LONDON MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY LECTURE NOTE SERIES Managing Editor: Professor J.W.S. Cassels, Department of Pure Mathematic...
112 downloads
522 Views
2MB Size
Report
This content was uploaded by our users and we assume good faith they have the permission to share this book. If you own the copyright to this book and it is wrongfully on our website, we offer a simple DMCA procedure to remove your content from our site. Start by pressing the button below!
Report copyright / DMCA form
LONDON MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY LECTURE NOTE SERIES Managing Editor: Professor J.W.S. Cassels, Department of Pure Mathematics and Mathematical Statistics, University of Cambridge, 16 Mill Lane, Cambridge CB2 1SB, England The books in the series listed below are available from booksellers, or, in case of difficulty, from Cambridge University Press. 4 5
16 17 18
20 21
23 24 25
27 29 30 31
34 36 38 39
40 41
42 43 44 45
46 48 49 50 51
52 54 55 56 57 58 59 60 61
62 63 64 65 66 67 68 69 70 71
72
Algebraic topology, J.F. ADAMS Commutative algebra, J.T. KNIGHT Topics in finite groups, T.M. GAGEN Differential germs and catastrophes, Th. BROCKER & L. LANDER A geometric approach to homology theory, S. BUONCRISTIANO, C.P. ROURKE & B.J. SANDERSON Sheaf theory, B.R. TENNISON Automatic continuity of linear operators, A.M. SINCLAIR Parallelisms of complete designs, P.J. CAMERON The topology of Stiefel manifolds, I.M. JAMES Lie groups and compact groups, J.F. PRICE Skew field constructions, P.M. COHN Pontryagin duality and the structure of LCA groups, S.A. MORRIS Interaction models, N.L. BIGGS Continuous crossed products and type III von Neumann algebras, A. VAN DAELE Representation theory of Lie groups, M.F. ATIYAH et at Homological group theory, C.T.C. WALL (ed) Surveys in combinatorics, B. BOLLOBAS (ed) Affine sets and affine groups, D.G. NORTHCOTT Introduction to Hp spaces, P.J. KOOSIS Theory and applications of Hopf bifurcation, S.D. HASSARD, N.D. KAZARINOFF & Y-H. WAN Topics in the theory of group presentations, D.L. JOHNSON Graphs, codes and designs, P.J. CAMERON & J.H. VAN LINT Z!2-homotopy theory, M.C. CRABB Recursion theory: its generalisations and applications, F.R. DRAKE & S.S. WAINER (eds) p-adic analysis: a short course on recent work, N. KOBLITZ Low-dimensional topology, R. BROWN & T.L. THICKSTUN (eds) Finite geometries and designs, P. CAMERON, J.W.P. HIRSCHFELD & D.R. HUGHES (eds) Commutator calculus and groups of homotopy classes, H.J. BAUES Synthetic differential geometry, A. KOCK Combinatorics, H.N.V. TEMPERLEY (ed) Markov processes and related problems of analysis, E.B. DYNKIN Ordered permutation groups, A.M.W. GLASS Joumees arithmetiques, J.V. ARMITAGE (ed) Techniques of geometric topology, R.A. FENN Singularities of smooth functions and maps, J.A. MARTINET Applicable differential geometry, M. CRAMPIN & F.A.E. PIRANI Integrable systems, S.P. NOVIKOV et at The core model, A. DODD Economics for mathematicians, J.W.S. CASSELS Continuous semigroups in Banach algebras, A.M. SINCLAIR Basic concepts of enriched category theory, G.M. KELLY
Several complex variables and complex manifolds I, MJ. FIELD Several complex variables and complex manifolds II, MJ. FIELD Classification problems in ergodic theory, W. PARRY & S. TUNCEL Complex algebraic surfaces, A. BEAUVILLE Representation theory, I.M. GELFAND et at Stochastic differential equations on manifolds, K.D. ELWORTHY Groups - St Andrews 1981, C.M. CAMPBELL & E.F. ROBERTSON (eds) Commutative algebra: Durham 1981, R.Y. SHARP (ed)
73 74 75 76 77 78 79 80 81
82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89
90 91
92 93 94 95
96 97 98 99 100 101
102 103 104 105 106 107 108 109 110 111
112 113 114 115 116 117 118 119 120 121 122 123 124 125 126 127 128
Riemann surfaces: a view towards several complex variables, A.T. HUCKLEBERRY Symmetric designs: an algebraic approach, E.S. LANDER New geometric splittings of classical knots, L. SIEBENMANN & F. BONAHON Spectral theory of linear differential operators and comparison algebras, H.O. CORDES Isolated singular points on complete intersections, EJ.N. LOOIJENGA A primer on Riemann surfaces, A.F. BEARDON Probability, statistics and analysis, J.F.C. KINGMAN & G.E.H. REUTER (eds) Introduction to the representation theory of compact and locally compact groups, A. ROBERT Skew fields, P.K. DRAXL Surveys in combinatorics, E.K. LLOYD (ed) Homogeneous structures on Riemannian manifolds, F. TRICERRI & L. VANHECKE Finite group algebras and their modules, P. LANDROCK
Solitons, P.G. DRAZIN Topological topics, I.M. JAMES (ed) Surveys in set theory, A.R.D. MATHIAS (ed) FPF ring theory, C. FAITH & S. PAGE An F-space sampler, NJ. KALTON, N.T. PECK & J.W. ROBERTS Polytopes and symmetry, S.A. ROBERTSON Classgroups of group rings, M.J. TAYLOR Representation of rings over skew fields, A.H. SCHOFIELD Aspects of topology, I.M. JAMES & E.H. KRONHEIMER (eds) Representations of general linear groups, G.D. JAMES Low-dimensional topology 1982, R.A. FENN (ed) Diophantine equations over function fields, R.C. MASON Varieties of constructive mathematics, D.S. BRIDGES & F. RICHMAN Localization in Noetherian rings, A.V. JATEGAONKAR Methods of differential geometry in algebraic topology, M. KAROUBI & C. LERUSTE Stopping time techniques for analysts and probabilists, L. EGGHE Groups and geometry, ROGER C. LYNDON Topology of the automorphism group of a free group, S.M. GERSTEN Surveys in combinatorics 1985, I. ANDERSON (ed) Elliptic structures on 3-manifolds, C.B. THOMAS A local spectral theory for closed operators, I. ERDELYI & WANG SHENGWANG Syzygies, E.G. EVANS & P. GRIFFITH Compactification of Siegel moduli schemes, C-L. CHAI Some topics in graph theory, H.P. YAP Diophantine Analysis, J. LOXTON & A. VAN DER.POORTEN (eds) An introduction to surreal numbers, H. GONSHOR Analytical and geometric aspects of hyperbolic space, D.B.A.EPSTEIN(ed) Low-dimensional topology and Kleinian groups, D.B.A. EPSTEIN (ed) Lectures on the asymptotic theory of ideals, D. REES Lectures on Bochner-Riesz means, K.M. DAVIS & Y-C. CHANG An introduction to independence for analysts, H.G. DALES & W.H. WOODIN Representations of algebras, P.J. WEBB (ed) Homotopy theory, E. REES & J.D.S. JONES (eds) Skew linear groups, M. SHIRVANI & B. WEHRFRITZ Triangulated categories in the representation theory of finite-dimensional algebras, D. HAPPEL Lectures on Fermat varieties, T. SHIODA Proceedings of Groups - St Andrews 1985, E. ROBERTSON & C. CAMPBELL (eds) Non-classical continuum mechanics, RJ. KNOPS & A.A. LACEY (eds) Surveys in combinatorics 1987, C. WHITEHEAD (ed) Lie groupoids and Lie algebroids in differential geometry, K. MACKENZIE Commutator theory for congruence modular varieties, R. FREESE & R. MCKENZIE Van der Corput's method for exponential sums, S.W. GRAHAM & G. KOLESNIK New directions in dynamical systems, TJ. BEDFORD & J.W. SWIFT (eds) Descriptive set theory and the structure of sets of uniqueness, A.S. KECHRIS & A. LOUVEAU
London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series. 115
An Introduction to Independence for Analysts
H.G. DALES School of Mathematics, University of Leeds
W.H. WOODIN Department of Mathematics, California Institute of Technology
The right fthe University of Cambridge to prim and sell
all manner f books war granted by
Henry Vlll in 1534. The University has printed and published cominuously since 1584.
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge
New York New Rochelle Melbourne Sydney
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo
Cambridge University Press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 8RU, UK
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York www.cambridge.org Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521339964
© Cambridge University Press 1987
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1987 Reprinted 1988 Re-issued in this digitally printed version 2008
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library ISBN 978-0-521-33996-4 paperback
V CONTENTS
Preface 1.
vii
Homomorphisms from algebras of continuous functions
2.
Partial orders, Boolean algebras, and ultraproducts
22
3.
Woodin's condition
43
4.
Independence in set theory
54
5.
Martin's Axiom
80
6.
Gaps in ordered sets
104
7.
Forcing
130
8.
Iterated Forcing
183
Bibliography
229
Index of notation
235
Index
237
vii
PREFACE
The purpose of this book is to explain what it means for a proposition to be independent of set theory, and to describe how independence results can be proved by the technique of forcing. We do this by presenting an application Our of forcing to a deep and interesting problem in analysis. application is, by current standards in set theory, fairly non-technical, and so it offers an excellent setting in which to exhibit to analysts these new techniques from set theory. Most analysts will have a certain acquaintance with They will know naive set theory up to the level of ordinals and cardinals. They will have heard logic and set theory.
that forcing is a powerful technique that enables one to
prove that certain propositions of set theory are independent of specified axioms, and, in particular, that Cohen developed the method of forcing in his proof that the Continuum Hypothesis theory,
(CH)
is independent of the basic axioms of set
They may also know of more recently formulated (MA), which can be used to axioms, such as Martin's Axiom ZFC.
establish independence results without the necessity of knowing any of the technicalities of forcing.
However, it is possible that analysts harbour two negative feelings about these matters. First, they may feel that, although logic and set theory are of interest in their own right, they have little to contribute concerning questions
which "really" arise in mathematical analysis, and so can be safely left to their disciples. But this is not true. For example, several natural questions about sets of real numbers cannot be resolved in the theory
ZFC.
For some of these
viii
questions the set-theoretic entanglements are quite subtle, in that these questions can be resolved by invoking the existence of large cardinal numbers. example.
is a continuous function, then for each Borel subset
f,g
:
Here is a specific
It is not difficult to show that, if
3t + 3t
B
f(B)
P.
of
Lebesgue measurable for each Borel set ZFC.
-. ]R
Now suppose that
Is f(]R\g(B))
are continuous functions.
cannot be decided in
f: 3t
is Lebesgue measurable
B?
This problem
However if there is a measurable
cardinal, then these sets are indeed all Lebesgue measurable. The main example that we present in this work did It concerns the automatic continuity of homomorphisms from a Banach algebra of continarise naturally in analysis.
uous functions into an arbitrary Banach algebra, and the formulation of the problem was such that a solution was expected (perhaps naively) in naive set theory.
But
eventually it was discovered that the existence of discontinuous homomorphisms from the algebras under consideration could not be decided in ZFC. Secondly, analysts may feel that the technicalities of forcing are too arcane to be readily accessible.
We seek
to challenge this view by presenting a reasonably complete account of forcing which is comprehensible to non-logicians: we hope that it will bring them to the point at which they can appreciate the application, which we shall give in detail, of these new ideas to the above automatic continuity problem. We should say, however, that it is not our intention to teach the practical use of forcing in general, but rather to explain quite explicitly how the method of forcing does yield independence and consistency results, and to exemplify this by the study of our chosen example.
Thus this book is directed towards non-logicians, and in particular to analysts.
We shall give an account of
the background in logic that we shall require, and we shall explain the key notions of proof, of consistency, and of independence. The approach to independence will be through the theory of models:
Godel's completeness theorem allows us
ix
to recast independence questions as problems of the construction of models with certain properties.
We shall give full proofs of the results about forcing and Martin's Axiom that we shall need. En route to our main theorem, we shall prove that CH is independent from
a result that we believe should be known to all
ZFC,
mathematicians.
We also hope that our account will be useful for students of set theory as a preliminary to other works.
Very
little knowledge of analysis is required to follow the details of our example, and the background that is required is given in Chapter 1.
We now describe the problem in analysis that we are Let X be a compact Hausdorff space, and let
to consider. C(X,C)
be the set of all continuous, complex-valued
functions on
X.
The set
C(X,C)
is a commutative algebra
with respect to the pointwise operations. IfIx = sup{If(x)l
Then
I.Ix
:
x E X}
is an algebra norm on
uniform norm - and
(f E C(X,C)).
C(X,C)
(C(X,C), I.IZ)
Set
- it is the The
is a Banach algebra.
question we ask is whether or not each algebra norm on C(X,C)
is necessarily equivalent to the uniform norm:
the topological structure of
C(X,C)
if so,
as a normed algebra
would be completely determined by its algebraic structure. This question was first discussed by Kaplansky in 1948, and it was eventually "resolved" independently by Dales and by Esterle in 1976:
if the Continuum Hypothesis holds, then,
for each infinite compact (Hausdorff) space algebra norm on
C(X,C)
X,
there is an
which is not equivalent to the
uniform norm.
The appeal to CH in this theorem was thought at the time (at least by those involved) to be an accident and a weakness of the given proofs.
However, also in 1976, it was
proved by Solovay, using a condition of Woodin, that, if there is a model of set theory, then there is a model of set
x
theory in which each algebra norm on each C(X,C) is equivalent to the uniform norm. Shortly afterwards a different, and easier, approach to the theorem was developed by Woodin;
the approach used some techniques of Kunen.
It
is this approach, which involves Martin's Axiom, that we present here.
These results are included in Woodin's thesis,
written at the University of California, Berkeley, and a presentation for experts in forcing is given in the recent volume [45] of Jech, but apart from this ours is the first account of the theorem to appear in print.
The original work
of Solovay has never been published.
A revised version of Woodin's thesis is to appear [72]; this memoir, which will also include several more complicated independence results, is written for logicians, and we can say with quiet confidence that it will be unintelligible to analysts. Chapter 1 contains only analysis:
following the
seminal work of Bade and Curtis, we shall analyze the
structure of an arbitrary homomorphism from C(X,C) into a Banach algebra. In Chapter 2, we shall discuss partially ordered sets, Boolean algebras, and ultraproducts, topics
which form the background to much of our later work, and in Chapter 3 we shall relate our question to one which is amenable to the techniques which are given to us in the theory of forcing:
if there is an algebra norm on any
C(X,C)
which is not equivalent to the uniform norm, then there is a free ultrafilter V on N and an isotonic map from a subset /V of the ultraproduct (R'J/V, satisfying certain rules: identifies
8
outside logic, one usually
with its underlying set
this in Chapters 1 - 6 of this book.
B,
and we shall do
However, in Chapters 7
and 8 it seems to be necessary for us to maintain the distinction between
8
and
B.
Here are some particular notations that we shall use.
(An index of notation is given on pages 235-236.) First, N = {1,2,3,...}, whereas Zz+ = {0,1,2,...} (so
that, again, we are following the analysts). allows the possibility that
S = T.
Second,
S c T
Third, in a phrase such
as
rad A = {a E A : e - ab E Inv A the bracket
"(b E A)"
means
"for all
(b E A) } b
in
A".
We give some references in the notes at the end of the chapters to the theorems proved. Although some results are new or have simplified proofs, it is of course not the
case that unattributed results are claimed as original.
The authors first discussed this work when the first author visited Caltech in 1984:
we are grateful to
Professor W. Luxemburg for arranging this visit.
We also
acknowledge the award of a Visiting Fellowship to the second author by the United Kingdom Science and Engineering Research Council that enabled him to visit Leeds in September, 1984.
The second author is an A.P. Sloan Fellow, and we are grateful that this fellowship provided financial support for us to meet at later times, both in the snows of Leeds and in the sunshine of Pacific Palisades, and for us to arrange the typing of this book. A number of people, both analysts and set theorists,
have read some chapters of a preliminary version of this work, and we are very grateful to them for their comments.
They
include William Bade, John Derrick, Peter Dixon, Peter We give special thanks to K.P. Hart and to the referee for reading
McClure, Neil Mowbray, John Truss and Tom Ransford.
the entire book in manuscript and for making many valuable suggestions: of course, the decisions on the approach, the (possibly tendentious) opinions, and the errors are all our responsibility.
We owe a special debt of thanks to our typist, Mrs. Joan Bunn. A large amount of information in a work of this type is carried by the details of the symbolism and the We have tried hard to eliminate errors in this area (presumably unsuccessfully): without the skill and accuracy of Mrs. Bunn's transcription, the process of correcting our fonts.
errors would surely have diverged.
H.G. Dales and W.H. Woodin, Leeds, April, 1987
1
1
HOMOMORPHISMS FROM ALGEBRAS OF CONTINUOUS FUNCTIONS
Throughout this book, we shall work in the naive set theory familiar to analysts:
the formalization of this
theory is the axiom system
which will be discussed in
ZFC,
Chapter 4.
We first summarize some elementary facts about Banach algebras that we shall use.
The account in the
standard text of Rudin (58, Chapters 10 and 11] covers essentially all that we shall require. All the algebras that we shall consider are linear
and associative, and their underlying field is either the An algebra is complex field C or the real field ]R. in this case, we often denote unital if it has an identity; e. The algebra formed by adjoining an identity to a non-unital algebra A is denoted by A#, and we take A# = A if A is unital. The set of invertible elements of a unital algebra A is denoted by Inv A. A character on a complex algebra A is a non-zero homomorphism from A onto C. The set of characters on A is the character space of A, written @A. Let A be a commutative algebra. An ideal I of A is modular if the quotient algebra A/I is unital. The (Jacobson) radical, written rad A, of A is defined to be the intersection of the maximal modular ideals of A; if A has no such ideals, then rad A = A, and in this case A is
the identity by
a radical algebra.
(So our convention is that a radical
algebra is necessarily commutative.) semisimple if
rad A = {O}.
It is standard that
The algebra A
is
2
rad A = {a E A : e - ab E Inv where
e
is the identity of
the fact that, if then
a E A
A#.
(b E A#) },
A#
Several times we shall use for some b E rad A,
ab = a
and
a = 0.
An element an = 0
of an algebra A
a
n E N.
for some
is nilpotent if for the set of
nil A
We write
nilpotent elements in A. If A is commutative, then is an ideal in A (it is the nilradical of A), and
nil A
nil A c rad A.
An ideal
P
in a commutative algebra A
is a
prime ideal if either a E P or b E P whenever a,b E A with ab E P. The algebra A is an integral domain if the zero ideal is a prime ideal in A. We shall occasionally use is an ideal in A (n E N), then there is
the standard algebraic fact that, if and if
a E A a prime ideal 1.1
is such that
with
P
I
an 4 I and
I c P
a 0 P.
DEFINITION
Let A be an algebra over a field
on A
is a map
p : A - Bt
(i)
p(a) > 0
(ii)
p(aa) =
(iii)
p(a + b) < p(a) + p(b)
(iv)
p(ab) < p(a)p(b)
A norm on A
p(a) # 0
The algebra A
A seminorm
(a E A);
(a E k, a E A);
Iaip(a)
is a seminorm
(v)
k.
such that:
p
(a,b E A);
(a,b E A).
such that
(a E A\{O}).
is seminormable (respectively, normable) if
there is a non-zero seminorm (respectively, a norm) on
A.
It would be more precise to say "algebra seminorm"
and "algebra norm", but this extra precision seems to be unnecessary for us.
A norm is usually denoted by
A Banach
3
Each normed
algebra is an algebra with a complete norm.
algebra A
is a dense, normed subalgebra of a Banach algebra,
A
the completion of
([8, 1.12]).
The starting point for the "automatic continuity" theory of Banach algebras is the following basic fact.
A be a Banach algebra, and let tinuous, and in fact 11+11
0 E
oD A.
Then
0
Let
is con-
4 1.
The character space
is a locally compact space with
to
respect to the relative weak *-topology from the dual space of
(We adopt throughout the convention that a locally
A.
compact space is Hausdorff.)
unital Banach algebra, then
A
Let 4P
A
# 0,
A
If
is a commutative,
is compact and non-empty.
to
be a commutative Banach algebra.
then the map
f+ ker 0
4
onto the set of maximal modular ideals of
rad A = (1{ker 0
:
If
is a bijection from
4
A
and so
A,
0 E IA} .
(1)
If 4A = 0, then A is a radical algebra. Since each character is continuous on A, each maximal modular ideal is
closed, and so
is a closed ideal in
rad A
Let A be an algebra, and let the spectrum of
a,
A.
a E A.
Then
a(a),
is the set
a(a) = {z E C
ze - a 0 Inv
:
A#}.
Let A be a Banach algebra. ([58, 10.13])
subset of
C
asserts that for each
r(a) = sup{I zI
Then
r(a)
a(a)
a E A.
:
A fundamental theorem is a non-empty, compact
Set
z E a(a)}
is the spectral radius of
radius formula asserts that
(a E A).
a,
and the spectral
4
r(a) = lim IlanIil" = inf IIanIIl/n
(a E A).
n+=
If
A
is commutative, then
a(a) = {q(a)
:
0 E D #},
and
A
Thus a a E rad A if and only if r(a) = 0 ([58, 11.9]). commutative Banach algebra is a radical algebra if and only so
IIanII1/n - O
if
as
n - -
for each
a E A.
We now describe in more detail the specific Banach algebras that we are studying. Let
be a topological space.
X
(respectively,
C(X))
Then
C(X,C)
denotes the set of continuous,
complex-valued (respectively, real-valued) functions on X. (In making this definition, we implicitly assume that X is non-empty.) Then C(X,C) and C(X) are, respectively, complex and real algebras with respect to the pointwise algebraic operations on X. The constant function 1 is the identity of these algebras.
Let function
on
f
be a subset of
S
S,
set
IfIS = sup{If(x)I
Then
Let
x E S}.
S.
be a compact (Hausdorff) space.
X
set
a
x
(f)
(f E C(X,C)).
= f(x)
homeomorphism of X onto Oc(x,C), identify these two spaces. Let z
and set
f E C(X,C),
is the complex conjugate of
E C(X,C).
A subalgebra A
of
For
Then it is a
standard result ([58, 11.13(a)]) that the map
where
Then
is a commutative, unital Banach algebra.
(C(X,C),I.Ix)
x E X,
:
is the uniform norm on
I.IS
For each bounded
X.
x r e
x
is a
and we shall henceforth f(x)
= f x
z E C.
C(X,C)
(x E X),
Then
is self-adjoint if
We shall use the standard fact ([58, 11.18]) (f E A). E A that each closed, self-adjoint subalgebra of C(X,C) which for a contains 1 is isometrically isomorphic to C(Y,C) certain compact space Y. Let f E C(X,C). Then Z(f) = f-1'({O}) is the
zero-set of
f.
A subset
F
of
X
is a zero-set if
5
F = Z(f)
f E C(X,C).
for some
Let
be an ideal in
I
the closed subset of
h(I) _ (1{Z(f) Let
The hull of
is
I
f E U.
:
be a closed set in
F
C(X,C).
X:
Then we throughout set
X.
I(F) = {f E C(X,C)
:
Z(f) z F}
J(F) = {f E C(X,C)
:
Z(f)
and
is a neighbourhood
of F}. It is easily seen that
and
I(F)
the maximal and minimal ideals in that
Let
is closed, and that
I(F)
C(X,C)
respectively.
Jx and We see that
whose hull is
is dense in
J(F)
Then we write
x E X.
I({x}),
are, respectively,
J(F)
Mx
for
{M
: x E X}
x
F,
I(F).
and
J({x})
is the
C(X,C).
family of maximal ideals in
We use the same notations I(F), J(F), Jx and Mx C(X) when we are considering
for the analogous ideals in real-valued functions.
We write
(respectively,
L'(C)
k7)
for the set
of bounded, complex-valued (respectively, real-valued) sequences on
(alN Then
and we set
IN,
= sup( IanI
:
n E N}
(a = (an) E 1-(C)) .
is a complex, commutative, unital Banach Temporarily, we denote its character space by @.
(i°'(C),1.I3N)
algebra.
For n E N, a E RF(C),
set
set En(a) = an a(4) = (a)
(a = (an) E £°°(C)), (0 E @).
are standard and are easily proved;
and, for
The following results
they follow from the
Gelfand-Naimark theorem ([58, 11.18]), for example, and are given in greater generality in [35, 8.3]. (i)
The map
n F+ En, N - $,
is a homeomorphism
6
with dense range.
The map
(ii)
a N &, km(C)
is an
-r
isometric isomorphism.
Thus the compact space
@
define
to be
SIN
has the properties of the Stone-
BN
Cech compactification
N.
of
In our approach, we
different, topological
t:
characterizations are given in [36] and (69], for example, and we shall give a characterization in terms of ultrawith a filters in Chapter 2. Henceforth, we identify N
BN
and
then
MP
subset of p E BIN ,
Let
k (C)
with C(BN ,C).
is a maximal ideal in be a subset of
a
characteristic function of
the closure of
XQ (p) = 1} = a,
and let
IN,
Clearly
Q.
in
a
For example, if
k M. be the
XQ
{p E MN: BN . Thus,
if {a,T}
is a partition of N , then {o,r} is a partition of BIN into clopen sets: we shall use this fact several times. It implies that a n T = Q n T for a,T c N , and that, for a c N ,p E o} is a base of neighbourhoods of p E BIN, {a p in BIN consisting of clopen sets. The existence of this base shows that BN is a totally disconnected space. We note that, if p E BN , then JP is a prime ideal in k (C). For take f,g E k (C) with fg E J J. Then :
p E {n
:
{n
:
and so either or
p E {n
:
(fg) (n) = 0}
f(n) = 0}
p E {n
g(n) = O}
U {n
f(n) = 0}
:
,
:
,
g(n) = O}
,
in which case
in which case
g E Jp.
f E Jp,
Thus
JP
is prime.
We write
c0(C)
(respectively,
for the set
c0)
of complex-valued (respectively, real-valued) sequences which converge to zero.
Then co(C) is an ideal in k (Q), our identification equates it with the ideal I(BN \N)
and in
C(BN C) . coo (C) and coo for the ideals in respectively, consisting of sequences
We write co(C)
and
such that
co,
an = 0
for all but finitely many
n.
(a n)
7
The question that we shall study in this book is the following.
QUESTION X
Let
algebra
be a compact space.
C(X,C)
Is each norm on the
necessarily equivalent to the uniform norm
I,IX?
The question was raised by Kaplansky in lectures
around 1948, and it was Kaplansky who gave the first partial result ([48)). 1.2
THEOREM Let
on
C(X,C).
be a compact space, and let
X
Then
be a norm
11.11
(f E C(X,C)).
IfIX 'IIfII
Proof
Let A be the completion of the normed algebra Then A is a commutative, unital Banach
(C(X,C), 11.11).
algebra.
The map 0 .. 4IC(X,C), 0A uous injection, and so we may regard space of x E X\@A. f(@A
Then there exist By (1),
and
f
such that
f E rad A,
g
C(X,(r),
A
P
# X,
A
in
g(x) = 1,
and so
is a contin-
as a closed sub-
Suppose, if possible, that
= g(4A) = {O},
fg = g.
Thus
X.
4D
C(X,C)
and take
such that
and such that
g = 0,
a contradiction.
0A = X.
Let
i f (x) I < I I f I I ,
and let
f E C(X,C),
and so I
I X< I I f II ,
x E X.
Since
x E 4
as required.
At
It follows immediately from 1.2 (via the open mapping theorem) that each complete norm on
C(X,C)
is equiv-
alent to the uniform norm, and so there is an inequivalent norm on C(X,C) if and only if there is an incomplete norm. Let be an incomplete norm on C(X,C), and
let A be the completion of bedding
C(X,C) -. A
(C(X,C), II.II).
Then the em-
is a discontinuous monomorphism.
other hand, suppose that
6
On the
is a discontinuous homomorphism
8
from
into a Banach algebra.
C(X,C)
= max{If IX, IIe(f)II}
IIf1I Then
11.11
Set (f E C(X,C)).
is an incomplete norm on
C(X,C).
Thus our
question is equivalent to the question of the existence of a discontinuous homomorphism from C(X,C) into a Banach algebra, and it will usually be convenient to formulate it in this way.
The next advance in the study of norms on
C(X,C)
after the work of Kaplansky was the seminal paper of Bade and Curtis of 1960 ([2]).
In this paper, the structure of an
arbitrary homomorphism from
into a Banach algebra
C(X,C)
was analysed, and the key notions of singularity set and radical homomorphism (see below) were introduced. Later, in 1976, Johnson ([47]) extended Bade and Curtis's theorem, and used the extension to show that, if there is an incomplete norm on
for any compact space X, then there exists a radical Banach algebra R, and a non-zero
C(X,C)
P E $N\N, homomorphism
9
from
c0(C)
into
R
such that
ker 9
J
.
It is this reduction theorem that we shall need in Chapter 3.
Our proof is slightly more direct, and gives a little more information, than that obtained by following the original route.
The main technical device in the proof of Bade and Curtis's theorem is the following main boundedness theorem, which originates in [2, Theorem 2.1]. 1.3
THEOREM
A and B be Banach algebras, and let 6 be a homomorphism from A into B. Suppose that there are sequences (a (b and in A such that a b = 0 n n m n (m,n E IN, m $ n). Then there exists a constant C such Let
)
)
that 11 6 (anbn) I I
< C II an 11 II bn II
(n E 10 .
9
Proof
(n E Ilan II = Ilbn II = 1 Suppose, if possible, that the result is false.
We can suppose that Then for each
E N x N,
(i,j)
such that the map
we may choose
n(i,j) E N
is injective and such
I+ n(i,j)
(i,j)
that
Ile(uijvij) II > 4i+j where
and
uij = an(i,j)
(i,j E N)
vij = bn(i,j).
Set
m
fi so that each
=
v
E
R=1
(i E N) ,
it /2R
Choose
fi E A.
IIe(fi) II < 2j (i)
j(i) E N
so that
(i E N)
and set
g=
k k=1
so that
g E A.
uk,j(k)/2
Now, for
i E IN,
k+R
cc
=
1l RL1 k=1
u
i,j(i)vi,j(i) /2i+j(i)
and so
Ile(gfi)II
> 4i+j(i)/2i+j(i) = 2i+j(i).
Ila(gfi) II
2i
IIa(g) II Ila(f1) II < 2j(i) Ile(g) II , for all
Thus the result holds.
i E N , I
N) .
a contradiction.
10
Let
We introduce some further notation. We write
compact space.
N
neighbourhoods of a point set of
X,
those functions of
C(X,T)
a closed ideal in
C(X,T).
1.4
Let
of
is an open sub-
U
If
X.
consists of
KU
so that
which vanish off
U,
KU
and
is
K0 = {0}.
For example,
be a homomorphism from
8
A point
if, for each
x E X
U E Nx, BlKU
C(X,C)
into a
is a singularity point for is discontinuous. The set of
singularity points is the singularity set for 1.5
be a
DEFINITION
Banach algebra. 8
x
x
KU = I(X\U),
then
X
for the family of open
8.
DEFINITION
A radical homomorphism at morphism from a maximal ideal
M
is a non-zero homo-
x
of
x
C(X,T)
into the
radical of a commutative Banach algebra. Let
and let
x E X,
: M
8
into a commutative Banach algebra
be a homomorphism We claim that 0 is a - A
X
A.
radical homomorphism if and only if 8lJx = 0. For suppose that 8(M ) c rad A, and take f E J Then there exists x x g E Mx with fg = f, and 0(f)8(g) = 8(f), so that .
0(f) = 0.
Thus
BjJx = 0,
and take
elJx = 0. E
4D
Conversely, suppose that Then 4o8 E 0M U {O}, A.
and
x
4oe)l.x = 0.
Since
8(Mx) c ker 0.
Thus
homomorphism.
Jx
Mx, 08 = 0,
is dense in
8(Mx) c rad A,
and
8
and so
is a radical
The claim is established.
It is further clear that there is a radical homomorphism at x if and only if M /J is seminormable. x
x
We shall several times use the elementary fact that, if F is an infinite subset of a regular space X, then there exist x E F and U E N such for n E N n
that
u
m
n u
n
= 0
Then there exist
and
U U V = X.
so we can choose
n
(m
U E N
n).
x
x
For take
and V E N y
n
x,y E F with x # y. with x 0 V, Y E U,
Either u fl F or V a F is infinite, and x1 E F
and an open set
W1
such that
11
is infinite and
W1 fl F
W
set
such that
n
Set
xn )t Wn.
U
For
x1 fE W1.
successively choose xn E W1 fl
...
w n ... n w n 1_ = X\W1 and set
Un = (Wl n ...
n = 2,3,...,
and an open
fl Wn-1 A F fl F
fl Wn-1)\Wn
is infinite and
(n = 2,3,...).
There is one final remark before we prove the Let A be a Banach algebra, let
theorem of Bade and Curtis. 6
be a homomorphism and let I be an ideal of of the form KU or KU n J. Suppose that there is
C(X,C) - A
:
C(X,C)
(g E I). Take a constant k such that < kIgIX2 II6(g2)II f E I. Then f = f1 - f2 + i(f3 - f4), where fj E I and f(X) c [O,IfIX] (j = 1,...,4). Further, there exist gj E I with gj2 = fj, and so
II6(fj) II < kIf .IX Thus
116(f)II
< 4k I f I I.
then, for each n E N, > nlgn1X2.
II 6(gn2)II
6II is discontinuous, there exists g E I with
Hence, if
Similarly, we see that, if
g E I
then there exists
(j = 1,...,4).
such that 6(g 2)
611 # 0,
0.
We can now give the theorem of Bade and Curtis ([2, Theorem 4.3]). 1.6
THEOREM
Let X be a compact space, let homomorphism from F
C(X,C)
into a Banach algebra
be the singularity set of 6. Then: (i) F is empty if and only if F
(ii)
Now suppose that
be a
6
6
A,
and let
is continuous;
is finite. 0
is discontinuous and that
F = (xI'...,xn}.
(iii) There are a continuous homomorphism C(X,C)
that and
viIMx
A
and linear maps v1,...,vn : C(X,C) -' A such is a radical homomorphism at xi (i = 1,...,n)
0 = µ + vl + ... + vn
12
Proof
versely, suppose that exists
F = 0
Clearly
(i)
is continuous.
6
Then, for each
F = 0.
such that
Ux E Nx
if
Con-
there
x E X,
X
is continuous, and so
6IKU X
V such that 6IKv is continuous Using a partition of unity subordinate to
has a finite open cover
V E
for each V,
V.
we see easily that 6 is continuous. Suppose, if possible, that (ii)
Then there are an infinite sequence
is infinite.
F
(xn) c F
Un E Nx
and
n
Um n Un = 0
such that I
I
6(fn`) I
(n E N) .
n Ifn Ix`
>
I
(m # n).
such that
fn E KU
Choose
Since fm fn = 0
n
(m # n)
Thus
this contradicts the main boundedness theorem.
F
is
finite.
Let
(iii)
Ux E Nx
such that
x E F. 6I(KU
We claim that there exists
n Jx)
is continuous.
For suppose
x
that this is not the case. sequences n E N ,
Then we may inductively choose (fn) c Jx
and
(V n) c Nx
such that, for each and
fn E Kv
(i = 1,...,n),
fi(Vn+1) = {O} Ix 2. II 6(f n2) II > n Ifn Since f mf n = 0 contradicts the main boundedness theorem. n
,
this again
(m # n),
Thus the claim
holds.
It is immediate from the claim that
continuous, say Fix
Wi E Nx
6IJ(F)
is
(f E J(F)).
< klflx
110(f) II
such that
(i = 1,...,n) i
Wi n wj = 0
(i # j),
and fix
ei E Kw
such that i
Ietlx = 1
ei = 1
and
be the set of functions f - f(xi)1 E Jx
on some neighbourhood of Then
s algebra of J(P),
C(X,(C).
Let
such that
f E C(X,(C)
(i = 1,...,n).
x
is a dense sub-
B
n
For
f E B,
f(xi)ei
f -
belongs to
and so
110(f) II
< kIf -
i=1
f(xi)eilx +
< [(n + 1)k +
Ii
f(xi)6(ei) I
I
=1
II 6 (ei) II ]if lx.
B
13
Thus
is continuous on
a
Let C(X,C),
B.
be the continuous extension of
g
Then
v = e - M.
and let
continuous homomorphism, and Take
C(X,C) -. A
:
is a
vjJ(F) = 0.
and
f E I(F)
LL
to
e1B
g E J(F).
Then
e(f)LL(g) = e(fg) = M(fg) = M(f)LL(g),
and so v(f)LL(g) = (e(f) - M(f))M(g) = 0.
Since
LL
J F
is continuous and (f,g E I(F)).
v(f)LL(g) = 0
we have
= I(F),
f,g E I(F),
Thus, for
v(fg) = e(f)e(g) - M(f)M(g) (LL(f)
_
+ V(f)HM(g) + v(g)) - LL(f)LL(g)
= v(f)v(g), and so
is a homomorphism.
vII(F)
Set
vi,...,vn
Then
i = 1,...,n). (f E C(X,C), vi(f) = v(fei) C(X,C) + A are linear maps. Since :
n
v = vi + ... + vn.
ei E J(F),
1 -
Let
i E {1,...,n}
1=1
and let
Then
f,g E MX .
fei, gei E I(F),
and so
i
v(fei) v(gei) = v(fgei2) . But
e
2
- ei E J(F),
V (f)vi(g) = vi(fg), i
If
f E JX ,
then
and so and
Vi
v(fge2) = v(fgei). Thus : MX A is a homomorphism.
fei E J(F),
i
and so
vi(f) = 0.
Thus
i
vilMx
is a radical homomorphism.
I
i
1.7
COROLLARY
Let
X
be a compact space.
Then the following are
equivalent: (a)
there is a norm on
C(X,C)
which is not
14
equivalent to the uniform norm;
there is a discontinuous homomorphism from
(b)
into a Banach algebra;
C(X,C)
there is a radical homomorphism from a maximal
(c)
ideal of
C(X,C);
there exists
(d)
seminormable.
x E X
such that M /J x
x
is
I
THEOREM
1.8
Assume that there is a Let X be a compact space. discontinuous homomorphism from C(X,C) into a Banach algebra. Then there exists p E RN\ N, a radical Banach algebra R, and a non-zero homomorphism 0 from c0(C) into R such that ker 6 m J. fl co(C). Proof Let
0
be a discontinuous homomorphism from A. Then there exists
into a Banach algebra
C(X,C)
(f n ) c C(X,(C)
such that
if
=1
and
containing
if n, fn
Then
n E 3N).
:
isometrically isomorphic to space
Since
Y.
clearly
with
Mx -*,R Y.
Let
such that
Y
is
is metrizable, and
there is a singularity point
x E Y,
a
and a non-zero homomorphism vIJx = 0. Certainly x is not an isolated
radical Banach algebra :
B
is discontinuous.
0IB
By 1.6,
point of
and so
C(X,C),
for a certain compact
C(Y,C)
is separable,
B
is a closed,
B
separable, self-adjoint subalgebra of
v
Let
110(f )II
nIX n be the smallest closed, unital subalgebra of C(X,C)
B
Set
R,
Xo = Y\{x}.
be a sequence of open subsets of
(Un)
Um fl Un = 0
S = in E N
and let
(m # n),
:
X0
# 0}.
V IKU
n
For each
n E S,
there exists
gn E KU
such that n
v(gn2)
VIJx = 0,
0.
Since
KU
fl Jx
is dense in
we may suppose that
11v(gn2)11
KU
,
and since
> nIgnI Y. 2
Since
15
gmgn = 0
be a metric defining the topology on
d
(x ) c X n
< d
n+1
is finite.
S
Let
and take 46
it follows from the main boundedness
(m # n),
theorem that
such that
o
where
(n E N) ,
n
6
+ 0
n
Set
= d(x,xn).
d
Y,
and
It
Vn = {y E Xo
< d(y,x) < 26 }
:
(n E N).
26
The sets V Vm n v
are non-empty and open, and {a : m E N } (m # n). Let
n
= 0
n
into infinite subsets, and let Then
Um = U{Vn : n E Qm}.
sets of
X
such that
o
u
is a sequence of open sub-
(Um) f1 U
m
n
and so
(m # n),
= 0
for all but finitely many
= 0
vIKU
be a countable
m
partition of N
m.
By passing to a
m
subsequence of
V = V{V
n
we may suppose that
(xn),
where
vIKV = 0,
n E N }.
:
For n F
n
set
14,
= {y E X o
26
:
n+1
< d(y,x)
ld 2n
Suppose that V U {x}
F = 0 for all but finitely many n. Then n is a neighbourhood of x in Y, and so, if
f E Mx,
there exists
f = fl + f2, diction.
whence
For n
{1}, n
d(y,x) < 6n+i'
with
f2 E Kv
and
v(f) = v(fI) + v(f2) = 0,
Thus we may suppose that
F = U Fn U {x}, e (F
fl E Jx
a closed set in n E IN,
e (y) n
n
= 0
# 0
a contra-
Let
(n E 24).
Y.
en E Jx
take
and with
F
if
with
IenIY = 1,
d(y,x)
> 6
n
with
or
Set CO
ry(a)
= n11anen
(a = (an) E co(C)) .
For each
y E Xo, there exists W E NY with en (W) = 0 for all but two values of n, and so ry(a) is continuous on X0. Clearly, ty(a) E Mx, and voip c0(C) + R is a linear :
map.
For each
en2 - en E Kv
y E Xo\V, and
en(y) E {0,1}, and so v(en2 - en) = 0 (n E N). Also
16
(m # n),
emen = 0
and so
is a homomorphism.
vo
p(coo(C)) c ix c ker v, coo (C) = 0. Choose g E MX with v(g) 0, and let so that (Bn) E co. Take an > 0 (n E N), an = Ig IF n such that a = (a n) E c o and (6n /a n) E C o t set f = g/ a n Since
on
and set
F , n
f(x)
= 0.
Then
is continuous on the
f
in Y, and so f extends to a function in MX. Since *(a) f = g on F, (a) v(f) = v(g), and so (voi) (a) # 0. Thus v°V : c0(0) -+ R is a non-zero homomorphism with (voiy) Ic 00 (C) = 0.
closed set
F
We now regard
c
0
(C)
as an ideal in
C(BN ,C).
Set
E = {p E 61N
Since
vo p # 0,
E c $N \N . If sequence U
in
(U
fl Un = 0
Since
:
(v-,) I (KU n co(C) ) # 0
E # 0. Since E
(m O n)
and
there would exist a
(vole) Icoo(C) = 0,
such that
(n E N).
n
the argument of the third paragraph Thus
(vop) I (J (E) n co(C) ) = O.
Let
e = 1
gN
n c0(Q) ) # 0
(voip) I(KU
leads to a contradiction. such that
(vol,) Icoo(C) = 0,
were infinite,
of non-empty, open subsets of
)
n
(U E Np)
E
is finite.
p E E,
on a neighbourhood of
Clearly,
and take e E C (SN,C) p
and a= 0
neighbourhood of E\{p}. Set 0(f) = (vop)(fe) Then a is the required homomorphism.
on a
(f E c(0)).
Bade and Curtis left open the question of the existence of discontinuous homomorphisms from the algebras C(X,C)
into Banach algebras.
Eventually, such homomorphisms
were constructed for each infinite, compact space by Dales ([16]) and by Esterle ([26], [24], (27]) in 1976. However, both constructions required the assumption of the Continuum Hypothesis (CH), and are thus theorems of the system ZFC + CH. Neither Dales nor Esterle discussed whether or not CH was required. We now state without proof the results of Dales and of Esterle. We denote the cardinality of a set S by ISI;
17
a review of cardinal numbers will be given in Chapter 5. Theorems whose proof is given in the theory ZFC + CH
are labelled
(see Chapter 4)
which hold in
THEOREM
1.9
Let
X
(CH)
be a compact space, and let
maximal, prime ideal in Then the algebra
but theorems
"CH",
are not labelled.
ZFC
C(X,C)
X
be a non-
IC(X,C)/Pl = 2 0.
such that
is normable.
C(X,(Z)/P
Now, if
P
is infinite, then
C(X,C)
does contain K
non-maximal, prime ideals
such that
P
Further, it is easily seen that, if then the hull of
C(X,C),
exists
x E X
such that
IC(X,C)/Pl = 2 0.
is any prime ideal in
P
is a singleton, and so there
P
since J= M,
J c P c M ; x x
is closed if and only if
P
P
X x is equal to the maximal ideal
Thus it follows from 1.9 that, if the Continuum
Mx.
Hypothesis holds, then the four properties (a) - (d) of Corollary 1.7 are true for each infinite, compact space
X.
In particular, we have the following result.
THEOREM
1.10
Let
X
(CH)
be an infinite compact space.
exists a discontinuous homomorphism from Banach algebra, and there is a norm on
C(X,C)
Then there into a
which is not
C(X,C)
equivalent to the uniform norm.
Let
X
be a compact space.
X
If
is separable,
x
then
IC(X,Q)l = 2 0.
Mx # Jx
x
(so that
Suppose that is not a
Definition 2.22), and take
x
c P 1.11
f E M x\J x.
and so there is a prime ideal
(n E N), J
x E X
P-point of
and
f (E P.
THEOREM Let
X
Then P
is such that
X - see fn t Jx in
C(X,C)
Hence we have two further results. (CH)
be a separable, infinite compact space.
with
18
Each non-maximal, prime ideal of
(i)
C(X,C)
is
the kernel of a discontinuous homomorphism into a Banach algebra.
1.12
and if
x E X
If
(ii)
M /J
quotient algebra
x
THEOREM
M
x
# J , x
then the
is seminormable.
x
(CH)
(C)/j
p E aN\N. Then the algebras co(C)/(Jp n co(C)) are normable. Let
P
and
We have stated the above four theorems as results of ZFC + CH. In fact, they all follow from a more general result on the normability of integral domains that can be proved in
This more general result will be discussed
ZFC.
at the end of Chapter 6.
It is an immediate consequence of Theorem 1.8 that,
if there is a discontinuous homomorphism from any compact space
morphism from
X,
c (C). 0
C(X,C) for then there is a discontinuous homoIt is natural to enquire whether or
not all infinite compact spaces are equivalent for our problem. The first result in this direction is the following theorem. 1.13
THEOREM
Assume that there is a discontinuous homomorphism from
t"(C)
Then there is a discon-
into a Banach algebra.
tinuous homomorphism from
C(X,C)
each infinite compact space
into a Banach algebra for
X.
Proof Since
discrete subspace
X
is infinite, it contains an infinite, {xn}.
(f) (n) = f (xn) Then
For
f E C(X,C),
set
(n E N) .
T(f) E £°(C), and T : C(X,C) + £ (C) homomorphism with range B, say. For each
is a continuous a E B
and each
19
there exists f E C(X,(C) with TM = a and IfIX < IalN + E, and so B is a closed subalgebra of
E > 0,
k`°(C). Since there is a discontinuous homomorphism from
p E BN\N and a non-zero homomorphism into a Banach algebra A such that elm # 0
there exists
2°°(C),
from k°(C) and 611 = 0. 8
P
Take such that for
0
proof from T. It is now clear that, if T I- 0 and T }- s,
then
T F-
0 A
is a
: use the logical axiom
'0 - (* - (4' A j,)) ' and modus ponens twice. It is also true that T + 0 p if and only if T f- (4 » *). 4.3
DEFINITION
Let
be a theory in Y. inconsistent if there is a sentence T }-
otherwise,
4 A (-10);
sentence
Then
T
T
4,
T
such that
is consistent.
is inconsistent, then T T has little interest;
If
T
0,
and so
is
4,
for each we prefer
consistent theories. Note that T I- ¢ if and only if T + (10) T is inconsistent. Equivalently, if and 4,
only if
T + (10)
We write
is consistent.
60
Con T if the theory
is consistent.
T
A sentence
relatively consistent with a theory Con T i.e., either
T
T
is
0
if
Con(T + 0.
implies
is inconsistent or
T + 0
is consistent.
(Note that every sentence is relatively consistent with an We shall remark shortly that it
inconsistent theory.)
cannot be proved that ZFC is consistent, and so it is natural to consider whether or not a given sentence 0 is relatively consistent with
ZFC.
We now come to the notions of model and satisfaction, which will be central to much of our later work. 4.4
DEFINITION
A model N is a pair (M,E), where M is a nonempty set and E is a subset of M x M. The set M is the underlying set of N. The model N is countable if M is countable.
Throughout, we shall adopt the convention that a model is denoted by an upper-case fraktur letter and that the underlying set is denoted by the same roman letter. The subset
binary relation on
E M :
of
M x M can be regarded as a
aEb
if and only if
(a,b) E E.
Formally, our definition of a model has no connection with anything preceding the definition.
However,
it is formulated with a connection to the language
V
in
mind (and more general definitions of model would be appropriate if we were considering more general languages). "model" is sometimes termed an literature.
".5,-structure"
in the
Our
61
4.5
DEFINITION Let
m
McN
and if
and
N,
be models.
N = (N,EN)
and
9 = (M,EM)
is a submodel of
is an extension of
N
Then if
2,
EN n (M x m) = EM
For example,
(3t,< )
is a model, and
is a
(@,
is
logically derivable if and only if it is true in every model. More generally, if T is a theory, then if each model of T is also a model of
T 4>.
if and only This is the
F-
4>
importance of Godel's completeness theorem : it identifies
64
the notions of proof and of truth.
Our approach to the proof of the relative consistency of a sentence from a model of
ZFC
with
a model of
ZFC
will be to construct It is because we
ZFC + 0.
are willing to apply Godel's completeness theorem that we can step from this to the assertion that 0 is relatively consistent with
ZFC.
Models of quite a number of theories are studied, and we shall give a few rather elementary examples.
But the examples that we are seriously interested in here are "models of set theory itself".
More precisely, we shall eventually
be concerned with models of the theory
ZFC
this is
:
Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice.
(There
are other set theories that could equally well be considered, such as
GB,
Godel-Bernays set theory, but
ZFC
seems to be
the most popular.)
We first list axioms for
ZFC.
We give a formal
version of each axiom, and an informal interpretation:
it is not expected that the reader will always easily verify, and
it is not always true, that the formal version is a precise formalization of the interpretation. There are a number of variants on this list that are current;
we do not wish to
discuss the possible variations.
Our choice is made for the sake of later technical convenience. The point is that the
axioms are an attempt to capture basic intuitions about sets, and a judgement on the success of this attempt must be subjective.
AXIOM 0
Set existence.
3x (x = x) 'There is a set'.
AXIOM 1
Extensionality.
YxYy((x n y) 06 Yz((z E x)
40
(z E y)))
65
'Two sets are equal if and only if they have the same elements'.
AXIOM 2 Let
Comprehension.
4,(xl,.... xn)
be a formula in
Y.
Vx2...lxnVxn+l3xn+2Vx1((xl E xn+2) a ((x1 E xn+1) n 'If
{B E A : P(B)
A
is a set and
P
4,)
is a "property", then
is true} is a set.'
In fact, Axiom 2 is an infinite scheme of axioms,
one axiom corresponding to each formula 4i(xl,...,xn). The language V and the formally stated axiom make precise our intuitive notion of "property".
It follows from Comprehension that there is a set with no elements, and, by Extensionality, that this set is unique. It is denoted by 0. AXIOM 3
Pairing.
Vxdy3z((x E z) A (y E Z)) 'If
with A E C
A
and
A and
and
B
are sets, then there is a set
C
B E C.'
It follows from Pairing and Comprehension that, if B are sets, then so is {A,B}. We introduce the abbreviation
Vt(t E z AXIOM 4
z c y
for
t E Y) . Union.
Vx3yVz(z E x " z c y) 'If
A
is a set, then there is a set containing
the members of the members of
A.'
66
It follows from Union and Comprehension that, if A is a set, then so is U{B : B E A}; we often denote this latter set by UA. AXIOM 5
Power set.
Vx3ydz (z a x + z E Y) 'If
A
is a set, then there is a set whose
elements include all the subsets of AXIOM 6 Let
A.'
Replacement.
4(x1,x2)
be a formula in
..
Vx33x4Vx1((x1 E x3 A 3x2(4)) + 3x2(x2 E x4 A 4)) The essence of Replacement is the following. function
F
whenever
P(A,B)
is defined by a property
P
if
(A
F(A) = B
holds.)
'The image of a set under a function defined by a property is itself a set.'
Our formulation of Replacement is a slight variant of this, but each formulation can be proved from the other by using Axioms 0 - 5, and the Axiom of Regularity given below. Axiom 6 is also an infinite scheme of axioms. AXIOM 7
Regularity (or Foundation).
Vx3yVz ((z i x) v (y E X A (z E y - z i x)) ) 'Each non-empty set A contains an element B such that there are no elements belonging to both B and
A.'
It follows from Regularity and Comprehension that
67
A E A is prohibited. This fact is used in the theory of ordinals, to be given in Chapter 5. Infinity
AXIOM 8
3xdy3z((z E X) A (y E x
y E Z))
A
'There is a non-empty set ment of
form:
W
A
such that each ele-
is an element of an element of
A.'
This axiom is often stated in a slightly different W such that the empty set belongs to
'There is a set
and such that
element of
A U (Al belongs to W whenever A is an This form can be deduced from our version by
W.'
using the other axioms.
The purpose of the axiom is to
the set W establish the existence of an infinite set: contains 0, {0}, {O,{Oi}}, {O,{{},{(,(O}}},..., and hence "really" contains AXIOM 9
Vx3y3z (x (y
2Z+.
Axiom of Choice
AC
0 v (z E X A Z
p)
v
z A y f1 z
XAZEXAy
0)
(Vt3uVv(t i x v (u E t A U E Y A (v i t v v IE y v v where
'x = 0'
abbreviates
W
abbreviates
'Vx(x i y A x
'Vy(y E x)'
and
v
u))))) ,
'y n z 2 0'
W.
'For each non-empty set
A
of pairwise disjoint,
non-empty sets, there is a set B such that the intersection of B with each member of A contains exactly one element.' Assuming Axioms 1 - 8, AC is equivalent to 'For each non-empty set A, there is a function f : A + UA such that f(B) E B for each B E A with B 1 0.' Such a
68
is a choice function for A. It is manifest that the formal version of
function
f
AC
is
cumbersome and non-enlightening. 4.9
DEFINITION
The theory consisting of the set of sentences which are proved by Axioms 0 - 8 is
ZF,
and the theory
consisting of the set of sentences which are proved by Axioms 0 - 9
ZFC.
is
Thus
ZFC
is an infinite theory in the language
So.
We write "AI I Comprehension" if a model &I satisfies each sentence of the infinite axiom scheme of Comprehension, etc.
Our point of view is that models (and, in partZFC) are just algebraic objects. They
icular, models of
have the same ontological status as partially ordered sets, for example. Necessarily a model of the whole of ZFC will be complicated, but there are familiar algebraic objects which are models of some subtheories of the theory give some examples. 4.10
ZFC:
we
EXAMPLES
(i) ft
Let
It =
(]R, i a
then
for each
1 < a
n= Then
i=o Ql
("a
is
is the element such that no element
M=
a"). (2Z+,
where, for m,n E a+
E) ,
mth. digit in the binary expansion of
if the
i.e., if
Then
a = 1,
If
is an element of
b
(N, )
...pk k,
= p1
number, and write of the formula
pi r
for
4>
0.
where
i
r
ir(4>);
is the
prime
ith
i
is the Godel number
4>
For example,
x1)) = 25385372113138176198234294. (The coding map
it
Certainly
is not very efficient!).
it
is an injection.
The question which sentences of ZFC
a polynomial
PZFC
are theorems of
.zf
It is known that there is
now has a simple formulation.
in finitely many variables, say in
variables, with coefficients in
Z;,
such that, for each r
sentence
4>,
range of
PZFC
4>
E Thm(ZFC)
on
Nk.
k
if and only if
i
0
is in the
The existence of this polynomial
arises from Matijacevic's solution to Hilbert's tenth problem : it is not possible to find an algorithm for testing
an arbitrary polynomial equation
P(X1,.... Xn) = 0
with
coefficients in Z; for the possession of a solution in integers. One can take k to be nine, and PzFC could be written down explicitly if one had sufficient fortitude. r Thus, ZFC is consistent if and only if 3x1(1(x1 = x1)) is not in the range of PZFC' and it is tempting to attempt But Godel's second incompleteness theorem shows that the attempt would be futile. to prove that this is the case.
The question of the independence of sentences also has a simple formulation
:
a sentence
0
is independent of
78
i
f if and only if neither
ZFC
of
r
nor
4
7
'14
is in the range
PZFC'
In fact, this number-theoretic approach has not been successful in proving new independence results, and success does not seem to be imminent.
The second approach is algebraic, and involves the building of models.
We have already given an example of this approach when we showed in Example 4.15 that the theory of dense total orders without endpoints is complete. In this example, we used Godel's completeness theorem.
The point of this approach is that ZFC + ¢ is has a model, and one consistent if and only if ZFC + tries to build a model of
ZFC + 4,
given a model of
ZFC.
Godel was the first to be successful in this approach when he proved (in 1938) that Con ZFC implies Con(ZFC + CH). In fact, we have the following theorem. 4.19
THEOREM Assume that
submodel
Dl
of
N
ZFC
has a model
such that
K.
Then there is a
2 = ZFC + CH.
that, if ZFC has a then there is an extension Al of K such that
(We shall prove in 7.38
model 2
N,
ZFC + CH.)
In essence, Godel discovered an effective method for building new models of ZFC a given model.
by constructing submodels of
What remained undiscovered for 25 years was
an effective method for building extensions of a given model.
The technique of forcing was discovered by Cohen in 1963 forcing does give a method for building extensions, and it is the only such non-trivial method known today. Cohen's method :
allows one to extend a model by adding new elements in a controlled manner: the sentences which are true in the extended model are exactly those that are forced to be true. Forcing will be explained in Chapter 7.
79
4.20
NOTES
We have, in the formal definition of taken the alphabet to consist of a set of positive integers. This is merely to avoid some metamathematical considerations, and is not important.
For a general background in mathematical logic, see For model theory, see Bell and
[23] and [62], for example.
Slomson ([7]), and Chang and Keisler ([10]), for example. Godel's completeness theorem 4.8 is [3, 4.9],
The theorem applies to more r in the form that a theory is consistent if and only if it has a model. Lists of the axioms of ZFC are given in [13], [44] and [49]. For a discussion of the Axiom of Choice, There is an including many other formulations, see [43]. [10, 1.3.21], and [23, §2.5].
general languages than
interesting historical account of the origins of, and the controversies surrounding, this axiom in [53]. The Lindenbaum algebra is discussed in [7, Chapter 3, §4] and [44, §17].
For a discussion of Godel's incompleteness theorems, see Smorynski [66] and the standard texts. The formulation of
NDH
is due to Solovay.
An account of Matijacevic's work and of later results is given by Davis in [19]; We make one final remark.
see also [20].
As we stated on page 64,
we shall use Godel's completeness theorem to step from an assertion about the existence of models to the fact that a sentence is relatively consistent with
ZFC.
In fact,
because of the technical details of the method by which our models are constructed, it is possible in the cases which we consider to avoid the use of this theorem.
80
5
MARTIN'S AXIOM
In this chapter, we shall introduce Martin's Axiom (MA).
first, a key step in our
We have three motives:
NDH, Theorem 6.25, is given in
proof of the independence of the theory
second, the techniques used here
ZFC + MA + iCH;
in the applications of
MA
are similar to those to be used
and third, we believe that later in the study of forcing; some of the applications of MA to analysis that are given will be of general interest.
The axiom MA
was first studied (as "Axiom A") by
Martin and Solovay in [52].
The purpose of Martin and
Solovay was to settle questions in otherwise be resolved.
ZFC + iCH
that could not
In this aim, they were eminently
turned out to be an interesting and powerful axiom that does resolve many questions in ZFC + iCH, and successful:
MA
indeed it is only rather recently that some combinatorial statements that are independent of discovered.
MA + iCH
have been
At the present time, the study of some general-
izations of
MA is playing an important role in set theory. We shall prove in Chapter 8 that the theory
ZFC + MA + iCH
is relatively consistent with
Before dealing with
MA,
ZFC.
we shall first review the
elementary theory of ordinals and cardinals that we require, and we shall formally state the Continuum Hypothesis.
The
proofs that we omit of "easily checked" results can all be found in many texts, for example in [49, Chapter 11. We shall then introduce
MA
in the form of a
version of the Baire category theorem for compact spaces, and we shall show that it is equivalent to MA', the original
81
Axiom A. analysis:
Finally, we shall give some applications of MA in we hope these applications, all of which are well
known, will give the reader some feeling how the axiom is used.
However, it should be stressed that none of these
applications will be used in the proofs of our main theorems, and so they could be omitted by a single-minded reader. 5.1
DEFINITION Let
(P, 2 0.
DEFINITION
Martin's Axiom Let
x
(MA)
is the sentence:
be a compact topological space
satisfying the countable chain condition, and let
U
be a family of dense, open sets in
X
93
with in
< 2 °
JUI
is dense
Then n{U : U E U)
.
X.
implies
CH
Certainly,
We shall see in due
MA.
is consistent, then so is the theory ZFC + MA + -1CH, and so MA does not imply CH. First, however, we give a sentence which is equivalent to MA in ZFC. It is less natural, but easier to use, than the actual statement. course that, if
ZFC
DEFINITION
5.15
Let
A subset
(i)
each
with
a,b E Q
ccc
of
P
is an antichain if, for and b are incompatible. P
P
is countable;
be a subset of
V
V-generic if
is
is then
(P, 2°. 8
Thus whether or not in
=
X
(MA)
be a complete,
ccc
be a family of dense, open sets in
metric space, and let X with
K JUI
< 2 °.
Then
fl{U
:
U E U}
is dense in
X.
103
Proof V
Let
be the Stone-Cech compactification of
OX
as before, we write S
of
Since
X.
for the closure in
S
X
ccc,
is
suffices to show that
set in
V
with V fl x = V.
OX
and, for each
S = 0Vn) n X. X,
say
n,
X
y = x,
5.30
x E X,
$X.
V be an open
let
let
in
and let
X,
x =flWn.
is complete,
x EflWn,
Take
x E V.
with S
be the
Vn
Set
is a singleton in Then y x.
Suppose, if possible, that
there is a neighbourhood V of But eventually Vn a V, and so So
X,
1/n
We claim that choose Vn E Vn
Since
S = {y}.
in
For n E 1q,
family of open balls of radius Wn = U{V : V E Vn}.
and so it
GS-subset of
is a
X
For each open set
of a subset
OX
ccc,
is
$X
X;
and
y
in
X
such that
Vn - V c V,
X =flWn,
x 9 V.
a contradiction.
giving the result.
I
NOTES
The theory of ordinals and cardinals that we have Proposition 5.9 is a form of
given is quite standard.
Konig's theorem ([49,I.10.40)).
Most of the results about MA that we have given were first proved by Martin and Solovay [52], and are included in [44] and [49].
prehensive account of
MA.
The book [34] of Fremlin is a comIt includes our applications, and
many more, often in more general form, and it has a detailed account of the historical sources. Two articles about MA are (57] and [63];
a more recent account is [70].
Generalizations of
MA
to larger classes of
partially ordered sets have been studied. A certain maximal generalization is called MM ('Martin's Maximum'). See (32] and [45, Chapter 7]. It is known that, assuming the consistency of certain large cardinal axioms,
MM + ICH
is also K
consistent.
Curiously,
MM + iCH
Another variant of
implies that
2 ° =
2.
MA is PFA (the "Proper Forcing Axiom"): see [45] and [61]. In fact, MM implies PFA and PFA implies NDH: even the definitions of MM and of PFA are beyond the scope of this book.
104
GAPS IN ORDERED SETS
6
Our main story about the existence of discontinuous homomorphisms from the algebras C(X,C) into Banach algebras was left in Chapter 3. In the language of Chapter 4, the consistency of the axiom
with
NDH
by the construction of a model of of
will be established
ZFC
given a model
ZFC + NDH
We take a major step towards this goal in the
ZFC.
present chapter by proving in Theorem 6.25 that, with MA + -iCH,
NDH
follows from the fact that there is no
(NN, a).
Thus is
q(W)
a < w,
For
and
(a a
(a > T),
x < x,
xT = 0
So
za=0
a1 set.
so
(R, J u = w]J A
First, we want the
Secondly, we want
to be related to the value v(u) for u E dom v. I u E v] A first attempt at the definition of E U E v] is to set
I u E v I] = v (u)
for u E dom v
(and
[ u E v I] = 0 for
u !E dom v).
But this definition fails to satisfy our
desiderata.
For example, it could happen that
but that
v(w) > 0
for some
in this case, we must have
w E dom. u
with
J u E v I] > v(w).
v(u) = 0, I u = w I]
= 1:
We are
essentially forced by these considerations to our form of (2); a similar justification applies to (3).
hold for
We next show that the analogues of 7.1(i) - (v) do u,v,w E VB. This appears to prove that (VB,E,tiB
140
is a
$-valued model, where
E8(u,v) = jf u E vI] and but this is not the case because
ti8(u,v) _ I u = v] ,
V0
is a class and not a set.
PROPOSITION
7.8
Let
u,v E V0.
Iu (ii) Iu
Then:
UT = 1;
(i)
vI _ Iv ° uI].
Proof
If p(u) = 0, then Tu uI] = 1 by 7.7(i). (i) Now suppose that p (u) > 0 and that [Iv = v I] = 1 for all v E V8 with p(v) < p(u). For each t E dom u,
It E
uI]
= V{u(s) A It = sI]
:
s E dom u}
> u(t) A It = tI] = u(t) because
I t = t I] = 1, and so
u(t)' v It E u] > u(t)' Thus
T u c u I] = 1,
and so
V u(t) = 1.
E u = u I] = 1.
The induction
continues. This is immediate from the definition in
(ii)
7.7(v). 7.9
t
PROPOSITION Let
u,v,w E V8.
(i)
Iu = VI A
(ii)
Iu
(iii) Iu
Then:
TV = wI] < Jfu = wI];
VI A (IV vl] A [[w
w]1 < Ju VI < 1w
WI;
u]].
Proof
The proof is by induction on the position of (p(u),p(v),p(w))
in
(Ord3, Iv ° uD
and
[Lw c v]] > Iv = wI],
condition (i) follows.
Condition (ii) is immediate if Now suppose that
IV E W I] = 0.
t E dom w.
p(w)
w = 0,
for then
and take
> 0,
By the inductive hypothesis,
lu
Tv -t]] 0,
(6)
j w E v I] = O.
t E dom v.
Now
Then
TV c u] 5 v(t)' v It E u]], and so
Iv C u]] A (v(t) A [Lw = t]])
t]] A ItEu]] u (t)
and so
u(t)' v It E uI] > u(t)' v (u(t) u
a
Ifu c uaI] > a, I u a c uI] = 1,
Then
v
For
u,v E VB,
set
equivalent if
u tiv.
if
and
If u = uaI] % a. I
VO:
u
= 1.
and
v
are
We write
supp u = {t E dom u
(t E supp u).
and
if l[u = V1
u ' v
is an equivalence relation on
u ti v
A a) > a,
(t) ' v It E U I > (u(t) A a)' v u(t) = 1.
Thus
Set
and
:
u(t) # O}.
supp u = supp v and u(t) = v(t) Then % is an equivalence relation on
V$,
u tiv if u tiv.
Recall from 5.15(1) that a subset A of a Boolean A c B\{O} and if a A b= 0 a is an antichain if whenever a,b E A with a # b. The following result is algebra
sometimes called the mixing lemma. PROPOSITION
7.11
algebra
Let A be an antichain in the complete Boolean and let f : A + V8 be a function. Then there
g,
exists u E VB with If u = f(a) I] >a
(a E A).
Proof Set t E dom u,
dom u = V{dom f(a)
:
a E A},
and, for
set
u(t) = V{f(a) (t) A a : a E A with t E dom f(a)}.
144
Take
Since
a E A.
A
is an antichain, we have
u( t)
A a =
f (a) (t) A a if t E dom f (a) , and u(t) A a = 0 if t ,E dom f(a). Now ua % f(a)a, and so I ua = f(a)a I] = 1. By 7.10, [u = uaI] >a and f f(a) = f(a)a] 3 a, and so,
by 7.9(i),
1u = f(a) ] 3 a.
be a formula of ., and let at ul,...,un E V8. We define the truth of (ul,.... un) in V8 to be an element of B, to be again denoted by Let
(xl,.... xn)
11
as if
were a
(V8,E8,'8)
Formally, the
8-valued model.
rules are exactly those set out on pages 132/133. is required with Rule 3, however.
Some care The problem is that we
must be sure that each supremum of the form exists in
B:
proper class.
V{...
:
u E V8}
we are apparently taking a supremum over a To show the suprema do exist, it is sufficient
to show that
{a E B
:
a = D[ul....,ui-l,u,ui+ll...,un] 1J for some
is actually a set. formula
u E V8},
We shall note on page 156 that, for each there is a formula **(xi,.... xm+2)
p(xl,.... xm),
such that, for vl,...,vm E V8, I*[vl,...,vm] I] = a in
B
is true in V, and so the **[vl,...,vm,a,B] result follows from the Axiom of Comprehension because B is
if and only if a set.
(The formula * does not assert that
D[vl,.... vm]I] exists, but it specifies the conditions on a E B that ensure that a = I [v1,...,vm11. The construction of
**
depends on both
i4
and
in,
and involves
working through the finitely many subformulae of
*.)
Since this is a book about forcing, we should at least mention the standard notation used in the subject.
Let
145
B
be a complete Boolean algebra, and let
b E B.
Then one
writes
b IF '4[u1,...,un]' for b < D(ul,...,un] I] in
V0
However, we shall not use this notation.
On page 65, we introduced the abbreviation x c y for Vt(t E x r t E y). We now see that this is consistent with the notation in Definition 7.7. We must show that, for each u,v E V$,
Iu c VI] = A{Iw E uI]' v Iw E vI] This is immediate if
u = 0.
:
Now suppose that
w E V$}. (7) p(u) > O.
By
f[u c VI] A Irw E u] < jw E vJ], and so ju a vI] j w E u l ' v j w E v j for w E V$ . Also, for t E dom u,
(6),
u(t) 6 I t E uI,
and so
Iu C VI > A{It E uJ]' v It E v]
:
t E dom u}.
Thus (7) follows. and so u = 0 I] has two 0 E V$ possible interpretations: the first involves the equality of
Observe that
u and 0 as terms, the second is where O(x) = 14(u] I] Vz(z j x). Fortunately, both interpretations give the same
value.
Part (i) of the following result for a formula 4(x)
is
(u = v V
4 (u) )
4 (v) I]
= 1.
Part (ii) is the fullness lemma for to the Axiom of Choice,
V$ : its proof appeals
and indeed the result can be shown to
be equivalent to the Axiom of Choice.
Let
4(x1,...,xn) be a fixed formula of .'.
146
THEOREM
7.12
Let
be a complete Boolean algebra, and let
B
u11...,un E VB. For each
(i)
u E V
u ° ui11 A Em[u1,...,un] I S ¢[u
i-1,u,u
1
u E V0
There exists
(ii)
I
such that
[u,...,u1 1] = D[ul,...,ui-1,u,ui+l,...,unI I .
Proof
Let
(i)
D
be the set of subformulae
such that the result holds for By 7.9,
4D
of
p
V.
contains all the atomic formulae.
It
is an immediate consequence of the definition of truth in VB and X that contains V v X whenever t contains V contains and p v X is a subformula of 0, and that (D
4)
3xfor each variable 3x.*
is a subformula of Suppose that
of
say
y, = V,(x1)
whenever
x
0
contains
j
and
c.
and that -p is a subformula p E for notational convenience. Set 4D
a = FLu = u111, b = EVi[u11 1, and c= FLiy(u] 1]. Then a A b < a A C. Also, a = I u1 ° u 1] , and so a A c < a A b. Thus a A b = a A c, and so a A b' = a A c'. This implies
that
-j tp E
4D.
It follows that all subformulae V of and in particular the result holds for c
to
(ii)
suppose that
Again for the sake of notational sanity, we 0 _ (xl).
Let S = {I [u] 11 S
is a subset of
minimum ordinal Then
f
:
belong itself.
S - Ord
so that, as before,
For each b E S, let f(b) be the with b = F [u] ]1 for some u E V is a function defined by a property, and
B. a
u E VB },
147
so, by the Axiom of Replacement, the image of a
with
13X 4 j = V{ JL
Lu] 1J
So there is an ordinal
f(b) 4 a :
is a set.
S
We have
(b E S).
u E Va}.
Let
I = {b E B : b
0.
Set
such that, for
150
dom v = U{dom t and, for
set
s E dom v,
For
:
t E dom u}, v(s) = 1.
t E dom u, It c v I] = 1 because
I s E V I > V (S) A I s = s I] = 1 for s E dom t.
Take
Then
w E V$.
tI] A It cVI
tD < Jw
u(t) A fw
< FIw c vI, and so
I w E u I] < j w c v I] ,
as required.
Power set
5
Vx 3y dz (z c x * z E Y) u E V$,
Given
each w E
V8,
we require
We can suppose that and, for
define
set
t E dom v,
f:
dom u -+ B
p(u)
Set
> 0.
Take
v(t) = 1.
dom v = Bdom u,
w E V8,
and
by
f(t) = It e wI] For t E dom f, f(t)' v It Also, f E dom v, and so For
such that, for
v E VB
T W c U1 < T W E V I] .
(t E dom u).
E wI] = 1,
f c wI] =1.
and so
f E V I] ) v (f) A ff f
f I] = 1.
t E V0,
It E wI] A It E uI] p (u) , then (ii) If a > P (u) , then (i)
fFa E u I] = 0. cEav
..=
u I]
= 0.
Proof
We prove (i) and (ii) simultaneously by induction on the position of
(a,P(u)) in (Ord2 P(u),
j[a = t I] =o, 6 = P (u) .
Then
then
P(t) < a
whence
tLa E
(t E dom u),
and so
u j =O. If a> p (u) , set
166
Ia
= u l < . v c .1 = A{ U
E U] : w E a}
I a E U I] = 0. The induction continues. 7.22
LEMMA Let
and suppose that
u E V8,
I ' u is an ordinal' II # 0. Then there exists
a E Ord
with
., v I u = al]
0.
Proof V
For
a E Ord,
L 'a
is an ordinal']] = 1
by
and so
7.20(ii),
Eu E al v E. = a]] v Es E ul] 1'6v
3 I 'u
= I'u is an ordinal'] Take
a E Ord with
a E uI] = 0, and so j u
a< a
with
7.23
is an ordinal'
is an ordinal']] A # 0.
> p (u) . l)
0.
By 7.21,
u Il
By (9), there exists
I u 2 a I] # O.
DEFINITION Set
Then
Ordv = {a Ordv
:
I
a E Ord}.
is a class which is contained in
V$,
and 7.22 shows that it satisfies the condition specified on in fact, page 162:
Du is an ordinal' l= V{ j u
v
a I]
:
a E Ord}
=V{{u2al] : a a' I] = 1.
(v)
Pw is the least infinite ordinal']] = 1.
168
Proof
It is easy to check Examples (i) - (iii). were false, there would exist
8
with
Ia E s11 n [ES E (a+1)v]]
0,
Example (v) follows from
and, by 7.18, this is impossible. (iv).
If (iv)
I
However, other basic properties of sets may not be preserved in the passage from
V
to
These include the
V$.
power set operation (in general,
E['P(u) = (P(u))v']l # 1) There is a general theorem
and the cardinality of a set.
that asserts that properties specified by
"1 -formulae"
are
we shall return to this point in a more general
preserved:
context in Chapter S.
It follows from 7.24(iii) and (v) that, if
is a
a
v
countable ordinal, then I'a is countable' = 1. However, v if a is an uncountable ordinal, it is not always true that
T'va
is uncountable']]
0:
it is particularly important for
More generally, if
us to deal with this possibility. u,v E V,
then
_
Jul
I'iul
lvJ
implies that
lvi
does not imply that
=
JvJ']] = 1,
but Jul
7.25
DEFINITION Let
VS
if
f'lul # ivJ'I] = 1.
K
be a cardinal.
Then
K
is preserved in
is a cardinal' ]] = 1.
J[' K
We have seen that is preserved, then
R0
is preserved in
V8.
If
ktl
v
'H1
is the least uncountable cardinal']] = 1,
and we write this as
I'itl = !tl'I] = 1.
(To recap, in this
169 v
expression
is the image under the embedding v of the V, whereas K1 is the first
K1
first uncountable ordinal in
uncountable ordinal in the universe
is pre-
If
VD.)
2
served, then all we can say in general is that
'!t2
v
or h2 = K1'
= h2
= 1, V
but, if
and
h1
are preserved, then
R2
I'K2 =
14 21 I]
= 1.
To study the preservation of cardinals, we consider terms for subsets of where
Let
fv and, for
:
set
and for functions from
u E V.
For
tHI
V
u
to
v,
of = {s
:
we set
V E V$,
u -+B,
we define
f: u -+ B,
dom
Then
u
u,v E V.
of E V8
s E u},
by
Vf(s) = f(s).
TV
= 1. For VvE V$ E v f I] = v*f (s) and T V f c u I] v*I] g = f v and = T V c u I] , = v . Then T V = 4 v
and so
v ti v*
if
T V c u I]
= 1.
Thus, up to equivalence, v
we have obtained a canonical set of terms for subsets of
u.
We essentially repeat this construction in the next theorem, obtaining a canonical set of terms for bijections. 7.26
THEOREM
Let u,v E V.
Then
[' Iu I
and only if there is a function
(i)
Of (r, s)
:
(ii)
V{f (r, s)
:
sEv}=b rEu}=b
(iii) f(r,s1) A f(r,s2) = 0 (iv) f(r1,s) A f(r2,s) = 0
=
in V$ such that:
jv j' I] 3 b
f: u x v -+ B
(r E u) ; (s E v) ;
(r E U, sl
(s E v, rl
in v); r2 in u). s2
if
170
Proof
',u,
Suppose that
lemma, there exists
=
v,']j
By the fullness
b.
with
w E VS
[['w is a bijection from u to v' ]J > b. Define
by setting
f: u x v + B
f(r,s) = ['s is the value of Then
f
(iii) holds because
11w
is an injection' I]
(i)
[['w
dom w = {(r,s)v V
Clearly
:
f: u x v + B
w((r,s)v) = f(r,s).
and it is easily checked that
is a bijection from u
vJ' I
=
satisfies
v
IV
I'1uI
and (iv)
Z b.
r E u, s E v},
11'W c u x v'I] = 1, [['w
Thus
is a function' I] 3 b,
Conversely, suppose that - (iv). Define w E V8 by
I] A b.
1 'ran w = v' ]] ) b,
(ii) holds because
holds because
r'
(i) holds because
satisfies conditions (i) - (iv):
'dom w = u' ]] > b,
at
w
b,
to
v' I]
as required.
= b.
I
We can now show that cardinals are preserved in V8 provided that 8 satisfies the key countable chain condition introduced in Chapter 4.
antichain in
Recall that
8
is
ccc
if each
is countable.
B
THEOREM Let 8 be a complete ccc each cardinal is preserved in V8. 7.27
Boolean algebra.
Then
Proof Let
with
a < K.
K
be a cardinal, and let
Set
b = J'JaJ = JKJ'I].
a
If
be an ordinal K = H0,
then
171
by 7.24(v).
b = 0
Now suppose that K > $°. Let f: a X K - B be For a < a, set fa(S) _ the function specified in 7.26.
f(a,s)
and set
(8 < K), Sa = {B
By (iii) in 7.26,
f(a,8) # O},
:
fa :
is an injection and
Sa + B\{O}
is an antichain in
fa(Sa)
S = US C'.
Since
B.
B
ccc,
is
ISI < max{a,K°} < K. Take countable, and so Then b < V{f(a,8) a < a} = 0. that a 0 S.
Thus, in each case 'K
in
Let
IKI']] = 0,
and so
is preserved
K
be any complete Boolean algebra.
8
is preserved in
is a cardinal with
K
The above
K > 1BI,
then
V8.
THEOREM
7.28
Let K =
such
V$.
proof shows that, if K
c['Ial =
This shows that
is a cardinal']] = 1.
is
S01
S < K
K IBI °.
be a complete Boolean algebra, and set
8
Then K V 12 ° < K' ]] = 1 in V8.
Proof Set
A = K+,
the successor cardinal to
K.
We
V
first claim that
if'2 0 > x'I] = 0
the case, there exists
't
b E B\{O}
and
is an injection from
By the fullness lemma, for each va E V8
in
V8.
t E VB v A
a < A,
into
If this is not such that P(3N)
there exists
such that v
'the value of
t
at
a
is
va']] > b,
]] > b.
172
and then
m'Va C
fa
if fa = f8,
Inv
nF
:
then
(a < X).
3b
I]
N'
and so a =
b,
vSI]
I va
a < X,
set
N + B.
E vaI],
[ ' t is an injection' I] 3 b.
For
Thus
H
B
a I fa,
:
because
A + ON ,
x
is an injection, and so
of the hypothesis that
a contradiction A < IB NI _ JBI 0, K K < JBI °. Hence the claim holds.
The result is immediate from the claim. It can be shown that, if
is a complete Boolean
8
h
algebra and
is infinite, then
JBI
° =
JBI
It follows from 7.26 that, if is preserved in
CBI.
then
K % CBI,
K
and it then follows easily from 7.28
V8,
that, if
1'2x°
= (280)v' I] = 1 in JBI = 280, then We shall not need this remark, but we shall need the
VB.
following corollary of the theorem.
COROLLARY
7.29
Let
B
(i)
If
(CH)
be a complete Boolean algebra.
(ii) If
K
< K2,
then
1 ' 2 ° < K2' ]] = 1 in VB .
JBI < K1,
then
[[CH] = 1
IB I
in
VB.
Proof
and so
(i)
Since
K
K
CH
holds,
K2 ° = K2
by 5.11, K
JBI 0 < K2 ° = K2.
By the theorem,
v
1-2 ° < K2'I1 =1.
V
Certainly
I'K2 < K2'I] = 1, (ii)
Again using
12 0 < Kl' I] = 1. [['2 ° < K1' I] = 1,
and so the result follows. CH,
Certainly
i.e.,
JBI ° = Kl,
and so
J ' K1 < K1' II = 1,
[[CHI] = 1.
and so
B
We can now construct the complete Boolean algebra
173
B
such that
in V.
E[ CH I = O
We must show that
I' I P(NV) I > ttl' -fl = 1
in
V8
The following theorem gives a condition which reduces the problem to a combinatorial question about Boolean algebras.
be a complete Boolean algebra, let be the f,g : N - B be functions, and let v ,v corresponding terms, (see page 169), so that dom of = dom v g = {n : n E N }, vf(n) = f(n), and ) = g (n) Let
g
v(n
.
Then
Vf c vg I]
_ A{vf(n)' v In E vg]] = A{f(n) ' v g(n)
:
:
n E N}
n E N} ,
and so
I Vf # Vg1] = V{f(n) c g(n) where
a A b = (a' n b)
:
n E N} ,
(a,b E B).
v (a n b')
(11) This shows
that condition (12), below, arises naturally. 7.30
THEOREM Let
B
be a complete
Suppose that there is a set
Boolean algebra.
ccc
S c BN
such that
IS1 = K2
and such that
V{f(n) A g(n) Then
I CH 1]
= 0 in
:
n E N} = 1
(f,g E S, f # g) .
(12)
VB.
Proof
Suppose, if possible, that
By 7.28,
I CH I]
1 ' x 1 = K 1' I] = 1,
'there is a surjection from
ttl
= b # 0
in
VB.
and so onto
P(N V)'I] = b.
174
w E VB with
By the fullness lemma, there exists Rv
is a surjection from
11w
= b.
V
onto
1
I'vf E P(Nv)'II = IVf cIN VI] = 1 for f E S, there exists of < wl such that Since
T'vf is the value of Since and
# 0.
I]
= K21 there is a subset T of S with IS a < wl such that bf # 0, where, for f E T,
ITI = ti2
I
bf
=
I 'v f is the value of
Take
Uv f
vaf'
at
w
with
f,g E T
= v g I] = 0, and so
is an antichain in
B
b
f
f
g.
as required.
b = 0,
.
By (11) and (12),
n b = 0.
Thus
g
of cardinality
contradiction of the hypothesis that
va'
at
w
f
ccc,
is
B
{b
:
f E T}
But this is a
K2'
and so
I
Our choice of a Boolean algebra
B
to satisfy the
conditions of Theorem 7.30 was implicitly given in the original arguments of Cohen. 7.31
DEFINITION
Let 2N
be the Cantor set
{O,1)3N,
and set
Xc = (2N ) w2. The set
Xc
is a compact Hausdorff space with
respect to the product topology.
Xc
is homeo-
morphic to
2 2, the Cantor cube of weight w2. as the set of functions F: w x N - {0,1}; a < w2, set Fa(n) = F(a,n).
We regard
Xc
for
Of course,
w
The regular-open algebra
space
X
there that
of a topological was introduced in Example 2.7, and it was noted R(X)
R(X)
is a complete Boolean algebra.
175
PROPOSITION
7.32
The Boolean algebra
R(X
is
d
ccc.
Proof
Let 2 N.
T
Clearly
T
Let
P
be the standard base for the topology of is countable. be the collection of maps whose domain is w2 and whose range is contained in T.
a finite subset of For t E P, set
Ut = {F E XC Then
:
Fa E t(a)
is a clopen set in
Ut
base for the topology of
s(a) = t(a)
XC.
(a E dom t)}.
and
XC,
{Ut
:
Note that, if
then
(a E dom s fl dom t),
Suppose, if possible, that
t E P}
us nut
R(XC)
is a
s,t E P
and if
# W.
is not
ccc.
Then there exists an uncountable subset A of P such that Ug n Ut = 0 whenever s,t E A with s # t. Let F = {dom t Then, t E Al. Suppose that F is uncountable. :
by the
A-system lemma, Proposition 6.1, there is a finite
subset
T
w2 and an uncountable subfamily G dom s n dom t = T whenever dom s and
of
such that
are distinct elements of F. subset A* of A such that and
t
F
and
u. n Ut # 0 Thus R(XC) 7.33
A*.
s
This conclusion also
is countable.
Since s,t E A*
F
dom t
Thus there is an uncountable dom s n dom t = T whenever
are distinct elements of
holds if
of
T
is countable, we may suppose that, for s(a) = t(a). But this implies that
a E T,
a contradiction of the hypothesis.
(s,t E A*), is
ccc.
I
THEOREM There is a complete Boolean algebra
J CHI] = 0 in
8
such that
V$ .
Proof Set $
= R(XC),
so that
0
is a complete
ccc
176
we shall apply Theorem 7.30.
Boolean algebra.
a < w2,
For
define fa : N - P(X
fa(n) = {F E Xc Clearly each
f
a
(n)
F(a,n) = 1}
is clopen in
by setting
(n E N) . and so
XC,
fa(n) E B.
Set S = {fa : a < w2}. Since fa # fs if a # g, Take a,$ < w2 with a 8. Then
U{fa(n) o fa(n)
ISI = K2
n E N}
= {F E XC : F(a,n) # F(5,n) a set which is clearly dense in
for some n E N} ,
It follows from the
X C.
first of equations (3) of Chapter 2 (page 29) that
V{fa(n) n f6 (n) and so
S
n E N} = 1,
satisfies the conditions in 7.30.
follows.
The result
a
We have now achieved the following goal. 7.34
THEOREM Assume that there is a model
there is a model, extending
Ut,
of
Al
of
ZFC.
ZFC + -CH.
Then
I
We noted in Theorem 4.19 the result of Godel that, if there is a model pt
a
which is a model of
of
ZFC,
ZFC + CH.
then there is a submodel of
We shall prove, in Theorem
7.38, that, if there is a model of ZFC then there is a model of ZFC + CH; we shall also prove a related result, Theorem 7.39, that will be required in Chapter 8. 7.35
DEFINITION Let
injective maps ran f c P(K),
K
be a cardinal.
Then
f such that dom f E K+ the power set of K. For
Q(K)
is the set of
and such that f,g E Q(K),
set
177
f 6 g
if
dom g c dom f
Certainly By 2.10,
f1dom g= g.
and
is a partially ordered set.
(Q(K),b
and
I ' b* = O in u' I] Since
Eb* E v I] = 1,
and then
b*
Set
subalgebra of
b' .
we may, by (b), suppose that b* E C*,
is uniquely specified by these properties. B* = {b* : b E B}. C*;
isomorphism, and so
the map 8*
Then
b F* b*,
H*
fl + 8*,
is a Boolean is a Boolean
is complete.
We first claim that
C*
is complete.
be a subset of C*, so that Is E v I] = 1 (8 E S) and [ES# cvI] = 1. By the fullness lemma 7.12(11), there exists c E V$ such that IL'c = VSO in u' I] = 1, Let
S
192
1. E S#]] > S#(s) = 1, that
and that
d E C*
'c
u
and so s< c s o d
c < d.
so
is complete.
C*
(b E T),
Thus
c = VS
This establishes that
in
C*,
and
is a complete sub-
8*
C*.
Take c = V{b*
Now suppose
C*.
Then
s E S } = 1,
:
Secondly, we claim that algebra of
s E S,
(s E S#1' ]]
d
u
= A l l ' s
' b*
b.
I'c = 1
in
u'I] = 1,
c' ]] A I ' b * = 1
and so
c = 1.
in u' I]
This is
sufficient to establish the second claim.
We now choose a complete Boolean algebra
C conas a complete subalgebra such that there is a Boolean isomorphism ir: C - C* with ir(b) = b* (b E B). We finally claim that
taining
8
!'u
is isomorphic to
Take
c1,c2 E C
and
/tiGI I]
b E B.
= 1.
Then
b A c1 = b A c2
if and only if b* A 1T(c1) = b* A 7r(c2) in C*, 8.6(iv), if and only if b 4 J[c11G = (c21G]
I'b* A I(c1) = b* A 7r(c2) Since
j['b* = 1 in u' I] ) b,
and so, by
in u' ]] = 1.
(3) holds if and only if
(3)
193
= rt(c2) I] ) b.
7r(c1
Thus
[c2] GI] _ f 7r(c1)
rL [c1IG
Set S = {[c] G
f
c E C} and
:
S - D; f is well defined, for if C1 = c2
by 8.6(iii).
(4),
satisfies (2), and so
f
7r(c2) I]. (c)G 1+ 7T (c) ,
(c 11 G = (c2] G, then f is a homomorphism.
By 8.6(i),
Cv/tiG
where
f is the term corresponding to claim holds, and (i) is proved.
We write
(ii)
C
C*
for is
By
onto U11=1,
['f is an isomorphism from
We prove that
(4)
Thus the final
f.
2 0.
ccc
and has cardinality
t:
this is sufficient. Let S C C*\{O}
be an antichain in
S
and
s A t = 0
E'S#\{O} Since
j 'U
is
with s# t.
s,t E S
is an antichain in
ccc'I] = 1,
'S#\{O}
for
so that
C*,
Then
u']] = 1.
it follows that
is countable']] = 1.
By the fullness lemma, there exists
t E VB
with
Nv
['t
is a surjection from
Take
n E N.
Then there exists
I 'the value of t at For
sot E S
It n
with
onto
n
to E V8
with
is tn' I] = 1.
s # to I's A t = 0
= s I A Itn
S#\{O}'I] = 1.
t j < It n
in
u']] = 1,
=01
and so
194
I 't n
But Since
many
B
n
t :
Then a # 0, and so is and so for some n E N,
# O
]
n E N},
whence
Itn = sI]
Sn = {s E S
set
n E IN,
a C S.
is
S = U{S
For
S.
Take
# 0).
is
in
a
Thus
E S#\ {O }' I] = 1, and so It n = 81 A It n = t I] = O. is ccc, It n sI] = 0 for all but countably 0 I]
is a countable set.
S
# 1.
Thus
C*
ccc.
By hypothesis, li ' Iv I < t' I] = 1. Since IB I = t, it follows from 7.28 that li ' c < ' I] = 1. Thus, by the fullness lemma, there exists t E VB with ['t and, for each
is a surjection from
fs
s E C*,
takes the value
= 1,
a' I]
= 1.
define
v
:
v' I]
is the least ordinal at which t
For
onto
is E VB with
there exists
s E C*,
['t
C
c - B.
a F 11 a = is I] ,
If a # 6, then IVa = is I] n Isv= is I] = 0, and so, since B is ccc, {a : fs(a) # O} is countable. Since Tv
18 E v I] = 1, if
s,t E C*
that
s = t.
V{
8 = t8 I]
with
fs = ft,
Thus the map
a < c l = 1. This implies that,
:
then a
t
f
8
s
'
t,
and hence, by (a),
is an injection.
It follows that IC*I < 1{f E Bt : N
=
Since
1{a
:
f(a) # Oil ' H°}1
K
IBI °=t°=t.
IC*I = t, as required. = IBI, This completes the proof of the theorem.
IC*I % IB*I
195
We now fix a complete Boolean algebra complete Boolean algebra subalgebra, and a term
T' W=
C/ ti G'
(so that, by 8.7,
containing
C
8,
a
as a complete
8
such that
w E V8
10 = 1 is a complete Boolean algebra'
[['w
The next step is to define a class
V(w)
=1).
by
setting
Vow) = {t E V8
:
I't E Vw' ]JB = 1}.
(To be precise, ['t E VW' IJ 8 algebra and
belongs to
x
t, w) ]J B,
=
is the formula which formalizes
'y
where o (x, y)
is a complete Boolean
VY'.)
Our proof of the iteration theorem involves a map e
from VC
to V. We shall give a quite explicit
definition of
texts in logic avoid, perhaps wisely, the
e;
detailed verifications that we give, for they infer the existence of define
from general considerations.
e
eIVa by induction on the ordinal First set
In fact, we
a.
e(Q) = 0.
ejVa
Now suppose that
t E Va+1 \ V. Define
by
ft
dom ft = dom t,
has been defined, and take
and,
for s E dom ft, (5)
ft(s) = V{1[e(s) Then
ft
is a function from
1s E For
e(r) ]J$ A [[ r E tJ]C
tIC < ft(s)
61,82 E dom t,
:
to
C.
(a E dom
t).
dom t
r E dom t}. Certainly
(6)
we have
lEe(s1) = e(52) IJ8 < I (ft(81)1G = [ft(s2)1GI8:
(7)
196
to see this, it is sufficient by 8.6(ii) to check that
e(sl)
8
e(s2) ]
n ft(sl) =
Ie(s1) ° e(a2) ]
A ft(s2 (The reason
and this is immediate from the definition (5). for defining fail.)
ft
is that the analogue of (7) for
may
Now set e(t) = {{{e(s)}#, {e(s),(ft(s))G}#}#
(We are determined to be quite explicit!)
defined
t
e(t)
:
s E dom t}#
Thus we have
so that
D'e(t)
is a function with domain
{e(s) and so that, for each
:
s E dom t}#' I]$
= 1,
(8)
s E dom t,
['the value of e(t) at e(s) is [f t WIG' It follows that
I 'e(t)
The inductive definition of
term in 8.9
and so
E Vw'I]8 = 1, e
(9) e(t)
E V.
continues.
In summary, for each term t in VC, e(t) is a VS which is also a term for a "term in Vw". LEMMA
e(a) = e(t) ]]B s = tI]C (s,t E VC). (ii) For a E 1/C, fs(p) _ [p sIC (p E dom s). (i)
Proof
The proof is by induction on the position of in (Ord2, 0 because 1[ e(s) is vacuous if t = 0.
if and only if p(s),p(t) > 0
Now suppose that for each p E dom. s.
p,q E V$ Then
with
s # 0,
and (ii)
and that (i) holds
(p(p),p(q)) < (P(8),P(t)).
Take
fs(p) = y{[e(p) = e(r) 18 A Ir E sI]C : r E dom s} a and
{q = 010 > a' .
V
['p(q) < g in V'' 10 = 1, and so, by the inductive C VC such that hypothesis, there exists p E VC $ a $ B+1 a, I 'e (p) ti q in Vw' ]] = 1. We have I e (p) 2 r I] Then
and so
[[ ' [e(p)
E
8Jw A E[e(p) j e(t)
By definition,
Dw
dom t = Va,
follows from (9) and the fact that
> O' I]8 >. a.
and so
(11)
p E don t.
It
that
t(p) = ft(p)
If'Ife(p) E e(t):n' > (t(p)]G'IS = 1. Thus
If' Ie(p) E e(t) IIw 3 Ie(p) E aI W' 118 = 1. But this is a contradiction of (11). The proof of the lemma is complete.
4)(x1,...,x) be a formula.
Let 8.12
i
THEOREM Let
8
be a complete Boolean algebra, let
be a
t
complete Boolean algebra containing $ as a complete subv algebra and let w E V8 be such that I 'w = CA,G'I] = 1. Then, for
t1,.... tn E VC
and
c E C,
[Egt1,...,tnI IIc = c if and only if I ' I0[e(tI),...,e(tn)] IIw = [c]G' ] 0 = 1. Proof Let
0
be the set of subformulae
V
of
0
such
202
that the result holds for ,. By 8.10, contains all the atomic formulae in $. 0 By 8.6(i), contains i v X whenever 0 contains i and 0 and
X
is a subformula of
v X
whenever
0
contains
and
contains
0
c.
Similarly,
mp
is a subformula.
Suppose that contains p(x1) and that 3x1p is a subformula. Set c = 1 3x l* I] E, and take d E C with I' 13X J W = [d]al I] 8 = 1. By the fullness lemma, there exists I t E VC with f * [ t] 11 C = c. Since I' 14 (e(t) II w
I o = 1, it follows that c < d. By the fullness
[c]
lemma again,
'there exists t E Vw with J4 [tl
[d] G' J] s = 1,
fl u ' =
and so, by a third application of the fullness lemma, there exists
s E
V8 with
I' j * [ s] j W = [d] Go I S = I ' s E Vw-18 = 1. Now
s E
Ow),
u E VE with I i [ u] IC = d, 3xly, E
and so it follows from 8.11 that there exists
in
E[ ' e (u) ti s
and so d < c.
Vw' II
8
Thus
Since * E c = d, and hence
= 1.
,
(P.
It follows that all subformulae of
and in particular the result holds for completes the proof of the theorem.
belong to
¢
@,
This
itself.
I
We need one last lemma before we can complete our analysis of
V(w)
in terms of
Vf.
u E V8 with
Let
I l u is a complete Boolean algebra' II
a
= 1.
vt
For
t E Vol
we have
E V8.
But inside
v
"t
relative to
u".
V8 we can form
In an attempt to avoid confusion, we
denote this latter term by defined up to equivalence in
(t)u
V, 8
Of course,
(t)v U
is only
but this will not matter
203
because
8.13
will only appear in expressions of the form
(t)v
LEMMA
Let t E V$ .
J ' e (t) ', (t) v in
Then
Vw' ]]
= 1.
Proof
Let s E dom t. The main point of the proof is that the following equation holds:
e(a) E e(t)I]w = To see this, set
(s)' E
1. (12)
b = Is E t] Is.
By 8.10(1),
[[ ' fre(e) E e(t) I]w = [b]G' is = 1, and so
[E' ff e(s) E e(t) jw = 1' I]8 = b,
Ie(a) E e(t) Iw = O' II$ = b'. Also, we have
If 'If (a) I (a)w
1' ]J$ = s E tJj = b, (t) ;I]w = 0' 1$ = 1s
tIB = b'o,
and so (12) follows.
We now prove the lemma by induction on result is trivial if
p(t) = 0.
Suppose that
that the result holds for each Take
a E dom t.
p(t).
The
p(t) > 0
and
with
p(8) < p(t). s E V$ By the inductive hypothesis and
(12),
lL'tLe(8) E e(t) I W = Ife(s) and so, taking account of (12), we have
(t)vIW' $ = 1,
204
e(t) c (t)w ]
= 1' II$ = 1.
Also by the inductive hypothesis and (12),
(s)w E (t),Iw = I(s)" E e(t) I W' 113 we have
It c (dom t)#I]g = 1,
and so, since
I' I (t)w c e(t) 1w = 1' I$ = 1. The result for
follows, and the induction continues.
t
Let
4(x1,...,xn)
be a formula.
We need an observation: complete Boolean algebras, if isomorphism, and if
n
it(I4(a1,...,a] I81) 8.14
let
if
81
it: 81 -r 82
a ,...,a 1
I
E V,
=
and
82
are
is a Boolean
then
TI 10[a1...'an] 1182
(Iteration theorem)
THEOREM (i)
Let
8
t1,...,t
and
u
be a complete Boolean algebra, and be terms in VS such that
is a complete Boolean algebra' D S
EL'u
[(t11u,..., (tn)u] Th = 1' 11, = 1. Then there is a complete Boolean algebra C containing a complete subalgebra such that EL 4[tl...,tn] IC = 1. Suppose, further, that
(ii)
8
ccc
is
and has
ti
cardinality
2 °
and that K
EL'u
is
ccc
and has cardinality
Then we can suppose that Ro 2
.
C
is
ccc
8
< 2 °'I]8 = 1.
and has cardinality
as
205
Proof
By 8.8, there is a complete Boolean algebra containing 8 as a complete subalgebra such that is isomorphic to
'u
t
C/tiG']]$ = 1.
V
Choose I 'u
with
w E VB
11'w = E/,v G']]B = 1.
is isomorphic to
$ = 1,
w'
Since
the above observation
shows that
IjW = 1']]$ = 1.
]]u = l' ]]B = 1, and so, by
By 8.13, Theorem 8.12,
t[4[tl,.... tn] ]]f = 1. This follows from 8.8(11).
(ii)
1
Our strategy for building the complete Boolean algebra A for which I MA ]]A = 1 is to express A as a union of complete subalgebras which are themselves built by successively eliminating potential counter-examples.
To
carry out this strategy we shall require the following result. 8.15
PROPOSITION Let
be an ordinal and let
F
sequence of complete
ccc
be a
Boolean algebras such that:
whenever
BS
whenever
Ba
a < E.
is a
ccc
Boolean algebra, and
B
a
B
denotes the completion of
I]$ = 1, Q(t).
Proof Since ccc.
is
s
By 5.16,
I's
is a gap, Theorem 6.12 proves that 8
is a
Q(t)
Boolean algebra, and so
ccc
is an (8 1,K1)-pregap in (NN,