ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
TRENDS IN LOGIC Studia Logica Library
VOLUME 24 Managing Editor Ryszard Wójcicki, ...
22 downloads
707 Views
1MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
TRENDS IN LOGIC Studia Logica Library
VOLUME 24 Managing Editor Ryszard Wójcicki, Institute of Philosophy and Sociology, Polish Academy of Sciences, Warsaw, Poland Editors Vincent F. Hendricks, Department of Philosophy and Science Studies, Roskilde University, Denmark Daniele Mundici, Department of Mathematics “Ulisse Dini”, University of Florence, Italy Ewa Or á owska, National Institute of Telecommunications, Warsaw, Poland Krister Segerberg, Department of Philosophy, Uppsala University, Sweden Heinrich Wansing, Institute of Philosophy, Dresden University of Technology, Germany
SCOPE OF THE SERIES
Trends in Logic is a bookseries covering essentially the same area as the journal Studia Logica – that is, contemporary formal logic and its applications and relations to other disciplines. These include artificial intelligence, informatics, cognitive science, philosophy of science, and the philosophy of language. However, this list is not exhaustive, moreover, the range of applications, comparisons and sources of inspiration is open and evolves over time.
Volume Editor Heinrich Wansing
The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume.
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR by
GERHARD JÄGER University of Bielefeld, Germany
A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
ISBN-10 ISBN-13 ISBN-10 ISBN-13
1-4020-3904-2 (HB) 978-1-4020-3904-1 (HB) 1-4020-3905-0 (e-book) 978-1-4020-3905-8 (e-book)
Published by Springer, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands. www.springeronline.com
Printed on acid-free paper
All Rights Reserved © 2005 Springer No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. Printed in the Netherlands.
Contents
List of Tables Preface Acknowledgments
vii ix xiii
1. TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR: THE FRAMEWORK
1
1
Basic Categorial Grammar
1
2
Combinators and Type Logical Grammar
17
3
Historical and Bibliographical Remarks
65
2. THE PROBLEM OF ANAPHORA
69
1
Anaphora and Semantic Resource Sensitivity
69
2
Variables in TLG
72
3
Previous Categorial Approaches to Anaphora
76
4
Summary
116
3. LAMBEK CALCULUS WITH LIMITED CONTRACTION
119
1
The Agenda
119
2
Contraction?
120
3
The Logic LLC
121
4
Relation to Jacobson’s System
153
4. PRONOUNS AND QUANTIFICATION
157
1
Basic Cases
157
2
Binding by wh -operators
158
3
Binding by Quantifiers
159
4
Weak Crossover
169
5
Precedence Versus c-command
169
v
vi
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
6
Backward Binding and Reconstruction
174
5. VERB PHRASE ELLIPSIS 1 Introduction 2 VPE: The Basic Idea 3 Interaction with Pronominal Anaphora 4 Interaction of VPE and Quantification 5 VPE and Polymorphism 6 Parallelism Versus Source Ambiguity
183 183 186 187 195 201 206
6. INDEFINITES 1 Introduction 2 Dekker’s Predicate Logic with Anaphora 3 Bringing PLA into TLG 4 Donkey sentences 5 Indefinites and Scope 6 Sluicing 7 Summary and Desiderata
213 213 215 220 228 245 258 269
References
273
Index
283
List of Tables
1.1 1.2 2.1
The structural hierarchy Substructural Curry-Howard correspondences Categorial approaches to anaphora
vii
30 39 118
Preface
This book discusses how Type Logical Grammar can be modified in such a way that a systematic treatment of anaphora phenomena becomes possible without giving up the general architecture of this framework. By Type Logical Grammar, I mean the version of Categorial Grammar that arose out of the work of Lambek, 1958 and Lambek, 1961. There Categorial types are analyzed as formulae of a logical calculus. In particular, the Categorial slashes are interpreted as forms of constructive implication in the sense of Intuitionistic Logic. Such a theory of grammar is per se attractive for a formal linguist who is interested in the interplay between formal logic and the structure of language. What makes Lambek style Categorial Grammar even more exciting is the fact that (as van Benthem, 1983 points out) the Curry-Howard correspondence—a central part of mathematical proof theory which establishes a deep connection between constructive logics and the λ-calculus—supplies the type logical syntax with an extremely elegant and independently motivated interface to model-theoretic semantics. Prima facie, anaphora does not fit very well into the Categorial picture of the syntax-semantics interface. The Curry-Howard based composition of meaning operates in a local way, and meaning assembly is linear, i.e., every piece of lexical meaning is used exactly once. Anaphora, on the other hand, is in principle unbounded, and it involves by definition the multiple use of certain semantic resources. The latter problem has been tackled by several Categorial grammarians by assuming sufficiently complex lexical meanings for anaphoric expressions, but the locality problem is not easy to solve in a purely lexical way. The main purpose of this book is to develop an extension of Lambek style Type Logical Grammar that overcomes these difficulties and handles anaphora in a systematic fashion. The linguistic applications of the theoretical framework that is developed here focus on three classes of
ix
x
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
anaphora that are well-studied and well-understood as far as the empirical generalizations go. First and foremost, I will discuss the grammar of anaphoric third person singular pronouns, as illustrated by the following example. (1)
a. Johni invented a problem that hei could not solve. b. [Every student]i invented a problem that hei could not solve.
The second empirical domain that we are going to look at is verb phrase ellipsis, i.e., constructions like (2). (2)
a. John revised his paper, and Bill did too. b. John is happy with his job, but Bill isn’t.
As is well-known, VP ellipsis interacts with pronominal anaphora and quantification in complex ways. The logic of anaphora resolution that I will propose lends itself readily to a simple theory of this kind of ellipsis which covers the basic facts in an empirically adequate way. Finally, I will discuss a third class of anaphora, a version of ellipsis that has been called “sluicing” in the literature. Thereby I mean constructions in which a bare wh-phrase is interpreted as a (direct or indirect) question, as illustrated in (3). (3)
a. She’s reading something, but I can’t imagine what. b. A: She’s reading something. B: What?
The main goal of this work is not so much to develop a novel descriptive theory of anaphora but rather to demonstrate that anaphora can be integrated into Type Logical Grammar without giving up the attractive design of this theory of grammar. Nonetheless, the empirical predictions that we end up with do not always coincide with those of competing analyses, and I (naturally) try to argue that my analysis also gets the facts right in these cases. So the discussion might be interesting for non-Categorial grammarians who are interested in the analysis of anaphora as well. Also, the type logical analysis of donkey anaphora led to a partially novel account of the grammar of indefinites that diverges from established theories in several respects, both theoretically and empirically. The book does not expect prior knowledge of Categorial Grammar or any acquaintance with proof theory that goes beyond the level of some introductory logics course. I do assume though a working knowledge of set theory, first order logic and the typed λ-calculus. The technical level of the book should be easily accessible to anybody who has mastered
Preface
xi
some standard textbook on formal linguistics like Dowty et al., 1981 or Gamut, 1991. The structure of the book is as follows. Chapter 1 gives a selfcontained introduction to the framework of Type Logical Grammar. It does not make any reference to the issue of anaphora whatsoever. It can be used as an introductory text on its own. Readers that are already familiar with TLG, on the other hand, can safely skip this chapter. Chapter 2 discusses previous Categorial approaches to (pronominal) anaphora. This chapter too can be read on its own (or in combination with Chapter 1). The remainder of the book does not build on it in any significant way, so this chaper is not essential for understanding of the subsequent material. Chapter 3 is the core of the book. There I develop the novel type logical machinery that enables us to analyze anaphora resolution. In this chapter I focus on the proof theoretic properties of the resulting type logical calculus, i.e., I present the calculus in different proof theoretic formats, establish their equivalence, and prove essential meta-logical properties like Cut elimination, decidability, finite reading property, strong normalization, and completeness. The remaining chapters apply these theoretical tools to the mentioned empirical areas. Chapter 4 focuses on anaphoric pronouns and their interaction with quantification. Chapter 5 discusses two options for a type logical treatment of verb phrase ellipsis. In Chapter 6 I propose another extension of the underlying formalism to accommodate certain peculiarities of indefinite NPs. This has an impact on the issue of anaphora for two reasons. First, I believe that the problem of donkey anaphora is mainly a problem of indefiniteness, less a problem of anaphora. So an adequate treatment of donkey pronouns requires a theory of indefiniteness. Furthermore, sluicing is a form of ellipsis that interacts closely with the grammar of indefinites. I discuss these anaphora related aspects of indefiniteness, and I also consider some empirical issues pertaining to the grammar of indefinites as such, namely their peculiar scope taking behavior. Now that I have explained what the book is intended to be, a few words about what it is not. The intended audience are mainly formally inclined linguists and computational linguists with an interest in logic. I try to illustrate how a logical grammar can contribute to a both formally precise and empirically comprehensive linguistic theory. It is not my goal to give an introduction into the Lambek calculus and related substructural calculi for logicians. Therefore, issues that are important to logicians but of lesser relevance to the linguistic applications are not covered in great depth. This concerns especially model theory and the
xii
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
relation of type logics to modal logic and Linear Logic. Likewise, extensions of the Lambek calculus that are interesting from a logical point of view but without obvious linguistic applications—like negation or additive connectives—are not discussed. Neither could I deal with all facets of Type Logical Grammar that emerged within the last decade. The focus of the book is on the treatment of anaphora. The introductory Chapter 1 gives an overview over the “classical” version of Type Logical Grammar, but various new developments that have no immediate connection to anaphora are left out. This concerns especially non-associative Categorial calculi, multimodal extions of TLG, and the calculus of proof nets.
Acknowledgments
Most ideas that I present in this book were developed while I was a postdoc at the Institute for Research in Cognitive Science of UPenn in Philadelphia 1997 and 1998. It is no exaggeration to say that at that time, the IRCS was one of the best institutes in the world to conduct research on formal grammar. Thanks to Aravind Joshi for making the place what it is! I profited immensely from the discussions with my colleagues there. Many people gave me inspiration and feedback, but I feel the contacts to Robin Clark, Seth Kulick, Jeff Lidz, Mark Steedman and Yael Sharvit were especially important. Last but not least, Dick Oehrle’s occasional visits to Philadelphia were very rewarding. Natasha Kurtonina deserves a special mention. Due to a lucky coincidence, we came to the IRCS at the same time and wound up being office mates. She has an extraordinary gift for explaining things, and most of what I know about the “Logic” in “Type Logical Grammar”, I learned from her. She never tired of pointing out the flaws in my proofs and digging out literature that might be relevant for my research. Last but not least, I thank her for always being a good friend. When I left Philadelphia, my work on anaphora in TLG consisted of a couple of half finished papers and a lot of loose ideas. My time as a visitor at the Utrecht Institute of Linguistics in 2000 and 2001 gave me the opportunity to finally write everything down in a coherent way. It is hard to find a place with a higher concentration of excellent categorial grammarians than the OTS, and this created the right atmosphere to finish this work. Thanks to my Utrecht colleagues, especially to Michael Moortgat, for making the time in Utrecht a pleasant and productive one. While I was finally writing down the manuscript, Cornelia Endriss got me interested into the issue of indefiniteness again. We had a vivid intellectual exchange on this over several months. The last chapter of the book would have taken a different shape without this, and perhaps it
xiii
xiv
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
would not exist at all. Even though we finally drew different conclusions on what a correct approach to specificity should look like, many of the ideas and observations from this chapter are due to Neli. I had the opportunity to present material from this book at various talks at Berlin, UPenn, the MIT, Utrecht, D¨ usseldorf, Amsterdam and Leiden, and I am grateful for the comments I received at these occasions. I am also indebted to the students of my Categorial Grammar classes in Potsdam and in Utrecht for the feedback they gave me. I owe a lot to Raffaella Bernardi, Christian Ebert, Bryan Jurish, Manfred Krifka, Glyn Morrill, and Willemijn Vermaat for reading previous versions of the manuscript or parts of it, and making numerous helpful suggestions for improvement. All remaining errors are of course mine. Special thanks go to Bryan for spending a lot of effort correcting my English. This book is a revised version of my habilitation thesis that I defended at the Humboldt-University at Berlin in 2002. I would like to thank the committe members Marcus Kracht, Manfred Krifka and Michael Moortgat for their encouragement and support. It was also Marcus who suggested that I submit the manuscript to the “Trends in Logic”. Last but not least I thank the series editor Heinrich Wansing for the very good cooperation during the final preparations for publication, and the two anonymous reviewers for their suggestions and comments.
Chapter 1 TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR: THE FRAMEWORK
1. 1.1
Basic Categorial Grammar Informal Introduction
All versions of Categorial Grammar that have been developed in the past 30 years can be traced back to the pioneering work of Bar-Hillel, 1953. His system, despite its obvious limitations, in nuce contains most of the features that make the Categorial approach attractive to the present day. It is thus a natural starting point for a presentation of its more sophisticated descendant, Type Logical Grammar. It rests on a fundamental intuition about the structure of languages (both natural and formal ones) which says that linguistic signs may be complete or incomplete. Under this perspective, grammatical composition can be described as the process of completing incomplete linguistic signs. Basic Categorial Grammar (BCG henceforth) is probably the grammatical framework that expresses this intuition in its purest form. Consider the sentence (1)
Walter snores.
The name Walter has a simple semantic function; it just refers to the individual called “Walter”. We may thus consider the expression Walter to be complete, since its linguistic function does not depend on its linguistic context. Similarly, the sentence Walter snores is complete insofar as its denotation is a proposition with a truth value that depends on the extralinguistic context only. The verb snores, however, is incomplete in a sense. It serves to constitute a proposition, but it needs a subject to do so. Semantically it serves as a function that turns an individual into a proposition.
1
2
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Following standard practice, I use the label np for names (and phrases that have a comparable distribution) and s for sentences. The verb snores is thus an incomplete expression that turns an np into an s. Using a notation from Linear Logic (Girard, 1987), this intuition could be expressed by snores : np−◦s In words this says that the expression snores has the category np−◦s. An important piece of information is missing here though. Consider the more complex sentence (2)
Walter knows Kevin.
Here the transitive verb knows is doubly incomplete; it requires two nps to turn it into an s. We may express this with knows : np−◦(np−◦s) However, for an adequate description of the linguistic facts we also need the information that one np occurs to the right and one to the left of the verb. Following Bar-Hillel, 1953, I therefore distinguish between two kinds of incomplete expressions: forward looking functors that have a category of the form A/B (pronounced: “A over B”) and expect the missing piece on their right, and backward looking functors that have a category of the form A\B (“A under B”) and expect the missing piece on their left. A more adequate description of the facts collected so far would thus be Walter, Kevin : np snores : np\s knows : (np\s)/np The derivation of the two example sentences can conveniently be expressed in tree format as s
s
np
np\s
Walter
snores
np\s
np Walter
(np\s)/np
np
knows
Kevin
3
Type Logical Grammar: The Framework
In the sequel, I will refer to the A in the types A/B and B\A as the goal category and to the B as the argument category. The rules that are used in this derivation are (where ab is the concatenation of the strings a and b): 1 If a has category A/B and b has category B, then ab has category A. 2 If a has category A and b has category A\B, then ab has category B. These derivation schemes are sometimes called cancellation rules since they bear an obvious analogy to the arithmetic law1 x ×y =x y
Complex categories. It should be added that both the goal category and the argument category of a complex category may be complex themselves. The category of transitive verbs—(np\s)/np—already provides an example. Manner adverbs like faintly illustrate this point further; they combine with an intransitive verb phrase (category np\s) to yield an intransitive verb phrase. Both the argument category and the goal category are complex here. (3)
a. faintly : (np\s)\(np\s) b. Kevin snores faintly s c. np Kevin
np\s np\s
(np\s)\(np\s)
snores
faintly
Recursion. The category of adverbs also illustrates that the argument category and the goal category may be identical. If a BCG assigns such categories to an expression, the described language will display a recursive structure (but note that recursion may be realized in other ways as well). Adjectives are another case in point. They are attached to a common noun phrase (category n) to produce an expression of exactly this category. Figure 1.1 on the following page illustrates this. 1 Bar-Hillel’s system is based on the work of Ajdukiewicz, 1935 where the analogy is even more striking since it does not distinguish between forward looking and backward looking functors.
4
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR s
np
snores
n
np/n The
np\s
n
n/n old
n
n/n old
n/n old
Figure 1.1.
n n/n
n
old
man
Recursion
Semantic composition. Categories in Categorial Grammar represent two kinds of information. They encode how a sign combines with other signs both syntactically and semantically. Incomplete signs denote functions, and syntactic composition is accompanied by function application in semantics. The structure of the category of a sign is mirrored in the type of the function that it denotes. If the goal category of a sign is complex, its denotation is a curried function (i.e., a function whose values are functions themselves). Categories with complex argument categories correspond to higher order functions—functions that take other functions as arguments. If the semantic component of signs is represented by terms of the typed λ-calculus, syntactic and semantic composition can be displayed simultaneously in a tree structure, as illustrated in Figure 1.2.
1.2
The Formal System
1.2.1 Syntax After this rather informal description of BCG, let us make these intuitions precise. I begin with a formal specification of the notion of category. A BCG comprises finitely many basic categories (also atomic categories). Most linguistic applications make do with very few—the set {s, np, n, pp} is sufficient in many cases, but this is not essential. Complex categories are formed from basic ones by means of the connectives “/” (forward looking slash) and “ \ ” (backward looking slash).
5
Type Logical Grammar: The Framework s faintly’(λx.call’(x, kevin’))walter’
np\s faintly’(λx.call’(x, kevin’))
np walter’ Walter
np\s λx.call’(x, kevin’)
Figure 1.2.
(np\s)/np λyx.call’(x, y)
np kevin’
called
Kevin
(np\s)\(np\s) faintly’ faintly
Semantic composition of Walter called Kevin faintly
Definition 1 (Categories) Let a finite set B of basic categories be given. CAT(B) is the smallest set such that 1 B ⊆ CAT(B) 2 If A, B ∈ CAT(B), then A/B ∈ CAT(B) 3 If A, B ∈ CAT(B), then A\B ∈ CAT(B)
Bracketing convention:. I assume that the forward slash associates to the left, i.e., A/B/C is shorthand for (A/B)/C. The backward slash associates to the right, i.e., A\B\C stands for A\(B\C). Furthermore, forward slash takes precedence over the backward slash; A\B/C means A\(B/C). Like any formal grammar, a BCG consists of a lexical and a syntactic component. Ignoring semantics for a moment, the lexicon of a BCG is a mapping that assigns finitely many categories to each element of some finite set of strings. A lexical unit may have more than one category since linguistic units may be lexically ambiguous (as for instance walk in English, which is both a common noun and an intransitive verb). Definition 2 ((Uninterpreted) Lexicon) Let an alphabet Σ and a finite set B of basic categories be given. A BCG-lexicon LEX is a finite relation between Σ+ (the set of non-empty strings over Σ) and CAT(B).
6
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
The syntactic component is identical for all BCGs. It consists of a series of axiom schemes and rule schemes that jointly constitute a deductive system. I choose sequent presentation as a convenient format for a description of a deductive system. A sequent consists of a sequence of formulae A1 , . . . , An (of some formal language)—the antecedent, and a single formula B, the succedent. Antecedent and succedent are connected by the deduction symbol ⇒. A1 , . . . , An ⇒ B This sequent expresses that the succedent B can be derived from the antecedent A1 , . . . , An . Applied to BCG, the formulae in the sequents are elements of CAT(B). Trivially, every category A can be derived from itself. This is expressed by the identity axiom scheme id. Here and henceforth, I use letters A, B, C, . . ., possibly augmented with indices, as variables over categories.
A⇒A
id
Furthermore, it is possible to use lemmas in a derivation. In other words, a preliminary result of a derivation can be plugged into another derivation. This is expressed by the Cut rule. Letters X, Y, Z, . . . are variables over (possibly empty) sequences of categories.2 X⇒A
Y, A, Z ⇒ B
Y, X, Z ⇒ B
Cut
Finally, the fraction cancellation schemes informally given above represent valid deductions:
A/B, B ⇒ A
A>
B, B\A ⇒ A
A
t, t\e/t ⇒ e/t
e/t, t ⇒ e
t, t\e/t, t ⇒ e
t/n, n, t\e/t, t ⇒ e | | | | 1 2 = 1 Figure 1.3.
A
Cut
Cut
Sequent derivation of “12 = 1”
sequent X ⇒ A, the succedent A is a subformula of some formula in X. (All axioms have this property, and it is preserved under Cut.) So we can do bottom up proof search by testing for a sequent in question whether (a) it is an instance of an axiom, or (b) it is the conclusion of some instance of Cut, and the two premises are derivable. The premises of a Cut rule always have a lower complexity (consist of fewer symbols) than its conclusion, so this procedure is bound to terminate after finitely many steps. If deduction is decidable, string recognition by a BCG grammar is decidable as well. Since both the lexicon and the set of designated categories is finite, recognition of a given string reduces to derivability of finitely many different sequents.
1.2.2 Relation to Context Free Grammars Basic Categorial Grammars are closely related to Context Free Grammars. These two grammar formats in fact (weakly) recognize the same class of languages. This equivalence was established in the seminal paper Bar-Hillel et al., 1960. I will sketch the basic idea of an equivalence proof. For an in-depth discussion of this and related issues the reader is referred to the excellent overview article Buszkowski, 1997. The notion of a derivation in BCG and CFG (Context Free Grammars) are highly similar to start with. Context free derivations can also be seen as deductions in a deductive system that contains the identity axiom and is closed under Cut. Instead of the two application schemes, however, CFGs have context free rules as additional axioms. To transform a BCG into an equivalent CFG, it is thus sufficient to demonstrate that only finitely many instances of the application schemes are used in actual derivations. These instances can then be reinterpreted as CFG rules. As was mentioned above, in every derivable BCG sequent, the succedent is a subformula of one element of the antecedent of this sequent (since this property holds of all axioms, and it is preserved under Cut).
10
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Given this, it is straightforward to see that all categories that occur in a premise of a Cut rule are subformulae of categories that occur in the conclusion of this Cut. This in turn entails that in the derivation of a sequent X ⇒ A, only subformulae of X or of A are used. In particular, all application axioms used in the derivation consist of subformulae of the sequent to be derived. In the derivation of grammatical strings, only subformulae of lexical categories are used in the antecedents and only subformulae of designated categories as succedents. Since there are only finitely many such categories for a given BCG, in fact finitely many instances of application are sufficient. It follows from these considerations that every language that is recognized by a BCG is also recognized by some CFG. The inclusion in the other direction is much harder to establish—the proof is the central point of Bar-Hillel et al., 1960. It is easy to demonstrate though if we use the Greibach Normal Form Theorem (Greibach, 1965):
Theorem 1 (Greibach Normal Form Theorem) Every context free language L is recognized by some CFG G that only contains rules of the form A → aα (where “A” ranges over non-terminals, “a” over terminals, and “α” over (possibly empty) sequences of non-terminals). Let L be some context free language that is recognized by some CFG G in Greibach Normal Form. An equivalent BCG can easily be constructed. We identify the set of non-terminals of G with the set of basic categories. The CFG rules of G are transformed into lexical assignments by going from A→a to a;A and from A → aB1 . . . Bn to a ; A/Bn / · · · /B1 Finally we identify the start symbol of G as the only designated category of the BCG.
Type Logical Grammar: The Framework
11
1.2.3 Semantics Semantic types. Despite this strong similarity between BCG and CFG, the former has at least one conceptual advantage over the latter pertaining to its natural connection to semantic interpretation. As I alluded to in the beginning, the Categorial architecture is actually strongly motivated by semantic considerations. In phrase structure grammars and related formalisms, the syntactic category of a sign on the one hand and its semantic type on the other hand are independent semiotic dimensions that have to be specified separately. In Categorial Grammar, these components are closely linked. In other words, the category of a linguistic sign codes two kinds of information: it determines the (syntactic) combinatory potential of this sign, and it specifies which type of denotation the sign has. Let us make this precise. I assume that the reader is more or less familiar with type theoretic interpretation and summarize the basic notions very briefly. Analogously to basic syntactic categories, there is a finite set of basic semantic types. The set of semantic types is the closure of the basic types under function space formation: Definition 6 (Semantic types) Let BTYPE be a finite set (of basic semantic types). The set TYPE of semantic types is the smallest set such that 1 BTYPE ⊆ TYPE 2 If a, b ∈ TYPE, then a, b ∈ TYPE. In linguistic applications, the basic types usually contain at least the types e (for “entity”) and t (for “truth value), but this is not part of the general format. Semantic types correspond to ontological domains. The semantic type of a sign indicates what kind of object the denotation of this sign will be. The space of semantic domains has a recursive structure analogous to the set of semantic types; a complex type a, b always corresponds to the set of total functions from the domain of type a into the domain of type b.
Definition 7 (Domains) The function Dom is a semantic domain function iff 1 The domain of Dom is TYPE, 2 for all A ∈ TYPE, Dom(A) is a non-empty set, and 3 Dom(a, b) = Dom(b)Dom(a)
12
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
This definition does not restrict the assignment of domains to basic types (beyond the requirement that domains are non-empty). Following the lead of Montague, 1974, the conventional basic types e and t are usually mapped to some set E of individuals and the set {0, 1} of truth values respectively, but again, this is not part of the general architecture. Given a correspondence between basic categories and semantic types, the semantic type of a sign of an arbitrary category can be predicted from the internal structure of this category. More formally put, the semantic type of a linguistic sign is the homomorphic image of its syntactic category.
Definition 8 (Category to type correspondence) Let τ be a function from CAT(B) to TYPE. τ is a correspondence function iff τ (A\B) = τ (B/A) = τ (A), τ (B) Compositional Interpretation. Semantic types serve a double function. Primarily, they restrict the possible denotations of linguistic signs. If an expression has the syntactic category A, its denotation will be an element of Dom(τ (A)). Semantic types simply identify categories that differ only syntactically but not semantically (like np/np and np\np). For practical purposes, we are rarely concerned with actual meanings (i.e., model theoretic entities) but we deal with meaning representations that are formulated in the language of the typed λ-calculus. So we are mainly interested in a compositional translation from natural language into the semantic representation language. Since the denotation of λ-expressions is unambiguous and well-understood, such a translation indirectly determines a compositional interpretation of the object language. Semantic types not only determine the range of possible interpretations of a linguistic sign, they also determine the syntactic properties of its translation. The semantic types that we use are the syntactic categories of the semantic representation language. The category-to-type correspondence restricts possible translations from natural language to the λ-calculus. The translation—and thus indirectly the meaning—of a basic expression is determined in the lexicon. So a Categorial lexicon for an interpreted language is a three place relation, relating the form of an expression, its syntactic category, and its translation into the λ-calculus. I revise the definition of a lexicon accordingly. EXPa is the set of expressions of the typed λ-calculus that have type a. Definition 9 ((Interpreted) Lexicon) Let an alphabet Σ, a finite set B of basic categories and a correspondence
13
Type Logical Grammar: The Framework
function τ be given. An interpreted BCG-lexicon LEX is a finite subrelation of (Σ+ × {A} × EXPτ (A) ) A∈CAT(B)
The lexically determined form-category-meaning relation can be extended to all constituents that are recognized by the corresponding BCG. To this end, the axioms and rules of BCG have to be supplied with operations on the meanings of their operands (or, more precisely, with operations on their semantic representations). These are conveniently represented by means of labeled deduction. Antecedent formulae of sequents are labeled with variables and succedents with possibly complex terms of the λ-calculus. The actual translation of a constituent is obtained by replacing the free variables in the succedent term with the corresponding lexical translations of the formulae in the antecedent. The labeled BCG rules are given below. I write l : C for category C carrying the label l. First some remarks on notation are in order. I use lower case letters x, y, z, . . . as metavariables over variables of the λ-calculus and upper case letters M, N, O, . . . as metavariables over λterms. “N [M/x]” is the result of replacing all free occurrences of x in N by M . Variables (free or bound) that occur in different sequents are tacitly assumed to be different, so no variable clashes can arise. Finally, I omit brackets for function application; so the term “M N ” is the result of applying the functor M to the argument N (which is sometimes also written as “M (N )”). x:A⇒x:A
X⇒M :A
id
x : A/B, y : B ⇒ xy : A
Y, x : A, Z ⇒ N : B
Y, X, Z ⇒ N [M/x] : B A>
x : B, y : B\A ⇒ yx : A
Cut
A
A
to talk talk’ np\s
ask’b’ (np\s)/(np\s)
j’ np
f aintly
lex
faintly’ (np\s)\(np\s) faintly’talk’ np\s
ask’b’(faintly’talk’) np\s
lex A
A
talk’ np\s
ask’b’ (np\s)/(np\s) John
lex
to talk
ask’b’talk’ np\s
j’ np
lex f aintly
A>
faintly’ (np\s)\(np\s)
faintly’(ask’b’talk’) np\s
lex A
The derivation of the Right Node Raising construction (14) requires lifting of the two subjects to the category of quantifiers, followed by function composition of the lifted subjects with the transitive verbs. It is given in Figure 1.8 on page 24.
2.1.3 Left Node Raising Coordination of chunks that a phrase structure grammar (or BCG) would not analyze as constituents is pervasive in natural language. Right Node Raising constructions can informally be described as involving
22
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
deletion of right peripheral material in the first conjunct. The mirror image pattern exists as well. The following example, where clusters of arguments are conjoined, is a case in point. (16)
John introduced Bill to Sue and Harry to Sally.
Here apparently the sequence John introduced is missing in the second conjunct. A surface compositional derivation is possible in an extended Categorial Grammar if we make use of mirror images of the rules introduced above. Both backward type lifting T< and backward function composition B< are necessary here. Their semantics is identical to their forward oriented twins, and they differ from them just by the directionality of the slashes. (17)
a.
b.
X⇒M :A X ⇒ λx.xM : (B/A)\B X ⇒ M : A\B
T
b’ : np
24
John
lex
λx.xb’ : s/(np\s)
detests
T>
detest’ : (np\s)/np
λy.detest’yb’ : s/np
λz.(like’zj’) ∧ (detest’zb’) : s/np
lex B>
Conj
broccoli
lex
broccoli’ : np
A>
(like’broccoli’j’) ∧ (detest’broccoli’b’) : s
Bill
λy.yb’ (tvp/np)\tvp introduced John j’ np
lex
lex
λx.x pp/np
lex
b’ np
lex
T
Harry
B
λy.think’(like’ymary’)y np\s
john’ np
himself λRx.Rxx ((np\s)/np)\np\s
lex A
lex
know’ (np\s)/np λyz.know’(yz) (np\s)|np/np|np
G>
λz.know’z (np\s)|np
λv.know’vmary’ s|np Figure 2.12.
him λx.x np|np
lex A>
A>
Derivation for (41)
Binding of pronouns is achieved by identifying the anaphora slot that originates from the lexical entry of the pronoun with some np argument slot of a superordinate functor. This is implemented by means of the combinator Z. Since it operates on two-place functors, it comes in four directional variants.14 (45)
a.
b.
c.
14 Jacobson
X ⇒ M : A/B/C X ⇒ λxy.M (xy)y : A/B/C|B
Z> >
X ⇒ M : (B\A)/C X ⇒ λxy.M (xy)y : (B\A)/C|B X ⇒ M : C\A/B X ⇒ λxy.M (xy)y : C|B\A/B
Z< >
Z>
his mother mother’ np|np
λz.love’(mother’z)z np\s
lex A>
A>
every’man’(λz.love’(mother’z)z) s
In Jacobson’s “official” theory the formulation of Z is somewhat more complicated, but I skip over this here for ease of exposition. The purpose of the G-combinators is to pass unbound anaphora slots from subconstituents to superconstituents. As I have presented G up to now, this will only work for one single slot, but of course a 15 A
remark on terminology: I use the term “Skolem function” as synonymous to “function of type e, e” throughout this book, regardless whether or not an operation of “Skolemization” is involved.
103
The Problem of Anaphora
constituent may contain more than one unbound pronoun. Therefore a generalization of G is required as well. Jacobson assumes that there are infinitely many instances of G that are defined recursively. The definition given above represents the base case. The recursive rule takes the form of the following monotonicity rule (Jacobson assumes that the input to this inference scheme has to be obtained by applications of G> , G< , and G∗ only. I ignore this aspect for simplicity.) (47)
x:A⇒M :B y : A|C ⇒ λz.M [(yz)/x] : B|C
G∗
Written in tree format, this rule amounts to a form of hypothetical reasoning. To derive a conclusion B|C from a premise A|C, assume some hypothesis of type A, try to derive B from it, and discharge the hypothesis. The general scheme is given in Figure 2.13. y : A|C
1
yz : A .. . M :B λzM : B|C Figure 2.13.
G∗ , 1
G∗ in tree format
I illustrate the application of G∗ in example (48) below. To summarize this mechanism, suppose the argument in a functorargument structure contains an anaphora slot. Then either of two options apply: 1 The functor undergoes some version of G and the anaphora slot is thus projected to the superconstituent (as illustrated in Figure 2.12 on page 101). 2 The functor undergoes Z prior to applying it to its argument. As net effect, the anaphora slot in the argument is bound by some superordinate syntactic argument place of the functor (cf. (46)). As a consequence, Jacobson’s system agrees with Szabolcsi’s in the prediction that in a binding configuration, the binder always c-commands the pronoun.16 A welcome consequence of this is that the system han16 To
apply this view on binding for double object constructions, Jacobson also employs a wrapping operation in these cases, following basically the suggestions from Bach, 1979.
104 (48)
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
a. His mother loves his dog. b.
loves
lex
love’ (np\s)/np λrs.love’(rs) (np\s)|np/np|np his mother
λs.love’(dog’s) (np\s)|np
lex
mother’ np|np λx.xmother’ s|np/(np|np\s|np)
G>
dog’ np|np
G>
λuv.love’(dog’s)(uv) np|np\s|np λsuv.love’(dog’s)(uv) (np|np\s|np)|np
λzv.love’(dog’z)(mother’v) s|np|np
lex A>
1
love’(dog’s) np\s
T>
λyz.yzmother’ s|np|np/(np|np\s|np)|np
his dog
G< G∗ , 1 A>
dles basic cases of Weak Crossover correctly. Consider the contrast in (49). (49)
a. Every Englishmani loves hisi mother. b. *Hisi mother loves every Englishmani .
The binding in (49a) is achieved by applying Z to the verb loves before it is combined with the object. To get a similar binding effect in (49b), we would need a mirror image of Z, something like x : (A\B)/C ⇒ λyz.xz(yz) : (A|C\B)/C Incidentally, this is a directional version of Curry and Feys’ (1958) combinator S. Since, according to Jacobson, the grammar of English does not contain this combinator, the subject-object asymmetry observed in connection with crossover violations is correctly accounted for. Jacobson presents a considerable list of empirical arguments to show that the view “pronouns as identity maps” is in fact superior to both to the standard view using variables and to the Categorial treatments that locate the binding in the lexical entry of the pronoun. I will briefly review the most important arguments.
The Problem of Anaphora
105
Functional questions. Consider a question like (50a): (50)
a. Who does no Englishman admire? b. Margaret Thatcher. c. His mother-in-law.
There is a general agreement in the literature (cf. Groenendijk and Stokhof, 1984, Engdahl, 1986, Chierchia, 1993) that such questions are ambiguous between an individual reading (which elicits answers like (b)) and a functional reading (where we expect answers like (c)). The two readings can be paraphrased as (51)
a. Which individual x is such that every Englishman y admires x? b. Which Skolem function f is such that every Englishman y admires f y?
As a consequence of this observation, it is inevitable to assume that a wh-phrase like who is semantically ambiguous, binding either an individual gap or a Skolem function gap in its sister clause. The advantage of the Jacobsonian approach is that no further apparatus is needed to handle the ambiguity. The functional gap is bound by exactly the same means as an ordinary pronoun, namely by employing Z. (This is in clear contrast to the mentioned alternative approaches, where considerable extra apparatus like internally structured traces is needed.) In a Jacobsonian approach, the interrogative pronoun receives the two lexical entries below. Here Q is the syntactic category of questions, and the formula ?xϕ is to be interpreted as the question “Which x is such that ϕ”. (I remain neutral with regard to the correct semantics of questions since this has no bearing on the issue discussed here.) (52)
a. who – λP ?x.P x : Q/(s/np) b. who – λP ?f.P f : Q/(s/np|np)
The functional reading is now easily derived (see Figure 2.14 on the next page), using Z and the lexical entry for who in (52b). (I give a simplified treatment of auxiliary inversion since this issue is inessential here.) Since the binding of functional gaps is treated analogously to the binding of pronouns here, the approach predicts that functional gaps are subject to Weak Crossover effects. This is in fact the case (as for instance discussed at length in Chierchia, 1993). A functional reading is missing if subject and object are reversed: (53)
a. Which woman admires no Englishman?
106
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR no λQR¬∃x(Qx ∧ Rx) s/(np\s)/n does
who
lex
lex
lex
Englishman englishman’ n
λR¬∃x(englishman’x ∧ Rx) s/(np\s)
A>
λy.¬∃x(englishman’x ∧ admire’(yx)x) s/np|np ?y.¬∃x(englishman’x ∧ admire’(yx)x) q
Figure 2.14.
lex
(np\s)/np admire’ λyz.admire’(yz)z (np\s)/np|np
λy.¬∃x(englishman’x ∧ admire’(yx)x) s/np|np
λx.x s/s
λP ?f.P f q/(s/np|np)
admire
lex
Z< > B>
B>
A>
Derivation of the functional reading of (50a)
b. Margaret Thatcher. c. *His mother-in-law. The argument in favor of the Jacobsonian treatment can be further strengthened if the meaning of a constituent question is identified with the set of (denotations of) its correct constituent answers (as for instance proposed in Hausser and Zaefferer, 1978, Zaefferer, 1984 and, more recently, in Krifka, 1999). Then the answer his mother-in-law to the question Who does no Englishman admire has to be interpreted as the Skolem function mapping each individual to his mother-in-law. Jacobson’s system provides this as the basic meaning anyway, while a variable-based account would need an extra type shifting device that λ-abstracts over the variable corresponding to the pronoun.17
Sloppy inferences. Free relative clauses display a similar polymorphism. This can be observed most clearly in connection with so-called “sloppy” inferences as in (54) (taken from Jacobson, 2000 who attributes it to Tanya Reinhart): (54)
a. John will buy whatever Bill buys. b. Billi will buy hisi favorite car. c. Therefore Johnj will buy hisj favorite car.
In its most prominent reading, (54a) is to be interpreted as ∀xe (buy’xbill’ → buy’xjohn’) 17 Needless
to say this argument does not apply if the meaning of a question is identified with a set of propositions, as in Karttunen, 1977 or in Groenendijk and Stokhof, 1984.
The Problem of Anaphora
107
In this reading, the inference from (54a) and (b) to (c) is not valid. (54a) has another reading though that renders the argument valid. The critical reading can be represented as ∀fe,e (buy’(f bill’)bill’ → buy’(f john’)john’) A discussion of the semantics of free relatives would lead us too far afield here. The essential aspect of Jacobson’s analysis of the functional reading of free relatives is more or less parallel to her analysis of functional questions. In its basic meaning, a free relative pronoun like whatever binds an np gap inside the relative clause, and the free relative as a whole binds an np-position in the matrix clause. Jacobson assumes that whatever has a second reading where it binds an np|np-gap in the embedded clause and creates a free relative that binds such a position in the matrix clause. The meaning of whatever in this functional reading is basically a universal quantifier over Skolem functions. Again, binding is achieved by the same means as in the case of ordinary pronouns. In the example above, this means that the main verb both in the relative clause and in the matrix clause has to undergo Z. The same strategy can be applied if the object is sentential rather than nominal. So sentence (55a) is predicted to be ambiguous between the readings (b) and (c). (55)
a. Every Englishman believes whatever every Frenchman believes. b. ∀pt (∀x(french’x → bel’px) → ∀y(english’y → bel’py)) c. ∀Pe,t (∀x(french’x → bel’(P x)x) → ∀y(english’y → bel’(P x)y))
Under the second reading, the inference from (56a) and (b) to (c)— among others discussed by Chierchia, 1989 under the heading of “believe de se”—is correctly predicted to be valid. (56)
a. Every Englishman believes whatever every Frenchman believes. b. Every Frenchmani believes that hei should drink lots of red wine. c. Therefore, every Englishmanj believes that hej should drink lots of red wine.
Right Node Raising. In paragraph 2.1.2 (starting on page 21) I introduced a surface compositional Categorial treatment of Right Node Raising constructions like
108 (57)
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
John likes and Bill detests broccoli.
The analysis rests on the assumptions that the strings John likes and Bill detests form constituents that denote properties (the property to be liked by John and the property to be detested by Bill), and that the coordination particle and is polymorphic and denotes the join operation on properties (i.e., set intersection) in the construction above. Now consider a somewhat more complicated example where the object contains a bound pronoun: (58)
Every man loves but no man wants to marry his mother.
The sentence has a reading where the pronoun his is simultaneously bound by both quantifiers. It can be paraphrased by (59)
Every mani loves hisi mother but no manj wants to marry hisj mother.
If we analyze pronouns as variables and adopt the Categorial treatment of non-constituent coordination, this reading is underivable. The closest we can get at is the semantic representation (60)
λy(∀z(man’z → love’yz) ∧ ¬∃z(man’z ∧ wtm’yz))(mother’z)
Now λ-conversion would lead to the intended reading, but it is illicit without prior renaming of the quantified variables since y is not free for z here. With the renaming, we only obtain the reading where the pronoun is free. If one wants to maintain an analysis of pronouns as variables, one is forced to abandon the Categorial treatment of Right Node Raising. One has to adopt a reconstruction approach instead. So the input for the interpretation of (58) would be (61)
Every mani loves hisi mother but no mani wants to marry hisi mother.
This would give us the intended reading. However, a reconstruction approach without further constraints on the management of variable names leads to considerable overgeneration. For instance nothing prevents an interpretation of (62a) as (62b), where the pronoun is bound by the matrix subject in the first conjunct and by the local subject in the second one. Such a reading is impossible. (62)
a. Each boy believes that every man loves and no man marries his mother.
109
The Problem of Anaphora
b. Each boyi believes that every mank loves (hisi mother) and no mani marries hisi mother. A variable free analysis of pronouns is compatible with the general Categorial treatment of coordination, and the resulting analysis avoids both the undergeneration of the Categorial approach and the overgeneration of the reconstruction approach that comes with the variable analysis. The critical reading (59) is derived if the conjunction operates on the category s/np|np, i.e., the two conjuncts are interpreted as properties of Skolem functions. Besides, it is possible to do coordination in the category s/np and to pass the anaphora slot up to the entire coordinated structure. This admits binding from outside. The two derivations are given in Figure 2.15. There are no further options, so non-parallel binding patterns as in (62b) are excluded. loves every man λP ∀x(man’x → P x) s/(np\s)
lex
wants to marry
lex
love’ (np\s)/np λyzlove’(yz)z (np\s)/np|np
λy∀x(man’x → love’(yx)x) s/np|np
Z B>
no man λP ¬∃x(man’x ∧ P x) s/(np\s)
wtm’ (np\s)/np
lex
λyzwtm’(yz)z (np\s)/np|np
λy¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’(yx)x) s/np|np
λy.∀x(man’x → love’(yx)x) ∧ ¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’(yx)x) s/np|np
lex Z B> his mother
Conj
mother’ np|np
∀x(man’x → love’(mother’x)x) ∧ ¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’(mother’x)x) s
every man λP ∀x(man’x → P x) s/(np\s)
lex
loves love’ (np\s)/np
λy∀x(man’x → love’yx) s/np
lex B>
no man λP ¬∃x(man’x ∧ P x) s/(np\s)
lex
wants to marry wtm’ (np\s)/np
λy¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’yx) s/np
λy.∀x(man’x → love’yx) ∧ ¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’yx) s/np λzw.∀x(man’x → love’(zw)x) ∧ ¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’(zw)x) s|np/np|np
A>
lex
B>
Conj
G
his mother
λw.∀x(man’x → love’(mother’w)x) ∧ ¬∃x(man’x ∧ wtm’(mother’w)x) s|np
Figure 2.15.
lex
mother’ np|np
lex A>
Bound and free reading of (58)
i-within-i effects. In the literature, this is the common name for the observation that a pronoun inside a complex definite NP cannot be coreferential with the matrix NP. So the following coindexations lead to ungrammaticality:
110
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
(63)
a. *[The wife of heri childhood sweetheart]i left. b. *[The wife of heri sister’s childhood sweetheart]i left. c. *[The wife of the author of heri biography]i left.
(64)
a. *[Heri childhood sweetheart’s wife]i came to the party. b. *[The author of heri biography’s wife]i came to the party.
Neither is it possible that a quantificational determiner binds a pronoun inside its (complex) complement noun. So the following structures are excluded as well. (65)
a. *[Every wife of heri childhood sweetheart]i left. b. *[Every wife of heri sister’s childhood sweetheart]i left. c. *[Every wife of the author of heri biography]i left.
(66)
*[Every author of heri biography’s wife]i came to the party.
If indices are taken to be part of the theory, this suggests a simple generalization which Chomsky, 1981:212 formulates as follows: (67)
“*[γ . . . δ . . .], where γ and δ bear the same index.”
However, there are systematic exceptions to this generalization (which are accommodated by Chomsky in a complication of the above rule given in a footnote). The indicated indexation becomes possible if the pronoun sits inside a relative clause that modifies the head noun of the matrix NP: (68)
a. [The woman whoi married {heri sister’s / heri } childhood sweetheart]i left. b. [The woman whoi married the author of heri biography]i left.
(69)
a. [Every woman whoi married {heri sister’s / heri } childhood sweetheart]i left. b. [Every woman whoi married the author of heri biography]i left.
Under the Jacobsonian view on pronoun binding, this pattern is in fact expected. Let us start with a good example like (69b). The anaphora slot originating from the pronoun her is inherited by the NP the author of her biography by repeated application of G. So this NP will receive category np|np. The verb married undergoes Z before it is combined with its object. As a consequence, the VP married the author of her biography receives the interpretation “λx.marry’(author’(biography’x))x”.
The Problem of Anaphora
111
Starting from this VP meaning, the relative clause, the matrix NP and the matrix clause are assembled in the usual fashion, leading to the final meaning ∀x(woman’x ∧ marry’(author’(biography’x))x → leave’x) which corresponds to the coindexation in (69b). The same mechanism works ceteris paribus for all other good examples. So why is it impossible to assign the same meaning to (65c)? As far as the semantics goes, nothing prevents this. To get the reading in question, the 2-place predicate wife of has to undergo Z, just like married does in (69c). This is impossible though because the preconditions for the application of Z are defined in terms of syntactic categories rather than semantic types. While both married and wife of are semantically of type e, e, t, the former has category (np\s)/np and the latter category n/np. Only the former meets the preconditions for Z.
Paycheck pronouns. There is a class of pronoun occurrences that can neither be accommodated under “binding” nor under “coreference”. The name “paycheck pronouns” comes from the following example (from Karttunen, 1969). (70)
a. The man who gave his paycheck to his wife was wiser than the man who gave it to his mistress. b. The man whoi gave hisi paycheck to hisi wife was wiser than the man whoj gave hisj paycheck to hisj mistress.
Sentence (70a) has a reading which is synonymous with (70b). The example is problematic because the pronouns it does not have a coreferential/binding antecedent, even though it is evidently anaphorically related to the NP his paycheck in the first conjunct. There are two possible strategies to analyze this kind of anaphor in the literature. One may consider the critical pronoun as an E-type pronoun in the sense of Evans, 1977, i.e., as shorthand for a definite description. The paraphrase given in (70b) would thus be the main part of the analysis. This kind of analysis is incompatible with the program of surface compositionality since a certain syntactic copy mechanism has to be evoked before interpretation can proceed. Alternatively, one may assume that the paycheck pronoun it retrieves two meaning components from the context by means of anaphora resolution, namely a Skolem function and an individual, and it denotes the result of applying the function to this individual. In the above example, these components are the function f mapping individuals to their
112
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
paychecks, while the individual slot is bound by the relative pronoun who. Analyses along these lines were among others proposed in Cooper, 1979 and Engdahl, 1986. The latter kind of analysis has the advantage of being compositional. It is faced with three problems: 1 How can a pronoun take several antecedents simultaneously? 2 How can the NP his paycheck evoke a Skolem function as value of a subsequent paycheck pronoun? 3 How exactly does anaphora resolution of the two anaphoric components of paycheck pronouns proceed? Obviously, the second question receives an immediate answer if we assume Jacobson’s analysis—the meaning of his paycheck is the paycheckfunction. Let us turn attention to the first question. Syntactically, the paycheck pronoun in the example above takes his paycheck as one antecedent, and its second anaphoric slot is bound by a relative pronoun. The category of his paycheck is np|np, and the relative pronoun binds a gap of category np. The category of the paycheck pronoun should thus be (np|np)|(np|np)—an anaphor that takes first an np|np and second an np as antecedent and returns an np. This category is derivable from the basic pronoun category np|np by a variant of the well-established Geach rule: x : A|B ⇒G λyz.x(yz) : (A|C)|(B|C) | Applying this rule to the lexical entry of it gives us the derived sign (71)
it – λf.f : (np|np)|(np|np)
(Note that λf x.f x = λf.f due to the extensionality of functions.) So the first question is answered by assuming G| as a general type shifting rule. Given this, no extra apparatus is needed to answer the third question. The value for the Skolem function is retrieved by means of accidental coreference, while the individual component is bound by Z. A sample derivation for the critical clause in the simplified example in (72) is given in Figure 2.16 on the next page. The category of the clause is s|(np|np), i.e., it denotes a function from Skolem functions to propositions. The Skolem function slot is filled by the denotation of the antecedent phrase his paycheck. (72)
Every man spent his paycheck. Mary kept it.
113
The Problem of Anaphora kept M ary
lex
mary’ np λP.P mary’ s/(np\s)
lex
keep’ (np\s)/np λyz.keep’(yz)z (np\s)/np|np
T>
λuv.uvmary’ s|(np|np)/(np\s)|(np|np)
G>
λrsz.keep’(rsz)z (np\s)|(np|np)/(np|np)|(np|np)
G>
λsz.keep’(sz)z (np\s)|(np|np)
λv.keep’(vmary’)mary’ s|(np|np)
Figure 2.16.
it
Z< >
lex
λx.x np|np λf.f (np|np)|(np|np)
G| A>
A>
Derivation for (72)
Bach-Peters sentences. The above analysis of paycheck pronouns leads to a straightforward account of Bach-Peters sentences, i.e., sentences with two complex NPs each containing a pronoun that is coindexed with the other NP. A classical example is (73)
[The man who deserves iti ]k gets [the prize hek wants]i .
Even though this coindexation pattern leads us to expect a kind of circular reference (and thus pragmatic deviance), the construction is perfectly intelligible. The question is how the interpretation is to be derived in a compositional way. Let us first note some asymmetries in these constructions. To start with, the first NP is unrestricted with regard to the form of its determiner. It may be indefinite, definite (as above) or quantified: (74)
a. [A man who deserved iti ]k got [the prize hek wanted]i . b. [Men who deserved iti ]k got [the prizes theyk wanted]i . c. [Every man who deserved iti ]k got [the prize hek wanted]i .
On the other hand, the second matrix NP must be definite (or specific if indefinite). (75)
a. ??? [The man who deserves iti ]k gets [a prize hek wants]i . b. *[The man who deserves iti ]k gets [every prize hek wants]i .
This pattern is not really surprising; the attempted backward bindings in (75) are ruled out as mundane Weak Crossover violations. Definites and specific indefinites are known to be exempted from Weak Crossover.
114
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Furthermore, the first pronoun seems to be subject to Weak Crossover as well. Exchanging the pronoun and the gap corresponding to the relative pronoun in the first NP results in deviance. (76)
*[The man whom iti always evaded]k finally got [the prize hek wanted]i .
The second pronoun can occur both in subject position and in object position though. (77)
[The man who deserves iti ]k finally got [the prize that always evaded himk ]i .
The kind of subject-object asymmetry displayed by the first pronoun is also characteristic for paycheck pronouns: (78)
a. The man who sees [his brother]f regularly is better off than the man whoi never visits himf i . b. *The man who sees [his brother]f regularly is better off than the man whomi hef i is never visited by.
This asymmetry is predicted by Jacobson’s account; the relative pronoun binds the np slot of the paycheck pronoun just like an ordinary pronoun, and an object relative pronoun cannot bind an anaphora slot in the subject. Finally it should be observed that paycheck pronouns can precede their functional antecedent. This is not surprising either, given that accidental coreference does not involve binding and thus does not evoke Weak Crossover. (79)
The man whoi sees himf i regularly is better off than the man who never visits [his brother]f .
Putting these pieces together, we have evidence that the first pronoun in a Bach-Peters sentence is a paycheck pronoun, while the second one is an ordinary bound pronoun. This is exactly the analysis Jacobson proposes: In a sentence like (80), it is analyzed as a paycheck pronoun. Its Skolem function slot remains free on the level of sentence semantics— the category of the whole sentence is thus s|(np|np), while its np slot is bound by the relative pronoun (i.e., deserves undergoes Z). The pronoun him is treated as an ordinary pronoun that gets bound by the matrix subject (i.e., gets undergoes Z as well). The full derivation is given in Figure 2.17 on the facing page. (80)
Every man who deserves it gets the prize that pleases him.
lex who
man lex man’ n
every λP Q∀x.(P x → Qx) s/(np\s)/n
lex
n/(n\n) G>
(s/(np\s))|(np|np)/n|(np|np)
λP Qx.Qx ∧ P x (n\n)/(np\s)
T>
n|(np|np)/(n\n)|(np|np)
G>
lex
(np\s)/np|np G>
(n\n)|(np|np)/(np\s)|(np|np)
(np\s)|(np|np)/(np|np)|(np|np)
λf Q∀x(man’x ∧ deserve’(f x)x → Qx) (s/(np\s))|(np|np)
lex G>
(np\s)|(np|np)
(n\n)|(np|np) n|(np|np)
it Z< >
A>
A>
λx.x np|np (np|np)|(np|np) A>
G| A>
The Problem of Anaphora
deserves deserve’ (np\s)/np
pleases lex that
prize lex prize’ n
the lex gets lex get’ (np\s)/np (np\s)/np|np
Z< >
λP ιx.P x np/n np|np/n|np
G>
n/(n\n)
(s/np\s)\s
T>
λP Qx.Qx ∧ P x (n\n)/(np\s)
lex
(n\n)|np/(np\s)|np
n|np/(n\n)|np
(np\s)|np/np|np G> (n\n)|np
n|np np|np
np\s
please’ (np\s)/np
him G>
(np\s)|np
lex λx.x np|np
A>
A>
A>
A>
A>
T
∃] b. Every girl will be happy if some movie is shown. [∃ > ∀][∀ > ∃]
Fodor and Sag, 1982 suggest that indefinites are ambiguous between a quantificational and a referential (= specific) reading. This predicts though that indefinites take either local or global scope. The existence of intermediate readings has been established by several authors, however, notably by Farkas, 1981 and by Abusch, 1994. The following two examples are taken from Kratzer, 1998 (they are slight modifications of examples from Abusch, 1994): (44)
a. Every professor rewarded every student who read some book he had recommended. ∀ > ∃ > ∀ b. Every one of them moved to Stuttgart because some woman lived there. ∀ > ∃ > because
The conclusion that has to be drawn from the investigations of the authors mentioned and others is that the scope of indefinites is structurally unrestricted, even if local and global scope readings might be preferred pragmatically. The sharp contrast between indefinites and other quantifiers suggests that different mechanisms are at work here. Existential closure in the sense of DRT is an obvious candidate for a mechanism to assign scope to indefinites. It leads to mispredictions though if the indefinite has a non-trivial descriptive content. The following example from Reinhart, 1995 illustrates this point. (45)
a. If we invite some philosopher, Max will be offended. b. ∃x((philosopher’x ∧ invite’xwe’) → offended’max’)
Analysing (45a) in a DRT-style way without employing any further scoping mechanisms leads to a semantic representation like (45b) for the specific reading of (a), where the existential impact of the indefinite some philosopher takes wide scope, while the descriptive content remains in the antecedent of the conditional. As already observed in Heim, 1982 for a parallel example, (45b) does not represent the truth conditions of the specific reading of (45a). The former is true if there is one nonphilosopher, while (45a) in the wide-scope reading requires the existence of a philosopher x with the property that Max will be offended if we invite x. Since the existence of the non-philosopher Donald Duck is sufficient to verify (45b) but not (45a), this problem is sometimes called the Donald Duck problem in the literature.
247
Indefinites
To overcome this and related problems, several authors have proposed to employ choice functions for the analysis of indefinites (see for instance Reinhart, 1992, Reinhart, 1995, Reinhart, 1997, Kratzer, 1998, Winter, 1997). To cut a long story short, according to these theories, the semantic counterpart of an indefinite determiner is a variable over a choice function, i.e., a function that maps non-empty sets to one of their elements. This variable is subject to existential closure in a way akin to the treatment of free individual variables in DRT. (45a) would therefore come out as (46)
∃f (CH(f ) ∧ (invite’f (philosopher’)we’ → offended’max’))
The extension of the predicate constant CH is the set of choice functions of type e, t, e, i.e., ∀f (CH(f ) ↔ ∀P (∃xP x → P (f P ))) (46) in fact represents the truth conditions of (45a) in an adequate way. Generally speaking, the choice function approach solves two problems in one stroke. Since it uses unselective binding to assign scope to indefinites, it covers the fact that the scope of indefinites is structurally unrestricted. Second, the choice function mechanism makes sure that the existential impact of an indefinite is not unduly divorced from its descriptive content. On the other hand, the choice function approach faces at least two serious problems. First, what happens if the extension of the descriptive content of an indefinite is empty? Consider a slight variation of (45a): (47)
If we invite some Polish friend of mine, Max will be offended.
If the indefinite some Polish friend of mine receives a specific reading, the sentence can be paraphrased as There is a certain Polish friend of mine, and if we invite him, Max will be offended. Suppose I don’t have any Polish friends. In this scenario the sentence is false in the relevant reading. The choice function approach as such does not supply clear truth conditions in this case, since the argument of the choice function f in the term f (polish friend of mine’) denotes the empty set. Both Reinhart and Winter suggest mechanisms that make the smallest clause containing such a term false. This works fine for simple sentences such as (48)
We invited some Polish friend of mine.
248
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
This sentence is in fact false if there are no Polish friends of mine. This very fact would make (47) true though, while the sentence should come out as false. Let us call this problem the empty set problem. The second problem arises if the descriptive content of an indefinite contains a pronoun that is bound by some superordinate quantifier. The following example (from Abusch, 1994) can serve to elaborate this point. (49)
Every professori rewarded every student who read some book hei had recommended.
According to the choice function approach, the sentence should have a reading which can be represented as (50)
∃f (CH(f ) ∧ ∀x(professor’x → ∀y(student’y ∧ read’(f (λz.book’z ∧ recommend’zx)) → reward’yx)))
Suppose two professors, a and b, happened to recommend exactly the same books to their students. Then the expressions λz.book’z ∧ recommend’za and λz.book’z ∧ recommend’zb denote the same set, and thus the terms f (λz.book’z ∧ recommend’za) and f (λz.book’z ∧ recommend’zb) denote the same individual. So the reading that is described in (50) can be paraphrased as follows: Every professor has a favorite book. He recommends this book (possibly along with other books), and he awards students that read his favorite book. Furthermore, if two professors recommend the same books, they have the same favorite book. The last condition is entirely unnatural, and the sentence has no such reading. This problem is discussed among others by Kratzer, 1998 (who attributes the observation to Kai von Fintel and P. Casalegno) and Winter, 1997. Again, the literature contains several proposals regarding how to circumvent this kind of overgeneration, but so far no suggested solution is really satisfactory. I will call this problem the bound pronoun problem bound pronoun problem.
Indefinites
249
These and a variety of other problems for the choice function approach have been pointed out by several authors, see for instance Reniers, 1997, Geurts, 2000 and Endriss, 2001. The works mentioned also contain discussions of the possible solutions of these problems, and arguments why they are not fully satisfactory. The conclusion that has to be drawn from the discussion in the literature so far is that the choice function approach is not a viable alternative to a quantificational treatment of indefinites. So an adequate theory of indefinites should avoid the problems that were discussed in this section so far. At the same time, such a theory should take the fact into account that the scope taking behavior of indefinites is virtually unrestricted, and it should be able to deal with the peculiar pronoun binding abilities of indefinites which were the subject of the previous two sections. The theory I sketched there already meets the first two requirements. The scope of indefinites is syntactically handled by the rule ∧ , and its applicability is determined by the scope of static closure. In other words, an indefinite is predicted to take scope either over an entire sentence or over a constituent that is subject to static closure. If we assume that clause embedding operators like verbs of propositional attitude etc. apply static closure to their arguments, this generalization is empirically correct. The scope of ordinary quantifiers on the other hand is syntactically modeled by means of the rule qE in our type logical framework. While I only gave a formulation of this rule that does not take domains of its applicability into account, the clause boundedness of quantifier scope can easily be modeled by means of multimodal techniques, as for instance Morrill, 1994 demonstrates. While multimodality goes beyond the scope of this book, it is important to point out that the scoping mechanisms for indefinites and for quantifiers are independent from each other in our framework, and it is thus not surprising that they are subject to different constraints. In the previous two sections, I demonstrated how the “dynamic” binding abilities of indefinites can be modeled in TLG. It remains to be shown how this framework can take the descriptive content of indefinites into account, thereby avoiding the Donald Duck problem, the empty set problem, and the bound pronoun problem. The basic idea underlying my proposal can be sketched as follows. Recall that I assumed that an indefinite like something denotes the identity function over individuals. Let us extend this idea to other indefinites. For some philosopher, I assume that it denotes the identity function as well, but the domain of this function is confined to the set of philosophers. The application of this function to non-philosophers is not defined. This function combines with its linguistic environment in the
250
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
manner discussed above for indefinites with trivial descriptive content. A sentence like (51)
John invited some philosopher.
will denote a partial function f from individuals to truth values. Applying f to a philosopher that was invited by John yields the value 1. Applying f to a philosopher that was not invited by John yields the value 0. The application of f to non-philosophers is not defined. The sentence is true with respect to a sequence e iff there are individuals c such that applying f to c yields the value 1. This is the case iff there is at least one philosopher that was invited by John. Likewise, the static closure of the denotation of (51) is 1 iff there is a c such that f c = 1 and 0 otherwise. So the descriptive content of an indefinite is interpreted as a domain restriction for the argument place that corresponds to this indefinite. Existentially closing such an argument place has the effect of asserting the existence of an element of this domain. This makes sure that the descriptive content of an indefinite always has the same scope as its existential impact. Thus we avoid the Donald Duck problem. If this domain happens to be empty, both static closure and the global truth definition lead to falsehood, so there is no empty set problem either. Finally, since the descriptive content of an indefinite always has the same scope as its existential impact, a wide scope reading for the indefinite in (49) is excluded, since then the pronoun could not be bound by the quantifier. So the bound pronoun problem does not arise either.7 To formalize this idea, I extend the term language. ε-abstraction now optionally comes with an explicit domain of the function that is created. I thus add the following clauses to the syntax and the semantics of the term language respectively:
Definition 64 1 If x is a variable of type A, M is a term of type t, and N is a term of type B, then εxM N is a term of type B A . 2 εxM N M,g = {c, N M,g[x→c] |c ∈ Dom(A) ∧ M M,g[x→c] = 1} 7 A very similar analysis could probably be carried out within an unselective bindingframework if the descriptive content of indefinites is analyzed as a restriction on the corresponding variables, and if restricted variables are assumed to be undefined if their value does not obey their restriction. Farkas, 1999 points out that the Donald Duck problem can be avoided by using restricted variables, but she does not develop a semantics with a partial interpretation function.
Indefinites
251
So the denotation of εxM N is similar to the denotation of λxN , except that the domain of this function is restricted to the extension of λxM . The truth definition and the definition of semantic closure on denotations have to be adjusted accordingly. Basically, while existential closure of ε-arguments involves existential quantification over the whole domain of the type of the bound variable, we now only quantify over the extension of the restriction.
Definition 65 (Truth) 1 e |= α : t iff α = 1 2 e |= α : A|e iff e − 1 |= αe1 : A 3 e |= α : Ae iff ∃c ∈ Dom(α) : e |= αc : A
Definition 66 (Static closure of sentential denotations) 1 ↓ (α : t) = α : t 2 ↓ (α : S|e) = λc. ↓ (αc) :↓ S|e
3 ↓ (α : S e ) = {(↓ (αc) :↓ S)|c ∈ Dom(α)} There are some noteworthy facts concerning the behavior of restricted abstraction.
Fact 5 1 e |= εx1,M1 · · · εxn,Mn N : t iff e |= ∃x1 .M1 ∧· · ·∧∃xn .Mn ∧N 2 (↓ εxM N ) : t = ∃x(M ∧ ↓ N ) 3 εxM [((εzN O)x)/y] = εxN [x/z] M [(O[x/z])/y] provided x is free for z in O and N , and no variable in N that is bound on the left hand side is free on the right hand side Proof: Immediate from the definitions.
The first two parts simply state that existential closure of restricted εabstraction turns it into restricted existential quantification. The third part is basically a restricted version of β-reduction for ε-abstraction. If we apply an ε-abstract εzN O to a variable x that is itself ε-bound, we may perform β-reduction (subject to the usual restrictions) and thus simplify the function application to O[x/z], but the restriction N on z has to be passed on to the ε-operator that binds x. The side condition ensures that no variable in N may become unbound by this operation.
252
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Indefinites are still analyzed as identity functions, but these are created by restricted ε-abstraction, and the common noun phrase of an indefinite NP supplies the restriction on the abstract. So the lexical entry for the indefinite determiner some comes out as in (52). (The indefinite article a is treated analogously.) (52)
some – λP εxP x x : npnp /n
In the remainder of this section I will demonstrate that this treatment of the descriptive contents of indefinites adequately extends the treatment of indefinites of the previous two sections to the general case, and that it avoids the problems of the unselective binding approach and the choice function approach that were discussed above. Let us start the discussion with a simple example like (53)
John invited some philosopher.
The syntactic derivation does not differ from previous examples where the descriptive content of the indefinite was empty. It is given in Figure 6.13 for completeness. some
philosopher
lex
λP εxP x x npnp /n invited John john’ np
lex
lex
invite’ (np\s)/np
philosopher’ n
εxphilosopher’x x npnp (εxphilosopher’x x)y np
invite’((εxphilosopher’x x)y) np\s invite’((εxphilosopher’x x)y)john’ s
lex /E
i /E
\E
∧, I
εy.invite’((εxphilosopher’x x)y)john’ snp Figure 6.13.
Derivation of (53)
The semantic representation of the sentence is (54a). According to the third part of Fact 5, this is equivalent to (54b), which in turn has the same truth conditions as (54c). (54)
a. εy.invite’((εxphilospher’x x)y)john’
253
Indefinites
b. εyphilospher’y .invite’yjohn’ c. ∃y(philospher’y ∧ invite’yjohn’) I continue with another look at the interaction between indefinites and negation. Example (55) is analogous to (17) apart from the fact that someone has been changed to some farmer. (55)
Some farmer doesn’t beat his donkey.
The syntactic derivations of (55) are structurally identical to the four derivations of (17) (which are given in the figures 6.5 – 6.8). They lead to the four semantic representations in (56). (56)
a. ∼ πwεv.beat’(donkey of’w)((εxfarmer’x x)v) b. εv ∼ πw.beat’(donkey of’w)((εxfarmer’x x)v) c. ∼ εv.beat’(donkey of’((εxfarmer’x x)v)) ((εxfarmer’x x)v) d. εv ∼ beat’(donkey of’((εxfarmer’x x)v)) ((εxfarmer’x x)v)
According to the third part of Fact 5, these terms can be rewritten by the equivalent (57)
a. b. c. d.
∼ πwεvfarmer’v .beat’(donkey of’w)v εvfarmer’v ∼ πw.beat’(donkey of’w)v ∼ εvfarmer’v .beat’(donkey of’v)v εvfarmer’v ∼ beat’(donkey of’v)v
Some further elementary transformations render these representations truth conditionally equivalent to8 (58)
a. b. c. d.
πw¬∃v(farmer’v ∧ beat’(donkey of’w)v) πw∃v(farmer’v ∧ ¬beat’(donkey of’w)v) ¬∃v(farmer’v ∧ beat’(donkey of’v)v) ∃v(farmer’v ∧ ¬beat’(donkey of’v)v)
So in all four readings, the restriction on ε-abstraction is always turned into a restriction of an existentially quantified variable. This fact accounts for the absence of a Donald Duck problem in the present account. Reconsider the critical example (45), which is repeated here in 8 The calculation for (b) makes use of the fact that εx πyN and πyεx N are truth condiM M tionally equivalent if y is not free in M , which follows directly from the definitions.
254
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
a slightly modified form as (59a). Giving the indefinite wide scope over the conditional leads to the semantic representation (59b). (59)
a. If John invites some philosopher, Max will be offended. b. εx(invite’((εyphilosopher’y y)x)john’ → offended’max’)
Transferring the restriction on the inner ε to the outer ε leads to (60a). Expanding the abbreviational convention for → gives us (b), and employing the correspondence between the Dekker-connectives and the classical first order connectives makes this equivalent to (c). This in turn is truth conditionally equivalent to (d). (60)
a. b. c. d.
εxphilosopher’x (invite’xjohn’ → offended’max’) εxphilosopher’x ∼ (invite’xjohn’ & ∼ offended’max’) εxphilosopher’x ¬(invite’xjohn’ ∧ ¬offended’max’) ∃x(philosopher’x ∧ (invite’xjohn’ → offended’max’))
Note that the truth conditional equivalence between (59b) and (60d) holds for all models, including those where philosopher’ has an empty extension. If there are no philosophers, the sentence is predicted to be false. So the present account avoids the empty set problem. The semantic reason for this is the fact that the denotation of (59a) is a function from philosophers to truth values. If there are no philosophers, this is the empty function. A truth valued function is true according to our truth definition iff there are arguments for which the function returns the value 1. The empty function never returns any value, therefore the sentence is false in such a model. Let us now turn our attention to a run-of-the-mill conditional donkey sentence like the classical (61)
If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it.
The syntactic derivation of this sentence is analogous to the one for (21). It leads to the semantic representation (62)
εxfarmer’x εydonkey’y own’yx → πzπwbeat’wz
Expanding the definition of → leads to (63a). Dynamic binding makes this equivalent to (b). Employing the interaction between the Dekker connectives, static closure and the classical connectives allows us to rewrite (b) as (c). Using the second part of Fact 5 twice, we get (d), and this is first-order equivalent to (e).
255
Indefinites
(63)
a. b. c. d. e.
∼ (εxfarmer’x εydonkey’y own’yx & ∼ πzπwbeat’wz) ∼ εxfarmer’x εydonkey’y (own’yx & ∼ beat’yx) ¬ ↓ εxfarmer’x εydonkey’y (own’yx ∧ ¬beat’yx) ¬∃x(farmer’x ∧ ∃y(donkey’y ∧ own’yx ∧ ¬beat’yx)) ∀x(farmer’x → ∀y(donkey’y ∧ own’yx → beat’yx))
Quantificational donkey sentences are analyzed in a similar way. Apart from the form of the indefinite, the example in (64) is analogous to (30), which was discussed in the previous section. Again, the syntactic derivation is analogous (cf. Figure 6.12 on page 244), and we end up with the semantic representation in (64b,c) for the weak and the strong readings, respectively. (64)
a. Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. b. ∀z(↓ εx(farmer’z ∧ own’((εydonkey’y y)x)z) → ↓ (εx(farmer’z ∧ own’((εydonkey’y y)x)z) & πu.beat’uz)) c. ∀z(↓ εx(farmer’z ∧ own’((εydonkey’y y)x)z) → ↓ (εx(farmer’z ∧ own’((εydonkey’y y)x)z) → πu.beat’uz))
β-reduction leads to (65)
a. ∀z(↓ εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ↓ (εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) & πu.beat’uz)) b. ∀z(↓ εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ↓ (εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → πu.beat’uz))
Expanding the definition for → and performing dynamic binding (together with some minor routine manipulations) leads to the reformulations (66)
a. ∀z(↓ εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ↓ εxdonkey’x .(farmer’z ∧ own’xz) & beat’xz) b. ∀z(↓ εxdonkey’x (farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ∼↓ εxdonkey’x .(farmer’z ∧ own’xz) & ∼ beat’xz)
Crucially, all ε-operators in these representations are immediately preceded by ↓. Due to Fact 5, this amounts to existential quantification over the corresponding argument places, i.e., we get (67)
a. ∀z(↓ ∃x(donkey’x ∧ farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ↓ ∃x(donkey’x ∧ farmer’z ∧ own’xz) & beat’xz)
256
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
b. ∀z(↓ ∃x(donkey’x ∧ farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ∼↓ ∃x(donkey’x ∧ farmer’z ∧ own’xz) & ∼ beat’xz) This in turn is equivalent to (68)
a. ∀z(∃x(donkey’x ∧ farmer’z ∧ own’xz) → ∃x(donkey’x ∧ own’xz ∧ beat’xz)) b. ∀z(farmer’z → ∀x(donkey’x ∧ own’xz → beat’xz))
So to sum up this point, the domain restriction on ε-bound variables is always turned into a restriction on the corresponding existential quantifier when this ε-slot is existentially bound. This avoids the Donald Duck problem, and the treatment of donkey constructions that was proposed in the previous section carries over to indefinites with non-trivial restrictions without problems. It remains to be shown how the present system handles cases where the descriptive part of an indefinite contains a bound pronoun. A simple example is (69)
Every girli visited some boy that shei fancied.
In the indicated binding configuration, the subject quantifier must take scope over the indefinite object because otherwise the corresponding proof tree would not be well-formed (cf. the discussion of this issue on page 167 in Chapter 4). So the only derivation of (69) is the one that is sketched in Figure 6.14 on the next page.9 The semantic representation of (69) is thus (70)
∀x(↓ girl’{x} →↓ (girl’{x} & (λuεv.visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v)u){x}))
According to the laws of structural function application,this is equivalent to (71)
∀x(↓ girl’x →↓ (girl’x &εv.visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yx y)v)x))
β-reduction leads to (72)
∀x(↓ girl’x →↓ (girl’x &εvboy’v∧fancy’vx .visit’vx))
Some elementary transformations lead to the equivalent first order formula 9 I use only the weak reading of every here since the strong reading leads to an equivalent result.
(73) i
lex
∧, k
Figure 6.14.
Derivation of (69)
∀x(↓ girl’{x} →↓ (girl’{x} &(λuεv.visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v)u){x})) s
εv.visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v)u snp
visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v)u s
\E
qE, i
(εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v np
/E
k
λw.boy’w ∧ fancy’wu n
εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y npnp
lex
πzλw.boy’w ∧ fancy’wz n|np
visit’((εyboy’y∧fancy’yu y)v) np\s
visit’ (np\s)/np
λQ.∀x(↓ girl’{x} →↓ (girl’{x} & Q{x})) q(np, S, s)
[u]j np
visited
every girl
λP εyP y y npnp /n
some
boy that she f ancied
/E
|E, i
Indefinites
257
∀x(girl’x → ∃v(boy’v ∧ fancy’vx ∧ visit’vx))
According to these truth conditions, the sentence could also be true in a situation where two girls fancy the same boys but visit different boys. This is in line with the semantic intuitions. As discussed above, the
258
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
choice function approach furthermore predicts a non-existent reading where girls that fancy the same boys must visit the same boy to make the sentence true. It might be argued that this reading is actually there but hard to detect, because it is logically stronger than the ordinary narrow-scope reading (73). This is not the case anymore though if we use a downward monotonic quantifier in subject position, as in (74)
At most three girls visited a boy that they fancied.
According to the choice function approach, this sentence should have the reading given in (75a), which is truth-conditionally equivalent to (75b). (75)
a. ∃f.CH(f )∧|λx.girl’x∧visit’(f (λy.boy’y∧fancy’yx))x| ≤ 3 b. |λx.girl’x ∧ ∀y((∃z(boy’z ∧ fancy’zx) → boy’y ∧ fancy’yx) → visit’yx)| ≤ 3
Under the assumption that every girl fancies some boy, the prediction is that the sentence has a reading that is synonymous to At most three girls visited every boy that they fancied. Intuitions are fairly solid here that such a reading does not exist. Intuitively, this bound pronoun problem in connection with the choice function approach is similar to the Donald Duck problem of unselective binding: In both approaches, the interpretation of the descriptive content of an indefinite is divorced from its existential impact, while these two semantic components of indefinites always occur in tandem. Modelling the scope of indefinites by means of existential closure over partial functions covers this fact. It deserves to be mentioned that the bound pronoun problem of the choice function approach has been taken as evidence by Geurts, 2000 and by Endriss, 2001 that the scope of indefinites is assigned by means of some form of syntactic movement. The present solution proves that this conclusion is not inevitable. The scope of indefinites is assigned in an entirely surface compositional way here, without making reference to transformations between syntactic representations. (Recall that the manipulations of the semantic representation that I used in the discussion above are meaning preserving reformulations in the semantic representation language without any significance for the meanings that the theory assigns to natural language expressions.)
6.
Sluicing
Donkey anaphora is an empirical domain where the grammar of indefinites is intricately linked with the grammar of anaphora. The same
Indefinites
259
holds for the phenomenon of sluicing. After a brief recapitulation of the basic issues that arise in connection with this form of ellipsis, I will demonstrate that the LLC-treatment of anaphora in combination with the analysis of indefinites that was developed in the previous sections can easily be combined in a natural approach to sluicing. Briefly put, sluicing is a version of ellipsis where under certain contextual conditions, a bare wh-phrase stands proxy for an entire (embedded or matrix) question. The phenomenon was first systematically described in Ross, 1969, where also the name is coined. Typical examples are (76)
a. She’s reading something, but I don’t know what. b. Some guy knows how to get in here. Do you have any idea who? c. They hired a new system administrator. Guess who!
As with VP ellipsis, sluicing involves a source clause and a target clause. The source clause is typically a declarative clause which contains an indefinite NP. The target clause is (interpreted as) the question that is obtained if this indefinite is replaced by a wh-phrase. At the surface structure, everything but this wh-phrase is deleted. So on the face of it, the examples above are related (via deletion, reconstruction or whatever) to the non-elliptical counterparts (77)
a. She’s reading something, but I don’t know what she’s reading. b. Some guy knows how to get in here. Do you have any idea who knows how to get in here? c. They hired a new system administrator. Guess who they hired!
Interestingly, sluicing constructions remain grammatical in cases where the non-elliptical counterpart involves an island violation of the whphrase. Consider the following example (like some of the subsequent examples, it is taken from Merchant, 1999).10 (78)
10 I
a. They wanted to hire somebody who speaks a Balkan language, but I don’t know which.
follow the standard assumption that the deletion of the common noun phrase inside the wh-phrase (i.e., which instead of which Balkan language) is independent of sluicing, and I will ignore this kind of ellipsis.
260
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
b. *They wanted to hire somebody who speaks a Balkan language, but I don’t know which Balkan language they wanted to hire somebody who speaks. In the non-elliptical version (78b), the wh-phrase which Balkan language binds a gap inside a relative clause island. Therefore the example is ungrammatical. Nonetheless, the corresponding sluicing construction (78a) is impeccable. The same point can be made with regard to a whole range of syntactic island constraints. The following list is not meant to be exhaustive.
Adjunct islands. (79)
a. Ben will be mad if Abby talks to one of the teachers, but she couldn’t remember which. b. *Ben will be mad if Abby talks to one of the teachers, but she couldn’t remember which of the teachers Ben will be mad if Abby talks to. (from Merchant, 1999)
Complex NP islands. (80)
a. The administration has issued a statement that it is willing to meet with one of the student groups, but I’m not sure which one. b. *The administration has issued a statement that it is willing to meet with one of the student groups, but I’m not sure which one the administration has issued a statement that it is willing to meet with. (from Chung et al., 1995)
Sentential subject islands. (81)
a. That certain countries would vote against the resolution has been widely reported, but I’m not sure which ones. b. *That certain countries would vote against the resolution has been widely reported, but I’m not sure which ones that would vote against the resolution has been widely reported. (from Chung et al., 1995)
Embedded question islands. (82)
a. Sandy was trying to work out which students would be able to solve a certain problem, but she wouldn’t tell us which one.
Indefinites
261
b. *Sandy was trying to work out which students would be able to solve a certain problem, but she wouldn’t tell us which one Sandy was trying to work out which students would be able to solve. (from Chung et al., 1995)
Coordinate structure constraint. (83)
a. Bob ate dinner and saw a movie that night, but he didn’t say which. b. *Bob ate dinner and saw a movie that night, but he didn’t say which movie Bob ate dinner and saw that night. (from Merchant, 1999)
These facts suggest that sluicing does not involve syntactic operations like reconstruction or deletion. Rather, an approach that requires some form of semantic correspondence between source clause and target clause seems viable. On the other hand, the morphological form of the remnant wh-phrase is not arbitrary. In languages with overt case marking, the wh-phrase has to have the same case as the indefinite in the source. The following German example is from Ross, 1969, where this effect (as well the island insensitivity of sluicing) was first observed. (84)
a. Er will jemandem schmeicheln, aber sie wissen nicht {wem / *wen}. He wants someoneDAT flatter but they know not {whoDAT / *whoACC } b. Er will jemandem schmeicheln, aber sie wissen nicht, {wem / *wen} er schmeicheln will. he wants someoneDAT flatter but they know not {whoDAT / *whoACC } he flatter wants ‘He wants to flatter someone, but they don’t know who (he wants to flatter)’
(85)
a. Er will jemanden loben, aber sie wissen nicht {*wem / wen}. He wants someoneACC praise but they know not {*whoDAT / whoACC } b. Er will jemanden loben, aber sie wissen nicht, {*wem / wen} er loben will. he wants someoneACC flatter but they know not {*whoDAT / whoACC } he praise wants ‘He wants to praise someone, but they don’t know who (he wants to praise)’
262
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
The German verbs schmeicheln (‘to flatter’) and loben (‘to praise’) govern dative case and accusative case respectively on their object. The sluiced wh-phrases in the (a)-examples have to have the same case marking as the corresponding indefinites in the source clause. In other words, they must have the same case marking that they would have in the corresponding non-elliptical constructions. Under a pure identity-of-meaning approach, this morphological correspondence would seem mysterious. A third peculiarity of sluicing is the fact that the wh-phrase in the target clause and the corresponding indefinite in the source clause must have parallel scope. (This has been pointed out by Chung et al., 1995.) Recall that in (43b)—repeated here as (86a)—the indefinite some movie may have narrow scope or wide scope relative to the quantifier every girl. If this sentence is used as a source clause in sluicing, only the wide scope reading is possible. (86)
a. Every girl will be happy if some movie is shown. [∃ > ∀][∀ > ∃] b. Every girl will be happy if some movie is shown, but I don’t know which movie. [∃ > ∀] *[∀ > ∃]
As I will try to demonstrate in the remainder of this section, the theory of indefinites that was developed in the previous sections lends itself naturally to a TLG account of sluicing that is based on LLC and covers the empirical generalizations just discussed. Let us consider a simple example like (87)
John invited someone, but it is unclear who John invited.
The details of the semantics of questions that one adopts are of minor importance for the subsequent discussion. Therefore I remain neutral in this respect and represent the semantics of the sluiced question who John invited as (88a). The interrogative pronoun who has the lexical entry in (88b). So the missing piece of meaning that is required to interpret the ellipsis in (87) is (88c). (88)
a. ?x.invite’xjohn’ b. who – λP ?xP x : Q/(s/np) c. λx.invite’xjohn’
The denotation of the term in (88c) is identical to the denotation of the source clause John invited someone according to the semantics of indefinites given above. So the adequate reading can easily be derived via anaphora resolution if we assign the interrogative pronoun who the additional lexical entry
263
Indefinites
(89)
who – λP ?xP x : Q|(snp )
The semantics of the two readings of who is identical. In the sluicing version, who is an anaphor that needs a declarative clause containing an indefinite as antecedent to yield a question. This is just a formal reformulation of the informal description of sluicing patterns given above. Note that the only difference between the two lexical entries for who lies in the fact that they use different substructural versions of Intuitionistic implications. This is similar to the relation between the ordinary English auxiliaries and their VPE-counterparts. They too have pairwise identical meanings, and their categories differ with regard to the implication they use (vp/vp versus vp|vp). An analogous lexical ambiguity has to be assumed for all interrogative pronouns and interrogative determiners. What happens if the descriptive content of the indefinite is nontrivial, as in (90)? (90)
John invited some philosopher, but it is unclear which philosopher.
Here, the missing piece of meaning is also λx.invite’xjohn’, but the meaning of the source clause is the partial function εxphilosopher’x .invite’xjohn’ We can transform this partial function into a total function by means of an operation tot’, which is defined as 1 iff f c = 1 ∀f, c.tot’f c = 0 else So for the sluicing version of the interrogative determiner which we have to assume the lexical entry11 (91)
which – λP λR?x.P x ∧ tot’Rx : Q|(snp )/n
The (simplified) syntactic derivation for (90) is thus as in given in Figure 6.15 on the following page. The semantic representation which corresponds to this derivation is (92a), which is truth conditionally equivalent to (92b). (I treat but as synonymous with and.) 11 The
correct analysis of the semantic contribution of the restrictor of which is an intricate issue since it gives rise to a de re/de dicto ambiguity (cf. the discussion in Groenendijk and Stokhof, 1984, pp 89). I think that an analysis using Boolean conjunction as in the entry in (91) can be maintained if we admit free world indexing of common nouns in the restrictor of operators, which is arguably necessary anyway. The issue is orthogonal to our present concerns, so I omit further discussion.
264
some npnp /n
John np
lex
(np\s)/np
lex np\s
s [snp ]j s
npnp np
philosopher n
lex
/E
which
i
Q|(snp )/n
/E
\E
but
∧, i
(s\s)/s
k
it is unclear
Q|(snp )
s/Q
Q
lex
s s\s
s snp
∧, k
Figure 6.15.
lex
Derivation for (90)
\E
/E
philosopher n |E, j
/E
/e
lex
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
invited
lex
Indefinites
(92)
265
a. εx.(εyphilosopher’y invite’yjohn’)x∧ unclear’?z.philosopher’z∧ tot’(εyphilosopher’y invite’yjohn’)z b. ∃x.philosopher’x ∧ invite’xjohn’∧ unclear’?z.philosopher’z ∧ invite’zjohn’
Let us now change the example slightly to (93)
John invited some philosopher, but it is unclear who.
Here, the descriptive content of the indefinite in the source clause does not coincide with the restrictor of the wh-phrase in the target. Nevertheless, (93) is synonymous to (90). To derive this fact, I have to revise the lexical entry of who slightly. The example (93) demonstrates that the antecedents of who-sluices may be partial functions. Therefore, the totalizing function tot’ has to be incorporated into the semantics of sluicing-who as well. The modified entry is thus12 (94)
who – λP ?xtot’P x : Q|(snp )
Given this, the interpretation of (93) comes out as in (95a), which is truth-conditionally equivalent to (92b) as well. (95)
εx.(εyphilosopher’y invite’yjohn’)x∧ unclear’?z.tot’(εyphilosopher’y invite’yjohn’)z
The fact that the descriptive content of the source indefinite always serves as an additional restriction of the remnant wh-phrase in the sluiced question was first observed (and accounted for) in Chung et al., 1995. It provides a major stumbling block for any theory that analyzes sluicing via syntactic copying or deletion. The prime obstacle for a purely syntactic approach to sluicing is of course the lack of island sensitivity of sluiced constructions. Ross, 1969 suggested that syntactic island constraints only apply to phonetically non-empty structures. Versions of this idea recur at several places in the relevant literature, most recently—in a qualified form—in Merchant, 1999. A full discussion of how this problem is dealt with in TLG would of course require a discussion of islandhood within this framework. Like the problem of restrictions on quantifier scope, this issue goes beyond the 12 We
may as well assume that ordinary who has the same semantics and thus maintain the synonymy between the two readings, since the argument of who in ordinary questions is always a total function and the presence of tot’ does not make any difference.
266
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
scope of this work, and the interested reader is referred to the relevant discussion in Morrill, 1994. However, quite independently of the precise type logical analysis of islandhood that we adopt, it should be clear that sluicing is predicted to be insensitive to it. Consider again a relevant minimal pair such as (96)
a. They wanted to hire somebody who speaks a Balkan language, but I don’t know which one. b. *They wanted to hire somebody who speaks a Balkan language, but I don’t know which Balkan language they wanted to hire somebody who speaks.
The wh-phrase which one in (96a) has the syntactic category Q|(snp ). So it acts as a question as soon as the linguistic context supplies an antecedent of category snp —a clause containing a wide scope indefinite. The source clause in (96a) has this category, provided the indefinite a Balkan language is given wide scope there. The (ungrammatical) nonelliptical question in (96b) plays no role in the analysis of (96a), so no matter how we exclude (96b), this analysis will not affect the analysis of (96a). Instead, we predict that the locality constraints in sluicing exactly mirror the locality constraints for the scope of indefinites. Since the latter is in principle unbounded, so is sluicing. The discussion in the previous paragraph readily suggests an explanation of one half of the scope parallelism facts mentioned above. Note that the source clause in (96a), taken in isolation, is ambigous between a narrow scope reading and a wide scope reading of the indefinite a Balkan language. According to the present theory of indefiniteness, this semantic difference is reflected in the syntactic category of this clause. If the indefinite has narrow scope, the matrix clause has the category s. Wide scope of the indefinite corresponds to the category snp for the matrix clause, and only in this category may it serve as antecedent for the sluice in the second conjunct. These considerations derive one half of the scope parallelism constraint: the indefinite in the source clause that licenses sluicing must at least have scope over the entire source clause. We predict that it may have wider scope though. The derivation in Figure 6.15 on page 264 already provides an example. If cross-clausal binding of pronouns by indefinites is analyzed in the way done here, i.e., by assuming that the binding indefinite takes scope over the entire construction, this conclusion is desired and even inevitable. Nonetheless in examples like (97), only the reading where the indefinite and the wh-phrase take exactly parallel scope (i.e., some girl takes narrow scope with respect to knows) is possible.
Indefinites
(97)
267
Everybody knows that John wants to marry some girl, but John’s mother still doesn’t know which one (John wants to marry).
This might be due though to the fact that constituent questions trigger existential presuppositions. So the sluiced question in (97) triggers the presupposition John wants to marry some girl (with a girl having wide scope). If the indefinite takes wider scope than the wh-phrase, this presupposition has to be bound via bridging, while it can be directly bound if the scopes are parallel. Let us now turn to the third empirical generalization discussed above, the morphological parallelism between the licensing indefinite in the source clause and the remnant wh-phrase in the target. I repeat Ross’ example. (98)
a. Er will jemandem schmeicheln, aber sie wissen nicht {wem / *wen}. He wants someoneDAT flatter but they know not {whoDAT / *whoACC } ‘He wants to flatter someone, but they don’t know whom’ b. Er will jemanden loben, aber sie wissen nicht {*wem / wen}. He wants someoneACC praise but they know not {*whoDAT / whoACC } ‘He wants to praise someone, but they don’t know who (he wants to praise)
For a detailed discussion of the treatment of morphology in TLG, I have to refer the reader once again to Morrill, 1994, but for the present purposes a sketch will do. Suffice it to say that basic categories in a morphologically informed version of TLG are not unstructured atoms but (atomic) first order formulae, i.e., they consist of a predicate (unary predicates suffice) which takes complex terms as arguments. Morphological feature structures can be coded as first order terms. Underspecified aspects of the morphological structure can be represented as universally quantified individual variables. Morphological feature structures can thus be incorporated into a first order version of LLC+∧ . In such a first order version of TLG, the category of a dative NP in German will be an atomic formula of the form np(...dat...), where dat is a (possibly complex) term representing the case information “dative”. Let us abbreviate this category with np(dat). Likewise, the category of accusative NPs shall be sketched as np(acc). The German interrogative pronouns wem (dative) and wen (accusative) thus have the syntactic categories Q/(s/np(dat)) and Q/(s/np(acc)) respectively, i.e., they bind an np-position with the matching case information in the interrogative clause.
268
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
The case features of an indefinite NP appear at two places: at the argument and the result of the substructural implication in its syntactic category. An indefinite in dative case has the category np(dat)np(dat) , and likewise for other cases. A clause containing a wide-scope indefinite in dative thus has the category snp(dat) . The sluicing version of the dative interrogative pronoun has the category Q|(snp(dat) ), i.e., it requires a clause as antecedent that contains a wide scope indefinite with dative case. The ungrammatical versions of (98) are excluded because the case features of the anaphoric wh-phrase do not match with the corresponding feature in the antecedent. Among the analyses of sluicing from the literature, the present one is probably closest to the one from Chung et al., 1995. These authors adopt a DRT style unselective binding analysis of indefinites. According to them, sluicing invokes the copying of the LF of the IP of the source clause into the target clause. So after this copying operation, our previous example (99a) would receive approximately an LF as (99b). (99)
a. John invited some philosopher, but it is unclear who. b. ∃x[IP John invited some philosopherx ], but it is unclear whox [IP John invited some philosopherx ].
So the indefinite some philosopher introduces a free variable both in the source clause and the target clause. This variable is bound by unselective existential closure in the source and by the wh-operator in the target. If the source did not contain a free variable (i.e., an indefinite), vacuous binding in the target and thus ungrammaticality would ensue. Furthermore, the copying mechanism ensures that the descriptive content of the indefinite contributes to the interpretation of the target question. Finally, the connection between the wh-operator in the target and the variable that it binds is not established via movement and thus not predicted to be sensitive to island constraints. The main problem of Chung et al.’s (1995) approach is inherited from the unselective binding approach as such—it is susceptible to the Donald Duck problem. The example (100a) will receive the LF (100b). (100)
a. Max will be offended if we invite some philosopher, but it is unclear who. b. Max will be offended if we invite some philosopher, but it is unclear whox [IP Max will be offended if we invite some philosopherx ].
So the question part of this sentence can be paraphrased as which x is such that Max will be offended if x is a philosopher that we invite. Given
Indefinites
269
that Donald Duck is not a philosopher, “Donald Duck” should be a good answer to this question, but it isn’t. To sum up the discussion of sluicing, it can be said that the present theory covers the core facts of this kind of ellipsis in a simple and adequate way. However, our theory is essentially an identity-of-meaning theory, and the literature contains quite a few instances of sluicing that prima facie do not lend themselves easily to such an analysis. The most problematic cases are those where sluicing is not licensed by an overt indefinite; implicit existentially quantified arguments in the source clause can do that job as well. Chung et al., 1995 call this version of sluicing “sprouting”. The following illustrate this phenomenon (101)
a. She served the soup, but I don’t know to whom. (from Chung et al., 1995) b. She was reading, but I couldn’t make out what. (from Chung et al., 1995) c. He’s writing, but you can’t imagine where/why/how fast. (from Ross, 1969)
While it might be suggestive to assume that here, the licensing indefinite is somehow incorporated into the verb, such an analysis won’t work in examples like the following (also from Chung et al., 1995). (102)
Joan ate dinner but I don’t know with whom.
Here, the source clause does not entail that Joan ate dinner with someone, so the elided material in the target clause is not present in its entirety in the source clause, no matter what identity criterion we assume. So a plain identity-of-meaning theory like the present one has nothing to say about these cases. One might argue that these cases seem to involve some version of bridging, a phenomenon that is well attested in all classes of anaphora.
7.
Summary and Desiderata
The main purpose of this chapter was to demonstrate that the LLCanalysis of anaphoric pronouns can be extended to donkey pronouns. However, the difficult part of the analysis of donkey anaphora is not how to analyze pronouns but how to analyze indefinites, so most space was devoted to this problem. The chapter consisted of three parts. In the first part, I introduced Dekker’s Predicate Logic with Anaphora, and I showed how the PLA-analysis of indefinites can be combined with the LLC-treatment of pronouns. I thereby extended LLC to the Categorial logic LLC+∧ . Basically, indefinites are treated analogously to pronouns,
270
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
with the crucial difference that indefinites cannot be resolved. Another way to look at it is to say that I gave a type logical reformulation of Heim-style DRT, where free variables are replaced by identity functions. The Novelty Condition for indefinites is reconstructed as the absence of resolution rules. By translating Dekker’s analyses of the standard logical connectives of conjunction and negation into the term language accompanying LLC+∧ , we were able to reproduce the core of the DRT analysis of donkey anaphora within TLG. The second part focused on the issue of how the descriptive content of indefinites is to be analyzed. I suggested that indefinites in general denote (possibly partial) identity functions over individuals, and that the descriptive content of an indefinite supplies the domain of this function. These functions function-compose with their linguistic environment, and the descriptive content of an indefinite is thus inherited by the denotations of its super-constituents. I showed that this mechanism, paired with an operation of existential closure of argument slots, circumvents certain problems which plague other current theories of the scoping of indefinites. The last part of the chapter applied these findings to the problem of sluicing. I showed that the functional semantics of indefinites, paired with the LLC-mechanism of anaphora, lends itself naturally to a simple identity-of-meaning theory for sluicing. The basic empirical generalizations about this kind of ellipsis fall out immediately. Each of these three topics is of considerable complexity, and a host of issues has to remain untouched, let alone resolved. As for our account of donkey anaphora, this analysis basically reformulates “classical” Dynamic Semantics (i.e., Dynamic Predicate Logic in the sense of Groenendijk and Stokhof, 1991b), even though the philosophical underpinning is different. This of course means that the empirical weaknesses of DPL are inherited. Our account of the scoping of indefinites is confined to singular NPs. The issue becomes considerably more intricate if plural NPs are taken into account. Weak quantifiers like three men are as unrestricted in their scope taking behavior as singular indefinites, so one would expect the same mechanisms to be at work. However, with plural indefinites, two scoping mechanisms are involved. For instance, sentence (103a) (taken from Winter, 1997 who attributes it to Ruys, 1995) has a reading that can be paraphrased as (103b). (103)
a. If three relatives of mine die, I’ll inherit a fortune. b. There are three relatives of mine, and if each of them dies, I’ll inherit a fortune.
Indefinites
271
The specific reading of three relatives of mine thus actually involves two quantifiations, a wide scope existential quantification over sets of relatives of mine with the cardinality three, and a narrow scope universal quantification over elements of this set. It seems that the former is as unrestricted as the existential impact of singular indefinites, while the universal quantification is confined to the local clause (i.e., obeys the same constraints as other non-indefinite quantifiers). Reniers, 1997 gives a TLG analysis of these facts using two versions of Moortgat’s in situ binder. A reformulation into the present framework, where locally restricted quantification is handled by qE and unrestricted existential quantification by ∧ is easy to provide. However, a lot of issues remain open in in connection with this issue, such as the question of which quantifiers exactly can be subject to a double scope interpretation, and what properties qualify a determiner to belong to that class. These issues have been discussed in different theoretical frameworks in Szabolcsi, 1997 and Endriss, 2001. It remains to be seen whether the findings of these authors are compatible with the present theoretical setting. Finally, the analysis of sluicing presented here remains somewhat sketchy for two reasons. First, a detailed semantics of questions has to take intensionality into account. While there is no fundamental obstacle against a Curry-Howard style intensional semantics,13 the syntaxsemantics interface becomes considerably more complex and less transparent if relativization to possible worlds is added. Therefore, this issue was left out throughout this book. Second, I believe that an adequate treatment of sluicing requires a theory of presupposition resolution and a theory of bridging, and it has to take the effects of information structure into account. While there is no lack of formal approaches to these phenomena, they are completely independent of the type logical aspects of anaphora. The discussion was therefore confined to those aspects that have a direct bearing on the topic of the book as a whole.
13 See
for instance Morrill, 1994 for a fully worked out formalization.
References
Abusch, Dorit (1994). The scope of indefinites. Natural Language Semantics, 2:83–135. Ades, Anthony E. and Steedman, Mark J. (1982). On the order of words. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4:517–558. Ajdukiewicz, Kazimierz (1935). Die syntaktische Konnexit¨at. Studia Philosophica, 1:1–27. Anderson, Alan and Belnap, Nuel (1975). Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, volume I. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Anderson, Alan, Belnap, Nuel, and Dunn, Michael (1992). Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, volume II. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Andr´eka, Hajnal and Mikul´ as, Szabolcs (1994). Lambek Calculus and its relational semantics: Completeness and incompleteness. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 3:1–37. Bach, Emmon (1979). Control in Montague Grammar. Linguistic Inquiry, 10:515–531. Bach, Emmon and Partee, Barbara (1980). Anaphora and semantic structure. In Kreimann, K. J. and Ojeda, A. E., editors, Papers from the Parasession on Pronouns and Anaphora, pages 1–28. Chicago Linguistic Society. Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua (1953). A quasi-arithmetical notation for syntactic description. Language, 29:47–58. Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua, Gaifman, C., and Shamir, E. (1960). On categorial and phrase structure grammars. Bulletin of the Research Council of Israel, F(9):1–16. Barss, Andrew and Lasnik, Howard (1986). A note on anaphora and double objects. Linguistic Inquiry, 17:347–54. Barwise, Jon (1987). Noun phrases, generalized quantifiers and anaphora. In den fors, Peter G¨ ar editor, Generalized Quantifiers. Logical and Linguistic Approaches, pages 1–29. Reidel, Dordrecht. Bresnan, Joan (1994). Linear order vs. syntactic rank: Evidence from weak crossover. In Beals, Katie, Denton, Jeannette, Knippen, Bob, Melnar, Lynette, mi Suzuki, Hisa and Zeinfeld, Erika, editors, CLS 30-I: Papers from the Thirtieth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, pages 57–89. Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago. Bresnan, Joan (1998). Morphology competes with syntax: Explaining typological variation in weak crossover effects. In Barbosa, Pilar, Fox, Danny, Hagstrom, Paul, McGinnis, Martha, and Pesetsky, David, editors, Is the Best Good Enough, pages 59–92. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.).
273
274
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Buszkowski, Wojciech (1997). Mathematical linguistics and proof theory. In van Benthem, Johan and ter Meulen, Alice, editors, Handbook of Logic and Language, chapter 12, pages 683–736. Elsevier, MIT Press. Carpenter, Bob (1998). Type-Logical Semantics. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Carpenter, Bob (1999). The Turing-completeness of multimodal categorial grammars. Papers presented to Johan van Benthem in honor of his 50th birthday. European Summer School in Logic, Language and Information, Utrecht. Chierchia, Gennaro (1989). Anaphora and attitudes de se. In Bartsch, Renate, van Benthem, Johan, and van Emde Boas, Peter, editors, Semantics and Contextual Expression, pages 1–32. Foris, Dordrecht. Chierchia, Gennaro (1993). Questions with quantifiers. Natural Language Semantics, 1:181–234. Chomsky, Noam (1957). Syntactic Structures. Mouton, The Hague. Chomsky, Noam (1963). Formal properties of grammars. In Luce, R. Duncan, Bush, Robert R., and Galanter, Eugene, editors, Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, volume 2, pages 323–418. Wiley, New York. Chomsky, Noam (1976). Conditions on rules in grammar. Linguistic Analysis, 2:303– 351. Chomsky, Noam (1981). Lectures on Government and Binding. Foris, Dordrecht. Chung, Sandra, Ladusaw, William, and McCloskey, James (1995). Sluicing and Logical Form. Natural Language Semantics, 3:239–282. Cohen, Joel M. (1967). The equivalence of two concepts of Categorial Grammar. Information and Control, 10:475–484. Cooper, Robin (1979). The interpretation of pronouns. In Heny, Frank and Schnelle, Helmut, editors, Syntax and Semantics, volume 10. Academic Press, New York. Cooper, Robin (1983). Quantification and Syntactic Theory. Reidel, Dordrecht. Curry, Haskell and Feys, Robert (1958). Combinatory Logic, volume I. North Holland, Amsterdam. ¨ Dahl, Osten (1973). On so-called sloppy identity. Synthese, 26:81–112. Dalrymple, Mary, Lamping, John, Pereira, Fernando, and Saraswat, Vijay (1997). Quantifiers, anaphora and intensionality. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 6(3):219–273. Dalrymple, Mary, Shieber, Stuart M., and Pereira, Fernando (1991). Ellipsis and higher-order unification. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(4):399–452. de Groote, Philippe and Retor´e, Christian (1996). On the semantic reading of proofnets. In Kruijff, Geert-Jan, Morrill, Glyn, and Oehrle, Dick, editors, Proceedings of Formal Grammar, pages 57–70. ESSLLI, Prague. Dekker, Paul (2000). Grounding dynamic semantics. manuscript, University of Amsterdam. Doˇsen, Kosta (1992). A brief survey of frames for the Lambek Calculus. Zeitschrift f¨ ur Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 38:179–187. Dowty, David R., Wall, Robert E., and Peters, Stanley (1981). Introduction to Montague Semantics. Reidel, Dordrecht. Dunn, Michael (1986). Relevance logic and entailment. In Gabbay, Dov and Guenthner, Franz, editors, Handbook of Philosophical Logic, volume III, pages 177–224. Reidel, Dordrecht. Endriss, Cornelia (2001). The double scope of quantifier phrases. Master’s thesis, University of Potsdam. Engdahl, Elisabeth (1986). Constituent Questions. Reidel, Dordrecht.
Reference
275
Evans, Gareth (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7:467–536. Farkas, Donka (1981). Quantifier scope and syntactic islands. In Papers from the 17th Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, pages 59–66. University of Chicago. Farkas, Donka (1999). Scope matters. In von Heusinger, Klaus and Egli, Urs, editors, Reference and Anaphoric Relations, pages 79–108. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Fiengo, Robert and May, Robert (1994). Indices and Identity. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Fodor, Janet and Sag, Ivan (1982). Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and Philosophy, 5:355–398. Fox, Danny (1998). Locality in variable binding. In Barbosa, Pilar, Fox, Danny, Hagstrom, Paul, McGinnis, Martha, and Pesetsky, David, editors, Is the Best Good Enough. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Gamut, L. T. F. (1991). Logic, Language, and Meaning: Introduction to Logic, volume I. University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Gardent, Claire (2000). Deaccenting and higher-order unification. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 9(3):313–338. Gawron, Jean Mark and Peters, Stanley (1990). Anaphora and Quantification in Situation Semantics. CSLI, Stanford. Gazdar, Gerald, Klein, Ewan, Pullum, Geoffrey, and Sag, Ivan (1985). Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar. Basil Blackwell, Oxford. Geach, Peter (1972). A program for syntax. Synth`ese, 22:3.17. Gentzen, Gerhard (1935). Untersuchungen u ¨ber das logische Schließen. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 39:176–210, 405–431. Geurts, Bart (2000). Indefinites and choice functions. Linguistic Inquiry, 31:731–738. Girard, Jean-Yves (1987). Linear logic. Theoretical Computer Science, 50:1–102. Greibach, Sheila A. (1965). A new normal form theorem for context-free phrase structure grammars. Journal of the ACM, 12:42–52. Groenendijk, Jeroen and Stokhof, Martin (1984). Studies on the Semantics of Questions and the Pragmatics of Answers. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam. Groenendijk, Jeroen and Stokhof, Martin (1991a). Dynamic Montague Grammar. In Groenendijk, Jeroen, Stokhof, Martin, and Beaver, David Ian, editors, Quantification and Anaphora I, DYANA deliverable R2.2a. Amsterdam. Groenendijk, Jeroen and Stokhof, Martin (1991b). Dynamic Predicate Logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(1):39–100. Hankamer, Jorge and Sag, Ivan A. (1976). Deep and surface anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry, 7(3):391–426. Hardt, Daniel (1993). Verb Phrase Ellipsis: Form, Meaning, and Processing. PhD thesis, University of Pennsylvania. Hausser, Roland and Zaefferer, Dietmar (1978). Questions and answers in a contextdependent Montague Grammar. In Guenthner, Franz and Schmidt, Siegfried J., editors, Formal Semantics and Pragmatics for Natural Language, pages 339–58. Reidel, Dordrecht. Heim, Irene (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. PhD thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst. Heim, Irene and Kratzer, Angelika (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell, Oxford. Hepple, Mark (1990). The Grammar and Processing of Order and Dependency: A Categorial Approach. PhD thesis, University of Edinburgh.
276
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Hepple, Mark (1992). Command and domain constraints in a categorial theory of binding. In Dekker, Paul and Stokhof, Martin, editors, Proceedings of the Eighth Amsterdam Colloquium. University of Amsterdam. Hirschb¨ uhler, P. (1982). VP-deletion and Across-the-Board quantifier scope. In Pustejovsky, James and Sells, Peter, editors, Proceedings of NELS 12, pages 132–139. GLSA, Amherst. Howard, William A. (1969). The formulae-as-types notion of construction. manuscript, published in Seldin and Hindley, 1980. Jacobson, Pauline (1992a). Antecedent contained deletion in a variable-free semantics. In Barker, Chris and Dowty, David, editors, Proceedings of SALT 2, number 40 in Working Papers in Linguistics, pages 193–213. Ohio State University, Columbus. Jacobson, Pauline (1992b). Bach-Peters sentences in a variable-free semantics. In Dekker, Paul and Stokhof, Martin, editors, Proceedings of the Eighth Amsterdam Colloquium. University of Amsterdam. Jacobson, Pauline (1994a). Binding connectivity in copular sentences. In Harvey, Mandy and Santelmann, Lynn, editors, Proceedings of SALT IV, pages 161–178. Cornell University. Jacobson, Pauline (1994b). i-within-i effects in a variable-free semantics and a categorial syntax. In Dekker, Paul and Stokhof, Martin, editors, Proceedings of the Ninth Amsterdam Colloquium. University of Amsterdam. Jacobson, Pauline (1996a). The locality of interpretation: The case of binding and coordination. In Proceedings of SALT 6, Cornell Working Papers in Linguistics. Cornell University. Jacobson, Pauline (1996b). The syntax/semantics interface in categorial grammar. In Lappin, Shalom, editor, The Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, pages 89–116. Blackwell Publishers. Jacobson, Pauline (1999). Towards a variable-free semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22(2):117–184. Jacobson, Pauline (2000). Paycheck pronouns, Bach-Peters sentences, and variablefree semantics. Natural Language Semantics, 8(2):77–155. Jacobson, Pauline (2001). Binding without pronouns (and pronouns without binding). manuscript, Brown University. J¨ ager, Gerhard (2001). Anaphora and quantification in categorial grammar. In Moortgat, Michael, editor, Logical Aspects of Computational Linguistics, number 2014 in Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence, pages 70–89. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. Janssen, Theo (1997). Compositionality. In van Benthem, Johan and ter Meulen, Alice, editors, Handbook of Logic and Language, pages 417–473. Elsevier, MIT Press. Kamp, Hans (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In Groenendijk, Jeroen, Janssen, Theo, and Stokhof, Martin, editors, Formal Methods in the Study of Language, pages 277–322. Amsterdam. Kamp, Hans and Reyle, Uwe (1993). From Discourse to Logic. Introduction to Modeltheoretic Semantics of Natural Language, Formal Logic and Discourse Representation Theory. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Kanazawa, Makoto (1994). Weak vs. strong readings of donkey sentences and monotonicity inference in a dynamic setting. Linguistics and Philosophy, 17(2):109–158. Kandulski, M. (1988). The equivalence of nonassociative Lambek categorial grammars and context-free grammars. Zeitschrift f¨ ur Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 34:41–52.
Reference
277
Karttunen, Lauri (1969). Pronouns and variables. In Binnick, Robert I., Davison, Alice, Green, Georgia M., and Morgan, Jerry L., editors, Papers from the Fifth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, pages 108–115. University of Chicago. Karttunen, Lauri (1977). Syntax and semantics of questions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1:3–44. Kayne, Richard (1978). Logical types for natural language. UCLA Occasional Papers in Linguistics 3. Kayne, Richard (1994). The Antisymmetry of Syntax. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Keenan, Edward L. and Faltz, Leonard M. (1985). Boolean Semantics for Natural Language. Reidel, Dordrecht. Kehler, Andrew (1993). A discourse copying algorithm for ellipsis and anaphora resolution. In Proceedings of the Sixth Conference of the European Chapter of the Association for Computational Linguistics (EACL-93), pages 203–212. Utrecht. Kempson, Ruth M. and Cormack, Annabel (1983). Type lifting rules and VP anaphora. In Barlow, Michael T., Flickinger, Daniel P., and Wescoat, Michael T., editors, Proceedings of WCCFL 2, pages 140–152. . Kratzer, Angelika (1998). Scope or pseudscope? Are there wide scope indefinites? In Rothstein, Susan, editor, Events and Grammar, pages 163–196. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Krifka, Manfred (1999). For a structured account of questions and answers. In Smith, Carlota, editor, Proceedings to Workshop on Spoken and Written Text. University of Texas at Austin. Kurtonina, Natasha (1995). Frames and Labels: A Modal Analysis of Categorial Inference. PhD thesis, University of Utrecht. Lakoff, George (1971). Presupposition and relative well-formedness. In Steinberg, Danny D. and Jakobovits, Leon A., editors, Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguistics and Psychology, pages 329–340. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (UK). Lamarche, Fran¸cois and Retor´e, Christian (1996). Proof nets for the Lambek calculus. In Abrusci, V. Michele and Casadio, Claudia, editors, Third Roma Workshop: Proofs and Linguistic Categories, pages 241–262. CLUEB, Bologna. Lambek, Joachim (1958). The mathematics of sentence structure. American Mathematical Monthly, 65:154–170. Lambek, Joachim (1961). On the calculus of syntactic types. In Jakobson, Roman, editor, Structure of Language and Its Mathematical Aspects. Providence, RI. Lambek, Joachim (1988). Categorial and categorical grammar. In Oehrle, Richard T., Bach, Emmon, and Wheeler, Deirdre, editors, Categorial Grammars and Natural Language Structures, pages 297–317. Reidel, Dordrecht. Larson, Richard (1988). On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry, 19:335– 392. Lewis, David (1975). Adverbs of quantification. In Keenan, Edward L., editor, Formal Semantics, pages 3–15. Cambridge University Press. Link, Godehard (1991). Plural. In von Stechow, Arnim and Wunderlich, Dieter, editors, Handbook Semantics. de Gruyter, Berlin, New York. May, Robert (1985). Logical Form, its structure and derivation. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Merchant, Jason (1999). The syntax of silence: Sluicing, islands, and identity in ellipsis. PhD thesis, University of California at Santa Cruz. Montague, Richard (1974). Formal Philosophy. Yale University Press, New Haven.
278
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Moortgat, Michael (1988). Categorial Investigations. Logical and Linguistic Aspects of the Lambek Calculus. Foris, Dordrecht. Moortgat, Michael (1990). The quantification calculus: Questions of axiomatization. In Hendriks, Hermann and Moortgat, Michael, editors, Theories of flexibel interpretation, volume R1.2.A of Dyana deliverable. Centre of Cognitive Science, Edinburgh. Moortgat, Michael (1996a). Generalized quantification and discontinuous type constructors. In Sijtsma, Wietske and von Horck, Arthur, editors, Discontinuous Constituency. De Gruyter, Berlin. Moortgat, Michael (1996b). In situ binding: A modal analysis. In Dekker, Paul and Stokhof, Martin, editors, Proceedings or the Tenth Amsterdam Colloquium, pages 539–549. ILLC, University of Amsterdam. Moortgat, Michael (1997). Categorial type logics. In van Benthem, Johan and ter Meulen, Alice, editors, Handbook of Logic and Language, chapter 2, pages 93–178. Elsevier, MIT Press. Moot, Richard and Bernardi, Raffaella (2000). Generalized quantifiers in declarative and interrogative sentences. Proceedings of ICoS-2. Morrill, Glyn (1990). Intensionality and boundedness. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13:699–726. Morrill, Glyn (1994). Type Logical Grammar. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Morrill, Glyn (1995). Discontinuity in categorial grammar. Linguistics and Philosophy, 18:175–219. Morrill, Glyn (2000). Type-logical anaphora. Report de Recerca LSI-00-77-R, Departament de Llenguatges i Sistemes Inform`atics, Universitat Polit`ecnica de Catalunya. Morrill, Glyn, Leslie, Neil, Hepple, Mark, and Barry, Guy (1990). Categorial deduction and structural operations. In Barry, Guy and Morrill, Glyn, editors, Studies in Categorial Grammar, volume 5 of Edinburgh Working Papers in Cognitive Science, pages 1–21. University of Edinburgh. Morrill, Glyn and Merenciano, Joseph Maria (1996). Generalising discontinuity. Traitement Automatique des Langues, 37(2):119–143. Morrill, Glyn and Solias, Teresa (1993). Tuples, discontinuity and gapping. In Proceedings of the Meeting of the European Chapter of the Association of Computational Linguistics, pages 287–297. Utrecht. Pankrat’ev, Nikolai (1994). On the completeness of the Lambek Calculus with respect to relativized relational semantics. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 3:233–246. Partee, Barbara and Rooth, Mats (1983). Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity. In B¨ auerle, Rainer, Schwarze, Christoph, and von Stechow, Arnim, editors, Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language, pages 361–383. de Gruyter, Berlin, New York. Pentus, Martin (1993). Lambek grammars are context-free. In Proceedings of the 8th Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science. Montreal. Pentus, Martin (1994). Language completeness of the Lambek calculus. In Proceedings of the Ninth Annual IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, Montreal. Pentus, Martin (2003). Lambek calculus is NP-complete. Technical Report TR-2003 005, CUNY Ph.D. Program in Computer Science. Pereira, Fernando (1990). Categorial semantics and scoping. Computational Linguistics, 16(1):1–10.
Reference
279
Pesetsky, David (1995). Zero Syntax: Experiencers and Cascades. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Postal, Paul (1972). A global constraint on pronominalization. Linguistic Inquiry, 3:5–59. Pullum, Geoffrey K. (1991). Footloose and context-free. In The Great Eskimo Vocabulary Hoax, pages 131–138. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Reinhart, Tanya (1976). The Syntactic Domain of Anaphora. PhD thesis, MIT, Cambridge (Mass.). Reinhart, Tanya (1983). Anaphora and Semantic Interpretation. Croom Helm. Reinhart, Tanya (1992). Wh-in-situ: an apparent paradox. In Dekker, Paul, editor, Proceedings of the Eighth Amsterdam Colloquium, pages 483–491. University of Amsterdam. Reinhart, Tanya (1995). Interface Strategies. OTS Working Papers. Research Institute for Language and Speech, Utrecht University. Reinhart, Tanya (1997). Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between QR and choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy, 20:335–397. Reniers, Fabien (1997). How to (s)cope with indefinites. Master’s thesis, University of Utrecht. Restall, Greg (2000). An Introduction to Substructural Logics. Routledge, London, New York. Roorda, Dirk (1991). Resource logics: Proof-theoretical investigations. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam. Rooth, Mats (1987). Noun phrase interpretation in Montague Grammar, File Change Semantics, and Situation Semantics. In G¨ardenfors, Peter, editor, Generalized Quantifiers. Reidel, Dordrecht. Rooth, Mats (1992). Ellipsis redundancy and reduction redundancy. In Berman, Steve and Hestvik, Arild, editors, Proceedings of the Stuttgart Ellipsis Workshop, Arbeitspapiere des SFB 340 “Sprachtheoretische Grundlagen f¨ ur die Computerlinguistik”, Nr. 29. IBM Heidelberg. Ross, John (1969). Guess who? In Binnick, Robert I., Davison, Alice, Green, Georgia M., and Morgan, Jerry L., editors, Papers from the Fifth Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, pages 252–286. University of Chicago. Ruys, Eddy (1995). Weak crossover as a scope phenomenon. manuscript, Utrecht University. Sag, Ivan A. (1976). Deletion and Logical Form. PhD thesis, MIT. Seldin, Jonathan P. and Hindley, J. Roger, editors (1980). To H. B. Curry: Essays on Combinatory Logic, Lambda Calculus and Formalism. Academic Press Limited. Sem, Helle Frisak (1994). VP-ellipsis and DRT. In DYANA deliverable, Task 2.2, subtask 4. University of Amsterdam. Shieber, Stuart M., Pereira, Fernando, and Dalrymple, Mary (1996). Interaction of scope and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy, 19(5):527–552. Solias, Teresa (1992). Gram´ aticas Categoriales, Coordinaci´ on Generalizada y Elisi´ on. PhD thesis, Universidad Aut´ onoma de Madrid. Stalnaker, Robert (1998). On the representation of context. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 7(1):3–19. Staudacher, Peter (1987). Zur Semantik indefiniter Nominalphrasen. In Asbach-Schnitker, Brigitte and Roggenhofer, Johannes, editors, Neuere Forschungen zur Wortbildung und Historiographie der Linguistik. Festgabe f¨ ur Herbert E. Brekle zum 50. Geburtstag, pages 239–258. Narr, T¨ ubingen.
280
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Steedman, Mark (1990). Gapping as constituent coordination. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13(2):207–263. Steedman, Mark (1996). Surface Structure and Interpretation. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Steedman, Mark (2000). The Syntactic Process. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.). Szabolcsi, Anna (1989). Bound variables in syntax (are there any?). In Bartsch, Renate, van Benthem, Johan, and van Emde Boas, Peter, editors, Semantics and Contextual Expressions, pages 295–318. Foris. Szabolcsi, Anna (1992). Combinatory grammar and projection from the lexicon. In Sag, Ivan and Szablocsi, Anna, editors, Lexical Matters. CSLI, Stanford. Szabolcsi, Anna (1997). Strategies for scope taking. In Szabolcsi, Anna, editor, Ways of Scope Taking, pages 109–154. Kluwer, Dordrecht. Szabolcsi, Anna (2000). Cross-sentential anaphora in Combinatory Grammar. manuscript, New York University. Thrainsson, Hoskuldur (1976). Reflexives and subjunctives in Icelandic. In Proceedings of NELS 6, pages 225–239. Universite du Quebec a Montreal. Tiede, Hans-Joerg (1999). Deductive Systems and Grammars: Proofs as Grammatical Structures. PhD thesis, Indiana University. van Benthem, Johan (1991). Language in Action. Elsevier, Amsterdam. van Benthem, Johan (1983). The semantics of variety in categorial grammar. Report 83–29, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby. Versmissen, Koen (1991). Discontinuous type constructors in Categorial Grammar. Master’s thesis, University of Utrecht. Wansing, Heinrich Theodor (1993). The Logic of Information Structures. Springer Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 681. Springer Verlag, Berlin. Wescoat, Michael T. (1989). Sloppy readings with embedded antecedents. manuscript, Stanford University. Williams, Edwin (1997). Blocking and anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry, 28(4):577–628. Winter, Yoad (1997). Choice functions and the scopal semantics of indefinites. Linguistics and Philopsophy, 20:399–467. Zaefferer, Dietmar (1984). Frageausdr¨ ucke und Fragen im Deutschen: Zu ihrer Syntax, Semantik und Pragmatik. Fink, M¨ unchen.
About the Author
Gerhard J¨ ager is professor of linguistics at the University of Bielefeld.
281
Index
214, 219, 222, 223, 225–227, 232, 238, 256, 260, 267–269 deep a., 181 donkey a., x, xi, 256, 267, 268 surface a., 181 Anderson, 28 Andreka, 61 antecedent, 6, 8–10, 13, 14, 23, 25, 26, 28–31, 37, 39, 41, 49, 52, 55, 58, 59, 61, 63, 64, 70, 73, 83, 84, 88, 91, 93, 95, 97, 109, 110, 112, 114, 118–122, 137, 138, 142–145, 155, 156, 165, 167, 172, 175–178, 181, 183– 193, 196, 198, 200, 202–205, 209, 210, 222, 244, 260, 263, 264, 266 application (function a.), 4, 6, 8–10, 13, 17, 23, 25, 31, 41, 42, 54, 56, 75, 80, 100, 108, 121, 125, 133, 135–137, 139, 140, 148, 162, 163, 176, 185, 186, 190, 238, 247–249 structural function a., 240, 254 argument category, 2–4, 45 arrow, 31, 54, 55, 59, 146, 147 assignment function, 32, 71, 73, 206, 215, 225, 228, 229 associative, 31, 54, 57–59, 61, 65, 83, 86, 144, 148, 150, 155 auxiliary, 33, 69, 103, 173, 182, 184, 185, 198, 199, 201, 204, 209, 210, 227, 229, 261 auxiliary inversion, 103, 173 axiom, 6–10, 13, 23, 25, 27, 42, 54–56, 59, 92, 93, 122, 146–148, 150 -atic presentation, 54, 146, 148 -atic system, 54–56, 59, 147, 148
α-equivalence, 33, 141 αβη-equivalence, 33, 141 β-redex, 135, 137, 139 β-reduction, 33, 36, 131, 135, 140, 163, 249, 253, 254 ε-operator, 225, 249 η-redex, 135, 136, 139, 140, 162 η-reduction, 33, 36, 43, 45 λ-abstraction, 31, 71, 81, 136, 137 λ-calculus, ix, x, 4, 12, 13, 16, 31, 33, 34, 36–38, 43, 67, 70, 73, 135, 141, 221, 224, 225 λ-conversion, 33, 106 A, 6, 9, 13, 14, 99–101, 103, 107, 110 A’-movement, 45 Abusch, 244, 246 accessibility relation, 57 accidental coreference, 110, 112, 156, 172, 176, 177 accusative, 76, 78, 86, 88, 158, 259, 265 Ades, 65 adjective, 3, 122 adverb, 3, 158, 212 Ajdukiewicz, 3, 65 alphabet, 5, 7, 12, 42 ambiguity, 15, 74, 103, 117, 134, 154, 158, 176, 185–187, 191, 194, 195, 200, 204, 207, 212, 261 lexical a., 15, 53, 116, 261 scope a., 163, 166 spurious a., 15, 53, 207, 208, 229 structural a., 14, 15, 53, 74, 143, 237 anaphora, ix–xii, 30, 67, 69, 70, 74, 79, 86, 91–93, 96, 98, 100, 101, 106, 108, 109, 112, 114–118, 121, 122, 125, 137, 142, 143, 145, 150, 151, 155, 165, 167, 168, 170–173, 177–179, 181, 183– 187, 193, 198, 204, 211, 213,
283
284
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR identity a., 6, 9, 15, 17, 26, 41, 49, 51, 54, 58, 62, 119, 130, 131, 137, 146, 147 scheme, 6, 25, 26, 49, 54, 62
B, 77, 103, 107 Bach, 83, 102, 171, 172 Bach-Peters sentence, 110, 112, 154, 176 Bar-Hillel, 1, 2, 9, 10, 61, 65 Barry, 39, 92 Barss, 168 Barwise, 212 Basic Categorial Grammar, 1, 3–11, 13, 15–17, 19–21, 23, 25, 26, 40– 43, 46, 49, 56, 61, 62, 65 BCG, see Basic Categorial Grammar Belnap, 28 Bernardi, 165 binary reduction lemma, 63, 64, 73 binding, 45, 69, 70, 74–79, 81, 82, 84, 91– 93, 98, 99, 102–104, 106, 108, 109, 112, 114, 151, 154, 156, 157, 159–161, 165–172, 175– 179, 203, 206, 209, 214, 226, 232, 238, 243, 247, 254, 264, 266 backward b., 111, 171, 172, 175–178, 214 dynamic b., 211, 217, 234, 243, 247, 252, 253 Interpretation Rule, 94–96 Theory, 75, 237 Principle A, 78 Principle B, 78, 88, 91, 209 Principle C, 75 Bresnan, 168, 176 bridging, 265, 267, 269 implicational b., 203 Buszkowski, 9, 62 c-command, 16, 75, 76, 88, 91, 114, 116, 118, 151, 167–172, 178 canonical model, 60, 150, 151 Carpenter, 45, 66, 163, 165 Cartesian product, 119 Casalegno, 246 cataphora, 172, 176, 177 Categorial Grammar, ix, x, 1, 4, 11, 16, 17, 22, 23, 25, 46, 61, 65–67, 92, 96, 114, 171, 200 CFG, see context free grammar CG, see Categorial Grammar Chierchia, 102, 103, 105 choice function, 244, 245 approach, 245–247, 250, 254, 256 Chomsky, 43, 61, 65, 75, 108, 167 conjecture, 61 Chung, 258, 260, 263, 266, 267
Church-Rosser property, 36, 163 classical logic, 26, 27, 29, 30, 38 Cohen, 61 combinator, 17, 21–23, 46–49, 73, 75–77, 81, 96, 98, 102, 114, 116, 151, 160, 178 Combinatory Categorial Grammar, 96 combinatory logic, 22, 74 common noun, 3, 5, 239, 241, 249, 257, 261 complete, 58, 60, 61, 142, 144 completeness, xi, 59, 61, 149–151, 250 complexity, 9, 34, 50, 60, 61, 65, 122, 123, 125, 130, 141, 150, 224, 268 compositional interpretation, 12, 16 compositionality, 73, 143 principle of c., 67, 72, 219 surface c., 109 concatenation, 3, 83, 85, 86 confluent, 141, 142 constituent, 13, 14, 16, 18, 20, 21, 30, 46, 71, 76, 81, 83–85, 91, 94, 96–98, 100, 104, 105, 121, 122, 168, 170, 171, 183, 202, 213, 247, 264, 268 constructive logic, 28 context free grammar, 9–11, 61, 62, 64–66 Contraction, 26, 27, 29, 30, 49, 74, 79, 92, 93, 95, 117–119, 121, 122, 137 Cooper, 81, 109, 163 coordinate structure constraint, 258 coordination, 17–22, 43, 48, 68, 74, 78, 105, 106, 115, 158, 182, 183, 199, 205, 210 Boolean c., 18, 19 non-constituent c., 46, 106 scheme, 18–20 Cormack, 200 curried, 4, 239 Curry, 21, 22, 35, 49, 102, 178 Curry-Howard correspondence, 31, 34, 35, 38, 48, 65, 114, 118 Curry-Howard isomorphism, 35 Cut, xi, 6–10, 13–17, 25–27, 36, 41, 49–54, 56, 58, 62–64, 95, 96, 116, 118, 120–126, 128, 130–132, 142, 147, 148, 150–152, 160, 162, 222 elimination, xi, 49, 51, 54, 95, 96, 116, 118, 122, 123, 125, 130, 142, 160–162, 222 Dahl, 191, 205 Dalrymple, 69, 189, 190, 202, 205, 206 dative, 259, 265, 266 de Groote, 66 de-accenting, 192, 206
Index decidability, xi, 49, 50, 53, 96, 118, 123, 125, 160, 161, 175, 176, 222, 224 decidable, 8, 9, 53, 95, 118, 123, 142 Dekker, 212–214, 216, 218, 219, 222, 224– 226, 228, 229, 232–234, 243, 252, 267 denotation, 1, 4, 11, 12, 20, 56, 71, 110, 156, 173, 176, 185, 215, 218– 220, 224, 225, 228, 239, 248, 252, 260 designated category, 7–10, 42, 61, 64, 65 determiner, 43, 107, 111, 164, 211, 212, 240, 241, 243, 245, 249, 269 interrogative d., 175, 261 discontinuity, 79, 83 Discourse Representation Structure, 16, 216 Discourse Representation Theory, 16, 74, 212, 213, 216, 218, 222, 225, 239, 244, 245, 266, 267 disjunction, 26, 35 Doˇsen, 58, 61 dominance, 16, 127, 128 immediate d., 127 Donald Duck problem, 244, 247, 248, 251, 254, 256, 266 donkey anaphora, see anaphora donkey sentence, 211, 212, 217, 218, 226, 234, 238–240, 243, 252, 253 double object construction, 76, 102, 151, 158, 170, 171, 182 Dowty, x DRS, see Discourse Representation Structure DRT, see Discourse Representation Theory Dunn, 28 dynamic binding, see binding Dynamic Predicate Logic, 218, 226, 227, 234, 268 Dynamic Semantics, 212–216, 239, 268 E-type pronoun, 109 ellipsis, x, xi, 19, 69, 79, 114–116, 154, 177, 178, 181–196, 200, 202, 204–207, 209, 210, 224, 256, 257, 260, 266, 268 antecedent contained deletion, 183, 184 cascaded e., 187, 188, 194, 199 coordination e., 68, 115, 183 gapping, 177, 182, 183 sluicing, x, xi, 183, 184, 213, 256, 257, 259–261, 263, 264, 266– 269 stripping, 115, 182, 183
285 verb phrase e., x, xi, 69, 181, 182, 184, 185, 193, 194, 196, 198– 203, 205–210, 257 empty abstraction, 37, 38 empty category, 16, 171 empty set problem, 245, 247, 248, 252 Endriss, 247, 256, 269 Engdahl, 102, 109 Evans, 109 existential closure, 216, 218, 228, 244, 245, 249, 256, 266, 268 extensionality, 33, 110 f-command, 172 Faltz, 68, 69 Familiarity Condition, 222 Farkas, 244, 248 Feys, 21, 22, 35, 49, 102, 178 Fiengo, 185, 191, 199, 202, 203 finite reading property, xi, 53, 95, 96, 118, 153, 160, 161, 222, 224 Fodor, 243, 244 Fox, 191 frame, 57, 60, 61 associative f., 57–59, 61, 144, 148, 150 conditions, 60 language f., 61 relational f., 60 ternary f., 56–58, 60, 61 free relative, 104 Frege, 65 function composition, 21, 22, 46, 47, 49, 77, 81, 96 function space formation, 11, 119, 221 functional gap, 103 functional question, 102, 104, 116, 121, 154, 175, 179 functional reading, 102–104 G, 98–101, 107, 108, 110, 114, 115, 152– 155 Gaifman, 9, 10, 61, 65 Gamut, x Gardent, 206 Gawron, 78, 168, 178, 188–190, 194, 195, 199 Gazdar, 73 Geach, 47 Geach rule, 47, 73, 76, 96, 98, 110, 153 gender, 97, 237 generative capacity, 65, 66, 73 Gentzen, 26 Gentzen style sequent presentation, see sequent presentation Gentzen style sequent system, see sequent system Geurts, 246, 256
286
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
Girard, 2, 29, 66 glue language, 67, 73, 74 goal category, 2 Greibach, 10 Greibach Normal Form, 10, 61 Groenendijk, 102, 104, 212, 218, 261, 268 Hankamer, 181 Hardt, 185, 192, 202, 203 Hausser, 104 Heim, 16, 70, 212, 244 Hepple, 39, 66, 92–97, 115–119, 142 Hirschb¨ uhler, 199–201 Howard, 35 Husserl, 65 hyperintensional, 142 hyperintensionality, 145 hypothetical reasoning, 25, 43, 45, 86, 100, 156, 157, 165, 172, 178, 188 i-within-i effects, 106, 154 in situ binder, see q indefinite, x, xi, 111, 164, 184, 196, 211– 214, 218–224, 226, 227, 229, 232, 233, 236–241, 243–251, 253, 254, 256, 257, 259–261, 263–268 intension, 142 interpolation, 62, 63 interpretation function, 32, 57, 59, 215, 224, 248 Intuitionistic Logic, ix, 25, 27–31, 33–35, 38, 92, 118, 121, 135 island, 46, 257–259, 263, 266 adjunct i., 258 complex NP i., 258 embedded question i., 258 sentential subject i., 258 J¨ ager, 122 Jacobson, 74, 92, 96, 97, 100, 102–104, 108, 109, 112, 114–117, 119, 151–155, 167, 175, 176, 183 Janssen, 17 Kamp, 16, 74, 212, 218 Kanazawa, 212 Kandulski, 66 Karttunen, 104, 109 Kayne, 168, 171 Keenan, 68, 69 Kehler, 191 Kempson, 200 Kleene star, 7 Klein, 73 Kratzer, 16, 70, 244–246
Krifka, 104 Kurtonina, 60, 61 L, xi, 17, 23, 25, 26, 29–31, 39–43, 45, 46, 48–51, 53–66, 68, 72, 73, 80, 83, 84, 86, 92, 94–96, 117, 119, 121–125, 127, 132, 141, 142, 145–150, 155, 158–160, 163, 201 labeled deduction, 13, 34 Ladusaw, 258, 260, 263, 266, 267 Lakoff, 206 Lamarche, 66 Lambek, ix, 17, 23, 25, 31, 39, 49, 50, 53– 55, 65, 160 Lambek calculus, see L Lambek Calculus with Limited Contraction, see LLC Lamping, 69 Larson, 171 Lasnik, 168 left node raising, 21 left rule, 49, 119 Leslie, 39, 92 Lewis, 212 lexicon, 5, 7–9, 12, 14, 17, 70, 72, 74, 91, 95, 100, 115, 117, 154, 178, 184, 199 LF, see Logical Form lifting, 20–22, 46, 48, 53, 54, 73, 76, 81, 96, 98, 160 Linear Logic, xi, 2, 29, 30, 37–39, 49, 68, 70, 92, 114, 115 Link, 173 LLC, 117, 119–121, 123–126, 128, 130, 135, 137, 138, 141–144, 146, 148–155, 157, 160–163, 171, 172, 178, 179, 181, 184, 188, 189, 193, 198, 201, 206, 210, 218–222, 232, 256, 260, 265, 267, 268 LLC+∧ , 221, 222, 232, 265, 267 Logical Form, 16, 70, 266 logical rule, 26–29, 41, 43, 49, 51–53, 56, 86, 119, 122, 160, 222 m-command, 16 many pronoun puzzle, 199 May, 163, 185, 191, 199, 202, 203 McCloskey, 258, 260, 263, 266, 267 meaning multiplication, 70, 181, 183, 184 Merchant, 183, 257–259, 263 Merenciano, 83 Mikulas, 61 modal logic, xi, 57 model, xi, 12, 16, 56–60, 71, 92, 142, 144, 145, 148–151, 157, 181, 215, 220, 225, 232, 252
Index theory, xi, 56, 142 Modus Ponens, 25, 53, 121, 155, 185 monostratal, 16, 172 Monotonicity, 26–28, 30, 68, 143 Montague, 12, 20, 65, 69, 163, 211, 213 Montague Grammar, 211 Moortgat, xiii, xiv, 46, 49, 66, 79–84, 87, 88, 115, 157, 159, 165, 172, 195, 268 Moot, 165 Morrill, xiv, 39, 45, 46, 66, 79, 82–84, 86, 91, 92, 115, 118, 122, 154, 166, 176, 184, 247, 263, 265, 269 multimodal, xii, 46, 49, 66, 83, 96, 119, 165, 247 Multimodal Type Logical Grammar, 66 natural deduction, 25, 26, 34, 40, 66, 71– 73, 80, 85, 86, 88, 94, 121, 125, 127, 130, 132, 134, 135, 142, 155, 160–162, 221–223 negation, xii, 27, 214, 216, 226–229, 232, 235, 250, 267 nominative, 76, 78, 88 non-associative, xii, 31, 60, 65, 66, 83 non-subject sloppy reading, 203, 209 normalization, 36, 68, 137, 138, 141, 162 β-n., 36, 135, 136, 138–140, 162, 163 η-n., 36, 135, 137, 140, 162, 163, 187 proof n., 36, 135, 141, 142, 163 strong n., xi, 36, 137, 222 term n., 36, 163 Novelty Condition, 222, 267 NP-complete, 65 number (morph. category), 97 pair formation, 32, 33, 37, 83 Pankrat’ev, 61 parallelism, 65, 181, 202–208, 264, 265 Partee, 47, 172 Peirce’s Law, 27 Pentus, 61, 62, 65, 66, 73 Pereira, 69, 165, 189, 190, 202, 205, 206 Permutation, 26, 27, 29, 30, 46, 49, 92, 95, 194 Pesetsky, 168, 171 Peters, x, 78, 168, 178, 188–190, 194, 195, 199 pied piping, 80 pied-piped, 78, 175 PLA, see Predicate Logic with Anaphora plural, 173, 268 polymorphic, 17, 18, 78, 105, 158, 175, 204, 210, 227, 228, 235, 241 polymorphism, 104, 199, 224, 227, 235 possessive, 100, 172 possible world semantics, 57
287 Postal, 167 pre-order, 54, 55, 61 precedence, 5, 97, 127, 128, 151, 167–172, 179 Predicate Logic with Anaphora, 213–219, 224, 227, 232, 234, 235, 239, 243, 267 presupposition, 264, 265, 269 product, 25, 28, 29, 37, 38, 43, 49, 54– 56, 59, 60, 62, 83, 84, 86, 119, 121, 130, 131, 134, 144, 146– 148, 150, 163 elimination, 37, 131 pronoun, 69, 70, 77–79, 84, 86–88, 91, 93, 96, 98–100, 102–112, 114, 116, 117, 143, 154–156, 166– 173, 175–179, 185–188, 191, 192, 195, 196, 199, 202, 203, 205, 208–211, 213–222, 224, 226, 229, 232, 233, 236–239, 246–248 anaphoric p., 74 bound p., 70, 77–79, 81, 82, 105, 112, 165–167, 175, 176, 211, 254, 256 problem, 246–248, 256 donkey p., xi, 235, 267 interrogative p., 103, 175, 260, 261, 265, 266 paycheck p., 109, 110, 112, 177 reflexive p., 68, 74–78, 81, 82, 84, 86, 88, 94, 127, 145, 171, 172 relative p., 43, 45, 46, 104, 109–112, 156, 167, 184 proof nets, xii, 66 proof search, 9, 50, 53, 96, 118, 123 proof tree, 13, 14, 40, 41, 72, 127–135, 137, 138, 140, 141, 155, 161– 163, 165, 166, 190, 193, 194, 196, 198, 222, 254 proposition, 1, 23, 27, 29, 35, 97, 104, 110, 112, 206 prosodic labeling, 85 Pullum, 65, 73 q, 80–84, 115, 157, 159–166, 169, 174, 193–198, 201, 226, 229–231, 241–243, 247, 255, 268, 269 Quantifer Raising, 163 quantification, x, xi, 155, 157, 159, 160, 193, 195, 212, 214–217, 232, 249, 253, 268, 269 quantifier, 19–21, 70, 79–81, 84, 91, 99, 104, 105, 157–160, 163–169, 172, 175, 178, 179, 193–196, 198, 200, 201, 207, 210, 211, 214, 216, 219, 224, 226, 232,
288
ANAPHORA AND TYPE LOGICAL GRAMMAR
238, 241, 243, 244, 246–248, 254, 260, 263, 268, 269 downward monotonic q., 256 existential q., 212, 215, 217, 225, 226, 254 interrogative q., 173 Quantifying In, 163 recipe, 39, 43, 66, 68, 73 reconstruction, 106, 170, 172, 173, 175– 177, 179, 185, 213, 257, 259 recursion, 3, 72, 227 reflexive, see pronoun Reinhart, 78, 79, 167–169, 202, 244, 245 relative clause, 43, 70, 71, 91, 104, 105, 108, 167, 183, 198, 257 Relevant Logic, 28–30, 37, 38, 49, 118 Reniers, 246, 268 residuation, 56, 83, 84 resource conscious logic, 28 resource sensitivity, 67 Restall, 30 Retor´e, 66 Reyle, 16, 74, 212 right node raising, 21, 105, 106, 154, 182, 183 right rule, 49, 119 Roorda, 62, 63, 66 Rooth, 47, 202, 203, 205, 212 Ross, 257, 259, 263, 267 rule of proof, 49, 121, 122, 125 rule of use, 49, 119, 122, 125 Russell, 65 Ruys, 268 Sag, 73, 181, 184, 193, 199, 205, 243, 244 Saraswat, 69 satisfaction, 213–216, 224 scope, xi, 45, 46, 79, 81, 83, 91, 160, 163–167, 190, 193–196, 198– 202, 207, 208, 210–212, 214, 216, 225–227, 229, 232, 235– 238, 240, 241, 243–245, 247, 248, 251, 254, 256, 260, 263– 266, 268 double s., 269 inversion, 201 parallelism, 264 secondary wrap, see wrapping Sem, 191 semantic composition, 4, 65, 68, 70, 74, 79, 86, 93, 97, 185, 188, 219 sentential category, 223, 224 sequent, 6–10, 13, 15, 25, 31, 34, 36, 37, 39, 41, 49–51, 53–56, 58, 60– 65, 72, 73, 80, 94, 95, 99, 119,
123–125, 130–132, 134, 142– 144, 147–149, 151, 153, 159, 160, 189, 221 calculus, 53 derivation, 13, 63, 66, 147, 198 format, 40, 41, 131, 132, 160, 166, 198 presentation, 6, 39, 41, 49–51, 55, 120, 123, 142, 146, 161 proof, 49–51, 123, 134 rule, 23, 50, 53, 73, 95, 121, 131, 132, 160, 161 system, 49, 50, 125, 142, 147, 148 Shamir, 9, 10, 61, 65 Shieber, 69, 189, 190, 202, 205, 206 Skolem function, 100, 102–104, 106, 109, 110, 112, 154, 173, 177, 186, 191, 220 slash, ix, 4, 5, 22, 23, 25, 65, 83, 86, 95–97, 119, 125, 142, 143, 150, 151 elimination, 25, 41, 46, 55, 56, 62, 86, 95, 143 introduction, 25, 41, 43, 46, 47, 49, 55, 56, 62, 86, 95 sloppy, 104, 154, 177, 178, 185, 187–192, 195, 196, 198, 202, 203, 205, 207–210 Solias, 83, 184 sound, 39, 58, 60, 142, 144 soundness, 58, 146, 148 specific, 111, 200, 235, 241, 244, 245, 268 sprouting, 267 Stalnaker, 213, 222 static closure, 227–229, 232, 233, 241, 247, 248, 252 Staudacher, 212 Steedman, 17, 22, 49, 65, 184 Stokhof, 102, 104, 212, 218, 261, 268 strict, 79, 97, 119, 185–189, 191, 192, 195, 196, 201, 205, 207–209, 224 string recognition, 8, 9, 43, 61, 64 structural hierarchy, 17, 26, 29, 30 structural rule, 26–30, 37, 38, 46, 49, 60, 68, 74, 92, 118, 119, 137, 194 subformula, 9, 49, 50, 53 property, 50, 96, 118, 122, 123, 142, 161 substructural logic, 65, 198 succedent, 6, 9, 13, 14, 25, 28, 38, 39, 49, 52, 54, 58, 73, 121, 142 surface structure, 16, 17, 257 syntactic composition, 4, 145 Szabolcsi, 68, 69, 74–79, 81, 82, 87, 88, 102, 115, 213, 269 S, 49 T, 20–22, 75, 99, 101, 110 Tarski, 218
Index
289
Thrainsson, 172 Tiede, 66 TLG, see Type Logical Grammar topicalization, 45, 175 trace, 16, 43, 45, 103 transformation, 16, 17, 41, 51, 135, 256 truth, 1, 11, 12, 18, 27, 28, 58, 59, 71, 142, 148, 150, 151, 212, 214, 216, 219, 220, 224, 225, 228, 233, 235, 248, 251, 252, 261 conditions, 207, 213, 214, 216, 217, 219, 224, 225, 227, 229, 237, 244, 245, 250, 254 Turing, 66 Type Logical Grammar, ix–xii, 1, 17, 23, 35, 43, 45, 46, 49, 66, 67, 70– 73, 79, 91, 115, 117, 157, 166, 172, 194, 198, 201, 213, 218, 219, 224, 225, 234, 235, 239, 247, 260, 263, 265, 267, 268
validity, 58, 59, 142, 146 van Benthem, ix, 61, 65 variable free, 67, 70, 73, 74, 106, 203, 213, 224 Versmissen, 83 von Fintel, 246 VPE, see ellipsis, verb phrase
underspecification, 69 unselective binding, 240, 245, 248, 250, 256, 266
Z, 98–103, 105, 107, 108, 110, 112, 114– 116, 151, 152, 155 Zaefferer, 104
Wall, x Wansing, 38 weak crossover, 102, 103, 111, 112, 154, 167, 177, 178 Wescoat, 202 Williams, 176, 178, 191 Winter, 245, 246, 268 wrapping, 76, 81, 83, 84, 88, 91, 92, 102, 151, 171 secondary wrap, 83–86
TRENDS IN LOGIC 1.
G. Schurz: The Is-Ought Problem. An Investigation in Philosophical Logic. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4410-3
2.
E. Ejerhed and S. Lindstr¨om (eds.): Logic, Action and Cognition. Essays in Philosophical Logic. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4560-6
3.
H. Wansing: Displaying Modal Logic. 1998
ISBN 0-7923-5205-X
4.
P. H´ajek: Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. 1998
ISBN 0-7923-5238-6
5.
H.J. Ohlbach and U. Reyle (eds.): Logic, Language and Reasoning. Essays in Honour of Dov Gabbay. 1999 ISBN 0-7923-5687-X
6.
K. Do˘sen: Cut Elimination in Categories. 2000
7.
R.L.O. Cignoli, I.M.L. D’Ottaviano and D. Mundici: Algebraic Foundations of manyvalued Reasoning. 2000 ISBN 0-7923-6009-5
8.
E.P. Klement, R. Mesiar and E. Pap: Triangular Norms. 2000
ISBN 0-7923-5720-5
ISBN 0-7923-6416-3 9.
V.F. Hendricks: The Convergence of Scientific Knowledge. A View From the Limit. 2001 ISBN 0-7923-6929-7
10.
J. Czelakowski: Protoalgebraic Logics. 2001
11.
G. Gerla: Fuzzy Logic. Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning. 2001 ISBN 0-7923-6941-6
ISBN 0-7923-6940-8
12.
M. Fitting: Types, Tableaus, and G¨odel’s God. 2002
ISBN 1-4020-0604-7
13.
F. Paoli: Substructural Logics: A Primer. 2002
ISBN 1-4020-0605-5
14.
S. Ghilardi and M. Zawadowki: Sheaves, Games, and Model Completions. A Categorical Approach to Nonclassical Propositional Logics. 2002 ISBN 1-4020-0660-8
15.
G. Coletti and R. Scozzafava: Probabilistic Logic in a Coherent Setting. 2002 ISBN 1-4020-0917-8; Pb: 1-4020-0970-4
16.
P. Kawalec: Structural Reliabilism. Inductive Logic as a Theory of Justification. 2002 ISBN 1-4020-1013-3
17.
B. L¨owe, W. Malzkorn and T. R¨asch (eds.): Foundations of the Formal Sciences II. Applications of Mathematical Logic in Philosophy and Linguistics, Papers of a conference held in Bonn, November 10-13, 2000. 2003 ISBN 1-4020-1154-7
18.
R.J.G.B. de Queiroz (ed.): Logic for Concurrency and Synchronisation. 2003 ISBN 1-4020-1270-5
19.
A. Marcja and C. Toffalori: A Guide to Classical and Modern Model Theory. 2003 ISBN 1-4020-1330-2; Pb 1-4020-1331-0
20.
S.E. Rodabaugh and E.P. Klement (eds.): Topological and Algebraic Structures in Fuzzy Sets. A Handbook of Recent Developments in the Mathematics of Fuzzy Sets. 2003 ISBN 1-4020-1515-1; Pb 1-4020-1516-X
21.
V.F. Hendricks and J. Malinowski: Trends in Logic. 50 Years Studia Logica. 2003 ISBN 1-4020-1601-8
22.
M. Dalla Chiara, R. Giuntini and R Greechie: Reasoning in Quantum Theory. Sharp and Unsharp Quantum Logics. 2004 ISBN 1-4020-1978-5
23.
B. L¨owe, B. Piwinger and T. R¨asch (eds.): Classical and New Paradigms of Computation and their Complexity Hierarchies. Papers of the conference “Foundations of the Formal Sciences III” held in Vienna, September 21–24, 2001. 2004 ISBN 1-4020-2775-3
24.
G. J¨ager: Anaphora and Type Logical Grammar. 2005
springeronline.com
ISBN 1-4020-3904-2