Contesting the Logic of Painting
Visualising the Middle Ages Editorial board
Professor Madeline Caviness, Tufts Univ...
312 downloads
1295 Views
3MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
Contesting the Logic of Painting
Visualising the Middle Ages Editorial board
Professor Madeline Caviness, Tufts University (USA) Dr Eva Frojmovic, University of Leeds (UK) (series editor) Professor Diane Wolfthal, Arizona State University (USA) Professor Catherine Harding, University of Victoria (Canada)
VOLUME 2
Contesting the Logic of Painting Art and Understanding in Eleventh-Century Byzantium
by
Charles Barber
LEIDEN • BOSTON 2007
Cover illustration: The Mandylion and Keramion. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Rossianus gr. 251, fol. 12v detail. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library. Brill has made all reasonable efforts to trace all rights holders to any copyrighted material used in this work. In cases where these efforts have not been successful the publisher welcomes communications from copyrights holders, so that the appropriate acknowledgements can be made in future editions, and to settle other permission matters. This book is printed on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A C.I.P. record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
ISSN 1874-0448 ISBN 978 90 04 16271 6 Copyright 2007 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishers, IDC Publishers, Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. printed in the netherlands
This book is dedicated to my wife and daughters Sophie, Cleome, and Josephine
CONTENTS List of Illustrations ...................................................................... Foreword ..................................................................................... Acknowledgements ..................................................................... List of Abbreviations .................................................................. Chapter One
ix xi xv xvii
The Synodikon of Orthodoxy and the Ground of Painting ...........................................................
1
Symeon the New Theologian: Seeing Beyond Painting ..................................
23
Chapter Three Michael Psellos: Seeing Through Painting ....
61
Chapter Two
Chapter Four
Eustratios of Nicaea and the Constraints of Theology .........................................................
99
Leo of Chalcedon, Euthymios Zigabenos and the Return to the Past ............................
131
Afterword ....................................................................................
159
Bibliography ................................................................................
165
Index ...........................................................................................
177
Chapter Five
Illustrations
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS Fig. 1. St. Athanasios prays to an icon Christ. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 15r. Source: by permission of The British Library. Fig. 2. Reading of the Synodikon of Orthodoxy. Mt. Athos, Dionysiou Monastery, ms. 587m, fol. 43r. Source: after Stylianos Pelekanidis et al., The Treasures of Mount Athos: Illuminated Manuscripts, vol. 1 (Athens: Ekdotike Athenon, 1973), g. 220. Fig. 3. Crucixion. Moscow, State Historical Museum, cod. 129, fol. 67r. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études. Fig. 4. Christ Antiphonetes. Koimesis Church, Nicaea (Iznik). Source: after Theodor Schmit, Die Koimesis-Kirche von Nikaia. Das Bauwerk und die Mosaiken (Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter, 1927), pl. XXVII. Fig. 5. Synodikon of Orthodoxy. Icon, London, British Museum. Source: copyright The Trustees of the British Museum. Fig. 6. Nikephoros tramples John the Grammarian. Moscow, State Historical Museum, cod. 129, fol. 51v. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études, Paris. Fig. 7. Nikephoros of Contantinople, Theodore of Stoudios and the Iconoclastic Synod. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 27v. Source: by permission of The British Library. Fig. 8. Matthew the Monk prays to the Mother of God. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 55, fol. 260r. Source: Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 31. Fig. 9. Monks in a Penitential Prison. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 394, fol. 42r. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library. Fig. 10. The Creation of Adam. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 162r. Source: by permission of The British Library. Fig. 11. Adam outside Paradise. Baltimore, The Walters Art Museum. Source: The Walters Art Museum, Baltimore.
x
list of illustrations
Fig. 12. Michael Psellos before Michael VII Doukas. Mt. Athos, Pantokrator Monastery, ms. 234, fol. 254r detail. Source: after Stylianos Pelekanidis et al., The Treasures of Mount Athos: Illuminated Manuscripts, vol. 3 (Athens: Ekdotike Athenon, 1979). Fig. 13. Crucixion and Saints. Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the Michigan-PrincetonAlexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai. Fig. 14. A Persian artist depicts the Mother of God. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 14, fol. 106v detail. Source: after Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 69. Fig. 15. The Blachernae Theotokos detail. Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the MichiganPrinceton-Alexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai. Fig. 16. Ambassadors before the Oracle at Delphi. Mt. Athos, Esphigmenou Monastery, ms. 14, fol. 396v detail. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études. Fig. 17. The Magi and Christ. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 14, fol. 106v. Source: after Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 69. Fig. 18. The Mandylion and Keramion. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Rossianus gr. 251, fol. 12v detail. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library. Fig. 19. Abgar and the Mandylion detail. Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the MichiganPrinceton-Alexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai. Fig. 20. Fathers in the Dogmatic Panoply. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 666, fol. 1v. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library. Fig. 21. Alexios I Komnenos before Christ. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 666, fol. 2r. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library.
FOREWORD What is it that we see when we look at a work of art? The answer seems obvious, a representation of a given subject, fashioned by an artist, mediated by the materials of painting, and recognized by those looking. This model is all too familiar. It sets the work of art within our perceptual horizon, demarcating the limits of human understanding, and thence embodying a modern conception of the world. It is a model that is assumed in much of our writing on the history of art, afrming the modernist foundations of this discipline.1 Yet, is this model always apt? What happens when the subject of a given painting exceeds the boundaries of human perception and thence of painting itself ? These questions come to the fore whenever we look at an image of the Christian God. This strangely doubled gure, human and divine, limited and limitless, visible and invisible, challenges our assumptions about representation, inviting us to think again about art’s possibility. While it is tempting to treat Christ’s face as a special case, cloistered away in the sub-category of religious art and lost in the mists of the medieval world, such disregard deprives those who would dismiss this category of image of an opportunity to challenge some commonplace assumptions regarding the possibilities of painting. Christ’s face provokes questions about what it is that we see in the work of art, and thus raises questions about the assumption of visibility that has grounded the modernist project of our art history. This book addresses these assumptions by examining a body of writings on art and vision produced in eleventh-century Byzantium. When studying the history of the icon in Byzantium, it is tempting to assume that the theological framing for the work of art had been settled by the years of debate during the iconoclastic crisis of the eighth- and ninth centuries. As we shall see in the course of this study, this assumption is given some grounds by the later reiteration of iconophile doctrine in such texts as the Synodikon of Orthodoxy and the various compendia of heresies produced in the Middle Byzantine era as well as by the lack
1 A useful critique of these foundations is to be found in Georges Didi-Huberman, Confronting Images: Questioning the Ends of a Certain History of Art (College Park, PA: Pennsylvania State Press, 2005).
xii
foreword
of actual iconoclastic episodes in the centuries that followed the end of iconoclasm in the ninth century. But beneath this appearance of a stable and unchallenged doctrine, the question concerning the icon did not remain uncontested. Without the opening shaped by the dramatic and familiar moment of actual iconoclasm, scholars have overlooked the vigor of this iconomachy (a discursive “iconoclasm” that does not imply the breaking of images). In so doing, we have perhaps missed the degree to which our understanding of the icon, the material manifestation of the human knowledge of sacred things, can be enhanced by the various manners in which key thinkers of the eleventh- and early-twelfth century contested the implications of the horizon both opened and framed by iconic depiction. This study will therefore invite the reader to reconsider a familiar problem through the lens and writings of these Byzantine authors, most of whom are probably unfamiliar to all but specialists in the eld. Each of these eleventh-century writers has asked whether the work of art is adequate to convey the truth of a sacred subject? In addressing this topic they also necessarily asked whether it was indeed possible for a philosopher or theologian or artist to claim that he or she could understand or dene or describe or depict such a sacred subject? At rst glance such questions appear limited to the narrow realm of sacred art in a distant and troubled land. I will, however, endeavor to show that the lines of enquiry opened by these authors remain pertinent to those concerned with conceptualizing works of art in the postmodern era. In particular, I believe that these writers invite us to reect upon the grounds of our discipline by drawing us away from the representational assumptions that underlie the practice of art history and that have so often failed to open paths to understanding the Byzantine icon. What we shall nd is that these eleventh-century writings enquire into the conditions that might or might not permit a painting truthfully to convey its subject. This was a primary concern of the texts examined here and so invites our attention. Rather than focusing on the constructed roles of the maker or consumer of the painting—whose fate is so often in the care of the art historian—, these texts will lead us to consider the dening role of the subject of an image. By these means, they draw our attention away from the human horizon of the artist or the beholder and ask us to consider the implications of the necessarily absent subject or ground that both precedes and exceeds the frame of the work of art. In so doing, these writers provide language that allows us to explore paths that might allow the more adventurous among us to break from
foreword
xiii
the horizon of our crumbling age of the world picture and thence to learn to understand an horizon dened by an age of the world icon.2 As much of the material found in this study is relatively under-used by art historians and is little known to non-specialists in the eld, I have provided the reader with lengthy passages from the original materials and have provided translations of all the Greek texts. I hope that by these means the readers of this book will gain some familiarity with the language in play in Byzantine discussions of art and that Byzantium’s surprisingly varied, exploratory, and contested contribution to the wider discussion of art will thereby become more widely appreciated.
2 I borrow these terms from: Martin Heidegger, “The Age of the World Picture,” in Martin Heidegger, Off the Beaten Track, ed. and trans. Julian Young and Kenneth Haynes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002): 57–85 and Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2004): 302–307.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In the course of writing this book I have accumulated many people to whom I owe the debt of gratitude. I would like to thank Julian Deahl and Marcella Mulder for their willingness to publish this work. I would like to thank the participants in two workshops in Byzantine Intellectual History at the University of Notre Dame for listening to and discussing versions of some of the material contained in this book. I am grateful to have been able to discuss this material in various venues, including the University of Chicago, the Johns Hopkins University, the Institute of Fine Arts, the Courtauld Institute, the Byzantine Studies Conference in Athens, Georgia, and the College Art Association meeting in Boston. For numerous instances of help, encouragement and advice that contributed in a variety of ways to the making of this book I would like to thank: Robin Cormack, Catherine Jolivet-Lévy, Herbert Kessler, Derek Krueger, Henry Maguire, Robert Nelson, Glenn Peers, Maria Vassilaki, Panayotis Vocotopoulos. A very special debt is owed to my colleague at Notre Dame, David Jenkins, who is a constant source of encouragement. Finally, I would like to dedicate this book to my wife, Sophie White, and to my daughters, Cleome and Josephine.
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS Mansi = Mansi, J. D. Sacrorum Conciliorum Nova et Amplissima Collectio. Florence and Venice: A. Zatti, 1759–98. PG = Patrologiae cursus completus, Series graeca. Ed. Jacques-Paul Migne. 161 vols. in 166 parts. Paris: Migne, 1857–66.
CHAPTER ONE
THE SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY AND THE GROUND OF PAINTING It is always difcult to recover the commonplace understanding of an icon at a given moment in the past. When examining an icon, numerous questions arise concerning what it shows (g. 1): what is it that one sees here? Is it Christ, or a painting of Christ, or perhaps a painting and Christ? If this is Christ, then what exactly is it that we see of him? Since Christ is both human and divine, does the depicted face show both of these natures or just one? If it shows both natures, then can we presume that the divine can be depicted? If so, then how is the divine in the painting? If not, then what does the depiction of the human nature alone imply regarding the relation of the painting and its subject? Does painting permit an accurate and adequate account of this subject? Or rather, what does this subject disclose of itself through the painting? How, then, ought one to look at or pray to this icon? Undoubtedly, the answers to such questions will vary from time to time, place to place, and person to person. They might be found in the traces left on the objects themselves, or considered in light of related works of art, or through the evidence of practices and beliefs brought to bear upon the image. By these means one can accumulate an array of data that permits a varied and nuanced account of the icon. Rather than follow these paths, this study’s primary focus will be upon a series of theoretical texts that attempted to police one’s perception of the icon by dening competing interpretations of the play of the painted image in eleventh-century Byzantium. While we shall in due course nd that these claims on the icon are varied, it will also become clear that they contest a common ground, namely the implications of the icon’s relation to the visible. This relation dened the icon quite narrowly, limiting the potential of the icon to an imitation of that which was visible to the human senses.1 This reading was a legacy of the iconoclastic era (730–87, 815–43) and was reiterated annually on
1 Most recently: Charles Barber, Figure and Likeness: On the Limits of Representation in Byzantine Iconoclasm (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002).
2
chapter one
the rst Sunday of Lent, when the Synodikon of Orthodoxy, one of the key texts for dening the theology of images, was read out in the churches of Byzantium.2 It is this theological statement and its attendant readings that can give us an entry to a commonplace understanding of the icon and can describe for us the implications of the common ground of painting, the visible, in eleventh-century Byzantium. The Synodikon achieved its rst denitive form in the late-ninth century. Beginning in the mid-eleventh century and then increasingly during the Komnenian era (1081–1185), the document received a series of additions. These changes redened the limits of orthodoxy, building upon the fundamental question of the image that rst shaped the Synodikon. This point of departure was reinforced by the procession of icons that preceded the actual reading.3 The regular feast is rst mentioned in the Kletorologion of Philotheos, which dates to 899, and is rmly established in the imperial Book of Ceremonies of the mid-tenth century.4 While this performance was notionally commemorative, recalling the ending of the iconoclastic dispute in 843, the changes noted above indicate that the text was also a living entity that described and revised an orthodoxy that was built upon the notion that the icon itself embodied and manifested this same orthodoxy and thence the culture as a whole.5 A glimpse of the performance of this text is offered in g. 2. Taken from an eleventh-century lectionary, this image shows an ambo upon which nine lectors and priests stand.6 One of these holds open a scroll from which he reads the Synodikon of Orthodoxy. Neither the manuscript
2
Jean Gouillard, “Le Synodikon de l’Orthodoxie. Édition et commentaire,” Travaux et mémoires 2 (1967): 1–316. 3 Gouillard, “Synodikon:” 14. 4 Nicolas Oikonomides, Les listes de préseance byzantines du IX e et X e siècle (Paris: CNRS, 1972): 195; Constantine Porphyrogenitos, De ceremoniis aulae byzantinae, ed. Johann Jacob Reiske, vol. 1 (Bonn: E. Weber, 1829–30): 156–60. 5 The theoretical basis for my analysis of the cultural signicance for the icon lies in Martin Heidegger, “The Origin of the Work of Art,” Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002): 1–56 and Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd revd. ed. (New York: Continuum, 2004). 6 Kurt Weitzmann, “An imperial lectionary in the Monastery of Dionysiou on Mount Athos. Its origins and its wanderings,” Revue des études sud-est européenes 7 (1969): 239–53; S. Pelekanides, P. Christou, Ch. Tsoumis, The Treasures of Mount Athos, vol. 1 (Athens: Ekdotike, 1973): 439; Christopher Walter, “The date and content of the Dionysiou lectionary,” Deltion tes christianikes archaiologikes hetaireias 4/13 (1985–86): 181–89; MaryLyon Dolezal, “Illuminating the liturgical word: text and image in a decorated lectionary (Mount Athos, Dionysiou Monastery, cod. 587),” Word and Image 12 (1996): 23–60.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
3
tradition of the Synodikon itself, nor our liturgical sources are clear regarding the precise moment for this reading of the text. Some sources place it in the course of the eucharistic liturgy, either before the reading from the Epistles or from the Gospels. Other manuscripts place the reading after the orthros (dawn) service. Our image does not settle this dispute, but it does provide an eleventh-century icon for the feast, one that is clearly focused upon the public reading of our text. It is fortunate that we are in a position to reconstruct an eleventhcentury performance of the Synodikon. The Synaxarion of the Theotokos Evergetis monastery in Constantinople describes quite fully the subsidiary texts that would have framed a reading of the Synodikon.7 While this monastery was founded in 1049,8 the liturgical document dates a little later. The latest saints mentioned are Lazaros of Mt. Galesion who died in 1054 and Timothy the second Abbot, who died after 1067. The liturgical practices of this community were available for imitation by such mid-twelfth-century foundations as the Kosmosoteira (1152) and St. Mamas (ca. 1146–58). It is reasonable, then, to assume that the core of the liturgical practice that has come down to us dates within this time period.9 Given this, the Synaxarion offers us an opportunity to recover the performance of a public reading of the Synodikon in the monasteries of eleventh-century Constantinople. In Evergetine practice the Sunday of Orthodoxy began at vespers on the Saturday. Specic hymns regarding the feast were sung. Two of these were addressed to the prophets, as the day was also dedicated to Moses and Aaron, and two to the icons. The Synaxarion is unclear about the precise identity of these verses. Later in this service we nd two texts that specically address the meaning of the feast. The rst of these introduces the link between orthodoxy and the image:
7
Aleksandr Dmitrievskij, Opisanie liturgiceskich rukopisej, vol. 1 (Kiev, 1895): 520–22. The fundamental study on this monastery: Jean Pargoire, “Constantinople: le couvent de l’Évergétis,” Echos d’Orient 9 (1906): 371–72; 10 (1907): 155–67, 249–63 is being superseded by a research project undertaken by the Center for Byzantine Studies at Queen’s University, Belfast. Publications from this project include: The Theotokos Evergetis and Eleventh-Century Monasticism, eds. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby, Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.1 (Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1994); Work and Worship at the Theotokos Evergetis, eds. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby, Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.2 (Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1997). 9 On issues in dating this text see John Klentos, “The Synaxarion of Evergetis: algebra, geology and Byzantine monasticism,” Work and worship at the Theotokos Evergetis, ed. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby, Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.2 (Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1997): 329–55. 8
4
chapter one
, ! " # $ %& ' , %' ( ) * $ % , & + %%! $ ./ 0 1 , 23, # 45 , 6# 3' , 1 7 83 # 81 !6 * 9 $ 7 0 , ; 6 < , = 13 8 * + & %3 3 >61 , .? @ )= 9 #, # 45 , 86! 9 & = A .10
Advancing from ungodliness to the true faith, and illumined with the light of knowledge, let us clap our hands and sing aloud, offering praise and thanksgiving to God; and with due honor let us venerate the holy icons of Christ, of the all-pure Virgin and the saints, whether depicted on walls, on wooden panels, or on holy vessels, rejecting the impious teaching of the heretics. For, as Basil says, the honor shown to the icon passes to the prototype it represents. At the prayers of your undeled mother and of all saints, we beseech thee, Christ our God, to bestow upon us your great mercy.
What is striking about this prayer is the focus on the quality of worship brought to bear on an icon. This is dened as veneration, a relative form of worship, rather than the adoration addressed to the Trinity. Furthermore, this relational aspect is validated by reference to Basil the Great’s fundamental denition of the meaning of the veneration addressed to an imperial10image.11 The second short text serves as a frequently repeated motif throughout the liturgy of the day. This is the apolytikion, a verse used to mark the end of discrete sections within the liturgical performance:12 C7 D% 1 3 3/ E5!, + 3%6 # 9 #, .? @ )1 * 3' $ 6816 !& 3, F G+H I A 83 / %!/* J! % # * .K ' $ , @ L7 9 #, 1 = # = 1 .12
We venerate your holy icon, loving Lord, asking you to forgive our transgression, Christ our God. For you of your own will was pleased in the flesh to ascend upon the Cross in order to deliver from the bondage of the enemy those whom you have fashioned. Therefore in thanksgiving we cry aloud to you: You have lled all things with joy, our Savior, when you came to save the world.
10 Triodion (Athens: Apostolic Diaconias of the Church of Greece, 1960): 134; The Lenten Triodion, trans. Mother Mary and Archimandrite Kallistos Ware (London: Faber and Faber, 1978): 301. 11 Basil of Caesarea, Liber de Spiritu sancto, 2nd ed., ed. B. Pruche, Sources chrétiennes 17bis (Paris: Cerf, 1968): 406.19ff. 12 The Lenten Triodion: 302; Triodion: 133.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
5
Here the practice of prayer before an icon is neatly linked to the economy of salvation opened by Christ’s death and resurrection. This introduces a favored iconophile theme in that it is the death of Christ’s human nature—the nature that is seen in the image—that opens the possibility of Christian salvation. In addition to these brief troparia, the meaning of the feast was elaborated by a series of readings performed during the orthros (dawn) service. These readings provide a carefully constructed account of the icon and its history. They not only serve as a preface for the more theoretical reading of the Synodikon text, but also remind their audience of the importance of the icon to the celebration of Orthodoxy itself and provide them with the narratives with which to articulate this evaluation. The rst two stories reveal the power of images. They do this in the context of the competition between Judaism and Christianity and so draw on a range of anti-semitic stereotypes. The rst of these passages was a well-known narrative of an icon from Beirut renowned for having resisted attacks made on it by its Jewish owner. The story was used in the fourth session of the Seventh Oecumenical Council in 787 and perhaps dates from the seventh century.13 The narrative tells the story of a Christian who has rented a room in the Jewish quarter of Beirut. There he had hung an icon of Christ. A little later, when this Christian moved to a larger dwelling he left the icon behind. Next, a Jewish man moved into the room containing the icon. He did not notice its presence or perhaps recognize its subject until a fellow Jew saw the painting and identied its subject. The rst Jew was then reported to the Chief Priests and the Elders of the Jewish community, who then expelled him, believing him to be a devotee of Christ. The rest of the Jews then began to spit at, mock and beat the image, declaring: “Whatever our fathers did to him, we will also do all of it to his icon (J 6 9 , ' 3 9 & M = /).”14 They then “crucied” the icon, putting nails through the portrait’s hands and feet, offering it gall and vinegar, beating it with a reed, and spearing it in the side. As the spear pierced Christ’s side,
13 The story was told at the Seventh Oecumenical Council: Mansi 13.24E–32A. The date might be suggested by the description of blood and water owing from Christ’s side: Anna Kartsonis, “The Emancipation of the Crucixion,” in Byzance et les images (Paris: La Documentation française, 1994): 164–169. 14 Mansi, 13: 28B.
6
chapter one
blood and water began to ow from the icon. The Jews collected these liquids, as they planned to show that they had no miraculous healing powers. But when the liquids were applied to the paralyzed, the blind, and others, they were all healed. Rather than undermining Christianity, the story recounts that these miracles led these Jews to convert. They took the damaged icon and their tale to the local bishop and asked him to baptize them. The entire community was then baptized and their synagogue became a church dedicated to Christ.15 The other synagogues in the city became martyria. The second story continues the Christian-Jewish thread of the rst. The story is set in the early seventh century and is identied with the image of Christ Antiphonetes, a much-favored miraculous icon in Constantinople. In this instance, the narrative concerns a merchant named Theodore who was shipwrecked as he returned from Syria to Constantinople.16 Having lost his merchandise, Theodore despairs and wishes to leave the mercantile world and to become a monk. He is, nonetheless, persuaded to try one more trading trip. To do this, he borrows money from a Jew called Abraham. The transaction between them is made before the image of Christ Antiphonetes. Unfortunately, this trading expedition also fails. Abraham then loans Theodore another sum. Once more, this takes place before Christ’s icon. This time, Theodore journeys to an island in the Atlantic (perhaps the British Isles). Here he trades for a cargo of lead and tin. He also receives fty pounds of gold, which he throws into the sea. This gold oats all the way to Abraham in Constantinople. Upon Theodore’s return to Constantinople, he nds that his cargo has turned to silver. Following these miracles, Abraham converts to Christianity. Both texts present the image as something more than a simple portrait. In both instances the image is shown to be a site of power. In the case of the narrative of the Beirut icon the image is treated as if it were Christ and then responds by bleeding and thence providing the materials for miraculous healing. The story relates well to the emphasis
15 One can suggest that the icon provided the identity for this church, cf. Charles Barber, “Early Representations of the Mother of God,” in Mother of God: Representations of the Virgin in Byzantine Art, ed. Maria Vassilaki (Milan: Skira, 2000): 253–61. 16 Fr. Combes, Historia haeresis monothelitarum (Paris: A. Bertier, 1648): 612–44. An English version of this story can be found at: Sabine Baring Gould, Historic Oddities and Strange Events, First Series (London: Methuen, 1891): 103–20. See: Cyril Mango, The Brazen House: A Study of the Vestibule of the Imperial Palace of Constantinople (Copenhagen: i kommission hos Ejnar Munksgaard, 1959): 142–46.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
7
upon Christianity’s materialism in the Adversus Judaeus literature of the seventh century.17 It also underlines the narrow divide that separates and icon from its subject, quite clearly afrming that what happens to the icon affects its subject.18 An anti-semitism that presents the Jews as models of both otherness and redemption then frames these descriptions of the icon’s power. They are here turned into Christ-killers, a theme that occurred with some frequency in the polemical construction of the iconoclasts. This is seen most clearly in the ninth-century Khludov Psalter’s presentation of the Crucixion as being both an act committed by Jews and as a parallel to the fate of the icon at the hand of the iconoclasts (g. 3). The Antiphonetes narrative is less dramatic (g. 4). Nonetheless, the story reiterates the themes we have seen in play, with the icon presented as a locus for the performance of divine power and as a material proof of Christianity’s superiority over Judaism. Together these stories emphasize the particularity of Christianity and the power of the icon. The Evergetes Synaxarion then asks for a text that provides an historical account of orthodoxy. It is probable that this was the Life of St. Theodora, wife of the Emperor Theophilos (828–42) and mother of Michael III (842–867).19 Her signicance for the celebration of this feast is vividly shown in a Palaeologan icon for the Feast of Orthodoxy now owned by the British museum icon (g. 5).20 Here, the presence of the Hodegetria icon has emphasized the centrality of the icon to the meaning of this feast. Theodora and Michael are shown in a foremost position among the heroes of the iconoclastic era. The text of Theodora’s life presents an account of the end of iconoclasm, one that provided a key source for the Chronicle written by George the Monk, ca. 867.21 Theodora’s 17 For a recent discussion with reference to further literature see Charles Barber, Figure and Likeness: On the Limits of Representation in Byzantine Iconoclasm (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002): 13–37. 18 Glenn Peers, Sacred Shock: Framing Visual Experience in Byzantium (College Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2004): 35–58. 19 Athanasios Markopoulos, “< )8 (BHG 1731),” Symmeikta 5 (1983): 249–85; trans. Martha P. Vinson, “Life of St. Theodora the Empress,” in Byzantine Defenders of Images: Eight Saints’ Lives in English Translation, ed. Alice-Mary Talbot (Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks, 1998): 361–82. 20 Robin Cormack, “Icon of the Triumph of Orthodoxy,” Byzantium: Treasures of Byzantine Art and Culture, ed. David Buckton (London: British Museum Press, 1994): 129–31; Dimitra Kotoula, “The British Museum Triumph of Orthodoxy icon,” Byzantine Orthodoxies, ed. Andrew Louth and Augustine Casiday (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006): 121–30. 21 Discussed at Vasilii Regel, Analecta Byzantino-Russica (NewYork: Burt Franklin,
8
chapter one
story portrays iconoclasm in graphic terms as an instance of disorder and disruption: These were not images of the kind whose destruction results in no great peril or even little harm; on the contrary, they were images whose installation was a mark of pious zeal and whose abolition was a bitter form of tyranny. As a result, church thought was perverted, books were altered, sanctuaries were stripped of decoration, priests replaced, innocent men subjected to legal investigation, criminals placed in positions of power and the most illustrious sees. Nor was this all: whole regions were torn by civil strife, monasteries were deserted, people took to the hills, their family property conscated by the state. This is how far the heresy of the iconoclasts went.22
As was typical of the iconophile literature of the mid-ninth century, the iconoclastic Patriarch John VII (838–43) was presented as the primary force behind the Emperor Theophilos’ personal turn to iconoclastic policies. Here, the Patriarch is accused of being “the chief conspirator or rather chief sorcerer and chief demon” as well as a new Apollonios of Tyana and Balaam. This theme was to be found in an array of visual and verbal sources from the end of iconoclasm. The Patriarch Methodios (843–47) cast John in this light in his engagingly hostile hymn written for the Feast of Orthodoxy.23 John was portrayed in a similar manner in the Khludov Psalter (g. 6), where he is shown with the wild hair of a sorcerer and is compared to Simon Magus.24 By such means, the iconoclasts were to become “enemies of the truth” who had sought to undermine and alter the tradition of the seven oecumenical councils.25 Having described the evils of iconoclasm, the Theodora narrative then introduces a number of iconophile heroes from the second phase of iconoclasm: Ioannikios of Mount Olympos (752/54–846), Patriarch 1964): iv–x. The Life of Theodora and The Absolution of the Emperor Theophilos are included in a collection of saints’ lives in the British Library (BL Add. 28.270). The manuscript was completed in 1111 by the scribe Nicholas. It contains a marginal note that the Life of Theodora was to be read on the Feast of Orthodoxy. For a recent evaluation of these texts, their dates, and the discussion of the Emperor Theophilos see: Athanasios Markopoulos, “The rehabilitation of the Emperor Theophilos,” in Byzantium in the Ninth Century: Dead or Alive? ed. Leslie Brubaker (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1998): 37–49. 22 Markopoulos “< :” 258; Vinson “Life:” 362. 23 Methodios, Canon on the setting up of the holy images: PG, 99: 1767–80. 24 Kathleen Corrigan, Visual Polemics in the Ninth-Century Byzantine Psalters (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992): 27–28. 25 Markopoulos “< :” 260–62; Vinson “Life:” 367–69.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
9
Nikephoros (ca. 750–828), Theodore of Stoudios (759–826), Patriarch Methodios (2nd half 8th c.–847), Michael Synkellos (ca. 761–846), Theophanes the Confessor (ca. 760–817/818), Theodore Graptos (ca. 775–841/844) and Theophanes Graptos (ca. 778–845).26 It is notable that these gures, together with Isaiah of Nikomedia (. mid–9th c.) are represented on the British Museum icon seen above. In number and kind these are understood to provide an overwhelming contrast to the isolated and idiosyncratic iconoclasm embodied in the person of John the Grammarian. The text then introduces a further comparison. This begins when the military disasters of the 830s were blamed on Theophilos’s iconoclastic policies.27 This ill-starred account of the emperor continues until Theophilos is presented being tormented on his deathbed for his adherence to iconoclasm. This suffering is only brought to an end when he embraces an image of Christ found on an enkolpion worn by the kanikleios Theoktistos.28 The Life then contrasts the reign of Theophilos with that of his son, Michael III, who, having acceded to the throne, immediately restores the cult of icons and achieves military success. The restoration of the icons is also attributed to the Patriarch Methodios, who replaced the deposed John the Grammarian, and three hermits from Mount Olympos in Bithynia, Arsakios, and the already introduced Ioannikios and Isaiah.29 The text characterizes Methodios in these terms: “he conrmed and proclaimed our blameless orthodox faith after demolishing [iconoclasm] in its entirety, using the clearest and most forceful arguments.”30 Lastly, the nal sections of the book dwell on Theodora’s enforced monastic retirement, which began in 856 and lasted until her death.31 The Evergetes typikon then asks for a reading concerning Theophilos. Given the generally dark portrayal of him in the Life of St. Theodora, this can perhaps be understood as a supplement to restore his reputation.32 The text is focused upon what can be described as Theophilos’ return
Markopoulos “< :” 262; Vinson “Life:” 369–70. Markopoulos “< :” 263; Vinson “Life:” 370–71. 28 Markopoulos “< :” 263–64; Vinson “Life:” 371–73; Martha Vinson “The Terms 1 and and the Conversion of Theophilus in the Life of Theodora (BHG 1731),” Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 36 (1995): 89–99. 29 Markopoulos “< :” 265–67; Vinson “Life:” 373–77. 30 Markopoulos “< :” 266; Vinson “Life:” 376. 31 Markopoulos “< :” 267–71; Vinson “Life:” 377–382. 32 Regel, “Analecta:” 19–39. 26 27
10
chapter one
to truth.33 In this regard it can be read as a continuation of one of the themes found in the rst two readings discussed above. The rst part of the narrative follows closely upon the account of Theophilos’ death and the restoration of icons found in the Life of Theodora.34 The story adds Theodora’s requests for forgiveness for her husband.35 Having heard these requests the Patriarch Methodios goes to Hagia Sophia to pray with other orthodox clerics, monks, and laymen.36 That night Theodora had a dream in which she sees Theophilos naked, beaten, and facing judgement before the Chalke Gate of the Great Palace. In her dream, Theodora appeals to the enthroned and awesome judge on behalf of her husband and the judge then forgives Theophilos.37 In the meantime, Methodios, having completed his prayers, inscribed Theophilos’s name in a volume that listed all the iconoclasts and then placed this beneath the altar cloth of the high altar in Hagia Sophia.38 Having done this, Methodios went to bed and there dreamed of an angel. This angel tells Methodios that Theophilos has been forgiven. On hearing this, the Patriarch then hastens to Hagia Sophia where he nds that Theophilos’s name has already been removed from the stillsealed book.39 Thanks to these two visionary interventions Theophilos’ absolution is assured. It is only then that the orthodox are able to celebrate the rst Feast of Orthodoxy.40 These two narratives provide a history of the formation of the feast itself. While they do not enter into precise accounts of the icon and its worship, they offer models of good and bad behavior in regard to images. These show the society surviving heresy and the restoration of due order. The narratives also draw the audience’s attention to the second phase of iconoclasm. Leo III, Constantine V, the Patriarchs Germanos and Tarasios do not feature in the list of those condemned or praised. Rather those that shaped the icon question in the ninth century take the attention. By these means we see the commemoration of iconoclasm become oriented toward its later phase and the denitions that arose then. In this regard, it is notable that the Synaxarion for
33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40
Regel, Regel, Regel, Regel, Regel, Regel, Regel, Regel,
“Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:” “Analecta:”
20. 21–32. 28–30. 31–32. 33–35. 36. 36–37. 37–39.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
11
the Evergetes monastery does not include a celebration of the Seventh Oecumenical Council.41 The monks in the Theotokos Evergetes would then have listened to two theoretical texts regarding icons. The emphasis in both is on the veneration of images. The rst of these has its origin in the rst phase of iconoclasm. This is identied in the Evergetine text as the letter of Gregory Dialogos to Leo the heretic. This can be identied as one of the two letters written by Pope Gregory II (715–31) to the Emperor Leo III (717–41).42 While the authenticity and dates of composition of these letters has been much debated, it is evident from the manuscript tradition that both were available to an eleventh-century audience in the form that they have come down us. The two letters present a lengthy defense of icon veneration. The rst letter begins by expressing Gregory’s surprise at Leo’s critique of holy icons.43 He then touches on some of the themes prevalent in the early defense of icons. First, Gregory rejects Leo’s literal reading of the second commandment’s prohibition of divine images, suggesting that Leo ought to be aware of the tradition of Christian interpretations of this text, which has argued that the commandment was only directed at false idols and not legitimate Christian images.44 Second, Gregory noted that the incarnation had changed our means of knowing God, hence: “Having seen the Lord, as they have said, they painted his form (N81 = O+, !P (8 ' Q6).”45 Third, Christians were not deceived into worshipping matter when they prayed before images, as they did not adore the stones, walls, or boards that conveyed images, rather—following Basil the Great—worship was
41 The Horos of the Seventh Oecumenical Council was, however, to be read in Hagia Sophia on October 11th: Juan Mateos, Le typicon de la Grande Église, Orientalia Christiana Analecta 165 (Rome: Ponticium Institutum Orientalium Studiorum, 1962): 66–67. 42 Jean Gouillard, “Aux origines de l’iconoclasme: le témoignage de Grégoire II?” Travaux et Mémoires 3 (1968): 243–307; H. Grotz, “Beobachtungen zu den zwei Briefen Papst Gregors II. an Kaiser Leo III,” Archivum Historiae Ponticiae 18 (1980): 9–40; H. Grotz, “Weitere Beobachtungen zu den zwei Briefen Papst Gregor II. an Kaiser Leo III.,” Archivum Historiae Ponticiae 24 (1986): 365–75; H. Grotz, “Die früheste römische Stellungsnahme gegen den Bildersturm (Eine These, die es zu beweisen gilt),” Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 20 (1988): 150–61; H. Michels, “Zur Echtheit der Briefe Papst Gregors II. an Kaiser Leon III.,” Zeitschrift für Kirchengeschichte 99 (1988): 376–91; Alexander Alexakis, Codex Parisinus Graecus 1115 and Its Archetype, Dumbarton Oaks Studies 34 (Washington: Dumbarton Oaks, 1996): 108–10, 119–23. 43 Gouillard, “Origines:” 277.3–279.29. 44 Gouillard, “Origines:” 279.30–281.68. 45 Gouillard, “Origines:” 283.69–285.109, esp. 283.91–92.
12
chapter one
addressed to the ones represented there and was conveyed to them by means of homonymy.46 Fourth, images are benecial to mankind as they provoke a love of God when the narratives of Christ’s life continue to be seen in them.47 The letter then recounts the destruction of the icon of Christ Antiphonetes at the Chalkoprateia church, using this instance to underline the bad reputation that Leo had gained by his attacks on images.48 The letter then reports Leo’s threats against the Papacy should they fail to support his policies.49 The second letter reiterates several themes in the rst. Images, for example, are said to edify those that look at them and thence lead them up towards God.50 In addition, Gregory asks Leo to maintain the traditions and the state of the church that he had inherited. This leads Gregory to devote the greater part of his letter to an argument for a strong distinction between the roles of the emperor and the bishops in formulating doctrine.51 The second more theoretical text was a catechetical homily written by Theodore of Stoudios.52 This introduces a few themes that were prevalent in the second phase of the iconoclastic dispute. Theodore begins by addressing the dispersed Stoudite community, exiled because of their resistance to the renewed iconoclasm of the ninth century.53 He then argues that those who do not accept images cannot know Christ.54 A point predicated on the belief that an icon commemorates and afrms the visible aspect of the incarnation. Theodore then condemns those who are willing to accept images, but who refuse to venerate them.55 This appears to have been a compromise position proffered by the iconoclasts in the early years of the second phase of iconoclasm. The letter of the Emperors Michael II and Theophilos to the Emperor Louis the Pious raises this possibility.56 In response, Theodore argues that such iconoclasts deny the logic of representation, which would demand
46
Gouillard, “Origines:” 287.121–37. Gouillard, “Origines:” 289.153–291.166. 48 Gouillard, “Origines:” 293.218–295.235. 49 Gouillard, “Origines:” 295.236–297.275. 50 Gouillard, “Origines:” 301.310–11. 51 Gouillard, “Origines:” 301.316–303.366. 52 Theodore of Stoudios, Parva Catechesis, ed. Emmanuel Auvray (Paris: Victor Lecoffre, 1891): 53–57. 53 Parva Catachesis: 53.1–54.13. 54 Parva Catachesis: 54.13–15. 55 Parva Catachesis: 54.16–22. 56 Mansi 14: 422 for the letter. 47
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
13
that an image receives the worship that is appropriate to the person represented therein.57 Indeed, he adds, images should be considered to be better than relics in dening a relation to the holy: “How much better is it to honor and venerate the icon of Christ, on which, as in a mirror, he is himself manifest and venerable. For it is the nature of the icon itself to convey the one represented according to form (1R K 7 1 ./ 6 36, ’ S, T 1R, 1 @ 1 1 3+ * + $ U6 1 = Q1 ’ F8 ).”58 This last denition, which reminds the audience of the formal relation between an icon and its subject, is a typical expression of an understanding of icons that was claried by the iconophile fathers of the ninth century. Finally, Theodore urges his ock to live a proper monastic life and thence receive their rewards.59 These texts offer authoritative testimony to the main lines of iconophile doctrine. These distinguish an image from an idol while retaining value for the material icon as a means of conveying visual witness to the incarnation. The nature of the relation between an icon and its subject was carefully described. The icon portrayed the formal particularities of its subject, thus establishing a relation that was mediated by a common likeness and a common name. This relational model of representation then necessitated that worship was also to be described as relational. Following the singing of the Trisagion Hymn the monks would nally hear the text of the Synodikon read from the ambo.60 The consistency of this text is suggested by a mid-eleventh century recension that apart from some brief references to the context of its delivery clings closely to the core of the Synodikon as it has come down to us. This is a homily on the Feast of Orthodoxy attributed to Patriarch Michael I Keroularios (1043–1058).61 The composition of the text dates after the death of
57
Parva Catachesis: 55.30–34. Parva Catachesis: 55.39–42. 59 Parva Catachesis: 56.58–57.70. 60 The Synaxarion does not specify this, but this was the normal moment for reading the synodika produced by the church councils that were commemorated in the liturgy: Gouillard, Synodikon: 6–7. 61 PG, 120.724A–736C. Discussion at Gouillard, “Synodikon” 20. Gouillard’s text provides a few improved readings of this earlier edition: lines 1–183, 753–762, and 767–770. Since the publication of Gouillard’s edition a German translation of a Georgian version of the primitive Synodikon text has been published. The Georgian text belongs in a complitation formed in 1028: Michael van Esbroeck and Nural 58
14
chapter one
the Empress Zoe in 1050 and before the death of Constantine IX Monomachos in 1055.62 This witness allows us to glimpse the text prior to the changes that began to be made to it in the second-half of the eleventh and to which we shall return later in this study. What the text betrays is an understanding that Orthodoxy has its origins in the correct interpretation of Christ’s icon. The text of the Synodikon read before the monks of the Evergetes monastery reiterates an understanding of the icon that was formulated at the end of the iconoclastic era. It is not a lengthy statement, running to some 170 lines in the modern edition, but it is rich in the ideas it embraces. The Synodikon immediately marks a link between the material and the spiritual church when it begins by proclaiming a new founding of the church.63 This is expressed by borrowing themes from Gregory of Nazianzos’s homily In novam dominicam.64 This renewal is not limited to the fabric of church buildings, but must also embrace all the activities performed within the church.65 This restoration was necessitated by the thirty-years of iconoclastic rule that had dishonored the cult offered to holy icons.66 This chronology reminds us that the Synodikon was concerned with the second phase of iconoclasm, encompassing the reigns of Leo V (813–20), Michael II (820–29), and Theophilos (829–42). The Synodikon then asserts the equivalence of icons and homilies as means of knowing the Christian understanding of salvation: “the great work of economy is made known by means of both verbal homilies and iconic figurations (8 13 6+ , 3 , 8’ V = W & 3 ).”67 This brief phrase touches on two key issues in discussion in the ninth-century. The rst of these was the relative value of visual and verbal knowledge. The iconoclasts had argued that images were an insufcient means of knowing the divine, as they could only describe external appearances and so could not offer more than a
Karadeniz, “Das Synodikon vom Jahre 843 in georgischer Übersetzung,” Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 19 (1987): 300–313. 62 PG, 120.732D. 63 Gouillard, Synodikon: 45.1–3. 64 For example there are echoes of this homily (PG, 36.608–21) at Gouillard, Synodikon: 45.4–5, 11–19, 47.38, 46–47. 65 Gouillard, Synodikon: 45.7–9. 66 Gouillard, Synodikon: 45.20–47.23. 67 Gouillard, Synodikon: 47.27–28.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
15
supercial knowledge. In response, the iconophiles argued that images were an essential proof of the reality and fullness of the incarnation.68 This then leads to the second issue raised in this phrase, which is the relation between icons and the economy of salvation. Iconoclasts had offered a very spiritual and verbal account of salvation, in which the words of the Gospel narrative were to impress themselves upon the heart of the believer and raise them towards their salvation. Iconophiles argued that such a model ignored the importance of the incarnation as a moment when such salvation became assured. Icons were thereby presented as having particular value as a record of the fact that Christ was incarnate as a particular and individual human and thus served to afrm this new reality.69 Both the verbal and visual knowledge of Christ were also understood to provide ethical assistance to those listening or seeing. As we have just seen, iconoclasts had privileged words as the medium that could best guide Christian behavior. For iconophiles, on the other hand, it was the icon that provided the best model for humans to imitate as they offered a condescension to our corporeal nature and the somatic ground of our knowledge.70 The Synodikon then develops this interest in the icon’s relation to the body by proposing that icons and their subjects both share in the wounds inicted on either. The narrative of the Beirut icon has already prepared such a possibility. It clearly implies a close relation, if not an identity between icon and subject. A point that is further underlined by the claim that the wound suffered by the icons should be deemed a form of second martyrdom.71 The precise nature of this relationship is discussed later in the text. Having made these points, the initial conclusion drawn is that it is thanks to such images that Christ’s sufferings and those of his saints become available to us for us to see.72 By these quick steps the Synodikon is able to make the point that images are a legitimate means of Christian knowledge. They
68
Barber, Figure and Likeness: 61–81. The importance of this point for the ninth-century iconophiles is particularly well articulated by Ken Parry: Kenneth Parry, “Theodore Studites and the Patriarch Nicephoros on Image-Making as a Christian Imperative,” Byzantion 59 (1989): 164–83. 70 Gouillard, Synodikon: 47.30–31. The ethical function of images was much discussed in the period of iconoclasm: Barber, Figure and Likeness: 131–35; Milton Anastos, “The Ethical Theory of Images Formulated by the Iconoclasts in 754 and 815,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 8 (1954): 153–60. 71 Gouillard, Synodikon: 47.32–38. 72 Gouillard, Synodikon: 47.44–47. 69
16
chapter one
are intimately tied to the incarnation and are a necessary and specic means of understanding the continuing implications of this event. The precise grounds for this brief denition are elaborated in a series of blessings and anathemas that address particular topics regarding the denition and cult of images. These are carefully ordered so that the audience can understand the precise steps taken in the unfolding of this doctrine. The text begins by praising those who know that the Logos became incarnate and who profess this by verbal and visual means.73 In offering this praise, the Synodikon draws the discussion immediately to Christ’s incarnate manifestation and the manner in which this can be described in words and images. The rst anathema reiterates this, but emphasizes the particular value of images as witnesses to the incarnation. Hence, it condemns those that claimed to accept verbal witness of the incarnation, while denying visual witness. Those professing this opinion are said to be denying the reality of salvation.74 This point is extended in the second blessing, which praises those who understand fully the Christological implications of this incarnation. These implications are then introduced succinctly. Christ’s human and divine essences are understood to be distinct within his one hypostasis. The presence of these two essences mean that Christ is always dual, being both created and uncreated, visible and invisible, passable and impassable, limited and unlimited. Of these, the uncreated and similar terms apply to his divine nature, while the limited human nature is professed in both word and images (M 8? ! H + D = = + 1R ).75 This returns us to the proper role of the verbal and visual in that we are reminded that they are able to offer a positive account of Christ’s human nature alone. On the other hand, the Synodikon condemns those that overemphasize the uncircumscribability of God in its application to Christ. In the view of the iconophile authors they should be condemned for not admitting the fullness of the incarnation in the esh.76 A third and fourth blessing follow upon this point by offering praise for different but equivalent experiences of word and image. Once again, homilies and icons are treated as interchangeable means of imparting knowledge as there is praise for those who proclaim words in writing or 73 74 75 76
Gouillard, Gouillard, Gouillard, Gouillard,
Synodikon: Synodikon: Synodikon: Synodikon:
49.61–62. 55.138–141. 49.63–67. 55.141–144.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
17
deeds in venerable images and vice-versa, and also for those who preach by means of words and conrm the truth by means of images (# 31 8633 X Q Y 13 , $ %6 , Z 3& 7 [* ' 8$ 1 '3 7 8’ 1 6! ). As can be seen, slightly different operations are given to word and image. Images are equated with the representation of deeds and are also granted the role of afrming the truth of what is imparted by verbal means. This interest in imparting both value and difference to these media was a particularly important aspect of the ninth-century discussions.77 The text then draws attention to the somatic aspect of the delivery and acquisition of such knowledge. It blesses those whose lips are sanctied by holy words and whose words sanctify those listening to them. In a similar manner, those who know and proclaim that icons sanctify the eyes of those who look, elevating the mind to the knowledge of God, should be blessed ( 81 631 T 8$ # # 1 @ \Q ? $ ] # @, 8? 8’ # @ / = ! ). By these means, both the ears and the eyes are granted value as conduits that allow for both the reception of information and for initiating the ascent of the mind towards God. While icons are offered as a primary vehicle for such an ascent, the Synodikon also notes that spiritual knowledge can also be attained through the images found within the divine churches and on the sacred vessels and other holy objects.78 The Synodikon then turns to the relation between the forms of knowledge available in the worlds of the Old and New Testaments. This is introduced when a blessing is offered to those who distinguished between pregurative types for the Virgin Mary, such as the staff of Moses, the tablets of the law, the ark and the menorah and the actual Virgin who was born a woman and chose virginity after the birth of Christ. The reason given for this blessing was that it was better to portray the corporeal Mary than types that were unlike her ( 8$ / K 16 7 & 1 ^ & +
77 Charles Barber, “The Body within the Frame: A Use of Word and Image in Iconoclasm,” Word and Image 9 (1993): 140–53 and then Charles Barber, “Mimesis and Memory in the Narthex Mosaics of the Nea Moni on Chios,” Art History 24 (2001), 323–337. 78 Gouillard, Synodikon: 49.68–75.
18
chapter one
+).79 A distinction is thus drawn between a symbolic and an iconic knowledge. This point is taken further when the text praises those who accept prophetic visions of God as an authentic iconic experience. This had particular value in that it helped to establish the possibility of a visible deity in the usually aniconic religion of the prophets. The iconoclasts were anathematized for having accepted the textual record of such visions, while denying the possibility of iconic depictions of such pre-incarnational iconographies as Ezekiel’s vision that have derived from these accounts of visions. On the one hand, the iconoclasts had argued that the Old Testament visions, which were manifest as images or gures or delineations, were of the invisible essence and so could not be reproduced in the material medium of an icon (’ ^ 7 6 7 _61 1 `! & ! /, ^ 1 ? / 6! + %' ! & Z%1 3! , & 8? !' = a1 $ b? 9 # / !6 % ). On the other hand, the iconophiles felt that such experiences provided a precedent for and continuity with the depiction of the incarnate Christ and his passion, while the iconoclasts denied this possibility.80 As such the Synodikon then offered a condemnation of those that were willing to accept the validity of verbal prophecy, but were unwilling to accept the representation of the incarnation that had been seen.81 This series of statements on the Old Testament show that the play of word and image has remained in question, with the iconoclasts strongly privileging verbal testimony and the iconophiles arguing that visual witness both follows upon and exceeds such verbal grounds.
79
Gouillard, Synodikon: 49.76–51.81. Gouillard, Synodikon: 55.145–150. Theophany was a subject of some interest in the second phase of iconoclasm. For example, Methodios included a lengthy discussion of this topic in his Life of Euthymios: Jean Gouillard, “La vie d’Euthyme de Sardes (d. 831),” Travaux et mémoires 10 (1987): 75.771–98. Notable discussions on this topic include: André Grabar, L’Iconoclasme byzantin: Le Dossier archéologique, revd. ed. (Paris: Flammarion, 1984): 252–69; Jacqueline Lafontaine-Dosogne, “Théophanes—visions auxquelles participent les prophètes dans l’art byzantin après la restauration des images,” Synthronon. Art et archéologie de la n de l’antiquité et du moyen âge (Paris: Bibliothèque des Cahiers Archéologiques, 1968): 135–43; Jean Gouillard, “Art et littérature théologique à Byzance au lendemain de la querelle des images,” Cahiers de Civilisation Médiévale 12 (1969): 1–13; Leslie Brubaker, Vision and Meaning in Ninth-Century Byzantium: Image as Exegesis in the Homilies of Gregory of Nazianzus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999): 281–307. 81 Gouillard, Synodikon: 55.151–158. 80
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting
19
The Synodikon then blessed those who accepted one of the traditional arguments in support of icons. This was the common supposition that a written and an unwritten tradition existed. This assumption allowed the church to develop practices and doctrine that were not self-evidently present in the Biblical text. For iconophiles the icon was a part of this long unwritten tradition. Indeed, much of the Seventh Oecumenical Council had been devoted to this question.82 In contrast, the iconoclasts had argued that the written tradition had specically disallowed the representation and veneration of God and his saints in images.83 The concluding blessing and anathema offer quite different nal notes. The blessing is offered to those who could distinguish between that which had been forbidden by the Law and that which was now possible thanks to Grace. This distinction is presented in primarily visual terms with the Law being associated with invisible knowledge, Grace with the visible. Here, the visible is strongly privileged.84 The nal anathema was laid against those that continued to be iconomachs (or Christomachs) and had thus continued to reject a tradition that reached from the prophets to the present church. These iconomachs are deemed to be beyond the pale, having allied themselves with Jewish and Pagan thought. Furthermore, they are reminded that the harm they do to images is a harm done against the one depicted there.85 This lengthy account of the meaning and performance of the Synodikon of Orthodoxy allows us to reconstruct some of the reiterated stories and concepts that annually prepared this monastic audience for an understanding of the icon. What they heard, until the insertions that began in the second half of the eleventh-century, was a document that was specically rooted in its ninth-century origins, commemorating the thirty years of persecution prior to its rst delivery in 843.86 This underlines the point that when the Patriarch Keroularios delivered his homily on the Feast of Orthodoxy he was not presenting an account of images that was the product of the mid-eleventh century, rather he
82
As recently reiterated in Ambrosios Giakalis, Images of the Divine: The Theology of Icons at the Seventh Ecumenical Council, revd. ed. (Leiden: Brill, 2005): 22–50. A useful discussion of the question concerning written and unwritten tradition can be found at: Kenneth Parry, Depicting the Word: Byzantine Iconophile Thought of the Eighth and Ninth Centuries (Leiden: Brill, 1996): 156–65. 83 Gouillard, Synodikon: 51.82–86. 84 Gouillard, Synodikon: 51.87–97. 85 Gouillard, Synodikon: 55.159–170. 86 Gouillard, Synodikon: 47.40–43.
20
chapter one
presented words and concepts that were probably written by the Patriarch Methodios (843–47).87 In the rst instance, then, the performance of the Synodikon was a reiteration of an understanding of the icons that was written at the end of the iconoclastic era itself. In the course of this study we shall see that this should not lead us to assume that this was an anachronistic event, commemorating ideas from a distant past. The Synodikon not only summarized the fundamental understanding of the icon, but, thanks to the additions that began to be made to the document in the course of the eleventh century, was clearly also a living text engaged with contemporary denitions of correct belief. The Synodikon text has, therefore, maintained the currency of a core understanding of the icon. The text reminds its audience that icons were not idols. Rather, legitimated by Christ’s incarnation, they served as witnesses to and records of the reality of Christ’s historical life. Furthermore, while such images had the potential to become the site for the manifestation of miracles, the material object was not itself deemed to be holy. To avoid any confusion between the material image and its subject the text proposes a relationship, mediated by likeness and homonymy, that both connects and distinguishes the icon and that which it portrays. In a similar manner, the veneration brought to bear on an image was considered to be a relational activity that led from the icon to its subject and did not imply an adoration of the material object itself. The terms used to dene and to describe the icon reiterate a ninth-century understanding. This had been most fully articulated by such theologians as the Patriarch Nikephoros and Theodore of Stoudios. Their signicance is underlined by their being represented together in an image of the iconoclastic council of 815 that dates to 1066 (g. 7). Both theologians had brought the logical categories of Aristotle to bear on the image question. In so doing, they not only denitively altered the discourse on icons but also established a fresh ground for theological practice in Byzantium. The central role of art within this system is perhaps best shown by a canon produced by a church council that met in Constantinople in 869–70. Sometimes called the Eighth Oecumenical Council, this meeting produced some of the last statements on the long running period of iconoclasm.88 One of these was the seventh canon that had declared:
87 88
On the question of authorship see Gouillard, Synodikon: 157–58. Barber, Figure and Likeness: 114–115.
the SYNODIKON OF ORTHODOXY and the ground of painting C= $ \ $ 1 6/ Y 6 88 $ !' ! ! 6 , `61* = 8? / 7 $ # !* +3 % 68 # 3& & & & Y ! ! !cQ , ' 7 R8' 1R 88, % d # 8 6 . 0e f $ / 9 # = J = Q7 \ 1 6 g h 887 Y @/ 8 K, ? 61 , = e8 833 ! 1, 8? i1 , Q!, ! # ! 36 .89
21
Setting up holy and venerable icons and teaching the similar disciplines of divine and human wisdom are very benecial. It is not good if this is done by those who are not worthy. For this reason no one is to paint the holy churches who has been anathematized by what has been decreed, nor to teach in a similar place, until they have turned back from their deceit. Therefore, if anyone after our declaration were to allow these in whatever manner to paint holy icons in the church or to teach, if he is a cleric he will endanger his rank, if he is a layman he will be banished and deprived of the divine mysteries.
Here, painting, theology and philosophy are placed on the same plane and are subject to the same policing. The Synodikon of Orthodoxy helped to dene the precise terms by which the painting of a sacred subject could convey the truth. It presented the icon as an embodiment of human knowledge. As a made thing, detached from its subject, the icon was understood to encompass that which was possible for human understanding. As such knowledge was built upon the visible, a point re-asserted by the condescension of the incarnation itself, and therefore the icon had to become the primary space for the description of human understanding.89 When one looks at an icon, it is the face of the subject that looks back at one (g. 1). It is this body perceived by the viewer’s body that marks the bounds of understanding. Throughout the texts above, we have seen that the icon is closely equated with the body. This not only provides its ground, but also its limits. In this instance, the icon presents a depiction of Christ. This describes the particular human aspects of his incarnate person. These open a relation that links the painting and its subject, but does not admit the confusion of these distinct entities. The icon, as a product of human thought and capacities, is bound to these origins and limited by them as the visible both circumscribes and prescribes the horizon of human knowledge. Further, given the icon’s 89
148.
Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta, ed. P.-P. Ioannou (Freiburg: Herder, 1962):
22
chapter one
centrality to the description of Orthodoxy as well as its manifestation of the human horizon, any conceptualization of the icon that differed from the narrow prescription set forth above could be conceived as a fundamental challenge to traditional belief and thence traditional order. In what follows, we shall see that this narrow denition provoked a desire to exceed its narrow connes, an abyss of excess that overows the painting’s frame and human perception. It is here in this abyss that the disquiet that marks the eleventh-century discourse on art found its point of departure, namely in that which is always masked by the coming-to-be of the visible object.
CHAPTER TWO
SYMEON THE NEW THEOLOGIAN: SEEING BEYOND PAINTING When a blind man gradually recovers his sight and notices the features of a man and bit by bit ascertains what he is, it is not the features that are transformed or altered into the visible. Rather, as the vision of that man’s eyes becomes clearer, it sees the features as they are. It is as though they wholly imprint themselves on his vision and penetrate through it, impressing and engraving themselves, as on a tablet, on the mind and the memory of the soul. You Yourself became visible in the same manner when by the clear light of the Holy Ghost You had completely cleansed my mind. Thence seeing more clearly and distinctly, You seemed to come forth and shine more brightly, and allowed me to see the features of Your shapeless shape. Having said these things You became silent and little by little, O sweet and good Lord, You were hidden from my eyes; whether I became distant from You or You departed from me, I know not. I returned once more wholly into myself and entered into my former dwelling, whence I had thought to have left. When I recalled the beauty of Your glory and of Your words, as I walked about, sat down, ate, drank, and prayed, I wept and lived in an indescribable joy, having known You, the Maker of all things. How could I have failed to rejoice? But I again fell into sorrow and so desiring to see You again, I went off to embrace the spotless icon of the one who bore You and having bowed down before it, You became visible to me within my wretched heart before I could stand up, as if You had transformed it into light, and then I knew that I knowingly have You within me. Therefore from then onwards I loved You, not by recollection of You and that which surrounds You, nor for the memory of such things, but I in very truth believed that I had You, Substantial Love, within me. For You, O God, are love indeed.1
1 ! " #$ , % & ' ' ( ) * + , # - . #. % !, , ! , &/, 0 1 $ % (0 2 # 2 3 4 35 0 0 6 $ 0 2 2 0 2 7 , 8 9 % 6+0, 2 9 . :;$ $ ! , % ! $ 3! ? ! $, ! &- ) , @?9 ! ! $0 3. A) , . . % @39—, B04 3"C 2 3) (9 (D .
24
chapter two
This evocative passage is found in the Second Thanksgiving written by St. Symeon the New Theologian. It offers a rich and quite precise account of this monk’s experience of spiritual vision. The passage’s signicance lies in part in the importance of Symeon, who was the key voice for a new model of monastic spirituality that developed in the late tenth- and early-eleventh century in the monasteries in and around Constantinople. Central to this new spiritual economy was the belief that it was possible for one to experience God while still in this world. Visual metaphors frame this experience, giving rise to a rich analysis of vision, such as can be found in the text quoted above. Yet, given this interest in visual experience, it is notable that one of the most striking features of Symeon’s writings is the very limited place granted to the
E0 , F G H , + , $ I; ! 9 . K9 0?$9 B 9 0. ?9 , ? D D 2 . F L$ K M 3!? 8 0 ! 0 4 0 4 ; + C ) 9 K9 ) M $ , S9 % +? ( U R9 + W $, @?9 4 0 + #$ 9 $ X B), &) 3 A 0$h $ * % 34 , 3N @?9 0U, ! . ( 2 9 g g & /, 8 9 ! K 3300! . . ( @?9 ! ! . &99 9. > N 4 ! 6 $ ` 2 ` + 0 ' K9 + B!, ) 3N . M$ $R ., @?9 3N 4 +0 , K , ! , BN @ BN ! BN - . ! ., 3N
2 9 $D - ) U U 4 W ! + K9 , K S , A 3$ 3 . c. ) 9)F ) $ %3N ( 4 9 $ .
37
he starts to become used to the light, and his original astonishment begins to recede . . . the rst man comes to learn through the sun’s light that he has been conned from birth and lives in a gloomy prison. From that little bit of light, he begins to sense the existence outside of certain wonderful things, but he is unable to reason out or understand what in truth they are. Whenever, though, it happens that he is released from his jail, then he comes to the light together with everything and everyone who dwells within it. Even so, picture with me the one who is now released from the bondage of the body’s needs and, for a while, comes to be altogether outside the world and the wretchedness of visible things. Further, picture this whole world as being in fact a dark and lightless prison, and the light of our sun as like that of a little lamp, while outside there lies the inexpressible and ineffable light of the Sun in Three Persons, the light which transcends word and thought and every created light. The things in the world which are lit by that sun are both invisible and unknowable, ineffable and unsearchable, for everyone who inhabits our prison . . . In seeing heaven both day and night, the soul is taught from it, and every day learns from it that it is without evening, innite, and inexpressible. Returning to this prison again the soul no longer desires the world, but longs to see once more that other place and that which it contains.
38
chapter two
:[0$ C +W 3U, +W $ !D R0 S, % A3) @?9 4 0 ., %3N 2 9 $D !D + —%3 . R0 4 9 ^?0 A3), %3" % ' ?9S $ % ! +—, +? Q, ), ), s $, 0 3$ M) p #S 2 &9D 4 D #!D % B+9 4 . Ka! 0 3$ F o M 7 ' 3 (0 !
?$ , (0 S , &., +3? o ! %39 , t p ]R0 A % R0 X ) ) 4 !0 + 2 % M 33+ " f+ 0 ) ( , ( K B+ K , ( ' ' 4 0
C % U (9 % 4 .32
In this important passage, Symeon both underlines the visual ground of knowledge—it is through sight that the prisoner engages with the world—and undermines the value of the visible. For he portrays the prisoner’s advancement to self-knowledge as an overcoming of the visible world and the discovery of the pure illumination that lies beyond, a “light that transcends word and thought and every created light.” It is an image of heaven that surpasses reason and that provokes, upon the prisoner’s return to this world, a profound longing. The prisoner must then discipline himself to maintain this experience as a new permanent condition of his existence:3233
32 33
Traités: 298.364–302.415; Golitzin, On the Mystical Life, vol. 1: 76–77.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting [8 9 3N + $, 6 0N " #$, 6 $ 4 D , $R F 4 3N 4 S 0$ 9$ 9$,
! ? % " p, V" Y9, &. . 4
33+ F s A + S, %3N + 0 %3N % 2,
$7 3, X, & ! % ?04 .. j- 3, . K +7 3 S ' 3 + \0, K ` K0 + W; [ 6 9 , - 9 !, 4 % 6 + 3 ), f " % / T 0$ V A ( , @?9 4 0 0 + ' + , . ) K ( +0 ,
% 2 F s # % X3 C % u 3$ % 0, s M $ & Q ) . % ! (1 Cor. 2:9), S % 2 ! 3 % 2 ` 9 B" Z 9 $R F % 4 ! 9$R * , " 6 & ! 9 9 3?, ' 9 ! 0 9$, !9 - M Q . M 9$, & 9 M . S9 ) + D 03$h + @ A A. A9.33
33
39
And, when he has thus further persevered so that, little by little, he becomes used to the light and lives as if he had always been within it, then, if I may put it so, that which follows may be reckoned as this: he both sees and knows, is initiated into and taught wonders upon wonders, and mysteries upon mysteries, and visions upon visions. And if he were to want to write them all down, there would not be enough paper nor ink to sufce him. I think that he would lack the time even to tell of these things in any detail. Indeed, how could he in any case write down what cannot be spoken, but which is entirely inexpressible and ineffable? Now, as in the light or—better—as united with it, and as no longer in ecstasy, he instead comes to perceive himself and what is his own. He sees his neighbors as they are in their own right. He knows and predicts that, when he comes to depart this prison and, in particular, after the general resurrection, he will also look upon that unwavering light as it is, and that all the good things within it “which no eye has seen, nor ear heard, nor the heart of man conceived, what God has prepared for those who love Him,” will be revealed to him the more clearly through the same light within him now and by which he is illumined. We shall not be deprived then of knowing or seeing, but, as we have demonstrated above, according to the measure which each has of the radiance and vision of the light, both the knowledge and vision of God, and the recognition and knowledge of one another shall grow ever greater and more clear in joy inexpressible and rejoicing forever and ever.
Traités: 302.424–304.448; Golitzin, On the Mystical Life, vol. 1: 78.
40
chapter two
Conditioned by the possession of divine light, the prisoner has now come to know himself, the things of the world and divine things. Such knowledge cannot be communicated, it can only be possessed. This is understood to be a visual experience, but is not to be confused with the perception of visible things. Needless to say, it has not gone unnoticed that this text bears a remarkable resemblance to Plato’s famous allegory of the cave in the Republic.34 While the extent of Symeon’s direct engagement with Plato’s text is hard to judge, it can be suggested that Symeon’s echo of such a famous passage was an attempt to dene his own account of human knowledge by means of a familiar example. Like Symeon, Plato has placed his men in a subterranean cavern. Plato’s is a more complex space. For example, it is open to the light along its entire width. Unlike Symeon, Plato positions his prisoners within an elaborate staging. These men are only able to look at what is immediately in front of them. There they see the shadows cast by puppets that have been illuminated by a light burning behind the prisoners. They see nothing of themselves or of each other. Hence, Plato concludes that: “in every way such prisoners would deem truth to be nothing else than the shadows of the articial objects.”35 This experience conditions the knowledge that Plato’s prisoners might obtain. Hence, if one of Plato’s prisoners were to be freed from his bonds and was thus able to see the illuminated objects themselves, he would be at a loss as to what it was that he was seeing and would remain dependent upon the prior knowledge obtained from the cast shadows to describe the newly seen object. Given this condition, Plato believed that the prisoner would probably seek to return to the “comfort” of his bonds and the cast shadows. Thus both Plato and Symeon use the cave to describe the conditions of knowledge in this world. For both of them, it is a limited space that needs to be left behind. For Plato, the prisoner must be forced to ascend from the cave before rst looking into the light and thence becoming accustomed to its brilliance. Step by step he could progress from shadows to reections to the
34 Golitzin, On the Mystical Life, vol. 1: 74 n. 5. The secondary literature on Symeon has, however, not explored this signicant echo of Plato’s cave in any depth. My reading of this text and Plato’s have been inuenced by Martin Heidegger, “Plato’s Doctrine of Truth,” in Pathmarks, ed. William McNeill (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998): 155–182. 35 Republic 515b–c.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
41
things themselves. A process of formation, akin to what can be termed an education, achieved this knowledge of things on the earth and in the heavens. Finally, this prisoner would be able to look directly at the sun, the source of the light, and so understand its nature as a manifestation of the Good. In contrast, the light of illumination is made available to Symeon’s cave dweller from the beginning. Thereafter, the prisoner must become acclimatized to this light, adapting to its unchanging nature. For Symeon, this light was that of the Creator. As such it pervaded everything and was prior to and beyond the material light of Plato’s sun. Finally, when Plato follows his prisoner back to the cave, he is left doubting whether his fellow prisoners could understand this man’s mode of seeing, for he had changed, while they had remained in the shadows. While Plato wished that his prisoner could return and guide his fellows, Symeon deemed the experience of the light to be solitary, exclusive and incommunicable. At the heart of both accounts is the formation necessary for the acquisition of truthful knowledge. For Plato such knowledge had its origins in the Good, which was the origin of all things, including reason and truth: And if you assume that the ascent and the contemplation of the things above is the soul’s ascension to the intelligible region, you will not miss my surmise, since that is what you desire to hear. But God knows whether it is true. But, at any rate, my dream as it appears to me is that in the region of the known the last thing to be seen and hardly seen is the idea of good, and that when seen it must needs point us to the conclusion that this is indeed the cause for all things of all that is right and beautiful, giving birth in the visible world to light, and the author of light and itself in the intelligible world being the authentic source of truth and reason, and that anyone who is to act wisely in private or public must have caught sight of this.36
To achieve this vision, Plato’s prisoner must turn from the shadows to light and thence learn to see its object: Then, if this is true, our view of these matters must be this, that education is not in reality what some people proclaim it to be in their professions. What they aver is that they can put true knowledge into a soul that does not possess it, as if they were inserting vision into blind eyes . . . the true analogy for this indwelling power in the soul and the instrument whereby each of us apprehends is that of an eye that could not be converted
36
Republic 517b–c.
42
chapter two to the light from the darkness except by turning the whole body. Even so this organ of knowledge must be turned around from the world of becoming together with the entire soul . . . until the soul is able to endure the contemplation of essence and the brightest region of being. And this, we say, is the good, do we not?37
For both Symeon and Plato, higher knowledge involves a transformation of the prisoner, who must become accustomed to the light that opens the objects of their vision to visibility. The knowledge that derives from this experience is built from two conditions. First, the one looking must adapt and change in order to see. Second, the thing seen makes itself available to sight. This conuence of adaptation and availability privileges the object of vision. It is this that determines the conditions of its being seen and therefore of its being known. For Plato, this is determined by the Good. For Symeon, it is God who delimits the boundaries of the visible. Correct vision, determined by its object, has thus become the means of accessing the truth. Granted these similarities, there are also key differences. For Plato, it was important that the prisoner returns with knowledge of the forms and attempt to disseminate these among his fellow prisoners. Symeon, on the other hand, offers no sense of such a possibility of educating his fellows. Rather, the experience of the light is conceived in very personal and incommunicable terms. It cannot be expressed and in an important sense, cannot be a communal knowledge. Instead, each prisoner must await his or her own personal illumination. The path to this illumination also diverges from that proposed by Plato. For Plato, the prisoner, once released from their chains in the prison, must be forced into becoming accustomed to the light. This is a form of education, whereby the prisoner learns and changes so that he might come to understand this light. While, for Symeon, this turning is brought about by penitence. This is less an acquisition of knowledge and rather more an emptying of the self, such that the penitential act opens the human body of the prisoner, so that it might receive the divine vision and accept the conditions of this unveiling. Once this process has been successful, then all vision and all knowledge are subsequently altered. This difference of preparation inserts a distinctively monastic theme into the narrative of the allegory. Symeon’s concern in all his discourses
37
Republic 518b–d.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
43
is with the preparation of a monk to receive the kind of divine vision that Symeon had himself received. A key aspect of this preparation was the process of penitence: “hurry to cleanse it [the soul] and wash its spiritual eyes and face with hot tears.” The persistance of the penitential path suggests a second cave that might have inuenced Symeon’s Allegory of the Prisoner. One of the formative texts for Symeon the New Theologian was the seventh-century Ladder of Divine Ascent written by John Klimakos.38 This was a key spiritual text in Byzantium and was popular among lay and monastic readers.39 The fth step of the ladder, a chapter entitled On Penitence, offers a visit to another cavernous prison. In graphic detail, John describes the self-inicted torments of those within the cavern. The purpose of this is dened in the following manner: Repentance is the renewal of baptism and is a contract with God for a fresh start in life. Repentance goes shopping for humility and is ever distrustful of bodily comfort. Repentance is critical awareness and a sure watch over oneself. Repentance is the daughter of hope and the refusal to despair. (The penitent stands guilty—but undisgraced.) Repentance is reconciliation with the Lord by the performance of good deeds, which are the opposites of the sins. It is the purication of conscience and the voluntary endurance of afiction. The penitent deals out his own punishment, for repentance is the erce persecution of the stomach and the ogging of the soul into intense awareness.40
It is notable that this is one of the most heavily illuminated sections of an eleventh-century manuscript of the Klimakos text produced in the Stoudios monastery in Constantinople. This visual emphasis underlines the signicence of this penitential theme for the Stoudite community and its conception of proper monastic practice.41 The manuscript in question is Vatican gr. 394 and it can be dated to the later eleventh
38 Symeon read a copy of this work that was held in his parent’s library. He cited it extensively in his writings. 39 Charles Barber, “Icons, Prayer, and Vision in the Eleventh Century,” Byzantine Christianity, ed. Derek Krueger (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2006): 160–163. 40 Climacus, Ladder: 121. 41 Penitence has been helpfully discussed at Irénée Hausherr, Penthos: The Doctrine of Compunction in the Christian East (Kalamazoo: Cistercian Publications, 1982). Stoudite spirituality is introduced at Irénée Hausherr, Saint Théodore Studite: L’homme et l’ascète (d’après ses Catéchèses), Orientalia Christiana Analecta 22 (Rome: Ponticium Institutum Orientalium Studiorum, 1926).
44
chapter two
century.42 Between folios 41v and 48v there are nineteen images of penitents in a monastic prison.43 If we look at the images on folio 42r (g. 9), we can be drawn into the imaginary world of this monastic space. The text on this folio describes two different groups of prisoners: Others raised their eyes to heaven, wept, cried, and implored help from there.44 Others prayed with their hands tied behind their backs, like criminals, their faces blackened with grief and bent earthward, since they thought themselves unworthy to look up to heaven. Overcome by their reections and the weight of conscience, they could not speak, could not pray to God, could not even make a beginning of prayer; and lled, as it seemed, with darkness and empty despair, they could offer God only a blank soul and a wordless mind.45
These texts and their accompanying images offer a spectacle of abasement. The goal offered by Klimakos for these monks was that they should purify the senses through their acts of penitence.46 As such the prison functions as a key monastic site for overcoming our present sensible conditions. Central to this operation is penitence, and central to penitence is the economy of tears. As such, we are returned to the eyes. The centrality of penitence for Symeon’s visual economy is brought forth by the role of tears. We have already been introduced to this in the First Ethical Discourse. There, Symeon asks that his reader cleanse the passions from his heart by washing his eyes and face with hot tears. For Symeon, it is Adam who embodies the play of vision and penitence. The gift of life to Adam was mediated through his eyes (g. 10). Here in this image from the Stoudite Theodore Psalter, completed in 1066, we see God reach down and touch Adam’s eyes. This is the moment of his animation, when the soul enters his material body. Since the eyes were granted such a central place in the Creation, they remained
42 John Rupert Martin, The Illustration of the Heavenly Ladder of John Climacus (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954): 47–87 and 177–81; Kathleen Corrigan, “Constantine’s problems: the making of the Heavenly Ladder of John Climacus, Vat. gr. 394,” Word and Image 12 (1996): 61–93. Note also Henry Maguire’s important discussion of sorrow in Byzantine art: Henry Maguire, “The Depiction of Sorrow in Middle Byzantine Art,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 31 (1977): 123–74. 43 These were to become the basis for the later distinct illustration of the penitential canon: Martin, Illustration: 128–49. 44 Climacus, Ladder: 122. 45 Climacus, Ladder: 122. 46 Climacus, Ladder: 131.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
45
crucial to the imagery of the Fall. The tears that Adam weeps as he sits outside Paradise, seen here on an ivory plaque from Baltimore (g. 11), mark our present condition.47 His weeping marks the loss of the sight of God that had been available to him from the moment of Creation. In Paradise he had been with God and had seen and conversed with God. Outside of Paradise’s gates, God was to become a distant and hidden voice mediated by angels and symbols. The tears shed on leaving the Garden of Eden thus mark this loss. At the same time they also introduce the penitential quality of human existence and the path of return to the sight and presence of the divine. The value of the eyes for this visual economy of salvation is exemplied in Symeon’s Hymn 53.48 The hymn, probably written after 1009, opens with an exchange of looks. The author invites Christ to look upon him. This is necessarily prior to Symeon’s ability to look at Christ:49 +7 6 + 4 7 S F T #4 &- , . ! .49
Shine on me even now as before and illumine my soul, enlighten my eyes to see You, Light of the world.
The reason for this request is given in the following somewhat anxious question:50 L$ !9! 4 ; L$ 9$RW , Q , o % 9 . 4 9;50
Why do You hide Your face? Why do You separate Yourself from me, O my God, who never wish to be separated from those who love You?
Sight thus becomes a means of reassurance, assuring one of a mutual presence. This economy of common yet orderly vision is underlined by this description of the saints:
47 Henry Maguire, “The Panels from Adam and Eve Caskets,” in The Glory of Byzantium: Art and Culture of the Middle Byzantine Era A.D. 843–1261, ed. Helen C. Evans and William D. Wixom (New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art, 1997): 234–36. 48 Symeon the New Theologian, Hymns of Divine Love, trans. George Maloney (Denville: Dimension Books, nd): 267–73; Symeon the New Theologian, Hymnes 41–58, ed. Johannes Koder, Sources Chrétennes 196 (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1973): 212–235. 49 Symeon, Hymns: 267; Symeon, Hymnes: 212.7–10. 50 Symeon, Hymns: 267; Symeon, Hymnes: 214.18–21.
46
chapter two
4 ) % T &. &- B" % . $9 +.51
With them You share and seeing them You are seen by them in turn.
Christ’s51response is to deny that he has separated himself from man.52 Rather, Christ, who was light before all creation is everywhere and in all things.53 The nature of this presence is then examined:54 - ?$F % &- 3N & S0, " &- + 9, 6 M$ !0, 0 % ) +, K0 n " %$. :_ N - ,
) 3N -, % 0 S , p Y, S 9.68
66
If you do not see Him, know that you are blind and, though you are in the midst of the light, you are completely lled with darkness. He shows Himself to those who are worthy of it. They do not see the One who lls everything but they see Him in an invisible manner, as a unique ray of light, and for them He is perceptible, He the imperceptible by essence. It is the ray that we see —He, the sun, blinds instead— and its ray is perceptible for you, as we have said, in an imperceptible manner.
Hymnes II 194.86–196.102; Hymns 115. Here we might note the similar description of vision offered by Plato in the section of the Republic that immediately precedes, and indeed prefaces, the allegory discussed above: Republic VI.18–19 (507C–509B). 68 Hymnes II 202.226–204.239; Hymns 118. 67
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
51
Thus, those that are worthy, are able to see God by means of a ray of light that is both perceptible and imperceptible. This experience is highly individualized and surpasses both the material and intellectual levels of perception:69 [ & 9 @?9 + 9 ! ! @ %3N . + 9 & . * 9F !0 ' L+3 .69
And he who sees Him, outside of everything, is alone with the Alone and he sees nothing of all the visible and intellectual things. It is the Trinity alone that he sees.
Having thus limited and elevated this visual encounter with the Trinity, Symeon then returns to the double nature of human vision:70 c. 3 B+ 3 T @ T , A0 T 4 , 6 3 . M$9 ` 9 3 9 64 9, A0 0 , A , 6 $00 " K9 @W. PA 3N A0 N , 0 %3. 3N
, M' + + 9.70
Know then that you are double and that you possess two eyes, the sensible and the spiritual. Since there are also two suns there is also a double light, sensible and spiritual, and if you see them, you will be the man as you were created in the beginning to be. If you see the sensible sun and not the spiritual sun, you are really half dead.
Here Symeon argues that man has both an intellectual and sensible capacity. If he exercises both as fully as he ought, then he will be like Adam. But if he only sees the sensible sun, then he is limited, almost lifeless. As is clear from these quotations, Symeon deploys oxymoronic language to police a paradoxical knowledge.71 Hence, we nd the following passage in the fourth Ethical Treatise:
69 70 71
Hymns II 216.425–429; Hymns 122. Hymns II 218.448–458; Hymns 123. Fraigneau-Julien, Sens spirituels: 109.
52
chapter two
[ 1 0! &. + 9 % Q K +F +9, S 9 $3 X3 % , ' K ' 0+ + D h 9 + $ 9 .72
Having been made rich with Him, they shall see invisibly the inexpressible beauty of God Himself. They shall hold Him without touching. They shall comprehend incomprehensibly His imageless image, His formless form, His shape without shape which, in sight without seeing and in beauty uncompounded, is ever varied and unchanging.
By these means Symeon continually challenges the limits of human knowledge, bringing attention to that which is beyond the ordinary boundaries of our perceptions. By keeping both the intelligible and the sensible in play, Symeon succeeds in delineating and disrupting the connes of sensible experience. This dualism pervades his discourses. When it is brought to bear on the senses themselves, Symeon argues in the Third Ethical Discourse that the different knowledges mediated by the senses need to be both superceded and brought to some unity by the intellect working within a divine order that organizes them:72 $ Y0 @9 / 7 U !D, A . 3$R ) ) + , N 9 3 . 3 0 3 9 AS9, u 9 0 ' 3$ , % % S, 3’ % M 7 S, 8 9 3N 4 #0 0 U ]U 3$ . ’P 3N ) ) % $ AS9 3) +R , % R0 ) T #T A3) u . ` 9 +, %3N ! A3?, %3N `0 - A #?9 #$F %3N 3) 9 * 0 ' * & 3+, %3N .
72
[Man] possesses a single perception in a unique soul and intellect and reason. While this perception is divided up ve ways according to the physical necessities of the body, it manifests its activity by changing unchangeably, such that it is not sight which sees, but the soul which sees by means of sight, and the same holds true for hearing and smelling, for tasting, and for distinguishing by touch. With regard to spiritual matters, however, the soul is no longer obliged to discern through the windows of the senses. It no longer seeks to open the eyes in order to see or contemplate some existing thing, nor the ears in order to admit discourse. Neither does it require lips or tongue in order to distinguish
Eth. II 68.856–70.861; Mystical Life 2.39.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting - A3 3" % . 4 ) &!. ’; 4 9 ]+ 9 M Y0
0 (0 ! ) 2 2, 6 . % 2 0 9$ 9 $ C, @ AS f U, 6 i * $ , A) . . . [ C & Q U / U 7 U 3" 479 #S , - 4 W 4 3 . . 4 0 AS9 & 2 % 2 &- % U, 4 , $ # %93+R, 70- , 9$R F ) ) , , ( ) . :[ Q 9! X3 ( & Q &. X3 ( &/ & Q!F & 3 ' &. Q % X3 ( &/ % & Q!, 6 %3N &/, A %3N % 0.73
53
sweet from bitter, nor hands in order to know by means of them what is rough, or soft, or smooth. Rather, perception goes outside all of these and is gathered together wholly within the intellect, as being naturally consequent upon the latter and inseparably one with it. To put it more precisely, it possesses the ve senses within itself as one rather than several . . .Therefore, when the one God of all appears in revelation to the one and rational soul, every good thing is revealed to it and appears to it at one and the same time through all is senses. He [God] is both seen and heard, is sweet to the taste and perfume to the sense of smell; He is felt and so made known. He both speaks and is spoken. He knows and is recognized, and is perceived as knowing. For the one who is known by God knows that he is known, and he who sees God knows that God sees him. He who does not see God, however, does not know that God sees him, in that he does not see, though he may see everything else and miss nothing.
Thus while sensible perception is unied by the soul following its mediation by the ve senses, intelligible perception is singular and beyond the sensible domain. Thence, its object, God, unies this spiritual perception.73 It is apparent from the texts discussed above that sight was foremost among the senses for Symeon.74 He builds this point from an understanding that knowledge begins with vision. It is an assumption that embraces both the things in the world and divine matters. Hence: “There is no other way for anyone to know about God unless it is by means of the contemplation of the light which is sent by Him.”75 The reason for this is that:
73
Eth. I 400.153–404.197; Mystical Life 1.122–123. This point is discussed at length in the Fifth Ethical Discourse: Eth. II 96.224–106.354; Mystical Life 2.51–56. 75 Eth. II 98.254–257; Mystical Life 2.52. 74
54
chapter two
. & Q 6 . M % F U 9 h . 0 ( Q!, ' . % , X (, 2 % A3) . ( K9!
Z u .76
God is light and the vision of Him is as light. Thus, in the vision of the light there is knowledge rst of all that God is, just as in the case of a man there is rst hearing about him, then sight of him, and with the sight of him the knowledge that the man about whom one has heard does in fact exist.
For76Symeon such a gift of vision opens divine presence in the world. This light is understood to be unmediated. A point that is underlined when Symeon offered a comparison of the knowledge of God with the knowledge of man. God is only known by the immediate vision of divine light, while in the case of a man vision serves as an afrmation of a knowledge rst introduced by verbal means. This distinction is important, as can be seen when we now turn to the second major account of an icon that can be connected to Symeon. This was not written by the New Theologian, but was given a central place in the Life of Symeon written by Niketas Stethatos. The icon appears toward the end of Niketas’s account of Symeon’s lengthy dispute with Stephen of Nikomedia, which culminated in debate over the proper status of an icon of Symeon’s spiritual father, Symeon the Pious.77 The events that precede this debate begin with the death of Symeon the Pious in 986 or 987.78 Soon after this date, and prompted by divine inspiration, Symeon initiated a cult of this father. This consisted of the normal trappings for the cult of a saint: a feast day marking Symeon the Pious’s death, encomia written in praise of the man, hymns sung in his honor, a biography, and an icon.79 When the popularity of the cult had brought it to the attention of Patriarch Sergios II (1001–1019), he invited Symeon the New Theologian to explain the basis for his devotion. Symeon presented him with his writings on Symeon the Pious. Once these were read and approved, the Patriarch undertook to send candles and incense on the feast day of the holy man. The cult and
76
Eth. II 100.276–279; Mystical Life 2.53. Hausherr, Vie de Syméon: 98–128. This is examined at length in: Barber, “Icon and Portrait” from which this section of the chapter is drawn. 78 For an introduction to the life and writings of this gure see Hilarion Alfeyev, Syméon le Studite, Discours Ascétique, Sources chrétiennes 460 (Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 2001). 79 Vie de Syméon: 98. 77
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
55
all its trappings thereby received Patriarchal sanction at the start of the eleventh century, perhaps in 1001 or 1002.80 In 1003 Stephen of Nikomedia, a synkellos in the Patriarchate of Constantinople whose particular province was to advise the Patriarch on theology and teaching within the church, challenged this new cult before the Holy Synod. Two related issues were discussed at this meeting. First, Sergios II criticized Symeon for having allowed the cult to become excessive. Signicantly, Sergios noted that while the celebration of Symeon the Pious had become popular, the status of the holy man, even granted the existing Patriarchal sanction, remained open to question. Given this, the Patriarch asked Symeon to limit the cult to the precinct of his own monastic community. Stephen of Nikomedia elaborated on this point. He claimed that Symeon the New Theologian had wrongfully proclaimed “a sinner, his spiritual father, a saint among saints.” In response to this double charge, Symeon said little regarding the specic nature of the holiness of Symeon the Pious. As we shall see, silences play signicant roles in the narrative of these events. Symeon focused upon the question of an excessive cult. Using a series of Biblical and Patristic quotations, he argued that the practice of veneration was an important Christian act as the honor directed towards his spiritual father was passed on through him to Christ. Furthermore, Symeon contended that the cult was benecial, as it provided in the person of the saint a model of holiness for those that participated in it.81 Niketas presents this second trial as a victory for Symeon, even though it appears to result in a re-privatization of the cult of this particular saint. Furthermore, while this meeting did not specically address the role of the icon in the cult, the issue of the saint’s holiness was to return as a crucial turning point in the distinction between the icon of a holy man and the portrait of a beloved forebear. At the end of 1008 Stephen of Nikomedia persuaded the Holy Synod to return to this matter. This time, the icon itself was made the central issue in the dispute. Immediately preceding the trial, renegade monks from Symeon’s own community had taken the icon of Symeon the Pious from the church of the monastery of St. Mamas, Symeon the New Theologian’s monastery. They brought it to the patriarchal
80 81
Vie de Syméon: 100. Vie de Syméon: 112–118.
56
chapter two
palace and there subjected it to a remarkable visual test. The icon was compared to images of other saints and of Christ himself. This action implies that, in a very specic manner, they were trying to provide a visual test to dene whether Symeon the Pious could literally be seen to be “a saint among saints.” Unfortunately, the participants in this examination could come to no rm conclusion. One party felt that Symeon could indeed be imagined among these saints, while a second party argued that the icon did not in fact show a saint. This difculty is important for the narrative being constructed by Niketas, as it reiterates the disputability of human knowledge. Since the matter remained unresolved after this act of comparison, the icon was then brought before the permanent patriarchal synod.82 The Life then jumps to Symeon’s defense of the icon and its cult. This is largely a recapitulation of his earlier case, but with the icon inserted as a point of reference. Hence he argued that it was not only important to honor the saints, but also to honor them through their icons. The notion of the “saints-as-models” introduced in the rst trial is similarly given a more precise visual framing when, for example, he notes that he also painted the saint on the walls of his monastery as a “model and archetype of virtuous conduct.”83 Once he has made this more visually oriented case, Symeon then turned to the icon itself and prays before it in these terms: Saint Symeon, thanks to the participation of the Holy Spirit you have come to resemble the icon of my Lord Jesus Christ. Following a long struggle, you are dressed in the brilliant garb of the passionless. You are bathed in your own tears, which in their abundance are like the waters of baptism. You bear Christ within yourself, whom you have loved, and who loved you so very much. You whose holiness, which equals that of the apostles, was revealed to me by a voice from on high, come now to my defense. O wretched me, who is on trial for your sake. Bring me the strength that I need to struggle on behalf of you and your image. Or rather on behalf of Christ, as he has taken upon himself all that is ours except sin, and takes upon himself, being God, all the affronts and mockery that men do to us. Until I also will share in the glory that you have already had in this life; as I witnessed when I was shown you standing at God’s right hand. A glory that you among all the saints deserve even more now.84
82 83 84
Vie de Syméon: 120. Vie de Syméon: 124. Vie de Syméon: 124.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
57
Following this prayer, Symeon falls silent. Without any reported argument and without any resistance, Stephen of Nikomedia then simply walked up to the icon and erased half of the inscription that named the saint. As one would expect in a post-iconoclastic icon, the saint was named on his icon. This would have read: [ ]$ , literally “The Holy Symeon.” Stephen removed the rst part of this, leaving only the personal name, “Symeon.” The portrait was then returned to Symeon the New Theologian. The following day, he was sent into exile, his homilies and hymns on the holy man were banned from public performance, and all other icons of Symeon the Pious were destroyed.85 While this narrative tells us a great deal about the formation of a cult around an icon and the person it presents, it is even more important, in the context of this chapter, for the manner in which it illustrates the fundamental distinction between the thought world represented by Symeon the New Theologian and that of Stephen of Nikomedia. Stephen’s role in this text is to embody the style of theology that Symeon is seeking to overturn. Stephen can be dened as a scholastic theologian. As such he deploys Aristotle’s logic to the analysis of language in order to perfect human description and therefore knowledge of holy things. Symeon rejects this model. Where Stephen offers discourse, Symeon falls silent. In so doing, he discloses one of his fundamental assumptions. Namely, that the knowledge of divine things is ineffable. They might be experienced, should one open oneself to such a participatory experience, but such experience cannot be communicated. Furthermore, Symeon believed that those who attempted to describe and dene divine things could not even begin to do so unless they had rst experienced the mystery of the divine. In the case of this icon of Symeon the Pious we can witness Stephen of Nikomedia applying a traditional conception of the power of language to designate an human understanding. This has been suggested in the text from the Third Ethical Treatise quoted above. But Symeon does not accept language’s power to designate. He is silent because the experience of Symeon the Pious’s holiness cannot be transmitted by graphic means, whether visual or verbal. Niketas’s text reminds us that Symeon the New Theologian made use of icons, even though he rarely discussed them. This use falls into traditional patterns. The icon provides a focus for prayer as well as a
85
Vie de Syméon: 126–128.
58
chapter two
visible model of holiness. Yet, as was seen at the start of this chapter and also in Symeon’s lack of defense for the icon of his spiritual father, Symeon sought something more than was possible from the man-made icon. If we now return to the evidence for the use of icons by Symeon we can understand the terms of this rst encounter a little more. Symeon has looked at the icon in the hope of recovering the original vision of Christ that is now lost to him. While the immediate object of vision is an icon of the Theotokos, Symeon’s actual experience is of Christ alone. This distinction between the visible object and the visual experience once again reinforces the point that what we see is that which is given to us to see rather than that which we choose to see. The point is summarized in this passage from the First Thanksgiving:86 L M- Q +, 3$. ’;9 3N M. , % 6 ! K * $3 & K $3 @ * ' $ K? 9 % 9U M- +R . ’; .; ’P U , ' QF Q 3N % S * , " S D 0+D !D 9 9 ] 3$ —%3N A) *
+ 3 +—, 9 . 3$ 9$R + 9 . $ &- . & ! , + 9 ) 4 $, 6 Y $ $ 9$D, ) & 4 Q ) + ? % 0) ), 6 ' / . 1. ) K . $ 4 ? ! K , S ) " % . ?$9 3 +, S 9U 4 !.86
86
Symeon, Cat. III, 320.196–322.211.
Brothers, these are the wonders of God toward us! When we ascend toward the More Perfect, the shapeless and formless appears to us, but not as previously shapeless or formless, nor does He silently bring forth in us the presence and the coming of his light. But how is this so? In a certain shape, a divine shape nevertheless. God is not in a drawing or a representation, but has taken shape in an incomprehensible and inaccessible and shapeless light—about which we are unable to say or evoke any more. He shows Himself as He is and makes Himself knowable in an altogether conscious manner. The invisible One, lets Himself be seen in full. Invisibly He speaks and listens as friend to friend, face to face. The One who is God by nature converses with the gods born of Him by grace. He loves his sons like a father and is loved by them. He becomes to them a thing strange to see and even more awesome to hear, no longer being able to be expressed by them and not wanting to be buried in silence.
symeon the new theologian: seeing beyond painting
59
Symeon’s writing, while celebrating the possibility of divine vision, contains a profound critique of the limited quality of human vision and knowledge and the iconic culture that is produced in relation to these. Icons, as man-made things, are bound by these limits and so are not able to participate in Symeon’s visual economy of the divine. The writings of Symeon the New Theologian have bequeathed a very rich account of mystical vision. In examining this Christian visual experience, Symeon develops a strong distinction between the human and the divine as they exist in themselves and in each other. Symeon seeks to recover man’s original condition, understood as being a state of being with God. This was known by means of sight. But here Symeon drew a distinction between spiritual and material vision. Both were possessed by man in Eden. However, spiritual vision, the means by which one might see God, was lost at the Fall. Man was left with the limited possibilities of material vision and the visible world. While God might be present in this world, he was not visible there. This condition could only be overcome by divine intervention and was signalled by an experience of formless light. The formless, immaterial, and inexpressible quality of this light removes it from the realm of the visible that can be represented in an icon or conveyed by language. Thus the monk does not look at an icon and thence ascend to that which lies behind it. Rather, he disregards this manufacured object and opens himself to receive a visual experience that lies beyond the visible limits of the given icon. Clearly, then, while Symeon privileges visual experience, his understanding of this must lead him to limit the value of the all-too-human icon.
CHAPTER THREE
MICHAEL PSELLOS: SEEING THROUGH PAINTING Therefore on one occasion he set up her [the Theotokos’s] icon before him and having looked at it earnestly, he spoke to her with the voice of the Archangel saying both parts of the “Hail.” And in this manner he shaped a rhythmic song of praise, so that while he looked at the divine icon (and now trembling and astonishment have seized me) she changed completely into her eshly nature. And then when she rst gazes upon him with her eyes, O awesome countenance and voice and such gracious eyes, she speaks gently, whispering softly through her lips: “Hail you as well, father!” With a calm soul he said: “Hail! For I see you, the cause of joy!” If someone does not believe these things, I might not argue. But, if one might be disposed to accept this [account], one should not stop at this [acceptance]. Rather, [one should] imitate the virtue of the man and yearn for his dispassion, with which, or by means of which, one might achieve these things. For the struggle and exertion better enable one to conquer nature, to rise up above struggles of all kinds until one sees the divine visibles. When this has been achieved, one speaks with the higher things, for then while the mind has contemplated the unchanging, the corporeal eyes have received the manifestations of the divine. There is nothing that spirits embedded in matter are more anxious about than being separated from matter (which is the outcome of these actions). Hence, they that come near and act spitefully to us are clothed in the complete darkness of matter. For as long as we are in the esh we are in the middle of extremes, the material and the intellectual, and are neither purely intellectual nor purely material; for something is contributed to us by each of these. As we are a mixture of the intellectual and the material it is necessary that our actions be in accordance with God. For if we cease to act in this way, then we will not achieve the city of the living God, and shall be cast into the furnace of re. But if we are satised with ignorance, we might see light, but replete with deceptions and trickery. Rather, we ought to be in divine darkness whence the light without dissimulation and the truth shine. For the intellect has revealed that what is in the body is neither wholly natural nor material, for the burdens that are united to this [body] disclose the assaults, like the stalk and the husks and the beard [disclose] the corn. The devil does not remain distant from spiritual vision. For the devil knows that that which is in the material, is that from which he gains his power.1
1
, !
62
chapter three
The above text is taken from an Epitaphios written by the philosopher Michael Psellos for Nicholas, the deceased Abbot of the Monastery of the Beautiful Source on Mount Olympos in Bithynia. The text perhaps dates to 1055, when Psellos endured a brief and unhappy monastic life on Mount Olympos. This Epitaphios is much more than a commemoration of the deceased abbot, as it also serves as a kind of manifesto for Psellos’s belief that philosophy could be brought to bear on Christian theological problems and practices and thence lead to a more intellectually rigorous monasticism. As such, his thought and writings stand in marked contrast to those of Symeon the New Theologian. When Psellos states: “But if we are satised with ignorance, we might see light, but replete with deceptions and trickery” we should understand this to be a reiteration, in opposition to Symeon, of his belief in the value of intellectual preparation for a proper understanding of spiritual experience. The story of Nicholas’s prayer can also allow us to begin to dene how Psellos’s accounts of icons exemplies his wider intellectual project. The story occurs in the part of the text that discusses Nicholas’s rst
" # $% %& ' , () *!!, ) *!!, "+ -, %( , .& " ( ! /( 0& #%( 12 —!!3 ( ( 4 4—(5! & %6 " - 7%!(-
&' " # , 8 % 13( 6(, 9! : ;((, - 6, 3, $ ( ;! !T (%3( E 6 K(- 30 . ?U(- ) ( *& 3 , .! , ( V W ( X( , Y
Y
%D Z & + E - K(- - M E [" K(- 3& E M .! ( . O ) ( , M () 0 [ 3 ( !&, ) !( !3 6(+ \ ; ( , % () (, !!D
6L 5!' !(
' -. ’!!’ R 1 ! 6; x ) " (%- 3( .
J () M %!% x ', T ) ! E 6 ( >! ( P %' 7 Y6 ) N sB /N! = , ( P r $ ! 6 ( ) N. E 0 4 2 2 W !VV ('; Y' $@, 6 B! , !$@ , # @' B', # & 2B, # & B !&, B$, Q !, ( Z(& !2 ( 4 0 s8 & , 9 C /(' @&, 2 @2:! 0 Z(& /(:!$ /(' .46
Yet the icon takes the outline and the shape of the depicted, not the essence. The outline and shape are simply a quality and the fourth kind of quality. Every quality is simply an accident. No accident should be adored. Equally no outline or shape should be adored. What we are talking about when we talk about the icon is perfectly obvious: the artistic and the mimetic. The pre-eternal Divine Logos has assumed into himself at the end of days the additional from the holy virgin and Theotokos, the rst fruit of our mixture. The hypostasis of the Divine Logos has required the adoption of our nature, so that the two natures might be contemplated in the one hypostasis. So, just as the Son of God has maintained his infallible hypostatic particularities, according to which the hypostasis is distinguished from the Father and the Spirit. So, too, did the Son of Man possess other particularities by which he differs from the mother and other men. What are these secondary things, substance or accident? By which I mean, colors, size, perhaps the curve of a nose, or the hair for instance, or the outlines from which he has emerged: the eyebrows, the eyes, and each part that is manifest on his exterior, by means of which when we see them on icons we recognize who each icon is representing.
These are traces of the accidents that manifest this subject. In the case of Christ, these naturally pertain to his humanity and therefore cannot be worthy of adoration. Nonetheless, they do have great value, as they convey Christ’s particularity. As such they afrm that Christ was an individual and not some diffuse embodiment of human nature.46
46
Demetrakopulos, Biblitotheca Ecclesiastica: 154–55.
112
chapter four
This attention to the accidental ground of painting reiterates an account of painting that wishes to distinguish sharply between an icon, a man-made object, and its natural subject. This difference is substantial. While Eustratios identies the availability of the divine through a post-incarnational divinized nature, he is unwilling to allow this presence within the work of art. It becomes necessary, then, for him to distinguish that which is in nature from that which is visible in a painting. A painting remains the trace of the visible, a record of the accidents that describe the particular manifestation of a given subject but that should not be confused with their substance. As Herbert Kessler has shown, we nd echoes of this distinction in a representation of the Spiritual Tablets in an early twelfth-century Klimakos manuscript (g. 18).47 Here, not only have the written tablets of the Law been replaced by the iconic knowledge of the post-incarnational world, but the possibility of the reproduction of Christ’s face is afrmed by the relation between the mandylion and the tile. This form, here reversed in the transfer from the primary cloth to the secondary ceramic, remains distinct from the material that bears it. Neither the cloth nor the tile have become sacred in themselves, even as they become valued as a material medium that allows the form of Christ to become available to us as something visible. Turning to the question of worship, Eustratios argues that one cannot develop a theory of icon adoration that assumes that it is possible to use the image to bring one to the adoration of the divine in the person of Christ. This would be to ignore the material nature of the icon itself. Furthermore, one ought to build an iconic theory from premises drawn from the imagination or memory.48 Returning to the question of worship, Eustratios reminds his audience that any abstraction, such as human nature, cannot be worshipped, as worship is only owed to concrete particulars—those traits that have dened the individual.49 Finally, he reiterates that the Logos cannot be worshipped in the icon as this image can have nothing to do with the divine even when the divinity has become incarnate.50
47 Herbert L. Kessler, Spiritual Seeing: Picturing God’s Invisibility in Medieval Art (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2000): 83. 48 Demetrakopulos, Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica: 155–56 and 158. 49 Demetrakopulos, Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica: 157. 50 Demetrakopulos, Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica: 159.
eustratios of nicaea and the constraints of theology 113 Eustratios’s two texts reiterate the ofcial church position on the icon that had been formulated by the ninth-century fathers, particularly Theodore of Stoudios and Nikephoros of Constantinople.51 This deployed logical categories to clarify the relation between an image and its prototype. In developing this line of thought, Eustratios provides a narrowly focused text that, with great concision, remains within the narrow constraints of the logic of painting. We are left with two signicant points. First, these texts reiterate the point that the icon remains embedded in the terms that dene the proper limits of human knowledge. Second, these essays mark a continuity of thought.52 What Eustratios presents to us is a very strong sense of the continuing power of the logical, ultimately Aristotelian denition of the work of art, whereby painting presents an account of the accidents of appearance, is limited to that which it is humanly possible to see, and allows nothing of the subject’s substance to be present in a given image. By these means, the logic of painting has both distinguished and limited the function of the manufactured object. Eustratios returned to the question of art in his commentaries on Books One and Six of the Nicomachean Ethics. This work was pursued under the patronage of Anna Komnena and perhaps dates to the years after Eustratios’s condemnation in 1117. In his discussion of art here Eustratios pulls themes from the text that continue his earlier discussions of the nature of art. He also adds something of signicance to Aristotle’s text. This addition, an identication of the best wisdom with theology, presents an attempt by Eustratios to remove the icon from the contentious theological position it had occupied throughout the eleventh-century in Byzantium by lessening its status in regard to theology proper. This was a challenge to the role to which the icon had been elevated by the seventh canon of the eighth oecumenical council and by the Synodikon of Orthodoxy itself. Eustratios introduces this addition towards the end of his commentary on the section in the sixth book of the Nicomachean Ethics that concerns Aristotle’s distinction of art from prudence and the respective values 51 The authority of these fathers is underlined by their use in the iconoclastic debate of the eleventh century. They are cited in the now lost dossier compiled against Leo of Chalcedon, which will be discussed in the next chapter. 52 Eustratios also addresses some aspects of art in his commentary on the sixth book of the Nicomachean Ethics: Eustratii et Michaelis et Anonyma in Ethica Nicomachea Commentaria, ed. Gustavus Heylbut, Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 20 (Berlin: George Reimer, 1892): 256–406.
114
chapter four
of doing and making. The particular passage is found in Eustratios’s response to section 1141a9 of Aristotle’s text:53 E0 2 C $B C )(V& 4 $B )2!, . 2 @6 6 ( >( ) ', ! ( ) 6 6 7!&:, )(VC ( 6 4 !!* C 2 ( 4 6 @B F %(!$G !.54
Polykleitos is called a wise sculptor, making accurate imitations in the stones according to what is possible as regards the subject.
In this phrase we can hear a condition introduced by Eustratios when he tells us that the imitation is determined by that which is: “possible as regards the subject.” This recalls the distinction that Eustratios had drawn regarding Christ’s icon. There only the accidental traces of Christ’s humanity were available for depiction. It is a model that suggests that the artist is dependent upon what the subject discloses of itself. Eustratios then expands upon this:55 7 @4 # ! 2 u L, 4 2w ( 0 2 B L k , )& u =( $@ , ( 2 2 k, x ' 2 W ' 2 W B$ W $, 7 6 (C ( y ( ) ((2 , W 6 'G . 0 2 W 6 B'G
53 54 55
Since substance is being proper, the things in and around substance are not beings proper, but each is said to be a kind of being and a kind of being of substance, as the quantity of substance, or the quality of substance or the relation or position, like lying, standing and leaning, or substance being in a place or in time or any
Eustratios, In Ethica Nicomachea Commentaria VI.7 318.27–30. Eustratios, In Ethica Nicomachea Commentaria VI.7 319.19–21.
eustratios of nicaea and the constraints of theology 115 I [ ( @, 5 ( B Z(& , 2 %(!$ 2w ( 0 2 @&: 2 , (2 @(*, z @&: ( o 2w ( 0 2 2 . $ 6 ( 4 0 $B ., o /(2w 5A $B %6 B2 )C . $ !VV (', ( 4 ' u B L, ( 4 ' 2 # ( ’ 6 ' ( )*, # 2 L 0 k @ ( @!$ , I , K u @N( )’ L k, I@ !VV (' ; k ’ 2 W L k [.] 7 $ ( ( 4 & sB 0 6 6 ' , !'G $ F / F, ( > 6 @4, / ( !0 !’ 6 sB 6 . . > @! (0 # N ( ) 7 sB V0 , B ( 2: ( /(2: & 4 %’ !$ ( ) V& '! @$ , D # & /('! ) C ( /(2: 6 B! !$ %’ ( a(, + !6 R !$@ (& . E(0 $, # )& ( )N ! ( @@!$ ( 6 )!4 ( ' )& 4 @4 / 2 ! 2G (2w @(& ? , !$A $! @( (2, ( )’ Q 2w !*!
2: (S @4 ’ [ (&!A R , ) C ) ! ( & 4 C )@@$ 4 ( ' ' : ( k!! ( BC ( ($ 2 , ( 0 )2@
95
On Images An icon is a likeness portraying the prototype, but having some difference from it. The icon is not like the archetype in every way.95 It is called an icon because it is like the other, this is the likeness. The icon is spoken of in ve ways: natural, paradigmatic, gurative, enigmatic, mnemonic (this kind is twofold, logical and aesthetic). 96 The Son is a natural and undeviating image of the invisible God and Father, bearing in himself the whole Father, equal to him in every respect, differing only in being caused, for he is from the Father, without having his being after him.97 Paradigmatic is his will before eternity and thus eternal, portraying and representing everything predetermined by him, that will unfailingly come to pass before it comes to be, just as, if one wants to build a house, the mind gures and represents the outline so as to build the better house, as the great and insightful Dionysios has said.98 Figurative images are of invisible and formless things, that provide in bodily form a dim understanding of what is represented. For through the senses a certain imaginative image is constituted in the front part of the brain, then brought to the middle and the logical faculty, and then is stored in the memory behind. The intellect, tiring of trying to get past all things corporeal, realizes its impotence.99 For this reason wings and faces and eyes and hands and legs are applied
Cf. Bonifatius Kotter, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos III. Contra imaginum calumniatores orationes tres, Patristische Texte und Studien 17 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1975): I.9.3–6. 96 Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: III.18–23. 97 Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.9.6–13. 98 Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.10.2–3, 8–13. 99 Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.11.1–3, 16–21.
eustratios of nicaea and the constraints of theology 125
/(2: ( ’ #2 ( 6 ( )(C ( @ ):N ( B ! ! ( ' ( ( [ ( ( '@ ( ( ’ #!? ( [ : ( B !&, 4 L& 4 2 !& )! #!C ! 2: . 3/@! N $, # 6 !$ 4 !V' :@ 7 # & ( 4 6 ’3' 6 5 V 2! ( # $ 6 9@ >! /(':. ~ 4 !*! $, # 6 g$ !$ 5 2 )' @@' 5 & '@ @@&, 7 6 R 6 6 '! 2 B& 8, ( & L@2 4 V2V @ ($, ( ’ / 2 , 7 0 &! ( 0 &V / ! !' (VF R ; $ 8 ', ( ’ o ' )2 ) 4 /(' ( 4 )4 ) @&! ( V ) !.103
to angels although they differ from the living, and the uncircumscribable nature of God is represented also by the sun, its light and its ray, or in a fountain welling up or the stream owing out, or a rose, its ower and scent, or our mind and reason and spirit, by which we see outlines in living things, through which the divine appearance is dimly manifest to us.100 Enigmas represent the things to come through symbols that depict in accordance with the Apostle the sea as the water of baptism and the Holy Spirit as a cloud.101 In terms of memory, these present something for the benet of those who behold them later. This is twofold: through the written word, as God engraved the Law on stones, and commanded that the books of the saints be written in ancient times, and through sensible contemplation, as when the God of everything ordered the jar and the rod to be placed in the ark as a memorial, consequently we describe and most piously set up the images [showing] the excellent deeds of virtuous men.102
Granted that this is John Italos’s most extensive consideration of icons, it is notably orthodox in the manner in which it re-states John of Damaskos’s hierachical account of the various kinds of images that were available in the Biblical text. Icons are situated within the last category and are thus valued for their mnemonic qualities. Of course, this text does not address the question of worship and adoration that dominated the charges laid against him.100101102103
100
Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.11.25–29. Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.12.2, 5–7. 102 Cf. Kotter, Schriften III: I.13.1–12. 103 Ioannes Italos, Quaestiones Quodlibetales, ed. Perikles Joannou, Studia Patristica et Byzantina 4 (Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag, 1956): 151. Joannou is troubled by the orthodoxy of this text at Perikles Joannou, “Zwei vermisste Traktate aus den 93 Quaestiones quodlibetales des Iohannes Italos,” Studi bizantini e neoellenici 9 (1957): 235. Gouillard, “Religion:” 310 notes the text’s dependence on the writings on images of John of Damaskos: PG, 94.1240C–1244A, 1337C–1344A. 101
126
chapter four
This problem arose in the discussion of John Italos’s Profession. Once again, it appears that John was not using his own words when he formulated his denition of the icon and its worship. In this instance, it appears that he has borrowed from an earlier Profession that had been offered by John’s teacher, the philosopher Michael Psellos. Psellos’s text was probably written in 1054–55.104 Psellos’s Profession has a similar shape to that of Italos. It, too, denes the nature of the Trinity and the incarnation, but in terms that were both clear and clearly orthodox, thus avoiding some of the difculties that Italos’s more convoluted text presents. Furthermore, Psellos’s close dependence on John of Damaskos’s On the Orthodox Faith ensures that his Profession as a whole would not offend orthodox ears.105 The only potentially unusual passage occurs in the very last section, when Psellos turns to the question of images:106 >( ( /(' ( $ Y , F G N! L@2 ! ', C 4 B!& ! C )’ / & F, ( !!$ C C ( C, )’ / 6 ' ) $ 0 R!' .106
I venerate and adore the icon of the incarnate Son of God, the figure of the esh of His holy mother, the shapes in colors of those most beloved to him throughout time, not remaining with their shadows, but transferring the likeness to the prototype.
While the echoes of Basil the Great’s fundamental denition of icon worship, namely that veneration passes from the image to the prototype, are readily identied here, there are difculties in the language that would later come back to haunt John Italos. Although Italos’s discussion of the images is only quoted in part, what we are given makes the dependence apparent. Where Italos writes: “ /(' ( $ Y , C ( C !!$, )P 6 ' 0 !0 ) $,”107 we nd this in Psellos: “ /(' ( $ Y . . . ( !!$ C C
104 Michael Psellus, Theologica, vol. II, ed. Leendert Westerink and John Duffy (Munich and Leipzig: K. G. Saur, 2002): 133–136. An earlier edition and translation can be found at Antonio Garzya, “On Michael Psellus’ Admission of Faith,” Epeteris tes hetaireias byzantinon spoudon 35 (1966–67): 41–46. 105 Garzya, “Admission.” 106 Psellus, Theologica II: 136.72–76. 107 Gouillard, “Procès:” 153.315–16.
eustratios of nicaea and the constraints of theology 127 ( C, )P / 6 ' ) $ 0 R!' .”108 Both, therefore, consider adoration a possibility for the icon and this was a problematic concept. In light of our understanding of Psellos’s interpretation of the icon, it might be possible to suggest that this double sense of worship was intended to accommodate the icon in both its normal state as a work of art and in its possibility as a site of miraculous encounter. In the passage quoted he is at pains both to speak of the esh, colors, and shapes that make one of the Trinity (the Son of God) available for a higher contemplation. Such dualism does not surprise, but it was not strictly orthodox. Eustratios appears to have wished to escape from the ambiguities bequeathed by his teachers. His sustained critique of the possibility for the adoration of an icon, while provoked by Leo of Chalcedon, allowed him to distance himself from the charges leveled against Italos. Furthermore, when his own views on the icons came under scrutiny, he took his analysis further and, following the logic of painting, argued, as we have seen, that the work of art could not be theology. Eustratios was probably provoked into this further turn when, in the summer of 1117, Niketas of Serres, Metropolitan of Herakleia wrote a discourse that demanded the removal of Eustratios from his episcopal see. Niketas represented a new kind of ecclesiastical gure, the product of a reform edict issued by Alexios I in 1107.109 This edict emphasized the role of the clerical elite, rather than the monasteries, in safeguarding order and orthodoxy. Furthermore, the reform marks an attempt to improve the quality of the clergy by re-organizing education in the capital.110 One consequence of this was that the reform regularized the control of the schools by the church.111 Twelve teaching posts
108
Psellus, Theologica II: 136.72–73, 75–76. Paul Gautier, “L’Édit d’Alexis 1er Comnène sur la réforme du clergé,” Revue des études byzantines 31 (1973): 165–201; Paul Magdalino, “The reform edict of 1107,” in Alexios I Komnenos, ed. Margaret Mullett and Dion Smythe (Belfast: BBTT 4.1, 1996): 199–218. 110 For background on eleventh- and twelfth-century education in Constantinople see: Robert Browning, “The Patriarchal School at Constantinople in the Twelfth Century,” Byzantion 32 (1962): 167–202 and 33 (1963): 11–40; Paul Lemerle, “Le Gouvernement des philosophes: notes et remarques sur l’enseignement, les écoles, la culture,” Cinq études sur le XI e siècle byzantin (Paris: Éditions CNRS, 1977): 195–248. 111 Browning, “Enlightenment and Repression:” 16. The sharp divide between church and state implied by this characterization is complicated by the fact that the church has already been the space in which professional education has taken place. 109
128
chapter four
were designated.112 These teachers were to be both virtuous and to be capable of teaching, with their curriculum being tied to the liturgical life of the church. They were to instruct those living in their respective quarters of the city and to reprimand those among the citizens who were leading a less than virtuous life. Furthermore, they were to police itinerant monks and those acting as spiritual fathers.113 By these means a salaried and ecclesiastical elite was organized to oversee the intellectual and moral life of the city. While this reform did not produce an entity that should be deemed a “school,” it nonetheless supported an intellectual elite that was rmly located within the church hierarchy.114 As key rhetoricians and guardians of orthodoxy these teachers became signicant articulators of Byzantine orthodoxy.115 Niketas of Serres had served as one of the theological educators, didaskolos tou evangeliou, and has also left works on grammar, commentaries and catenae on Gregory of Nazianzos, Job, the Psalms, the Gospels, and the Epistles.116 In his work and in his attack on Eustratios Niketas represents a theology built upon the weight of tradition and a narrowly scholastic apparatus. In his critique he argued that Eustratios had not been sufciently punished for an overly philosophical approach to theological problems. To make this point, he chose to link the Demonstration text to Eustratios’s writings addressed to the Armenians, which had been written in 1114.117 The latter offer one of the most precise accounts of the terms in play in Christological discourse.118 Read together, Niketas argued that these texts betrayed a consistent and inappropriate overuse of logic to describe the mystery of Christ’s incarnate being. The most relevant passage from Niketas’s text reads:
112
Magdalino, “Edict:” 206–214. Gautier, “L’Édit:” 193.223–239. 114 Magdalino usefully corrects Browning. 115 Browning, “Patriarchal School (1962):” 168. Browning’s study provides lists the works associated with these teachers. 116 Browning, “Patriarchal School (1963):” 15–17. 117 Demetrakopulos, Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica: 160–98. 118 This judgement is offered in Anthony C. Lloyd, “The Aristotelianism of Eustratios of Nicaea,” Aristoteles Werk und Wirkung, vol. 2, ed. Jürgen Wiesner (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1987): 341–51. 113
eustratios of nicaea and the constraints of theology 129 ; %2(! 0 8!'@ + R ( 2 * , $@ ; e @'! '8A ( )@ W $ ' , 7 R p6 ., , ’ 8 &A )(' @!$ @4 ( 6 4 4 '. ~ @4 F /(' '@G 6 ' !! . )&, )B ! '@ /2 )& . ) '! 6 . (', ( 6 = h6 / 6 ( )&, (06 ( )( , [( , F $ '@ 2w 2 &@ *!! , ( 6 ! $ ( ’ Z 6 %&8 B V' J'@ ( ’ Z 6 ( 2 ( (*, + ( %’ 2 (C &!, ). E A ’ 2 *!! $ ( C '@ x )V& B &!, / 6 )(' '8 !$( V& . J6 1 ( "# K 2 ! $ *( */ "# ?7 , 0; "# ; , "# )" 2 "9 6 2; , 3 7 , *( 3 L *, 3
: "# " M , 2: . O ) *L. O 6 2; ) *L. P5 *( "# ?L ?1 ; , 6 Q 2R 2 *L, )- ?; - " ?! $ S @ "# )1 TL $ / )1 ? / 1" , . ! ) ? , "# 6 *6 2 / 1 . We are dependent upon the
publications of Lauriotes for much of our knowledge of this material. The original manuscript from which he had worked disappeared before the publication of the 1925 Lavra catalogue. Note the comments on Lauriotes’s editorial practice offered at Paul Gautier, “Diatribes de Jean l’Oxite contre Alexis 1er Comnène,” Revue des Études Byzantines 28 (1970): 6, 16–17. 5 A reasonably extensive bibliography exists for this topic. Useful introductory narratives can be found at: Pelopidas Stephanou, “La Doctrine de Léon de Chalcédoine et de ses adversaires sur les images,” Orientalia Christiana Periodica 12 (1946): 177–99; Apostolos Glavinas, He epi Alexiou Komnenou (1081–1118) peri hieron skeuon, keimelion kai agion eikonon eris (1081–1095) (Thessalonike: Centre for Byzantine Studies, 1972); John P. Thomas, Private Religious Foundations in the Byzantine Empire, Dumbarton Oaks Studies 24 (Washington, DC: Dumbarton Oaks, 1987): 192–207; Jeffrey C. Anderson, “The
134
chapter five
In addition to protesting the removal of church property, Leo also asked that the expropriations be investigated by Alexios and that the Patriarch Eustratios Garidas resign for having supported the removal of these materials.6 Leo was soon joined by others, including Basil, Metropolitan of Euchaita and George Palaeologos. In response to this rst letter, Alexios issued a chrysobull on August 5, 1082. This stated that he and his successors would never again expropriate church treasures. Alexios also undertook to repay the churches that had suffered losses when resources allowed.7 In spite of this proclamation, the matter did not go away. Alexios had to address the topic again in the course of the winter of 1083–84.8 Two lingering issues were brought to the forefront at this time: the reparations for damage caused and Leo’s repeated demand that the Patriarch be removed from ofce for having supported these expropriations.9 In early 1084 the Patriarch was exonerated of any wrongdoing. Nonetheless, he was to abdicate in July of the same year.10 In spite of this abdication, Leo continued to pursue the matter through 1084 and 1085. He felt that the Patriarch had not been punished. As a sign of this protest, he refused to celebrate the liturgy in Hagia Sophia until the name of Eustratios Garidas had been removed from the diptychs read in the course of the liturgy. At this point the Emperor’s patience appears to have worn thin and he brought proceedings against Leo in November 1085, accusing him of insubordination.11 Leo was unable to mount a strong case during this trial. He had, after all, opposed legitimate imperial and patriarchal actions. Nonetheless, the proceedings did provide Leo with an opportunity for a very strong reassertion, if not a convincing account, of his rejection Date and Purpose of the Barberini Psalter,” Cahiers Archéologiques 31 (1983): 35–67; Annemarie Weyl Carr, “Leo of Chalcedon and the Icons,” Byzantine East, Latin West: Art-Historical Studies in Honor of Kurt Weitzmann, ed. Doula Mouriki et al. (Princeton: Department of Art and Archaeology, 1995): 579–84. 6 Leo of Chalcedon, Alexion: 403–04. 7 Venance Grumel, “L’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine. Le chrysobulle d’Alexis Ier sur les objets sacrés,” Études Byzantines 2 (1944): 130–33. 8 Alexiade: 6.3. 9 J. Sakkélion, “Décret d’Alexis Comnène portant déposition de Léon, Métropolitain de Chalcédoine,” Bulletin de Correspondance Hellénique 2 (1878): 116. 10 Sakkélion, “Décret:” 116. 11 The account of this phase of the debate is to be found in: Sakkélion, “Décret:” 102–128. Note the discussions of this text at: Venance Grumel, “L’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine. Le décret ou ‘semeioma’ d’Alexis Ier Comnène (1086),” Échos d’Orient 39 (1940): 333–341 and Glavinas, Alexiou Komnenou: 99–132.
the return to the past
135
of any alienation of consecrated property.12 The synod condemned Leo in January 1086. Despite this, Leo refused to be reconciled with the church and continued to espouse his position. In a letter to Anna the Protovestiarios, Alexios I’s mother-in-law, that was written immediately following his condemnation in January 1086, Leo set forth a defense of his position that described icons and their veneration in terms that laid him open to the charge of heresy. He argued that there was a very close relation between an image and its subject, such that when one insults or harms an icon one does this to the person represented therein.13 This need not have necessarily been problematic, but Leo’s expression of this relation was both novel and clumsy.14 With this letter in hand the synod met again in February or March of 1086 and removed Leo from his bishop’s throne. Finally, following Leo’s protest at new expropriations in the summer of 1086, Alexios had the synod banish Leo to Sozopolis in the Crimea. This action brought the rst phase of this dispute to a conclusion. While much of the discussion had focused upon the question of the respective rights of church and state over church property, by 1086 Leo had begun to formulate a novel theological account of the sacred image. The second phase of the affair opened in 1091. Then, John, the Patriarch of Antioch revived the debate over the control of church property when he opposed Alexios’s request for further expropriations.15 He did this in the course of a homily delivered before Alexios I and also in a text that offered advice to the same emperor. John argued that the Empire’s ills could be healed by a number of reforms. John found support for these views in the Patriarchate. The early 1090s also saw many at court seeking the recall from exile of Leo, whose return was permitted once Leo had agreed to renounce his views on the adoration of icons.16 Leo’s restoration became ofcial and the affair came to an end at the synod held at the Blachernae palace in 1094/5.17 12
Thomas, Private Religious: 197. Sakkélion, “Décret,” 123; Leo of Chalcedon, Epistole pros [Marian] ten Protovestiarisan, ed. Alexander Lauriotes, Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900) 404–05. 14 Leo of Chalcedon, [Marian] ten Protovestiarisan: 405. 15 Paul Gautier, “Diatribes de Jean l’Oxite contre Alexis Ier Comnène,” Revue des Études Byzantines 28 (1970): 5–55. 16 Venance Grumel, Les regestes des actes du Patriarcat de Constantinople, vol. 1,3 (Paris: Socii Assumptionistae Chalcedonenses, 1932): no. 967. 17 PG, 127:972–84. The precise date of this synod remains uncertain. Compare: Paul Gautier, “La synode de Blachernes (n 1094). Étude prosopographique,” Revue des Études Byzantines 29 (1971): 213–84 and Glavinas, Alexiou Komnenou: 179–82. 13
136
chapter five
Leo of Chalcedon’s position has justly been seen as part of a wider concern about the proper boundaries of lay and ecclesiastical domains.18 Our concern is less with this broader point and rather more with the specic issue of the nature of iconic representation that Leo developed to justify his defense of church objects. As such, the focus in what follows will be on Leo’s reading of the implications of the depiction of Christ for the proper denition of worship. One of the overriding themes of Leo of Chalcedon’s understanding of the icon was his assertion of a particular kind of presence within the image, one in which little distinction could be drawn between the image and the one represented therein.19 In asserting this position he continually returns to a description of the icon as living or animate (thus playing with the idea of zoographos, painting, or more literally living writing). In contrast to Michael Psellos’s occasional account of such animation in the icon, Leo argued for its inherence there. His focus was the paradigmatic image of Christ, and he argued that Christ’s icons deserved adoration rather than veneration because of what they showed (g. 1). To make this argument, he needed to demonstrate that Christ was formally present in the icon, a participation that was not essential but that nonetheless transformed the value of the object in which the image was inscribed. Leo’s position is outlined most fully in a letter to his nephew, Nicholas of Adrianople. This was perhaps written in 1093 or 1094.20 This letter was written to refute a position proposed by an old ally of Leo, Basil, Metropolitan of Euchaita, who will be discussed below. It was the terms of Leo’s response that led to the council held at the Blachernae on the image question in 1094/95.21 The key point from which Leo builds the argument in his letter was that it was a sacrilege to use matter once impressed with a holy image for any other purpose. To justify this point, he needed to demonstrate
18 Strongly argued in Thomas, Private Religious: 192–207. For responses to this reading see: Rosemary Morris, Monks and laymen in Byzantium 843–1118 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995): 267–95 and Michael Angold, Church and Society in Byzantium under the Comnenoi 1081–1261 (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1995): 46–48. 19 Carr, “Leo of Chalcedon:” 581–82 emphasizes the question of presence. 20 Leo of Chalcedon, Epistole pros ton Nikolaon Adrianoupoleos, ed. Lauriotes, Ekklesiastike Aletheias 20 (1900) 414A–16A, 445A–47A, 455B–456B. Stephanou, “Doctrine:” 178–79 followed by Glavinas, Alexiou Komnenou: 161 and Carr “Leo of Chalcedon:” 580–81 identify this letter as the key source for our understanding of Leo’s interpretation of the icons. 21 The importance of the letter and its widespread dissemination are noted at the very start of the published record of the council: PG, 127:972B.
the return to the past
137
both what an image was and, as a manifestation of this understanding, to describe the kind of worship the image deserved. For Leo, as for most Christian theologians, the word image was rooted in an essential relation between the image and its archetype, a point that builds from the trinitarian notion of the relationship between God the Father and God the Son:22 "# $"% V ? "# , "# E- & W! , "% ** " 2 ! “8 ? $"% & 2 ” "% )" 9 1 X 7 Y , )*( 1Z , )*( 1 T "# ? , 2’ $"% 0 , A *, "# ) 0; )" ? 1; ! , 2[ )Q Q ) R, 2 " * :0 .22
For the Son of God the Father both is and is called an icon, as the great apostle teaches, saying: “Who is the image of the invisible God (Col. 1:15):” an image that is not inanimate, nor cut by hand, nor a work of art or intelligence, but a living image and, indeed, a self-existing life. They remain indistinguishable, not through the forms of likeness, but essentially.
This was a common point of departure for the denition of an image. John of Damaskos had begun his denition of the image from this point in his eighth-century orations in defense of images.23 As we have seen, John Italos had also used this concept of the image in his denition of the icon. Next, Leo pointed out that Adam and his descendents were also an image of God, having been made in the image and likeness of God.24 From this, according to Leo, it follows that an icon was “a portrait inscribed in matter ($"% "# ! / @ ?7! 1";).”25 To make this point he leans on passages from the fourth-century Cappadocians Basil the Great and Gregory Nazianzos to argue that the portrait and its archetype should not be distinguished.26 The text from Basil reads: “One calls the image of the emperor “emperor” without thereby implying that there are two emperors, for one neither splits the power nor divides the glory.” The
22 Leo, Nikolaon: 414B. The reference to Basil is from his Fourth Homily on the Sabellians, Arios, and the Anomians: PG, 31:608A. 23 Bonifatius Kotter, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos III. Contra imaginum calumniatores orationes tres (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1975): 83–84, 126–27. 24 Leo, Nikolaon: 414. 25 Leo, Nikolaon: 414. 26 Leo, Nikolaon: 414; Basil the Great, On the Holy Spirit 18.45 (PG, 32:149C); Gregory Nazianzos, Homily 40: On the Holy Baptism (PG, 36:396C).
138
chapter five
passage from Gregory reads: “Let us take two seal rings, one is gold, the other iron, which bear the same engraved imperial image . . . Let us then impress these in the wax. What difference is there between the two seals? None. Look at the wax and, even if you are very wise, can you tell me which form has been impressed with iron and which with gold. How then have these two become the same? It is because the difference derives from the material and not the portrait.” These passages lead Leo to make two points. First, that only the portrait and not the material can be addressed by the name of the subject. Second, that this formal identity means that there is no difference between the image and the subject as regards their portrait, they are only distinguished in terms of matter: T *( )* *7 \", ] ? "# ^ " 2 < ? # G- "# = ) 1"B .27 What he is attempting to do here is to distinguish the portrait of the given subject from the materials of the icon itself. This portrait shares both the formal and essential qualities of its subject and is therefore in effect identical with that subject. Leo then attempts to resolve potential difculties in the denitions of an image found in canon 82 of the Quinisext Council of 691/692 as well as the synodikon of the seventh oecumenical of 787. To do this Leo argues that we need mentally to distinguish the portrait from the material of the icon when worship is brought to the image. Thus on the one hand the icon-as-object can receive a relative worship because of the relation between the material and the image inscribed in it. On the other hand, the sensible image of Christ himself that is seen in the icon can receive adoration, as this cannot be separated from Christ.28 Here one might think back to Psellos’s use of both adoration and veneration in reference to the worship of icons. It is the presence of the divine in the icon that leads Leo to value the icon as an object and to denounce the destruction of sacred images. To support this point he quotes from a canon on the Mandylion, which was the perfect model for his notion of an identity mediated by the sacred portrait.29 The Mandylion was one of the most signicant relics held in the Great Palace at Constantinople. The Emperor Constantine VII had brought it to the city in 944 and installed it as a 27
Leo, Nikolaon: 414. Leo, Nikolaon: 415. 29 Venance Grumel, “Léon de Chalcédoine et le canon de la Fète du Saint Mandilion,” Analecta Bollandiana 68 (1950): 135–52. 28
the return to the past
139
major object of devotion. The relic was a cloth that Christ had reportedly pressed against his face, thus making an image, and had then sent to Abgar, King of Edessa. Aspects of this narrative can be seen in a tenth-century icon from Sinai where we see the Abgar—in the guise of Constantine VII—receive the Mandylion (g. 19).30 In his letter to Nicholas, Leo used a verse from the canon of the feast of the Mandylion (August 16th) to support his ideas. This can be translated:31 _5 ! ` W# " 6 ) 6 a";, 2 "# 1 B " , 2 ? "7# $"/ < K 1 , b ?7 /. cI - : 1"B 1 B "- C*!L &- "# .31
Being equal in honor to the Father according to the divine essence, O immortal one and maintainer of the creation, inclined by an innite compassion, because you are full of pity, you have appeared to us as well. Those to whom you have presented your divinized eshly portrait offer you an orthodox cult as God and man.
This verse has not survived into modern texts, a fact that Grumel attributes to the presence of the problematic formulation: “a divinized eshly portrait.” This conception is echoed in Leo’s writing and is perhaps what had attracted him to this passage, offering, as it does, some legitimation for his understanding of the iconic portrait being divine.32 Although Leo was insistent that the portrait of Christ was itself divine, he rejected any notion that the material of the icon that conveyed this portrait became divine thanks to the presence of this portrait. In so doing, Leo sought to distance himself from an old ally, Basil of Euchaita, who had proposed this possibility. Basil had raised this profoundly problematic, almost sacramental understanding of the icon in a letter to Isaak Sebastokrator.33 Here, Basil wrote of his own change of opinion regarding the nature of icons. The basis for his change of
30 There has been a recent ourishing of writing around the Mandylion. The essays in The Holy Face and the Paradox of Representation, ed. Herbert L. Kessler and Gerhard Wolf (Bologna: Nuova Alfa Editoriale, 1998) and Mandylion: intorno al Sacro Volto, da Bisanzio a Genova, ed. Gerhard Wolf, et al. (Milan: Skira, 2004) should be consulted. 31 Leo, Nikolaon: 415B. The relevant text has been edited and translated at Grumel, “Léon de Chalcedoine:” 136–37. 32 Grumel, “Léon de Chalcedoine:” 135–36. 33 Basil of Euchaita, Letter to Isaak Sebastokrator, ed. Alexander Lauriotes, Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900): 411B–413A. On his earlier opposition to Leo see Grumel, “Documents Athonites:” 117. Grumel, “Documents Athonites:” 122–23 notes that Leo misrepresents Basil’s ideas.
140
chapter five
heart was to be found in the 68th canon of the Quinisext Council that had met in Constantinople in 691–92. This canon reads: That volumes of the Old and New Testament are not to be destroyed, nor to be cut up for the perfumers. [That] absolutely no one is to be allowed to destroy any volume of the Old or New Testament, or of our holy and approved preachers and teachers, nor to cut it up, nor to give it to so-called perfumers or anyone else who will destroy it, unless it has been completely ruined by worms or dampness or in some other wise. Anyone found doing this henceforth shall be excommunicated for one year. Likewise, if anyone buys such books, unless he keeps them for his own edication or gives them to another as a benefaction and for safekeeping, but rather undertakes to destroy them, he shall be excommunicated.34
Basil interpreted this text to be saying that the fathers of the Quinisext Council had sought to protect the sacred thing, namely the vellum and ink that formed the manuscript, because they believed that the material of these books had been transformed by the sacred texts that they now made present in the physical object. His argument was thus that the sacred content of the text transformed the medium that conveyed that text. Furthermore, he argued that this principle should be extended to include holy icons.35 Given this, Basil argued that all matter has the potential to be iconic:36 K *( $""6 "[ d e , - 6 $"! 7 , "# " , 6 6 *0 - - 21 2[ ?" d e K $"";, 6 2*!7, "# *[ g * 6 * $"! S * *7 .36
No one should call matter iconic because it bears an image of the prototype, and that we worship this believing that the honor passes to the prototype. Rather let us call this [matter] iconic matter even if it has no shape, and through which we might be able to shape such and such an image.
This presents a remarkable re-evaluation for the material aspect of an image, granting it more than a passive and mediatory role. Leo of Chalcedon, however, did not want to be identied with such a
34 The whole canon is quoted at Basil, Isaak: 411B–412A. The translation is from: The Council in Trullo Revisited, ed. George Nedungatt and Michael Featherstone, Kanonika 6 (1995): 150–151. 35 Basil, Isaak: 412A. 36 Basil, Isaak: 412A.
the return to the past
141
re-evaluation of matter. Hence, he declared that he did not worship the iconic material, but only the person represented there.37 In so doing he kept his attention rmly on the relation between the subject and its portrait, rather than between the subject and the icon understood as both form and matter. Leo used a number of sources to support his understanding of the relation between the subject and its icon. For example, he quoted from Theodore of Stoudios’s Third Refutation of the Iconoclasts:38 _h 1 " - i ? . 4 - e "# ) * , S !
- B ) *7.38
Relation is used in regard to the copy in the prototype. And the one is not distinguished from the other because of this, excepting the difference of essence.
This point is then reiterated in an often-quoted borrowing from PseudoDionysios the Areopagite:39 - 2( ? . ! - 21 ? Q $"!, - ?" ? ?"4
- B ) *7.39
The truth in the likeness, the archetype in the image, the one in the other, except for the difference of essence.
Leo used these texts to support his double understanding of the relation between the subject and its icon. On the one hand the essence of the icon, its material being, cannot be a part of the subject it conveys, while on the other hand the portrait seen in the icon does establish a truthful relation between this icon and its subject.40 Having identied a relation between these entities Leo then needed to describe a distinction between the sensible form of the original and its manifestation in the image, as these could not be distinguished by
37
Leo, Nikolaon: 446B. Leo, Nikolaon: 445B; Theodore of Stoudios, Antirrheticus III: PG, 99:424D. The notion of the “copy in the prototype” can be traced to John of Damaskos’s chapter on images in his Expositio Fidei: Bonifatius Kotter, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos II. Expositio Fidei, Patristische Texte und Studien 12 (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1973): 206.8–10. 39 Leo, Nikolaon: 446A; Dionysios the Areopagite, Ecclesiastical Hierarchy 4.3 (PG, 3:473C). Used in iconophile literature: for example, Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to Plato Concerning the Worship of Holy Icons, in Theodori Studitae, Epistulae, vol. 1, ed. Georgios Fatouros (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1991): 164.19–21 and Theodore of Stoudios, Second Refutation of the Iconoclasts 10: PG, 99:357C. 40 Leo, Nikolaon: 446A. 38
142
chapter five
the normal conditions of perception.41 To assist him, Leo used two terms to address the idea of form: - i* (form) and - 1"; (portrait). The rst term denes the form that belongs to the subject, the second expresses the secondary manifestation of this form in a sensible image.42 The more common term for this iconic manifestation was “shape (7).” But Leo resists using this, as he seeks to avoid the usual understanding that shape is the form mediated by the material of the icon. As we have seen, Leo needed to limit the function of this iconic matter. The distinction he draws thereby allows him to argue that one sees the hypostasis, the person, of Christ in the icon and not simply a sensible outline. It is by these means that the Trinity can come into presence.43 Yet the material aspect of the icon was distinct from this formal presence, instead gaining value and the right to veneration because of its role in making Christ available.44 The distinctions that Leo has drawn in his account of representation lead him to dene a double worship for the icon. For Leo, the icon presents the divine portrait of Christ while not actually bearing this image in its iconic material. As such, a need arises for two descriptions of the worship addressed to the icon. On the one hand a relative worship is addressed to the icon itself, while adoration is addressed to the one portrayed there. Hence:45 ( $""6 K " "# 1" " / ) * 6 - - j ! k 1"B 1 *( ? )B : ) 1";, ) *[ l , 2[ \- *[ G - "
" /.45
While the iconic matter is to be worshipped honorably and relatively (this relation is mediated by the divinized portrait of Christ), when we see his portrait in itself, not through something else, but through itself, we venerate in terms of adoration.
This could be understood as an attempt to verbalize the multivalent performance of worship. It invites us to accept that those bringing worship to bear on an icon could both see and worship the Christ in the icon and see and adore Christ himself. But Leo’s articulation of this distinction was not clear. The biggest problem was the lack of
41 42 43 44 45
Leo, Leo, Leo, Leo, Leo,
Nikolaon: Nikolaon: Nikolaon: Nikolaon: Nikolaon:
415A. 445B–446A. 415A, 446B. 446B. 415A.
the return to the past
143
denition regarding the meaning of his key description of the icon as a divinized portrait.46 For Leo, the term was a necessary description, as it maintained language that underlined that Christ was one of the Trinity. Furthermore, he suggested that this understanding not only permitted adoration, but that the adoration addressed to the image would also necessarily embrace God the Father and God the Holy Spirit.47 It is this possibility that ensures the holy status of the icon as a bearer, if not a participant, of the divinized portrait.48 The circulation of this letter to Nicholas provoked a response from the Sebastokrator Isaak, who appears to have played a leading role in the intellectual trials of the 1080s and early 1090s.49 Our understanding of his role revolves around a orilegium, a collection of citations, gathered from earlier iconophile writers. These were used both to refute Leo’s conception of the icon and also to re-assert the authority of the fathers of the iconoclastic era over the question of icons. Unfortunately, the manuscript that contained this orilegium has been lost and so we can only reconstruct a partial account from Lauriotes’ description of the codex published in 1886/1887 and from other more circumstantial evidence.50 The authorities cited include Theodore of Stoudios, the Patriarch Nikephoros, the Patriarch Germanos, and the Seventh Oecumenical Council. Not all of the passages are readily identiable. Nonetheless, from those that can be located and from a signicant related document it is possible to discern how Isaak or the theologians that worked with him shaped a counter argument to that proposed by Leo.51 46
Look at texts at 406B, 415B, and 446A. Leo, Nikolaon: 415A. 48 Carr, “Leo of Chalcedon:” 581 draws attention to this question. 49 For an account of Isaak Sebastokrator see: Basile Skoulatos, Les Personnages byzantins de l’Alexiade: Analyse prosopographique et synthèse (Louvain: Éditions Nauwelaerts, 1980): 124–130. 50 Alexander Lauriotes, “Anagraphe chierographou tes en Athoi hieras Mones Megistes Lauras,” Eklesiastike Aletheia 2 (1886/1887): 168–172. For discussions of this lost manuscript see: Grumel “Documents Athonites:” 123–124 and Stephanou, “Doctrine:” 180, 188–89. 51 The passages in the orilegium are taken from: Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to the monk Severianos (Fatouros 445: 627–29); Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to the spatharios Niketas (Fatouros 476: 685–87); Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to the asecretis Diogenes (Fatouros 491: 725–26); Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to Athanasios (Fatouros 428: 599–600); Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to John the Grammarian (Fatouros 546: 825–27); Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to Platon (Fatouros 57: 164–68); Theodore of Stoudios, unidentiable excerpt from his First Refutation of the Iconoclasts (PG 99.328–52); Nikephoros of Constantinople, unidentiable passage; Nikephoros of Constantinople, unidentiable excerpt from his 47
144
chapter five
Much of the orilegium echoes themes found in Leo’s arguments, but gives greater value to the material aspect of the icon and denies the possibility of an adoration offered to this object. To begin with the material nature of the icon is given great signicance by Germanos’s Letter to John of Synada as well as Theodore of Stoudios’s Letter to John the Grammarian. For both of them this material nature is a key to the visibility of Christ. It is thanks to the iconic matter itself that one can see Christ in the icon.52 The challenge then is to dene the relation between the material nature of the icon and the form mediated therein. One means of tackling this problem is offered by mental worship. Leo of Chalcedon had rejected this, arguing that it diminished the actual value of what was present in the icon.53 The iconophile texts, in contrast, used this notion to deny any presence in the icon. For example, in the Letter to the monk Severianos Theodore of Stoudios argued that worship was not only relative, but also a mental process that directed one beyond the icon to that which it portrayed.54 In his Letter to the spatharios Niketas Theodore rened this point further by distinguishing between the relative worship mediated by the icon and the absolute worship owed the Trinity itself.55 In the Letter to the asecretes Diogenes it was argued that this distinction prevented any confusion between object and subject. Indeed, it underscored the point that the depicted Christ could only be worshipped relatively in the icon.56 This point is then extended in the Letter to Athanasios in which Theodore argued that while worship was directed at the depicted Christ and not the image as a whole, this worship was not the absolute worship reserved for the Trinity, rather it was a relative worship directed at Christ in so far as he is a man visible in the icon.57 The points raised in this letter are very important. Its signicance is underlined by the fact that it was also used in the council of 1095 as an authoritative rejection of Leo of Chalcedon’s views. Finally, the differences between Isaak’s position and
First Discourse against the Iconoclasts; Germanos of Constantinople, Letter to John of Synada (Mansi 13.100B–105B); unidentiable excerpt from the Acts of the Seventh Oecumenical Council; Synodikon of the Seventh Oecumenical Council (Mansi 13.1135C–1154E). 52 Mansi 13.100B–105B and Fatouros 826. 53 Leo, Nikolaon: 415A–416A. 54 Fatouros 627. 55 Fatouros 686. 56 Letter to the asecretis Diogenes: Fatouros 725. 57 Fatouros 599.
the return to the past
145
those of Leo are brought out in the use of Theodore of Stoudios’s Letter to Platon.58 This letter also offers a meditation on Basil’s example of the imperial icon and on the sealed image, as well as Pseudo-Dionysios.59 Where Leo had argued that the identity of form permitted the adoration of Christ in the icon, Theodore wrote that the icon as a whole dened both a distinction and a relation between Christ himself and his depiction. Consequently, for Theodore, the icon could only permit a relative worship:60 . . . ? # *( B "B $"! "#
21 , V B $"! k "# k , " \ ! k , "# ?
" ? , " - )- *B 8 B A \ , ) G/ 7 k "# B $"! . $ *( m " - )- B \ @ "# " )- B 7 7 i 6 " B $"! - ! , )" *7 $"! "# $"0 , 2[ > < \ ! K "# 7 B $"! k "# ) *6 k , "# ? $ G"6 n, A K $ k $"! 1"0 .60
. . . in the case of the imitative picture and its archetype, such as Christ and Christ’s image, granted that the person of Christ is one, then the worship is also one, because it is clear that the identity of the one is hypostatic, and does not have the difference of natures [that exists between] Christ and his icon. If, however, we acknowledge that the worship towards icon and archetype was one, not only because of the identity of person but also of nature, we would be disregarding the difference between the image and the one depicted, and would thus speak of one person and of one nature of the icon of Christ and Christ himself, and falling into pagan polytheism by deifying every kind of material which is fashioned into an icon of Christ.
Theodore then argues against adoration being directed toward the material of the icon by drawing an analogy between an icon and a mirror:61
58
Fatouros 1.164–68. Fatouros 1.165 for Basil. The seal is discussed at 1.167–68. Theodore does not specically cite Gregory Nazianzos, but is clearly indebted to his example. PseudoDionysios is cited at 1.164. 60 Fatouros 1.165:49–66:59. 61 59
146
chapter five
o!L *[ l "2"/ )", ? *6 " , 6 $"! k Q _pR O*. ][ >" 6 $*% *7
" ; ? # " ] , 2[ ) )/ , "# l1 " ! , 2[ )*[ )/ . > M 3 ) B ) B $"! ? # " ( >" "# ! Q " - " >), 2 ? Q $"!
" k , 2"; B $""B K - - " ? )Q k - . : 3 ? # e* B \ k , "1 B K , "l ? )Q A. " *"/ . ? "! 4 * ?" "2"/ E# *7 - ! "# >L s K - . "d *’!L 2 6 G ?"/ $"!, ) 6 K L, 3 *( *[ )6 ! , 2 - ? )Q 2 " ( ) , *[t "#
7 Q Ku. 2 ) ? ! ). "# - e*, < 6 " Q ? ! Ku, m M "# ? # B $""B K , 3 27 ? )Q : , ?7[ v " , > K 2 " , < *( " . :.61
61
Fatouros 1.167:81–101.
Now a man might also say this: “Granted that worship is adoration, it follows that the image of Christ is adored together with the Holy Trinity.” This man would appear not to know the different nature of worship, inasmuch as we worship the saints, but do not adore them, neither do we adore those who rule by God’s dispensation. Furthermore, he should learn that worship is not directed to the essence of the image (for it would be extraordinary to adore the creator by means of the created work), but towards Christ who is revered in His image, while the material of the image remains altogether unrelated to Christ who is revered in it by virtue of likeness: which is the same as the person of Christ, when formed in matter and seen in this. It seems to me that the example of the mirror is appropriate, for in it, too, the spectator’s face is, as it were, represented, but the likeness remains outside the material. It also seems that when one embraces the image of this one, it is not the material that one touches, nor the one himself, rather it is the likeness of the same represented in it, because of which one also the matter. And when he moves away from the mirror, the reection is simultaneously removed since it has nothing in common with the material of the mirror. The same applies to the material of the image: once the likeness that is visible upon it and towards which worship is directed has been obliterated, the material remains without worship inasmuch as it has no connection whatever with the likeness.
the return to the past
147
This prepares the reader to accept Theodore’s use of the Gregorian example of the seal ring. Here Theodore points out that the likeness belongs to the ring itself and not to the materials in which the image is impressed. He then applies this point to the icon:62 K M "# - k , "d ? R Ku "1"; , 2":! ? Q ? w *" Ku, ? Q k \ , g ? "# e*. "# ] $ /, ) $"% k , 2[ ? )Q " k ! , "# " )Q " )- B \ k ,
*( - B ) B $"! *7.62
The same applies to the likeness of Christ irrespective of the materials upon which it is portrayed, it is not a participant in the designated material, but remains in the person of Christ, which is also particular. And to say simply, the icon of Christ is not to be adored, but the Christ in it is to be worshipped, and to be worshipped in it in terms of this very person of Christ, which differs from the essence of the icon.
It is this last section that distinguishes Theodore and Leo. For Theodore the person of Christ is available for veneration rather than adoration in the icon. For Leo, this person deserved adoration. The Leo of Chalcedon affair was brought to an end at a synod held at the Blachernae Palace in Constantinople in 1194/95. There the Emperor Alexios I himself posed a series of carefully prepared questions to the synod. The rst of these was: “Do you say that the icon of our Lord and God and Savior Jesus Christ is to be worshipped relatively or in terms of adoration (1" x " 7 " / ; $"! H " & " B ’5 k ;)?”63 The answer was: “We worship it relatively, as an icon of our Lord and God and Savior Jesus Christ. Those that do not worship in this manner, anathema (1" " );, < $"! H " & "# B ’5 k E * ; z
" , 2).”64 The Emperor then asked: “What do you call images? The iconic materials or the likenesses appearing in these ({$"! ; $"" z x ? 7! :;)?”65 To which the response was: “The likenesses appearing
62 63 64 65
Fatouros 1.167:107–168:113. PG, 127:980D. PG, 127:980D. PG, 127:981A.
148
chapter five
in the materials (O : ? z 7!).”66 Alexios then asked: “Is it possible to worship in terms of adoration the likeness of Christ that is visible in the material (o ! k ! ? zu : " " / ;)?”67 The participants in the synod replied: “No.”68 John of Claudiopolis then asked a question: “Some say that holy icons do not participate in divine grace (O ) 1 1 ] $"! ).”69 To which the emperor and everyone answered: “Anathema to those who say this. For while the holy icons participate in divine grace, they are not of the same nature as the prototypes (| . z4 1 1 E d $"! , 7 / * / )" $ ).”70 Then the emperor asks: “The likeness of Christ inscribed in matter, is this the divine nature (O! ? zu 7! ! k , ! ? 7 ;)?”71 He was answered: “No. The divine nature is uncircumscribable (c)1 7 2 ).”72 A concluding passage from the Synodikon of Orthodoxy was then read.73 After which, Alexios I drew the following conclusion: Christ himself and the other members of the Trinity were owed adoration, while icons could only be offered a relative worship. The two could not be confused.74 The authority cited for this was the letter of Theodore of Stoudios to Athanasios that had been cited in Isaak Sebastokrator’s orilegium.75 This crisp conclusion to the affair is notable for its reiteration of an understanding of the icon formulated in the ninth century. The authorities cited are Theodore of Stoudios and the Synodikon of Orthodoxy. The interpretation given reiterates that the image resides in the likeness seen in the icon and not in the materials of the icon itself. This likeness is worthy of veneration, but cannot be adored, as it has become inscribed in matter. The icon nonetheless has a special status in that while it participates in divine grace it does not have the same nature
66 67 68 69 70 71 72 73 74 75
PG, PG, PG, PG, PG, PG, PG, PG, PG, PG,
127:981A. 127:981A. 127:981A. 127:981A. 127:981A. 127:981B. 127:981B. 127:981C–D. 127:984A. 127:981D–984A.
the return to the past
149
as the prototypes. Rather, this participation is mediated by likeness.76 None of this betrays any addition to the logical understanding of the icon that had been formulated in the ninth century. Indeed, the synod and the preparations that led up to it mark a precise return to and reassertion of this model for the interpretation of the icon. This model was followed in arguably the denitive Komnenian essay on the question of images. This was “authored” by a court theologian, Euthymios Zigabenos, who, at the request of Alexios I, produced a denition of dogmatic theology and a lengthy account of the major heresies that had aficted Orthodoxy.77 The text as a whole can be understood as part of a wider attempt to police the permissible limits of theological discourse in the Komnenian court and church of the early-twelfth century. In particular, it manifested a preference for existing authority rather than enquiries led by the overt use of philosophical categories. The interpretations of this change in intellectual discourse have been several. Robert Browning, for one, has drawn a strong comparison between the ourishing of philosophy in the eleventh century and its repression under the Komnenian regime.78 In particular, he identied the trial of John Italos as a turning point: “I believe that this event more than any other marks the beginning of the emasculation of Byzantine culture so characteristic of the age of the Comneni.”79 Further studies have supported the identication of this moment as marking a signicant change in Byzantium’s intellectual history.80 More nuanced accounts of this climate have emphasized the continuities rather than occasions for change in Byzantine culture and society at this period.81
76
Barber, Figure and Likeness: 107–23. The lengthy panegyric for Alexios I at the start of the text (PG, 130:20–26) as well as references to the work by Anna Komnena (Alexeiade, ed. B. Leib 223–224) indicate that Alexios I had much to do with the commissioning of the work. 78 Robert Browning, “Enlightenment and repression in Byzantium in the eleventh and twelfth centuries,” Past and Present 69 (1975): 3–23; Robert Browning, “Church, State, and Learning in Twelfth Century Byzantium (London: Friends of Dr. Williams’s Library, 1981) 79 Browning, “Enlightenment and Repression:” 15. 80 Paul Lemerle, Cinq études sur le Xie siècle byzantin (Paris: CNRS, 1977): 293–312 and Lowell Clucas, The Trial of John Italos and the Crisis of Intellectual Values in Byzantium in the Eleventh Century, Miscellanea Byzantina Monacensia 26 (Munich: Institut für Byzantinistik, Neugriechische Philologie und Byzantinische Kunstgeschichte der Universität, 1981). 81 Alexander Kazhdan and Ann Wharton Epstein, Change in Byzantine Culture in the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985). 77
150
chapter five
Paul Magdalino, in particular, has questioned the model of repression that Browning proposed.82 In its place he has argued that a more apt description might be to think of this as a persecuting society. It is a conception that invites us to think of this as a society in which one should imagine a contest of ideas in play. By these means, it is possible to avoid a simple binarism of oppressor and oppressed, of the forces of ignorant reaction opposed to the forces of a medieval enlightenment. Rather, a more uid model emerges, in which both parties are considered to be of equal intellectual stature. As such, it becomes possible to argue that the reform led by a newly professionalized clergy should be seen less as a moment of repression than as a broadening of the intellectual terrain engendered by the Komnenian reforms. Even granted this expansive reading, the play of ideas is rarely without questions of power and in the case of Byzantium rarely operates far from the imperial purview.83 In the case of the Panoplia Dogmatica, this is made overt by the effusive dedication to Alexios I Komnenos and, in the case of a Vatican manuscript of this text, an illustration that brings these authorities to the hands of Alexios himself (gs. 20–21).84 Written by ca. 1111, this Panoplia Dogmatica included a chapter on iconoclasm, chapter twenty-two.85 This chapter is in need of a new edition.86 Granted this, it is apparent that Euthymios adhered closely to an earlier work of uncertain pedigree for the core of his essay on the image 82 Paul Magdalino, Manuel I; Paul Magdalino, “Enlightenment and Repression in Twelfth-Century Byzantium, the Evidence of the Canonists,” in Byzantium in the 12th Century: Canon Law, State and Society, ed. Nicolas Oikonomides (Athens: Society of Byzantine and Post Byzantine Studies, 1991): 357–373; Paul Magdalino, “The reform edict of 1107,” in Alexios I Komnenos, ed. Margaret Mullett and Dion Smythe, Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 4.1 (Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1996): 199–218. 83 Here one should bear in mind Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge (New York: Pantheon, 1982). 84 Iohannis Spatharakis, The Portrait in Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts (Leiden: Brill, 1976): 122–29. 85 PG, 130:1164–73. An introduction to Euthymios and the Panoplia can be found at Jacob Wickert, “Die Panoplia dogmatica des Euthymios Zigabenos: Untersuchung ihrer Anlage und ihrer Quellen, ihres Inhaltes und ihrer Bedeutung,” Oriens Christianus 8 (1908): 278–388. 86 For example, the Patrologia Graeca edition contains a lengthy quotation from John of Damaskos’s chapter on icons in the On the Orthodox Faith that is by no means a persistent presence in the manuscript tradition. It is also notable that the fteenth-century manuscript that was the basis for Hergenröther’s edition (Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Palatinus greca 361) is largely devoted to issues that were signicant in the later eleventh century, particularly matters of dispute between the Latin and Greek churches. A more thorough edition of this text and its afterlife in the works of Euthymios Zigabenos and Niketas Choniates will clarify this situation.
the return to the past
151
question. Hergenröther and Thümmel have attributed this earlier work to the Patriarch Photios.87 As such the chapter on iconoclasm is often treated as an historical rather than a contemporary text. Certainly, the passages referenced by this document depend upon earlier sources, but, as we shall see below, its relationship to the contemporary discussion and understanding of icons is more complicated and perhaps indicates a more recent authorship. Direct quotations recur throughout this text (unusually for Zigabenos, he does not provide attributions for these sources). In addition he also paraphrases a number of texts. Once these are disentangled, it becomes clear that this text is a carefully constructed meditation on the icon and its worship that is wholly fabricated from iconophile sources.88 Theodore of Stoudios is the primary source used, with quotes from his First Refutation of the Iconoclasts, as well as his letters to Platon, Athanasios, and Niketas Spatharios.89 There are also quotes from the Seventh Oecumenical Council and Patriarchs Germanos and Nikephoros.90 Of these it is clearly the letter written by Theodore of Stoudios to his uncle Platon that has most inuenced Zigabenos’s account of iconoclasm. We have already noted its importance in the Sebastokrator’s orilegium.
87 Joseph Hergenröther, Monumenta Graeca ad Photium ejusque Historiam Pertinentia (Regensburg: George Joseph Manz, 1869): 53–62; Hans-Georg Thümmel, “Patriarch Photius und die Bilder,” in Eikon und Logos. Festschrift Konrad Onasch, ed. H. Goltz (Wittenberg: Wissenschaftliche Beiträge der Martin-Luther Universität, 1981): 275–289; Hans-Georg Thümmel, “Eine Schrift über das Wesen der Ikone,” Stimme der Orthodoxie 10 (1982): 53–58; Hans-Georg Thümmel, “Eine wenig bekannte Schrift zur Bilderfrage,” in Studien zum 8. und 9. Jahrhundert in Byzanz, ed. Helga Köpstein and Friedhelm Winkelmann (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1983): 153–157. 88 Attempts to identify these sources can be found at: Jacob Wickert, “Die Panoplia dogmatica des Euthymios Zigabenos: Untersuchung ihrer Anlage und ihrer Quellen, ihres Inhaltes und ihrer Bedeutung,” Oriens Christianus 8 (1908): 278–388 and Andreas Papavasileiou, Euthymios-Ioannes Zygadenos: vios, syngraphai (Nicosia: Papavasileiou, 1979): 102–119. Additional references are to be found in Hergenröther and Thümmel. 89 The passage from the First Refutation is PG, 99:341B–C, this is found at PG, 130:1165D; the letter to Platon is quoted and paraphrased at various points in Zigabenos’s text: Fatouros 57.33–35 at PG, 130:1165A; Fatouros 57.93f at PG, 130:1168A, Fatouros 57.98–100 at PG, 130:1168B, Fatouros 57.102–110 at PG, 130:1168B–C, and Fatouros 57.118 at PG, 130:1169C; cf. Fatouros 428.4–11 at PG, 130:1165D–68D; cf. Fatouros 476.31–43 at PG, 130:1168A. 90 Seventh Oecumenical Council: PG, 130:1169B–B6 is based on Mansi 13:225A2; PG, 130:1169B6–C is based on Mansi 13:44D; PG, 130:1169D8–13 is based on Mansi 13:45A. Germanos: PG, 130:1169C5 is based on the letter to John of Synada: PG, 98:160C4. Nikephoros: PG, 130:1164D–1165A quotes Nikephoros’s First Antirrhetikos, PG, 100:277A; PG, 130:1165D–1168A is also from the First Antirrhetikos, PG, 100:277C–D.
152
chapter five
The account of iconoclasm given in the Panoplia Dogmatica opens with a direct quote from Patriarch Nikephoros’s First Antirrhetikos:91 |1 ! ? 216 "# * \7 "- 2 [ ) 1"0 e* , "# B B "! e. {$": ? 21 8 ? G Q ? - i* * B ?7 ? , . *7!4 B ) " 6 @ ! x 21 , "# 2 " , V 1 2 " 21 $* Q ) R *7.91
The archetype is an existing origin and paradigm of a form portrayed after it, the cause from which derives the resemblance. An icon is a likeness of an archetype, having represented in itself by means of likeness the entire form of the one being represented, distinguished only by an essential difference with respect to matter; or an imitation and copy of an archetype, differing in essence, or an artifact completely formed in imitation of an archetype, but differing in essence.
It is a very strong opening, one that immediately and repeatedly proposes an essential difference between the icon and its subject. The point is continued when Zigabenos draws on Theodore of Stoudios’s second Antirrhetikos and his Letter to Platon to elaborate upon the distinction between a natural and a thetic image: {$"% ?". Pp 7 "6 $"% "# "6 ( ) 7 "6 *7 T1 - b, 2’ \ "6, < }E- - - W ( 7 , * *( \ *( ) )1 \ "6 *7 T1 - 21 , 2 7 "6, < $"% k - - k !. D ( \ ! , * *( 7 . Pp 7 \7 , "# k " - 2: , "’ ~ "# 7, "# 21 $"! " . ’{ # ( B "B
An icon is named according to that of which it is a likeness. A natural image is one thing, an imitative icon is another. One has no natural difference from its cause, but an hypostatic one, as the Son [differs] from the Father: for they have one nature, but two hypostaseis. While the other has no hypostatic distinction from the archetype, only a natural one, such as the icon of Christ in terms of Christ: for these have one hypostasis, but two natures. For the iconic material is one thing, while Christ’s humanity, according to which he is circumscribed, is another. And the icon renders the
91 PG, 100:277A quoted at PG, 130:1164D–65A. This is probably the text identied in the descriptions of the manuscript containing the orilegium as being: From the rst discourse of St. Nikephoros against the iconoclasts.
the return to the past $"! " 6 $*, 76 ? # *( B 7 "B " 6 ) , ! ! "# ? # ( B 7 "B , *! 7 }E "# W- , * # "#
" , 2’ ) * " - *7 \ ? # *( B "B , *! \ ! $"! k , "# ) k , "#
" , 2’ ) * " - *7 7 . c) $*j ! ! ? "6 $"%, 2 21 6 \ ! 7, "# " ) $"% ) ? . _} ! *( ) - ] \7 % , 2’ ) $*, "’ d *10 9 *. O- $*j )" $"%, 2’ 21 .92
153
archetype: that which is in the imitative icon accords with form, which is shape or likeness; that which is natural accords with essence, which is divine and the same. In terms of the natural, there is one nature for the Son and the Father, because of this there is one worship for the two of them, and not two because of the difference of the hypostases. In terms of the mimetic, because there is one hypostasis for the icon of Christ and Christ himself, there is also one worship of them, and not two because of the difference of nature. For the mimetic icon is not self-existent, but bears the person from the archetype, and the icon is itself in relation to this. Now we do not call the hypostasis a simple thing, but an essence with particularities, by which it is differentiated from those with the same form. Therefore the self-existent is not an icon, but the archetype.
It is notable that the passage uses the difference between the material of the icon and the material of Christ’s human nature to lead us toward the formal relation, mediated by likeness and manifest in a shape that allows us to see Christ in the icon.92Having arrived at this denition, Zigabenos is able to argue that veneration is mediated by the common appearance of the image and the prototype, and that an icon depicts the person and not the nature of the one represented. This is the form impressed into the image, but not the material itself, which becomes worthy of worship.93 Zigabenos then introduces, by way of Theodore of Stoudios, a relational model to dene more precisely how an icon and its subject are linked:
92 PG, 130:1165A–C. The opening denition perhaps draws on Theodore of Stoudios, Antirrhetikos II: PG, 99:368C. This is then followed by a direct quote from Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to Plato: Fatouros, 57:33–35. The remaining section of the quote paraphrases the Letter to Plato: Fatouros, 57:17–70 until the last few lines, when the writer echoes Nikephoros, Antirrheticus I:16 (PG, 100:225–28). 93 PG, 130:1165C.
154
chapter five
$"% 1 T1 - - 21 , "# $ ? # $!. ’p" M * "# ! i "# . O ! 1 , *( ! ) l ? # G i , "# 2 7 6 1 - . ’p1 $"! 21 "# $"% 21 $":. H# )" 1 $"! 6 - $"! 7. p , "# / 4 .94
The icon has a relation towards the archetype, and derives from this cause. It is also necessary for this to be both toward something and to be called. For being towards something is a relation, the things toward which one is are to be called other, and the relation toward these others is the converse. For the archetype of an image is an archetype; the image of an archetype is an image. Nor can an image, which has no relation to anything, be called an image of something. For both follow upon the other, and manifest the one in the other.
Continuing94this thread, Zigabenos introduces the notion of the icon as a mirror that was found in Theodore of Stoudios’s letter to Platon. This is then reinforced by reference to the discussions of the implications of the imperial image and the seal found in the same source, which are used to illustrate the by now familiar point that the form seen in the image is not to be confused with the material that bears it.95 Having introduced this idea, Zigabenos then denes the visual quality of the icon:96 O E $"! 2 e *’ ) *" ) 21 , "# / \ ;, "# ! - ! .96
What the sacred icons make visible are those visible aspects of their archetypes that become the memory and desire for the prototypes for us.
Zigabenos then returns to one of the primary themes in the debates introduced by Leo of Chalcedon, namely the nature of the worship brought to bear on icons. He states that while the Holy Trinity is to be adored, icons can only be venerated, doing otherwise would be to adore creation or matter.97 Thus: “I worship Christ in it (the icon), who is visible there in a carnal depiction according to his carnal form, whence
94 PG, 130:1165D–68A. This quote paraphrases Theodore of Stoudios, Letter to Athanasios, within a Letter to John the Grammarian: Fatouros, 528:51–54. 95 PG, 130:1168A–C. 96 PG, 130:1168C. 97 PG, 130:1168C–D.
the return to the past
155
the veneration is relative and hypostatic.”98 Hence, it is Christ’s somatic visibility that brings value to an icon. Underscoring the importance of visibility, Zigabenos then contrasts the icon with shadows, and praises the clarity that such icons bring.99 This clarity comes from the forms portrayed and not from the materials of the icon itself. Indeed, should an image be damaged or a cross broken, then it should be thrown away.100 Zigabenos thus reiterates, through the words of his theological forebears, the conception of the icon proposed at the Blachernae Council of 1095. The precise terms of the Zigabenos material betray interests that respond to some of the particular problems raised by Leo of Chalcedon’s letter to Nicholas. There, Leo had argued for a distinction between the portrait and the iconic material that permitted the presence of the divine within the space of the icon and therefore made the adoration of the icon possible. The Zigabenos text addresses the same issues by drawing a distinction between the portrait and the material of the icon. This, however, did not lead to adoration, rather the material presence of the icon itself differentiated the portrait from its subject rather than identied it with it. The possibility of a connection between Zigabenos’s account of the icons and this recent discussion of the topic can be extended when we take note of the choice of texts used in the Zigabenos text and compare these with the records that we have of the orilegium associated with Isaak Sebastokrator that was produced to respond to Leo’s letter to Nicholas. The record of the orilegium that has come down to us describes excerpts from the following texts:101 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to the monk Severianos;102 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to the spatharios Niketas;103 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to the
98
PG, 130:1168D. PG, 130:1169A. 100 PG, 130:1169B. 101 Alexander Lauriotes, “Anagraphe chierographou tes en Athoi hieras Mones Megistes Lauras.” Eklesiastike Aletheia 2 (1886/1887): 168–172; the orilegium was found on folios 42–55 of the now lost manuscript. The list is also to be found in Venance Grumel, “Les documents Athonites concernant l’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine,” in Miscellanea Giovanni Mercati, vol. III Letteratura e Storia Bizantini, Studi e Testi 123 (Vatican City: Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, 1946): 123–124; Pelopidas Stephanou, “La Doctrine de Léon de Chalcédoine et de ses adversaires sur les images,” Orientalia Christiana Periodica 12 (1946): 188–189; Glavinas, 175–176. 102 Fatouros: 445. 103 Fatouros: 476. 99
156
chapter five
asekretis Diogenes;104 the rst Antirrhetikos by Theodore of Stoudios;105 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to Athanasios;106 a passage written by Nikephoros of Constantinople;107 quotes from the Seventh Oecumenical Council held at Nicaea in 787;108 the letter of Patriarch Germanos of Constantinople to Bishop John of Synada;109 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to John the Grammarian;110 the rst Logos against the Iconoclasts by Patriarch Nikephoros of Constantinople;111 a letter of Theodore of Stoudios to his uncle Platon.112 The Panoplia offers direct quotes and paraphrases from: the rst Antirrhetikos of Nikephoros;113 the Antirrhetoikoi of Theodore of Stoudios;114 the letters from Theodore of Stoudios to Platon, Diogenes, Niketas, Severianos, John the Grammarian and Athanasios;115 the letter of Germanos to John of Synada;116 and excerpts from the seventh oecumenical council.117 This proximity is suggestive and probably excludes the possibility that these are entirely independent works. Granted this, some options arise. First, the orilegium and the Zigabenos text might rely on an older common source. Second, that the orilegium provided the raw material for Zigabenos’s composition. Third, that a composition that accompanied the orilegium was copied into Zigabenos’s compilation. While the relationship between this orilegium and the text of Euthymios Zigabenos’s treatment of iconoclasm awaits both a modern edition of the “Photios” essay and the Panoplia Dogmatica as well as the
104
Fatouros: 491. PG, 99:328–352. 106 Fatouros: 428 or 528. 107 Unidentiable. 108 Unidentiable. 109 PG, 98:156–161. 110 Fatouros 586. 111 Unidentiable. 112 Fatouros 57. 113 PG, 130:1164D–1165A = PG, 100:277A; PG, 130:1165BC = cf. PG, 100.225–228; PG, 130:1165D–1168A = PG, 100:277CD; PG, 130:1168CD = PG, 100:584. 114 PG, 130:1165A = PG, 99:368C; PG, 130:1165C = PG, 99:405A; PG, 130:1165D = PG, 99:421A; PG, 130:1165D = PG, 99:341BC; PG, 130:1168D–1169A = PG, 99:433B; PG, 130:1169D = PG, 99:404D. 115 PG, 130:1165AB, 1168A–C, 1169C = Fatouros 57:33–53, 91–110, 118–121; PG, 130:1165C = Fatouros 491:12–17; PG, 130:1168A = Fatouros 476:31–33; PG, 130: 1168CD = Fatouros 445:22–42; PG, 130:1168CD = Fatouros 546 ; PG, 130:1168D = Fatouros 428:4–10. 116 PG, 130:1168C = PG, 98:160C. 117 PG, 130:1168C = Mansi 13:377D; PG, 130:1169B = Mansi 13:225A; PG, 130:1169BC = Mansi 13:44D; PG, 130:1169D = Mansi 13:45A. 105
the return to the past
157
re-discovery of the missing Athonite manuscript containing the Leo of Chalcedon dossier, the striking parallels between these ensembles remain suggestive. Until this editorial work happens, the precise relationship between these bodies of material remains open to debate. Nonetheless, what can be seen is that the two texts suggest that court theologians drew upon the same corpus of iconoclastic texts when they sought to resolve the problem of the implications of worship. It is a model that is narrowly focused upon existing authority. It avoids the existential mysticism that Symeon the New Theologian propounds. It also avoids the overt application of philosophical method found in both Psellos and Eustratios. The Zigabenos text should, therefore, be understood as an exemplary instance of the Komnenian re-assertion of a narrowly dened and traditional theological practice. It is the weight of authority, rather than the essays of Eustratios of Nicaea, that ultimately denes the response to Leo of Chalcedon’s extraordinary attempt to describe a divine presence in the icon.
AFTERWORD Euthymios Zigabenos appears to have brought us full circle. The language that frames the icon in the early years of the twelfth century is the same language that had framed the icon in the ninth century, with the texts of Nikephoros of Constantinople and Theodore of Stoudios overshadowing both eras. But we should be wary of the insistence of this return, just as we should resist the constraints of the grounding offered by the Synodikon of Orthodoxy. For, as the preceding chapters have shown, the icon remained a site of contest throughout the eleventhand early-twelfth centuries. While this iconomachy did not, in the end, overturn the dominant discourse on the icon, it disclosed discontent with the limits of this inheritance. Each of the major authors addressed by this study—Symeon the New Theologian, Michael Psellos, Eustratios of Nicaea, Leo of Chalcedon, and Euthymios Zigabenos—sought to dene the truth in painting. Each examined how the icon framed the visible limits of human knowledge, setting forth a truth bound to human perception and production, which, given its subject, deserved worship. Some of our authors reiterated or extended this horizon of the visible, while others sought to overcome its limitations, opening the iconic space for divine things, and thence asked whether it might not be apt to adore what was seen in an image. Although they each shared an assumption that the icon has its ground in the human, both the body and the mind, each also developed a distinct reading of the implications of the logic of this common ground, as they went on to ask whether the icon was in fact an adequate medium for a knowledge of God. In the case of Symeon the New Theologian the challenge was directly aimed at the existing theological status quo. Symeon argued that theology was impossible. First, because without rst having experienced God one could not speak of divine things and, second, one could not practice theology because this experience of God could not be adequately represented in either words or images. Consequently, while Symeon was not hostile to images and, indeed, deployed them in the cult of his own spiritual father and in prayer, he considered them to be inadequate for true theological understanding. Of necessity, he came to disregard the icon as a true source of the knowledge of divine things. Such knowledge was to be achieved by a different kind of visual
160
afterword
experience, one marked by the divine revealing itself to the deserving recipient of such a vision. Icons could not in themselves convey this experience, as they were the products of human making and thus were necessarily limited by the horizon dened by this origin. Michael Psellos shared this understanding of the origin of painting. For him, painting was a human product, however, this origin was not considered a negative attribute, as painting, as was proper to it, could manifest all that was possible for the human mind to encompass. Nonetheless, Psellos, like Symeon, considered the divine to be other than and beyond this material medium. Unlike Symeon’s insistence upon the extraordinary experience of formless divine light, Psellos was drawn by the extraordinary experience of the divine that could be had through the medium of the icon. Here, the miraculous disclosure of the divine both took on the shape of the material medium and also transformed it momentarily into its divine subject. By these means, Psellos retains a value for the icon in the process of divine perception. In contrast to the desire for an authentic divine experience that guides Symeon the New Theologian and Michael Psellos along their divergent readings of the icon’s possibility, Eustratios of Nicaea remained rmly focused upon describing its limited capacities to their fullest extent. In his hands the icon remained inextricably bound to its human origins. For Eustratios this was appropriate. God was manifestly knowable thanks to the incarnation. The icon was, therefore, the perfect expression of man’s somatic relation to God. Like Symeon the New Theologian, he too believed that the icon was inadequate for the task of theology itself. But unlike Symeon, Eustratios sought to argue for a human knowledge that was higher than the iconic and so distinguished the work of art from the intellectual work of either theology or philosophy. In this way, he hoped to remove the icon from its central role in the denition and description of Orthodoxy. Unlike these other thinkers, Leo of Chalcedon had attempted to account for a permanent presence for the divine in the icon. Sharing the basic distinction between the material and the spiritual, he did not argue that the icon as a whole was an holy object. Rather, he argued that the image conveyed by, but not to be confused with, the material of the icon could be considered divine and thence receive adoration. In this way, like Symeon and Psellos, he had sought to satisfy the desire for the divine in human experience. Against this, the responses found in Isaak Sebastokrator’s orilegium and in Euthymios Zigabenos’s Panoplia reveal a strong re-assertion by court theologians of the iconophile argument that such an experience was not to be had in the icon itself.
afterword
161
In their different ways, these thinkers offer us a lively and varied account of the icon, confronting, opening, and exploring the implications of the fundamental understanding of this object that had been bequeathed by the iconoclastic era. These varied attempts to describe the conditions of Christian sacred art in eleventh-century Byzantium not only open the potential variety of Byzantine thinking on the icon to us, but they also pose a challenge to our own art-historical assumptions regarding the painted image. While I have primarily presented these studies in terms of the narrow context of Byzantine intellectual history, I believe that some of the lines of enquiry found in these writings can be brought to bear upon our present practice as art historians. Here, one might begin by considering the problematic fate of the icon within modernist discourse. In the hands of Giorgio Vasari, the icon functioned as a foil for his account of the re-emergence of a naturalistic paradigm, an instance of repetitive copying from one image to another image rather than the creative product of an attentive and observant artist.1 On a more positive note we can nd Roger Fry co-opting Byzantine art as he sought to dene what has come to be termed Neo-Impressionism in opposition to the Vasarian paradigm.2 Needless to say, neither use of the icon does justice to the evident dualism of the icon’s surface, where likeness and unlikeness, visibility
1
GiorgioVasari, Vite de’ più eccellenti architetti, pittori e scultori italiani: nel readaioni del 1550 e 1568, ed. Rosanna Bettarini (Firenze: Sansoni, 1966): 37.26–30: “la qual maniera scabrosa e goffa et ordinaria avevano non mediante lo studio, ma per una cotal usanza insegnato l’uno all’altro per molti e molti anni I pittori di que’ tempi, senza pensar mai a migliorare il disegno a belleza di colorito o invenzione alcuna che buona fusse (Giorgio Vasari, The Lives of the Artists: A Selection, trans. George Bull (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1965): 50–51: To be sure, their crude, stiff, and mediocre style owed nothing to study, but came from blindly following what had been handed on year after year by painters who never thought of trying to improve their drawing and never sought after lovely colours or any creditable inventions);” and: 97.4–9: “Là dove venuto, in poco tempo, aiutato dalla natura et ammaestrato da Cimabue, non solo pareggiò il fanciullo la maniera del maestro suo, ma divenne così buono imitatore della natura che sbandì afatto quella goffa maniera greca, e risuscitò la moderna e buona arte della pittura, introducendo il ritrarre bene di naturale le persone vive, il che più di dugento anni non s’era usato (Bull: 58: After he had gone to live there, helped by his natural talent and instructed by Cimabue, in a very short space of time Giotto not only captured his master’s own style but also began to draw so ably from life that he made a decisive break with the crude traditional Byzantine style and brought to life the great art of painting as we know it today, introducing the technique of drawing accurately from life, which had been neglected for more than two hundred years).” 2 For discussion see: J. B. Bullen, “Byzantinism and Modernism 1900–14,” The Burlington Magazine 141 (1999): 665–75. Note these essays by Roger Fry: “Post-Impressionism,” and “The Post-Impressionists,” in A Roger Fry Reader, ed. Christopher Reed (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1996): 99–110 and 81–85.
162
afterword
and invisibility play off each other and work against the unity of the painted surface.3 While our art-historical practice remains bound by the modernist representational values that have privileged rst the artist’s perception recorded on the painting and then the viewer’s recognition of what is seen there, we will be unable to incorporate the elusive aspects of the icon into a History of European Art that assumes representation to be its fundamental ground. This ground has given rise to the expectation that the work of art is intended to provide an adequate rendering of the visible world in the visual language that is common to a given space and moment in time. As such it embodies an historically-situated horizon of human understanding. Importantly, our eleventh-century thinkers have challenged us to consider whether this model of adequation is sufcient for a true knowledge of the subject depicted therein and thereby have drawn our attention to the historical conditions that dene representation. In effect they invite us to consider whether it might be possible or desirable for the work of art to break this hermeneutic circle of human production and perception and thus expand our understanding of painting’s potential. To do this, we need to turn from the traditional grounds of arthistorical enquiry, the hand of the artist or the eye of the viewer, and enquire further into the possibility that the icon manifests an experience that lies beyond both its manufacture and the occasions when it was viewed. This entails that we consider the nature of the relationship between the subject and the icon that depicts that subject. For our authors, the question became focused upon the conditions that permit the subject to disclose itself in painting. For Symeon the New Theologian the distinction between matter and spirit rendered this impossible. Similarly, Eustratios of Nicaea also believed that the icon, while an adequate account of Christ’s humanity, was an inadequate medium for the description of Christ’s divine being. In contrast, Leo of Chalcedon attempted to place the divine nature in the icon without identifying it with the material of the icon itself. For Michael Psellos, the subject became present as and when it chose to emerge through the human framing provided by the material image. None of these models overcame the prevailing narrow understanding of the icon’s adequate
3
See Barber, Figure and Likeness: 120–21.
afterword
163
rendering of Christ. Nonetheless they opened a signicant broadening of the icon’s possibility. By drawing attention to that which lies beyond human representation, these thinkers sought to overcome the limits of knowledge embodied in the work of art. It was an attempt to bring that which was fundamental to but outside the icon, its subject, into human experience. Yet the only means by which this could be expressed and the circle broken was by means of miraculous intervention. This event changes the object, as the one depicted in the painting becomes present there, marking the introduction of a second order of truth within the painting. The rst of these was the circular human understanding of the visible. The second was the fullness of the truth in painting when its subject let itself become present through the icon. It is the advent of this double truth that is desired in the age of the icon. Neither the painting, the painter, nor the beholder has power over this experience. The icon bears the traces marked upon it by the painter, who delineates empty forms on the icon’s surface, where they can be viewed by an onlooker, who can see the outline of a face. Yet there is nothing there to be seen, only a space that opens itself toward an absent subject, awaiting the fulllment of a presence that is beyond representation.
BIBLIOGRAPHY Primary Sources: Published Editions and Translations Mansi = Mansi, J. D. Sacrorum Conciliorum Nova et Amplissima Collectio. Florence and Venice: A. Zatti, 1759–98. PG = Patrologiae cursus completus, Series graeca. Ed. Jacques-Paul Migne. 161 vols. in 166 parts. Paris: Migne, 1857–66. anon. De Theophili imperatoris absolutione. Regel, Vasilii. Analecta Byzantino-Russica. New York: Burt Franklin, 1964: 19–39 anon. Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta. Conciliorum Oecumenicorum Decreta. Ed. P.-P. Ioannou. Freiburg: Herder, 1962. anon. Oracula Chaldaica. Oracles Chadaïques. Ed. Édouard des Places. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1971. anon. Blachernae synod. PG, 127:980D–984A. anon. Synodikon Orthodoxiae. Gouillard, Jean. “Le Synodikon de l’Orthodoxie: Édition et commentaire.” Travaux et mémoires 2 (1967): 1–316. anon. Vita Cyril Philotheos. Sargologos, Etienne. La Vie de Saint Cyrille le Philéote moine byzantin (=1100). Brussels: Société des Bollandistes, 1964. anon. Vita Imp. Theodora Markopoulos, Athanasios. „Bios ten autokrateiran Theodoran (BHG 1731).“ Symmeikta 5 (1983): 249–85. Vinson, Martha P. “Life of St. Theodora the Empress.” Byzantine Defenders of Images: Eight Saints’ Lives in English Translation. Ed. Alice-Mary Talbot. Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks, 1998: 361–82. Alexander of Aphrodisias, In de Sensu. Alexander of Aphrodisias. In de Sensu. Ed. P. Wendland. Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 3, 1. Berlin: George Reimer, 1901: 1–173. Alexander of Aphrodisias. On Aristotle’s “On Sense Perception.” Trans. Alan Towey. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2000. Alexios I Komnenos. Decree. Sakkélion, J. “Décret d’Alexis Comnène portant déposition de Léon, Métropolitain de Chalcédoine.” Bulletin de Correspondance Hellénique 2 (1878): 102–28. ——. Edict. Gautier, Paul. “L’Édit d’Alexis 1er Comnène sur la réforme du clergé.” Revue des études byzantines 31 (1973): 165–201. Aspasius of Athens. In Ethica Nicomachea Aspasius of Athens. In Ethica Nicomachea. Ed. Gustavus Heylbut. Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 19, 1. Berlin: George Reimer, 1889: 1–186. Attaleiates, Michael. Historia. Attaleiates, Michael. Historia. Eds. Wladimir Brunet de Presle, Immanuel Bekker. Bonn: Weber, 1853. Basil of Euchaita. Isaakion. Basil of Euchaita. Letter to Isaak Sebastokrator. Ed. Lauriotes. “Historikon Zetema:” 411B–413A. Constantine Porphyrogenitos, De Ceremoniis
166
bibliography
Constantine Porphyrogenitos, De ceremoniis aulae byzantinae, ed. Johann Jacob Reiske, 2 vols. Bonn: E. Weber, 1829–30. Eustratios of Nicaea. Dialogue. Demetrakopulos, Andreas. Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1965: 127–51. ——. Demonstration. Demetrakopulos, Andreas. Bibliotheca Ecclesiastica. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1965: 151–60. ——. In Ethica Nicomachea Commentaria. Eustratii et Michaelis et Anonyma in Ethica Nicomachea Commentaria. Ed. Gustavus Heylbut. Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 20. Berlin: George Reimer, 1892: 256–406. ——. In Analyticorum Posteriorum Commentarium Eustratii in Analyticorum Posteriorum Librum Secundum Commentarium. Ed. M. Hayduck. Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca 21, 1. Berlin: George Reimer, 1907. Euthymios Zigabenos. Panoplia Dogmatica. PG, 130: 20–1360. Evergetis Monastery. Liturgical Typikon. Dmitrievskij, Aleksandr. Opisanie liturgiceskich rukopisej, vol. 1. Kiev, 1895. Great Church. Liturgical Typikon. Mateos, Juan. Le typicon de la Grande Église. Orientalia Christiana Analecta 165. Rome: Ponticium Institutum Orientalium Studiorum, 1962. Gregory II. Epistulae. Gouillard, Jean. “Aux origines de l’iconoclasme: le témoignage de Grégoire II?” Travaux et mémoires 3 (1968): 243–307. Iamblichus. De Mysteriis. Jamblique: Les mystères d’Égypte. Ed. and trans. Édouard Des Places. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1996. Iamblichus, On the Mysteries. Trans. Emma C. Clarke, John M. Dillon and Jackson P. Hershbell. Atlanta: Society of Biblical Literature, 2003. Italos, John. Quaestiones Quodlibetales. Italos, Ioannes. Quaestiones Quodlibetales. Ed. Perikles Joannou. Studia Patristica et Byzantina 4. Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag, 1956. John of Antioch. Diatribes. Gautier, Paul. “Diatribes de Jean l’Oxite contre Alexis 1er Comnène.” Revue des Études Byzantines 28 (1970): 5–55. John of Damaskos. Contra imaginum. Kotter, Bonifatius. Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos III. Contra imaginum calumniatores orationes tres. Patristische Texte und Studien 17. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1975. St. John of Damascus. Three Treatises on the Divine Images. Trans. Andrew Louth. Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2003. ——. Expositio Fidei. Kotter, Bonifatius. Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos II. Expositio Fidei. Patristische Texte und Studien 12. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1973. St. John of Damascus. Writings. Trans. Frederic H. Chase. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1958. ——. In Nativitatem Christi Kotter, Bonifatius. Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos V. Homilien. Patristische Texte und Studien 29. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1973. Klimakos, John. Scala Paradisi. PG, 88:631–1163. John Climacus. The Ladder of Divine Ascent. Trans. Colm Luibheid and Norman Russell. New York: Paulist Press, 1982. Komnena, Anna. Alexiad. Anne Comnène, Alexiade. Ed. Bernard Leib, vol. 3. Paris: Budé, 1937.
bibliography
167
The Alexiad of Anna Comnena. Trans. Edgar Sewter. Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1969. Leo of Chalcedon. Alexion. Leo of Chalcedon. Epistole pros ton basilea Alexion ton Komnenon. Ed. Alexander Lauriotes. Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900): 403–04. ——. Nikolaon. Leo of Chalcedon. Epistole pros ton Nikolaon Adrianoupoleos. Ed. Alexander Lauriotes. Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900): 414A–16A, 445A–47A, 455B–456B. ——. Protovestiarisan. Leo of Chalcedon. Epistole pros [Marian] ten Protovestiarisan. Ed. Alexander Lauriotes. Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900): 404–05. ——. Isaakio. Leo of Chalcedon, Isaakio. Ed. Alexander Lauriotes. Ekklesiastike Aletheia 20 (1900): 411B–13A. Methodios of Constantinople. Canon on the setting up of the holy images. PG, 99:1767–80. ——. Life of Euthymios. Gouillard, Jean. “La vie d’Euthyme de Sardes (d. 831).” Travaux et mémoires 10 (1987): 1–101. Nikephoros of Constantinople. Antirrhetikoi PG, 100:205–534 Niketas of Serres. On Bishops. Darrouzès, Jean. Documents inédits d’ecclésiologie byzantine. Archives de l’Orient chrétien 10. Paris: Institut français d’études byzantines, 1966: 276–309. Plato. Republic. Plato. The Republic, Books I–V. Trans. Paul Shorey. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1937. Plato. The Republic, Books VI–X. Trans. Paul Shorey. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1935. Psellos, Michael. Chronographia. Psellos, Michel. Chronographie. Ed. Émile Renaud, vol. 1. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1926. Psellus, Michael. Fourteen Byzantine Rulers: The Chronographia of Michel Psellus. Trans. Edgar Sewter. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1966. ——. Epitaphios. Gautier, Paul. “Eloge funèbre de Nicolas de la Belle Source par Michel Psellos moine à l’Olympe.” Byzantina 6 (1974): 11–69. Weiss, Günter. “Die Leichenrede des Michael Psellos auf den Abt Nikolaos vom Kloster von der Schönen Quelle.” Byzantina 9 (1977): 221–322. ——. Epitataphios for his mother. Psello, Michele. Autobiograa: encomio per la madre. Ed. Ugo Criscuolo. Naples: M. D’Auria 1989. ——. Letter to Michael Keroularios. Psello, Michele. Epistola a Michele Cerulario. Ed. Ugo Criscuolo, 2nd revd. ed. Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990. ——. Letter to John Xiphilinos. Psello, Michele. Epistola a Giovanni Xilino. Ed. Ugo Criscuolo, 2nd revd. ed. Naples: Bibliopolis, 1990. ——. Orationes Forenses et Acta. Psellus, Michael. Orationes Forenses et Acta. Ed. George Dennis. Stuttgart and Leipzig: Teubner, 1994. ——. Orationes hagiographicae. Psellus, Michael. Orationes hagiographicae. Ed. Elizabeth A. Fisher. Stuttgart and Leipzig: Teubner, 1994. ——. Philosophica minora.
168
bibliography
Psellus, Michael. Philosophica Minora. Vol. 2. Ed. Dominic J. O’Meara. Leipzig: Teubner, 1989. ——. Scripta minora. Psellus, Michael. Scripta minora. Eds. Edward Kurtz and Francis Drexl, vol. 2. Milan: Socièta editrice “Vita e pensiero”, 1941. ——. Theologica. Psellus, Michael. Theologica, vol. II. Ed. Leendert Westerink and John Duffy. Munich and Leipzig: K. G. Saur, 2002. Stethatos, Niketas. Vita Symeon. Hausherr, Irénée. Un grand mystique byzantin: Vie de Syméon le Nouveau Théologien (949–1022) par Nicétas Stethatos. Orientalia Christiana Analecta 45. Rome: Ponticio Institutum Orientalium Studiorum, 1928. ——. Works. Darrouzès, Jean. Nicétas Stéthatos, Opuscules et lettres. Sources chrétiennes 81. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1961. Symeon the New Theologian. Catecheses. Symeon the New Theologian. Catéchèses 23–34, Actions de Grâces 1–2. Ed. and trans. Sources chrétiennes 113. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1965. Symeon the New Theologian. The Discourses. Trans. New York: Paulist Press, 1980. ——. Hymns. Symeon the New Theologian. Hymnes 16–40. Ed. Johannes Koder. Sources chrétennes 174. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1971. Symeon the New Theologian. Hymnes 41–58. Ed. Johannes Koder. Sources chrétiennes 196. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 1973. Symeon the New Theologian. Hymns of Divine Love. Trans. George Maloney. Denville: Dimension Books, n.d. ——. Theological and Ethical Treatises. Darrouzès, Jean. Syméon le Nouveau Théologien, Traités théologiques et éthiques. Sources chrétiennes 122. Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 1966. Golitzin, Alexander. St. Symeon the New Theologian, On the Mystical Life: The Ethical Discourses, Vol. 1: The Church and the Last Things. Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1995. Symeon the Stoudite. Ascetic Discourse. Alfeyev, Hilarion. Syméon le Studite, Discours Ascétique. Sources chrétiennes 460. Paris: Éditions du Cerf, 2001. Theodore of Stoudios. Antirrhetici. PG, 99: 327–435. ——. Epistulae. Theodori Studitae. Epistulae, 2 vols. Ed.Georgios Fatouros. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1991. ——. Parva Catechesis. Theodore of Stoudios. Parva Catechesis. Ed. Emmanuel Auvray. Paris: Victor Lecoffre, 1891. Zonaras, John. Epitome historiarum. Zonaras, John. Epitome historiarum. Ed. Louis Dinsdorf. Leipzig: Teubner, 1868–75. Secondary Sources Alexakis, Alexander. Codex Parisinus Graecus 1115 and Its Archetype. Dumbarton Oaks Studies 34. Washington: Dumbarton Oaks, 1996. Anastos, Milton. “The Ethical Theory of Images Formulated by the Iconoclasts in 754 and 815.” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 8 (1954): 153–60. Anderson, Jeffrey C. “The Date and Purpose of the Barberini Psalter.” Cahiers Archéologiques 31 (1983): 35–67.
bibliography
169
Angold, Michael. Church and Society in Byzantium under the Comnenoi 1081–1261. Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1995. Avner, Tamar. “The Impact of the Liturgy on Style and Content: The Triple-Christ Scene in Taphou 14.” XVI Internationaler Byzantinistenkongress Akten II.5. Vienna: Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 1982: 459–67. Barber, Charles. “Mimesis and Memory in the Narthex Mosaics of the Nea Moni on Chios.” Art History 24 (2001), 323–337. ——. Figure and Likeness: On the Limits of Representation in Byzantine Iconoclasm. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2002. ——. “Icon and Portrait in the Trial of Symeon the New Theologian.” In Icon and Word: The Power of Images in Byzantium. Ed. Antony Eastmond and Liz James. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2003: 25–34. ——. Icons, Prayer, and Vision in the Eleventh Century. Byzantine Christianity. Ed. Derek Krueger. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2006: 160–163. ——. “Living Painting, or the Limits of Pointing?” In Reading Michael Psellos. Eds. Charles Barber and David Jenkins. Leiden: Brill, 2006: 117–30. Baring Gould, Sabine. Historic Oddities and Strange Events, First Series. London: Methuen, 1891. Browning, Robert. “The Patriarchal School at Constantinople in the Twelfth Century.” Byzantion 32 (1962): 167–202 and 33 (1963): 11–40. ——. ”Enlightenment and Repression in Byzantium in the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries.” Past and Present 69 (1975): 3–23. ——. Church, State, and Learning in Twelfth Century Byzantium. London: Friends of Dr. Williams’s Library, 1981. Brubaker, Leslie. “Byzantine Art in the Ninth Century: Theory, Practice, and Culture.” Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies 13 (1989): 23–93. ——. Vision and Meaning in Ninth-Century Byzantium: Image as Exegesis in the Homilies of Gregory of Nazianzus. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Cacharelias, Dimitris. The Mount Athos Esphigmenou 14 Codex: Pagan and Christian Myth in Middle Byzantine Manuscript Illumination. Unpublished PhD. New York University, 1995. Canal, J. M. El libro ‘De laudibus et miraculis Sanctae Mariae’ de Guillermo de Malmesbury. Rome: 1968. Ciggaar, Krijnie. “Description de Constantinople traduite par un pèlerin anglais du XIIe siècle.” Revue des Études Byzantines 34 (1976): 211–67. ——. “Une description de Constantinople dans le Tarragonensis 55.” Revue des Études Byzantines 53 (1995): 117–140. Clarke, Emma. Iamblichus’ De Mysteriis: A manifesto of the miraculous. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001. Clucas, Lowell. The Trial of John Italos and the Crisis of Intellectual Values in Byzantium in the Eleventh Century. Miscellanea Byzantina Monacensia 26. Munich: Institut für Byzantinistik, Neugriechische Philologie und Byzantinische Kunstgeschichte der Universität, 1981. Combes, François. Historia haeresis monothelitarum. Paris: A. Bertier, 1648. Cormack, Robin. “Icon of the Triumph of Orthodoxy.” Byzantium: Treasures of Byzantine Art and Culture. Ed. David Buckton. London: British Museum Press, 1994: 129–31. Corrigan, Kathleen. Visual Polemics in the Ninth-Century Byzantine Psalters. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992. ——. “Constantine’s problems: the making of the Heavenly Ladder of John Climacus, Vat. gr. 394.” Word and Image 12 (1996): 61–93. Cotsonis, Nicolas. “The Virgin with the ‘Tongues of Fire’.” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 48 (1994): 221–27. The Council in Trullo Revisited. Eds George Nedungatt and Michael Featherstone. Kanonika 6 (1995).
170
bibliography
Cutler, Anthony and Robert Browning. “In the margins of Byzantium? Some icons in Michael Psellos.” Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies 16 (1992): 21–32. Didi-Huberman, Georges. Confronting Images: Questioning the Ends of a Certain History of Art. College Park, PA: Pennsylvania State Press, 2005. Dolezal, Mary-Lyon. “Illuminating the liturgical word: text and image in a decorated lectionary (Mount Athos, Dionysiou Monastery, cod. 587).” Word and Image 12 (1996): 23–60. Draeseke, Johannes. “Zu Eustratios von Nikaea.” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 5 (1896): 319–36. ——. “Psellos und seine Anklageschrift gegen den Patriarchen Michael Kerullarios.” Zeitschrift für wissenschaftliche Theologie 48 (1905): 194–259, 362–409. Duffy, John. “Reactions of Two Byzantine Intellectuals to the Theory and Practice of Magic: Michael Psellos and Michael Italikos.” Byzantine Magic. Ed. Henry Maguire. Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks, 1995: 83–97. van Esbroeck, Michel and Nural Karadeniz. “Das Synodikon vom Jahre 843 in georgischer Übersetzung.” Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 19 (1987): 300–313. Fisher, Elizabeth A. “Image and Ekphrasis in Michael Psellos’ Sermon on the Crucixion.” Byzantinoslavica 55 (1994): 44–55. ——., “Michael Psellos in a Hagiographical Landscape: The Life of St. Auxentios and the Encomion of Symeon the Metaphrast.” Reading Michael Psellos. Ed. Charles Barber and David Jenkins. Leiden: Brill, 2006: 57–72. Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge. New York: Pantheon, 1982. Fraigneau-Julien, Bernard. Les sens spirituels et la vision de Dieu selon Syméon le nouveau théologien. Théologie historique 67. Paris: Beauchesne, 1985. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer philosophischen Hermeneutik. 2nd ed. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr, 1965. ——. Truth and Method. 2nd revd. ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. New York: Continuum, 2004. Garzya, Antonio. “On Michael Psellus’ Admission of Faith.” Epeteris tes hetaireias byzantinon spoudon 35 (1966–67): 41–46. Gautier, Paul. “La synode de Blachernes (n 1094). Étude prosopographique.” Revue des Études Byzantines 29 (1971): 213–84. ——. “Un discours inédit de Michel Psellos sur la Crucixion.” Revue des Études Byzantines 49 (1991): 16–24. Giakalis, Ambrosios. Images of the Divine: The Theology of Icons at the Seventh Ecumenical Council, revd. ed. Leiden: Brill, 2005. Giocarinis, K. “Eustratius of Nicaea’s Defense of the Doctrine of Ideas.” Franciscan Studies 24 (1964): 159–204. Glavinas, Apostolos. He epi Alexiou Komnenou (1081–1118) peri hieron skeuon, keimelion kai agion eikonon eris (1081–1095). Byzantina Keimena kai Meletai 6. Thessalonike: Centre for Byzantine Studies, 1972. Golitzin, Alexander. St. Symeon the New Theologian, On the Mystical Life: The Ethical Discourses, Vol. 3: Life, Times and Theology. Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1997. Gombrich, Ernst. Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation. 2nd. ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press: 1969. Gouillard, Jean. “Art et littérature théologique à Byzance au lendemain de la querelle des images.” Cahiers de Civilisation Médiévale 12 (1969): 1–13 ——. “Constantine Chrysomallos sous le masque de Syméon le Nouveau Théologien.” Travaux et Mémoires 5 (1973): 313–327. ——. “La religion des philosophes.” Travaux et Mémoires 6 (1976): 305–24. ——. “Quatre procès de mystique à Byzance (vers 960–1143). Inspiration et autorité.” Revue des Études Byzantines 36 (1978): 5–81.
bibliography
171
——. “Le procès ofciel de Jean l’Italien, les actes et leurs sous-entendus.” Travaux et Mémoires 9 (1985): 133–74. Grabar, André. L’Iconoclasme byzantin: Le Dossier archéologique, revd. ed. Paris: Flammarion, 1984. Grotz, H. “Beobachtungen zu den zwei Briefen Papst Gregors II. an Kaiser Leo III.” Archivum Historiae Ponticiae 18 (1980): 9–40. ——. “Weitere Beobachtungen zu den zwei Briefen Papst Gregor II. an Kaiser Leo III.” Archivum Historiae Ponticiae 24 (1986): 365–75. ——. “Die früheste römische Stellungsnahme gegen den Bildersturm (Eine These, die es zu beweisen gilt).” Annuarium Historiae Conciliorum 20 (1988): 150–61. Grumel, Venance. “Le ‘miracle habituel’ de Notre Dame des Blachernes.” Échos d’Orient 30 (1931): 129–146. ——. “L’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine. Le décret ou ‘semeioma’ d’Alexis Ier Comnène (1086).” Échos d’Orient 39 (1940): 333–341. ——. “L’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine. Le chrysobulle d’Alexis Ier sur les objets sacrés,” Études Byzantines 2 (1944): 126–33. ——. “Les documents Athonites concernant l’affaire de Léon de Chalcédoine.” Miscellanea Giovanni Mercati, vol. 3. Studi e Testi 123. Vatican City: Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, 1946: 116–35. ——. “Léon de Chalcédoine et le canon de la Fète du Saint Mandilion.” Analecta Bollandiana 68 (1950): 135–52. Hausherr, Irénée. Saint Théodore Studite: L’homme et l’ascète (d’après ses Catéchèses). Orientalia Christiana Analecta 22. Rome: Ponticium Institutum Orientalium Studiorum, 1926. ——. Penthos: The Doctrine of Compunction in the Christian East. Kalamazoo: Cistercian Publications, 1982. Heidegger, Martin. Nietzsche. Vol. 4. Ed. David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1982. ——. “Plato’s Doctrine of Truth.” Pathmarks. Ed. William McNeill. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998: 155–182. ——. “The Origin of the Work of Art” Off the Beaten Track. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002: 1–56. ——. “The Age of the World Picture” Off the Beaten Track. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002: 57–85. Hergenröther, Joseph. Monumenta Graeca ad Photium ejusque Historiam Pertinentia. Regensburg: George Joseph Manz, 1869. Holl, Karl. Enthusiasmus und Bussgewalt beim griechischen Mönchtum: eine Studie zum Symeon dem neuen Theologen. Leipzig: J. C. Hinrich,1898. The Holy Face and the Paradox of Representation. Ed. Herbert L. Kessler and Gerhard Wolf. Bologna: Nuova Alfa Editoriale, 1998. Hussey, Joan. Church and Learning in the Byzantine Empire 867–1185. London: Oxford University Press, 1937. ——. Ascetics and Humanists in Eleventh-Century Byzantium. London: Dr. Williams’s Trust, 1960. James, Liz. Light and Colour in Byzantine Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996. ——. and Ruth Webb. “ ‘To Understand Ultimate Things and Enter Secret Places’: Ekphrasis and Art in Byzantium.” Art History 14 (1991): 1–17. Joannou, Perikles. “Eustrate de Nicée. Trois pièces inédites de son procès (1117).” Revue des Études Byzantines 10 (1952): 24–34. ——. “Die Denition des Seins bei Eustratios von Nikaia. Die Universalienlehre in der byzantinischen Theologie im XI. Jh.” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 47 (1954): 358–68. ——. “Der Nominalismus und die menschliche Psychologie Christi. Das Semeioma gegen Eustratios von Nikaia (1117).” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 47 (1954): 369–78.
172
bibliography
——. Christliche Metaphysik in Byzanz, 1: Die Illuminationslehre des Michael Psellos und Joannes Italos. Ettal: Buch-Kunstverlag, 1956. ——. “Zwei vermisste Traktate aus den 93 Quaestiones quodlibetales des Iohannes Italos.” Studi bizantini e neoellenici 9 (1957): ——. “Le sort des évêques hérétiques réconciliés. Un discours inédit de Nicétas de Serres contre Eustrate de Nicée.” Byzantion 28 (1958): 1–30. Johansen, T. K. Aristotle on the Sense-Organs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997. Kaldellis, Anthony. The Argument of Psellos’ Chronographia. Leiden: Brill, 1999. Kartsonis, Anna. Anastasis: The Making of an Image. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1986. ——. “The Emancipation of the Crucixion.” Byzance et les images. Paris: La documentation française, 1994: 151–87. Kazhdan, Alexander. “Predvaritel’nye zamecanija o mirovozzrenii vizantijskogo mistika x–xi vv. Simeona.” Byzantinoslavica 28 (1967): 1–38. —— and Ann Wharton Epstein. Change in Byzantine Culture in the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1985. Kessler, Herbert L. Spiritual Seeing: Picturing God’s Invisibility in Medieval Art. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2000. Klentos, John. “The Synaxarion of Evergetis: algebra, geology and Byzantine monasticism.” Work and Worship at the Theotokos Evergetis. Eds. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby. Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.2. Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1997: 329–55. Kotoula, Dimitra. “The British Museum Triumph of Orthodoxy icon.” Byzantine Orthodoxies. Ed. Andrew Louth and Augustine Casiday. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006: 121–30. Krivocheine, Basil. In the Light of Christ. Trans. Anthony Gythiel. Crestwood: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1986. Lafontaine-Dosogne, Jacqueline. “Théophanes—visions auxquelles participent les prophètes dans l’art byzantin après la restauration des images.” Synthronon. Art et archéologie de la n de l’antiquité et du moyen âge. Paris: Bibliothèque des Cahiers Archéologiques, 1968: 135–43 ——. “L’Illustration du cycle des Mages suivant l’homélie sur la Nativité attribuée à Jean Damascène.” Le Muséon 100 (1987): 211–24. Lauriotes, Alexander. “Anagraphe chierographou tes en Athoi hieras Mones Megistes Lauras.” Eklesiastike Aletheia 2 (1886/1887): 168–172. Lemerle, Paul. “Le Gouvernement des philosophes: notes et remarques sur l’enseignement, les écoles, la culture.” Cinq études sur le X ie siècle byzantin. Paris: Éditions CNRS, 1977: 195–248. The Lenten Triodion. Trans. Mother Mary and Kallistos Ware. London: Faber and Faber, 1984. Lindberg, David. C. Theories of Vision from Al-Kindi to Kepler. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976. Lloyd, Antony C. “The Aristotelianism of Eustratios of Nicaea.” Aristoteles Werk und Wirkung. Vol. 2. Ed. Jürgen Wiesner. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1987: 341–51. ——. The Anatomy of Neoplatonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. Magdalino, Paul. “Enlightenment and Repression in Twelfth-Century Byzantium, the Evidence of the Canonists.” Byzantium in the 12th Century: Canon Law, State and Society. Ed. Nicolas Oikonomides. Athens: Society of Byzantine and Post Byzantine Studies, 1991: 357–373 ——. The Empire of Manuel I Komnenos 1143–1180. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. ——. “The reform edict of 1107.” Alexios I Komnenos. Eds. Margaret Mullett and Dion Smythe. Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 4.1. Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1996: 199–218.
bibliography
173
——. “Constantinopolitana.” Aetos: Studies in honour of Cyril Mango. Ed. Ihor Sevcenko and Irmgard Hutter. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1998: 220–227. Maguire, Henry. “The Depiction of Sorrow in Middle Byzantine Art,” Dumbarton Oaks Papers 31 (1977): 123–74. ——. Image and Imagination: The Byzantine Epigram as Evidence for Viewer Response. Toronto: Canadian Institute of Balkan Studies, 1996. ——. The Panels from Adam and Eve Caskets. The Glory of Byzantium: Art and Culture of the Middle Byzantine Era A.D. 843–1261. Eds. Helen C. Evans and William D. Wixom. New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art, 1997: 234–36. Mandylion: intorno al Sacro Volto, da Bisanzio a Genova. Ed. Gerhard Wolf, et al. Milan: Skira, 2004. Mango, Cyril. The Brazen House: A Study of the Vestibule of the Imperial Palace in Constantinople. Copenhagen: I kommission hos Ejnar Munksgaard, 1959. Markopoulos, Athanasios. “The rehabilitation of the Emperor Theophilos.” Byzantium in the Ninth Century: Dead or Alive? Ed. Leslie Brubaker. Aldershot: Ashgate, 1998: 37–49. Martin, John Rupert. The Illustration of the Heavenly Ladder of John Climacus. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954. Mercken, H. Paul F. The Greek Commentaries on the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle in the Latin Translation of Robert Grosseteste, Bishop of Lincoln (= 1253). Vols. 1 and 3. Leiden: Brill, 1973–. Michels, H. “Zur Echtheit der Briefe Papst Gregors II. an Kaiser Leon III.” Zeitschrift für Kirchengeschichte 99 (1988): 376–91. Morris, Rosemary. Monks and laymen in Byzantium 843–1118. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995. Nelson, Robert S. “To Say and to See: Ekphrasis and Vision in Byzantium.” Visuality Before and Beyond the Renaissance. Ed. Robert S. Nelson. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2000: 143–168. Oikonomides, Nicolas. Les listes de préséance byzantines des IX e et X e siècles. Paris: CNRS, 1972. Onians, John. “Abstraction and Imagination in Late Antiquity.” Art History 3 (1980): 1–23. Papadopoulos, Ioannes. B. Les Palais et les églises des Blachernes. Thessaloniki: Imp. de la Société commerciale et industrielle de Macédoine, 1928. Papaioannou, Eustratios N. “The ‘Usual Miracle’ and an Unusual Image: Psellos and the icons of Blachernai.” Jahrbuch der Österreichischen Byzantinistik 51 (2001): 177–88. Papavasileiou, Andreas. Euthymios-Ioannes Zygadenos: vios, syngraphai. Nicosia: Papavasileiou, 1979. Pargoire, Jean. “Constantinople: le couvent de l’Évergétis.” Echos d’Orient 9 (1906): 371–72; 10 (1907): 155–67, 249–63. Parry, Kenneth. “Theodore Studites and the Patriarch Nicephoros on Image-Making as a Christian Imperative.” Byzantion 59 (1989): 164–83. ——. Depicting the Word: Byzantine Iconophile Thought of the Eighth and Ninth Centuries. Leiden: Brill, 1996. Pätzold, Andreas. Der Akathistos-Hymnos: Die Bilderzyklen in der Byzantinischen Wandmalereien des 14. Jahrhunderts. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1989. Peers, Glenn. Subtle Bodies: Representing Angels in Byzantium. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2001. ——. Sacred Shock: Framing Visual Experience in Byzantium. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2004. Pentcheva, Bissera V. “Rhetorical images of the Virgin: The icon of the ‘usual miracle’ at the Blachernai.” RES 38 (2000): 35–54. ——. Icons and Power: The Mother of God in Byzantium. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 2006.
174
bibliography
To portraito tou kallitexne sto Byzantino. Ed. Maria Vasilake. Heraklion: Panepistemiakes Ekdoseis Kretes, 1997. Reading Michael Psellos. Eds. Charles Barber and David Jenkins. Leiden: Brill, 2006. Rydén, Lennart. “The Vision of the Virgin at Blachernae and the Feast of the Pokrov.” Analecta Bollandiana 94 (1976): 63–82. Schulz, M. “Die Nikopeia in San Marco: Zur Geschichte und zum Typ einer Ikone.” Byzantinische Zeitschrift 91 (1998): 473–501. Seibt, Werner. “Der Bildtypus der Theotokos Nikopoios. Zur Ikonographie der Gottesmutter-Ikone, die in 1030/31 in der Blachernenkirche wiedergefunden wurde.” Byzantina 13 (1985): 549–564. Shaw, Gregory. Theurgy and the Soul: The Neoplatonism of Iamblichus. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995. Skoulatos, Basile. Les Personnages byzantins de l’Alexiade: Analyse prosopographique et synthèse. Louvain: Éditions Nauwelaerts, 1980. Spatharakis, Iohannes. The Portrait in Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts. Leiden: Brill, 1976. Stephanou, Pelopidas. “Le procès de Léon de Chalcédoine.” Orientalia Christiana Periodica 9 (1943): 5–64. ——. “La Doctrine de Léon de Chalcédoine et de ses adversaires sur les images.” Orientalia Christiana Periodica 12 (1946): 177–99. The Theotokos Evergetis and Eleventh-Century Monasticism. Eds. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby. Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.1. Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1994. Thomas, John P. Private Religious Foundations in the Byzantine Empire. Dumbarton Oaks Studies 24. Washington, DC: Dumbarton Oaks, 1987. Thümmel, Hans-Georg. “Patriarch Photius und die Bilder.” in Eikon und Logos. Festschrift Konrad Onasch. Ed. H. Goltz. Wittenberg: Wissenschaftliche Beiträge der MartinLuther Universität, 1981: 275–89. ——. “Eine Schrift über das Wesen der Ikone.” Stimme der Orthodoxie 10 (1982): 53–58. ——. “Eine wenig bekannte Schrift zur Bilderfrage,” in Studien zum 8. und 9. Jahrhundert in Byzanz, ed. Helga Köpstein and Friedhelm Winkelmann (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1983): 153–57. Tognazzi Zervou, I. “L’iconograa e la ‘Vita’ delle miracolose icone della Theotokos Brefokratoussa: Blachernitissa e Odighitria.” Bollettino di Grottaferrata 40 (1986): 215–287. Trizio, Michele. “Eustratius of Nicaea on Absolute and Conditional Necessity. A Survey of the Commentary on Book VI of the Nicomachean Ethics.” Archiv für mittelalterliche Philosophie und Kultur 12 (2006): 35–63. Vinson, Martha. The Terms ȀƥƬƽƭƫưƮ and ƵƧƮƞƮƵƫưƮ and the Conversion of Theophilus in the Life of Theodora (BHG 1731). Greek, Roman, and Byzantine Studies 36 (1995): 89–99. Völker, Walther. Praxis und Theoria bei Symeon den neuen Theologen: Ein Beitrag zur Byzantinischen Mystik. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner Verlag, 1974. Walter, Christopher. “The date and content of the Dionysiou lectionary.” Deltion tes christianikes archaiologikes hetaireias 4/13 (1985): 181–89. Weitzmann, Kurt. “An imperial lectionary in the Monastery of Dionysiou on Mount Athos. Its origins and wanderings.” Revue des études sud-est européenes 7 (1969): 239–53. Weyl Carr, Annemarie. “Leo of Chalcedon and the Icons.” Byzantine East, Latin West: Art-Historical Studies in Honor of Kurt Weitzmann. Ed. Doula Mouriki et al. Princeton: Department of Art and Archaeology, 1995: 579–84. ——. “Court Culture and Cult Icons in Middle Byzantine Constantinople.” Byzantine Court Culture from 829 to 1204. Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks, 1997: 81–99.
bibliography
175
Wickert, Jacob. “Die Panoplia dogmatica des Euthymios Zigabenos: Untersuchung ihrer Anlage und ihrer Quellen, ihres Inhaltes und ihrer Bedeutung.” Oriens Christianus 8 (1908): 278–388. Wolska-Conus, Wanda. “Les écoles de Psellos et de Xiphilin sous Constantin IX Monomaque.” Travaux et Mémoires 6 (1976): 223–43. Work and Worship at the Theotokos Evergetis. Eds. Margaret Mullett and Anthony Kirby. Belfast Byzantine Texts and Translations 6.2. Belfast: Belfast Byzantine Enterprises, 1997. Zervos, Christophe. Un philosophe néoplatonicien du XI e siècle: Michel Psellos. Sa vie, son oeuvre, ses luttes philosophiques, son inuence. Paris: Éditions Ernest Leroux, 1920.
INDEX Aaron, 3 Abgar, 139 Adam, and Eve, 28; and Paradise, 28–45, 48; seeing God, 28–29, 44–49, 59 Akathistos Hymn, 63 Alexander of Aphrodisias, 93 Alexios I Komnenos, Emperor, 88, 99–100, 118, 121, 127, 131–32, 134–35, 147–50 Anna Komnena, 100, 113; Alexiad, 99 Angelic depiction, 103 Anti-semitism, 7 Apollinarism, 120 Apollonios of Tyana, 8 Arianism, 120 Aristotle, 20, 30, 57, 65, 71, 100, 113, 116; On Sense Perception, 93–96 Arsakios, 9 Art, and wisdom, 116–117 Art History, xii; 161–63 Artist, 74, 92–93, 105–06, 114–16 Aspasius of Athens, 93 Balaam, 8 Baltimore, Walters Art Gallery, Adam outside Paradise ivory, 45 Basil the Great, 4, 11, 67, 126, 137, 145 Basil, Metropolitan of Euchaita, 134, 136, 139–40 Bera, Theotokos Kosmosoteira Monastery, 3 Blachernae Synod, 147–48, 155 Book of Ceremonies, 2 British Museum, Feast of Orthodoxy icon, 7, 9 Browning, Robert, 149–50 Chios, monks, 71 Christ, Antiphonetes, 6–7, 12, 83–85, 88, 97; crucixion, 5–6, 72–80; depiction, 1; face, xi, 45–46, 58, 111; Kerameion, 112; Mandylion, 112, 138–39; polymorphous, 92–93 Chrysippos, 68–69 Constantine V, Emperor, 10 Constantine VII Porphyrogenitos, Emperor, 138–39
Constantine IX Monomachos, Emperor, 14, 65, 117 Constantinople, Blachernae Palace, 135, 147–48; Great Palace, 138, Chalke Gate, 10; Hagia Sophia, 10, 118; St. Mamas Monastery, 3, 27, 55; Stoudios Monastery, 26–27; Theotokos Blachernae, 80, 97–98; Theotokos Chalkoprateia, 132–33; Theotokos Everegetis Monastery: Abbot Timothy, 3, Synaxarion, 3–22; Cyril, Patriarch of Alexandria, Treasures, 119 Dalassena, Anna, 131 Delphi, 86 Democritus, 95 Dodona, 86 Dyrrachium (Dürres), 131 Empedocles, 95 Eustratios, Metropolitan of Nicaea, 99–130, 131, 156, 159–60, 162; Demonstration, 110–12, 128; Dialogue, 101–10; On the Nicomachean Ethics, 100, 113–16, 130; On Book 2 of the Posterior Analytics, 100 Ezekiel, Prophet, 18 Feast of Orthodoxy, 3, 10, 13, 19, 121 Fry, Roger, 161 Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 97 Gabriel, Archangel, 63 Garidas, Eustratios, Patriarch, 134 George the Monk, Chronicle, 7 Germanos, Patriarch, 10, 143, 151; Letter to John of Synada, 144, 156 Gregory II, Pope, 11–12 Gregory Nazianzos, Patriarch, 67, 119, 128, 137–38, 145, 147; Homilies, 92; In novam dominicam, 14 Grossolanus, Peter, Archbishop of Milan, 99–100 Grumel, Venance, 139 Guiscard, Robert, 131 Hergenröther, Joseph, 151
178
index
Iamblichus, 119 Icon, and the accidental, 104–12; and accuracy, 114–16; and ambiguity, 72–80; Antiphonetes, 6–7, 12, 83–85, 88, 97; Beirut, 5–7, 15; Blachernae, 80–98; and body, 17, 21; and change, 97; as divine portrait; 101, 137–39, 141–43; and ethics, 15; and the essential, 104–12; and formalism, 13, 108–09; ground, xii, 1–22; and horizon, xii, 21; and incarnation, 15–16; and Jews, 5–7; living, 72–80, 136; and miracles, 80–98, 107; and prophetic vision, 17–19; as relative, 20; subject, xii; and veneration, 13; and the visible, 21–22, 72–80, 102–03, 154–55 Iconoclasm, xii, 1, 121, 132–33 Iconomachy, xii, 19, 121, 159 Ioannikios of Mt. Olympos, 8, 9 Isaak I Komnenos, Emperor, 131 Isaak Sebastokrator, 131–32, 139, 143, 148, 151, 155 Isaiah of Nikomedia, 9 Italos, John, 99–100, 117–27, 130, 131, 137; Quaestiones, 123; Profession of Faith, 118–21, 126–27; trials, 117–27, 149 Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 14, 74, 91–93 Job, 128 John VII, Patriarch, 8, 9 John VIII Xiphilinos, Patriarch, 64–65 John of Antioch, Patriarch, 135 John of Claudiopolis, 148 John of Damaskos, 92, 137; First Oration on the Images, 123–25; On the Orthodox Faith, 123; John Klimakos, Ladder of Divine Ascent, 43–44 Kaspakes, 121 Kerameion, 112 Kessler, Herbert, 112 Lauriotes, Alexander, 143 Lazarios of Mt. Galesion, 3 Leo III, Emperor, 10, 11–12 Leo V, Emperor, 14 Leo, Metropolitan of Chalcedon, 101, 118, 127, 131–57, 159, 162; Alexion, 132–34; and the divine portrait; 101, 137–39, 141–43; Isaakion, 139–41; Marian, 135; Nikolaon, 136–43, 155
London, British Library, Add. 19.352 (Theodore Psalter), 44 Louis the Pious, Emperor, 12 Magdalino, Paul, 150 Magus/Magi, 92 Mandylion, 112, 138–39 Maximos the Confessor, 66–67 Methodios, Patriarch, 8, 9, 10, 20 Michael II, Emperor, 12, 14 Michael III, Emperor, 7, 9 Michael VII Doukas, Emperor, 80, 88, 117 Michael I Keroularios, Patriarch, 13, 19, 27, 70, 86 Michael Synkellos, 9 Modernism, xii, 161–63 Monophysitism, 100 Moscow, Khludov Psalter, 7, 8 Moses, 3; and Sinai, 67–68 Mother of God: icons of, 23, 61–64, 80–98 Mt. Athos, Dionysiou Monastery ms. 587m, 3 Mt. Olympos, 8, 9, 62, 64 Neoplatonism, 61–98, 100 Nicholas, Abbot of the Monastery of the Beautiful Source, 62–64, 88 Nicholas of Adrianople, 136 Nikephoros, Patriarch, 8–9, 20, 113, 123, 143, 151, 156, 159; First Antirrhetikos, 152, 156 Niketas of Serres, Metropolitan of Herakleia, 127–30 Niketas Stethatos, 27, 54–59 Oecumenical Council: Seventh, 11, 19, 138, 143, 151, 156; Eighth, 20, 113, 117 Oropos, 86 Palaeologos, George, 134 Pheidias, 114 Philotheos: Kletorologion, 2 Photios, Patriarch, 151, 156 Plato, 65–69, 71, 95; Republic, 35, 40–42, Timaeus, 122 Pliny, 75 Polykleitos, 114 Postmodernism, xii Proclus, 71, 90, 119; Elements of Theology, 90 Psellos, Michael, 61–98, 100, 104, 107,
index 117–18, 136, 138, 156, 159–60, 162; Accusation, 71, 86; Chronographia, 83–84; and color, 85, 96–97; Discourse on the Crucixion, 72–80; Discourse on the Miracle, 80–98; Epitaphios, 61–64; Letter to Michael Keroularios, 70–71; Letter to John Xiphilinos, 64–69; and oracles, 86–87; On Perception and Perceptibles, 93–96; Profession, 126–27; and ritual, 90–91 Pseudo-Dionysios the Areopagite, Celestial Hierarchy, 103, 145 Quinisext Council, Canon 68, 140; Canon 82, 138 Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 666, 150; Rossianus gr. 251, 112 Sabellianism, 120 Sergios II, Patriarch, 54 Simon Magus, 8 Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine, Mandylion icon, 139; Miracles icon, 81–82 Sozopolis, 135 Stephen of Nikomedia, 27, 54–59 Symeon the New Theologian, 23–59, 62, 68, 98, 100, 156, 159–60, 162; against philosophy and theology, 29–30, 32, 34; Allegory of the Prisoner, 34–45; First Ethical Discourse, 28–45; Fourth Ethical Treatise, 51–53; Hymn 21, 32–33; Hymn 23, 49–51; Hymn 52, 33–34; Hymn 53, 45–49; Life, 54–59; and penitence, 43–45, 48; First Thanksgiving, 58; Second Thanksgiving, 23–26; and tears, 32, 43–45; trial, 54–59 Symeon the Pious, 27, 54–59
179
Synodikon of Orthodoxy, xi, 1–22, 100, 113, 117, 121–22, 130, 148, 159 Tarasios, Patriarch, 10 Theodora, Empress: Life, 7–9, 10 Theodore Graptos, 9 Theodore, Abbot of Stoudios, 9, 12–13, 20, 113, 123, 143, 148, 159; Letter to Athanasios, 144, 148, 151, 156; Letter to the asecretes Diogenes, 144, 156; Letter to John the Grammarian, 144, 156; Letter to the spatharios Niketas, 144, 151, 155, 156; Letter to Platon, 145–47, 151, 152–54, 156; Letter to the Monk Severianos, 144, 155, 156; First Refutation, 151, 156; Second Refutation, 152–53; Third Refutation, 141 Theoktistos kanikleos, 9 Theophanes the Confessor, 9 Theophanes Graptos, 9 Theophilos, Emperor, 8, 9, 12, 14 Thümmel, Hans-Georg, 151 Trisagion Hymn, 13 Vasari, Giorgio, 75, 161 Vision, 25, 49–54, 93–96, 103–04; and body, 64; and light, 28–29, 36–40, 45–51, 53–54, 98; and touch, 96 Word and image, 14–18 Worship, adoration, 20, 109–10; 120, 126–27, 138, 141–47, 155; veneration, 20, 126–27, 138, 141–47, 153 Zeus-Helios, 92 Zigabenos, Euthymios, 149–57, 159–60; Panoplia Dogmatica, 149–57 Zoe, Empress, 14, 83–85, 88
ILLUSTRATIONS
illustrations
183
Fig. 1. St. Athanasios prays to an icon Christ. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 15r. Source: by permission of The British Library.
Fig. 2. Reading of the Synodikon of Orthodoxy. Mt. Athos, Dionysiou Monastery, ms. 587m, fol. 43r. Source: after Stylianos Pelekanidis et al., The Treasures of Mount Athos: Illuminated Manuscripts, vol. 1 (Athens: Ekdotike Athenon, 1973), g. 220.
184 illustrations
illustrations
185
Fig. 3. Crucixion. Moscow, State Historical Museum, cod. 129, fol. 67r. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études.
186
illustrations
Fig. 4. Christ Antiphonetes. Koimesis Church, Nicaea (Iznik). Source: after Theodor Schmit, Die Koimesis-Kirche von Nikaia. Das Bauwerk und die Mosaiken (Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter, 1927), pl. XXVII.
illustrations
187
Fig. 5. Synodikon of Orthodoxy. Icon, London, British Museum. Source: copyright The Trustees of the British Museum.
188
illustrations
Fig. 6. Nikephoros tramples John the Grammarian. Moscow, State Historical Museum, cod. 129, fol. 51v. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études, Paris.
illustrations
189
Fig. 7. Nikephoros of Contantinople, Theodore of Stoudios and the Iconoclastic Synod. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 27v. Source: by permission of The British Library.
190
illustrations
Fig. 8. Matthew the Monk prays to the Mother of God. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 55, fol. 260r. Source: Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 31.
illustrations
191
Fig. 9. Monks in a Penitential Prison. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 394, fol. 42r. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library.
192
illustrations
Fig. 10. The Creation of Adam. London, British Library, Add. 19.352, fol. 162r. Source: by permission of The British Library.
illustrations
193
Fig. 11. Adam outside Paradise. Baltimore, The Walters Art Museum. Source: The Walters Art Museum, Baltimore.
194
illustrations
Fig. 12. Michael Psellos before Michael VII Doukas. Mt. Athos, Pantokrator Monastery, ms. 234, fol. 254r detail. Source: after Stylianos Pelekanidis et al., The Treasures of Mount Athos: Illuminated Manuscripts, vol. 3 (Athens: Ekdotike Athenon, 1979).
illustrations
195
Fig. 13. Crucixion and Saints. Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the Michigan-Princeton-Alexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai.
196
illustrations
Fig. 14. A Persian artist depicts the Mother of God. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 14, fol. 106v detail. Source: after Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 69.
Fig. 15. The Blachernae Theotokos detail. . Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the Michigan-Princeton-Alexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai.
illustrations 197
198
illustrations
Fig. 16. Ambassadors before the Oracle at Delphi. Mt. Athos, Esphigmenou Monastery, ms. 14, fol. 396v detail. Source: Collection Gabriel Millet, École Pratique des Hautes Études.
illustrations
199
Fig. 17. The Magi and Christ. Jerusalem, Patriarchal Library, Taphou 14, fol. 106v. Source: after Panayotis L. Vocotopoulos, Byzantine Illuminated Manuscripts of the Patriarchate of Jerusalem (Athens and Jerusalem: Greek Orthodox Patriarchate of Jerusalem, 2002), g. 69.
Fig. 18. The Mandylion and Keramion. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, Rossianus gr. 251, fol. 12v detail. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library.
200 illustrations
illustrations
201
Fig. 19. Abgar and the Mandylion detail. Sinai, Monastery of St. Catherine. Source: reproduced through the courtesy of the Michigan-Princeton-Alexandria Expedition to Mount Sinai.
202
illustrations
Fig. 20. Fathers in the Dogmatic Panoply. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 666, fol. 1v. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library.
illustrations
203
Fig. 21. Alexios I Komnenos before Christ. Rome, Biblioteca Apostolica Vaticana, gr. 666, fol. 2r. Source: courtesy of the Vatican Library.