
So what is the law's place in this struggle? What should it be?
The freedom that the Internet created did not come from any law; it
came from an architecture that disabled concentrations of power over
speech and communication. That architecture threatens those who
have most prospered in the world before the Internet. They, smartly,
have responded by challenging the very essence of this architecture.
They have responded by building and forcing to be built an architec-
ture that again gives controllers the power to control.
And to great effect. Network architects built a network that-in its
end-to-end form-many enthusiastically embraced. It got codified into
our lives, and every aspect of our life became increasingly affected by
it. It has become a second nervous system, rich with content and
enabling extraordinary communication. But then, using the tools of
code and law, interests of yesterday have rearchitected the place, to
vest back in themselves the power to control how this potential
emerges. They code it to build within its place the power to enforce pri-
vate control over public life. They have commandeered that which has
become our splendid second nervous system, and they are controlling
it to their ends.
The law could have a place in this transformation. It could defend
the values of decentralized, diverse innovation that the original archi-
tecture established. Or vice versa. But this has not been the law's role.
And as the law stands aside, these other modalities remake the space
that the Internet was.
The consequences of this need not be imagined; they are practically
upon us. The place of innovation and unrestrained creativity; the loca-
tion of an explosion of something new; the home to creators without
connection; the territory where no one gets to control which innova-
tions are allowed: This place is passing. In its place is a familiar space of
relatively concentrated, relatively normal, effectively managed "cul-
tural" production. The consequences of a potentially radicalizing archi-
tecture have been averted, in part through the help (inaction) of law.
This is the consequence of a change in the architecture of cyberspace,
induced by actors within the market, aided by the force of rights pro-
tected through law. Yet it occurs practically unnoticed, because we are
142
THE PLACE OF LAW
not trained to see values built into architecture. We are therefore insen-
sitive to the changes brought about by the changes in that architecture.
Even here, where the changes affect the most profound features of the
early Internet, the changes are invisible.
Invisible is thus the place of law in this change to the Internet. In the
mix of modalities that effect this change, the most important is not seen,
and yet this part unseen has the most profound effect. Altering the
basic neutrality of the network's platform alters fundamentally the
incentives, and freedom, to create and innovate on the network. This
new architecture becomes the Net's new law. Were the law aware of the
place this architecture had in its regulation, it might well respond to the
changes this change in architecture effects. So far it has not.
NOTES
I am grateful to Elisa Garza Kammeyer and John Neukom for excellent research
help.
1. Lawrence Lessig, Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace (New York: Basic
Books, 1999), 3-8 ("The claim now was that government could not regulate
cyberspace, that cyberspace was essentially, and unavoidably, free. Govern-
ments could threaten, but behavior could not be controlled; laws could be
passed, but they would be meaningless").
2. I describe these more extensively in "The New Chicago School," Journal
of Legal Studies 27 (1998): 661, and in chapter 2 of Code and Other Laws of Cyber-
space. Other authors have discussed the interaction of these modalities with
varying emphases. For a discussion primarily focused on the interaction
between the law and norms, see, e.g., Robert C. Ellickson, Order without Law:
How Neighbors Settle Disputes (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991),
131-32 ("Different controllers can combine their efforts in countless ways to
produce hybrid systems of social control"); Robert C. Ellickson, "A Critique of
Economic and Sociological Theories of Social Control," Journal of Legal Studies
26 (1987): 76. For discussions of the interaction between the law and architec-
ture in regulation, see, e.g., Erving Goffman, Frame Analysis: An Essay on the
Organization of Experience (Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1986); Jeremy
Bentham, The Panopticon Writings, ed. Miran Bozovic (New York: Verso, 1995).
For examples of analyses of the law and the market interacting in a regulatory
scheme, see Gary Minda, "Antitrust at Century's End," Southern Methodist Uni-
versity Law Review 48 (1995) 1749; and Herbert Hovenkamp, "Antitrust Law
after Chicago," Michigan Law Review 84 (1985) 213 (both discussing the interac-
tion between the law and market forces in antitrust regulation); Frank H. East-
erbrook and Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (Cam-
bridge: Harvard University Press, 1991), chap. 5 (discussing the interaction
between the law and market forces in securities regulation).
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
143
3. See, e.g., Neal Kumar Katyal, "Architecture as Crime Control," Yale Law
Journal 111 (2002): 1039 (discussing the potential of architecture-literally the
physical architecture of buildings and spaces-to prevent and control criminal
activities in a manner more effective than traditional law enforcement); Neal
Kumar Katyal, "Criminal Law in Cyberspace," University of Pennsylvania Law
Review 149 (2001): 1003-14.
4. There are other differences among these constraints that we might note
as well. First, we can't say in the abstract which of these four constraints is
strongest. Norm-wimps like me, for example, could commit twelve felonies
before breakfast; but I could never imagine showing up to a talk in a dress. This
is not, as the economist might think, because of differences in the expected
value of these two actions. The expected value of a felony is always negative,
regardless of whether I would be caught; but the expected value of showing up
to a lecture in a dress-among academics, at least, and given your view of
lawyers-might well be positive. You might, e.g., think, "not quite as boring as
I expected."
Instead, the relative effectiveness of each of these modalities of constraint
must be determined empirically. It depends upon the people and the context.
Thus whether a constraint is effective is something we must explore rather than
posit. And how we make a certain constraint effective is something we must lis-
ten for, rather than pronounce.
This last point suggests a quibble with my claim that the constraints of law
and norms can be escaped, while the constraints of architecture cannot. A well-
socialized sort, one might argue, doesn't "escape" the constraint of law or
norms just because he succeeds in evading the detection of his deviance-slip-
ping the perfume, for example, into his pocket and leaving the store. The well-
socialized, one might well argue, have those constraints architected into their
souls. The theft would bear upon his or her soul, regardless of detection.
This objection is correct, though it shows how psychology might function as
a kind of architecture in social life, not how norms are indistinct from architec-
ture. Whether or not the well-socialized can escape social norms, there are
some persons who, to some degree, do. And this continuum of escape is all we
need to note for the purposes of the argument I want to make here.
Second, although I am speaking about constraints, obviously, these modali-
ties do more than constrain. Without the law enforcing contracts, this would be
an extremely poor world. Contract law enables as much as it constrains. It is the
same with norms of civility, or markets that feed the poor, or airplanes that
carry me from sunny California to the chills of central Massachusetts. These are
expressions of law, norms, markets, and architectures; but they are not expres-
sions of constraint.
But for the purposes that I am sketching this picture of the world we know,
focusing narrowly on the constraints that these modalities impose, and not on
their empowerments, won't matter to the conclusion. The point is the same
whether or not you count the other half.
5. Robert L. Rabin and Stephen D. Sugarman, eds., Smoking Policy: Law,
Politics, and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993); Lawrence Lessig,
144
THE PLACE OF LAW
"The Regulation of Social Meaning," University of Chicago Law Review 62 (1995):
943, 1025-34; Cass R. Sunstein, "Social Norms and Social Roles," Columbia Law
Review 96 (1996): 903. See also California Labor Code, sec. 6404.5 (2001) (codify-
ing the California legislation banning smoking indoors for any places of work).
6. Jasper Womach, "Tobacco Price Support: An Overview of the Pro-
gram," Report for Congress, available at http://www.cnie.org/nle/ag-61.html
(visited July 18, 2001).
7. David Hackett Fischer, Albion's Seed: Four British Folkways in America
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).
8. Jeremy Bentham, Panopticon (London: T. Payne and Son, 1791); Janet
Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1993).
9. Alain Plessis, The Rise and Fall of the Second Empire, 1852-1871, trans.
Jonathan Mandelbaum (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), 121.
10. Robert A. Caro, The Power Broker: Robert Moses and the Fall of New York
(New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1974), 318.
11. For a more in-depth discussion of the protocols, and layering thereof,
that constitute the World Wide Web, see Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas:
The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World (New York: Random House, 200ool),
chap. 3.
12. Ibid., chap. 8.
13. "Internet Cookies: Cookie Basics," Web Street Studios, available at
http://www.webstreetstudios.com/school/cookies.htm (visited July 19,
2001); Neil Randall, "How Cookies Work," PC Magazine Online, available at
http://www.zdnet.com/pcmag/features/cookie/cksl.htm (visited July 19,
2001).
14. See Microsoft Internet Explorer 6: Web Privacy (August 27, 2001), at
http:/ /www.microsoft.com/windows/ie/evaluation/overview/privacy.asp
(explaining the technology in the Microsoft browser that protects the user from
cookie deposits according to the expressed user-preferences).
15. See Jerome H. Saltzer, David P. Reed, and David D. Clark, "End-to-End
Arguments in System Design," available at http://Web.mit.edu/Saltzer
/www /publications/endtoend/endtoend.pdf; David P. Reed, Jerome H.
Salzer, and David D. Clark, "Active Networking and End-to-End Arguments,"
available at http://Web.mit.edu/Saltzer/www/publications/endtoend
/ANe2ecomment.html.
16. As background, see Peter Cukor and Lee McKnight, "Knowledge Net-
works, the Internet, and Development," Fletcher Forum of World Affairs 25, no. 1
(2001): 46; George Gilder, Telecosm: How Infinite Bandwidth Will Revolutionize
Our World (New York: Free Press, 2000), 70-71.
17. Lessig, The Future of Ideas, 34-39.
18. "When I came to Silicon Valley, everybody said.., there's no way in hell
that you could ever fund another desktop software company. That's just over.
And then in 1995, 1996, 1997, and 1998, all those developers who previously
worked on desktop software said, Ah-hah, we're upgrading to a brand-new
THE PLACE OF CYBERLAW
145
platform not controlled.., by anybody-the Internet. [A]ll of a sudden there
was an explosion of innovation, a huge number of applications, and [a] huge
number [of] companies." Telephone interview with Marc Andreessen, Decem-
ber 15, 2000.
19. Internet Tax Freedom Law, P.L. 105-277, Title XI-XII, October 21, 1998;
summary
available at http://www.house.gov/chriscox/nettax/lawsums
.html.
20. See 47 U.S.C., sec. 223 (Supp. 1996); Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844 (1997).
But see 47 U.S.C., sec. 230 (2002); Ashcroft v. ACLU, 122 S.Ct. 1700 (2002).
21. Mark A. Lemley and Lawrence Lessig, "The End of End-to-End: Pre-
serving the Architecture of the Internet in the Broadband Era," UCLA Law
Review 48 (2001): 925.
22. I describe these changes in depth in Lessig, The Future of Ideas.
23. According to the National Cable Association, the top seven "multiple
system operators" or MSOs controlled 90 percent of the national cable televi-
sion market at the end of 2000; figures available at http://www.ncta.com
/industryoverview/top5omso.cfm; Robert W. McChesney, Rich Media, Poor
Democracy: Communication Politics in Dubious Times (Urbana: University of Illi-
nois Press, 1999), 17-18; Eric Boehlert, "Pay for Play," Salon, March 14, 2001,
available at http://www.salon.com/ent/feature/2001/03/14/payola/print
.html; Allyson Lieberman, "Sagging Warner Music out of Tune with AOL TW,"
New York Post, April 19, 2001, 34 (as of April 2001). See also Charles Mann, "The
Heavenly Jukebox," Atlantic Monthly, September 2000, 53.
24. See, e.g., UMG Recordings, Inc. v. MP3.com, 92 F. Supp. 2d 349 (S.D.N.Y.
2000); A&M Records, Inc. v. Napster, Inc., 239 F.3d 1004 (9th Cir. 2001); MGM v.
Grokster, CV 01-08541 SVW (PJWx) (C.D. Ca. 2002, and pending); S3 Inc. v.
nVIDIA Corp., 259 F.3d 1364 (Fed. Cir. 2001).
25. Telephone interview with Michael Robertson (Nov. 16, 2000).
26. Ibid.
27. See Lawrence Lessig, "The Internet under Siege," Foreign Policy, Novem-
ber-December
2001, http: //www.foreignpolicy.com/issuenovdec_2oo001
/lessig.html.
28. Niccol6 Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. Robert M. Adams, 2d ed. (New
York: Norton, 1992), 17.
Against Cyberspace
Richard Ford
According to Wired magazine the hottest Internet start-up may well be
HavenCo. Ltd., a business that is currently building a state-of-the-art if
no-frills Internet server site on a old antiaircraft deck in the North Sea,
about three miles off the coast of the British Isles. On this platform is
scrawled the name "Sealand." Wired reports that the facility "isn't
much to look at.... It consists of a rusty steel deck sitting on two hol-
low, chubby concrete cylinders that rise 6o feet above the churn of the
North Sea. Up top there's a drab building and a jury-rigged helicopter
landing pad.... The server's location means [that potential customers]
won't have to worry about fires, earthquakes, tornadoes, thefts, bomb
threats, industrial sabotage, or killer-bee attacks."'
According to its British owner and the entrepreneurs of HavenCo,
Sealand has one overwhelming advantage over the competition. Its six
thousand square feet of concrete are the sole territory of an indepen-
dent microsovereign. Businesses operating from Sealand will do so
outside the jurisdiction of any nation-state, free from national regula-
tion of content but with ready access to the people of all nations and
their nationally stabilized currency through the world wired web.
"Companies using Sealand to house their data can choose to operate
according to the special laws of Sealand, and those laws will be partic-
ularly lax.... So if you run a financial institution that's looking to oper-
ate an anonymous and untraceable payment system-HavenCo can
help. If you'd like to send old-fashioned adults-only pornography into
a grumpy country like Saudi Arabia-HavenCo can help there too."2
Territorial secession is the latest high-tech innovation.
HavenCo's Sealand may be simply one in a long line of "silicon
snake oil" schemes-as common in the world of e-commerce as pop-up
147
148
THE PLACE OF LAW
advertising and spam email. But it encapsulates nicely a certain con-
ceptual tension in much of the contemporary discourse surrounding
the Internet. There is a tendency to describe the Internet as something
more than a sophisticated medium of communication-as instead an
almost supernatural discovery. In this discourse-the discourse of
cyberspace-each computer is a portal to a undiscovered country; on-
line communications and transactions take place in a digitally conjured
parallel domain, an e-elsewhere. The infrastructure of cyberspace
physically located servers, fiber optic and old-fashioned copper cables
run underneath city streets, and modems and computers sitting on
desks and kitchen tables-is of course much more pedestrian, if not
mundane, and rarely figures in the discussions that imagine the Inter-
net as a space.
But of course this physical infrastructure is cyberspace, stripped of
its metaphysical pretensions, and this physical infrastructure lies very
much in the jurisdiction of territorial sovereigns.3 And so HavenCo's
Sealand promises to fulfill the dream of the Internet as an
autonomous space, even as it is silently premised on the incoherence
of that very dream: the need for a Sealand demonstrates the depen-
dency of cyberspace on the terra firma of political sovereigns. It
reveals that the image of the Internet as an autonomous domain is a
digitally generated illusion or, perhaps, that oldest form of misdirec-
tion, a play on words.
The virgin virtual territory of cyberspace proves fertile for the imagi-
nation. Like any new frontier, cyberspace offers the hope of leaving con-
stricting social conventions, mores, and laws behind and starting from a
clean slate. This innocent is not only fertile but also rather loose with its
charms: the Internet has become the repository for all manner of utopian
and dystopian fantasy-some of it totalitarian (for example, the film The
Matrix or the television show Harsh Realm), much of it libertarian. From
Wired magazine to on-line chat rooms to the pages of the nation's law
reviews, the commanding trope of the Internet is overwhelmingly that
of the free market; the commanding political aspiration is not democra-
tic self-governance but nongovernmental self-regulation.
The libertarian position is best articulated by David Johnson and
David Post:
The rise of an electronic medium that disregards geographical
boundaries throws the law into disarray by creating entirely new
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
149
phenomena ... that cannot be governed satisfactorily, by any
current territorially based sovereign.... Because events on the
Net occur everywhere but nowhere in particular, are engaged in
by online personae who are both "real" and "intangible" and
concern things that are not necessarily separated from one
another by any physical boundaries, no physical jurisdiction has
a more compelling claim than any other to subject these events
exclusively to its laws. Many of the jurisdictional and substan-
tive quandaries raised by bordercrossing electronic communica-
tions could be resolved by one simple principle: conceiving of
Cyberspace as a distinct "place" for purposes of legal analysis by
recognizing a legally significant border between Cyberspace and
the "real world."4
Like ancient Venice or the lost continent of Atlantis, the Internet is an
island state.
Having conceived of the Internet as a territory-analogous to the
territory of existing sovereigns-it may seem to follow that we must
respect its autonomy and grant it self-governance:
The problem with using existing territorial governments as the
source of rules for activity on the net is ... that no existing sover-
eign possesses the legitimate authority to make such rules. This
model of governance represents, in effect, an extra-territorial
power grab when transposed to the net, a form of colonialism
long rejected (and rightly so) in the non-virtual context...
because any sovereign's rules for online conduct, even if they are
arrived at democratically, do not take into account the interests
of all of those who are affected by those rules when they are
implemented in the online world-no country's efforts to "plant
its flag" on the net and in effect declare sovereignty over the net
is more clearly grounded in legitimacy than any other's, and is
going to-and should-be met with fierce resistance.5
This remarkable passage rests the full weight of its argument on the
rather thin analogy between the Internet and the territory of nations
(hence talk of "colonialism," an analogy made even less sturdy by the
authors' own insistence elsewhere that the Internet is not like a physical
territory). The cyberspace discourse rests, not on a useful analogy, but
150
THE PLACE OF LAW
on a radical contradiction: activity on the Net is so unlike all that has
gone before in "real space" that it cannot be governed by existing terri-
torial sovereigns; but at the same time it is so similar to a physical terri-
tory that we can make casual and yet confident assertions that regula-
tion by existing sovereigns or international institutions is a form of
"colonialism."
The most knowledgeable of commentators take the spatiality of the
Internet for granted. For instance Jerry Kang (to whom we will return)
argues,
The concepts of location, borders, and distance translate into a
cyber-geography. Location in cyberspace can map to a unique
Internet Protocol address and any associated domain names,
which exist for each computer on the internet.... A cyberspace
can also have clear borders that explicitly notify visitors about
the nature of the place they are about to enter. Borders can be
secured, not by installing barbed wire, but by requiring registra-
tion and passwords to gain entry.... Finally, even distance
translates to cyberspace, although it must be understood in
transaction cost, not physical terms.6
Similarly Larry Lessig-despite his prudent insistence that actions
in "cyberspace" have profound consequences for "real space" such that
the autonomous jurisdictional status that Johnson and Post advocate
may be inappropriate-nevertheless seems to accept Johnson and
Post's invitation to treat Internet activities as spatially distinct from
other activities.
Cyberspace is a place. People live there. They experience all the
sorts of things that they experience in real space there.... While
they are in that place, cyberspace, they are also here. They are at
a terminal screen, eating chips, ignoring the phone.... They
have this life there, while here, and then at some point in the day
they jack out and are only here. They rise from the machine, in a
bit of a daze, and turn around. They have returned.7
Of course this is an exercise in poetic license;8 Lessig means this to be
a somewhat loose metaphor. But only somewhat loose: Lessig contin-
ues to analogize the issues of law in cyberspace to those of territorial
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
151
sovereigns with competing claims to jurisdiction. For instance, to Jack
Goldsmith's contention that cyberspace presents few if any new legal
issues, only new incidents of familiar conflict-of-laws problems, Lessig
responds: "We have not had a time when we could say that people are
actually living in two places at once.... This is the challenge that we
will face in the future."9
We may face such a challenge in the future. But if we do, I expect it
will be because we have chosen-perhaps implicitly and not self-con-
sciously-to create such a challenge by spatializing the Internet: by cre-
ating cyberspace. If the Internet becomes cyberspace, it will be because
we made it so. As I have argued extensively elsewhere, the territorial
administration of policy-indeed legally salient territories them-
selves-is an invention and a product of public policy.'0 Territories are
made, not found. A long historical discussion, which I have only
started elsewhere, would make this point most convincingly. For our
purposes I simply restate two of the hypotheses that form the germ of
my argument.
First hypothesis: Territorial jurisdiction may appear to be as natural
and inevitable as the ground we stand on, a natural outgrowth of the
very existence of government. But jurisdiction is not an ahistorical fix-
ture of political organization. Instead, the emergence of jurisdiction is
the product of the coincidence of two innovations, one technological
the science of cartography-and one normative-the ideology of ratio-
nal, humanist government. Each development was necessary. Cartog-
raphy created the conceptual space of jurisdiction, while the
aspirations of rational government provided the incentive to direct the
ordering potential of the map inwards-toward national consolidation
and the administration of government-as well as outward-toward
defense and conquest. Therefore we can speak of jurisdiction as a tech-
nology that was "invented" or "introduced" in a given social setting at
a particular time.
Second hypothesis: We can tie certain historical developments in the
art of government to the availability of jurisdiction as a tool, just as we
can tie certain developments in the art of war to the availability of gun-
powder. When jurisdiction emerged, it advanced a set of identifiable
social projects. It disrupted existing social relations based on personal
status and replaced them with a set of social relationships based on ter-
ritorial location. To use the terms of private law, it initiated a shift from
statuses in gross or in personam to statuses appurtenant to territory. Fur-
152
THE PLACE OF LAW
ther, jurisdiction produced a new set of governmental institutions and
helped to construct a type of political subjectivity that was amenable to
a new and more comprehensive form of institutional knowledge, man-
agement, and control.
In the absence of historical examples perhaps a short, provocative
analysis will do. Almost anything that is organized territorially could
be organized in some other way. For instance, territorially defined local
governments generally have jurisdiction over land use, property taxa-
tion, health and safety regulation, traffic and parking, and law enforce-
ment as well as authority to provide a host of public services such as
sanitation, parks and recreation, maintenance of roads, and public edu-
cation. Even when one or more of these services is provided by a spe-
cialized district or authority rather than a "general purpose" local gov-
ernment, they are almost always organized territorially: so a school
district may not coincide with municipal boundaries, but it is still a ter-
ritorially defined entity.
But all of these services could, in theory, be provided statewide or
nationwide and organized according to some other criterion. The
"national public education bureau" could administer schools and
assign students in order to promote race and class integration, or seg-
regate them according to scores on IQ tests. The Park Services Admin-
istration could take over Central Park, Golden Gate Park, Amherst
Commons-all parks-and run them as federal parks. Law enforce-
ment could be performed by a vastly expanded federal police, orga-
nized according to type of crime or the identity of victims or perpetra-
tors-the Drug Enforcement Agency could handle all drug-related
offenses, or we could have a federal violence-against-women unit to
deal with the domestic offenses that the local police let slip.
One might object that the activities at issue are still "really" physi-
cally located, regardless of how they are organized administratively.
An act of domestic violence takes place somewhere as well as against
someone. We could choose to assign jurisdiction based on the status of
the victim (our imagined Violence Against Women Special Force) or
the type of weapon used (Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco and Firearms) or
the likely motivation of the perpetrator (create a division of the FBI to
handle all hate crimes). But that is simply a choice-it doesn't make the
activity any less located. This is just my point: the habit of organizing the
administration of policy in any particular way is a choice. The practice
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
153
of describing certain activities as first and foremost occurring in a
defined place rather than against a particular type of person for
instance, is a habit, not a necessity.
This doesn't mean we should abolish territorial jurisdiction. There
are some good reasons to treat certain activities as if they take place in
a distinctive space. Spatial metaphors are useful- in fact almost
inevitable-in dealing with a variety of textual, temporal, or mathe-
matical problems: we map out solutions to technical problems, we dia-
gram sentences, we think of social issues in terms of a spatial "struc-
ture" of relationships, we construct spatial time lines to make sense of
a history that in fact unfolds only in time. Many people seem almost
hardwired to think in spatial terms and can grasp complicated issues
readily if they are presented as a diagram but are lost when presented
with a verbal or written narrative.
But a spatial depiction is a stylized mode of representation. It reflects
an epistemology, a way of knowing, that is only one among many pos-
sible ways of knowing. This does not mean that a spatial representation
is "wrong" or "distorting"; but it is also not "right" in the sense of
telling us the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth. A spa-
tial representation can be extremely accurate on its own terms, but it is
still accurate only on its own terms. There are other terms, others ways
of being accurate that can tell us something more, something else.
Take for example a spatial depiction of a biological family: the clas-
sic family tree. The chart will show us the biological and legal relation-
ships between a group of people: mothers and fathers, siblings, aunts
and uncles, in laws, and so on. It is much easier for most people to
understand family relationships by looking at a family tree than it is to
hear or read a lengthy narrative containing the same information. But
the family tree is a stylized representation of these relationships
because, of course, the spatial connections it depicts are entirely con-
ceptual. The spatial depiction makes solid what could otherwise seem
somewhat vaporous; it reifies relationships that may be contingent or
ambiguous. It silently incorporates the laws of marriage and adoption
as they exist at some time and place or at several different times and
places. It takes Aunt Lizzy's word about the legitimacy of Cousin Jake
even though everyone thought Jake looked a lot like the mailman. It
omits Thomas Jefferson's children with Sally Hemings.
A spatial metaphor, like any metaphor, is not a transparent repre-
154
THE PLACE OF LAW
sentation of an underlying truth, nor is it an ideologically neutral mode
of elucidation. The decision to think of the Internet in spatial terms
and increasingly only in spatial terms-will not help us to understand
the Internet so much as it will affect the way we understand the Inter-
net. Treating the Internet as a place makes it easier to make certain deci-
sions, as Johnson and Post suggest. But it does not necessarily make it
easier to make appropriate decisions or to see all that is at stake in a
given decision. The metaphor of cyberspace simplifies decision making
by allowing us to ignore much of the technical and normative com-
plexity of this new set of technologies and social practices.
More than this, cyberspace suggests new ways of filling in the gaps
in what we experience on-line. The spatial metaphor encourages us to
uncritically import what we believe about space in other contexts to
resolve ambiguities in cyberspace. Ideas about territorialism and law
that are taken for granted in the context of "real space" transactions and
activities may be similarly taken for granted in the metaphysical cyber-
space. Some of the taken-for-granted ideas may be wrong, incomplete,
or outdated even the context of geographical territory. I have argued
elsewhere that much of what is second nature in the context of territo-
rialism-that legal location should be defined by domicile, territorial
boundaries mark off naturally and prepolitically distinctive places,
decentralization of formal territorial authority is equivalent to auton-
omy-is based on a questionable metaphysics of legal presence." This
second nature is a nature that is made, not found.
Performing Territory: Jurisdiction as a Social Practice
It is tempting to examine jurisdiction solely in terms of its material or
spatial attributes, as if it were simply an object or a built structure. But
jurisdiction is also a discourse, a way of speaking and understanding
the social world. Much of what is fascinating and vexing about territo-
rial jurisdiction is that it is simultaneously a material technology, a built
environment, and a discursive intervention. These elements cannot be
neatly severed. Territorial jurisdiction operates on all three levels
simultaneously. Further, no one level is foundational and the others,
epiphenomenal. Instead, all three levels are equally essential. To prop-
erly understand jurisdiction, we must reject the way of thinking that
severs fact from representation or "the real" from "the ideological."
Perhaps it is best to think of territorial jurisdiction as a set of social
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
155
practices, a code of etiquette. Social practices must be learned and com-
municated to others. In one sense they exist in the realm of discourse;
they are representations of approved behavior as well as the behavior
itself. For example, the social practice called "the tango" is a combina-
tion of the diagram that "maps" the steps and the actual movement of
individuals in rhythm (hopefully) and to music ("when dancing the
tango, the man leads and the lady follows; each partner should move
according to the diagram"). These representations have material conse-
quences. They determine who leads and who follows, as well as where
one places her feet. The dance is both an actual spatial practice and the
graphical representation of that practice. One could learn the tango just
by watching people actually dance, but the diagrams standardize the
learning process and thereby in a real sense define the dance itself.
Note that it would be absurd to describe dance notation as "ideology"
or "legitimation" as if it misled us as to the nature of the practice, yet it
would also be incomplete to think of it as a innocent description, as if
the graphical representation only describes and has nothing to do with
perpetuating and regulating the "actual practice."
Similarly, jurisdiction is a function of its graphical and verbal
descriptions. It is a set of practices that are performed by individuals
and groups who learn to "dance the jurisdiction" by reading descrip-
tions of jurisdictions and by looking at maps. This does not mean that
jurisdiction is "mere ideology," that the lines between various nations,
cities, and districts "aren't real." Of course the lines are real, but they
are real because they are constantly being made real, by county asses-
sors levying property taxes, by police pounding the beat (and stopping
at the city limits), by registrars of voters checking identification for
proof of residence. Without these practices the lines would not "be
real"- the lines don't preexist the practices.
Of course each of these practices can be described as "responding" to
the lines or working within the lines rather than making them. When
we think of the practices as happening "within the lines" and imagine
that the boundary lines exist independently of the practices that give
them significance, we think of jurisdiction in the abstract, removed
from any particular social content. Thinking in this way, we imagine
that jurisdiction is the space drawn on a map, rather than a collection of
rules that can be represented graphically as a map.
For many purposes, this way of thinking about jurisdiction is per-
fectly reasonable: sometimes everyone understands the jurisdictional
156
THE PLACE OF LAW
dance and knows where to step. At these times the map does seem to
precede the practices. Indeed, the representation of jurisdictional space
may at times precede the actual practices that give a jurisdiction life
and meaning. Nevertheless, we must not treat jurisdiction as a thing
that precedes practice. Lines on a map may anticipate a jurisdiction, but
a jurisdiction itself consists of the practices that make significant the
abstract space depicted on a map. Moreover, when the stakes of a juris-
diction are in question, one cannot simply refer to lines on a map. In
order to understand the significance of jurisdiction as an institution, we
must constantly remind ourselves that jurisdiction is itself a set of prac-
tices, not a preexisting thing in which practices occur or to which prac-
tices relate.
The Forbidden Dance: Jurisdiction as Production of
Status Identity
The tango, like many dances, establishes quite specific roles for the
individual dancers. There is a male and a female role, quite assertively
marked by costume (suits for the gents, glamorous and often aggres-
sively "sexy" dresses for the ladies) as well as by the requirements of
the dance steps. The male "leads" and the female "follows." There is a
set of prescribed actions that rely on the assumed superior physical
strength of the person occupying the male position and the assumed
diminutive size and gracefulness of the person occupying the female
position. These positions can be seen as simple reflections of a preexist-
ing reality. There is a distinction between men and women based in
biological nature; this distinction corresponds to a number of charac-
teristics such as strength, size, assertiveness, and gracefulness. The
dance just reflects these facts. Because men are more assertive, they
lead while the more submissive women follow.
But this way of thinking too easily assumes a relationship of cause
and effect. It may be, on the contrary, that hundreds of social practices,
of which the tango is one, construct these gendered roles and encour-
age people to conform to them. A physically strong, tall, and assertive
woman will not be offered the "male" position, even if she is naturally
well suited for it. She will be encouraged by dance instructors, parents,
potential partners, and friends to conform to the female role: learn to
accept the guidance of the male, develop grace at the expense of
strength.
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
157
Notice that it may become very difficult to distinguish between
"coerced" and "voluntary" conformity to the status roles. Our strong
and assertive woman will find it easier to conform to the female role
than to attack the structure of the tango. No one need force her in the
sense of establishing formal punishment for assertive women. Instead,
the status quo effectively sanctions her assertiveness by depriving her
of acceptable roles in which she can be assertive. Her friends will sanc-
tion her by telling her that she could get a date easily if she were a bit
"nicer" or "more feminine." Men will silently punish her by refusing to
ask her to dance. If she wants to dance, she will conform. Over time
conformity will become "second nature." Our now accomplished
dancer will remember her assertive past as an "awkward phase" that
she grew out of, as a butterfly emerges from a cocoon. At that point the
status will have also become her identity.
To some extent, the dance is a highly stylized context in which gen-
der identity and gender status is performed or constructed. The tango
teaches us that men and women have different statuses because they
have different natures. It builds a status and simultaneously justifies
that status as a biological or natural fact. It provides its own evidentiary
justification: men and women in fact behave differently while dancing;
they demonstrate by their own actions that the premise of the gendered
dance is accurate.12
Similarly, jurisdiction constructs legal statuses. Territoriality con-
structs statuses or identities based on the type of jurisdiction with which
one is associated: one's jurisdictional position is analogous to the gen-
dered positions in the choreographed dance. When we perform these
jurisdictional roles often enough, they too become "second nature." But
this type of "second nature" is the product of social practices that are
enforced by social custom, and more importantly, by law.13
The transfer of this type of unreflective habitual practice from phys-
ical territory to the Internet would be an unfortunate development for
at least two reasons. It would be bad because in thinking of the Internet
as a place, we would import ideas better suited to physical territory
into a different set of issues. For instance, many of the good reasons for
antipornography zoning just don't apply to the Internet: there are no
neighborhoods to get slummy or streets where children must pass a
porn shop as they walk to school.
But perhaps the most severe problem with this conception of cyber-
space is not what it assumes about the Internet but what it assumes
158
THE PLACE OF LAW
about geographical territory. Cyberspace also encourages us to import
our biases, mythologies, misperceptions, and unreflective habitual
practices concerning land and territory into a new domain.
In the following sections I'll suggest how the discourse of cyberspace
might have numerous regulative effects, both on expression and on
identity.
First, I'll explore a case in which the cyberspace conception is
employed in an attempt to justify more extensive regulation of on-line
expression than might otherwise be constitutionally permissible.
Second, I'll explore an argument in favor of the regulation and nor-
malization of identities on the Internet, an argument that, again,
employs the idea of cyberspace in a way that naturalizes and makes
invisible the process of regulation that is being proposed.
Sex in the Virtual City: "Cyberspace" as Regulation
In reviewing the scholarship of cyberspace, it is tempting to assert that
the spatialization of the Internet comes with a distinctive ideological
bent: libertarianism. But theorists such as Larry Lessig and Jerry Kang
are not libertarians. They invoke the cyberspace metaphor in order to
suggest the necessity of governmental intervention. For now, an exam-
ple from the pages of the Supreme Court Reporter (or the Lexis Fed
Courts "library") will demonstrate that the conception of the Internet
as a space can as easily serve to justify extensive regulation of on-line
activity as it can serve to delegitimate such regulation.
The Communications Decency Act of 1996 (CDA) ... criminally
prohibit[s] (1)... the knowing transmission, by means of a
telecommunications device, of "obscene or indecent" communi-
cations to any recipient under 18 years of age; and (2) ... the
knowing use of an interactive computer service to send to a spe-
cific person or persons under 18 years of age.., or to display in a
manner available to a person under i8 years of age... communica-
tions that, in context, depict or describe, in terms "patently offen-
sive" as measured by contemporary community standards, sex-
ual or excretory activities or organs. Violators of the CDA face
penalties including up to 2 years in prison for each violation.
However, the CDA provides affirmative defenses.., with
respect to those who (1) take good faith, reasonable, effective,
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
159
and appropriate actions to restrict access by minors to the pro-
hibited communications; or (2) restrict such access by requiring
certain designated forms of age proof, such as a verified credit
card or an adult identification number or code.14
Interestingly, the subject of this dispute is one that might interest
HavenCo's Sealand as well, the regulation of pornography for the ben-
efit of minors (Wired reports that even Sealand will not tolerate child
pornography or obscenity directed at children, this being one of the few
offenses-along with sending spam email-for which Sealand will pull
the plug on a client's secure server.)'5 While the government of Sealand
imagines that it will be easy to draw a line between "adults-only"
pornography and smut that implicates the innocence of children, the
more experienced members of the United States Supreme Court know
better.
The provision of the CDA that most directly implicated the "stakes
of cyberspace," if you will, was the "display provision" italicized in the
quotation above. I will therefore focus my analysis on the Court's treat-
ment of that provision.
In defense of the CDA the government argued that the statute was
analogous to local zoning ordinances directed at obscene expression.
The government cited two examples of constitutionally permissible
restrictions on pornography: age restrictions on access, upheld by the
Court in Ginsberg v. New York,16 and zoning restrictions on porno-
graphic entertainment and merchandising venues, upheld by the Court
in City of Renton v. Playtime Theaters.'7
The government's zoning-based defense of the CDA treated the
Internet as analogous to a territorial jurisdiction-a cyber city-and
thought of restrictions on Internet obscenity as analogous to local land
use regulation. On this analysis, the purpose of land use restrictions on
pornographic entertainment and merchandising is to insure that
minors do not have access to the obscene material. These ordinances
make a legitimate distinction between minors and adults for First
Amendment purposes.
In a similar vein, Justice O'Connor in a separate opinion, argued that
the CDA was "little more than an attempt by Congress to create adult
zones on the internet."'8 Unlike the majority, she articulated a position
that would have left open the possibility that a more carefully drafted
statute, combined with technological innovations that allow for better
16o
THE PLACE OF LAW
"cyberzoning," might yield a constitutional restriction on cyber porn.
In so doing, O'Connor treated both the Ginsberg age restriction ordi-
nance and the Renton zoning ordinance as forms of antipornography
land use restrictions:
The Court in Ginsberg... necessarily assumed.., that an
adult zone, once created, would succeed in preserving adults'
access while denying minors' access to the regulated speech.
Before today, there was no reason to question this assumption,
for the Court has previously only considered laws that operated
in the physical world, a world that with two characteristics that
make it possible to create "adult zones": geography and identity.
... A minor can see an adult dance show only if he enters an
establishment that provides such entertainment. And should he
attempt to do so, the minor will not be able to conceal com-
pletely his identity (or, consequently, his age). Thus, the twin
characteristics of geography and identity enable the establish-
ment's proprietor to prevent children from entering the estab-
lishment, but to let adults inside.19
O'Connor suggested that an analogous "zoning" of cyberspace would
likewise pass constitutional muster, but alas, such zoning was not pos-
sible given the limits of contemporary technology:
The electronic world is fundamentally different. Because it is no
more than the interconnection of electronic pathways, cyber-
space allows speakers and listeners to mask their identities....
[But] Cyberspace is malleable. Thus, it is possible to construct
barriers in cyberspace and use them to screen for identity, mak-
ing cyberspace more like the physical world and, consequently,
more amenable to zoning laws. Such technology requires Inter-
net users to enter information about themselves-perhaps an
adult identification number or a credit card number-before
they can access certain areas of cyberspace, much like a bouncer
checks a person's driver's license before admitting him to a
nightclub. Internet users who access information have not
attempted to zone cyberspace itself, but have tried to limit their
own power to access information in cyberspace.... This user-
based zoning.., is not complete. Cyberspace still remains
largely unzoned-and unzoneable....
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
161
Although the prospects for the eventual zoning of the Internet
appear promising, I agree with the Court that we must evaluate
the constitutionality of the CDA as it applies to the Internet as it
exists today.... Given the present state of cyberspace, I agree
with the Court that the "display" provision cannot pass
muster.20
O'Connor's embrace of the cyberspace metaphor was more than
casual-she, like Johnson and Post, Kang, and Lessig took it as given
that the Internet was well understood as a kind of territory. For O'Con-
nor, informed by the cyberspace conception of the Internet, the CDA's
display provision is analogous to the zoning ordinance upheld by the
Court in Renton. Both, in her view, attempt to restrict access to porno-
graphic materials to adults by requiring the spatial segregation of
minors from sites of pornographic expression.
For O'Connor, the problem with the government's cyberzoning
argument was not that cyberspace lacked a geography but rather than
cyber-users lacked (or could hide their) identities:
Cyberspace undeniably reflects some form of geography; chat
rooms and Web sites, for example, exist at fixed "locations" on
the Internet. Since users can transmit and receive messages on
the Internet without revealing anything about their identities or
ages.., however, it is not currently possible to exclude persons
from accessing certain messages on the basis of their identity.21
So for O'Connor, adequate identification technology would transform
the display provision from an unconstitutional restriction to a consti-
tutionally acceptable form of land use planning, like that upheld in
Renton.
This analysis is odd if we reject the cyberspace metaphor. First,
although the age restriction ordinance at issue in Ginsberg, the zoning at
issue in Renton, and the CDA's display provision were all laws restrict-
ing pornography, the similarity among them ends there. The Ginsberg
statute was not a land use regulation and was not analyzed as one-it
was a blanket age restriction that had nothing to do with the location of
the businesses in question or the use of real property. Its purpose was
to prevent minors from purchasing pornography, wherever it was
located. It was constitutional because it only restricted access by minors
and did not have a chilling effect on the expression or access of adults.
162
THE PLACE OF LAW
The zoning statute at issue in Renton is distinguishable from the
CDA because it does involve land use-conflicting uses of real estate by
geographical neighbors-and the CDA does not. As the majority opin-
ion by Justice Souter points out, the CDA was distinguishable from the
zoning upheld in Renton, which targeted the secondary effects of
obscene expression rather than its content.
According to the Government, the CDA is constitutional
because it constitutes a sort of "cyberzoning" on the Internet. But
the CDA applies broadly to the entire universe of cyberspace.
And the purpose of the CDA is to protect children from the pri-
mary effects of "indecent" and "patently offensive" speech,
rather than any "secondary" effect of such speech. Thus, the
CDA is a content-based blanket restriction on speech, and, as
such, cannot be "properly analyzed as a form of time, place, and
manner regulation."22
The primary purpose of antipornography zoning is not to prevent
access by minors-this objective can be achieved much more directly
by simple restrictions on sale of pornographic materials and admis-
sions to pornographic entertainment venues. The legitimate primary
purpose of antiporn zoning is to avoid the secondary effects of porno-
graphic merchants and entertainment on neighboring land uses: nega-
tive perceptions of the neighborhood, diminished property values, the
presence of unsavory persons often associated (or thought to be associ-
ated) with pornography. This is why the Supreme Court has upheld
zoning restrictions that either quarantine or disperse pornography
merchants, leaving it to local officials to determine whether local inter-
ests are best served by restricting all pornography merchants to a single
red-light district and thereby protecting the rest of the city from its ill
effects, or by dispersing it and thereby preventing a red-light district
from forming anywhere.23
Although zoning that prohibits pornographic entertainment within
a certain distance of a school (also upheld by the Court) might be
understood as designed to prevent access by minors, it is better under-
stood as, again, directed at secondary effects. Assuming effective age
restrictions on admission, physical proximity to pornographic enter-
tainment does not increase the likelihood of direct access by minors. If
the fear is that minors might still be influenced by signs or advertise-
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
163
ments or might glimpse the entertainment through windows or open
doors, this likewise could be (and is) controlled directly by ordinances
requiring opaque window shades and curtains in front of doors (the
merchants also have an economic incentive to prevent access to non-
paying passersby) and banning explicit advertisements visible to the
street. Instead, these zoning ordinances are better understood as
designed to segregate schoolchildren from the secondary effects of
porn: the demimondaine of the smut trade.
Secondary effects are understood to provide a legitimate, content-
neutral justification for restrictions on obscene expression. Indeed,
antiporn zoning can be understood to be simple land use regulation
with a side effect of the restriction of a certain form of expression. Just
as land use restrictions on slaughterhouses do not reflect a bias against
meat, so too restrictions on pornographic entertainment need not
reflect any concern about access to pornography-even for minors.
What looks like secondary effects from the perspective of First Amend-
ment jurisprudence looks like the primary problem of neighboring
incompatible uses from a traditional land use perspective. Hence the
secondary effects of pornographic expression in physical proximity to
other land uses arguably justify restrictions that might otherwise be
constitutionally suspect.
This classic land use problem doesn't exist in "cyberspace" for the
simple reason that there is no physical proximity in "cyberspace." The
cyberspace metaphor has consequences in this context: it makes it plau-
sible to (mis)describe content-based antiporn regulation as content-
neutral land use planning and thereby to justify relaxed constitutional
scrutiny.
Let's suppose that fifteen minutes or so in the future, we have avail-
able the age verification technology that O'Connor anticipated in Reno.
Such technology might make the CDA's display provision constitu-
tionally permissible because with it, we could more reasonably expect
pornographers to police the age of their customers. But the technology
would not transform the Internet into a territory or the display provi-
sion into a zoning ordinance like that at issue in Renton, which could be
justified because it targets secondary effects. The question in Reno is
and would remain: Under what conditions is it constitutionally per-
missible to require on-line pornographers to police the age of the cus-
tomers? The cyberspace metaphor does not help us to answer this ques-
tion-it only distracts us from it.
164
THE PLACE OF LAW
Of course one could cling to the spatial metaphor by claiming, as
many have, that in cyberspace "distance . . . must be understood in
transaction cost, not physical terms,"24 in download time or file size,
and not in miles, yards, or feet. We could say, along with Justice O'Con-
nor, that colorful metaphors such as "chat room" and "multi user dun-
geon" "undeniably reflect"25 an underlying geography, as if language
is necessarily mimetic. We could insist that two websites are engaged in
"neighboring" incompatible cyberspace uses when a user is likely to
accidentally get one site while looking for the other (so we might
employ nuisance doctrine to enjoin the operator of the "Youho"
pornography site for interfering with the "neighboring" Yahoo site).26
Or we might say any website is "too close" to the homes of families if
access isn't restricted by some age verification system.
But are such heroic efforts at spatial translation worth the trouble?
We could also say that local telephone calls placed to rural areas where
the cost of providing access is relatively great are "long distance" calls
in cyberspace terms, while calls placed to distant urban areas blessed
with economies of scale are cyberspace "local." We could say that tele-
vision stations occupy "locations" on the dial and therefore the regula-
tion of broadcast media should analyzed as a form of land use plan-
ning, or for that matter that age-of-consent laws are a form of "sexual
zoning" designed to "virtually distance" minors from sexual relations
best reserved to adults.
Sex in the Virtual City II: Manhattan as the Matrix
My point is not that any such system would be unworkable. Just the
opposite: we could make it work if everyone started thinking in this
way. We would all get better and better at describing Internet issues as
real property issues and land use issues and issues of territorial juris-
diction. Perhaps more importantly, we would internalize those
descriptions and act on them. Cyberspace would become "second
nature" to us, not because it is natural to think of the Internet as a space
(as Johnson and Post claim) but because it would become a habitual
practice, reinforced by the equally habitual practices of countless other
people and reinforced by law.
To illustrate this point, let's look at a "space" where territorial analy-
sis is already second nature: land use planning in cities. Immediately
one might object: "But in cities the analysis is appropriate; it is 'second
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
165
nature' because it is in fact natural." Not so fast. There are plenty of
issues that are understood as spatial but could as easily-and perhaps
more appropriately-be thought of in other terms. A great deal of what
we take as natural about physical territories-jurisdictions-is in fact
the product of a legally codified habitual practice.27
We have seen how the idea of antipornography zoning is question-
able when applied to the Internet. But the idea that antipornography
regulation is well understood as land use planning can be questioned
when applied in cities and towns as well. There, too, the use of a spatial
metaphor can distract attention from what is at stake in the regulation.
Consider an antipornography zoning initiative that followed the Ren-
ton opinion: the rezoning of New York City accomplished by Mayor
Rudolph Giuliani. I will argue that the Manhattan neighborhoods reg-
ulated by Giuliani's ordinance were, like the territory of cyberspace,
discursively produced; in a sense as virtual as an Internet chat room.
The New York antiporn zoning was famously about the control of
secondary effects: Giuliani promised to-and did-clean up the seedy
Times Square District, transforming a blighted red-light district that
even hardy New Yorkers avoided into a tourist zone fit to be the east
of the Hudson River pied-a-terre of Mickey Mouse. Other targets of
the ordinance are less celebrated: for instance, social critic Michael
Warner describes a gay-identified neighborhood that was a target of
the ordinance:
The first aim of the bill's five-hundred-feet rule is to disperse
adult businesses.... But for queers the concentration of adult
businesses has been one of the best things about then. The gay
bars on Christopher Street draw customers from people who
come there because of its sex trade.... The boutiques that sell
freedom rings and Don't Panic T-shirts do more business for the
same reasons. Not all of the thousands who migrate or make pil-
grimages to Christopher Street use the porn shops, but all benefit
from that fact that some do.... [Over time the neighborhood]
becomes a base for non-porn businesses like the Oscar Wilde
bookshop. And it becomes a political base.28
Here the concentration of adult businesses is not "secondary"-it is a
primary part of their function in a public culture. The supposed sec-
ondary effects that are the legitimate target of the zoning law under
166
THE PLACE OF LAW
Renton are, in Warner's description, a part of the primary expressive
and political content of the adult businesses.
Here, as is Reno, the spatial metaphor of zoning misdirects our atten-
tion. "Zoning" evokes the rational organization of activities in space,
the segregation of "incompatible uses," the minimization of Coasian
joint costs, the classical governmental duty to abate common-law nui-
sances. Through this spatial metaphor, the physical nature of territory
appears to literally ground decision making: we can measure appropri-
ate distances, draw objective maps, and assign various activities their
statuses and their places according to their objective social costs and
benefits. The notion of spatial zoning implies a cool-headed objectivity
and a certain inevitability: in a world of physically proximate incom-
patible activities and joint costs, zoning is necessary to minimize costs
and maximize social utility. Just as "quality of life zoning" sounds
more urbane (not to mention more constitutional) than "censorship of
public sexual expression," so too "zoning cyberspace" sells better than
"censoring on-line expression." Zoning seems to be about objective
social problems and rational solutions, while the regulation of expres-
sion entails the imposition of inherently subjective norms of decency
and delicacy.
But Warner's discussion demonstrates that the two are not so easily
severed, even in a discursive context in which "the physical" has its
strongest and most widely accepted conventional application. For
Warner part of what makes the adult businesses on Christopher Street
what they are-part of what they "sell" and what they say-is their
proximity to other such businesses in a gay business district. And this
expression is precisely what the Giuliani ordinance is directed to pro-
hibit (at least as it is applied to that neighborhood). By describing that
medium of expression as nothing more than objective physical loca-
tion, the city can present the ordinance as a form of "simple" land use
regulation and nuisance abatement.
The constitutional discourse of secondary effects imagines a sharp
division between the regulation of expression-highly suspect under
the First Amendment-and the regulation of land uses that is almost
entirely within the discretion of government. But to the extent that
space itself is a discourse, a form of expression, this division cannot
hold.
Consider first the secondary effects argument in New York's zoning
law. Here the natural, inevitable, organic properties of the territory of
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
167
the neighborhood are invoked to justify an antiporn ordinance on land
use grounds: certain uses (residences, schools, churches) simply are
incompatible with pornography. Moreover, the neighborhood natu-
rally is the property of its residents, whose chosen uses of the territory
are primary to all others.
We find a tacit analogy to a classical land use case in which the phys-
ical properties of activities are at issue: for instance, industrial uses
make an area unsuitable for residences due to unavoidable pollution
and noise: this is taken as settled because of the physical properties of
industrial activity (although, of course, one can argue that buildings
can be equipped with air filters and soundproofing). But the analogy to
pornography is weak: the physical properties of pornography are no
different than any other type of expression. Instead the incompatibility
on secondary effects analysis comes from the social properties of
pornography: the self-fulfilling association of pornography with vice
and crime.
And this raises a problem for the New York zoning law, not only
because social phenomena are generally more susceptible to change
than physical phenomena, but also because expression is precisely the
means by which citizens are supposed to go about trying to change
them. If Warner's description of the queer community as a "sex pub-
lic"29 is credited, then the use of public space for sexual expression is a
social project-an attempt to intervene in the social life of the city and
to change the association of explicit sexuality with vice and degeneracy.
This makes the social "nuisance" of porn quite different than the nui-
sance of, say, coal-burning factories in residential neighborhoods: no
industrialist ever believed he was trying to raise awareness about the
benefits of coal smoke, nor would any doctor entertain the suggestion
than polluted air would be fit to breathe if the nation's asthmatics sim-
ply freed their minds.
Which brings us to the issue of residence and ownership. Here the
analogy to a classical common-law property nuisance is stronger, but it
raises a problem that nuisance law and zoning have never adequately
resolved. Common-law nuisance is a tort against property: by defini-
tion only property owners can sue for nuisance, and their damages are
measured in terms of harm to property values or to the use and enjoy-
ment of property. In many nuisance cases, we consider only the neigh-
boring property owners who litigate the dispute: say the polluting fac-
tory owner versus the suffering residents. But we tacitly and at times
168
THE PLACE OF LAW
explicitly acknowledge that the litigants "stand in" for many other
affected parties: the factory owner represents the interests of his
employees and customers, who benefit from his profitable enterprise,
while the homeowner represents the interests of nonresident pedestri-
ans who must also breathe the polluted air. The difficulty is in deter-
mining how appropriately to account for the interest of these broader
publics in resolving the dispute. In some cases, the court attempts to
estimate the costs and benefits to the society as a whole, the benefits of
cheaper products made by coal-burning factories to society and the cost
of coal pollution. But in other cases, the societal interests are "virtually
represented" in a simple cost-benefit calculus that includes only the
costs to the litigants: presumably the idea is that in a well-functioning
market the true cost to the factory owner includes the cost to society,
since the value to society will be reflected in the firm's profitability.
The powers of the state to regulate land uses in the public interest
were derived from common-law nuisance doctrine. But with the shift
from private to public enforcement, the goal should be to consider the
interest of society as a whole-not just property owners-in determin-
ing how to regulate incompatible uses. After all, the power of the state
to regulate land uses goes far beyond anything that could be justified as
a proxy for judicially administered common-law nuisance abatement.
But in practice, land use decisions often fall back on the common-law
nuisance analysis from which the zoning power derived; analysis con-
siders the interests of property owners as proxies for different classes of
people in society as a whole. This introduces a severe bias into land use
planning: a tendency to elevate the interests of property owners over
other interests and often to ignore almost completely those interests that
cannot be virtually represented by a property-holding proxy. This bias
is explicitly articulated in a discourse and formal procedure that privi-
leges the interests of the residents of a community (those with a property
interest-at least a leasehold-in land) over any and all others.30
In the case of pornography, the porn merchant might represent the
interests of Warner's queer sex public that consumes the porn and uses
the public space created by the concentration of queer businesses. But
such virtual representation fails miserably to capture the political and
social nature of the interests Warner describes. For Warner's queer sex
publics, the battle was over as soon as the Giuliani administration
chose land use planning as it modus operandi. Or perhaps the real bat-
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
X69
tle was lost years earlier when the regulation of expression was upheld
against constitutional challenges as land use planning in Renton.
Zoning cyberspace is an attempt to import this type of land use
analysis to the Internet. The consequences of such an attempt, if suc-
cessful, are, I think, predictable. Like existing zoning, zoning in cyber-
space will likely privilege propertied interests over others. On the Inter-
net, this is likely to mean businesses with an interest in intellectual
property and private domestic entities (families) who can evoke the
right to control what enters the private home.
On the Internet, as in Manhattan, there are other people with com-
peting interests. The individual or group that wishes to use explicit sex-
ual expression in order to create a open and visible public presence
Warner's "sex publics"-would have been the victim of the CDA's
display provision, much more than the vilified "pornography indus-
try," which has already accommodated itself to the privatization of sex-
uality in "real space" by moving from public theaters to home video
and pay-per-view and which is already happy to demand, without
legal prompting, identification for its on-line ventures, not in order to
protect impressionable children but in order to ensure prompt pay-
ment for its services.
The idea of "zoning cyberspace" encourages us to think of the Inter-
net as a neighborhood that some class of "stakeholders" have a right to
control at the expense of "mere users." It is no accident that one of the
first attempts to zone cyberspace involved a restriction on expression
that challenges comfortable norms of domesticity. Like land use plan-
ning generally, zoning the Internet involves a certain domestication of
a pluralistic phenomenon, the remaking of a public medium as a pri-
vate preserve.
To some extent the protection of children is simply an excuse for
this private hijacking of a commons. But even to the extent that the
danger to children is real, cyberzoning raises questions about the
costs, to both adults and to children, of child-proofing society at large
that land use analysis, with its roots in nineteenth-century conceptions
of physical of causation and harm, is wholly unequipped to answer.
The urbanist Lewis Mumford observed that suburbia, a place to some
extent designed for children, made the adults who spent their time
there increasingly child-like: "[There is] the temptation to retreat from
unpleasant realities, to shirk public duties, and to find the whole
170
THE PLACE OF LAW
meaning of life in the most elemental social group, the family, or even
in the still more isolated individual . . . even as a single phase of life,
that of childhood, became the pattern for all the seven ages of man."31
We should hesitate before "zoning" the Internet to become a plastic
bubble fit for infants, ultimately as confining and sterile for children as
for adults.
Virtual Identity and Racial Zoning
Jerry Kang poses the following provocative question: "Can cyberspace
change the very way that race structures our daily lives?" Kang sug-
gests that it can, by providing unique opportunities for forms of racial
interactions that are either impossible or rare in everyday life. But, like
Justice O'Connor in Reno, he adopts a spatial conception of the Internet
that threatens to undermine the transformative potential of the Internet
and to enlist it as an instrument of a regressive status quo.
Kang argues that cyberspace allows for three types of racial interac-
tion: racial anonymity, racial passing, and transracial interconnection,
which correspond to three possible policy goals: racial abolition, racial
transmutation, and racial integration.
Cyberspace promotes racial anonymity/abolition to the extent that
the technology masks or fails to reveal the racial identity of its users. If
I were to deliver this paper in person, my racial identity would be
revealed to the audience, under normal circumstances. If I were to
deliver this paper on a website, I would not be required to reveal my
racial identity, and indeed it might be odd for me to do so. The Internet
could be structured, either through legal mandates or through techno-
logical mechanisms, to make racial identification impossible or easily
sanctioned (for instance, filter programs could be programmed to
search for and block out references to race, or statutes could forbid
questions about race, much as current antidiscrimination law forbids
questions about age in some contexts). Such a set of policies would pro-
mote racial anonymity.
Kang argues persuasively that racial anonymity/abolition offers
real benefits in situations where racial identity is normatively irrele-
vant, such as economic transactions.32 In such contexts, we expect that
individuals and groups should treat each other in strictly market-ratio-
nal terms, as a sort of embodied capital. Hence, an employer should
treat its employees as their predicted contribution to net profit (gross
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
171
profitability added by the employee's contributions minus the costs of
employing him or her, including opportunity costs). Similarly a land-
lord, public accommodation, or retail business should treat its cus-
tomers or tenants as predicted net profit (the income paid by the cus-
tomer or tenant minus the cost of providing the service or goods in
question). Such a conception excludes decision making based on irra-
tional bias: if a woman can do a given job as a well as a man without
imposing additional costs on the employer, she should receive identical
compensation and identical consideration. This conception of market-
rational behavior (with some exceptions and refinements) underlies the
judicial interpretation and enforcement of federal civil rights laws such
as Title VII and Title VIII of the Civil Rights Act.33
Kang also correctly points out that anonymity also has drawbacks: if
members of racial groups wish to organize for political or social pur-
poses, compulsory anonymity effectively prevents them from doing so.
Because the majority of users of the Internet are not members of minor-
ity groups, abolition could be seen as placing an asymmetrical burden
on minority group members: members of the majority will be less likely
to desire race-based organizing because as members of the majority,
they are less likely to have explicitly racial concerns. By contrast, major-
ity group members are more likely to in fact encounter groups in which
they are in the majority without the need for explicit racial identifica-
tion and coordination.34
Cyberspace promotes racial transmutation/passing to the extent
that the technology allows one to "pass" as a member of a different
race. Kang uses the examples of avatars in MUDs and characters or
personae in chat rooms: if one chooses a persona or avatar of a race dif-
ferent from one's "real space" race, one has engaged in racial transmu-
tation.35 Again, legal rules and technological fixes could either promote
or discourage transmutation. And like abolition, transmutation comes
with risks and benefits. Transmutation has positive potential: users
might come to empathize with members of other racial groups were
they to adopt unfamiliar racial personae and walk a cyber mile in the
shoes of person of another race. But, as Kang points out, racial trans-
mutation also raises the risk of stereotyping and minstrelsy.36 Nothing
would prevent the racist from acting out the most demeaning racial
stereotype, an insult that would include injury to the extent that other
users believed the cyberminstrel was in fact a member of the racial
group she parodied.
172
THE PLACE OF LAW
Racial integration is a somewhat different case. Here we rely on
some assumptions about what types of interaction is likely to occur on
the Internet. If we imagine, as Kang does, that the Internet is likely to
produce a greater number of protracted and engaged transracial inter-
actions than physical public spaces, then we might see cyberspace as a
potentially fertile site for racial integration.
Kang points out that in order for racial integration to occur, we must
avoid racial anonymity and racial passing: "As a threshold matter, any
integration environment requires some degree of racial authentication
... people must feel relatively secure that the racial signal broadcast in
cyberspace is the same signal broadcast in real space."37 This is an intu-
itively reasonable suggestion: If everyone were racially anonymous,
there could be no racial integration because, for the purposes of the
interactions, there would be no races to integrate (or perhaps more
likely, most users would assume that all users were members of the
majority racial group). By the same token, if users regularly passed for
races not "their own," other users might not trust the racial signal they
received in cyberspace-one would never know whether one was
"really" dealing with a person of different race or not.
Kang's proposed approach to these issues is one that Justice O'Con-
nor might find amenable: he suggests that cyberspace could be divided
into "zones" in which one of the three policy goals-abolition, trans-
mutation, or integration-would be pursued. In this way, we could
have the benefits of abolition in the economic sphere while allowing for
the benefits of transmutation or integration in the social sphere.
Kang's discussion provides a great deal of valuable insight. Kang is
one of the few commentators who has taken issue of race on the Internet
seriously. Here he fills a real void: as he points out, issues of race will not
vanish on the Internet: "we should not presume that by logging into
cyberspace, we enter some digital promised land that deletes centuries of
racial conflict."38 Still, Kang's racial "zoning" raises at least two ques-
tions. First, is "zoning" the appropriate way to think of what Kang pro-
poses? I have already suggested why it may not be in the context of Jus-
tice O'Connor's opinion in the Reno case. I will have more to say against
this spatialization of the Internet, specifically as it pertains to race, below.
For now I'd like to focus on a second question: How should we think
of the salience of race on the Internet? Is cyber-race simply the faithful
reflection of an objective racial identity in a new medium-"the digital
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
173
projection of your virtual self," in the language of The Matrix? If not
if, for instance, racial identity is the product of social practice and a
social conversation-then perhaps the nature of the medium through
which this discourse occurs alters-even partially determines-the
nature of the identity. In a sense, we ask a question Marshall McLuhan
would understand: if the medium is the message, then isn't cyber-race,
a racial discourse that takes place in a new medium, a fundamentally
new discourse? On this account, cyber-race cannot simply be the inno-
cent reiteration of a given and familiar racial discourse through a rela-
tively transparent medium; it must instead be the active and engaged
production of a novel racial discourse. In this sense, cyber-race is an
invention and its use, a decision.
Kang's own discussion makes this apparent: he spends over seventy
law review pages working out in fairly precise terms the way that the
discourse of cyber-race should be structured and implemented. For
instance, he argues that in order to have racial integration, a proscribed
discourse of race must be "enforced."39 People must have a way of
reading race into interactions where it would not otherwise be visible,
and they must have certainty that others will read racial signals in the
same way that they do.40 In short, integration-indeed any racialized
interaction-requires a lingua franca of race, a shared idiom through
which race is spoken and understood.
Any integration environment requires some degree of racial
authentication. In other words, people must feel relatively secure
that the racial signal broadcast in cyberspace is the same signal
broadcast in real space.., any virtual community could make
clear that its ground rules preclude cyber passing.... This clear
ground rule could be enforced by members of the community to
various verification strategies.... Verification could take place
through some regime of registration... [or] verification can take
place through interrogation. When someone claims to be a grad-
uate of a prestigious university in a chat room, one might ask
which dormitory she was affiliated with.... Men passing as
women often are unmasked when they cannot answer elemen-
tary questions about menstruation. Soon, people may simply ask
for a virtual business card, which includes a photograph or per-
sonal web page.41
174
THE PLACE OF LAW
If the Internet is place, it may seem appropriate that people bring
their physical selves-including racial markers-with them, just as we
do when traveling from one neighborhood or one city to another. In
language reminiscent of O'Connor's discussion of age verification in
Reno, Kang describes such practices as "authentication."42 But a policy
of racial authentication might seem less benign were we to think of the
Internet, not as a space, but as a medium of communication. Suppose,
for instance, that someone were to propose racial authentication for
communication through the mail or over the telephone. Such a policy
would share much in common with that at issue in Ferrill v. The Parker
Group:
TPG [The Parker Group] is a telephone marketing corporation,
often hired to perform work for political candidates. The con-
duct at issue in this case involves TPG's work making "get-out-
the-vote" calls for various political candidates ... Approximately
io% of such calling is race-matched, such that black voters are
called by black TPG employees who use the "black" script, while
white voters are called by white TPG employees who use a dif-
ferent "white script."... TPG employees doing the race matched
calling in 1994 were assigned separate calling areas and separate
scripts according to race... TPG also physically segregated
employees who worked at race matched calling. Black callers
were segregated into one room and white callers segregated into
another.43
Although for the Ferrill court, the physical segregation of employees
was most disturbing, I would like to focus instead on TPG's use of
racial scripts. TPG's policy could be defended as an innocent form of
racial authentication-a way of letting potential voters know with
whom they are communicating in a medium that does not adequately
register racial data. But it should be obvious that this type of racial
identification entails something more than a faithful reflection of the
reality at the end of the telephone receiver. In order to produce race
through the wire we need a stylized racial script. The policy of the
Parker Group can be seen as a high-tech apartheid: black and white
employees were not only physically segregated (in an almost quaint
nod to the heritage of the American South) but more importantly, dis-
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
175
cursively segregated, divided by compulsory scripts; each individual
required to play out a racial identity written for it. And through its use
of racial scripts and racial demographic data, the Parker Group installs
Jim Crow as master of ceremonies, not only for its own employees but
also for the potential voter who its practices target: she too is interpel-
lated into the racial script that was written with her votes, her mind and
her body as its object.
TPG's practice is, as the court held, racially discriminatory. But more
than that, TPG's practice produced racial identity-it produced race in
the form dictated by a script and imposed that particular racial script
on its employees and on every household its employees called.
How different is the production of race that Kang proposes? Very
different one might argue, if evaluated in terms of motivations. But of
course we don't know that the motivations of TPG were racist: perhaps
TPG simply thought its racial scripts were the best means of getting its
message out given certain underlying social facts about race. Perhaps
they thought that potential black voters would appreciate the racial
camaraderie that their policy offered. Perhaps they were right. The evil
of TPG's racial scripts policy was that it was self-fulfilling: TPG took a
contingent idea of racial identity for granted and in so doing con-
tributed to entrenching it as a practice, to making it second nature.
By the same token, I would assert that what Kang calls authentica-
tion is a regime of regulation through which racial identity is produced
and inscribed. What Kang proposes is that the racial status one is
assigned in one context should follow her to another. It is not clear why
this policy should be understood as simple "authentication" any more
than it would be authentication if we were to require persons from
caste-based societies to regularly announce their caste status while on
holiday in the United States or require convicted felons to regularly
recount their former crimes once released from incarceration (a sort of
expanded Megan's Law). Viewed from this perspective, the term
authentication takes on an Orwellian tone, a tone that is amplified by
Kang's suggestion that this "authentication" could be underwritten by
a "regime of registration and.., interrogation."44
If self-identification is insufficient to establish racial membership,
how is membership to be evaluated? It may seem that this is a simple
matter, no more difficult than racial identification in "real space." But
in most social contexts we don't have need of racial authentication, and
176
THE PLACE OF LAW
when we do, racial authentication is a source of crisis and anxiety, not
easy or obvious evaluation. If we were to use photographs,45 would,
say, lighter-skinned blacks or Asians with "Anglo" features be disbe-
lieved? If interrogation were employed, what responses would authen-
ticate racial identity? Knowledge of ethnic food or music? Use of ethni-
cally identified language patterns or slang? These criteria might
inscribe the stereotypes that Kang justifiably worries about in the con-
text of racial transmutation. Of course we cannot stop people from
racially identifying on the Web, nor should we. But a policy of requiring
racial identification in any context, with the regulative normativity
such a policy would necessarily entail, raises questions that it is easy to
overlook if we think of the Internet as a space with physical properties
waiting to be revealed.
While I question some Kang's proposals, I wholly share his concerns
about the future of cyberspace. I too "fear that cyberspace will reinscribe
a repressive racial mechanism even deeper into our nation."46 This is
one reason that I'm against it. As in O'Connor's description of antiporn
zoning in Reno, the idea of cyberspace as something with natural-if not
inevitable-attributes serves to legitimate a proposal that should be at
least controversial, and perhaps alarming. In both cases the analogy to
land use facilitates a story about a natural and wholesome activity-the
domestic pleasures of the family home in one case, the highly normative
discourse of identity politics on the other-which needs protection from
infiltration by a perverse doppelginger: in the first instance, pornogra-
phy, which mocks, mutates, and infects the conventional sexuality-for-
procreation of the heterosexual marriage, and in the second, racial trans-
mutation, a sort of queer racial cross-dressing that undermines the
conventional commitments and assumptions of identity politics.
Both narratives are undergirded by a pervasive and dangerous fic-
tion of the private: in the first instance, that sexuality can and should be
restricted to the private realm of the home, where it can and should be
domesticated and quarantined; in the second instance, that racial iden-
tity is a thing about which there are truths and that those assigned a
identity could guard and control those truths and their circulation if
given a private property-like right in them. Finally, both narratives
imply that the authentication of identity is nothing more than the inno-
cent verification of a prepolitical fact, even as they require ever more
elaborate mechanisms to produce, assign, and inscribe those identities;
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
177
they imply that the verification of identity has no consequences for
those with nothing to hide, even as the apparatuses of identification
require an ever more ubiquitous and comprehensive intervention into
the lives of anyone within their reach.47
Conclusion
To be "against cyberspace" is not to oppose the Internet, nor is it to cri-
tique an inaccurate description of the Internet. It is to question an ill-
considered design of the Internet. Cyberspace tempts us with a tale that
is both exhilarating and comforting: that the Internet is a new frontier,
a terra nullius laden with the opportunities of first discovery, and is at
the same time familiar, presenting only issues we have dealt with
before. The story concludes that it can be domesticated in the same way
we have domesticated much of the natural environment.
The metaphor of territory promises to provide a literal grounding
for policy analysis-a set of physical constants that can be referred to as
fact and taken for granted. This idea is often inappropriate in the con-
text of physical territory: The economist Ronald Coase demonstrated in
the context of nuisance law that physical proximity does not produce a
physics of causation and harm that can help to resolve a dispute but
instead a conflict of joint costs requiring value judgments about who
should bear socially created burdens. Modern land use planning has
inherited the same problem: at its best, land use analysis acknowledges
the necessity of value judgments about the worth of various land uses.
Similarly the rights and duties of local citizenship seem to naturally
attach to residency, but residence itself is a contingent legal status, not
a feature of physical location.
Even more so in the case of the Internet, a metaphysics of space
threatens to derail sound analysis and to smuggle in, as inevitable or
logically compelled, background rules that should be subject to debate.
Whether deployed to support anarchic "self-regulation" or to justify
the domestication of threatening or destabilizing expression, the cyber-
space trope serves neither justice nor democracy. The idea of cyber-
space is not incorrect; it is unwise. We could, through discourses like
cyberzoning, remake the Internet as cyberspace. We could make the
metaphor reality. This project called cyberspace is what, I propose, we
should be against.
178
THE PLACE OF LAW
NOTES
1. Simson Garfinkel, "Welcome to Sealand. Now Bugger Off." Wired, July
2000, http://www.wired.com/wired/archive/8.o7/haven.html.
2. Ibid.
3. The telecommunications companies that increasingly administer the
Internet know this very well: they have lobbied hard for federal regulation of
telecommunications, not in order to keep government out of the Internet, but to
secure governmental intervention in the physical world that is favorable to
their interests.
4. David R. Johnson and David G. Post, "Law and Borders: The Rise of
Law in Cyberspace," Stanford Law Review 48 (1996): 1376, 1378.
5. David R. Johnson and David G. Post, "And How Shall the Net Be Gov-
erned?" http://www.cli.org/emdraft.html.
6. Jerry Kang, "Cyber-Race," Harvard Law Review 113 (2000): 1186.
7. Lawrence Lessig, Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace (New York: Basic
Books, 1999), 190.
8. Greater evidence that Lessig means this only poetically is that earlier in
the same text he asserts that cyberspace is "not a place, it is many places" (ibid.,
63). The thrust of Lessig's argument in largely in line with my own: the dimen-
sions and implications of cyberspace or cyberspaces are not given; they are a
function of law, technology, and other social practices. I wish to add that the
Internet as a territory-a conception that Lessig and many other commentators
take for granted-is also not given. It too is one of the technologies that will
determine what the Internet will be.
9. Ibid., 193.
10. See generally, Richard T. Ford, "Law's Territory: A History of Jurisdic-
tion," Michigan Law Review 97 (1999): 843.
11. Ibid.
12. I owe this line of analysis regarding gender to Judith Butler, Gender
Trouble (New York: Routledge, 1990). Note that it is not necessary to deny the
existence of biological differences between the sexes in order to question the
thoughtless conflation of these biological differences with a host of social differ-
ences.
13. In no way do I wish to suggest that because it produces statuses, juris-
diction (much less the tango!) should be abolished. Nor is the "answer" to
replace structured practices with "fluid" ones that allow individuals autonomy
(All dance must be modern interpretive dance! Down with choreography!). At
this point, I simply wish to draw attention to an aspect of the jurisdiction that
has been overlooked, and to suggest that this aspect is not accidental, but
instead a central and indispensable function of the jurisdiction.
14. Reno v. A.C.L.U., 521 U.S. 844 (1997).
15. Garfinkel, "Welcome to Sealand."
16. Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U.S. 629, 20 L.Ed. 2d 195, 88 S.Ct. 1274.
17. City of Renton v. Playtime Theaters, 475 U.S. 41, 89 L.Ed. 2d 29, 1o6 S.Ct.
925.
AGAINST CYBERSPACE
179
18. Reno v. A.C.L.U., 886.
19. Ibid., 889; emphasis added.
20. Ibid., 889-90.
21. Ibid., 890.
22. Ibid., 867-68.
23. See generally Renton; Young v. American Mini Theaters, 427 U.S. 50 (1976).
24. Kang, "Cyber-Race," 1187.
25. Reno v. A.C.L.U., 890.
26. The reader might object that we in fact do exactly this. Through trade-
mark law we do enjoin activities likely to lead to confusion with an established
mark. But this proves my point: it makes more sense to treat the Yahoo/Youho
conflict as a trademark dispute under established law than as, say, a zoning dis-
pute under a new law informed by the cyberspace metaphor.
27. See generally Ford, "Law's Territory."
28. Michael Warner, The Trouble with Normal (Cambridge: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1999), 157-59.
29. Ibid.
30. Warner notes that the zoning bill's "procedural politics.., are set up to
guarantee the dominance of the rhetoric of neighborhood at every step. [The
bill first was considered at] every community board in the city, followed by the
borough boards. Only then did the City Planning commission hold public hear-
ing at which non-neighborhood organizations could testify.... The assumption
remained that people have a right to control their neighborhoods" (ibid.;
emphasis added).
31. Lewis Mumford, The City in History (New York: Harcourt, Brace and
World, 1961), 494-95.
32. Kang, "Cyber-Race," 1189.
33. See generally, Mark Kelman, "Market Discrimination and Groups,"
Stanford Law Review 53 (2ool): 883.
34. See Kang, "Cyber-Race," 158-59.
35. See ibid., 1180-85.
36. See ibid., 1184-1188.
37. Ibid., 1196.
38. Ibid., 1154.
39. Ibid., 1197.
40. Ibid., 1196.
41. Ibid., 1196-98.
42. Ibid., 1196.
43. Ferrill v. The Parker Group, 168 F. 3d 468 (1999).
44. Kang, "Cyber-Race," 1198.
45. Ibid.
46. Ibid., 1208.
47. This is not to say that these "zoning" proposals do not attempt to deal
with real social conflicts. It may be that children are harmed by exposure to cer-
tain types of sexual imagery. And it is almost certainly true that the evils Kang
worries about-especially racial minstrelsy by insensitive or racist persons-
180
THE PLACE OF LAW
are real problems in an unregulated Internet. But what is odd about both cyber-
space analyses is the underlying implication that these problems are somehow
new and unprecedented in "cyberspace." Children have been exposed to sex-
ual imagery since there were children and sexual images. And there is no rea-
son to think that sexual imagery is more damaging today than in the past (Mar-
quis magazine-a periodical dedicated to sexual fetish imagery-is tame fare
compared to the writings of its namesake, the marquis de Sade). The first clan-
destine peek by preteen boys at some neighborhood father's not-so-well hid-
den porn collection, is, ironically, a staple rite of passage in that exemplary zone
of American domesticity, the middle-class suburb.
Similarly, one need only note the history of the word minstrelsy to know that
racial "transmutation" in the service of stereotyping predates the Internet, the
computer, indeed the telephone and the motion picture. And surely racial
stereotypes acted out by live people, at times people of color themselves-the
televised version of Amos' n' Andy comes to mind, but there are countless other
examples-are at least as damaging to healthy race relations as anonymous
encounters on the Internet, where hoaxes and scams are already sufficiently
pervasive as to make the intelligent user view any "information" with a skepti-
cal eye.
Contributors
Wai Chee Dimock is Professor of English at Yale University.
Lawrence Douglas is Associate Professor of Law, Jurisprudence and
Social Thought at Amherst College.
Patricia Ewick is Professor of Sociology at Clark University.
Richard Ford is Professor of Law at Stanford University.
Lawrence Lessig is Professor of Law at Stanford University.
Annelise Riles is Professor of Law and Professor of Anthropology at
Cornell University.
Austin Sarat is the William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Jurispru-
dence and Political Science and Professor of Law, Jurisprudence and
Social Thought at Amherst College.
Saskia Sassen is Professor of Sociology at the University of Chicago.
Susan S. Silbey is Professor of Anthropology at the Massachusetts
Institute of Technology.
Martha Merrill Umphrey is Associate Professor of Law, Jurispru-
dence and Social Thought at Amherst College.
181
Index
Academy of Science, 85
Ackerman, Bruce, 25
Activist politics, 1o9-10, 118-24. See
also Human rights; NGOs (non-
governmental organizations)
Adjudication, 26, 53
Adultery, 51, 53
AIDS, 96. See also Sexually trans-
mitted diseases
Akhmatova, Anna, 30
Alcohol, regulation of, loo100-101o
Alexander, Gregory, 61
Alien life-forms, 30-36
Anachronism, 34
Analogy, doctrine of, 23
Anderson, Benedict, 26-27
Anonymity, 170-76
Anthropology, 43, 45, 56-57
Antiessentialism, 56
Antiformalism, 52, 53
Architecture: of cyberspace, 13-14,
133-42; use of the term, 133
Argentina, 129n. 41
Aristocracy, 83, 84
Aristotle, 33, 35
Asian financial crisis, 116, 128n. 32,
129n. 41
Atomic theory, 35
Australia, 46, 58
Authentication, of identity, 174-76
Authoritarianism, 44
Averroes, 33, 35
Bentham, Jeremy, 135
Berkeley, H. S., 55, 56
Berman, Harold, 22
Blomley, Nicholas, 16n. 6, 44
Bosnia, 43
Boundaries: and digital networks,
114, 116-17; Douglas, Sarat, and
Umphrey on, 2-3, 5-6, 8-10; Ewick
and Silbey on, 89-90; and legal for-
malism, 9-10, 43, 52-53; between
public and private space, 89-90;
Riles on, 43, 52-53; Sassen on, 114,
116-17; and scientific laboratories,
89-90. See also Territory
Boyle, James, 111
Boyle, Robert, 10o3
Britain, 45, 46-53, 55, 62, 65
Brown, Clarence, 30
Browsers, 136-37
Cable companies, 139, 145n. 23
Campbell, David, 43
Capitalism, 5, 27, 49, 56-58, 60; and
cultural preservation, 47; and
"neutral space," 44
Carew, Walter, 51, 54
Carnarvon, Lord, 52
Cartography, 44-45, 151
Castes, 10o, 83. See also Half-castes
Christianity, 28, 51, 53, 55. See also
Religion
Cities, global, notion of, 118, 120
Citizenship, 46, 124, 177
City of Renton v. Playtime Theaters,
159-63, 165-66, 169
Civil rights, 3, 171
Civil Rights Act, 171
183
184
INDEX
184
Civil War (U.S.), 47
Clark, David, 138
Coase, Ronald, 177
Coleridge, Lord, 4-5
Colonialism, 10-11, 44-73, 149
Commodity, 101
Common law: and legal formalism,
50, 51, 55; and zoning laws, 167,
168
Communications Decency Act
(CDA), 14-15, 158-59, 161, 162, 169
Competition, 6, 139-40
Conquest, Robert, 22
Cookie technology, 137
Copyrights. See Intellectual property
Cultural state, 11, 43-73
Cyberspace: and activist politics,
109-10, 118-24; architecture of,
13-14, 133-42; and the authentica-
tion of identity, 174-76; and
browsers, 136-37; and cross-border
circuits, 118-24; and decentraliza-
tion, 111, 112, 115; and the distinc-
tion between private and public
space, 114-18; Douglas, Sarat, and
Umphrey on, 12-15; Ford on,
147-81; and global finance, 110,
114-18, 123-24; and human rights,
120, 121-22; and intellectual prop-
erty, 111-13, 119, 123; Lessig on,
131-46; and libertarianism, 13,
148-49, 158; and protocols, 136,
137, 14o; and regulation, 13-14,
110-14, 131-46, 158-64; and state
authority, 109-30; use of the term,
125n. 3; zoning of, 14-15, 159-76.
See also Digital networks; Internet
Dante Alighieri, 9, 28-39
Decentralization: and digital net-
works, 111, 112, 115, 141; Lessig on,
141; Sassen on, 111, 112, 115
Deleuze, G., 97
Democracy: and digital networks, 12,
110; Ewick and Silbey on, 11, 79,
83, 88-89; Sassen on, 12, 110; and
scientific laboratories, 11, 79, 83,
88-89
Democritus, 35, 41n. 39
Department of Lands and Surveys
(Fiji), 62-63
Descartes, Rene, 101
Digital networks: and activist poli-
tics, 109-10, 118-24; and the
authentication of identity, 174-76;
and browsers, 136-37; and
cross-border circuits, 118-24; and
decentralization, 111, 112, 115; and
the distinction between private
and public space, 114-18; Douglas,
Sarat, and Umphrey on, 12-15;
Ford on, 147-81; and global
finance, 110, 114-18, 123-24; and
human rights, 120, 121-22; and
intellectual property, 111-13, 119,
123; Lessig on, 131-46; and libertar-
ianism, 13, 148-49, 158; and proto-
cols, 136, 137, 14o; and regulation,
INDEX
INDEX
185
INDEX
96; Ewick and Silbey on, 78, 86;
Sassen on, 120, 121; and zoning
laws, 167-68
Environmental Protection Agency
(EPA), 86, 95, 96. See also Environ-
mental protection
Epistemology, 57, 78-82, 85, 104, 153.
See also Knowledge
Essentialism, 45, 56-57
Ethics. See Morality
Evolutionary theory, 45
Ewick, Patricia, 10-11, 75-108
Family trees, 153
Feminism, 83
Ferrill v. The Parker Group, 174-75
Fetus, legal status of, 99-10oo0
Feudalism, 83
Fiji, 10, 15, 46-73; Department of
Lands and Surveys, 62-63; and
half-castes, notion of, 10, 46, 53-57,
63-65; Property Law Act, 65
Financial markets, global, 12, 110o,
114-18, 123-24
Firewalls, 112
First Amendment, 163, 166
Fischer, David Hackett, 135
Ford, Richard, 14-15, 147-81
Formalism, 43-73
Foucault, Michel, 78, 97
Framework Convention on Climate
Change (U.N.), 113
France, 25-26, 31, 33
Freedom: and cyberspace, 141, 142;
Ewick and Silbey on, 98, 99, 104;
Lessig on, 141, 142; and scientific
laboratories, 98, 99, 104
Freehold land, notion of, 49
GDP (gross domestic product),
115-16
German language, 31
Germany, 25-26, 55
Gillett, Sharon Eisner, 113
Ginsberg v. New York, 159-61
Giuliani, Rudolph, 165, 166, 168
Global cities, notion of, 118, 120. See
also Globalization
Global finance, 12, 110, 114-18,
123-24. See also Globalization
Globalization: and digital networks,
12, 109-10, 114-18, 121, 123-24;
Dimock on, 26; Douglas, Sarat, and
Umphrey on, 5, 6, 8, 12; Sassen on,
109, 121; and time and territory,
relationship of, 26. See also Global
cities; Global finance
Goldsmith, Jack, 151
Gordon, Arthur, 45-52, 56-57, 63,
69n. 26
Gordon, Robert, 6-7, 19n. 41
Governmentality, 78, 98, o100, 102-4
Greek mythology, 34
Gusterson, H., 96
Habermas, Jirgen, 83
Habitation, history of, 101-2
Half-castes, 10, 46, 53-57, 63-65. See
also Castes
Harding, Sandra, 83
185
186
INDEX
i86
Innovation, 138, 141, 142, 159-60
Instrumentalism, 6-7, 59-60, 62
Intellectual property: and digital net-
works, 111-13, 119, 123; Ewick and
Silbey on, 11, 78, 86; Sassen on,
111-13, 119, 123; and scientific lab-
oratories, 11, 78, 86
International Monetary Fund (IMF),
5, 117, 129n. 41
International Telecommunications
Union (ITU), 113
Internet: and activist politics, o109-10,
118-24; and the authentication of
identity, 174-76; and browsers,
136-37; and the Communications
Decency Act (CDA), 14-15, 158-59,
161, 162, 169; and cross-border cir-
cuits, 118-24; and decentralization,
111, 112, 115; and the distinction
between private and public space,
114-18; Douglas, Sarat, and
Umphrey on, 12-15; Ford on,
147-81; and global finance, 110,
114-18, 123-24; and human rights,
120, 121-22; and intellectual prop-
erty, 111-13, 119, 123; Lessig on,
131-46; and libertarianism, 13,
148-49, 158; as a "place," 14, 150,
154; and protocols, 136, 137, 140;
and regulation, 13-14, 110-46,
158-76; and state authority, 109-30;
zoning of, 14-15, 159-76; use of the
term, 125n. 3
Internet Corporation for Assigned
Names and Numbers (ICANN),
112, 126n. 13
IP (Internet Protocol) addresses, 136
Isenberg, David, 138
Italy, 30, 33, 36-38
Jews, 28
Johnson, David, 114, 148-49, 154, 161
Judiciary Act (Soviet Union), 22
Jurisdiction: and cyberspace, 14-15,
147, 149, 151-58; definition of, 2;
Dimock on, 21-42; Douglas, Sarat,
and Umphrey on, 2, 5-6, 8-1o,
14-15; Ford on, 147, 149, 151-58;
Sassen on, 111-14; as a social prac-
tice, 154-56; without sovereignty,
26-28; and the Soviet Union, 8-9,
21-42; and time and territory, rela-
tionship of, 21-42
Kafka, Franz, 3
Kang, Jerry, 15o, 158, 161, 170-72,
174-76
Kapor, Mitchell, 113
Kennedy, Duncan, 17n. 16
Knowledge: Ewick and Silbey on,
80-84; Ford on, 153; and legal for-
malism, 45, 57; objective, 81-85;
Riles on, 45, 57; and scientific labora-
tories, 80-84. See also Epistemology
Kuhlman, Charles C., 113
Lab Standard (OSHA), 92-93. See also
Occupational Safety and Health
Administration (OSHA)
Land Claims Commission, 48-49,
INDEX
INDEX
187
INDEX
Mandelstam, Nadezhda, 23, 27-28
Mandelstam, Osip, 8-9, 14, 23-39
Marx, Karl, 101
Marxism, 22, 101
Mataquali (clan), 49
Mathiason, John R., 113
Matrix, The (movie), 173
Maurer, Bill, 73n. 86
McLuhan, Marshall, 173
Meaning-making, 44-45
Megan's Law, 175
Memory, 44
Methodists, 51, 53
Mexican financial crisis, 116,
128n. 32
Microsoft Corporation, 137
Modernism, 6o-61i
Modernity, 101-2
Morality: Coleridge on, 4-5; Ewick
and Silbey on, 104; and legal for-
malism, 52, 64; Riles on, 52, 64; and
scientific laboratories, 104
Morgan, Lewis Henry, 48
Moses, Robert, 135
mp3.com, 139
MUDs (multiuser dungeons), 164,
171
Mueller, Milton, 113
Multilateral Agreement on Invest-
ment, 119
Mumford, Lewis, 169
Music, distribution of, 139-40
Napoleon III, 135
National Academy of Sciences, 85
Nationalism, 26-27, 43
Nation-state: Dimock on, 8-9, 21-42;
Douglas, Sarat, and Umphrey on,
2, 8-1o, 12; and the Soviet Union,
8-9, 21-42; and time and territory,
relationship of, 21-42
Natural law, 2
Neoliberalism, 5
Netscape Web browser, 136-37
Neutrality, the state's claim to,
61
New England, founders of, 135
New York City, 165-70
New Zealand, 46
NGOs (nongovernmental organiza-
tions), 26, 110, 121-22. See also
Activist politics; Human rights
NKVD (People's Commissariat of
Internal Affairs), 24, 25
Nobel laureates, 85
North American Free Trade Agree-
ment (NAFTA), 5
Nuisance law, 177
Objectivity, 81-85. See also Epistemol-
ogy; Knowledge
Occupational Safety and Health
Administration (OSHA), 86, 92-93,
102
O'Connor, Sandra Day, 14-15,
159-61, 164, 170-74, 176
"On the Nature of the Word" (Man-
delstam), 35
Ontology, nonterritorial, 21
187
188
INDEX
i88
Plantation workers, 47
Poland, 31
Pornography, 157-70, 176
Positivist epistemology, 82. See also
Epistemology
Post, David G., 114, 148-49, 154, 161
Postcolonialism, 65-66
Power: and digital networks, 12, 111,
124; Douglas, Sarat, and Umphrey
on, 2-5, 12; Ewick and Silbey on,
97-102; and the Hobbesian state of
nature, 2-3; Sassen on, 111, 124
Pragmatism, 10o, 53, 57, 6o, 62
Present, universal, notion of, 28-29,
37. See also Time
Prince, The (Machiavelli), 140-41
Privacy, 131, 137-38, 176
Privatization, 114
Property: and legal formalism, 44-45,
58-66; notions of, 44; ownership,
58-66. See also Land use
Property Law Act (Fiji), 65
Protocols, 136, 137, 140
Queen v. Dudley and Stephens, 3-5,
20on. 43
Race: and half-castes, 10o, 46, 53-57,
63-65, 68n. 19; and zoning regula-
tions, 170-76. See also Civil rights
Reason, 44
Reed, David P., 138
Reidenberg, Joel R., 114
Relativity, of simultaneity, 28-29
Religion, 82, 99-100oo. See also Chris-
tianity; Heresy
Reno v. ACLU, 163, 170, 172, 174, 176
Representation, 155
Riles, Annelise, 9-10, 43-73
Robertson, Michael, 139-40
Rose, Nikolas, 11, 98, 99
Royal Society, 81, 107n. 22
Safety issues: and cyberspace, 152;
and scientific laboratories, 11, 78,
90-97. See also Occupational Safety
and Health Administration
(OSHA)
Saltzer, Jerome H., 138
Sarat, Austin, 1-20
Sassen, Saskia, 11-12, 14, 109-30
Scale, hierarchies of, 109
Scientific laboratories: and the
boundaries between public and
private space, 89-90; and democ-
racy, 79, 83, 88-89; and discipline,
97-99, 102; Douglas, Sarat, and
Umphrey on, 11-12, 15; and the
Enlightenment, 79, 82-84; and epis-
temology, 78, 80-82, 85, 104; and
governmentality, 78, 98, 100oo, 102-4;
and intellectual property, 78, 86;
and the liberal subject, 80-84,
97-102; and the management of
danger, 91-97; and religion, 82,
99-100oo; and self-regulation, 91-97;
and truth, 75-78, 80-82, 84-85, 102,
104
Self: despotism of, 98; -governance,
91-97, 149; -preservation, right of,
INDEX
INDEX
189
INDEX
Sassen on, 116; and time and terri-
tory, relationship of, 21-42
Soviet Union, 8-9, 14-15, 21-42; Judi-
ciary Act in, 22; the NKVD (Peo-
ple's Commissariat of Internal
Affairs) in, 24, 25; Soviet Criminal
Code of, 8-9, 21-42; Soviet Crimi-
nal Procedure Code of, 23, 24, 25
Space, 9, 11, 13; dangerous, 89-97;
and digital networks, 109-46;
Ewick and Silbey on, 79-84,
97-102; Lefebvre on, 44; Lessig
on, 131-46; metaphor of, perva-
siveness of, 14-15; private, 89-90,
114-18; public access to, 89-90,
114-18; safe, constructing, 90-97;
and scientific laboratories, 79-84,
97-102. See also Boundaries;
Territory
Special Board (Soviet Union), 24-
25
Stalin, Josef, 8, 14, 15, 23-24, 35
"Stalin Epigram" (Mandelstam), 8,
23-24
Standardization, 85, 92, 105n. o10
Stereotypes, 171, 176
Stewart, Potter, 3
Subjectivity: and cyberspace, 152;
Ewick and Silbey on, 80-84,
97-102; Ford on, 152; and scientific
laboratories, 80-84, 97-102. See also
Self
Sugar industry, 47
Suva, 65, 66
Szymborska, Wislawa, 31
TCP/IP (Transmission Control Proto-
col/Internet Protocol), 136
Territory: and cyberspace, 14-15,
109-30, 141, 149-60, 177; Dimock
on, 8-1o, 21-42; Douglas, Sarat,
and Umphrey on, 1-2, 6, 8-1o,
14-15; and Fiji, 5, 10, 45-73; Ford
on, 149-60, 177; and legal formal-
ism, 5, lo, 45-73; Lessig on, 141;
Riles on, 5, lo, 45-73; Sassen on,
109-30; and time, 21-42. See also
Boundaries; Space
Thailand, 116
Time: frames, conflicting, 28-30; and
literary culture, 8-9, 21-42;
national, 27; nonnumerical struc-
ture of, 28-29; nonterritorial, 36-39;
and ruptured chronology, 32-33;
synchronized, 27; and territoriality,
21-42; and a universal present,
notion of, 28-29, 37; warps, 27
Title registration, 58, 59-62, 64
"To the German Language" (Mandel-
stam), 31
Torrens, Robert, 59
Torrens system, of title registration,
58, 59-62, 64
Totalitarianism, 8-1o, 21-42, 148
TPG (The Parker Group), 174-75
Trademarks. See Intellectual
property
Transcendence, 84
189
190o
INDEX
Whippy family, 65, 66
Wilson, Richard, 6
Wired magazine, 147
Workplace safety, 11, 78, 90-97
World Bank, 5
World Intellectual Property Organi-
zation (WIPO), 113, 127n. 14
World Trade Organization (WTO), 5,
119
Worldviews, 1-2, 65
World Wide Web: and browsers,
136-37; and the domain name sys-
tem, 111; emergence of, 136; and
privacy, 136, 137; servers support-
ing, 136, 137, 147-49. See also
Cyberspace; Internet
Zilsel, Edgar, 83
Zoning: and cyberspace, 164-76;
racial, 170-76